ARTICLES It`s Not About the Money
Transcription
ARTICLES It`s Not About the Money
ARTICLES It’s Not About the Money: THE ROLE OF PREFERENCES, COGNITIVE BIASES, AND HEURISTICS AMONG PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES Michael A. McCann† I. INTRODUCTION Professional athletes are often regarded as selfish, greedy, and out-of-touch with regular people. They hire agents who are vilified for negotiating employment contracts that occasionally yield compensation in excess of national gross domestic products.1 Professional athletes are thus commonly assumed to most value economic remuneration, rather than the “love of the game” or some other intangible, romanticized inclination. Lending credibility to this intuition is the rational actor model; a law and economic precept which presupposes that when individuals are presented with a set of choices, they rationally weigh costs and benefits, and select the course of † Assistant Professor of Law, Mississippi College School of Law; LL.M., Harvard Law School; J.D., University of Virginia School of Law; B.A., Georgetown University. Prior to becoming a law professor, the author was a Visiting Scholar/Researcher at Harvard Law School and a member of the legal team for former Ohio State football player Maurice Clarett in his lawsuit against the National Football League and its age limit (Clarett v. Nat’l Football League, 369 F.3d 124 (2d Cir. 2004), cert. denied, 125 S. Ct. 1728 (Apr. 4, 2005)). The author wishes to thank Paul Weiler and Stephen Greyser for their insight and inspiration and Russell Korobkin, Jeffrey Rachlinski, Nancy Levit, Donald Langevoort, William Li, and Bryan Stroh for their thoughtful comments on an earlier draft. 1 In the extreme example, consider the ten-year, $252 million contract Alex Rodriguez signed with the Texas Rangers in 2002. $252 million represents eleven times the value of North Korea’s Gross Domestic Product. See John Blanchette, But It’s Baseball That Is the Real Loser in This Absurd Deal, SPOKESMAN REV., Dec. 12, 2000, at C1. 1459 1460 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 action that maximizes their wealth, happiness, or satisfaction.2 Since athletes are generally presumed to most value financial compensation, they simply behave “rationally” by selecting the most lucrative offer. Intriguingly, however, for every apparent athletic mercenary, there appear to be many who significantly discount financial compensation. Indeed, for a variety of expressed motivations, professional athletes regularly select the nonoptimal contract offer, at least in the traditional sense of optimality. Risk aversion and other deliberative strategies occasionally provide an explanation, but more often, the reason lies in intangibles, such as loyalty, regional affinity, weather preferences, familiarity with certain teammates or coaches, prospects for team success, and demographic traits. A law and economic explanation for such behavior would illuminate the ranking of alternative preferences, and then, as reflected by choice, a maximization of such ranking. Put differently, by accepting a less remunerative offer, professional athletes may consciously substitute subjective value for objective value, and their choice simply reflects that which makes them most happy. Though diagrammatic in many instances, preferences may not universally explain decision-making among professional athletes. Indeed, like all individuals, professional athletes appear vulnerable to cognitive biases, which are subconscious mental errors triggered by simplified informational processes, and heuristics, which are convenient, if unfinished predictive cues. Though cognitive biases and heuristics enable individuals to manage a complex array of stimuli, they often distort preferences and adversely affect decision-making. For instance, because of confirmation bias, individuals are subject to ignore or discount information that challenges existing beliefs. Alternatively, optimism bias leads individuals to assume that general risks do not apply with equal force to themselves. In the context of professional sports, these and other cognitive distortions may impair not only the pursuit of objective value, but also rational assessment of subjective value. This is especially true when teams adroitly manipulate distortions, such as impressing illusory variances among 2 See Peter A. Alces, “If You Don’t Have Anything Good to Say . . . .,” 15 BANKR. DEV. J. 383, 409, 411-12 (1999) (reviewing KAREN GROSS, FAILURE AND FORGIVENESS: REBALANCING THE BANKRUPTCY SYSTEM (1997)). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1461 themselves and other teams. Accordingly, when accepting a less remunerative offer, professional athletes may have unknowingly misinterpreted their preferences and rankings. To date, no published analysis has addressed the potential influence of behavioral tendencies on professional athletes in contemplation of contract offers. Perhaps this is not surprising, given the relative paucity of professional athletes among the general population, their presumptively unique modes of employment, and a general aversion among academics to the study of sports. A more scrupulous assessment of professional athletes, however, suggests a uniquely desirable group for examination. Indeed, aside from their striking influence on the world and economy around them, professional athletes, unlike most groups commonly studied by academics, furnish published commentary of their thought processes, typically through newspaper, television, and radio interviews. Accordingly, professional athletes offer a wealth of narration as to their values, beliefs, and priorities, and, equally important, such narration occurs in real world settings, rather than in experimental circumstances. Along those lines, by evading the alleged “experimental flaw” of many behavioral law and economic studies, analysis of decisionmaking among professional athletes may prove extraordinarily salient in the broader discussion of behavioral sciences and their influence on traditional law and economics. In pursuit of the above phenomena, this Article will begin by exploring the rational actor model and how individuals utilize preferences in determining their optimal choice. This Article will then discuss limitations to the rational actor model, namely the role of cognitive biases and heuristics. Thereafter, this Article will canvass decision-making among professional athletes in contemplation of contract offers. In that regard, this Article will examine why some professional athletes pursue the most lucrative offer, while others do not, and to what extent cognitive biases and heuristics influence their decision-making. This Article will conclude by highlighting implications for professional sports and proposing recommendations for further analysis by economists, psychologists, and legal academics. 1462 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW II. EXPLORING THE RATIONAL ACTOR MODEL IN BEHAVIORAL ECONOMICS A. Choice and Utility Among Rational Actors [Vol. 71:4 In assessing explanations for why individuals choose one option over another, many theories have emerged. In the context of economic activity, the rational choice theory has received particular praise for its alleged ability to predict human behavior.3 It posits that individuals are selfish actors who seek maximum utility, and when presented with a set of alternatives, select the alternative offering greatest utility.4 Utility may embody objective ends, such as material wealth or tangible property.5 It may also comprise subjective goals, such as happiness or satisfaction.6 Irrespective of its characteristics, utility is thought to demand a set of preferences that encourages a particular behavior, namely the satisfaction of utility-driven preferences in the most efficient manner.7 Put differently, “rationality” consists of pursuing preferences at minimal cost.8 While in search of maximum utility, rational actors are presumed to embody only “selfish” interests.9 Rational choice theorists contend that pursuit of selfish interests promotes cooperation with other persons. Such a contention is partly deduced from the scholarship of Robert Axelrod, who, in The 3 See, e.g., Mark R. Brown, Deterring Bully Government: A Sovereign Dilemma, 76 TUL. L. REV. 149, 160 n.59 (2001); Ronald A. Cass, Economics and International Law, 29 N.Y.U. J. INT’L L. & POL. 473, 509 n.114 (1997); Richard H. Pildes, The Destruction of Social Capital Through Law, 144 U. PA. L. REV. 2055, 2061 (1996). 4 See Alces, supra note 2, at 412. 5 See Alice G. Abreu, Taxes, Power, and Personal Autonomy, 33 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 1, 28 n.64 (1996) (noting that when economists refer to “maximizing utility,” they typically equate utility with material wealth). 6 See Jeanne L. Schroeder, The End of the Market: A Psychoanalysis of Law and Economics, 112 HARV. L. REV. 483, 513 n.103 (describing traditional law and economic metric of utility as a measure of happiness); see also Steven P. Croley & Jon D. Hanson, The Nonpecuniary Costs of Accidents: Pain-and-Suffering Damages in Tort Law, 108 HARV. L. REV. 1785, 1794-96 (1995) (discussing concept of satisfaction as an economic metric). 7 See W. Bradley Wendel, Mixed Signals: Rational-Choice Theories of Social Norms and the Pragmatics of Explanation, 77 IND. L.J. 1, 8 (2002). 8 See JON ELSTER, THE CEMENT OF SOCIETY: A STUDY OF SOCIAL ORDER 1112 (1989). 9 See Pamela H. Bucy, Games and Stories: Game Theory and the Civil False Claims Act, 31 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 603, 625 (2004); see also Neil S. Siegel, Sen and the Hart of Jurisprudence: A Critique of the Economic Analysis of Judicial Behavior, 87 CAL. L. REV. 1581, 1583-85 (1999) (discussing self-interest among legal actors). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1463 Evolution of Cooperation, concludes that humans interact optimally when their choices depend upon relative cooperativeness, patience, and egocentricity.10 Thus, rather than for the promotion of societal objectives, laws and normative aspirations are thought to emerge only to facilitate self-interested parties in achieving maximum utility.11 Naturally, a purely self-interested pursuit might render individuals predictable, since it would signal anticipated responses to incentives and other external influences.12 This is particularly true if, as rational choice theorists contend, preferences are “ranked, continuous, and stable.”13 Indeed, the presumption of stable preferences buttresses the very use and measurability of rational choice analysis; without such stability, it would be difficult, if not impossible, to determine whether a particular choice represents accordance with preferences, change in preferences, or simply disregard of preferences.14 A methodological preference among rational choice theorists for equating “utility” with monetary wealth signifies Such another component of rational choice analysis.15 preference enables legal economists to cultivate a more quantifiable framework,16 while also complying with traditional economic assessment of behavioral success by level of 10 See ROBERT AXELROD, THE EVOLUTION OF COOPERATION 31-33 (1984) (on file with author). 11 See Robert Sugden, Contractarianism and Norms, 100 ETHICS 768, 786 (1990); see also AXELROD, supra note 10, at 6-8 (examining role of aspirations in pursuit of utility). 12 See Jonathan R. Macey, Competing Economic Views of the Constitution, 56 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 50, 54 (1987). 13 Tanina Rostain, Educating Homo Economicus: Cautionary Notes on the New Behavioral Law and Economics Movement, 34 LAW & SOC’Y REV. 973, 976-77 (2000). Contra DONALD P. GREEN & IAN SHAPIRO, PATHOLOGIES OF RATIONAL CHOICE THEORY: A CRITIQUE OF APPLICATIONS IN POLITICAL SCIENCE 17-19 (1994) (finding that it may be impossible to determine whether a changed decision over time reflects a violation of the rationality criteria or a change in preferences). 14 See Rostain, supra note 13, at 977. 15 See Wendel, supra note 7, at 8 (noting that rational choice theory might be objectionable because of its overriding concern with wealth maximization); see also Russell B. Korobkin & Thomas S. Ulen, Law and Behavioral Science: Removing the Rationality Assumption from Law and Economics, 88 CAL. L. REV. 1051, 1066 (2000) (concluding that monetary accumulation is typically cited as the underlying motivation for rational actors). 16 Jon D. Hanson & Douglas A. Kysar, Taking Behavioralism Seriously: The Problem of Market Manipulation, 74 N.Y.U. L. REV. 630, 641 n.31 (1999) [hereinafter Hanson & Kysar, The Problem of Market Manipulation]. 1464 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 accumulated resources.17 It also, by implication, engenders a normative ethic whereby “it is normal—and hence appropriate—for people to pursue monetary wealth” and to measure the achievement of others by their extent of financial Put differently then, rational choice theorists wealth.18 generally assume that “rational actors will seek to gratify fundamental biological drives and, in a market economy, to accumulate monetary wealth.”19 Nevertheless, “utility” need not equate to monetary wealth in order to accommodate rational choice analysis. Indeed, though less preferred for purposes of rational choice analysis, individuals may place material value in measurable, but non-monetary forms of “wealth,” such as proximity to family or professional title.20 Similarly, individuals may value intangible wealth, such as perceived prestige or sense of fairness,21 and yet still engage in rational analysis.22 In other words, rational decision-making need not comprise the pursuit of maximum monetary wealth, but only that personal preferences are discernibly ranked and pursued accordingly.23 B. Application of Rational Choice Theory to Behavioral Relationships Legal scholars have applied rational choice theory to human behavior in specific and relatively familiar settings. 17 See David R. Lagasse, Undue Influence: Corporate Political Speech, Power and the Initiative Process, 61 BROOK. L. REV. 1347, 1370 (1995) (explaining traditional economic reliance on monetary gains and losses when evaluating micro-economic behavior). 18 Avery Wiener Katz, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Economics, 94 MICH. L. REV. 2229, 2243 (1996). 19 Mark C. Suchman, On Beyond Interest: Rational, Normative and Cognitive Perspectives in the Social Scientific Study of Law, 1997 WIS. L. REV. 475, 478. 20 See, e.g., Russell Korobkin, Ranking Journals: Some Thoughts on Theory and Methodology, 26 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 851, 860-62 (1999) (noting that, because student-run law reviews often select submissions in part based on the affiliation of the author, law professors consider reputation of their affiliated school when choosing between teaching offers). 21 See Daniel A. Farber, Toward a New Legal Realism, 68 U. CHI. L. REV. 279, 280 (2001) (reviewing BEHAVIORAL LAW AND ECONOMICS (Cass R. Sunstein ed., 2000)). 22 Existence of these phenomena is manipulated by related actors, such as employers, who “value prestige as an independent good because it closely relates to individual self-esteem and employee morale.” Andrew Cowan, Scarlet Letters for Corporations? Punishment by Publicity Under the New Sentencing Guidelines, 65 S. CAL. L. REV. 2387, 2401 (1992). 23 See, e.g., Russell Korobkin, Aspirations and Settlement, 88 CORNELL L. REV. 1, 7-10 (2002) [hereinafter Korobkin, Aspirations and Settlement]. 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1465 Perhaps best illustrating this scholarship is an analysis of litigants and their relative assessment of settlement and litigation.24 Litigants are said to value rational “aspirations,” which pertain to an “ideal target settlement sum, or set of terms,” and that guide litigants in negotiations.25 Conversely, a litigant’s “reservation price” comprises the least optimal value nevertheless sufficient for settlement. For plaintiffs, the reservation price dictates the minimum amount worth accepting, while for defendants, it refers to the maximum The area between these two amount worth paying.26 reservation prices comprises the “bargaining zone,” and when the two parties fail to identify a figure within that zone, adjudication results.27 Accordingly, rational choice theory regards the achievement of settlement as entirely dependent upon agreement to share wealth, thereby rendering immaterial “blame” or feelings of “revenge” and “justice.”28 In essence, then, bargaining between litigants resembles any other form of bargaining between rational actors, and it is thus fundamentally indistinguishable from a manufacturer and supplier negotiating a sales contract or a sports team and player negotiating an employment contract. Of course, this rational approach to civil litigation depends upon the ability of litigants to identify their bargaining zone. Indeed, rational choice theory surmises that litigants can determine the expected value of litigating, as well as the difference in transaction costs between out-of-court settlement and litigating.29 More concretely, as posited by rational choice theory, litigants equate the expected value of each prospective strategy to the probability of that strategy’s 24 Id. at 6 (describing the significance of rational choice theory in litigant behavioral assumptions). 25 Id. at 3. 26 HOWARD RAIFFA, THE ART AND SCIENCE OF NEGOTIATION 45 (1982); G. RICHARD SHELL, BARGAINING FOR ADVANTAGE: NEGOTIATION STRATEGIES FOR REASONABLE PEOPLE 27 (1999) (on file with author). 27 See John P. Gould, The Economics of Legal Conflicts, 2 J. LEGAL STUD. 279, 285 (1973); see also Steven Shavell, Alternative Dispute Resolution: An Economic Analysis, 24 J. LEGAL STUD. 1, 11 (1995) (identifying that parties will not settle when expected judgments exceed their expected costs). 28 See George L. Priest & Benjamin Klein, The Selection of Disputes for Litigation, 13 J. LEGAL STUD. 1, 12-13 (1984); see also Robert G. Bone, Agreeing to Fair Process: The Problem with Contractarian Theories of Procedural Fairness, 83 B.U. L. REV. 485, 520 (2003) (noting that scholars sometimes view settlement as “just a type of ex ante agreement, one that is ex ante relative to the final judgment”). 29 Priest & Klein, supra note 28, at 12. 1466 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 success multiplied by its predictive monetary value.30 For instance, a litigant might conclude that expending extraordinary resources on discovery would increase the chance of victory, and that the value generated from that option would exceed the value generated by expending fewer resources on discovery but with diminished probability of victory.31 In determining their bargaining zone, litigants—and their attorneys—must also account for rational choice decisionmaking among judges. Indeed, rational choice theorists surmise that trial judges consider the probability of reversal whenever ranking their preferences for case disposition.32 Thus, in its application to litigant behavior, rational choice theory demands expansive knowledge from litigants in order to devise informed preferences.33 Although application of rational choice theory most often concerns the pursuit of monetary wealth, “utility,” as noted in the preceding subsection, need not equate to monetary wealth.34 Indeed, individuals might place material value in measurable, but non-monetary characteristics, or intangible characteristics.35 Accordingly, rational decision-makers may rank preferences in line with non-monetary objectives, thus generating choices that optimally reflect those non-monetary preferences. To illustrate these “other” forms of utility, consider application of rational choice theory to decision-making among public actors. For instance, rational choice theory assumes 30 See generally ROBERT G. BONE, CIVIL PROCEDURE: THE ECONOMICS OF CIVIL PROCEDURE 20-40 (2003) (explaining how parties can use high discovery strategically to force settlements). Thus, in practice, both litigants will value litigation based on the weighted average value of all potential outcomes. See Korobkin, Aspirations and Settlement, supra note 23, at 7 (analyzing conclusions of Priest & Klein, supra note 28, at 29-30). 31 See David Rosenberg, Mass Tort Class Actions: What Defendants Have and Plaintiffs Don’t, 37 HARV. J. ON LEGIS. 393, 407 n.35 (2000) (discussing “real world assumptions” about the relationship between investment in discovery and probability of success in litigation); see also ROBERT COOTER & THOMAS ULEN, LAW AND ECONOMICS 55-70 (1988) (discussing the theory of rational choice and expected monetary value); Shavell, supra note 27, at 11 (illuminating predictive roles of cost and benefit expectations among plaintiffs and defendants). 32 See Frank B. Cross, Decisionmaking in the U.S. Circuit Courts of Appeals, 91 CAL. L. REV. 1457, 1483 (2003). The idea of “rational” decision-making by judges has received substantial critique in recent years. See generally Siegel, supra note 9 (arguing that economic models fail to provide an accurate explanation of judicial decision-making). 33 See Korobkin, Aspirations and Settlement, supra note 23, at 7-9. 34 See discussion supra p. 1464. 35 See id. 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1467 that elected officials and, more broadly, those drawn to politics, place greatest value in amassing power.36 Consequently, political actors appear less interested in monetary wealth than is traditionally assumed by rational choice theory.37 Similar deductions have been made of government attorneys, whose primary self-interest, be it apparent power or civic duty, appears distinct from that of attorneys engaged in private practice.38 The utility of these concepts can be further illustrated by observing the American workforce and opportunities for employment change. Indeed, studies find that when workers anticipate an increase in either respect for their labor or positive feelings of camaraderie, they tend to evince diminished demand for tangible compensation.39 Alternatively constructed, by merely accepting an offer that features less monetary compensation than another offer, an individual implicitly posits a higher actual value from the chosen offer.40 This phenomenon is sometimes apparent when law firm partners have opportunities to become judges or law professors. Although such positions typically pay less in terms of monetary compensation, their relatively high prestige and potential for 36 James R. Buckley, The Political Economy of Superfund Implementation, 59 S. CAL. L. REV. 875, 889 (1986) (concluding that “maximum wealth” for political actors includes power and job security). 37 Less admirably, rational choice theory also assumes that those drawn to politics are more interested in power than constituent representation or society’s best interests. See MORRIS P. FIORINA, CONGRESS: KEYSTONE OF THE WASHINGTON ESTABLISHMENT (1977). But see Daniel Shaviro, Beyond Public Choice and Public Interest: A Study of the Legislative Process as Illustrated by Tax Legislation in the 1980s, 139 U. PA. L. REV. 1, 66 & n.303 (dismissing analysis that concludes that politicians are “for sale” as inconsistent with the history of tax law promulgation). 38 See Edward Brunet, Class Action Objectors: Extortionist Free Riders or Fairness Guarantors, 2003 U. CHI. LEGAL F. 403, 454-56 (describing unique incentives and motivations of government attorneys); see also Jonathan R. Macey & Geoffrey P. Miller, Reflections on Professional Responsibility in a Regulatory State, 63 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 1105, 1115-18 (1995) (reasoning that, due to an absence of private market constraints, government attorneys are more likely to pursue self-interests than are those attorneys engaged in private practice). 39 Katherine K. Yunker, Addressing the Real Problems for Law and Economics of Factoring Interest Rates, Earnings Growth and Inflation into Awards for Lost Future Earnings, 56 U. PITT. L. REV. 1, 23 n.57 (1994). 40 See Saul Levmore, Self-Assessed Valuation Systems for Tort and Other Law, 68 VA. L. REV. 771, 802 (1982) (“By accepting a low paying job in lieu of a higher paying one, an individual demonstrates that the total returns from the chosen position—monetary and nonmonetary—are valued more than those from the job not taken.”). But see discussion of cognitive biases infra Part III.A. 1468 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 intellectual flexibility often induce law firm partners into concluding that they are superior positions.41 Neoclassical theory offers a useful corollary to employment opportunities in rational choice models. It suggests that workers select employment opportunities that offer “preference-maximizing packages” of compensation, working conditions, and subjective characteristics.42 Similarly, neoclassical theory finds that individuals order their preferences depending upon value assessed to each preference.43 To illustrate, consider that when workers may determine their own hours of work before a change in wage rates, they often adjust their work hours to reflect their preferences for work and leisure.44 Accordingly, neoclassical theory reaffirms predictive characteristics apparent in the application of rational choice theory. III. RETHINKING RATIONAL CHOICE DECISION-MAKING A. Raising Doubts: Cognitive Biases Superficially, rational choice theory furnishes a useful tool for assessing why individuals make certain decisions. Upon further reflection, however, it appears limited by cognitive biases, which are subconscious mental processes that impair rational thought-processes and ultimately lead to “irrational” choices. Such biases are prevalent among all 41 See Sidney A. Shapiro & Richard E. Levy, Judicial Incentives and Indeterminacy in Substantive Review of Administrative Decisions, 44 DUKE L.J. 1051, 1055 (1995) (noting that attorneys are often attracted to the position of judge because of its prestige and esteem); see also Kenneth F. Ripple, The Role of the Law Review in the Tradition of Judicial Scholarship, 57 N.Y.U. ANN. SURV. AM. L. 429, 434 (2000) (citing remarks by Justice Cardozo concerning the gradual rise in prestige of law professors in the legal world). But see Richard A. Posner, Florida 2000: A Legal and Statistical Analysis of the Election Deadlock and the Ensuing Litigation, 2000 SUP. CT. REV. 1, 54 (wondering whether judges “exaggerate the value of their prestige to society”). Some positions, of course, offer both maximum prestige and financial recompense. See A. Mechele Dickerson, A Behavioral Approach to Analyzing Corporate Failures, 38 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 1, 23 (2003) (noting that corporate directors often cite prestige and status associated with their occupation as meaningful). 42 Mark Barenberg, Democracy and Domination in the Law of Workplace Cooperation: From Bureaucratic to Flexible Production, 94 COLUM. L. REV. 753, 828 (1994). 43 See Ignacio de León, A Neo-Institutional Analysis of Vertical Integration and Its Implications for Antitrust Enforcement in Developing Countries, 26 BROOK. J. INT’L L. 251, 282 (2000). 44 Philip Harvey, Combating Joblessness: An Analysis of the Principal Strategies that Have Influenced the Development of American Employment and Social Welfare Law During the 20th Century, 21 BERKELEY J. EMP. & LAB. L. 677, 721 (2000). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1469 persons, and by simplifying the processing of information, often induce mental errors in deliberation of choice.45 To illustrate cognitive biases, consider that when individuals contemplate choice, many unknowingly distort the degree of risk or only selectively remember pertinent information.46 Furthermore, cognitive biases are distinct from other forms of biases (e.g., self-interest; ethnic or gender prejudice), as well as intellectual predispositions toward certain conclusions (e.g., conclusory analysis). Instead, they reflect subliminal mental procedures for processing information. Since 1955, the role of cognitive biases in decisionmaking processes has intrigued behavioral psychologists. In that year, Herbert Simon published A Behavioral Model of Rational Choice, which proposed “replac[ing] the global rationality of economic man with a” model inclusive of “the computational capacities that are actually possessed by organisms, including man, in the kinds of environments in which such organisms exist.”47 Since that time, economists, legal scholars, and psychologists have evaluated the desirability of utilizing cognitive bias analysis in adjusting expectations for human behavior. Such analysis has proven useful beyond the academic setting as well. For instance, businesses routinely adjust marketing and client practices to accommodate for cognitive biases among customers and Likewise, policy analysts often qualify consumers.48 recommendations to account for potential biases among affected groups.49 45 See generally RICHARDS J. HEUER, JR., PSYCHOLOGY OF INTELLIGENCE ANALYSIS (1999) (observing effects of cognitive biases on decision-makers); Christine Jolls et al., A Behavioral Approach to Law and Economics, 50 STAN. L. REV. 1471 (1998). 46 See generally Michelle G. Craske & Deborah C. Pontillo, Cognitive Biases in Anxiety Disorders and Their Effect on Cognitive-Behavioral Treatment, 65 BULL. MENNINGER CLINIC 58 (2001). 47 See Herbert A. Simon, A Behavioral Model of Rational Choice, 69 Q. J. ECON. 99, 99 (1955). 48 See, e.g., MARKET PSYCHOL. CONSULTING, Money and Investing Personality Test, http://www.marketpsych.com/simulations.php (last visited Jan. 4, 2006) (detailing how cognitive biases elicited from client bases can be exploited to generate profits). 49 See, e.g., Josh Kerbel (analyst in the Strategic Assessments Group in the Directorate of Intelligence), Thinking Straight: Cognitive Bias in the U.S. Debate About China, 48 STUD. IN INTELLIGENCE 1 (official journal of the Central Intelligence Agency) (2004), available at http://www.cia.gov/csi/studies/vol48no3/article03.html (discussing role of cognitive biases in American perceptions of policy choices by China). 1470 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Numerous studies have illustrated the role of cognitive biases in decision-making processes. Perhaps most heralded, consider the role of “framing effects” in shaping choice, and how they diminish assumed rationality among actors. The most notable such study was conducted by Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky in 1984. It revealed how individuals respond varyingly to two identical outcomes worded slightly Specifically, the authors found that when differently.50 individuals are presented with a hypothetical choice on how to dispense finite medical care to 600 persons afflicted with a fatal disease, with one choice resulting in 200 people being saved, and the other resulting in 400 people dying, they are less likely to endorse a policy where “400 people will die” than one where “200 people will be saved.”51 Such a conclusion contradicts the rational choice model, since a rational actor would make the same choice regardless of its description.52 Framing effects of these kinds have been found in other settings as well, and they diminish the certainty of rational choice predictions.53 Along those lines, framing effects belie the rational choice assumption that choices reflect a maximization of utility or relative strength of preferences, as such choices instead appear modifiable by unappreciated factors, such as wording of questions and other circumstances.54 Similarly, consider the effect of confirmation bias, whereby individuals are subject to ignore or discount information that challenges existing beliefs.55 Confirmation bias is especially prevalent among those who are overconfident, 50 See Daniel Kahneman & Amos Tversky, Choices, Values, and Frames, 39 AM. PSYCHOLOGIST 341, 343 (1984). 51 Id. 52 See David A. Hoffman & Michael P. O’Shea, Can Law and Economics Be Both Practical and Principled?, 53 ALA. L. REV. 335, 361 (2002) (describing how rational actor theory presumes that individuals rank outcomes with identical outcomes as equal, and thus would not prefer one option over the other). 53 See Hanson & Kysar, The Problem of Market Manipulation, supra note 16, at 644-46 (discussing use of framing effects by exploitative industry actors). 54 See Hoffman & O’Shea, supra note 52, at 361. 55 See Hanson & Kysar, The Problem of Market Manipulation, supra note 16, at 647-50. A corollary to confirmation bias is “self-serving” or “egocentric” biases, whereby individuals “interpret information in a way that disproportionately favors their own position.” Unlike confirmation bias, however, self-serving or egocentric biases are likely consciously present. Chris Guthrie, Framing Frivolous Litigation: A Psychological Theory, 67 U. CHI. L. REV. 163, 206 n.199 (2000) [hereinafter Guthrie, Framing Frivolous Litigation] (noting that these biases may increase plaintiffs’ risk in seeking frivolous litigation). See generally Linda Babcock & George Loewenstein, Explaining Bargaining Impasse: The Role of Self-Serving Biases, 11 J. ECON. PERSP. 109 (1997) (discussing the impact of self-serving biases on settlements). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1471 and it frequently leads to “irrational” decision-making.56 For instance, when business or policy managers discuss strategic planning, they often avoid consideration of worst-case scenarios, as well as refrain from consulting with “Devil’s advocates” among their group of advisors.57 Confirmation bias also affects how employers regard individual employees. Indeed, as soon as a manager develops reservations about an employee’s competence, the manager often becomes prone to negatively interpret confusing or ambiguous circumstances concerning that employee, while attributing positives circumstances to luck, coincidence, or someone else’s Also consider confirmation bias in the law assistance.58 enforcement setting: When police investigators believe they have identified the guilty party within a police lineup, they tend to ask eyewitnesses specifically about that person while not asking those same questions about others in the lineup.59 Optimism bias has likewise received scholarly attention as disturbing traditional assumptions among rational choice theorists. The concept posits that individuals assume that general risks “do not apply with equal force to themselves.”60 Put differently, optimism bias is “the belief that good things are more likely than average to happen to us and bad things 56 See John Kelly, Putting Investors on the Couch; With Equity Prices Having Fallen, Now Would Be a Good Time for Investors to Reappraise Their Portfolios, but Why Are So Few Actually Doing So?, INVESTMENT ADVISER, Mar. 24, 2003, available at www.lexis.com (search “News, All (English, Full Text)” for full title in quotes) (noting need for investment advisors to counter confirmation biases particularly among those overconfident investors). 57 See Lynne L. Dallas, The New Managerialism and Diversity on Corporate Boards of Directors, 76 TUL. L. REV. 1363, 1394 n.146 (2002). 58 Jean-Louis Barsoux & Jean-Francois Manzoni, The Downward Spiral, FIN. TIMES, Nov. 15, 2002, at 6. 59 See Gary L. Wells & Eric P. Seelau, Eyewitness Identification: Psychological Research and Legal Policy on Lineups, 1 PSYCHOL. PUB. POL’Y & L. 765, 767 (1995). Academic studies present another area where confirmation biases often emerge, as researchers tend to discount conflicting data discovered after conclusions have been made. See Richard E. Petty & John T. Cacioppo, Addressing Disturbing and Disturbed Consumer Behavior: Is It Necessary to Change the Way We Conduct Behavioral Science?, 33 J. MKTG. RES. 1, 5 (1996); see also Hans Baumgartner, On the Utility of Consumers’ Theories in Judgments of Covariation, 21 J. CONSUMER RES. 634, 638 (1995) (discussing existence of confirmation bias during process of data sampling by academic researchers). 60 Jon D. Hanson & Douglas A. Kysar, Taking Behavioralism Seriously: Some Evidence of Market Manipulation, 112 HARV. L. REV. 1420, 1511 (1999) [hereinafter Hanson & Kysar, Some Evidence of Market Manipulation]; see Melvin Aron Eisenberg, The Limits of Cognition and the Limits of Contract, 47 STAN. L. REV. 211, 216 (1995) (finding that “as a systematic matter, people are unrealistically optimistic”). 1472 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Most are less likely than average to happen to us.”61 illustratively, because of optimism bias, the average American estimates a one in five chance of personally being the victim of a non-terrorist violent crime, yet believes that the average American has about a two in five chance of being one.62 Alternatively, consider that smokers are inclined to perceive smoking as significantly less risky for themselves than for other smokers.63 Indeed, optimism bias tends to flourish when risks are long-term, or are presumed modifiable through behavior.64 For that reason, when consumers assume that signs of toxicity will appear early in product usage, they tend to then assume that an absence of such signs foretells exemption from future risk.65 Individuals are also distracted by irrelevant third options when making decisions. These options most often emerge in the consumer context. For instance, automobile manufacturers routinely make a particular model “appear less expensive by adding a higher-priced option to the product line.”66 Similarly, manufacturers of “risky” products, such as unfiltered cigarettes or untested dietary supplements, tend to 61 Korobkin & Ulen, supra note 15, at 1091. See Neal R. Feigenson, Emotions, Risk Perceptions and Blaming in 9/11 Cases, 68 BROOK. L. REV. 959, 981 n.82 (2003) (citing Jennifer S. Lerner et al., Effects of Fear and Anger on Perceived Risks of Terrorism: A National Field Experiment, 14 PSYCHOL. SCI. 144, 149 (2003), available at http://www.hss.cmu.edu/ departments/sds/faculty/Lerner/EffectsOfFearAndAngerOnPerc.pdf. 63 See William B. Hansen & C. Kevin Malotte, Perceived Personal Immunity: The Development of Beliefs About Susceptibility to the Consequences of Smoking, 15 PREVENTIVE MED. 363, 370-71 (1986); see also Suzanne C. Segerstrom et al., Optimistic Bias Among Cigarette Smokers, 23 J. APPLIED SOC. PSYCHOL. 1606, 1614-17 (1993). But see W. Kip Viscusi, Constructive Cigarette Regulation, 47 DUKE L.J. 1095, 1113-14 (1998) (presenting evidence that optimism bias is unsupported in the context of cigarette smoking, as “research on adolescents fails to indicate any significant difference between risks to oneself and one’s peers”). 64 See Hanson & Kysar, The Problem of Market Manipulation, supra note 16, at 657 & nn.106-09; see also Neil D. Weinstein, Unrealistic Optimism About Future Life Events, 39 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 806, 806 (1980) (presenting evidence that individuals ascribe to “unrealistic optimism”). 65 Paul Slovic, Do Adolescent Smokers Know the Risks?, 47 DUKE L.J. 1133, 1137 (1998). Along those lines, optimism bias may prove most pronounced among children smokers, who often rate their own chances of contracting lung disease as nearly identical to those of non-smokers. See Jonathan D. Reppucci et al., Unrealistic Optimism Among Adolescent Smokers and Nonsmokers, 11 J. PRIMARY PREVENTION 227, 235 (1991); see also Michael A. McCann, Dietary Supplement Labeling: Cognitive Biases, Market Manipulation & Consumer Choice, 31 AM. J.L. & MED. 215, 223-27 (2005) [hereinafter McCann, Dietary Supplement Labeling] (discussing optimism bias among consumers of dietary supplements and how supplement manufacturers may exploit such a bias). 66 Hanson & Kysar, Some Evidence of Market Manipulation, supra note 60, at 1440 (discussing irrelevant third options in context of used car sales). 62 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1473 adroitly frame the choice between something dangerous (e.g., regular cigarettes; supplements containing ephedra), something much less risky (e.g., “unfiltered cigarettes”; “ephedra-free supplements”), and no action at all. In doing so, they encourage continued usage from would-be quitters, as the individual becomes biased in favor of options that he originally disfavored.67 Also consider the salience of irrelevant third options in disturbing the presumed stability of ranked preferences within the rational actor model. For instance, when an individual is presented with a small or large box of popcorn, she might choose the small. That same consumer, however, would more likely choose the large box when also presented with the option of an extra large box.68 As noted by Richard Thaler, if actors were entirely rational in their deliberation of choice, and thus possessed stable options, then the presence of an extraneous choice, like an extra large box, would not affect the choice between a small and large box.69 Yet it does.70 Informational deficiencies and time constraints likewise inhibit strategic and rational decision-making, and they encourage individuals to make inferences from small sample sizes. For instance, law enforcement officers, who are uniquely taxed for time and expected to promptly solve cases, regularly make conclusive judgments of guilt on the basis of only one or two witness interviews.71 Similarly, consider trial judges, who, in contemplating judgment, often consider the probability of Rational actor analysis maintains that such appeal.72 consideration should compel judges to rank potential outcomes (e.g., appellate reversal; appellate remand) associated with 67 Id. at 1515 (discussing irrelevant third options in context of cigarettes); see also McCann, Dietary Supplement Labeling, supra note 65, at 224 & 226 (discussing irrelevant third options in the context of dietary supplements). 68 Daniel T. Ostas, Deconstructing Corporate Social Responsibility: Insights from Legal and Economic Theory, 38 AM. BUS. L.J. 261, 294 (2001). 69 See generally RICHARD H. THALER, QUASI RATIONAL ECONOMICS 42 (1991). 70 Ostas, supra note 68, at 294. See Roger Mason, Interpersonal Effects on Consumer Demand in Economic Theory and Marketing Thought, 1890-1950, 25 J. ECON. ISSUES 871 (1995) (finding that marketing schemes often construct, rather than react to consumer interests). 71 See Wells & Seelau, supra note 59, at 767 (explaining how law enforcement officers tend to make “strong judgments of validity on the basis of only one eyewitness”); see also Robert A. Prentice, Chicago Man, K-T Man, and the Future of Behavioral Law and Economics, 56 VAND. L. REV. 1663, 1709-10 (2003) (assessing cognitive biases experienced by witnesses while being interviewed by police). 72 See discussion supra p. 1465 and accompanying notes. 1474 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 possible trial choices (e.g., motion denied; motion sustained).73 Trial judges, however, often encounter time constraints, heavy workloads, and uncertain information that may impair any strategic value in pursuing these preferences.74 Legal scholars have observed that in order for judges to accurately discount the corresponding probability of reversal for each preference, they would have to possess information concerning the probability of appeal and settlement, as well as knowledge of precise preferences embraced by the relevant appellant judges.75 Thus, in the absence of such information, “rational” decision-making appears more like guesswork and conjecture. Cognitive biases may also affect retrospective assessment of choice. This is especially apparent with hindsight bias, which refers to the tendency of individuals to overestimate the extent to which they anticipated the fruition of a particular event.76 Put differently, individuals often believe that they knew something was going to happen when in fact they did not.77 This phenomenon is especially apparent when interviewing those prior and after a particular event. For instance, when voters are asked to project the outcome of an imminent election, and are later asked to remember their choice, far more claim to have predicted the correct outcome than actually did.78 Similarly, when individuals are asked to 73 See Christopher R. Drahozal, Judicial Incentives and the Appeals Process, 51 SMU L. REV. 469, 492 (1998). 74 Cross, supra note 32, at 1485; see also Susan P. Koniak & George M. Cohen, Under Cloak of Settlement, 82 VA. L. REV. 1051, 1124-25 (1996) (describing indifference of the public and politicians to insistence by trial judges of onerous workloads and corresponding diminution of quality of judging); Jeffrey A. Parness & Matthew R. Walker, Thinking Outside the Civil Case Box: Reformulating Pretrial Conference Laws, 50 U. KAN. L. REV. 347, 363 (2002) (identifying time pressures as observed by Judge Richard Posner). 75 See, e.g., Richard L. Revesz, Environmental Regulation, Ideology, and the D.C. Circuit, 83 VA. L. REV. 1717, 1767-68 n.103 (1997) (describing immense complexity of predicting reversals on statutory grounds); see also DAVID E. KLEIN, MAKING LAW IN THE UNITED STATES COURTS OF APPEALS 14 (2002) (illuminating obstacles for trial judges attempting to forecast probability of appeal success). 76 See W. Kip Viscusi, The Social Costs of Punitive Damages Against Corporations in Environmental and Safety Torts, 87 GEO. L.J. 285, 328-29 (1998). 77 See, e.g., Scott A. Hawkins & Reid Hastie, Hindsight: Biased Judgments of Past Events After the Outcomes Are Known, 107 PSYCHOL. BULL. 311, 311-12 (1990); Baruch Fischhoff, Hindsight ≠ Foresight: The Effect of Outcome Knowledge on Judgment Under Uncertainty, 1 J. EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOL. HUM. PERCEPTION & PERFORMANCE 288, 288 (1975) (first describing the effect). 78 Jeffrey J. Rachlinski, A Positive Psychological Theory of Judging in Hindsight, 65 U. CHI. L. REV. 571, 577 (1998). Similar findings have pertained to subjects who are asked to predict whether a business would be successful, with subjects claiming “I predicted it” at a higher rate than actually did. Clifton E. Brown & Ira 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1475 predict whether a particular line of products will succeed, an artificially high percentage will later claim to have identified the correct outcome.79 Significantly, by distorting individuals’ capacity to objectively evaluate their decision-making and pursuit of preferences, hindsight bias limits the potential for ameliorative redress of any other cognitive biases. Regret aversion, or the tendency to avoid feedback on forgone conclusions, only exacerbates hindsight bias.80 Such aversion encourages individuals to shield themselves from discovering “what might have been” had they pursued alternative choices.81 Individuals experiencing regret aversion are similarly averse to comparisons with imagined outcomes, which may likewise promote sadness or regret.82 Accordingly, both hindsight bias and regret aversion discourage retrospective analysis of decision-making. Empirical data corroborates this idea. Indeed, regret aversion has been found to influence consumer purchase decisions,83 investor preferences,84 physician choice of care,85 and, most recently, litigant behavior.86 Importantly, in light of the aforementioned cognitive biases, ostensibly objective measures, such as “market value” and “fair compensation,” may reflect irrational cognitive biases Solomon, Effects of Outcome Information on Evaluations of Managerial Decisions, 62 ACCT. REV. 564, 568-75 (1987). 79 Brown & Solomon, supra note 78, at 570-73. 80 See Chris Guthrie, Better Settle Than Sorry: The Regret Aversion Theory of Litigation Behavior, 1999 U. ILL. L. REV. 43, 43 [hereinafter Guthrie, Better Settle Than Sorry]. 81 See David S. Boninger, Faith Gleicher & Alan Strathman, Counterfactual Thinking: From What Might Have Been to What May Be, 67 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 297, 297 (1994); see also Richard P. Larrick, Motivational Factors in Decision Theories: The Role of Self-Protection, 113 PSYCHOL. BULL. 440, 445 (1993) (describing behavioral predilections commonly associated with avoidance of risk). 82 See Guthrie, Better Settle Than Sorry, supra note 80, at 69-70 & n.133 (citing conclusions in Marcel Zeelenberg et al., Consequences of Regret Aversion: Effects of Expected Feedback on Risky Decision Making, 65 ORGANIZATIONAL BEHAV. & HUM. DECISION PROCESSES 148, 149 (1996)). 83 J. Jeffrey Inman & Leigh McAlister, Do Coupon Expiration Dates Affect Consumer Behavior?, 31 J. MARKETING RES. 423, 423 (1994) (reasoning that anticipated regret may account for the increase in consumer coupon redemption behavior prior to coupon expiration dates). 84 Donald C. Langevoort, Selling Hope, Selling Risk: Some Lessons for Law from Behavioral Economics About Stockbrokers and Sophisticated Customers, 84 CAL. L. REV. 627, 652-53 (1996). 85 See Cheryl B. Travis et al., Judgment Heuristics and Medical Decisions, 13 PATIENT EDUC. & COUNSELING 211, 215 (1989) (proposing regret theory as one possible explanation for clinical treatment decisions). 86 Guthrie, Better Settle Than Sorry, supra note 80, at 72-79. 1476 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 as much as any rational bargaining. As a result, individual preferences may only partially account for market determinations, such as the “going-rate” for a particular type of worker (e.g., a talented chief executive officer; a 20-game winner in Major League Baseball).87 Indeed, for that very reason, Cass Sunstein maintains that rational choice models are “often wrong in the simple sense that they yield inaccurate predictions.”88 Similarly, Russell Korobkin and Thomas Ulen find that “individuals are systematically biased in their predictions of the probable results of various events89 . . . they frequently act in ways that are incompatible with the assumptions of rational choice theory.”90 B. Raising Doubts: Heuristics The failure of rational choice theory to absorb cognitive biases invites discussion of further cognitive limitations, namely human tendencies to incorporate rules of thumb into their decision-making processes. These “rules of thumb” are also known as heuristic devices or heuristics, which are convenient, if unfinished methods to process information.91 Such devices emerge primarily because of processing devices within the human brain that seek to conserve scarce resources.92 These devices allow the brain to manage a complex array of stimuli through shortcuts, largely based on predictive probability.93 Heuristics, however, exhibit a tendency to encourage decisions based on illusions, or distorted perceptions.94 For instance, heuristics may lead individuals to exaggerate health 87 Hoffman & O’Shea, supra note 52, at 361. Cass R. Sunstein, Behavioral Analysis of Law, 64 U. CHI. L. REV. 1175, 1175 (1997). 89 Korobkin & Ulen, supra note 15, at 1085. 90 Id. at 1055. 91 See Cass R. Sunstein, Introduction, in BEHAVIORAL LAW AND ECONOMICS 1, 3 (Cass R. Sunstein ed., 2000). 92 Jon Hanson & David Yosifon, The Situation: An Introduction to the Situational Character, Critical Realism, Power Economics, and Deep Capture, 152 U. PA. L. REV. 129, 137 (2003). 93 Jeffrey J. Rachlinski, Heuristics and Biases in the Courts: Ignorance or Adaptation?, 79 OR. L. REV. 61, 61 (2000). See Samuel Issacharoff, The Content of Our Casebooks: Why Do Cases Get Litigated?, 29 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 1265, 1275 (2002) (describing these phenomena in choices among individuals to seek litigation). 94 Rachlinski, supra note 93, at 61. 88 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1477 ailments,95 particularly when those individuals are unable to measure the presence of actual risk.96 Moreover, the human mind tends to minimize the role of complexifying context (e.g., background factors; situational pressures) and accentuate the role of salient behavior (e.g., expressed words; physical For that reason, individuals tend to manifestations).97 attribute another person’s behavior to her own dispositional qualities, rather than to circumstances or situational factors.98 The attribution of behavior to disposition rather than circumstances is considered part of a broader defect called the “fundamental attribution error,” and heuristics can evince its effect.99 Heuristics can also adversely influence negotiations. This is especially apparent with “anchoring and adjustment” effects, whereby a negotiator begins with a presumptively rational reference point, but then fails to adjust adequately for new information.100 Psychologists sometimes describe this effect as “belief perseverance,” or the tendency to cling to a viewpoint in the face of disconfirming evidence.101 For instance, a professional athlete negotiating a contract might estimate his market value based on a contract earned by a similar player.102 He might then adjust that figure based on perceived variances between himself and the similar player, such as age, experience, and injury-history.103 Although such an approach 95 See Robert A. McNutt et al., Patient Safety Efforts Should Focus on Medical Errors, 287 J. AM. MED. ASS’N 1997, 2001 (2002); see also Stephen B. Soumerai et al., Effect of Local Medical Opinion Leaders on Quality of Care for Acute Myocardial Infarction: A Randomized Controlled Trial, 279 J. AM. MED. ASS’N 1358, 1363 (1998) (discussing the salience of heuristics in the context of acute myocardial infarctions). 96 See Sidney T. Bogardus, Jr., Eric Holmboe & James F. Jekel, Perils, Pitfalls, and Possibilities in Talking About Medical Risk, 281 J. AM. MED. ASS’N 1037, 1041 (1999) (noting that people frequently utilize heuristic guides to counter difficulties in understanding risk). 97 See Hanson & Yosifon, supra note 92, at 137. 98 See SUSAN T. FISKE & SHELLEY E. TAYLOR, SOCIAL COGNITION 67-86 (2d ed. 1991). 99 For an extensive analysis of the fundamental attribution error, see Jon Hanson & David Yosifon, The Situational Character: A Critical Realist Perspective on the Human Animal, 93 GEO. L.J. 1 (2004). 100 Amos Tversky & Daniel Kahneman, Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, 185 SCIENCE 1124, 1128 (1974). 101 See Hanson & Kysar, The Problem of Market Manipulation, supra note 16, at 652-53. 102 See Donald Fehr, Union Views Concerning Agents: With Commentary on the Present Situation in Major League Baseball, 4 MARQ. SPORTS L.J. 71, 79 (1993). 103 See Michael A. McCann, Illegal Defense: The Irrational Economics of Banning High School Players from the NBA Draft, 3 VA. SPORTS & ENT. L.J. 113, 169- 1478 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 might appear sensible, studies find that individuals often fail to adjust sufficiently away from the initial anchor.104 Indeed, even in the absence of anchor-affirming information, individuals exhibit a natural reluctance to alter anchors.105 Consequently, the professional athlete might modify the anchor, but in a way that insufficiently reflects actual variations between himself and the similar player. Such phenomena are notable in other fields as well. For instance, in litigation, the opening offer in a settlement negotiation can influence the recipient’s judgment of a subsequent final offer, even when the opening offer does not convey relevant information.106 Likewise influential are “endowment effects,” whereby individuals perceive more utility from their current state of affairs than from altered and equivalent circumstances.107 As a consequence, individuals often demand more to relinquish an item than they would pay to obtain that same item.108 For instance, Kahneman and Tversky find that when individuals are hypothetically assigned one of two jobs, the first with a higher salary and the second with better working conditions, they prefer to remain in their assigned job rather than switch, 72 [hereinafter McCann, Illegal Defense] (discussing impact of age and experience on contract negotiations in the NBA). 104 See Russell Korobkin & Chris Guthrie, Heuristics and Biases at the Bargaining Table, 87 MARQ. L. REV. 795, 799 (2004). 105 See Gretchen B. Chapman & Eric J. Johnson, Incorporating the Irrelevant: Anchors in Judgments of Belief and Value, in HEURISTICS AND BIASES: THE PSYCHOLOGY OF INTUITIVE JUDGMENT 130-33 (Thomas Gilovich et al. eds., 2002); see also Nicholas Epley & Thomas Gilovich, Putting Adjustment Back in the Anchoring and Adjustment Heuristic, 12 PSYCHOL. SCI. 391 (2001) (discussing reluctance of individuals to move away from initial anchors). 106 See Russell Korobkin & Chris Guthrie, Opening Offers and Out-of-Court Settlement: A Little Moderation May Not Go a Long Way, 10 OHIO ST. J. ON DISP. RESOL. 1, 11-13, 18-19 (1994). Anchoring and adjustment has also been illustrated by utilizing different reference points in questioning. See, e.g., Edward J. Joyce & Gary C. Biddle, Anchoring and Adjustment in Probabilistic Inference in Auditing, 19 J. ACCT. RES. 120, 122-23 (1981) (illustrating how individuals’ estimation of the likelihood of corporate fraud varies significantly based on the phrasing of the question). 107 See Korobkin & Guthrie, supra note 104, at 802-03; see also Daniel Kahneman et al., Experimental Tests of the Endowment Effect and the Coase Theorem, 98 J. POL. ECON. 1325 (1990) (supplying findings that confirm the prevalence of endowment heuristics); Russell Korobkin, Policymaking and the Offer/Asking Price Gap: Toward a Theory of Efficient Entitlement Allocation, 46 STAN. L. REV. 663, 668-69 (1994) (discussing endowment heuristics in the context of negotiations). 108 See generally Russell Korobkin, The Endowment Effect and Legal Analysis, 97 NW. U. L. REV. 1227 (2003) (describing and suggesting strategies for the integration of endowment effect into legal analysis). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1479 regardless of which job they are assigned.109 Similar findings are evident in the investment context: individuals prefer to maintain existing investment instruments (e.g., stocks; bonds) and their levels of investment, regardless of the instrument Further, when negotiating type or investment level.110 contracts, individuals often prefer terms of trade that are conventional and generally accepted, simply because they are familiar.111 Correspondingly, consider myopic heuristics, which encourage individuals to “stay the course,” even when doing so would diminish their long-term welfare.112 This in part relates to the human tendency to be more concerned about losses than gains, and thus more averse to risk of loss than tempted by For instance, even in the presence of potential gain.113 conflicting evidence, shareholders often myopically view earnings reports to assume that short-term earnings are likely to continue indefinitely.114 Myopic heuristics also pertain to systematic over-estimation of costs inherent in change, such as time, thinking, and soliciting advice.115 To illustrate, consider that individuals often dismiss future environmental concerns because they are dissuaded by the complexity of the related literature, as well as the requisite effort to overcome such complexity.116 109 Kahneman & Tversky, supra note 50, at 348; see also Russell Korobkin, The Status Quo Bias and Contract Default Rules, 83 CORNELL L. REV. 608, 627 (1998) (discussing Kahneman & Tversky and related studies). 110 See William Samuelson & Richard Zeckhauser, Status Quo Bias in Decision Making, 1 J. RISK & UNCERTAINTY 7, 14 (1988) (studying MBA students at Boston University and public policy graduate students at Harvard University). 111 Russell Korobkin, Inertia and Preference in Contract Negotiation: The Psychological Power of Default Rules and Form Terms, 51 VAND. L. REV. 1583, 1587-88 (1998). 112 Jolls et al., supra note 45, at 1479 (describing “bounded willpower” and its effect on human choices); see also Erik Luna, Race, Crime, and Institutional Design, 66 L. & CONTEMP. PROBS. 183, 197 (2003) (discussing myopic heuristics in context of criminal law). 113 Behavioral Finance: Borrowing from Psychology to Explain Behavior, PENSIONS & INVESTMENTS, May 26, 1997, at 32 (discussing myopic risk aversion in context of investment strategies). 114 See Lucian Arye Bebchuck & Marcel Kahan, A Framework for Analyzing Legal Policy Towards Proxy Contests, 78 CAL. L. REV. 1075, 1102 (1990) (explaining how management might exploit this behavioral pattern among shareholders to present short-term earnings in a more favorable light by under-investing in research and development and other long-term projects). 115 John R. Hauser et al., How Consumers Allocate Their Time When Searching for Information, 30 J. MARKETING RES. 452, 458 (1993). 116 See U.S. Rep. Earl Blumenauer, Entrepreneurial Environmentalism: A New Approach for the New Millennium, 30 ENVTL. L. 1, 5 (2000) (observing that 1480 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 A more encompassing heuristic pertains to the human tendency to arrive at conclusions that they are motivated to reach.117 Indeed, motivation to achieve a certain conclusion often induces the mind to form impressions, evaluate observations, and make decisions pursuant to such motivation.118 The most salient of these motivations is the desire to see oneself in “self-affirming ways.”119 That is, people tend to view themselves as harboring good intentions and To ensure acting in accordance with moral norms.120 preservation of such selective views, individuals routinely make dramatic cognitive adjustments, including complete shielding of conflicting information.121 These adjustments are especially telling when individuals are confronted with challenging philosophical choices, such as participation in war crimes.122 Like cognitive biases then, heuristics may lead to systemic errors, as judgments about how to best respond to choice and circumstances can unknowingly discount meaningful data.123 Taken together, biases and heuristics reveal significant limits to the rational actor model, and suggest that individuals may unknowingly pursue less-thanpreferable course of actions. These deleterious tendencies are only accentuated by individuals’ vast and systematic underappreciation of their capacity to utilize and be manipulated by “[c]omprehensive environmental approaches are too often laid aside as overly complex or even impossible to implement”); see also Rebecca M. Bratspies, Myths of Voluntary Compliance: Lessons from the StarLink Corn Fiasco, 27 WM. & MARY ENVTL. L. & POL’Y REV. 593, 642 (2003) (discussing difficulty of understanding environmental regulation); Edward R. Morrison, Judicial Review of Discount Rates Used in Regulatory CostBenefit Analysis, 65 U. CHI. L. REV. 1333, 1346-47 (1998) (describing environmental regulation as an example of a topic where its complexity tends to dissuade inquiry). 117 Hanson & Yosifon, supra note 92, at 138. 118 Ziva Kunda, The Case for Motivated Reasoning, 108 PSYCHOL. BULL. 480, 480 (1990). 119 Hanson & Yosifon, supra note 92, at 138. 120 Id. 121 Adam Benforado, Jon Hanson & David Yosifon, Broken Scales: Obesity and Justice in America, 53 EMORY L.J. 1645, 1659 (2004); see also Abhijit Biswas et al., Consumer Evaluation of Reference Price Advertisements: Effects of Other Brands’ Prices and Semantic Cues, 18 J. PUB. POL’Y & MKTG. 52 (1999) (describing how consumers make cognitive adjustments in value judgments). 122 See Eddie Harmon-Jones & Cindy Harmon-Jones, Testing the Action-Based Model of Cognitive Dissonance: The Effect of Action Orientation on Postdecisional Attitudes, 28 PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. BULL. 711, 719-21 (2002) (presenting subjects with varying difficulties of decisions and assessing results). 123 See Cass R. Sunstein, Behavioral Analysis of Law, 64 U. CHI. L. REV. 1175, 1178 (1997). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1481 cognitive distortions.124 As a result, there often exists a considerable gap between an individual’s set of preferences and her pattern of choices, thus undermining the very premise behind rational choice theory. Nevertheless, the alleged effects of cognitive biases, heuristics, and, more broadly, behavioral decision theory are not without critique. One of the most often cited critiques suggests that while individuals may display cognitive errors in laboratory or controlled experiments, they may act more rationally in real world settings.125 There are also doubts as to how well cognitive biases and heuristics predict anomalous behavior, or how well such techniques forecast response to policy shifts or circumstantial changes.126 In the context of professional athletes contemplating contractual offers, the following section will assess the relative strengths and limitations of rational choice models and competing cognitive influences. IV. PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES & CONTRACTUAL DECISIONMAKING A. Relevance to the Study of Law and Economics and Behavioral Sciences The potential influence of alternative preferences and cognitive biases on professional athletes is, to date, an unexplored topic. Perhaps this is not surprising, since professional athletes comprise less than one-tenth of one percent of the population and are thus considered a statistically-insignificant population segment by most Moreover, with their often exorbitant demographers.127 salaries, generous work schedules, and glamorous lifestyles, professional athletes tend to be considered extraordinarily 124 See Hanson & Yosifon, supra note 92, at 138. See, e.g., Alan Schwartz & Robert E. Scott, Contract Theory and the Limits of Contract Law, 113 YALE L.J. 541, 551 & n.18 (2003) (doubting existence of heuristics and cognitive biases in contract law); Robert E. Scott, A Theory of Self-Enforcing Indefinite Agreements, 103 COLUM. L. REV. 1641, 1661 (2003). 126 See, e.g., Jessica L. Cohen & William T. Dickens, A Foundation for Behavioral Economics, 92 AM. ECON. REV. 335, 335 (2002). 127 See, e.g., Fares al-Braizat, Muslims and Democracy: An Empirical Critique of Fukuyama’s Culturalist Approach, 43 INT’L J. COMP. SOC. 269 (2002), available at http://www.worldvaluessurvey.org/Upload/5_Islamdem_2.pdf (describing as “insignificant” a population that comprises less than one percent of the total population). 125 1482 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 unique and sufficiently incomparable to more socially-relevant populations.128 Perhaps for these very reasons, professional athletes have warranted relatively scant consideration by legal academics.129 Other reasons for their academic marooning include a more than occasional dismissal of sports law as a frivolous area of study,130 as well as sports law’s only recent ascendancy in legal academia.131 Overlooking professional athletes, however, appears to be a disservice to the study of behavioral law and economics. Indeed, although a comparatively small group, professional athletes appear strikingly influential on the world around them. Most notably, professional athletes play on teams which supply tangible economic benefit to local communities, including the generation of employment opportunities for vendors, concessionaires, security, and other ameliorated groups, as well as the boosting of sales for adjoining businesses, such as restaurants, pubs, and hotels.132 Also consider the 128 See, e.g., Brown v. Pro Football, Inc., 518 U.S. 231, 255-57 (1996) (Stevens, J., dissenting) (highlighting the unique economic position of professional athletes); Dan Messeloff, The NBA’s Deal with the Devil: The Antitrust Implications of the 1999 NBANBPA Collective Bargaining Agreement, 10 FORDHAM INTELL. PROP. MEDIA & ENT. L.J. 521, 532 (2000) (quoting NATIONAL BASKETBALL ASSOCIATION UNIFORM PLAYER CONTRACT, ¶ 9) (explaining how the “extraordinary and unique skill and ability” of professional athletes renders them sufficiently distinct from other population groups considered by the law); Eric D. Scheible, No Runs. No Hits. One Error: Eliminating Major League Baseball’s Antitrust Exemption Will Not Save the Game, 73 U. DET. MERCY L. REV. 73, 100 n.209 (1995) (describing unique nature of professional athlete in the labor market, and implying how that nature might make legal comparison more challenging and less predictable). 129 Timothy Davis, What Is Sports Law?, 11 MARQ. SPORTS L. REV. 211, 212 (2001) (noting that many legal academics believe that analysis of sports does not warrant academic attention). 130 See, e.g., James R. Elkins, Troubled Beginnings: Reflections on Becoming a Lawyer, 26 U. MEM. L. REV. 1303, 1311 (1996) (quoting JOHN GRISHAM, THE RAINMAKER (1996)). 131 See Roger I. Abrams, Book Review, 54 U. CIN. L. REV. 1237, 1238 (1986) (describing how sports law became popular in the late 1980s, following growth of the modern sports industry). In fact, since the 1990s, a number of law schools, including Tulane Law School and Marquette University Law School, offer certificates in sports law. Larry Cata Backer, Toward General Principles of Academic Specialization by Means of Certificate or Concentration Programs: Creating a Certificate Program in International, Comparative and Foreign Law at Penn State, 20 PENN ST. INT’L L. REV. 67, 117 n.115 (2001). See http://www.law.tulane.edu (follow links to “Programs of Study” and “Sports Law”) (last visited Jan. 25, 2006). In contrast to many legal scholars, economists have tended to regard professional sports as a useful vehicle from which to examine a range of theoretical issues. See, e.g., J. Colin H. Jones et al., Ethnicity, Productivity and Salary: Player Compensation and Discrimination in the National Hockey League, 31 APPLIED ECON. 593, 594 (1999) (discussing role of professional sports in economic research). 132 See generally KENNETH L. SHROPSHIRE, THE SPORTS FRANCHISE GAME (1995) (claiming that sports teams provide a multiplier effect on local economies); 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1483 capacity of professional sports to effect meaningful broadcast revenue: the television contracts of the four largest leagues (the National Football League (“NFL”), Major League Baseball (“MLB”), the National Basketball Association (“NBA”), and the National Hockey League (“NHL”)) collectively exceed $4 billion annually.133 More subjectively, professional athletes supply appreciable, though intangible benefit to their surrounding communities, often in the form of team pride or simply the enabling of fandom and associated enjoyment.134 Perhaps more importantly, and unlike most population groups, professional athletes furnish published commentary of their thought processes, as evidenced by regular newspaper, television, and radio interviews. Moreover, burgeoning playerto-fan discussions, such as chat rooms or blogs, offer supplemental avenues for players to explain their decisionmaking processes.135 Further commentary is provided by the media, players’ agents, team executives, and a myriad of “insiders.”136 In short, there exists a wealth of statements by SPORTS, JOBS & TAXES: THE ECONOMIC IMPACT OF SPORTS TEAMS AND STADIUMS (Roger G. Noll & Andrew Zimbalist eds., 1997) (arguing that sports teams create jobs, boost tourism, and decrease crime). But see MARK ROSENTRAUB, MAJOR LEAGUE LOSERS: THE REAL COSTS OF SPORTS AND WHO’S PAYING FOR IT (2001) (on file with author) (dismissing the benefit of sports franchises on the local economy as miniscule); PAUL C. WEILER, LEVELING THE PLAYING FIELD: HOW THE LAW CAN MAKE SPORTS BETTER FOR FANS 267-69 (2000) (equating a publicly-financed stadium to a public park that charges expensive admission); Dale F. Rubin, Public Aid to Professional Sports Teams—A Constitutional Disgrace. The Battle to Revive Judicial Rulings and State Constitutional Enactments Prohibiting Public Subsidies to Private Corporations, 30 U. TOL. L. REV. 393, 418 (1999) (arguing against public finance for professional sports franchises due to lack of credible evidence such financing ultimately yields greater benefit than cost). 133 See PAUL C. WEILER & GARY R. ROBERTS, SPORTS AND THE LAW: TEXT, CASES, PROBLEMS 389 (2d ed. 1998). 134 See WEILER, supra note 132, at 170 (observing that sports fans follow their favorite teams and players similar to religious followers); see also Bruce W. Burton & Matthew J. Mitten, New Remedies for Breach of Sports Facility Use Agreements: Time for Marketplace Realism, 88 IOWA L. REV. 809, 820 n.37 (2003) (illuminating psychological benefits identified by sports fans). 135 Some players, such as Red Sox pitcher Curt Schilling, regularly utilize chat rooms to post their thoughts. Daniel G. Habib, Down to the Last Out, SPORTS ILLUSTRATED, Sept. 27, 2004, at Z8 (noting how Schilling regularly posts on the “Sons of Sam Horn” message board, which is primarily comprised of devoted Red Sox fans); see also Howard Bryant, Schilling’s Off Line, BOSTON HERALD, June 15, 2004, at 90 (criticizing Schilling for communicating his feelings directly through Sons of Sam Horn while refusing to discuss those feelings with reporters). 136 Such insiders even include player wives. See Steven M. Ortiz, The Ethnographic Process of Gender Management: Doing the “Right” Masculinity with Wives of Professional Athletes, 11 QUALITATIVE INQUIRY 265, 273 (2005) (interviewing players’ wives regarding their husbands’ choices in both the personal and professional arena). 1484 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 athletes and those close to them that attest to their values, beliefs, and priorities when deciding where, and for how much they want to play, among other choices. Accordingly, professional athletes illuminate real world behavioral patterns, rather than stimuli to experimental circumstances, and, in doing so, abrogate the alleged “experimental flaw” of many behavioral law and economic studies.137 Thus, exploring the decision-making processes of professional athletes in the context of employment opportunities may prove not only to be an engaging exercise, but an instrumental analysis of behavioral tendencies in realworld settings. This Article will now turn to this exploration, and will begin with a discussion of contracting and choice among professional athletes. Subsequently, it will canvass actual players who accepted the “less-than-optimal” contract offers, assuming optimality is defined as the most lucrative offer. In doing so, this Article will address whether their choices reflected conscious preferences, such as desire to be close to home or partiality to warm weather, or cognitive biases and heuristics that went unappreciated in their decisionmaking processes. B. Exploring Contract Negotiations Between Player, Agent & Team Like film actors, musicians, and other high-paid, service-oriented professionals, professional athletes enter into personal services contracts that reflect their unique skills or talents.138 In the case of professional athletes, those unique skills or talents comprise the exceedingly rare ability to athletically perform in a way that attracts financial As a result, their “employment” with remuneration.139 professional sports teams entails their “execution of personal services contract[s] with the owner or prospective owner of a 137 See supra note 125 and accompanying text. See M. Scott McDonald, Noncompete Contracts: Understanding the Cost of Unpredictability, 10 TEX. WESLEYAN L. REV. 137, 143 (2003). 139 To illustrate how exceedingly rare it is for an athlete to ever earn income playing sports, consider that “[o]nly 3 out of every 10,000 boys who play high school basketball ever make it to the pros,” and “[o]nly 1 out of every 75 college players ever makes the jump to the big time.” Fred Bowen, Going Pro: It’s a Long Shot, WASH. POST, June 29, 2001, at C12 (citing research conducted by the National Collegiate Athletic Association (NCAA)). Also consider that less than one percent of high school athletes receive college athletic scholarships. Tony Hansen, Havin’ a Ball at Camp, BATTLE CREEK ENQUIRER, May 26, 2004, at 1B. 138 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1485 professional sports team for the purpose of future athletic services.”140 Typically, players’ contracts are negotiated by their Generally, agents, who are contracted representatives.141 agents receive a fixed percentage of earnings under player contracts, which reflects their commission, although some receive compensation based on hourly rates instead.142 Player agents perform other services as well, such as negotiating endorsement contracts, providing financial management and accounting advice, and resolving disputes that arise under the athlete’s employment contract.143 Significantly, and as in any agency relationship, the player (client) possess decision-making authority for all aspects pertaining to his profession.144 The actual framework for contract negotiation between player/agent and team greatly depends on the sport and the player’s level of experience. In all four major sports leagues (i.e., the NFL, MLB, the NBA, and the NHL), players gain entrance by selection in an entry draft, whereby a team “drafts” the player, and obtains that player’s rights to play in the associated league.145 The primary purpose of a draft is to 140 See Rob Remis & Diana Sudia, Escaping Athlete Agent Statutory Regulation: Loopholes and Constitutional Defectiveness Based on Tri-Parte Classification of Athletes, 9 SETON HALL J. SPORT L. 1, 65 (1999) (quoting “Definition of Athlete” under CONN. GEN. STAT. ANN. § 20-553 (West 1997)). 141 Id. 142 Typically, the fixed percentage is between three and five percent of total earnings. Eric Willenbacher, Regulating Sports Agents: Why Current Federal and State Efforts Do Not Deter the Unscrupulous Athlete-Agent and How a National Licensing System May Cure the Problem, 78 ST. JOHN’S L. REV. 1225, 1244 & n.139 (2004) (citing Michael Cohen, Meet the Real Jerry Maguires, BOSTON BUS. J., Oct. 5, 1998). More recently, some agents, such as Lon Babby of Williams & Connolly, have begun utilizing an hourly rate, rather than commission. See generally Stacey M. Nahrwold, Are Professional Athletes Better Served by a Lawyer-Representative than an Agent? Ask Grant Hill, 9 SETON HALL J. SPORT L. 431, 458-60 (1999) (describing Babby’s work for Grant Hill of the Orlando Magic). 143 James G. Sammataro, Comment, Business and Brotherhood, Can They Coincide? A Search into Why Black Athletes Do Not Hire Black Agents, 42 HOW. L.J. 535, 545 & n.50 (1999) (citing Rob Remis, Analysis of Civil and Criminal Penalties in Athlete Agent Statutes and Support for Imposition of Civil and Criminal Liability upon Athletes, SETON HALL J. SPORT L. 1, 6 (1998)); see also Richard C. Webb, Personal Services Lawyering: Sports, Entertainment, Art or Just Plain Risky Business?, 5 S.C. LAW. 11, 12 (1993) (describing myriad duties of player agents, some of which include rather undignified duties, such as fielding late-night phone calls pertaining to trivial matters). 144 See Grace M. Giesel, Enforcement of Settlement Contracts: The Problem of the Attorney Agent, 12 GEO. J. LEGAL ETHICS 543, 587-88 (1999) (discussing rights of client versus those of agent). 145 See Michael A. McCann & Joseph S. Rosen, The Legality of Age Restrictions in the NBA and the NFL, 56 CASE W. RES. L. REV. (forthcoming, 2006), at Part 1 (discussing eligibility for NFL and NBA Drafts) (draft of article on file with 1486 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 prevent amateur players from bargaining with multiple teams.146 Indeed, in each of the four major leagues, once a team drafts an amateur player, his playing rights become the exclusive property of that team for at least one calendar year, and he can negotiate with no other teams during that time.147 If a player chooses not to sign and wait one year, the team that drafted him no longer controls his rights, but that player’s only option to gain entry into the league is to enter the draft again, “and if drafted a second time, he again becomes the property of [another] team for one year.”148 Practically, therefore, the draft is the exclusive entrance for amateur players into professional sports. Once drafted, an athlete signs a player contract in accordance with the league’s collective bargaining agreement. There are significant variations among the four major sports leagues for entry contracts, as parameters for such contracts reflect the product of negotiations between individual leagues and players’ associations. For instance, while players selected in the NBA Draft sign for pre-determined salary slots in accordance with their draft position,149 players selected in the MLB Draft can negotiate their own contracts. Though heavily influenced by draft position, such contracts may vary widely upon leveraging circumstances, such as whether the player has remaining collegiate eligibility, or whether the team possesses sufficient funds to sign its draft selections.150 author); Erik Ekblad, Note, A Slice into the Sand Trap: Why the PGA Was Unwise in Its Decision to Push Its Dispute with Casey Martin to the Supreme Court, 32 SW. U. L. REV. 151, 174 (2003) (noting mechanics of MLB Draft and NHL Draft). 146 See McCann, Illegal Defense, supra note 103, at 130. 147 See, e.g., NBPA, Collective Bargaining Agreement, July 30, 2005, art. X(1)(b)(ii), available at http://nbpa.org/cba_articles/article-X.php#section1 (last visited Jan. 26, 2006) (stipulating the rule for players selected in the NBA Draft); NFL Collective Bargaining Agreement, art. XVI, 4(b), at 44 (1993), available at http://www.nflpa.org/Members/main.asp?subPage=CBA+Complete#art16 (last visited Jan. 26, 2006) (stipulating that the playing rights of players selected in the NFL Draft remain the property of the drafting team for one calendar year); Jeffrey A. Rosenthal, The Amateur Sports Draft: The Best Means to the End?, 6 MARQ. SPORTS L.J. 1, 19 n.79 (1995) [hereinafter Rosenthal] (citing Major League Baseball Professional Rules Book 4(e) (1988), which stipulates that the playing rights of players selected in the MLB Draft remain the property of the drafting team for one calendar year or until the player returns to college, whichever is shorter)). While occasional exceptions to this standard exist, they are seldom employed. Peter N. Katz, Comment, A History of Free Agency in the United States and Great Britain: Who’s Leading the Charge, 15 COMP. LAB. L.J. 371, 384 n.82 (1994). 148 McCann, Illegal Defense, supra note 103, at 129-30. 149 See discussion infra pp. 1487-88. 150 Rosenthal, supra note 147, at 17-20; see also Jack Curry, Fulfilling Great Expectations: Barry Lamar Bonds, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 7, 2001, § 8, at 1 (describing how 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1487 Regardless of the league, a drafted player can only maximize his earning potential by eventually obtaining “free agent” status, whereby the player may negotiate and sign with any team.151 Typically, such status emerges only after a player has accrued a certain level of service time in a particular league, and only after his existing contract has expired.152 There are two types of free agency: “unrestricted” free agency, whereby a player can negotiate and sign with any team after his contract expires, and “restricted” free agency, whereby a player can likewise negotiate and sign with any team after his contract expires, but the original team reserves the right to “match” any signed contract or otherwise receive compensation, usually in the form of draft selections.153 Thus, an unrestricted free agent possesses the optimal bargaining position: he can sign with any team, and the team with which he signs owes no compensation to his prior team.154 To illustrate the economic path of a professional athlete, consider an amateur player who seeks to enter the NBA. This player must participate in the NBA Draft, in which he will either be drafted by a team in one of two rounds, or not selected. If he is drafted in the first round, he will sign a guaranteed two-year contract for a pre-determined amount, ranging from $9.0 million for the first pick to $1.8 million for the last pick in that round.155 The NBA team that drafts him Barry Bonds was originally drafted in 1982 by the San Francisco Giants, chose to attend Arizona State instead, and in 1985 was drafted by the Pittsburgh Pirates, with whom he signed). 151 See generally WEILER, supra note 132, at 170-97 (discussing free agency’s effect on the professional sports leagues). See also McCann, Illegal Defense, supra note 103, at 212 (discussing impact of free agency on career earnings opportunities for NBA players); Note, NFL Free Agency Restrictions Under Antitrust Attack, 1991 DUKE L.J. 503 (1991) (exploring impact of free agency on player salaries in the NFL). 152 For instance, in MLB, a player can only become a free agent after six years of service time. See Joshua Hamilton, Comment, Congress in Relief: The Economic Importance of Revoking Baseball’s Antitrust Exemption, 38 SANTA CLARA L. REV. 1223, 1240 & n.144 (1998) (explaining the history and rationale behind the rule). 153 See Note, supra note 151, at 503 nn.1-2. 154 See Ethan Lock, The Regulatory Scheme for Player Representatives in the National Football League: The Real Power of Jerry Maguire, 35 AM. BUS. L.J. 319, 32628 (1998) (explaining the implications of unrestricted and restricted free agency for professional athletes). 155 See NBPA, Collective Bargaining Agreement, supra note 147, at Exhibit B, available at http://nbpa.org/cba_exhibits/exhibitB.php (last visited Jan. 26, 2006); see also McCann, Illegal Defense, supra note 103, at 125 & n.37, 128 & tbl. 4 and accompanying text (describing draft pick economics in preceding collective bargaining agreement and how players selected in the first round of the NBA Draft can negotiate between 80% and 120% of stated annual salaries, and how, in practice, they always negotiate 120%). 1488 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 may extend his contract following his second and third seasons, although he may become a restricted free agent at the conclusion of his fourth season.156 Only at the conclusion of his fifth season may he become eligible for unrestricted free agency.157 In contrast, if he is drafted in the second round, he may obtain unrestricted free agency status earlier in his career, although most players selected in the second round sign either non-guaranteed contracts for the league minimum ($398,762) or simply fail to earn a contract.158 If he is not drafted in either round, then he immediately becomes an unrestricted free agent, though seldom does such a player ever play in the NBA.159 Assuming the player described in the preceding paragraph becomes a star, his earning capacity as an unrestricted free agent would prove quite impressive. Indeed, after completion of his rookie contract, and upon becoming an unrestricted free agent, that player may sign a contract worth up to the “maximum contract,” which reflects the longest and 156 NBPA, Collective Bargaining Agreement, supra note 147, at art. VIII, available at http://nbpa.org/cba_articles/article-VIII.php (last visited Mar. 2, 2006). 157 From a practical standpoint, most players remain with their team at the conclusion of the fourth season. Indeed, the 2005 Collective Bargaining Agreement preserves the so-called “Larry Bird exception,” which allows teams to exceed the salary cap in order to re-sign their own players (also called “Larry Bird rights”). See McCann, Illegal Defense, supra note 103, at 124-25. Thus, when a first round pick concludes his fourth season, usually the team for which he has played can offer him the most. 158 See NBPA, Collective Bargaining Agreement, supra note 147, at Exhibit C, available at http://nbpa.org/cba_exhibits/exhibitC.php (last visited Jan. 26, 2006). Very rarely, a second round pick will surprise the NBA and become a competent player or even a star player. Under the 1999 Collective Bargaining Agreement, such star players could gain optimal negotiating power at the conclusion of their second season— when their rookie contracts would typically expire—as they became “non-Larry Birdrights restricted free agents,” since Larry Bird rights only manifest after a player plays three seasons. As a result, the “restricted” nature of their free agency was curtailed, since, due to the absence of Larry Bird rights, the team for which they played could not re-sign them for any amount above the salary cap. This very machination arose in 2003, when 2001 second round pick Gilbert Arenas of the Golden State Warriors became a restricted free agent, and because Arenas had no Larry Bird rights and because the Warriors’ payroll exceeded the league-imposed salary cap, the Warriors could not match the six-year, $65 million free agent contract Arenas had signed with the Washington Wizards. See McCann, Illegal Defense, supra note 103, at 126-27. The 2005 Collective Bargaining Agreement, however, disallows other teams from offering such a player more than $4.5 million for his third season, an amount all NBA teams may utilize through its “mid-level exception” to the salary cap, regardless of whether the team’s payroll exceeds the salary cap. As a result, teams may hold on to their second-round picks long enough to invoke their Larry Bird rights. See NBPA, Collective Bargaining Agreement, supra note 147, at art. XI(5), available at http://nbpa.org/cba_articles/article-XI.php#section5 (last visited Mar. 2, 2006); see also NBPA, Collective Bargaining Agreement, supra note 147, at art. X(1)(b)(ii), available at http://nbpa.org/cba_articles/article-X.php#section1 (last visited Jan. 26, 2006). 159 See McCann, Illegal Defense, supra note 103, at 122. 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1489 most lucrative contract allowable under the NBA’s collective bargaining agreement.160 Currently, that maximum contract is worth approximately $91 million over a six-year period.161 Although such a contract is typically reserved for the league’s best players, even far less-heralded players may obtain This exorbitant deals as unrestricted free agents.162 phenomenon is not unique to basketball, as unrestricted free agents in baseball, football, and hockey likewise position themselves for extraordinarily lucrative contracts.163 Thus, the most dynamic setting for professional sports contracting occurs when a player becomes an unrestricted free agent, attracts meaningful interest from multiple teams, and negotiates with those teams to yield the optimal contract. Put differently, this setting offers a “competitive market,” since there exists a market of sellers (i.e., the teams) competing for the attraction of a buyer (i.e., the player).164 Though varying circumstances, such as number of interested teams and relative skill of representation, as well as collectively-bargained restraints of trade, such as “salary caps” and “luxury taxes,”165 160 See NBPA, Collective Bargaining Agreement, supra note 147, at art. II(7), available at http://nbpa.org/cba_articles/article-II.php#section7 (last visited Jan. 26, 2006). 161 Id. This figure is based on an amount up to thirty percent of the NBA’s salary cap in effect at the time the contract is executed, and can thus change in correspondence to any changes in the salary cap. Id. at art. II(7)(a)(2). 162 For instance, consider Mark Blount, the much-maligned Minnesota Timberwolves center, who, as an unrestricted free agent in 2004, managed to secure a six-year contract worth $42 million with the Boston Celtics. Shira Springer, Celtics Do New Deal for Blount, BOSTON GLOBE, July 9, 2004, at E1. Another strikingly lucrative free agent contract was obtained by Derek Fisher, the venerable but middling point guard, who, as an unrestricted free agent in 2004, signed a six-year contract worth $37 million. David DuPree, Lakers Have Plenty of Retooling To Do, USA TODAY, July 16, 2004, at 14C. 163 See, e.g., WEILER, supra note 132, at 185 (“[A]verage MLB salaries have soared under free agency.”); see also Mélanie Aubut, When Negotiations Fail: An Analysis of Salary Arbitration and Salary Cap Systems, 10 SPORTS LAW. J. 189, 198201 (describing optimal bargaining position for MLB players); Lock, supra note 154, at 335-39 (describing optimal bargaining position for NFL players); Stephen F. Ross, The NHL Labour Dispute and the Common Law, The Competition Act, and Public Policy, 37 U.B.C. L. REV. 343, 403 (2004) (describing optimal bargaining position for NHL players). 164 See Eyal Zamir, The Inverted Hierarchy of Contract Interpretation and Supplementation, 97 COLUM. L. REV. 1710, 1790 (1997). 165 A salary cap is a ceiling on the total amount teams may spend on player salaries, while a luxury tax requires teams with payrolls over a particular threshold to pay a percentage of the excess to the other teams in the league. Id. Thus, a salary cap imposes an actual limit on team payroll, while a luxury tax serves as a deterrent to teams that would otherwise spend above a certain threshold. See generally Thomas A. Piraino, Jr., A Proposal for the Antitrust Regulation of Professional Sports, 79 B.U. L. 1490 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 affect the degree of market competition, meaningful engagement among multiple parties tends to emerge whenever a player becomes an unrestricted free agent.166 Lastly, note the relatively brief earnings curve for most professional athletes, and thus their limited window of time to capitalize on lucrative earnings. Indeed, in all four major leagues, the average career only lasts between four and six years,167 and only a small percent of players within those leagues play into their late thirties or beyond.168 Along those lines, most professional athletes are considered in their “prime” for a mere two- or three-year stretch, which typically occurs between the ages of 27 and 30; outside of that window, athletes usually possess diminished earnings potential.169 Thus, and along with the need to accrue sufficient service time in order to obtain free agent eligibility, many professional athletes possess only one opportunity to “cash in” as unrestricted free agents. In part for that reason, many seek to maximize their earnings as free agents. This topic, along with evidence of alternative free agent pursuits, will be explored in the following section. V. IDENTIFYING CHOICE, BIAS, AND HEURISTICS AMONG PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES A. Evidence of Monetary-Maximizing Values Among Professional Athletes The setting of an unrestricted free agent negotiating with multiple teams drives several analytical interpretations. Traditional rational choice theory would posit that such an athlete, like any rational actor, would pursue maximization of REV. 889, 936-39 (1999) (comparing salary caps and luxury taxes as modes to ensure competitive play in professional sports). 166 Other externalities might include an absence of perfect information and certain obstacles to the execution of contracts, such as league approval. 167 See McCann, Illegal Defense, supra note 103, at 170 (noting that the average NBA career lasts five years); Alan Gersten, Show Me the Money: Why Professional Athletes Make Tough Clients, FIN. PLANNING, Mar. 1, 2005, at 5 (noting that the average NHL career lasts six years, the average MLB career lasts three and a half years, and the average NFL career also lasts three and a half years). 168 See, e.g., McCann, Illegal Defense, supra note 103, at 170 (discussing how only three percent of NBA players are over the age of thirty-five); Martin Miller, Raising the Bar at 40, L.A. TIMES, Sept. 29, 2003, at F1 (noting how, in 2003, only eleven MLB players, nine NHL players, six NFL players, and two NBA players were forty or older). 169 Id. But see Michael Russo, Many Free Agents, Not Much Money, SUNSENTINEL, July 1, 2001, at 15C (noting several large contracts obtained by aging NHL players). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1491 “utility,” as best, or most readily evidenced by monetary wealth. This deduction may be observed at both the macro and micro level. Most dramatically, consider the recent precipitous rise in player salaries, an ascent primarily attributed to the maximization of monetary interests during free agent bargaining.170 For instance, since 1995, the average NHL player salary has risen by 245 percent ($733,000 to $1.8 million), during which time league revenue has grown by only 163 percent.171 Similarly astounding, consider that since 1983, the average NBA player salary has grown by 1,892 percent ($246,000 to $4.9 million),172 or that since 1989, the average MLB player salary has risen by 423 percent ($497,000 to $2.6 million).173 These trends suggest that maximization of wealth proves a salient consideration to many professional athletes, thus corroborating a traditional rational choice model. On a micro level, traditional rational choice would find that when players (and their representatives) negotiate with teams, they each begin with a reservation price, defined in this context as the maximum amount each is willing to relinquish or the minimum amount each is willing to accept.174 To illustrate, imagine a player who seeks a contract extension 170 See generally MICHAEL LEWIS, MONEYBALL: THE ART OF WINNING AN UNFAIR GAME (2003) (discussing precipitous increase in salaries among MLB players since the advent of free agency, and how such a development has disadvantaged smaller-market teams); Richard A. Kaplan, Note, The NBA Luxury Tax Model: A Misguided Regulatory Scheme, 104 COLUM. L. REV. 1615 (2004) (studying economic trends in the NBA); Sanjay José’ Mullick, Browns to Baltimore: Franchise Free Agency and the New Economics of the NFL, 7 MARQ. SPORTS L.J. 1 (1996) (studying economic trends in the NFL); Joseph M. Weiler, Legal Analysis of the NHL Players’ Contract, 3 MARQ. SPORTS L.J. 59 (1992) (studying economic trends in the NHL); ANDREW ZIMBALIST, MAY THE BEST TEAM WIN: BASEBALL ECONOMICS AND PUBLIC POLICY (2003) (studying economic trends in MLB). 171 See Dave Stubbs, Europe Might Elbow NHL out of Picture, MONTREAL GAZETTE, Feb. 17, 2005, at A3 (noting the increase in player salary); Michael Arace, Players Ratify New Deal, COLUMBUS DISPATCH, July 22, 2005, at 1F (noting the increase in league revenue). 172 See Looking for a Model? Try the NBA, TORONTO STAR, Dec. 16, 2004, at C4 (noting the current average NBA salary); David Dupree, NBA: Red Ink and a Bleak Future, WASH. POST, Mar. 15, 1983, at D1 (noting the average NBA salary in 1983). The increase in average NBA salary has closely approximated the increase in league revenue, which has risen 1,840 percent since 1983 ($160 million to $3.1 billion). Looking for a Model?, supra (citing current league revenue); Union Alters Stance, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 26, 1983, at 1 (noting projected revenues for 1984-85 season). 173 See Murray Chass, Players’ Figures Show $497,254 Pay Average, SPORTING NEWS, Dec. 18, 1989, at 44 (noting the average MLB salary in 1989) (on file with author); Tim Tucker, Baseball Pay Creeps Up, ATLANTA J.-CONST., Apr. 10, 2005, at 2E (noting the current average MLB salary). 174 See DAVID A. LAX & JAMES K. SEBENIUS, THE MANAGER AS NEGOTIATOR: BARGAINING FOR COOPERATION AND COMPETITIVE GAIN 51 (1986). 1492 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 from his existing team, but because he has not yet accrued sufficient service time for free agent eligibility, he cannot pursue employment with any other team should such an extension fail.175 If this player enters contract negotiations with a reservation price of $2 million per year, it means that he is unwilling to accept any contract that pays him less than $2 million per year, and also that he is willing to pursue noncontractual resolutions in lieu of a contract for less than $2 million per year. The primary such resolution is a “hold-out,” whereby the player refuses to report to his team (and thus forfeits pay) in hopes that doing so will motivate that team to acquiesce.176 Importantly, there exists a meaningful distinction between “public” and “private” reservation prices, and such prices may evolve in accordance with unexpected or non-static market conditions.177 For instance, after completing his most recent contract with the Atlanta Braves in October 2003, pitcher Greg Maddux instructed his agent to inform teams that he would accept no less than a two-year contract worth $20 After four months of unexpectedly lukewarm million.178 interest, however, Maddux would agree to a two-year contract worth $15 million with the Chicago Cubs.179 175 This fact-pattern arises with some regularity in MLB, the NFL, and the NHL, though less often in the NBA, as the league’s CBA stipulates more discernable contract parameters, thus diminishing opportunities for discord between player and team in negotiating contract extensions. See McCann, Illegal Defense, supra note 103, at 195. 176 For instance, during NFL training camp in August 2004, Miami Dolphins’ defensive end Adewale Ogunleye held out in hopes of receiving a long-term extension instead of a one-year extension tendered by the Dolphins. Alex Marvez & Keven Lerner, Dolphins Reward Chambers, ORLANDO SENTINEL, Aug. 6, 2004, at D3. Rather than acquiescing to his demand, the Dolphins traded Ogunleye to the Chicago Bears, who promptly signed Ogunleye to a long-term extension. Mike Mulligan, Bears Can Alter Stingy Image in a Buy Week, CHI. SUN-TIMES, Aug. 24, 2004, at 105; see also Basil M. Loeb, Comment, Deterring Player Holdouts: Who Should Do It, How to Do it, and Why It Has to Be Done, 11 MARQ. SPORTS L. REV. 275, 275-79 (2001) (providing a detailed background of holdouts in professional sports and how players internalize the relative risks and benefits of pursuing holdouts). 177 See Lynn A. Stout, Are Takeover Premiums Really Premiums? Market Price, Fair Value, and Corporate Law, 99 YALE L.J. 1235, 1237 n.150 (describing how reservation prices are affected by modified expectations and how they may be strategically revised to accommodate such expectations). 178 See Tom Verducci, Hard Line: Will Scott Boras’s Waiting Game Help or Hurt His Clients This Year?, SPORTS ILLUSTRATED, Jan. 19, 2004, at 84. 179 Mike Kiley, Wood Takes Cubs’ Sales Pitch, CHI. SUN-TIMES, Feb. 28, 2004, at 102 (noting also that the contract included a possible third year for $9 million if Maddux pitches a certain number of innings during the 2004 and 2005 seasons). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1493 During actual negotiations, rational choice analysis would find players and teams attempting to identify their bargaining zone, which, as discussed in Section II, comprises the range of amounts between competing reservation prices.180 Within this range, any amount would prove “mutually beneficial, or ‘Pareto superior’ to the alternative of not reaching an agreement.”181 Put more succinctly by Richard Posner, Pareto superior “makes at least one person better off and no one worse off.”182 In the context of professional sports negotiations, effectively identifying the bargaining zone depends upon negotiation parameters, such as whether the negotiations concern a free agent or a current employee, as well as the number of potential suitors for the player. Predictably, a free agent with numerous teams pursuing his services generally has less of an incentive to identify a bargaining zone with any one of those teams than would a player negotiating a contract extension with his present team, particularly if that player would not become a free agent in the near future.183 Bargaining zones may also provide room for settlement when the parties reach incompatible estimates of each others’ reservation price.184 Along those lines, settlement proves especially likely 180 See discussion infra pp. 1464-65 and accompanying notes; see also Russell Korobkin, A Positive Theory of Legal Negotiation, 88 GEO. L.J. 1789, 1816-17 (2000). Professor Robert H. Mnookin characterizes the bargaining zone as the “zone of possible agreement.” See ROBERT H. MNOOKIN ET AL., BEYOND WINNING: NEGOTIATING TO CREATE VALUE IN DEALS AND DISPUTES 20 (2000). 181 See Korobkin, Aspirations and Settlement, supra note 23, at 5. 182 RICHARD A. POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW 14 (5th ed. 1998). 183 Even with the more favorable circumstances described herein, a player may nevertheless prove unwilling to constructively pursue the bargaining zone. For instance, as discussed below on pages 1520-1524, at the start of the 2003 MLB season, it is speculated that Boston Red Sox shortstop Nomar Garciaparra was unwilling to negotiate a contract extension, despite the team’s interest in consummating one, and despite the fact that Garciaparra would not be eligible for free agency until after the 2004 season. Dan Shaughnessy, Damaged Goods: Deal Garciaparra, BOSTON GLOBE, July 3, 2004, at G1 [hereinafter Shaughnessy, Damaged Goods] (asserting that Red Sox management doubted Garciaparra’s actual willingness to negotiate). But see Julie S. Turner, The Nonmanufacturing Patent Owner: Toward a Theory of Efficient Infringement, 86 CAL. L. REV. 179, 197 (1998) (describing the presence of multiple parties as an impediment to the consummation of an agreement between two parties). 184 George A. Loewenstein & Don A. Moore, When Ignorance Is Bliss: Information Exchange and Inefficiency in Bargaining, 33 J. LEGAL STUD. 37, 45 (2004) (describing the value of large bargaining zones in difficult negotiations). 1494 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 when parties perceive limited or unsatisfying alternatives to an agreement.185 Nevertheless, incompatible estimates of competing reservation prices occasionally yield impasse, whereby the parties, frustrated by their failure to reach a number within the bargaining zone, cease negotiations.186 Some traditional rational choice theorists believe that impasse arises due to a lack of shared information, which eventually motivates parties to misinterpret each others’ reservation price.187 More recent analysis, however, suggests that sharing of information may actually promote divergence between the parties, particularly when such information invites disparate interpretation.188 This later finding appears corroborated by the “self-serving” bias apparent during negotiations, as even contemporary rational choice analysis identifies a tendency among parties to interpret information in egoistic ways, thus further impairing their pursuit of a mutually-satisfying number.189 To illustrate the difficulties of identifying a number within the bargaining zone, as well as the presence of selfserving bias in estimating the competing reservation price, consider the effect of “market-setting” contracts in professional sports. These contracts establish an economic barometer by which other players and teams may determine market value in the same economic period. This barometer is especially illuminating in a free agency period, as it allows instant and contemporaneous comparisons of existing free agents with those who had recently signed contracts. Often, comparative 185 See Kevin C. McMunigal, The Costs of Settlement: The Impact of Scarcity of Adjudication on Litigating Lawyers, 37 UCLA L. REV. 833, 861 n.106 (1990) (noting that negotiations are guided by the presence of alternative and viable opportunities). 186 Impasse may be defined as “that point at which the parties have exhausted the prospects of concluding an agreement and further discussions would be fruitless.” Laborers Health and Welfare Trust Fund for N. California v. Advanced Lightweight Concrete Co., 484 U.S. 539, 543 n.5 (1988). 187 See RICHARD A. POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW 525 (3d ed. 1986); see also Steven Shavell, Sharing of Information Prior to Settlement or Litigation, 20 RAND J. ECON. 183 (1989) (applying information-sharing to the context of litigation, and finding that discovery promotes settlement since it reveals information to opposing parties). 188 See Loewenstein & Moore, supra note 184, at 38-39. 189 See George Loewenstein et al., Self-Serving Assessments of Fairness and Pretrial Bargaining, 22 J. LEGAL STUD. 135, 159 (1993) (identifying implications of selfserving assessments of fairness for bargaining). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1495 characteristics include relative performance to date, expectation of future performance, age, and injury history.190 For example, consider that when the New York Mets signed pitcher Kris Benson to a three-year, $22.5 million contract at the start of the 2004 free agency period, observers perceived the contract as “market-setting,” since it established a contemporary value for free agent pitchers of Benson’s ilk.191 Indeed, following consummation of Benson’s contract, a number of free agent pitchers elevated their asking prices, and estimated their market value as greater than that of Benson, and thus warranting a contract in excess of a three-year, $22.5 million term.192 In response, the relevant negotiating teams tended to dismiss the Benson contract as reflective of one team’s desperation to win—and thus its willingness to pay above market value.193 Therefore, the “new information” of Benson’s contract proved sufficiently ambiguous as to invite contrasting interpretations by the negotiating parties. In fact, several free agent pitchers and teams so disparately internalized the Benson contract that their negotiations reached irreparable impasses.194 Subsequently, those pitchers initiated negotiations with new teams, and reached contracts consistent with the market established by the Benson contract.195 Accordingly, by potentially bifurcating existing negotiations, a market-setting contract might establish a barometer of varying compatibility to existing and potential 190 See, e.g., Rick Carpiniello, Free Agent Situations Are Getting Sticky, J. NEWS, Oct. 17, 1999, at 7C (describing contract negotiations with star players in the NHL); see also Jeffrey D. Schneider, Note, Unsportsmanlike Conduct: The Lack of Free Agency in the NFL, 64 S. CAL. L. REV. 797 (1991) (discussing relevant characteristics for free agent analysis). 191 See Larry Stone, Winners of Winter, SEATTLE TIMES, Jan. 25, 2005, at D1 (“[T]he pitching market was established, most GMs agree, when the Mets signed Kris Benson to a three-year, $22.5 million contract.”). 192 See, e.g., Tyler Kepner, Age-Wary Yanks Pick Wright over Lieber, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 9, 2004, at D7 (noting that the Benson contract prompted free agent pitcher Jon Lieber to increase his own contract demands). 193 See Mark Hale, Sosa in Sight: But Fat Pact Could Break Deal for Mets, N.Y. POST, Nov. 13, 2004, at 72 (describing the desire of new Mets’ general manager Omar Minaya to “make a splash”). 194 See, e.g., Bob Elliott, D-Backs on Spending Spree: A Day After Landing Troy Glaus, Arizona Signs Russ Ortiz to a Four-Year, $33 Million Deal, TORONTO STAR, Dec. 11, 2004, at S8 (citing remarks by Blue Jays’ general manager J.P. Ricciardi that Russ Ortiz altered his contract demands with the Atlanta Braves after the Benson contract); Todd Zolecki, Yankees’ Missed Opportunity a Plus for Phillies, PHILA. INQUIRER, Mar. 6, 2005, at D6 (discussing how the New York Yankees refused the revised demands of free agent pitcher Jon Lieber following the Benson contract, leading Lieber to sign with the Philadelphia Phillies). 195 See supra note 192 and accompanying text. 1496 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 teams, and thus impair the capacity of contemporaneously negotiating parties to identify a number within the bargaining zone.196 B. Evidence of Alternative Preferences Among Professional Athletes The preceding discussion frames player-team contract negotiations as entirely driven by the distribution of monetary resources. That is, it assumes that players exclusively value financial compensation when seeking employment opportunities. Such an assumption is commonly held among Media and other journalists often feel Americans.197 198 similarly. Such framing begs an important question: Why should society assume that professional athletes are unusually interested in monetary wealth? Indeed, as discussed in Section II, when individuals pursue employment opportunities, they often identify considerable value in non-monetary forms of “utility.”199 Such forms of utility might include objective characteristics, such as preferred location or job title, or intangibles, such as projected happiness or anticipated social These ideas are also consistent with rational status.200 decision-making, since “rationality” of choice refers to the 196 See supra notes 186-89 and accompanying text. See Thomas Boswell, Players, Owners and Us, WASH. POST, Oct. 21, 1994, at F1. Similarly, most Americans believe that athletes are paid too much money. Don Walker, Baseball Slips a Bit on State Poll: Interest Drops with Attendance, MILWAUKEE J. SENTINEL, May 26, 2003, at 6C (citing survey conducted by the University of Wisconsin that found that 89 percent of Americans believe professional athletes make too much money); see also, Michael Hiestand, Put a Lid on Pro Player Salaries, USA TODAY, Sept. 2, 2004, at 3C (citing remarks by Ralph Cindrich, an NFL player agent and former NFL player, who stated the opinion that if Americans were polled, 98 percent would say that “athletes are paid too much” money). Data suggests that teenagers feel likewise. See, e.g., Teen Ink, February 2001 Poll: Do Baseball Players Make Too Much Money, available at http://www.teenink.com/Poll/PastPolls.html (last visited Jan. 4, 2006) (finding that 71 percent of teenagers believe baseball players “make too much money”); Most Kids Look Up To Athletes: Fewer Are Influenced by Them, 12 YOUTH MARKETS ALERT 1 (2000) (finding that 43 percent of children ages ten to seventeen believe that athletes appear in ads for charities to get paid and improve their personal image, rather than caring about the cause). 198 See, e.g., Mark Patinkin, For Too Many Pro Athletes, It’s All About the Money, PROVIDENCE J., Feb. 20, 2005, at A2 (regarding the NHL Lockout of 2004-05 as evidence of greed among NHL players); Bob Raissman, Going Ratings Bad News for Boss, DAILY NEWS (New York), June 11, 2000, at 67 (“This is [a sports] era where it’s all about the money.”). 199 See discussion supra pp. 1462-63. 200 See id. 197 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1497 methodological pursuit of personal preferences, which vary by individual. Thus, unless professional athletes prove somehow “more greedy” than the average person, they should exhibit, with similar frequency, a preference for non-monetary forms of utility when contemplating employment opportunities. A review of expressed player motivations for accepting offers reveals a wide-range of preferences. Although many athletes pursue the most lucrative offer available, many others opt for less remunerative opportunities. Through the following illustrations, this Article will explore alternative optimal preferences to monetary aggrandizement, and how professional athletes often embrace those preferences. In doing so, this Article will attempt to explain behavioral tendencies among professional athletes and how those athletes navigate preferences when contemplating contractual opportunities. To begin this analysis, this Article will examine a question framed strikingly dissonant with popular expectations: Why do many professional athletes choose to stay in a setting when playing elsewhere would pay substantially more? 1. Environmental Preference: Remaining in Place According to many economists, individuals find it efficient to preserve familiar settings, such as location or personal contacts, and they attribute appreciable value to that preservation.201 Similarly, psychologists often maintain that individuals derive confidence from acquainted surroundings, and that such confidence influences their decision-making.202 This phenomenon is sometimes described as “regional affinity” or “hometown bias,” whereby individuals internalize intrinsic 201 See, e.g., RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, FORBIDDEN GROUNDS: THE CASE AGAINST EMPLOYMENT DISCRIMINATION LAWS (1992) (assessing value of familiarity in decisionmaking among individuals in hiring capacities); see also J.D. Trout & Shahid A. Buttar, Resurrecting “Death Taxes”: Inheritance, Redistribution, and the Science of Happiness, 16 J.L. & POL. 765, 802 n.118 (2000) (describing the psychological cost of those who fled the United States to Canada to avoid service in the Vietnam War). 202 See ELIZABETH F. LOFTUS, EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 89 (1996) (noting that college students perform worse on tests taken in unfamiliar surroundings); see also Peter J. Cohen, How Shall They Be Known? Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals and Eyewitness Identification, 16 PACE L. REV. 237, 248 (1996) (describing how individuals function better in familiar surroundings); D. Michael Risinger & Jeffrey L. Loop, Three Card Monte, Monty Hall, Modus Operandi and “Offender Profiling”: Some Lessons of Modern Cognitive Science for the Law of Evidence, 24 CARDOZO L. REV. 193, 275 n.434 (2002) (quoting JOHN E. DOUGLAS ET AL., CRIME CLASSIFICATION MANUAL § 132 (1992)) (describing how criminal behavior is in part motivated by confidence through familiar surroundings). 1498 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 value in remaining in a set location, and perceive themselves as better off by doing so.203 Professional athletes sometimes evince striking value in the preservation of their surroundings. To illustrate, consider Edmonton Oilers goaltender Tommy Salo, who, in 2000, agreed to a three-year contract extension worth $10.4 million.204 Although impressive, his contract likely reflected a market discount of approximately $4 million, as he declined the opportunity to pursue unrestricted agency at the earliest date in his career.205 Salo, however, articulated a preference for staying in Edmonton, as it reminded him of his native land, Sweden, and its citizens reminded him of Swedes.206 His preferences illuminate how a professional athlete may internalize “wealth” as a concept inclusive of non-economic terms, including preservation of surroundings. Similarly, during his nineteen-year career with the Cincinnati Reds, shortstop Barry Larkin, a Cincinnati native, identified meaningful subjective value in maintaining existing conditions. Indeed, during that time, Larkin declined several more lucrative opportunities to play elsewhere, reasoning that his continued stay in Cincinnati would exceed in value.207 Intriguingly, the subjective benefit of preserving familiarity came with a subjective cost: throughout his career, Larkin endured disapprobation from fellow players and their agents for accepting less compensation to stay in Cincinnati, as doing so may have diminished the market value for players of his Thus, the opportunity cost of forgoing enhanced ilk.208 compensation may include not only the difference in tangible 203 See Marcel Kahan & Linda Silberman, The Inadequate Search for “Adequacy” in Class Actions: A Critique of Epstein v. MCA, Inc., 73 N.Y.U. L. REV. 765, 775 n.50 (1998). 204 See Mario Annicchiarico, Stop Sign: Salo Takes Long-Term Lease on Oilers’ Cord Cottage, EDMONTON SUN, Nov. 3, 2000, at SP1. 205 Id. (citing comments by Salo’s agent). 206 Id. (quoting Salo, “[My fiancée and I] both like it here, it’s almost like back home . . . . Friendly people, a good club and I’m happy to be here. That’s why I signed the contract.”). 207 See, e.g., Hal McCoy, Reds Sign MVP Larkin Through 2000, DAYTON DAILY NEWS, Jan. 3, 1996, at 1D (quoting Larkin: “I love Cincinnati—my wife (Lisa) and I are both are [sic] from here. I’m happy here and I’ve been treated well. The Reds have been good to me. And I didn’t want to have to test the free agent market after next season.”). 208 See Hal McCoy, Larkin Feels Asking Price Is Fair, DAYTON DAILY NEWS, July 20, 2000, at 1D (quoting Larkin: “[B]ecause I signed for less money when I signed my contracts in the past . . . I caught a lot of grief from guys around the league and other agents for signing for under value.”). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1499 compensation, but also the “cost” of coping with hard feelings from peers who are more interested in financial recompense. Other professional athletes indicate a preference to stay in a location because of positive relations with teammates and coaches, coupled with uncertainty as to whether such relations may manifest in other settings. To illustrate, when Teemu Selanne re-signed with the San Jose Sharks in 2002, he accepted a pay reduction of nearly $3 million from his prior annual salary of $9 million, even though, as an unrestricted free agent, a number of teams were offering to pay him more than $9 million per year.209 At the time, the cash-strapped Sharks lacked the budgetary resources to pay Selanne his market value, thus forcing him to compare the subjective value of remaining a member of the Sharks with the subjective value of playing elsewhere for more money.210 In explaining his decision to re-sign, Selanne described how, over the course of his eleven-year career, he had become increasingly appreciative of team camaraderie, as well as the feeling of playing for a “classy organization,” and that such “personal goals” proved greater in value than additional millions of dollars.211 Reflecting upon Selanne’s decision to forgo several million dollars, Sharks’ general manager Dean Lombardi noted, “this is clearly a case where money was not important.”212 In exploring the role of alternative preferences among professional athletes, loyalty may offer a useful corollary to positive relations with teammates and coaches. As a behavioral concept, “loyalty” refers to a continuous cognitive affirmation of a particular entity, such as a nation, employer, or team, and its continuousness results from the feelings of Continuous cognitive well-being that it generates.213 affirmation, however, tends to trigger suppression or obfuscation of negative associations, while promoting the exaggeration or even invention of favorable aspects.214 More 209 See Robin Brownlee, Selanne’s a Fine Fit in San Jose: Teemu Enjoying Life in Fast Lane with Sharks, EDMONTON SUN, Oct. 18, 2002, at SP2. 210 Id. 211 Id. (quoting Selanne, “I could have got more money other places, but you have to see the whole picture.”). 212 See Selanne Spurns East to Stay with Sharks, OTTAWA SUN, July 6, 2002, at 56. 213 See generally STANLEY MILGRAM, OBEDIENCE TO AUTHORITY (1974). 214 Id.; see also Erwin Chemerinsky, Opening Closed Chambers, 108 YALE L.J. 1087, 1103-04 (questioning the desirability of loyalty when Supreme Court clerks refrain from discussing their experiences on the Court); Randall Morck, Behavioral Finance in Corporate Governance-Independent Directors and Non-Executive Chairs, 1500 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 simply put, loyal persons tend to ignore the bad and focus on the good of their object of loyalty, and they do so because it makes them happy. Considering the subjective value of happiness engendered by loyalty, perhaps it should come as no surprise that certain professional athletes identify a duty of loyalty to their team as a rationale for accepting less compensation. To illustrate, consider the decision-making process of St. Louis Cardinals pitcher Matt Morris, who, in signing a three-year, $27 million contract in January 2002, accepted a steep hometown discount.215 At the time, the 26-year old Morris had recently completed a dominant, 22-win season and was eligible to become a free agent at the conclusion of the 2002 season, when he may have obtained twice the salary on the open market.216 Though acknowledging that he “definitely left money on the table,” Morris highlighted a sense of loyalty to the team, particularly since it had “always treated [him] well” and helped him recuperate from injuries.217 For Morris, this sense of loyalty may have been worth $27 million, thus illuminating the material degree of subjective value associable with alternative preferences. Professional athletes also occasionally cite family considerations as a rationale for remaining in a location, as some are willing to sacrifice meaningful compensation in order to stay in close proximity to family members. For instance, during the 2002 MLB season, Tampa Bay Devil Rays’ first baseman Fred McGriff initially refused to waive a no-trade clause in his contract after the team had agreed to trade him to the Chicago Cubs.218 At the time, the Devil Rays were in last place, while the Cubs were positioning themselves for a World Series run. Along with the opportunity to join a contending Harvard Institute Economic Research Discussion Paper 2037, at 3 (2004), available at http://post.economics.harvard.edu/hier/2004papers/HIER2037.pdf (discussing risks of loyalty among corporate officers). 215 See Rick Hummel, Morris Says Cards Were Fair in Negotiations on Contract, ST. LOUIS POST-DISPATCH, Jan. 5, 2002, at 18. 216 Id. In fact, Morris finished third in the balloting for the 2001 Cy Young Award. See Baseball-Reference.com, Awards Voting for 2001, http://www.baseballreference.com/awards/awards_2001.shtml (last visited Jan. 4, 2006); see also Bernie Miklasz, Rams Wouldn’t Mind Meeting “Someone New” in Playoffs, ST. LOUIS POSTDISPATCH, Jan. 5, 2002, at 3 (describing how Morris “could have made a lot more money if he’d waited a season to test the free-agent market”). 217 See Hummel, supra note 215. 218 See Stephen Cannella, Inside Baseball, SPORTS ILLUSTRATED, Aug. 6, 2001, at 70. 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1501 team, the Cubs also offered to raise McGriff’s annual salary from $6.75 million to $7.25 million, as well as extend his contract for an additional year at a salary of $8.5 million—an extraordinary economic conferral for a 39-year old first baseman.219 McGriff, however, posited the value of remaining with his wife and two young children as greater in value than playing for a contender and an enhancement in pay: “I get to see my family all the time [in Tampa]; I’m happy.”220 Nevertheless, such subjective value apparently contained a discernable limit: McGriff agreed to the trade 19 days later, after the Cubs had offered even more money, and apparently to a sufficient level for McGriff to value waiving his no-trade clause over remaining with his family in Tampa.221 2. Environmental Preference: Moving to a Preferable Setting Professional athletes also choose to play in new locales that satisfy certain wants over other opportunities that might pay more. In some instances, professional athletes yearn to return home, or to be close to family; in others, they seek to experience characteristics of the setting, such as favorable weather, cultural offerings, or societal tendencies. Social psychologists sometimes describe the desire to move to a particular location as part of one’s “active agen[cy],” whereby individuals interpret their preferences to be associative of a new locale.222 As evinced by the decision-making methodology of certain free agents, active agency appears highly salient in professional sports. To illustrate, consider the much-queried decision of Utah Jazz power forward and unrestricted free agent Donyell 219 Id. Generally, position players in their late thirties and early forties have difficulty securing such exorbitant contracts. See, e.g., Susan Vinella & John Mangells, Nothing Personal: The Indians’ Analysis Shows It Makes Little Business Sense to Offer Long Contracts to Older Players, PLAIN DEALER, Sept. 22, 2003, at A1. But see Gordon Edes, Dodgers Break Bank to Land Ace Brown, BOSTON GLOBE, Dec. 13, 1998, at E1 (citing concern by Sandy Alderson, executive vice president of baseball operations for Major League Baseball, that players in their late thirties and early forties will eventually obtain lucrative contracts with more regularity). 220 See Bruce Miles, Cubs Not Giving Up Hope on McGriff, CHI. DAILY HERALD, July 13, 2001, at 1 (emphasis added). 221 See Cannella, supra note 218, at 70. McGriff claimed that he ultimately agreed to the trade because he “didn’t want to make a hasty decision. I knew I had time to think about it. I wanted to analyze things.” Id. 222 See Dorothy Rowe, Watching You Watching Me, 10 OPEN MIND 45, 50 (2003). 1502 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Marshall during the 2002 off season: he elected to sign a threeyear, $14 million contract with the Chicago Bulls, even though he was offered a four-year, $27 million contract to stay with the Jazz.223 In explaining his decision, Marshall stated a preference for living in Chicago and experiencing its culture over living in Salt Lake City and continuing to experience its culture, and that such a preference was worth more to him than the significant disparity in pay.224 Paradoxically, that same offseason, Philadelphia 76ers power forward and fellow unrestricted free agent Matt Harpring signed a four-year contract with the Jazz worth $18.5 million, or $2.5 million less than he was offered by the Bulls for the same length of contract.225 In other words, while Marshall was willing to accept less money in order to leave Utah for Chicago, Harpring was willing to take less to move there instead of Chicago. Similarly influential may be preference for warm weather, particularly after playing in cold weather environments for some years. The decision-making process of nose tackle Fred Smerlas in 1990 demonstrated this concept. At the time, Smerlas, who had played the previous eleven seasons with the Buffalo Bills, was an unrestricted free agent in receipt of three offers: a guaranteed, two-year, $1 million offer from the New England Patriots; a non-guaranteed, oneyear, $650,000 offer from the Bills; and a non-guaranteed, oneyear, $500,000 offer from the San Francisco 49ers.226 Smerlas selected the 49ers’ offer, even though it was the least lucrative, 223 See Rich Evans, Marshall Gets Less $$$ to Sign with Chicago, DESERET NEWS, Aug. 17, 2002, at D5. 224 See Lacy J. Banks, Marshall Not Money Hungry, CHI. SUN-TIMES, Aug. 20, 2002, at 99 (quoting Marshall: “One reason was [that Chicago is] centrally located for myself, for my family as well as for [my fiancée’s] family” and, despite passing up $13 million in leaving the Utah Jazz, “[t]his is a decision that is going to . . . make my family happy.”); see also Tim Buckley, No Donyell? Marshall’s Agent Says Talks with Jazz Are Stalled, DESERET MORNING NEWS, July 20, 2002, at D1 (citing comments from Marshall’s agent that his client was concerned about “quality of life” and that he expressed a willingness to accept much less in compensation in order to obtain it elsewhere). The following year, Marshall was traded to the Toronto Raptors. Roman Modrowski, Rose, Davis Headline Bulls-Raptors Trade, CHI. SUN-TIMES, Nov. 30, 2003, at 114. 225 Lacy J. Banks, Harpring Signs with Jazz, CHI. SUN TIMES, Aug. 16, 2002, at 143; see also K.C. Johnson, Summer Snub Doesn’t Faze Harpring, CHI. TRIB., Nov. 24, 2002, at 13 (noting that Harpring also rejected a more lucrative contract to stay with the 76ers). 226 Larry Weisman, Smerlas, 49ers Agree to Terms, USA TODAY, Mar. 29, 1990, at 7C. Although the 49ers’ offer, unlike the offers from the Patriots and Bills, contained the prospect of a bonus, it lacked the guarantee and total value of the Patriots’ offer, and the Bills’ base salary was higher. Id. For those reasons, Smerlas’ agent, Jack Mula, acknowledged “we took less money.” Id. 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1503 and even though it lacked a guarantee.227 According to his representative, Jack Mula, Smerlas valued the “warm weather” of San Francisco in distinguishing between the offers.228 Neither Smerlas nor other professional athletes are especially unique in identifying worth in warm weather; scientific data suggests seasonal and weather changes may affect mood and happiness, thus motivating individuals to pursue settings most compatible with weather preferences.229 Other professional athletes prefer settings that ascribe to normative desires, and that also reflect appealing contrasts to existing conditions. For instance, when free agent outfielder Kirk Gibson signed with the Kansas City Royals in 1990, he declined several offers of greater economic value, reasoning that, after three years of living in Los Angeles, he most preferred a relaxed setting in a relatively small city.230 Similarly, he expressly desired an unhurried culture with midwest values.231 Gibson’s choice suggests that active agency may be fungible, and influenced by mirrored reflections of current conditions. Such a disposition appears corroborative of findings that individuals often proscribe value to new settings, simply because those settings contrast to existing and unfavorable circumstances.232 This is sometimes called the “grass is always greener” phenomenon.233 227 Id. Unlike in the MLB, the NBA, or the NHL, player contracts in the NFL may be non-guaranteed. See generally Adam W. Heller, Creating a Win-Win Situation Through Collective Bargaining: The NFL Salary Cap, 7 SPORTS LAW. J. 375, 389-97 (2000). 228 E-mail from Jack Mula, Chief Administrative Counsel, New England Patriots, to the author (Mar. 30, 2005) (on file with author). 229 See Leo Sher, Seasons and the Brain, 358 LANCET 2092 (2001) (describing research findings pertaining to “seasonal affective disorder,” a disorder causing individuals to become depressed when exposed to prolonged cold or dreary weather); see also Timo Partonen & Jouko Löonnqvist, Seasonal Affective Disorder, 352 LANCET 1369 (1998) (recommending greater exposure to warm weather and sunlight as best remedies to seasonal affective disorder). 230 See Royals Sign Kirk Gibson, UNITED PRESS INT’L, Dec. 1, 1990 (Lexis News Wire). 231 Id. (quoting Gibson, “I guess I’ve always been kind of a country boy. Coming from Los Angeles, I know I’ll never have to sit in six lanes of traffic at 1 o’clock in the afternoon to go six miles in 35 minutes.”). 232 See, e.g., Barbara Millar, Relocation: Where the Grass Is Always Greener, NURS. TIMES, June 14, 2001, at 28, 28-29 (2001) (describing methodology of nurses when they seek to move to new hospitals and new cities); Edilberto O. Pelausa, Moving to America: Is the Grass Really Greener?, 31 J. OTOLARYNGOLOGY 65, 73-75 (2002) (discussing dissonance between expectations and realities for foreign otolaryngologists who move to the United States). 233 Miller, supra note 232, at 29 (on file with author). 1504 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 The allure of playing on a championship-contending team also attracts professional athletes to sacrifice fortune. This is especially apparent among those professional athletes nearing the end of their careers. Consider, for instance, the decision of unrestricted free agent Alonzo Mourning to sign a four-year, $22 million contract with the New Jersey Nets in 2002.234 Though he was presented with a more lucrative offer from the Dallas Mavericks, Mourning believed that playing with the Nets would provide a greater probability of winning a championship.235 In the twilight of his career, Mourning identified particular value in this motivation, as he deemed a championship the critically missing piece of his professional For that reason, Mourning expressed a biography.236 willingness to sacrifice meaningful economic remuneration in exchange for enhanced probability of team success.237 Professional athletes also seek new settings that might enhance perceived personality traits. To illustrate, consider the decision-making process of pitcher Eddie Guardado, who, as an unrestricted free agent in 2003, opted to sign with the Seattle Mariners for less compensation than he was offered by teams in larger media markets, including the Boston Red Sox and the Chicago Cubs.238 Significantly, Guardado articulated a predilection for an environment in which he would “not [be in] the limelight.”239 Similarly, he aspired a setting where media commentary would prove less hurtful to his family.240 Thus, Guardado appeared highly cognizant of the relationship between playing environment and happiness, and he placed corresponding value in that recognition when choosing between offers. 234 Charlie Nobles, Mourning Shows the Rust, but Dreams About the Ring, N.Y. TIMES, July 14, 2003, at D2. 235 See Mike Celizic, Give Nets Credit for Major Coup, MSNBC SPORTS, July 11, 2003, http://msnbc.msn.com/id/3074478/. 236 See Nobles, supra note 234. 237 See Celizic, supra note 235 (quoting Mourning: “[I]t’s not just about the money . . . . It’s about winning, too.”). For a similar instance, consider Brett Hull’s decision to sign with the Detroit Red Wings in 2001. He signed for less because he perceived the opportunity to win a Stanley Cup as more valuable than millions extra in compensation. See Hull Joins Hasek, Robitaille in Detroit, ESPN.COM, Aug. 23, 2001, http://espn.go.com/nhl/news/2001/0821/1242288.html. 238 See Red Sox to Hire Francona Today, SEATTLE TIMES, Dec. 4, 2003, at D2; Mike Dodd, Setup Men Face High-Pressure Relief with Low Pay, USA TODAY, Mar. 26, 2004, at 1C. Guardado signed a three-year, $13 million contract with the Mariners. Dodd, supra, at 1C. 239 Dodd, supra note 238, at 1C. 240 See Red Sox To Hire Francona Today, supra note 238, at D2. 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1505 Lastly, by externally imposing alternate preferences, the families of professional athletes may also influence decision-making of free agent opportunities. Take, for instance, defensive end Sean Jones, who, as an unrestricted free agent in 1996, attracted significant interest from NFL teams.241 He ultimately chose to sign with the Green Bay Packers, even though he was offered more money by other teams.242 Jones revealed that his choice was “pretty much [his] wife’s decision,” as she required that he to play in a city where there would be comparatively few “late night” options for players.243 Indeed, Mrs. Jones wanted assurance that her husband “would be home at a reasonable time of night.”244 3. Risk Aversion A separate, non-geographic rational preference also deserves discussion: risk aversion, or the willingness to pay more money (or accept less money) to avoid participation in a risky activity, even when the expected value of the activity is favorable.245 As captured by the adage, “A bird in hand is worth two in the bush,” risk-aversion signifies that the prospect of losing a dollar already owned weighs more heavily than the More chance of gaining a dollar not yet owned.246 241 David Aldridge, Green Bay’s Low-Key High Life; Big-time Athletes Adjust to Small Town, WASH. POST, Jan. 13, 1996, at F3. 242 Id. 243 Id. 244 Id. For perhaps a similar illustration of familial influence, consider remarks by former Boston Red Sox great Johnny Pesky, for whom Fenway Park’s “Pesky Pole” is named, concerning his decision to sign with the Red Sox in 1940: Back then, you could sign with anybody—there was no draft yet. There were a number of teams interested in me, and some offered more money than Boston. My mother and father wanted me to sign with the Red Sox, though, because their scout brought her flowers when he came to the house—and bourbon for my father. They were immigrants, and even though it was the Depression, that was more important than the extra money. I’m glad it worked out the way it did. David Laurila, Interview with Johnny Pesky, RED SOX NATION, May 29, 2004, http://www.redsoxnation.net/forums/index.php?showtopic=5219. 245 See RICHARD A. BREALEY, AN INTRODUCTION TO RISK AND RETURN FROM COMMON STOCKS 47-54 (1969) (explaining the relationship between risk and value); Lynn M. Stout, Why the Law Hates Speculators: Regulation and Private Ordering in the Market for OTC Derivatives, 48 DUKE. L.J. 701, 736 (1999) (describing how individuals with greater tolerance for risk can reap benefits by accepting risks avoided by others). 246 See JOHN MUELLER, CAN FINANCIAL ASSETS BEAT SOCIAL SECURITY? NOT IN THE REAL WORLD 4 (1997), available at http://heartland.org/pdf/80785B.pdf. See also 1506 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 formalistically then, a risk-averse individual would prefer suffering a certain harm of $100 to suffering a harm of $1,000 with a 10 percent probability of occurring, in spite of their identical expected values.247 Such decision-making manifests itself across economic, political, and legal spectrums, and affects both individual and institutional choices.248 Professional athletes occasionally evince risk aversion in explaining their acquiescence to below-market contract offers. Cleveland Browns quarterback Kelly Holcomb is one such player. Prior to the start of the 2002 NFL season, Holcomb served as the primary backup quarterback to starting quarterback Tim Couch.249 At that time, Holcomb was 29 years old and appeared destined for a career as a backup quarterback.250 The Browns offered him a two-year contract extension worth nearly $2.2 million251, which essentially reflected the going-rate for backup quarterbacks.252 Significantly, Holcomb was set to become an unrestricted free agent at the end of the 2002 season. Considering that typically between 10 and 20 percent of starting quarterbacks miss more than five games each year due to injury, and that a similarly meaningful percentage play poorly and are benched, Holcomb, like any backup quarterback, DONALD N. MCCLOSKEY, THE APPLIED THEORY OF PRICE 65-70 (2d ed. 1985) (providing economic description of risk aversion). 247 See Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Fairness Versus Welfare, 114 HARV. L. REV. 961, 1074 (2001) (explaining risk aversion in the insurance context). See also Mark F. Grady, Proximate Cause and the Law of Negligence, 69 IOWA L. REV. 363, 36667 (1984) (discussing how risk aversion among townspeople affects their preferences for local policies). 248 See Richard Birke, Reconciling Loss Aversion and Guilty Pleas, 1999 UTAH L. REV. 205, 209 (1999) (reconciling risk aversion among criminal defendants with insufficient plea bargain offers by prosecution); Albert J. Boro, Jr., Banking Disclosure Regimes for Regulating Speculative Behavior, 74 CAL. L. REV. 431, 451 (1986) (explaining how fiduciary duties and the threat of legal liability encourages risk aversion among institutional investors); David A. Yalof, Dress Rehearsal Politics and the Case of Earmarked Judicial Nominees, 26 CARDOZO L. REV. 691, 697 (2005) (discussing risk aversion of President Bill Clinton when selecting judicial nominees for federal appellate positions). 249 American Football Conference Team Notes, SPORTING NEWS, July 29, 2002, at 51. 250 Id. (describing Holcomb in rather modest terms, “Kelly Holcomb is a steady backup who won’t win games but won’t lose them either”). 251 See Mary Kay Cabot, Former Browns Pay Disorderly Conduct Fine, PLAIN DEALER, Apr. 30, 2002, at D7 (noting that the contract included a signing bonus of $325,000 and base salaries of $825,000 and $975,000, for a total value of $2,175,000). 252 See, e.g., Mark Eckel, Brian’s Song, TIMES OF TRENTON, Aug. 7, 2005, at C9 (noting that, in 2005, NFL back-up quarterbacks tend to make at least $1.4 million per year). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1507 could have declined a market-value extension, and chosen instead to “gamble” that Couch would either suffer injury or play poorly, thus elevating Holcomb to the starting position.253 Indeed, in light of established NFL precedent, just one start may have offered the opportunity to catapult his market value: quarterback Rob Johnson had only one start in three seasons with the Jacksonville Jaguars between 1996 and 1998, but played very well in the start, prompting the Buffalo Bills to trade for him, and sign him to a five-year, $25 million contract.254 On the other hand, Holcomb was presented with a contract worth almost $2.2 million, and chances were, he would not play more than a few plays during the 2002 season, and thus not elevate his market value. Indeed, Couch had proven remarkably durable, not missing a single start in the 2001 season.255 Moreover, Holcomb recognized the prospect of injury in practice or otherwise during the 2002 season, and would have regretted not signing the extension in the event of such occurrence.256 Presented with these risk assessment variables, Holcomb elected to sign the contract extension.257 During the last preseason game for the Browns in 2002, Holcomb may have suddenly felt regret. In that game, Couch suffered an elbow injury that would cause him to miss the first two games of the regular season. Holcomb went on to start those two games, as well as play in most of the season’s third game, and would play extraordinarily well, throwing nine touchdowns and just two interceptions, while leading the NFL in Quarterback Rating.258 When confronted with speculation as 253 See, e.g., Will McDonough, Ironic Twists in Bledsoe Saga, BOSTON GLOBE, Apr. 28, 2002, at D2 (noting that one or two starting quarterbacks is typically injured in the preseason, and that several others tend to “fail miserably”). 254 See Larry Weisman, Bills’ Playbook a Work in Progress, USA TODAY, Aug. 5, 1998, at 10C. 255 See ESPN.com, Green Bay Packers, # 2 Tim Couch-QB, http://sports.espn.go.com/nfl/players /stats?statsId=4649 (last visited Jan. 4, 2006). 256 For instance, during the 1994 NFL season, Tampa Bay Buccaneers backup quarterback Trent Dilfer was set to ascend to the starting quarterback position, but was injured in practice, thus delaying his ascension. See David Elfin, Growing Pains: Rookies Schuler, Dilfer Find Life Tough in NFL, WASH. TIMES, Dec. 3, 1994, at C1. 257 See Tony Grossi, Holcomb Takes What’s Dealt: Backup Quarterback Doesn’t Regret Signing Contract Extension, PLAIN DEALER, Nov. 17, 2002, at C14. 258 See id. “Quarterback rating” is a composite statistic based on four criteria: 1) percentage of completions per attempt; 2) average yards gained per attempt; 3) percentage of touchdown passes per attempt; and 4) percentage of interceptions per attempt. See NFL Quarterback Rating Formula, NFL News, http://www.nfl.com/news/981202qbrate.html (last visited Jan. 4, 2006). 1508 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 to how much more money he could have earned had he declined the contract extension and pursued free agency, Holcomb noted a conscious internalization of risk: “It’s that old saying, one bird in hand is better than two in the bush.”259 In other words, by signing the contract extension, Holcomb prescribed subjective value to the nullification of risk, and that subjective value was worth more to him than the difference in objective value between the contract extension and his prospective free agent status, discounted by risk of injury, poor performance, or other impairments of play.260 Risk aversion also emerges when players attempt to forecast market changes. For instance, when former Red Sox outfielder Mike Greenwell declined to elect for free agency in 1994, and instead surprisingly agreed to a two-year, $7.3 million contract extension, he highlighted a market strategy Specifically, Greenwell based on his risk preferences.261 anticipated that because of public outrage associated with the baseball players’ strike in 1994, fans would soon turn away from baseball in droves, thus contracting the value of the game and leading to diminished player salaries.262 Consequently, Greenwell perceived a discounted contract in an existing market as more valuable than a market-value contract in an uncertain and future market. Unfortunately for Greenwell, his market projections would prove largely erroneous. Even though MLB player salaries dipped 1.3 percent from 1994 to 1995,263 they increased by 3.5 percent from 1995 to 1996, followed by a 17.0 percent Nevertheless, his expressed surge from 1996 to 1997.264 259 Id. Recent economic analysis suggests that risk aversion among professional athletes also affects contracting of off-court responsibilities, such as extent of team monitoring of player activities. See Örn B. Bodvarsson & Raymond T. Brastow, Do Employers Pay for Consistent Performance?: Evidence from the NBA, 36 ECON. INQUIRY 145, 152-58 (1998). 261 See Greenwell Remains in Red Sox Tradition, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 17, 1994, at B12. 262 See Nick Cafardo, Greenwell Not Holding a Grudge, BOSTON GLOBE, Apr. 3, 1995, at 46 (quoting Greenwell: “People were wondering . . . why I took the offer they made. Well, I’m not that stupid. I’m a little smarter than people think. I knew what was coming. Right now, I’m extremely happy I signed the contract that I did when I did.”). 263 See Baseball Salary Decline, WASH. POST, Apr. 30, 1995, at D6 (also noting that while many players took pay cuts following the strike of 1994, the top stars continued to observe their salaries surge considerably). 264 See Erik Brady & David Leon Moore, Big Sports, Bigger Bucks: Just How High Can Players’ Salaries Go?, USA TODAY, Apr. 3, 1997, at 1A. 260 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1509 rationale for negotiating a below-market value contract extension suggested a conscious, tactical strategy based on risk preferences. C. Evidence of Cognitive Biases and Heuristics The preceding subsection described alternative preferences among professional athletes when contemplating employment opportunities. In doing so, it largely endorsed rational choice theory: individuals appear to rank preferences, and then, as reflected in their choices, maximize those preferences in their decision-making process. Thus, when professional athletes choose a “discount” offer, it simply reflects a conscious ranking of non-monetary preferences ahead of remunerative preferences. Doubtless, a rational choice model strikes an appealing rubric, since it more broadly suggests that individuals act rationally when making decisions, and that such decisions reflect conscious preferences. Moreover, given societal skepticism towards the intellectual capacity of most professional athletes,265 typical individuals might infer confidence from the capacity of professional athletes to engage in rational decision-making. In short, based on the rationalchoices of professional athletes, individuals appear to possess not only the capacity to navigate through difficult professional decisions, but also the tendency to select the “optimal” choice. This analysis, however, is incomplete. Indeed, as discussed in Section III, cognitive biases and heuristics, unbeknownst to decision-makers, frequently disturb decisionmaking processes. Perhaps then it should come as no surprise that professional athletes appear likewise influenced by choice distortions. 1. Framing Effects Framing effects suggest that varied wording of equallyvaluable options can induce individuals into valuing them differently.266 How might framing effects influence professional 265 See Timothy Davis, The Myth of the Superspade: The Persistence of Racism in College Athletics, 22 FORDHAM URB. L.J. 615, 631 (1995) (describing how, even when they evince high intellectual capacity, collegiate athletes are frequently discouraged by scholastic advisors from taking “hard” classes, and instead enrolled in less burdensome courses). 266 See discussion supra p. 1470 and accompanying notes. 1510 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 athletes when selecting employment opportunities? Consider the influence of team negotiators, such as general managers or owners, and how some adroitly utilize invention, red herrings, and props to spawn illusory distinctions. Framing effects among professional teams are especially evident in the NBA, where salaries have maximum limits, meaning that teams often extend identical offers to premiere free agents.267 Without the potential of distinguishing financial terms, NBA teams routinely employ aggressive recruiting tactics, and these tactics sometimes amplify trivial distinctions. For instance, when the Chicago Bulls courted unrestricted free agents in the summer of 2001, they arranged for a band, assorted mascots, and numerous front office officials to greet each player upon his arrival at O’Hare International Airport.268 Bulls’ general manager Jerry Krause had hoped that such a marketing strategy would frame the Bulls as a franchise of particular “substance” and player care.269 Similarly, to promote distinction in relative levels of interest, NBA general managers are known to call free agents at the very first moment when teams are allowed to contact free agents. This moment usually occurs at 12:01 A.M. of an early July morning.270 Occasionally, this strategy appears influential in free agents’ decision-making. For instance, in explaining his decision to sign with the New York Knicks in 2004, free agent guard Jamal Crawford highlighted an enthusiastic phone call that he had received from New York Knicks’ general manager Isiah Thomas at the very first moment when teams could contact free agents.271 Crawford 267 See discussion supra pp. 1488-89 and accompanying notes. See Lacy J. Banks, Krause Made the Right Call Targeting Jones, CHI. SUNTIMES, July 14, 2000, at 138. 269 Id. This strategy did not work, however, as none of the five primary free agents Krause pursued (i.e., Tim Duncan, Tracy McGrady, Grant Hill, Eddie Jones, and Tim Thomas) signed with the Bulls, and they instead chose identical offers from other teams. See Fred Mitchell, Local Agent Discounts Talk of Anti-Bulls Conspiracy, CHI. TRIB., Dec. 12, 2000, at N3. 270 This date varies, depending upon the NBA calendar, but usually occurs between July 1 and July 15. 271 See Mike Lupica, Isiah Giving Crawford His Shot to Score with Fans, DAILY NEWS (New York), Nov. 3, 2004, at 74. Perhaps more often, however, this strategy proves immaterial. See, e.g., Mark Montieth, O’Neal to Visit Spurs, INDIANAPOLIS STAR, July 2, 2003, at 1D (noting that although Isiah Thomas personally called unrestricted free agents Jermaine O’Neal and Reggie Miller, neither of them signed with the Knicks); Liz Robbins, Kidd’s a Free Agent, and Phones Ring, N.Y. TIMES, July 2, 2003, at D6 (describing unsuccessful efforts by the Dallas Mavericks and San Antonio Spurs to recruit free agent Jason Kidd, and that such efforts entailed calling him at 12:01 A.M.). 268 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1511 regarded the call as instrumental in helping him distinguish between identical offers.272 Framing effects also emerge in other professional sports contexts, albeit more conjecturally. For instance, when the New York Mets successfully pursued free agent pitcher Pedro Martinez in 2004, Mets’ general manager Omar Minaya is thought to have intimated to Martinez that since he, like Martinez, was of Dominican descent, Martinez could “trust” him more than Theo Epstein, Minaya’s counterpart on the Boston Red Sox and for whom Martinez had been playing.273 Such fact patterns undermine the rational choice model, and suggest that choices may not reflect a pristine maximization of utility or relative strength of preferences, but rather vulnerability to unappreciated factors, such as sales pitches and manipulative overtures. 2. Confirmation Bias Similarly influential is the effect of confirmation bias, whereby individuals are subject to ignore or discount information that challenges existing beliefs.274 This disposition occasionally arises when professional athletes encounter a uniquely positive experience on a particular team, and are thereafter prone to positively interpret ambiguous circumstances and to dismiss negative associations. Since they are prone to misinterpret signals and cues, professional athletes affected by confirmation bias may unknowingly dismiss salient—and thus valuable—distinguishing characteristics. 272 Lupica, supra note 270, at 74. See Filip Bondy, Pedro Plays N.Y. Way in City, Everyone Has Own Set of Rules, DAILY NEWS (New York), Dec. 17, 2004, at 104; see also Gordon Edes, Martinez Is Starting Already in Mets Camp, He’s Starting Already!, BOSTON GLOBE, Feb. 16, 2005, at F1 (citing remarks by Martinez that he gave his word to Minaya while he could not do the same to Epstein, who he believed—in spite of facts supporting the opposite conclusion—was not genuinely interested in re-signing him). 274 See Hanson & Kysar, The Problem of Market Manipulation, supra note 16, at 647-50. A corollary to confirmation bias is “self-serving” or “egocentric” biases, whereby individuals interpret information in a way that disproportionately favors their own position. Unlike confirmation bias, however, self-serving or egocentric biases are likely consciously present. See Guthrie, Framing Frivolous Litigation, supra note 55, at 206 n.199 (noting that these biases may increase plaintiffs’ risk in seeking frivolous litigation); see also Linda Babcock & George Loewenstein, Explaining Bargaining Impasse: The Role of Self-Serving Biases, 11 J. ECON PERSPECTIVES 109 (1997) (discussing the impact of self-serving biases on settlements). 273 1512 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 To illustrate, consider the events that led to Jermaine O’Neal’s decision to re-sign with the Indiana Pacers in 2003. O’Neal’s NBA career began in 1996, when he was drafted by the Portland Trailblazers.275 After four unspectacular seasons, O’Neal was traded to the Pacers.276 As a Pacer, O’Neal developed a close bond with head coach Isiah Thomas, who devoted much of his time to O’Neal and helped him become a star. In fact, O’Neal would call Thomas his “father figure.”277 Besides his on-court instruction, Thomas would also serve O’Neal as an emotional buffer, as best evidenced by Thomas’ counseling of O’Neal after the player’s stepfather attempted suicide by shooting himself in the head—in O’Neal’s presence— in 2002.278 The O’Neal-Thomas relationship emerged as mutually beneficial. Indeed, O’Neal would often rush to the defense of Thomas, whose coaching strategies were widely-criticized and whose teams often appeared underachieving.279 For instance, when doubts were raised of Thomas’ competence, O’Neal would regularly characterize his coach as a victim of unrealistic expectations, saddled by prior management decisions that created an on-going re-building process.280 Such comments bewildered many observers, as the Pacers were generally regarded as one of the league’s most talented teams, and one 275 See Ken Vance, Blazers President Not Afraid of Change, COLUMBIAN (Vancouver, WA), June 30, 1996, at C1. 276 See Brian Meehan, O’Neal Becoming a Force on the Court for Indiana, OREGONIAN, Nov. 26, 2000, at C11. 277 See Lacy Banks, Pacers in Limbo After Firing Thomas, CHI. SUN-TIMES, Aug. 29, 2003, at 166 (quoting O’Neal: “[Thomas] was more than a coach to me. He was like a father.”); Mark Montieth, Lineup Shuffle Puts Strickland on Court, INDIANAPOLIS STAR, Jan. 7, 2003, at 4D (quoting O’Neal: “It’s like a father-son relationship”); Christian Red, O’Neal Gets Over Axing of Thomas, DAILY NEWS (New York), Feb. 4, 2004, at 48. 278 See Sekou Smith, Rising to the Occasion, INDIANAPOLIS STAR, Mar. 25, 2003, at 1D (describing how Thomas went to the emergency room to counsel O’Neal the night of his step-father’s attempted suicide). 279 See Bob Ryan, As Game 5 Beckons, Consider These Salient Topics on the Indiana-Boston Series 5 Points—Ok, Actually Five Observations on Basketball with a Bonus Entertainment Topic Thrown In, BOSTON GLOBE, Apr. 29, 2003, at F1 (describing the Pacers as one of the worst-coached teams in the NBA, particularly with their bizarre substitution patterns); see also Steve Bulpett, Celts Earn Playoff Berth by Default, BOSTON HERALD, Apr. 12, 2004, at 82 (criticizing Thomas for his coaching strategies against inferior Celtics teams that nevertheless beat the Thomas-coached Pacers). 280 See Mark Monteith, O’Neal: I’ll Play Only for Thomas, INDIANAPOLIS STAR, May 2, 2003, at 1D (quoting O’Neal: “This is still a learning process. Isiah’s got a team competing at a high level with a lot of guys who hadn’t played in the past. Isiah inherited a team that he didn’t put together but he’s winning with it.”). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1513 led by seasoned veterans, such as Reggie Miller and Brad Miller; a “rebuilding team” they were not.281 The 2002-03 season would prove to be a pivotal one for the O’Neal-Thomas relationship. First, consider that the Pacers lost 19 of their last 30 regular season games, and then, in a dismal showing, lost to the Boston Celtics in the first round of the 2003 NBA Playoffs.282 Following the playoff series, media and even Pacers’ players harshly criticized Thomas for his coaching strategies.283 Then, in May 2003, Pacers team president Donnie Walsh announced that Thomas would not receive a contract extension, a significant proclamation considering that Thomas had only one year left on his four-year contract, and a team declination of a coaching extension typically foretells a forthcoming coaching dismissal.284 Only making matters more dubious for Thomas, in early July 2003, the Pacers hired a new president of basketball operations, Larry Bird—a personal and professional archrival of Thomas—who immediately announced major organizational changes on the horizon.285 Along those lines, speculation quickly arose that Bird would replace Thomas with Rick Carlisle, Bird’s close friend and former Detroit Pistons’ head coach.286 In fact, only a year earlier, Bird had opined that if Carlisle, rather than Thomas, were the Pacers’ coach, the team would “be 10 to 20 percent better.”287 Accordingly, by all objective measures, the future of Thomas as Pacers’ head coach appeared very bleak in July 2003. For O’Neal, Thomas’ impending demise proved of great relevance, as he was set to become an unrestricted free agent 281 See, e.g., Al Iannazzone, Isiah Pining for Pacers, THE RECORD (Bergen County, NJ), Feb. 3, 2004, at S6 (describing Pacers 2002-03 squad as one that, “by most accounts, underachieved”); Doug Smith, Raptors “Open to All Discussions” at Draft, HAMILTON SPECTATOR (Ontario, Canada), May 28, 2003, at E5 (describing Pacers as “underachieving”). 282 See Peter May, Doubts on Thomas, BOSTON GLOBE, Apr. 30, 2003, at F8. 283 Id. (identifying complaints among players concerning unpredictable substitution patterns, with players receiving significant minutes in one game, and then no minutes in the next). 284 Id. 285 See Sekou Smith, Off and Running: Bird Identifies Pacers’ Faults, Wants Solutions, INDIANAPOLIS STAR, July 12, 2003, at 1D [hereinafter Smith, Off and Running]. 286 See Mark Monteith, “Isiah Thomas Is the Coach”; Carlisle Says He’s Pursuing TV Analyst Jobs, Not Pacers’ Position, INDIANAPOLIS STAR, July 13, 2003, at 5C. 287 See Jackie MacMullan, For Playoffs, Bird Still a Green Backer, BOSTON GLOBE, Apr. 18, 2002, at E1. 1514 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 on July 1, 2003.288 Despite Thomas’ precarious status, O’Neal expressed interest in re-signing with the Pacers, but as a precondition, he insisted that Thomas remain the coach.289 In response, Bird stated only that he had no immediate plans to make a coaching change, which O’Neal interpreted as unwavering confidence by Bird in Thomas.290 In contrast, most observers not only interpreted Bird’s comments as lukewarm support, but that Thomas would be retained only until O’Neal re-signed or signed elsewhere.291 Nevertheless, O’Neal chose to re-sign with the Pacers—a mere five days after Bird’s hiring.292 Less than a month later, Bird fired Thomas as head coach, and replaced him with Carlisle.293 Observers described the move as one of the most predictable coaching changes in recent NBA history.294 O’Neal perceived it a bit differently. He expressed shock and displeasure, and claimed that he had been “deceived” by Bird into signing the contract extension.295 He also stated that he would not have re-signed had he known that Thomas was going to be fired.296 O’Neal’s decision-making process appeared strikingly incongruous with both available information and his stipulated preferences for re-signing with the Pacers. Along those lines, O’Neal appeared to discount myriad informational sources that challenged his core belief, namely that Thomas would remain as his head coach, mentor, and father-figure. Even arguably ambiguous information, such as speculation of Bird’s fondness 288 See David DuPree, Big Names Are in Position for Free-Agent Free-for-All, USA TODAY, July 1, 2003, at 6C. 289 See Mark Monteith, Pacers’ Star Player Welcomes New Boss, INDIANAPOLIS STAR, July 12, 2003, at 8D [hereinafter Monteith, Pacers’ Star Welcomes New Boss]. 290 Monteith, Pacers’ Star Player Welcomes New Boss, supra note 289; Smith, Off and Running, supra note 285. 291 See, e.g., Jemal Horton, Bird and Thomas See a Future Together, INDIANAPOLIS STAR, July 12, 2003, at 1A (noting “myriad reasons to figure that Thomas’ days as the Pacers’ head coach were numbered”). 292 Mark Monteith, O’Neal Makes It Official: Pacers Forward Signs Huge 7Year Contract, INDIANAPOLIS STAR, July 17, 2003, at 1D. 293 See Dave Lewandowski, Isiah Ousted, Carlisle Courted, INDIANAPOLIS STAR, Aug. 28, 2003, at 1A. 294 See, e.g., Michael Lee, Inside the NBA, ATLANTA J.-CONST., Aug. 29, 2003, (regarding move as not surprising to any objective observer); Tom Enlund, Carlisle Clearly Was Saving Himself for Pacers All Along, MILWAUKEE J. SENTINEL, Sept. 7, 2003, at 19C (stating that Thomas’ “days with the team were numbered” following the hiring of Bird). 295 See Bob Kravitz, O’Neal Could Have Handled the Truth, INDIANAPOLIS STAR, Aug. 29, 2003, at 1D. 296 See Patrick Hruby, Coming Attractions; NBA Ready to Go Reel-to-Reel in 2003-04, WASH. TIMES, Oct. 28, 2003, at C1. 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1515 for Carlisle, was dismissed by O’Neal with ease. Thus, O’Neal appeared to unknowingly impair his own capacity to maximize choice: though he enunciated meaningful subjective value in playing for the Pacers only if Thomas was the coach, he either disregarded or misread evidence indicating that Thomas would not be the coach. Thus, when Thomas was dismissed, such impairment of preference-maximization dismayed O’Neal, as he had unknowingly suppressed the internalization of salient and distinguishing characteristics. 3. Optimism Bias Optimism bias likewise provides a useful mode of heuristic analysis by which to gauge decision-making among professional athletes, and how they may not always utilize rational choice. As discussed in Section III, optimism bias reflects the tendency of individuals to assume that general risks do not apply with equal force to themselves.297 Thus, when contemplating employment opportunities, might professional athletes overestimate the probability of positive outcomes and underestimate the probability of negative outcomes? Evidence for optimism bias sometimes emerges when professional athletes weigh the relative risk of incentive-laden contracts versus guaranteed contracts, with the former naturally offering greater potential for reward—and loss. For instance, consider the choice of New Orleans Saints’ running back Ricky Williams in 1999 to agree to an eight-year contract worth between $11 million and $68 million, depending upon his capacity to reach certain incentives.298 At the time, Williams was the fifth overall selection in the 1999 NFL Draft and was negotiating his first NFL contract. As a useful juxtaposition to Williams’ decision-making process, consider that of fellow rookie running back Edgerrin James, who was selected by the Indianapolis Colts with the fourth overall selection and was likewise negotiating his first NFL contract.299 In striking contrast to Williams’ incentive-laden contract, James agreed to a seven-year contract worth between $44 million and $49 297 See discussion supra pp. 1471-72. Mark Wiedmer, Maybe Ricky Should Lose Master P, CHATTANOOGA TIMES FREE PRESS, Aug. 26, 1999, at D1. 299 See id. 298 1516 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 million, with incentives primarily affecting Williams’ potential to void the last year of the contract.300 For two players selected at almost the same point in the NFL Draft, the Williams and James contracts appeared of exceptionally disparate values. In fact, performance projections estimated that Williams would earn at least $30 million less than James over the course of the contract.301 Indeed, for Williams to obtain much of his annual salary, he needed to amass at least 1,600 rushing yards each season, a feat that had only been accomplished by 15 players in the NFL’s 134-year history, and only once by a Saints’ running back in the franchise’s 33-year history.302 As a result of his apparent “bad gamble,” Williams bore the brunt of considerable ridicule.303 In explaining his decision, Williams reasoned that because he believed that he should have been the number one overall selection in the NFL Draft—and thus have warranted a more lucrative contract—the only way for him “to make that kind of money” was to agree to such a heavily-leveraged contract.304 As to the contract’s seemingly quixotic performance thresholds, Williams appeared undeterred, reasoning that if he performed to his potential, he would readily attain them.305 Further suggestive of optimism bias, Williams maintained this confidence even after seriously spraining his ankle a week prior to the start of his rookie season.306 Separately, Williams rationalized the contract by stating that he would use off-field promotional earnings to offset any opportunity costs triggered 300 See News Summaries, Colts Sign James to Seven-Year Deal, SPORTS NETWORK, Aug. 13, 1999. 301 See Wiedmer, supra note 297. See also Peter King, Inside the NFL, SPORTS ILLUSTRATED, Aug. 23, 1999, at 48 (noting that, based on probable performance, James would likely earn $11 million more than Williams over their first three seasons). 302 King, supra note 301, at 48; Rick Reilly, Ricky Williams, You Got Taken, but Good, SPORTS ILLUSTRATED, Aug. 9, 1999, at 100 (describing the contract as the worst contract in NFL history). 303 See, e.g., Ron Borges, Williams Giving Saints, Fans New Incentive, BOSTON GLOBE, June 20, 1999, at D4 (noting ridicule from agents); Reilly, supra note 302, at 100; Michael Silver, Rappin’ on the Door, SPORTS ILLUSTRATED, July 19, 1999, at 82 (citing mocking commentary from agents and NFL executives of the contract). 304 See Camping with Ricky, TIMES-PICAYUNE (New Orleans), Aug. 5, 1999, at D2. 305 Id. 306 See Don Pierson, Williams, Saints Go Limping In, CHI. TRIB., Aug. 27, 1999, at N1 (citing remarks by Williams that he believed he would obtain the 1,600rushing-yard-per-season milestone even if he missed two out of the sixteen regular season games). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1517 by unobtainable incentives (without apparently realizing that such off-field earnings would have been available irrespective of contract type).307 As predicted by most observers, Williams’ decision proved remarkably unwise. Though he ranked among the top 10 running backs in rushing yards during his first three seasons, he failed to reach most of the onerous performance standards necessary for incentive payment. As a result, he earned far below his market value.308 This proved most evident in his third season, when despite setting his franchise’s fourthhighest single-season record for rushing yards, and despite being named his team’s “most valuable player,” he earned only $389,000.309 To put this figure in perspective, consider that thirty-three of his fifty Saints’ teammates earned more that season,310 or that James—who rushed for fewer yards—earned slightly more than $7 million.311 The costly effect of Williams’ optimism bias begs an important question for assessing decision-making among professional athletes: How can player representatives diminish optimism bias and other cognitive biases when their clients seek patently unfavorable terms? In the case of Williams, a fatal negotiating defect may have existed to prevent such diminishment, as his representative, Percy Miller, had never before represented a professional football player.312 Indeed, Miller himself appeared the victim of optimism bias, as he dauntlessly assigned the drafting of technical, contractual language to a personal aide who had never before drafted a contract.313 Nevertheless, more seasoned agents may prove capable in discouraging players from desiring detrimental agreements.314 In the alternative, 307 See Kevin B. Blackistone, Give Saints’ Williams Credit for His Play-for-Pay Contract, DALLAS MORNING NEWS, Aug. 15, 1999, at 5B (quoting Williams: “I’m going to make a lot of money off the field, and I can use that as my salary.”). 308 See Silver, supra note 303. 309 See Brad Townsend, Unmasked: His Social Phobia in the Open, Williams Tries to Pull off Move, Dallas Morning News, Aug. 12, 2002, at 1B. See also New Orleans Saints Total Rushing Records, http://www.neworleanssaints.com/ custompage.cfm?pageid=72 (last visited Jan. 4, 2006). 310 See Townsend, supra note 309. 311 Id.; USA Today Salary Database: Edgerrin James, Dec. 10, 2003, http://asp.usatoday.com/sports/football/nfl/salaries/playerdetail.aspx?lname=J&player= 1162. 312 See Reilly, supra note 302. 313 See Silver, supra note 303 (describing work by Leland Hardy). 314 See generally Willenbacher, supra note 142 (discussing norms for agent behavior). 1518 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 and as vividly illustrated by Williams, professional athletes may fail to internalize critical components of the decisionmaking process, and thus ultimately pursue the non-optimal strategy. 4. Hindsight Bias and Regret Aversion Hindsight bias also appears salient in the decisionmaking of professional athletes. As discussed in Section III, hindsight bias refers to the tendency to overestimate anticipated fruition of a particular event.315 In the context of professional sports, hindsight bias may arise when athletes accept “hometown discounts” for unrealized reasons and then later rationalize those contracts on the occurrence of unanticipated events. To illustrate, consider the varying, and potentially competing rationales offered by John Flaherty in 1999, and then in 2002, regarding his decision to sign a discounted contract extension with the Tampa Devil Rays. The narrative begins in 1999, when Flaherty weighed whether to sign a three-year, $9 million contract extension or enter free agency. On one hand, Flaherty could have entered free agency as one of the premiere catchers available, and able to secure a contract far in excess of a three-year, $9 million term.316 Moreover, at age 31, and after a career of relatively modest earnings, Flaherty may have viewed free agency as a singular earnings opportunity.317 Indeed, until an unusually impressive 1999 season, Flaherty had primarily served as a back-up player who had earned not much more than the major league minimum.318 On the other hand, Flaherty perceived subjective value in playing on a winning team, with veteran star players, and in a regularly sold-out home stadium.319 According to Flaherty, 315 See discussion supra pp. 1474-75. See Marc Topkin, Flaherty Signs on for One More Hitch with Devil Rays, ST. PETERSBURG TIMES, Sept. 28, 1999, at 1C. See also John Romano, Flaherty Earns Chance with Another Team, ST. PETERSBURG TIMES, May 20, 2002, at 1C (revealing commentary from Devil Rays’ officials that they thought Flaherty was “selling himself short” by agreeing to the extension, and when he did, they “congratulated themselves on tying up an important position on the field at a reasonable salary”). 317 See Topkin, supra note 316. 318 See Bob Dick, Flaherty Becomes Big Hit, PROVIDENCE J., Aug. 6, 1996, at 1D (discussing Flaherty’s struggles); Kevin Wells, Flaherty Impressive on, off Field, TAMPA TRIB., Nov. 30, 1997, at 11 (discussing success of Flaherty in the 1996 and particularly 1997 seasons). 319 See Topkin, supra note 316, at 1C. 316 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1519 those characteristics appeared associable with the Devil Rays, as the team had recently re-signed star first baseman Fred McGriff and had expressed interest in obtaining other star players.320 Thus Flaherty predicted the Devil Rays would excel.321 Indeed, Flaherty praised the “commitment” evidenced by both Devil Rays’ management and ownership in developing a “championship” strategy.322 Taking account of these reasons, Flaherty found the Devil Rays’ contract offer sufficiently attractive, and despite its sub-market value, opted to sign it.323 Unfortunately for Flaherty, the Devils Ray would not win many games from 2000 to 2002. In fact, not only did the Devil Rays place last in their division in each of those seasons, but from 2001 to 2002, the team compiled the worst record of any of the 30 major league teams.324 Moreover, despite promises of pursuing star players, the Devil Rays featured the Not lowest payroll in baseball from 2000 to 2002.325 surprisingly then, the team attracted minimal fan interest, and because of poor revenue, even encountered difficulty meeting payroll commitments.326 In short, the subjective value Flaherty attributed to playing on a winning team, and one with star players and devoted fans, never materialized over the course of his contract. During the 2002 season—which represented the third and final year of Flaherty’s contract—Flaherty was asked whether he regretted signing the contract extension. After-all, his stated reasons for accepting a “hometown” discount never materialized. Perhaps surprisingly, Flaherty expressed no regret.327 Instead, he inferred that upon signing the contract, he had looked forward to serving as a mentor to young and inexperienced players, since he anticipated that such activities would prove valuable to him.328 Thus, Flaherty offered an 320 Id. Id. 322 Id. 323 See Bill Chastain, Flaherty in the Fold, TAMPA TRIB., Sept. 28, 1999, at 5. 324 See Dick Scanlon, Piniella Set to Captain Devil Ray’s Shaky Ship, LEDGER (Lakeland, Fla.), Oct. 29, 2002, at A1. 325 See Chris Anderson, Sweet Lou Is Home, SARASOTA HERALD-TRIB., Oct. 29, 2002, at C1. 326 See Carter Gaddis & Joe Henderson, Naimoli: Rays Won’t Miss Making Payroll, TAMPA TRIB., May 13, 2001, at 1. 327 See Romano, supra note 316, at 1C (quoting Flaherty: “Do I regret signing that contract? Hell no.”). 328 See Carter Gaddis, Veterans Bring Wisdom to Rays, TAMPA TRIB., Sept. 22, 2002, at 5 (quoting Flaherty: “I will look forward to the day when a winner does show 321 1520 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 entirely different subjective rationale for signing a sub-market value contract than he had expressed in 1999. Beyond its variance, such a rationale was likely incompatible, as seldom do winning teams with veteran star players feature young and inexperienced players.329 As illustrated by Flaherty, hindsight bias may distort one’s capacity to objectively evaluate prior decision-making and pursuit of preferences. As a result, it may impair redress of any defects within the decision-making process, a troubling outcome for athletes since many enter into subsequent series of negotiations. This phenomenon is only exacerbated by regret aversion, or the tendency among those prone to hindsight bias to resist information concerning forgone conclusions or hypothetical outcomes.330 Indeed, regret aversion offers further explanation for Flaherty’s unwillingness to acknowledge regret and for his substituted rationales: by shifting discussion from preferable and forgone alternatives to inferior and existing circumstances, Flaherty avoided discussion of information that might have triggered feelings of regret and unhappiness. Prescriptively then, while hindsight bias offered Flaherty an alternative rationale, regret aversion offered the means by which to discuss it. 5. Anchoring and Adjustment Effects The failure to adjust for new information may also impair rational-decision making among professional athletes. As discussed in Section III, psychologists often describe this tendency as “anchoring and adjustment” or “belief perseverance.”331 In professional sports, athletes negotiating contracts sometimes appear anchored to certain monetary values, particularly when negotiations occur during market fluctuations. Such anchoring may not only promote acrimonious negotiations, but also inferior outcomes. To illustrate, consider the futile efforts of shortstop Nomar Garciaparra and the Boston Red Sox to consummate a contract extension during the 2003 and 2004 MLB seasons. up out on that field and I’ll feel like in a small way . . . not that I’m part of it, but it’ll be very gratifying to see.”). 329 See, e.g., Joe Strauss, Hitting the Road, Eyeing Direction, BALT. SUN, July 12, 2001, at 1D (discussing difficulties of winning with young and inexperienced players). 330 See discussion supra p. 1475. 331 See discussion supra p. 1477. 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1521 The genesis of those negotiations traces back to March 1998, when, as second-year player, Garciaparra agreed to a five-year contract with the Red Sox that included team options for the 2003 and 2004 seasons.332 All together, the contract offered to pay Garciaparra $44 million between 1998 and 2004.333 At the time, observers regarded the contract as highly generous for a player of his experience, though its length also posed risk to Garciaparra, particularly given the rapid growth of player salaries in the late 1990s.334 Moreover, by enabling the Red Sox to control his rights in the 2003 and 2004 seasons, Garciaparra surrendered two years in which he could have elected to become a free agent.335 By 2000, Garciaparra, Alex Rodriguez of the Seattle Mariners, and Derek Jeter of the New York Yankees, were widely-regarded as the three best shortstops in baseball.336 Indeed, because of their similar talent, production, and age, they were often clustered together in baseball discussion.337 However, between the 2000 and 2001 seasons, the three would become compensated at highly variable levels. Indeed, Rodriguez would sign a 10-year, $252 million free agent contract with the Texas Rangers,338 and Jeter—who was set to become a free agent at the end of the 2001 season—would agree to a 10-year, $189 million contract extension with the New York Yankees.339 In contrast, Garciaparra would remain under contract to the Red Sox through 2004, during which time he would earn $32 million.340 Observers immediately described Garciaparra as wildly underpaid, because despite their similar 332 See Michael Silverman & Tony Massarotti, Nomar on the Money, BOSTON HERALD, March 11, 1998, at 100. 333 Id. 334 See Sean McAdam, Garciaparra Gets a $23.5 Million Pact, PROVIDENCE J.BULL., Mar. 11, 1998, at 1D. 335 Id. 336 See, e.g., Larry Lage, Deivi Cruz Not Known for Control, SOUTH BEND TRIB., Mar. 1, 2001, at B1 (describing the three best shortstops as Rodriguez, Jeter, and Garciaparra). 337 Id. 338 See Jay Weiner, Good for A-Rod, Bad for Baseball, BUS. WEEK, Dec. 18, 2000, at 59. 339 See Brad Biggs, Millions Not Enough: Latest Contracts Have Spawned Disgruntlement Among Stars Stuck in Long-Term Deals, CHI. SUN-TIMES, Feb. 26, 2001, at 89. 340 See Silverman & Massarotti, supra note 332, at 100. 1522 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 talent, production, and age, Rodriguez and Jeter would earn three to four times as much.341 Unfortunately for Garciaparra, the exorbitant contracts secured by Rodriguez and Jeter likely represented the apex of a prior market. Indeed, the sheer size of such contracts is thought to have triggered a backlash among MLB owners, which subsequently diminished their willingness to spend so unreservedly.342 Consequently, over the following two years, free agents tended to secure significantly less lucrative contracts than they would have previously secured.343 Undeterred by this apparent market contraction, Garciaparra approached the Red Sox in March 2003 about a contract extension that would pay him commensurate with Rodriguez and Jeter.344 In fact, since the Rodriguez and Jeter contracts paid annual average salaries of $25.2 million and $18.9 million, respectively, Garciaparra informed the Red Sox that he would accept no less than $17.0 million per year.345 Red Sox management had a different idea of Garciaparra’s value, however, reasoning that the Rodriguez and Jeter contracts no longer represented market value for premiere shortstops.346 Indeed, as Red Sox management noted, no player, of any position, had signed a contract paying in excess of $15 million per season during the previous two years.347 Instead of meeting Garciaparra’s demand, the Red Sox offered him a four-year 341 See, e.g., Jon Heyman, These Two Red Sox Are Exceptions to the Rule, NEWSDAY (New York), Feb. 28, 2001, at A71; Bob Hohler, Martinez Extends Advice to Duquette, BOSTON GLOBE, Dec. 23, 2000, at F3; Michael Silverman, Sox Cash In—Get Off Cheap with Nomar, BOSTON HERALD, Jan. 20, 2000, at 88. 342 See Tom Haudricourt, Huge Salaries Not Trickling Down to Journeymen Players, MILWAUKEE J. SENTINEL, Feb. 3, 2002, at 15C (describing market correction during off season between 2001 and 2002 seasons); Mike Klis, This Time, Collusion Too Tough to Unearth Superstar’s Big Contracts, DENVER POST, Feb. 2, 2003, at C5 (noting sentiment among free agent players that the owners were colluding to create a market correction during off season between 2002 and 2003 seasons). 343 Klis, supra note 342. See also Hal Bodley, 94 Strike: Lesson Learned?, USA TODAY, Sept. 13, 2004, at 1D (noting that from 2002 to 2003, free agent salaries declined by 3 percent). 344 See Michael Silverman, Breaking Up Is Hard to Do, SPORTING NEWS, Aug. 2, 2004, at 10 (discussing “failed contract negotiations” between Garciaparra and the Red Sox during spring training in 2003). 345 See Jeff Horrigan, Sox Upped the Ante, BOSTON HERALD, Aug. 4, 2004, at 90; see also Tony Massarotti, Nomar: I Want to Stay, BOSTON HERALD, Dec. 8, 2003, at 120 (citing salaries for Rodriguez and Jeter). 346 See Gerry Callahan, Trade a Necessary Evil, BOSTON HERALD, Apr. 10, 2003, at B13 (noting how Red Sox team President Larry Lucchino hoped to convince Garciaparra of the “new economic climate” in baseball (i.e., lower salaries)). 347 See Horrigan, Sox Upped the Ante, supra note 345, at 90. 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1523 contract worth $15 million per year.348 According to Red Sox owner John Henry, Garciaparra immediately rejected the offer, believing that the alleged market correction was either untrue or ephemeral.349 Garciaparra would then play the 2003 season often appearing unhappy, and his Red Sox teammates believed that his contract status had caused him to become increasingly irritated.350 In November 2003, the Red Sox once again offered Garciaparra a four-year contract, yet this time it offered an average annual salary of only $12 million.351 In explaining the reduction in annual value from $15 million to $12 million, Red Sox management cited a continuing “market adjustment” that Garciaparra had further diminished players’ salaries.352 refused the offer, vehemently asserting that no such market correction had occurred.353 In March 2004, the Red Sox made one final attempt to re-sign Garciaparra, offering a four-year contract worth $12.5 million per season, which Garciaparra also rejected for the same reason.354 With his free agent status looming, and with his increasingly dour attitude, the Red Sox traded Garciaparra to the Chicago Cubs in July 2004.355 After the 2004 season, Garciaparra finally obtained the right to become a free agent. Such an attainment proved bittersweet, however, as he would re-sign with the Cubs to one-year contract worth only $8 million, or less than his “less-than- 348 Id. Id. 350 See Dan Shaughnessy, Words Don’t Do Justice for Garciaparra, BOSTON GLOBE, July 23, 2003, at F1; see also Ken Fidlin, The Last Word, TORONTO SUN, Dec. 24, 2003, at 101 (stating Garciaparra’s disgust at being “disrespected not only by management, but by teammates as well” following his contract squabbles); Shaughnessy, Damaged Goods, supra note 183 (describing Garciaparra as “wildly unhappy”); Silverman, supra note 344 (describing how Garciaparra’s “funk in mood” was evidenced by his decision to physically separate himself from teammates during a pivotal game against the New York Yankees, also describing Garciaparra as “ticked off” at Red Sox management). 351 See Gordon Edes, Tales from Two Cities: Garciaparra, Sox Offer Differing Views on Pre-Trade Events, BOSTON GLOBE, Aug. 2, 2004, at D1. 352 See id. 353 See Jeff Horrigan, Sox in Winter Wonderland, BOSTON HERALD, Dec. 12, 2003, at 118 (noting that Garciaparra “scoffed at the offer” after the Red Sox justified it based on the “changing financial climate in baseball”). 354 See Gordon Edes, Force Play: On Trade, Henry Says Epstein Simply Did What He Had to Do, BOSTON GLOBE, Aug. 4, 2004, at F1. 355 Id. 349 1524 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 market value” $9 million annual salary over the preceding four years.356 Garciaparra’s decision to refute the existence of a market correction, and instead anchor his value to increasingly less-relevant contracts, proved a great disservice to him. Not only may he have cost himself over $40 million, but, by participating in unworkable negotiations, put himself through needless anguish. In fact, some believe that his unwillingness to recognize modified market conditions ultimately morphed a happy person into a miserable one.357 Accordingly, anchoring and adjustment effects may not only impair the pursuit of objective value (i.e., contractual compensation) but also equally-meaningful subjective value (i.e., level of happiness). 6. Endowment Effects Decision-making among professional athletes may also be influenced by endowment effects, whereby individuals perceive more utility from their current state of affairs than from altered, yet equivalent circumstances.358 Such phenomena are broadly evident among those contemplating new employment opportunities. For instance, as discussed in Section III, employees are often less willing to pay to acquire a right or privilege than they are willing to sell it.359 Among professional athletes, endowment effects appear especially apparent when they re-sign at discounted rates, and then, as a reason for accepting diminished salary, cite employment characteristics that are likely constant among employment options. Perhaps best evincing this idea, consider the subjective value ascribed by some professional athletes to the quality of their team training staffs.360 Primarily, these staffs treat players’ injuries and provide other therapeutic 356 See Mike Kiley, Cubs’ Daily Double: Nomar, Walker, CHI. SUN-TIMES, Dec. 8, 2004, at 143. 357 See, e.g., Jim Donaldson, Leaving Town Was Inevitable for Embittered Garciaparra, PROVIDENCE J., Aug. 2, 2004, at C1; Shaughnessy, Damaged Goods, supra note 183. See generally supra note 349 and accompanying sources (providing insight on Garciaparra’s unhappiness as a result of his futile contract negotiations with the Red Sox). 358 See Korobkin & Guthrie, supra note 105, at 802 & n.29, 803. 359 See discussion supra p. 1478. 360 See, e.g., George Vescey, Matthews Remembers Houston, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 26, 2000, at D1 (citing remarks by Bruce Matthews of the Tennessee Titans). 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1525 care.361 Although they undoubtedly vary in quality, empirical data suggests that among professional teams in the NFL, MLB, NBA, and NHL, all include highly-skilled staff and excellent facilities.362 In other words, any actual difference in quality may not prove appreciable. Some professional athletes, however, appear to place significant subjective value in their belief that training staffs vary widely in quality. For instance, when San Francisco Giants’ pitcher Jason Christiansen recently re-signed to a 1year, $1 million contract—a significantly less lucrative deal than he was offered by both the Tampa Bay Devil Rays and New York Mets—he cited his “affection for the Giants’ training staff” as a reason to take a hometown discount.363 Similarly, when the Tennessee Titans re-signed offensive lineman Bruce Matthews for less than his market value, he considered the team’s “great training staff” as a motivating reason.364 Thus, professional athletes may assent to substantial reductions in salary in exchange for presumed relative benefits that might, in practice, prove illusory. Professional sports teams appear cognizant of these heuristics. In fact, they often showcase their training facilities, and attempt to impress upon players the presence of variances among training facilities and staffs.365 Teams even construct new facilities in part for the very purpose of keeping star 361 See generally Chris Curran & Joe Recknagel of Detroit Lions Athletic Training Staff, A Week in an NFL Training Camp, NFL.COM, http://www.nfl.com/news/story/7616836 (last visited Jan. 4, 2006). 362 See Cherie Black, Trainers Help Athletes Get Back on Their Feet, FLA. TIMES-UNION, Sept. 12, 2004, at B1; see also Brian Biggane, Conditioning, Contracts Make Age Less an Issue, PALM BEACH POST, Oct. 15, 2000, at 6B (analyzing investment of NHL teams and players in training and fitness); Paul Hoynes, Focused on Fitness, PLAIN DEALER (Cleveland), May 31, 2005, at D1 (discussing “revolution” among training MLB training staffs over last twenty years and outstanding care players receive); Mike Preston, Bigger, Faster, Stronger, BALT. MORNING SUN, Sept. 20, 1996 (describing extensive training available for players on the Cleveland Browns and how other teams provide similar training); Patrick Saunders, Super Human or Super Medicine?, DENVER POST, May 16, 2003, at D1 (describing modern diagnostic tools available to NBA trainers and trainers in other pro sports leagues). 363 See Henry Schulman, Giants Re-Sign Left-Hander, S.F. CHRON., Dec. 18, 2004, at D3. It should be noted that Christiansen cited additional subjective reasons for his decision to stay in San Francisco, including his relationship with teammates and the geographic location of the team’s training facilities. Id. 364 See Vescey, supra note 360, at D1. 365 See Mike O’Hara, New Digs Are “Unbelievable,” DETROIT NEWS, Mar. 31, 2002, at 8D (noting this effect in the NFL); Bob Wolfley, July Has Become Courting Season for NBA Free Agents, MILWAUKEE J.-SENTINEL, July 19, 2000, at 2C (noting this effect in the NBA). 1526 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 players, as well as attracting free agents.366 These efforts are encouraged by team employees, including those players who regard training facilities and staff as crucial to their performance.367 Team manipulation of preferences among professional athletes highlights the malleability of employment choice. Indeed, by promoting the perception of greater utility from current states of affair than from functionally-equivalent states, teams exacerbate endowment effects among their players. Such a phenomenon further amplifies the presence of cognitive biases and heuristics among professional athletes, and thus further suggests non-optimal pursuits of preferences. VI. CONCLUSION In contemplation of employment opportunities, professional athletes appear to embrace a myriad mixture of preferences, and such preferences frequently reflect the placement of considerable value in non-monetary goals. Accordingly, for many professional athletes, “optimality” does not reflect greed, avarice, or other commonly-held assumptions about those individuals; instead, it often comprises intangible, even romanticized inclinations, such as loyalty, camaraderie, and aspiration for team success. For that reason, and upon deeper reflection, behavioral patterns among contemporary professional athletes may not only “remind us of all that was once good” in professional sports368—they may also suggest that such good never left. An analysis limited to preferences, however, ignores the presence of cognitive biases and heuristics among professional athletes. Significantly, such influences may distort preferences, and yield sub-optimal decision-making. This is especially apparent when professional sports teams impress illusory variances among themselves and other teams. 366 See, e.g., Matt Winkeljohn, New Facility an All-Around Improvement, ATLANTA CONST., Aug. 9, 2000, at E6 (describing thought-process among Atlanta Falcons’ management officials when contemplating the construction of a new training facility). 367 See Mike Cobb, Planned Facility Has Bucs Smiling, LEDGER (Florida), Mar. 18, 2004, at C3 (citing remarks by Tampa Bay Buccaneers wide receiver Joe Jurevicius). 368 FIELD OF DREAMS (Universal 1989). This particular comment refers to the belief that professional athletes from the early part of the twentieth century cared substantially more about winning games and less about financial remuneration than do contemporary athletes. 2006] PROFESSIONAL ATHLETES 1527 Consequently, professional athletes may unknowingly misinterpret their preferences, thereby triggering diminutions in both objective value and subjective value. The conclusions reached in this Article may prove both novel and complimentary. Indeed, they reflect the first of their kind. Such novelty may offer meaningful insight to professional athletes, their representatives, and teams, a group collectively worth billions of dollars. For professional athletes, knowledge of cognitive biases and heuristics in their decisionmaking may encourage ameliorative cognitive adjustments. For instance, instead of discounting or ignoring information that challenges existing assumptions about their teams, professional athletes might explore the validity and salience of such information and determine whether to utilize it in their decision-making process. Similarly, rather than assuming that established precedents, such as probable performance metrics, do not apply with equal force to themselves, professional athletes might instead pursue more expansive consultations. By doing so, they might refrain from assenting to poor risk contracts, particularly those that are incentive-based or otherwise unconventionally-constructed. Player representatives may likewise infer strategic guidance from these conclusions. If anything, their role appears bolstered by the presence of cognitive distortions among professional athletes. Indeed, player representatives may offer objective advice, and because of the intimacy of the player-agent relationship, may do so in uniquely compelling ways. Alternatively, player representatives may become more attune to subjective preferences among players. Although adherence to such preferences might diminish agent compensation, the quality of representation would rise commensurate with preference maximization. Of course, with any enlarged role for player representatives comes heightened responsibility, as well as the corresponding need to avoid cognitive biases in representation. Consider also the capacity of professional sports teams to adroitly manipulate cognitive biases, and how that capacity only amplifies the desirability of professional athletes and their representatives to respond accordingly. As discussed in this Article, teams routinely engage in machinations to distort the decision-making of professional athletes. Moreover, teams’ continued choice to do so supplies further evidence of cognitive biases, as otherwise, they would presumably pursue other recruiting and retention strategies. Accordingly, an enriched 1528 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 ability on the part of players and their representatives to counteract cognitive biases would presumably deter such behavior or make it more costly. Yet perhaps most engagingly, the conclusions reached in this Article illuminate the potential for behavioral sciences to influence traditional law and economics, as well as theories of contract formation. This is especially true since, unlike other population groups that frequently capture the attention of legal academics, professional athletes spontaneously furnish publishable commentary of their values, beliefs, and priorities, and they do so in real world, rather than experimental settings. Indeed, by escaping the alleged “experimental flaw” of many behavioral law and economic studies, professional athletes offer a uniquely appealing group for further examination. For that reason, recognition of how professional athletes respond to subjective stimuli, as well as cognitive distortions, may reveal as much about us as it does about them. CPLR 3212(a)’s Timing Requirement for Summary Judgment Motions ONA BRILL’S STROLL THROUGH BROOKLYN AND THE DRAMATIC EFFECT IT HAS HAD ON NEW YORK STATE’S CIVIL PRACTICE Patrick M. Connors † I. Introduction ...................................................................... 1531 II. Historical Background and the 1997 Amendment to CPLR 3212(a) .................................................................... 1532 III. The Court of Appeals Interprets CPLR 3212(a)’s Timeliness Requirements................................................. 1536 IV. Calculating CPLR 3212(a)’s Time Period ........................ 1537 A. Various Time Periods for Making Motion for Summary Judgment and Their Accrual .................... 1537 B. “Making” the Motion for Summary Judgment in a Timely Fashion ........................................................... 1538 C. Timeliness of Cross-Motion for Summary Judgment 1540 D. Effect of Mistrial on CPLR 3212(a)’s Timing Requirements .............................................................. 1542 E. Cases Stricken from the Trial Calendar.................... 1543 V. What Constitutes “Good Cause” Under CPLR 3212(a)? 1545 A. Adjudication of Good Cause ....................................... 1546 B. Stipulation to Extend CPLR 3212(a)’s Time Period 1548 C. Demonstrating Good Cause........................................ 1549 1. Outstanding Disclosure ........................................ 1549 † Associate Professor of Law, Albany Law School. Professor Connors is the author of the McKinney’s Practice Commentaries for CPLR Article 31, Disclosure and the co-author of the New York Practice column, which appears regularly in the New York Law Journal. He frequently presents continuing legal education programs to the bench and bar on recent developments in New York practice. © 2006 Patrick M. Connors. John R. Higgitt, Esq. provided substantial contributions to this piece. He drafted several sections of the article and reviewed the manuscript on numerous occasions, while providing keen insights and comments. Bob Emery, one of the finest research librarians in the nation, provided many helpful suggestions. We are very lucky to have Bob’s assistance at Albany Law School. 1529 1530 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 2. Other Potential Excuses Constituting “Good Cause”.................................................................... 1553 3. “Good Cause” – CPLR 3212(a) vs. CPLR 2004 .... 1557 VI. Extension of Time Periods Established by Court Rule or Order ................................................................................. 1558 VII. The Aftermath of Brill ................................................... 1562 A. What Does the Plaintiff Do Now? .............................. 1564 1. Search for Additional Proof .................................. 1565 2. The Prospect of Sanctions..................................... 1566 3. Voluntary Discontinuance .................................... 1569 4. Ethical Obligations To Client............................... 1570 B. What Does the Defendant Do Now?........................... 1573 1. CPLR 4401 – Motion for Judgment During Trial 1573 2. CPLR 3211(a)(7) – Motion to Dismiss.................. 1575 3. CPLR 3404 & 22 NYCRR § 202.27 – Laxness Dismissals ............................................................. 1578 4. Defense Lawyer’s Potential Exposure to Legal Malpractice............................................................ 1583 VIII. Conclusion .................................................................... 1585 Postscript by Chief Judge Judith Kaye, New York Court of Appeals ............................................................................. 1586 2006] I. CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1531 INTRODUCTION In 1997, the CPLR added another star to its galaxy of deadlines. CPLR 3212(a) was amended to require that motions for summary judgment be made no later than 120 days after the filing of the note of issue, unless the movant can establish “good cause.” As devoted followers of New York civil procedure have observed, a certain segment of the bar apparently enjoys living dangerously, and several reported cases began to test the limits of CPLR 3212(a)’s timeliness provisions. One particular case, however, has placed this timing requirement at the forefront of civil procedure in the New York State courts. On a cold February day in New York City, during the winter of 1998, a woman named Ona Brill was walking on a public sidewalk in Brooklyn when she tripped and fell. Although she did not realize it at the time, her name would gain a form of celebrity status with the bench and bar in New York State’s civil courts. Ms. Brill and her husband ultimately sued New York City, among other defendants, seeking compensation for her injuries. The City, which handles hundreds of slip-and-fall cases on an annual basis, apparently did not believe that the case required any heightened level of attention. It contended that Ms. Brill could not establish that the City had prior written notice of the defect, a necessary requirement in the lawsuit, and moved for summary judgment to dismiss the case before trial. Ms. Brill’s case ultimately came before the New York Court of Appeals, which issued a ruling addressing the importance of CPLR 3212(a)’s timing requirements, and the adherence to statutory time periods and court orders in general. This article will address the impact of the decision in Ms. Brill’s suit, which has spawned a healthy body of caselaw on the timing of summary judgment motions. We will identify the various factors that courts have considered in determining whether good cause has been established to allow a party to move for summary judgment beyond CPLR 3212(a)’s deadline. The cases have also issued several express and implied warnings to the bar regarding compliance with the statute’s language, which will be discussed below. In addition, the article will address several problems applying the statute that have yet to be resolved by the courts. We will also make recommendations to lawyers who wish to avoid jeopardizing 1532 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 their use of the important tool of the summary judgment motion. Finally, the article will examine the effect of CPLR 3212(a)’s amendment on civil practice from a broader perspective. There will be occasions, for example, when a defendant’s meritorious summary judgment motion is denied as untimely. As a result, the defendant’s attorney faces several problems, including the prospect of malpractice liability for failing to have disposed of the case with a timely motion for summary judgment. The plaintiff’s lawyer also faces several dilemmas, and may not be enthusiastic about advancing the case in light of the impending doom awaiting at trial. In fact, proceeding to trial in these circumstances may result in sanctions for frivolous conduct. II. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND AND THE 1997 AMENDMENT TO CPLR 3212(a) The legal system has always struggled to become more efficient and to reduce unnecessary delay without abridging litigants’ rights. To a substantial degree, the old common law lost this struggle. Common-law pleading sacrificed efficiency and even fairness to technicality and prolonged delay. 1 In response to these problems, New York State pioneered a system of summary judgment that expedited the resolution of lawsuits while preserving the valid claims of parties. As early as 1808, the New York State Supreme Court adopted one of the first forerunners of the modern summary judgment procedure. 2 In 1921, New York adopted a new summary judgment rule, 3 which influenced the adoption of the same device by the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure almost twenty years later. 4 1 ROBERT WYNESS MILLAR, CIVIL PROCEDURE OF THE TRIAL COURT IN HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE 237 (photo reprint 2005) (1952). 2 General Rule, 3 Johns. 542 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1808) (requiring defendants to submit an affidavit of “good and substantial defence”). For a further discussion of the history of the summary judgment motion in New York State, see N.Y. ST. B. ASS’N COM. & FED. LITIG. SEC., REPORT ON REFORM OF SUMMARY JUDGMENT PROCEDURES IN NEW YORK COURTS (1993), available at http://www.nysba.org/Content/ContentGroups/ Commercial_and_Federal_Litigation_Sec/SummaryJudgmenProcedurest.pdf [hereinafter, REPORT ON REFORM]. 3 N.Y. CIV. PRAC. R. 113 (replaced by CPLR 3212 in 1963). 4 FED. R. CIV. P. 56. See Paul H. Aloe & Joan Morgan McGivern, Rethinking New York’s Summary Judgment Procedures: Proposed Reform to Facilitate Disposition of Commercial Cases, N.Y. ST. B.J., May/June 1993, at 32. 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1533 The summary judgment device remains a source of constant controversy, however, on both the federal 5 and state level. 6 New York’s CPLR 3212(a), 7 which governs the timing of a summary judgment motion, continues New York’s tradition of innovation with respect to this important procedural device. It is an example of how one jurisdiction, in response to the realities of modern litigation, has tried to balance procedural efficiency with justice. Prior to 1997, summary judgment motions in New York State courts on the eve of trial were not uncommon. Courts had long recognized the problem, observing that “[t]he timing of a summary judgment motion so as to make it returnable on the eve of the trial of an action has a tendency to frustrate rather than to further the primary purpose of the remedy, which is to obviate delay in litigation.” 8 In 1980, however, the New York Court of Appeals held that the mere fact that a motion for summary judgment was made at this late date was not, standing alone, grounds for denying the motion. 9 Courts had the authority to deny such a motion, however, “when its merit [was] not evident and it appear[ed] to be made as a dilatory tactic.” 10 The Court reasoned that if a motion made on the eve of trial was “clearly meritorious,” its denial based on untimeliness grounds was error. 11 A denial of the motion in 5 See, e.g., CHARLES ALAN WRIGHT & MARY KAY KANE, LAW OF FEDERAL COURTS § 99, at 714-15 (6th ed. 2002). 6 See, e.g., Aloe & McGivern, supra note 4, at 32-35 (discussing New York); Paul D. Fogel & Valerie Mark, Summary Adjudication in the 90s: Problems and Proposals, L.A. DAILY J., June 1, 2003, at 7 (discussing California). 7 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3212(a) (McKinney 2005). 8 Jordan v. Levy, 16 A.D.2d 64, 65, 225 N.Y.S.2d 399, 400 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1962) (per curiam). Jordan observed that when a case “has progressed to the point of imminent trial in the usual course, the disposal of the litigation will not then be accelerated by a motion for summary judgment.” Id. 9 Kule Res., Ltd. v. Reliance Group, Inc., 49 N.Y.2d 587, 591, 404 N.E.2d 734, 735, 427 N.Y.S.2d 612, 613 (1980) (per curiam). In Kule, the trial court ruled that “the timing of the motion so as to make it returnable ‘on the eve of trial’ frustrated the purpose of summary judgment, and denied the motion.” Kule Res., Ltd. v. Reliance Group, Inc., 69 A.D.2d 753, 753, 415 N.Y.S.2d 13, 14 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1979), aff’d, 49 N.Y.2d 587, 404 N.E.2d 734, 427 N.Y.S.2d 612 (1980) (per curiam). The Appellate Division, in an order affirmed by the Court of Appeals, reversed, noting that the summary judgment motion was made as soon as the deposition transcripts were available. Id. “Inasmuch as the motion depends largely on evidence adduced at the depositions it could not have been made sooner. Accordingly, timeliness should not have been made the basis for denial.” Id. 10 Kule, 427 N.Y.S.2d at 613. 11 Id. Accord Guzman v. Estate of Fluker, 226 A.D.2d 676, 677, 641 N.Y.S.2d 721, 723 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1996) (“A motion for summary judgment should not be denied solely on the ground that it is made on the eve of trial, particularly where the 1534 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 these circumstances, the Court observed, “wastes judicial resources which, through ever increasing demands, daily become more precious.” 12 During the next two decades, the practice of allowing late motions for summary judgment placed a significant burden on the court system and litigants. If a successful “eleventh hour” motion established that defendant was entitled to judgment as a matter of law, a substantial portion of the time and money spent in preparation for trial was rendered worthless. These motions also significantly taxed the resources of the judiciary, often leaving inadequate time for proper consideration of the arguments and disrupting court calendars. 13 motion is meritorious.” (citations omitted)); Latimer v. City of New York, 219 A.D.2d 622, 623, 631 N.Y.S.2d 395, 395 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1995) (“[T]he mere fact that a summary judgment motion is made on the eve of trial is not in and of itself sufficient reason for denying the motion, especially in a case such as this where the motion is so clearly meritorious.” (citations omitted)). 12 Kule, 427 N.Y.S.2d at 613. 13 The Office of Court Administration summarized the problem in 1996 by observing that if a motion for summary judgment is delayed until the eve of trial, “there is no adequate time for an adversary to reply or for the court to consider the motion, thereby occasioning either a determination on the merits of the motion without adequate consideration or the delay of the trial, especially when the motion papers are voluminous.” OFFICE OF COURT ADMIN., MEMORANDUM ON SUMMARY JUDGMENT MOTIONS - TIMELINESS, 219th sess. (N.Y. 1996), reprinted in 1996 N.Y. Sess. Laws page 2685 (McKinney). The Memorandum notes that, “[a]t times, such belated motions may be filed in an attempt to delay a case or to secure transfer of the case to a different judge for trial.” Id. See also REPORT OF THE ADVISORY COMMITTEE ON CIVIL PRACTICE, 219th sess. (N.Y. 1996), reprinted in 1996 N.Y. Sess. Laws page 2699, 2724 (McKinney). The 1993 Report on Reform previously identified the problem of summary judgment motions being made “on the eve of trial for purposes of delay.” REPORT ON REFORM, supra note 2, at 4. The Report on Reform quoted from the October 1992 Report on the IAS System, which stated: Judges throughout the state expressed concern about the number of motions for summary judgment that are made on the eve of trial. It has been the universal experience of the bench that the vast majority of these motions are made primarily for delay or other tactical advantage. Id. at 4. The Report on Reform proposed an amendment to CPLR 3212(a)(4) that would have forbidden a party from making a motion for summary judgment within sixty days of a trial date where the trial had been set for a date certain, except by order to show cause which can only be granted where good cause is shown and the opponent consents to the making of the motion or has been given an opportunity to be heard in opposition to the granting of the summary judgment motion. Id. at 9. 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1535 Effective January 1, 1997, CPLR 3212(a) was amended to discourage parties from moving for summary judgment on the eve of trial. 14 The amendment allows trial courts to set a date after which no summary judgment motions can be made, but requires the court to allow the parties at least thirty days from the filing of the note of issue 15 to make such a motion. 16 Many courts exercise this authority in various places, including individual court rules, Uniform Rules for the Supreme Court, 17 preliminary conference orders, 18 or certification orders. 19 If no date is set by the particular court, CPLR 3212(a) mandates that the motion be made “no later than one hundred twenty 14 Act of Aug. 8, 1996, ch. 492, § 1, 1996 N.Y. Laws 2972. See N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3402 (McKinney 2005). The filing of the note of issue places the case on the trial calendar. N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3402(a). The note of issue must ordinarily be accompanied by the certificate of readiness. See infra notes 83-84 and accompanying text. 16 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3212(a) (McKinney 2005). The note of issue is utilized in the supreme and county courts. See N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.21 (2005). In the New York City Civil Court, the district courts and the city courts, the notice of trial is the equivalent of the note of issue. See N.Y. CITY CIV. CT. ACT §§ 1301, 1303 (McKinney 2005); N.Y. UNIFORM DIST. CT. ACT §§ 1301, 1303 (McKinney 2005); N.Y. UNIFORM CITY CT. ACT §§ 1301, 1303 (McKinney 2005). There is no outside limit on a court-imposed deadline. CPLR 3212(a) appears to permit a court-imposed rule that would allow summary judgment motions to be made, for example, 150 days after the filing of the note of issue. See N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3212(a) (McKinney 2005). Approximately three years prior to the passage of the amendment to CPLR 3212(a), the Report on Reform observed that a proposal barring summary judgment motions a certain number of days after the filing of the note of issue “appears too harsh given that cases sometimes are tried years after a note of issue has been filed.” REPORT ON REFORM, supra note 2, at 9 & n.12. 17 See, e.g., N.Y. COUNTY SUPREME COURT CIVIL BRANCH, R. 17, available at http://www.courts.state.ny.us/supctmanh/uniform_rules.htm (last visited Jan. 25, 2006) (sixty days from filing note of issue); UNIFORM CIVIL TERM RULES OF THE SUPREME COURT, KINGS COUNTY, R. 13, available at http://www.courts.state.ny.us/courts/2jd/kings/civil/civilrules.pdf (last visited Mar. 8, 2006) (sixty days from filing a note of issue). 18 See N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.12(c) & (d) (2005) (allowing court to consider and determine time frames for various matters at preliminary conference); see also Smith v. Nameth, 25 A.D.3d 599, 600, 807 N.Y.S.2d 411, 412 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2006) (holding that court providently exercised its discretion in entertaining defendant’s motion for summary judgment, made shortly after deadline established in preliminary conference order); Milano v. George, 17 A.D.3d 644, 645, 792 N.Y.S.2d 906, 907 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (mem.) (affirming denial of defendant’s motion for summary judgment, made one day beyond the court-imposed deadline of 90 days after the filing of the note of issue). 19 See, e.g., DiMetteo v. County of Nassau, No. 12089-02, 2005 WL 1644921 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Nassau County May 9, 2005) (although certification order required service of summary judgment motions within 60 days of filing of note of issue, court still considered motion on its merits). 15 1536 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 days after the filing of the note of issue, except with leave of court on good cause shown.” 20 III. THE COURT OF APPEALS INTERPRETS CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMELINESS REQUIREMENTS The Court of Appeals’ 2004 decision in Brill v. City of New York 21 provided a strict interpretation of the 1997 amendment, which has had a substantial impact in many subsequent cases. 22 In Brill, the City moved for summary judgment well after CPLR 3212(a)’s 120-day period had expired, asserting that it had no prior written notice of the alleged defect that caused plaintiff’s fall. 23 Despite the fact that the City failed to establish good cause for the delay, both the supreme court and the Appellate Division considered the motion in the interests of judicial economy, noting that plaintiff could not demonstrate prejudice in the face of this meritorious defense. 24 The Court of Appeals reversed, holding that a motion for summary judgment can only be entertained after 120 days from the filing of the note of issue if the movant can show “good cause,” i.e., “a satisfactory explanation for the untimeliness.” 25 The merits of the motion and the lack of prejudice to the respondent, which had supported good cause determinations in prior lower court cases, were deemed irrelevant to a determination of good cause under CPLR 3212(a). 26 Brill’s holding became further entrenched just five months later in Miceli v. State Farm Mutual Automobile Insurance Company, in which the Court specifically noted that the merits of a summary judgment motion cannot constitute good cause to extend CPLR 3212(a)’s 120-day period. 27 In the aftermath of Brill and Miceli, it is now clear that courts lack the power to extend the legislative time period to move for summary judgment on the basis of “the interests of justice” or 20 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3212(a) (McKinney 2005). 2 N.Y.3d 648, 814 N.E.2d 431, 781 N.Y.S.2d 261 (2004). 22 As of this writing, in a period of twenty-two months, Brill has been cited in over ninety-three reported decisions and by over sixty secondary sources. 23 Brill, 781 N.Y.S.2d at 266. 24 Id. 25 Id. at 264. 26 Id. 27 3 N.Y.3d 725, 726-27, 819 N.E.2d 995, 996, 786 N.Y.S.2d 379, 380 (2004) (mem). 21 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1537 “judicial economy,” regardless of the merits of the motion and the absence of prejudice to the opponent. 28 IV. CALCULATING CPLR 3212(a)’S TIME PERIOD The Court of Appeals’ strict interpretation of CPLR 3212(a) necessitates that lawyers carefully calculate the deadline for making a summary judgment motion. 29 This requires a prospective movant to: (1) ascertain the period of time for making a summary judgment motion, (2) ascertain the date on which CPLR 3212(a)’s time period begins to run, and (3) perform the steps required to “make” the motion within the period. A. Various Time Periods for Making Motion for Summary Judgment and Their Accrual At the outset, a lawyer planning to move for summary judgment must determine if the court has set a deadline pursuant to CPLR 3212(a). 30 If a court has not set its own date within which a motion for summary judgment must be made, CPLR 3212(a) generally provides that the “motion shall be made no later than one hundred twenty days after the filing of the note of issue.” 31 The 120-day period runs from the “filing” of a paper, not its service, and should not be the beneficiary of CPLR 2103(b)(2)’s five-day extension. 32 This has already caused 28 See, e.g., Perini Corp. v. City of New York, 16 A.D.3d 37, 39-40, 789 N.Y.S.2d 29, 31 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2005). In Rivera v. Toruno, 19 A.D.3d 473, 796 N.Y.S.2d 708 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005), defendant advanced an argument similar to the City’s contentions in Brill in an attempt to establish good cause. Rather than emphasizing the merits of the motion for summary judgment, defendant sought to establish good cause based on “the obvious lack of merit of the plaintiff’s case.” Id. at 709. The court rejected the argument, relying on Brill, because defendant failed to provide a satisfactory explanation for the delay. Id. 29 See, e.g., Milano v. George, 792 N.Y.S.2d 906, 907 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (mem.) (affirming order denying motion for summary judgment made one day past CPLR 3212(a)’s deadline); Dibella v. Long Island Jewish Med. Ctr., No. 18591/02, N.Y.L.J., March 1, 2005, at 21 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Nassau County) (denying motion for summary judgment served three days after time period authorized by CPLR 3212(a)). The Dibella court improperly added five days to the period within which motions could be made. See infra notes 32-33, and accompanying text. 30 See supra notes 16-19 and accompanying text. 31 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3212(a) (McKinney 2005). This discussion assumes that there is no good cause to allow the filing of the motion beyond CPLR 3212(a)’s time frame. A prudent lawyer will make this assumption at the outset of virtually every case. 32 CPLR 2103(b)(2) only grants a five-day extension “where a period of time prescribed by law is measured from the service of a paper and service is by mail . . . .” N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2103(b)(2) (McKinney 2005). The five-day extension may, however, apply 1538 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 some confusion in the cases, which have recognized a five-day extension in this context. 33 Although the party filing the note of issue must also serve it, 34 and can accomplish service by mail, 35 the moment of service is irrelevant for computing CPLR 3212(a)’s 120-day period. B. “Making” the Motion for Summary Judgment in a Timely Fashion Once a party moving for summary judgment has ascertained the relevant time period under CPLR 3212(a) and the moment at which it begins to run, she must ensure that she “makes” the motion before the deadline expires. A motion on notice is deemed “made when a notice of the motion or an order to show cause is served,” not the date when the motion is filed or made returnable. 36 CPLR 2103(b) offers many options for if the court sets a time period for the making of summary judgment motions, and the period runs from the service of a paper. Id. 33 Krasnow v. JRBG Mgt. Corp., 25 A.D.3d 479, 480, 808 N.Y.S.2d 75, 76 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2006); Szabo v. XYZ, Two Way Radio Taxi Ass’n, 267 A.D.2d 134, 135, 161, 700 N.Y.S.2d 179, 180 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1999); Connolly v. City of New York, N.Y.L.J., Mar. 7, 2005, at 19 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Bronx County); Dibella, N.Y.L.J., Mar. 1, 2005, at 21. Connolly based its holding on the First Department’s ruling in Szabo, 700 N.Y.S.2d at 180, which held that a party moving for summary judgment cannot be charged with knowledge of the running of CPLR 3212(a)’s time period until service of the note of issue by mail is completed. Szabo, in turn, relied on Levy v. Schaefer, 160 A.D.2d 1182, 1183, 555 N.Y.S.2d 192, 194 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 1990) in support of this conclusion. Levy addressed the twenty-day period in which a party must move to vacate a note of issue if a case is not ready for trial. See also N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.21(e) (2005). This time period, unlike the one in CPLR 3212(a), is measured from the service of a paper. Id. Therefore, Levy properly concluded that CPLR 2103(b)(2)’s five-day period can extend the time within which a party must move to vacate the note of issue. Levy’s reasoning is not, however, applicable to the 120-day period in CPLR 3212(a), which does not begin to run upon the mailing of a paper. 34 CPLR 3402(a) allows a party to “place a case upon the calendar by filing, within ten days after service, with proof of such service two copies of a note of issue with the clerk . . . .” N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3402(a) (McKinney 2005). See also N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.21(a) (2005) (requiring filing of note of issue accompanied by certificate of readiness, with proof of service on all parties, to place case on trial calendar). 35 See N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2103(b) (McKinney 2005) (authorizing several methods for service of interlocutory papers). 36 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2211 (McKinney 2005). See, e.g., Russo v. Eveco Dev. Corp., 256 A.D.2d 566, 566, 683 N.Y.S.2d 566, 567 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1998); LaSorsa v. Corrigan, 256 A.D.2d 313, 314, 681 N.Y.S.2d 300, 301 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1998); Greenfield v. Philles Records, Inc., 160 A.D.2d 458, 459, 553 N.Y.S.2d 771, 772 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1990); Ghumman v. Abdelshahid, No. 2002-1301 K C., 2003 WL 21696982, at *1 (N.Y. App. Term 2d & 11th Jud. Dists. June 24, 2003); Bouilland v. Angulo, 5 Misc. 3d 1031(A), No. 114116-01, 2004 WL 2941569, at *1 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. New York County Sept. 27, 2004); Dugas v. Bernstein, 5 Misc. 3d 818, 825, 786 N.Y.S.2d 708, 713-14 (Sup. Ct. New York County 2004); Siegel, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C2211:4 (1991); DAVID D. SIEGEL, NEW YORK PRACTICE § 243 (4th ed. 2005); see also Thompson v. Leben Home for Adults, 17 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1539 serving motions, 37 but service by mail is the most common method. 38 Service of a motion by mail is “complete upon mailing,” 39 not when the papers are received. If a motion is made by order to show cause, rather than with a notice of motion, 40 the motion is deemed made when the papers are served, not on the date that the order to show cause is signed by the judge. 41 An order to show cause will typically A.D.3d 347, 348, 792 N.Y.S.2d 597, 598 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (“The defendants’ untimely cross motion for summary judgment should not have been considered in view of their failure to offer a satisfactory explanation for not serving it within 120 days of the filing of the note of issue . . . .”). Cases incorrectly indicating that summary judgment motions are made either when filed, dated or returnable are legion. See, e.g., Balcerzak v. DNA Contracting, LLC, 9 Misc. 3d 524, 531, 802 N.Y.S.2d 324, 329 (Sup. Ct. Kings County 2005); Buckner v. City of New York, 9 Misc. 3d 510, 514, 800 N.Y.S.2d 333, 336 (Sup. Ct. New York County 2005); Singh v. Deopaul, 8 Misc. 3d 1019(A), No. 46334-01, 2005 WL 1774139 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Kings County July 12, 2005); Newsday, Inc. v. Nelkenbaum, 8 Misc. 3d 1005(A), 801 N.Y.S.2d 779 (N.Y. Civ. Ct. Kings County 2005); Hernandez v. 620 W. 189th Ltd. P’ship, 7 Misc. 3d 198, 792 N.Y.S.2d 822, 823 (Sup. Ct. New York County 2005); Florczyc v. Stahal, No. 25129-99, 2005 WL 119739, at *1 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Kings County Jan. 3, 2005). In Smith v. Nameth, 807 N.Y.S.2d at 412, the court’s deadline, established in a preliminary conference order, apparently required that the motion be made returnable by a certain date. 37 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2103(b) (McKinney 2005). A motion is an interlocutory paper “served upon a party in a pending action.” Id. Interlocutory papers must be served upon a party’s attorney. Id. CPLR 2103(b) lists seven methods for serving an interlocutory paper upon a party’s attorney. N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2103(b)(1)-(7). Each paper served on any party must be served on any other party who has appeared in the action. N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2103(e). Therefore, a motion must be served on all parties who have appeared in an action, even if the relief is not sought from them. See SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 203. 38 See SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 202. 39 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2103(b)(2) (McKinney 2005). See N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2103(f)(1) (McKinney 2005) (“mailing” means depositing paper in a properly addressed “first class postpaid wrapper” in a post office or official depository of the United States Postal Service “within the state”); Dugas, 786 N.Y.S.2d at 713-14. If the motion is mailed from outside New York State, it will not be deemed “made” on the date it is mailed but rather the date it was received. See Nat’l Org. for Women v. Metro. Life Ins. Co., 70 N.Y.2d 939, 519 N.E.2d 618, 524 N.Y.S.2d 672 (1988) (service was not “complete” within meaning of CPLR 2103(b)(2) when papers were mailed in Washington, D.C.). 40 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2214(d) (McKinney 2005) (“The court in a proper case may grant an order to show cause, to be served in lieu of a notice of motion, at a time and in a manner specified therein.”). 41 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2211 (McKinney 2005) (“A motion on notice is made when a notice of the motion or an order to show cause is served.”) (emphasis added). See Mortgage Affiliates Corp. v. Jerder Realty Serv., Inc., 62 A.D.2d 591, 593, 406 N.Y.S.2d 326, 327 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1978), aff’d 47 N.Y.2d 796, 391 N.E.2d 1011, 417 N.Y.S.2d 930 (1979) (motion to enter a deficiency judgment pursuant to Real Property Actions & Proceedings Law §1371 brought on by order to show cause is made when served and not when signed by judge); Slane v. Kalache, 7 Misc. 3d 717, 721, 794 N.Y.S.2d 835, 838 (Sup. Ct. Bronx County 2005) (motion for summary judgment deemed made when order to show cause served, not when papers presented to court for signing); Property Clerk, N.Y.C. Police Dept. v. Chevers, N.Y.L.J., Mar. 26, 1991, at 22 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. New York County) (where court signed order to show cause on last day for bringing motion, but movant did not serve motion until later date, motion was untimely). 1540 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 require more than one form of service, and the movant must be careful to carry out all service steps ordered by the judge prior to the expiration of the relevant period in CPLR 3212(a). C. Timeliness of Cross-Motion for Summary Judgment Timeliness issues frequently occur in the context of cross-motions for summary judgment. CPLR 2215 authorizes a party to make a cross-motion three days prior to the time a motion is noticed to be heard, but is silent on what act constitutes the making of the cross-motion. 42 A party making a cross-motion for summary judgment should assume that the motion is “made” when the cross-motion is served, not when the original motion was served. 43 In Bressingham v. Jamaica Hospital Medical Center, 44 the court concluded that defendant’s cross-motion for summary judgment was untimely and should not have been entertained without a showing of good cause for the delay. The court noted that the codefendant’s original motion for summary judgment could have provided good cause to consider the untimely motion “had the motion and crossmotion been nearly identical.” 45 This is a slim reed on which to 42 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2215 (McKinney 2005). Regardless of whether a party makes a motion or cross-motion for summary judgment, the party must pay a fee of $45 if the action is pending in supreme or county court. N.Y. C.P.L.R. 8020(a) (McKinney Supp. 2006) (“[T]he county clerk shall be entitled to a fee of forty-five dollars upon the filing of each motion or cross-motion.”). See also N.Y. C.P.L.R. 8022(b) (McKinney Supp. 2006) (“[T]he clerks of the appellate divisions of the supreme court and the clerk of the court of appeals are entitled, upon the filing of each motion or cross-motion with respect to a civil appeal or special proceeding, to a fee of forty-five dollars.”). As to issues related to the fee imposed on the making of a motion or cross-motion, see generally 142 Siegel’s Practice Review, Logistics of Collecting Fees for Motions Impose Expense in Time on Courts as well as Lawyers, to the Point Even of Offsetting the Fees Collected, at 1 (Nov. 2003); 137 Siegel’s Practice Review, As of July 14, 2003, Administrative Problems for Courts and Procedural Pitfalls for Parties Abound as Fees are Imposed for Making Motions and Cross-Motions, and Filing of Settlements is Made Mandatory (Part II), at 1 (July 2003); 136 Siegel’s Practice Review, Administrative Problems for Courts and Procedural Pitfalls for Parties Abound as Fees are Imposed for Making Motions and Cross-Motions, and Filing of Settlements is Made Mandatory (Part I), at 1 (June 2003). 43 Dugas, 786 N.Y.S.2d at 713-14. 44 17 A.D.3d 496, 496-97, 793 N.Y.S.2d 176, 176 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005). 45 Id. at 176. Bressingham’s conclusion that a court can consider a late crossmotion if it is “nearly identical” to a timely motion is based on caselaw that pre-dates Brill. See Boehme v. A Program Planned for Life Enrichment, Inc., 298 A.D.2d 540, 542, 749 N.Y.S.2d 49, 51 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2002); Miranda v. Devlin, 260 A.D.2d 451, 452, 688 N.Y.S.2d 578, 579 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1999). See also James v. Jamie Towers Hous. Co., 294 A.D.2d 268, 272, 743 N.Y.S.2d 85, 89 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2002), aff’d 99 N.Y.2d 639, 640, 790 N.E.2d 1147, 1148, 760 N.Y.S.2d 718, 720 (2003); Rosa v. RH Macy Co., 272 A.D.2d 87, 87, 707 N.Y.S.2d 407, 409 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2000). Boehme and Miranda also relied on the fact that the late cross-motions for summary judgment were meritorious and did not prejudice the respondent. Boehme, 749 N.Y.S.2d at 51; 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1541 establish good cause and, until the Court of Appeals approves of this linkage, the careful lawyer desiring to make a summary judgment motion should ensure that she independently satisfies CPLR 3212(a)’s time period. 46 There is still hope for a party who can no longer crossmove for summary judgment because of a failure to comply with CPLR 3212(a)’s timing requirements. In the event that another party in the action has made a timely motion for Miranda, 688 N.Y.S.2d at 579. These factors can no longer be considered after Brill and Miceli. See supra notes 25-28 and accompanying text. Nonetheless, in DiMetteo v. County of Nassau, 8 Misc. 3d at 1013(A), No. 12089-02, 2005 WL 1644921, at *1 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Nassau County May 9, 2005), the court considered a cross-motion seeking dismissal of plaintiff’s complaint, which was served 16 days after the period set by the court for making summary judgment motions had expired. The cross-motion sought dismissal of the plaintiff’s complaint on the same grounds as a timely motion made by a codefendant. Id. at *1. The court in DiMetteo, while applying the rule propounded in Bressingham, 793 N.Y.S.2d at 176, noted that the “nearly identical” test “appears to contradict Brill’s core holding – that the Court has no discretion to excuse the late service of any motion for summary judgment unless there is a satisfactory explanation for the untimely motion.” DiMetteo, 2005 WL 1644921, at *1. That portion of Nassau County’s cross-motion which sought dismissal of plaintiff’s complaint was not, technically, a cross-motion. CPLR 2215’s language allows a party to demand relief from a “moving party” with a cross-motion served three days prior to the return date of the main motion. N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2215 (McKinney 2005). Although the “relief need not be responsive to that demanded by the moving party,” the statute contemplates that the relief be sought from the moving party. Id. See Mango v. Long Island Jewish-Hillside Med. Ctr., 123 A.D.2d 843, 844, 507 N.Y.S.2d 456, 458 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1986) (“A cross-motion is an improper vehicle for seeking affirmative relief from a nonmoving party.”). Courts will frequently forgive this technical defect if it does not result in prejudice and the nonmoving party is afforded ample opportunity to be heard on the merits of the relief sought. See, e.g., Sheehan v. Marshall, 780 N.Y.S.2d 34 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004); Dugas, 786 N.Y.S.2d at 713 n.2. These factors are not, however, appropriate considerations in determining “good cause” under CPLR 3212(a). See supra notes 21-28 and accompanying text. For example, in Gaines v. Shell-Mar Foods, Inc., 21 A.D.3d 986, 801 N.Y.S.2d 376 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005), a codefendant moved for summary judgment 142 days after the note of issue was filed. Although it denominated its motion a “crossmotion,” the court concluded that “its effort to ‘piggyback’ on its codefendant’s timely motion for summary judgment is unavailing since a cross-motion can only be made for relief against a ‘moving party’ and the plaintiff was not a ‘moving party.’” Id. at 377 (citations omitted). The court held that the codefendant’s contentions that no prejudice resulted from delay and that its motion was meritorious were insufficient grounds to establish good cause. Id. 46 Bejarano v. City of New York, 18 A.D.3d 681, 795 N.Y.S.2d 732 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (late cross-motion denied in its entirety for failure to offer satisfactory explanation; no discussion of relation of cross-motion to main motion); Thompson v. Leben Home for Adults, 792 N.Y.S.2d 597, 598 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (same); Colon v. City of New York, 15 A.D.3d 173, 173, 788 N.Y.S.2d 606, 606 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2005) (same); Gonzalez v. ZAM Apartment Corp., 11 A.D.3d 657, 658, 782 N.Y.S.2d 922, 922-23 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004) (same). But see Osario v. BRF Constr. Co., 23 A.D.3d 202, 203, 803 N.Y.S.2d 525, 526 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2005) (holding that motion court properly considered plaintiff’s cross-motion for partial summary judgment, which, although untimely, was made in response to defendant’s timely summary judgment motion). 1542 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 summary judgment, the dilatory movant may obtain relief if the court “searches the record” on the underlying motion. 47 A court searches the record when, in the course of its consideration of a pending summary judgment motion, it grants summary judgment to a non-moving party. 48 This procedure is expressly authorized by CPLR 3212(b). 49 While a potent weapon, the court’s search of the record is confined to those causes of action or issues which are the subject of the underlying motion. 50 Since any relief awarded to a non-moving party under a search of the record is strictly limited by the relief sought by the movant, the procedure may prove fruitless for the non-movant. The decision to search the record is the court’s to make, and no request by a non-moving party is required. A party seeking relief on the back of another party’s summary judgment motion should, however, ask the court to search the record, marshal the evidence favorable to her position, and highlight in her answering papers why judgment as a matter of law should be awarded in her favor. D. Effect of Mistrial on CPLR 3212(a)’s Timing Requirements If a mistrial occurs and a new trial is required, it will not extend the period in CPLR 3212(a). In Hesse v. Rockland County Legislature, 51 the trial court improperly exercised its discretion by entertaining a late motion for summary judgment, without good cause, following a mistrial. There may 47 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3212(b) (McKinney 2005). See SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 282. 49 CPLR 3212(b) provides, in pertinent part, that “[i]f it shall appear that any party other than the moving party is entitled to a summary judgment, the court may grant such judgment without the necessity of a cross-motion.” N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3212(b) (McKinney 2005). 50 See, e.g., Dunham v. Hilco Constr. Co., 89 N.Y.2d 425, 429-30, 676 N.E.2d 1178, 1180, 654 N.Y.S.2d 335, 337 (1996); Cortez v. Countrywide Ins. Co., 17 A.D.3d 508, 509, 793 N.Y.S.2d 189, 189-90 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005); Sullivan v. Troser Mgmt., Inc., 15 A.D.3d 1011, 1012, 791 N.Y.S.2d 231, 232 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2005); WFR Assoc. v. Mem’l Hosp., 14 A.D.3d 840, 841, 788 N.Y.S.2d 459, 460 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 2005); Baseball Office of the Comm’r v. Marsh & McLennan, Inc., 295 A.D.2d 73, 82, 742 N.Y.S.2d 40, 48 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2002); see also Siegel, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C3212:23 (2005); SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 282. 51 18 A.D.3d 614, 614, 795 N.Y.S.2d 339, 340 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005). Cf. Noble v. Cole, 267 A.D.2d 702, 702-03, 699 N.Y.S.2d 527, 527 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 1999) (expert testimony barred at retrial because prior order precluding it during first trial was now law of the case); Hothan v. The Metro. Suburban Bus Auth., N.Y.L.J., Nov. 21, 2002, at 24 (N.Y. Sup. Ct., Nassau County) (defendant allowed to call expert witness barred from use at first trial); see generally Connors, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C3101:29A (2005). 48 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1543 be circumstances, however, in which the evidence submitted at the first trial forms the basis for a subsequent summary judgment motion. 52 If this evidence was not previously available, and it forms the basis for the motion, it could form the basis of a good-cause determination. 53 E. Cases Stricken from the Trial Calendar If a case is stricken from the trial calendar, however, and a subsequent note of issue is filed, a new period under CPLR 3212(a) may be available for moving for summary judgment. In Slane v. Kalache, plaintiff served and filed a note of issue and certificate of readiness and maintained that the case was ready for trial. 54 Approximately eighteen months later, the case was stricken from the trial calendar because plaintiff’s illness prevented her from proceeding to trial. 55 After the expiration of another eighteen months, the court granted plaintiff’s motion to restore the case to the trial calendar, contingent upon plaintiff filing a new note of issue. 56 The Slane court held that “the service and filing of the second note of issue in the case, pursuant to a restoration order, constitutes a new note of issue, restarting the 120-day period within which to move for summary judgment.” 57 The result in Slane could lead to mischief, by awarding a dilatory party a new opportunity to move for summary judgment. For example, a case may be stricken from the trial calendar if a party fails to attend a calendar call or appears without being ready to proceed. 58 In some circumstances, this 52 See 161 Siegel’s Practice Review, Even After Mistrial, No Summary Judgment May Be Allowed, at 2 (May 2005). 53 Id. 54 794 N.Y.S.2d 835, 836 (Sup. Ct. Bronx County 2005). No summary judgment motion was made by any of the defendants during the pendency of the first note of issue. 55 Id. The plaintiff’s illness was apparently disclosed at the pretrial conference. Id. See N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.26 (2005) (requiring judge to order pretrial conference within 15 to 45 days before anticipated trial date to discuss various issues with the aim of narrowing the issues for trial). 56 Slane v. Kalache, 794 N.Y.S.2d 835, 836 (Sup. Ct. Bronx County 2005). 57 Id. at 837. 58 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3404 (McKinney 2005) (requiring party to restore case to trial calendar within one year from when case was “marked ‘off’ or struck from the calendar”; failure to restore case within one year required that it “be deemed abandoned and shall be dismissed”). See N.Y. COMP. CODES R. REGS., tit. 22, § 202.27 (2005) (where parties do not appear and proceed or announce their readiness to proceed, judge may, among other things, note default and dismiss action); see generally SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 376; infra notes 217-53 and accompanying text. 1544 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 will require the filing and service of a new note of issue. 59 Courts should be circumspect in allowing a party who has caused the delay any additional time to move for summary judgment. 60 To avoid an extension of the period in CPLR 3212(a), the court could order a subsequent note of issue to be filed “nunc pro tunc,” which would simply amend the original note of issue without affecting its filing date. 61 On the other hand, if a note of issue is stricken based on outstanding disclosure, 62 CPLR 3212(a)’s time period should run from the filing of the subsequent note of issue. 63 Cases are frequently transferred from supreme court to the New York City Civil Court, either on consent 64 or without 59 “A case marked off pursuant to CPLR 3404 does not automatically result in the vacatur of the note of issue.” Basetti v. Nour, 287 A.D.2d 126, 133, 731 N.Y.S.2d 35, 40-41 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2001) (analyzing four possible options for court where party fails to appear or is unable to proceed after filing of note of issue). Basetti holds that “[i]f the court chooses to vacate the note of issue, the certificate of readiness must be incorrect in some material way. The basis for vacatur cannot be that the plaintiff failed to appear or for some other reason is unable to proceed.” Id. at 41. See infra notes 23153 and accompanying text (discussing four options for court in context of Brill problem). 60 Courts have inherent authority to condition the restoration under CPLR 3404. See, e.g., Indrunas v. Escher Constr. Corp., 277 A.D.2d 28, 28, 716 N.Y.S.2d 10, 11 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2000) (plaintiffs’ motion to vacate order dismissing complaint pursuant to CPLR 3404 granted, upon condition that plaintiffs’ counsel pay to each separately appearing defendant $1,250); Sanchez v. Javind Apartment Corp., 246 A.D.2d 353, 353, 667 N.Y.S.2d 708, 709 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1998) (plaintiff’s motion to restore case to trial calendar granted, upon condition that plaintiff’s counsel pay $5,000 to defendant); Barrada v. Target Constr. Corp., 31 A.D.2d 810, 810, 299 N.Y.S.2d 708, 708-09 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1969) (plaintiff’s motion to restore case to trial calendar granted, upon condition that costs be paid); Hood v. City of New York, 4 Misc. 3d 627, 632-33, 781 N.Y.S.2d 431, 435 (Sup. Ct. Bronx County 2004) (plaintiff’s motion to restore case to trial calendar granted, upon condition that plaintiff’s counsel pay $500 to municipal defendant). Therefore, courts appear to have the power to condition an order requiring the refiling of a note of issue to limit the ability to make any subsequent motions for summary judgment. See Basetti, 731 N.Y.S.2d at 41 (“[T]he trial court’s discretion is paramount and it alone has the ability to appropriately dispose of cases appearing on the trial calendar.”). Regardless of whether the court exercises this authority, a party should still be permitted to move for summary judgment “on good cause shown.” N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3212(a) (McKinney 2005). See infra Section V.C.1 & 2 and accompanying text. N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.21(e) (2005) also allows the vacatur of the note of issue in several circumstances. Section 202.21(f) outlines the standards for reinstating the note of issue after vacatur. 61 In Weitzner v. Elazarov, 189 Misc. 2d 646, 647, 735 N.Y.S.2d 362, 363 (Sup. Ct. Kings County 2001) the court permitted the first note of issue to be amended and refiled “nunc pro tunc” to add a demand for a jury trial. “Treating the new filing ‘now for then,’ the new filing merely amended the prior note of issue and had the same effect as if originally filed.” Id. Therefore, the court held that the refiling of the note of issue did not extend the time in which to make a motion for summary judgment. Id. 62 See infra notes 83-84 and accompanying text. 63 This will allow a party to obtain necessary disclosure for a summary judgment motion, without facing an untimeliness problem under CPLR 3212(a). 64 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 325(c) (McKinney 2005). 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1545 it. 65 If a case is transferred to a New York City Civil Court after a note of issue has been filed, questions may arise as to whether a party may move for summary judgment in the lower court after the transfer. In Istrefovic v. Santos, 66 the case was transferred by supreme court to the civil court pursuant to CPLR 325(d). 67 Apparently unaware of the transfer, defendant mistakenly made an otherwise timely motion for summary judgment in the supreme court, which was returned. 68 To the moving party’s chagrin, the court relied on the uniform rules of the New York City Civil Court, which generally require that transferred actions be placed on the trial calendar so they are reached for trial as if the note of issue had been originally filed in the civil court. 69 Thus, the court concluded that the motion for summary judgment subsequently served in civil court was untimely. 70 In addition, defendant failed to provide any good cause for the delay. 71 V. WHAT CONSTITUTES “GOOD CAUSE” UNDER CPLR 3212(a)? Demonstrating good cause is now the key to the door that CPLR 3212(a) has closed in the face of a dilatory movant. This section will first explore the matter of presenting the issue 65 N.Y. C.P.L.R 325(d) (McKinney 2005). See 22 N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.13 (2005). See generally SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 27. 66 No. 554-2002, 2004 WL 3245351 (N.Y. Civ. Ct. Bronx County Oct. 4, 2004). 67 Id. at *1. A transfer under CPLR 325(d) does not require consent. N.Y. C.P.L.R. 325(d) (McKinney 2005). CPLR 3212(a)’s time period applies in the New York City Civil Courts. See N.Y. C.P.L.R. 101 (McKinney 2005); N.Y. CITY CIV. CT. ACT § 2102 (McKinney 2005). 68 Istrefovic, 2004 WL 3245351, at *1. The motion was served and filed in the New York Supreme Court within 120 days of the filing of the note of issue in that court. The motion was “returned by the court because the motion was incorrectly served in Supreme Court.” Id. 69 N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22 § 208.15 (2005) (“Actions transferred from the Supreme Court to the Civil Court of the City of New York shall be placed in such order and relative position on the appropriate calendars that they will be reached for trial insofar as practicable as if a notice of trial had been filed in the Civil Court of the City of New York for the same date as that for which the note of issue was filed in the Supreme Court.”). 70 Istrefovic, 2004 WL 3245351 at *1. The court observed that no new “Notice of Trial” was required to be filed in Civil Court. Id.; see 22 N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 208.17 (2005) (governing procedure applicable to filing Notice of Trial and Certificate of Readiness in the New York City Civil Court). 71 Istrefovic, 2004 WL 3245351 at *2. The defendant requested the court to entertain the delayed motion “in the interests of justice and in the absence of prejudice to the plaintiff.” Id. The court held that these grounds do not constitute good cause under Brill’s holding. See supra notes 25-28 and accompanying text. 1546 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 of good cause to the court, and will then examine recognized and potential excuses constituting good cause. A. Adjudication of Good Cause The issue of the timeliness of a summary judgment motion will principally arrive before a court in an affirmation of counsel, submitted in support of or in opposition to a pending motion. 72 In light of the language employed by the courts regarding the necessity of the showing of good cause to consider a belated summary judgment motion, counsel for the movant should raise this issue in her affirmation in support of the motion, and proffer good cause for the delay in making the motion. 73 In the event that the dilatory movant fails to address the issue of good cause, the party opposing the motion should raise the issue of the timeliness of the motion in her papers opposing the motion. 74 Counsel for the party opposing the 72 See, e.g., Dettmann v. Page, 18 A.D.3d 422, 422, 794 N.Y.S.2d 406, 406 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005); Koloski v. Metro. Life Ins. Co., 5 Misc. 3d 1028(A), 799 N.Y.S.2d 161, No. 600231-02, 2004 WL 2903626 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. New York County Nov. 3, 2004); Lawrence v. Kuo, 5 Misc. 3d 1019(A), No. 265971-01, 2004 WL 2683632 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Queens County Aug. 16, 2004). 73 See, e.g., McNeill v. Menter, 19 A.D.3d 1161, 1162, 797 N.Y.S.2d 230, 231 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2005) (“Because defendant offered no explanation for her failure to move during the 120 days after the filing of the note of issue, the court erred in excusing its untimeliness.”) (citation omitted); Rivera v. Toruno, 796 N.Y.S.2d 708, 709 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (“[I]n the absence of a satisfactory explanation for the delay in filing the summary judgment motion, the motion should not have been considered, even if it appeared to be meritorious.”) (citation omitted); Nobile v. Town of Hempstead, 17 A.D.3d 647, 647, 792 N.Y.S.2d 910, 910 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (“The Supreme Court improvidently exercised its discretion in considering the defendant’s untimely motion for summary judgment, since the defendant failed to show good cause for the delay.”) (citation omitted); Bressingham v. Jamaica Hosp. Med. Ctr., 793 N.Y.S.2d 176, 176 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (“The branch of the cross-motion of defendant Jamaica Hospital Medical Center which was for summary judgment dismissing the complaint insofar as asserted against it, made more than 120 days after the filing of the note of issue, was untimely and should not have been entertained without a showing of good cause for the delay.”) (citation omitted); Kone v. Ritter Sysco Food Serv., Inc., 15 A.D.3d 627, 627-28, 789 N.Y.S.2d 902, 902 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (stating that “[t]he Supreme Court improvidently exercised its discretion in considering the untimely motion of the defendant Ritter Sysco Food Service, Inc., for summary judgment in view of its failure to offer a satisfactory explanation for not serving the motion within 120 days of the filing of the note of issue”); Thompson v. N.Y. City Bd. of Educ., 10 A.D.3d 650, 651, 781 N.Y.S.2d 617, 617 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004) (“The Supreme Court improvidently exercised its discretion in considering the defendant’s untimely motion for summary judgment in view of the defendant’s failure to offer a satisfactory explanation for not serving the motion within 120 days of the filing of the note of issue . . . .”). 74 See, e.g., Barracks v. Metro North Commuter R.R., 8 Misc. 3d 1024(A), No. 122591-02, 2005 WL 1919100 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. New York County Mar. 18, 2005); Slane v. Kalache, 794 N.Y.S.2d 835, 836-37 (Sup. Ct. Bronx County 2005). 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1547 motion should highlight the amount of time the parties had to make summary judgment motions following the filing of the note of issue, and demonstrate that the subject motion was made after the allotted time. The burden will then lie with the dilatory movant to demonstrate the existence of good cause for the late motion in a reply. 75 The issue of good cause may also be litigated through a motion for leave to make a belated summary judgment motion. Here, the dilatory movant does not move for summary judgment, but seeks permission to make a belated motion. Such a tactic was employed by the movant in Cooper v. Hodge, 76 in which the defendant, without seeking summary judgment, sought an extension of the period within which to make the motion. The Fourth Department reversed the order of the trial court denying the defendant’s motion, but did not entertain the merits of a summary judgment motion. Rather, the court simply issued an order granting defendant leave to file the motion with the supreme court. The procedural path illustrated in Cooper offers an efficient and economical alternative to the making of a late motion for summary judgment. By merely moving for permission to make a belated summary judgment motion, the movant need only submit the proof necessary to establish good cause for the motion, a quantum of proof which should pale in comparison to the proof necessary to support the summary judgment motion itself. Concomitantly, the movant, while testing the quality of its excuse for the late motion, will save time and financial resources. If the court grants permission to make a late motion for summary judgment, it should require that the motion be served promptly to avoid further delay. 75 See Singh v. Deopaul, No. 46334-01, 2005 WL 1774139, at *1-2 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Kings County July 12, 2005). Cf. Home Ins. Co. v. Leprino Foods Co., 7 A.D.3d 471, 472, 777 N.Y.S.2d 472, 472-73 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2004) (“Plaintiff’s no-oralmodification argument, although raised for the first time on reply, was directly responsive to defendant’s opposition to the summary judgment motion.”) (citation omitted); Davison v. Order Ecumenical, 281 A.D.2d 383, 383, 721 N.Y.S.2d 282, 283 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2001) (“The Supreme Court properly considered the arguments raised in the defendants’ reply affirmation, since they were made in direct response to the plaintiffs’ opposition papers.”) (citation omitted). 76 13 A.D.3d 1111, 1112, 787 N.Y.S.2d 551, 552 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2004); see also Brooks v. Ross, 24 A.D.3d 589, 808 N.Y.S.2d 358 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (supreme court properly granted defendant leave to file a late motion for summary judgment); Stimson v. E.M. Cahill Co., 8 A.D.3d 1004, 1005, 778 N.Y.S.2d 585, 585 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2004) (holding that supreme court erred in denying defendant’s motion seeking leave to serve a late motion for summary judgment). 1548 B. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Stipulation to Extend CPLR 3212(a)’s Time Period What is a court to do if there has been a violation of CPLR 3212(a)’s timing requirements, but the parties consent or stipulate to have the untimely motion heard? Several courts, without dedicating substantial discussion to the matter, have held or indicated that the untimely motion may be entertained. 77 More recently, however, in Balcerzak v. DNA Contracting, LLC, the court held to the contrary. 78 In Balcerzak, the parties entered into a written stipulation extending the period of time they had to move for summary judgment. 79 The stipulation was signed by counsel for each of the parties to the action prior to the filing of the note of issue. 80 Subsequently, two of the parties made summary judgment motions within the stipulated time frame, but after the court-imposed deadline. 81 While acknowledging that parties generally have the right to chart their own procedural course in litigation, the court held that the stipulation extending the time to move for summary judgment contravened the public policy of the state codified in CPLR 3212(a) and was, therefore, unenforceable. 82 Given the legislative history of CPLR 3212(a), and the important concerns expressed by the Court of Appeals in interpreting the 1997 amendment to the statute, Balcerak’s 77 See Gonzalez v. Zam Apartment Corp., 11 A.D.3d 657, 782 N.Y.S.2d 922, 922 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004); Mignott v. Kreidman, 7 Misc. 3d 1021(A), No. 1001732001, 2005 WL 1118074, at *1 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. New York County Mar. 15, 2005); Carvajal v. City of New York, 7 Misc. 3d 509, 511, 794 N.Y.S.2d 574, 575-76 (Sup. Ct. Kings County 2005); see also Buckner v. City of N.Y., 800 N.Y.S.2d 333, 336 (Sup. Ct. New York County 2005) (stating that parties could have entered into a stipulation extending the time to make summary judgment motions). 78 9 Misc. 3d 524, 802 N.Y.S.2d 324, 325 (Sup. Ct. Kings County 2005). 79 Id. 80 Id. 81 Id. at 329. The action, pending in Supreme Court, Kings County, was subject to the Uniform Civil Term Rules of the Supreme Court, Kings County, Rule 13, which requires all summary judgment motions to be made within 60 days of the filing of the note of issue. See supra note 17 and accompanying text. 82 Balcerzak, 802 N.Y.S.2d at 329. The parties, having failed to obtain a judicially sanctioned extension of time (e.g., “so-ordered” stipulation), had their motions denied as untimely. Id. See Powers v. Solomon, 4 Misc. 3d 1007(A), 791 N.Y.S.2d 872, No. 01-0222, 2004 WL 1586886, at *1 (Sup. Ct. Greene County July 13, 2004) (motions timely made under agreement between parties, but outside time frame established by court, denied in absence of good cause); Eighteen Assocs., LLC v. Nanjim Leasing Corp., 4 Misc. 3d 1004(A), 791 N.Y.S.2d 869, No. 12554-97, 2004 WL 1488393, at *3 (Sup. Ct. Kings County June 29, 2004) (“While it is understandable that the parties herein do not want to relitigate this matter, and as alleged, the granting of summary judgment may ‘streamline’ the issues and reduce the litigation, that fact alone does not form the basis for ‘good cause shown.’”). 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1549 conclusion more closely comports with the purpose of the rule limiting the time within which to make a motion for summary judgment. C. Demonstrating Good Cause Broadly stated, good cause is established under CPLR 3212(a) if the movant proffers a reasonable explanation for the delay in moving for summary judgment. The ingredients constituting good cause under the facts of a particular case will vary, but certain trends are emerging. 1. Outstanding Disclosure This heading, at first glance, might lead to confusion. The general period within which to obtain pretrial disclosure terminates with the filing of the note of issue and its loyal companion, the certificate of readiness. 83 Therefore, under the design of the CPLR and the Uniform Rules, all parties will have completed disclosure by the date on which the note of issue has been filed and will have sufficient time to move for summary judgment within the confines of CPLR 3212(a). If a party is served with a note of issue and certificate of readiness prior to the completion of disclosure, the proper remedy is to promptly move to vacate the note of issue and identify any outstanding disclosure. 84 The caselaw in this area 83 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3402(a) (McKinney 2005) (service and filing of note of issue places case on trial calendar); N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.21(a) (2005) (note of issue must be accompanied by certificate of readiness in the form prescribed by this section). The certificate of readiness form requires, among other things, that the party filing the document verify that disclosure is completed. N.Y. COMP. CODE R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.21(b) (2005). A party is only entitled to disclosure after the filing of the note if she can establish that “unusual or unanticipated circumstances” warrant it. N.Y. COMP. CODE R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.21(d) (2005). 84 N.Y. COMP. CODE R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.21(e) (2005) (party must move to vacate note of issue and certificate of readiness within 20 days after service; however, a party may belatedly move upon a showing of good cause, and court may vacate note if it appears that material fact in certificate of readiness is incorrect). See, e.g., Blamer v. Singh, 20 A.D.3d 440, 441, 797 N.Y.S.2d 777, 777 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (Supreme Court properly vacated note of issue, sua sponte, based on misrepresentation contained in certificate of readiness); Simon v. City of Syracuse Police Dept., 13 A.D.3d 1228, 1229, 787 N.Y.S.2d 577, 578 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2004) (In light of “the patent untruth of plaintiff’s certification that discovery had been waived, was unnecessary, or had been completed. . . . [T]he court should have exercised its power to treat the note of issue as a nullity and to vacate it sua sponte.” (citation omitted)); Costanza v. Skyline Towers 5, 8 A.D.3d 524, 525, 778 N.Y.S.2d 720, 721 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004) (“Supreme Court improvidently exercised its discretion in denying that branch of the appellant’s motion which was to vacate the note of issue in order to permit it to conduct discovery proceedings.” (citation omitted)); Lynch v. Vollono, 6 A.D.3d 505, 505, 774 N.Y.S.2d 433, 433 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004) (“A note of issue should be vacated when it is based upon a certificate of readiness that contains erroneous facts, such as that 1550 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 demonstrates, however, that disclosure frequently takes place after the filing of the note of issue with the consent of the parties and/or the court’s blessing. There are many circumstances in which a party, usually the plaintiff, files a note of issue prematurely to secure a place on the trial calendar or to comply with a preliminary conference order. In Gonzalez v. 98 Mag Leasing Corp., 85 for example, defendants moved to vacate the note of issue filed by plaintiff because two fact witnesses had not yet been produced pursuant to a court order. The court declined to vacate the note of issue, but granted defendants’ motion to the extent of allowing disclosure to continue. 86 The fact witnesses ultimately provided favorable testimony for the defendants, which was used in support of their motion for summary judgment. Although the motion was made long after the 120-day period in CPLR 3212(a) had expired, the Court of Appeals held that the supreme court properly exercised its discretion in concluding that there was good cause to entertain it. The Court emphasized that defendants promptly moved to vacate the note of issue due to the outstanding disclosure and moved for summary judgment “shortly” after the depositions were concluded. 87 The procedural history in Gonzalez is somewhat discovery has been completed.”); Munoz v. 147 Corp., 309 A.D.2d 647, 648, 767 N.Y.S.2d 1, 2 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2003) (“The recital in the certificate of readiness that discovery is complete is obviously incorrect since defendants have not yet been able to identify and depose essential firefighter witnesses and, thus, the motion to strike the note of issue should have been granted.” (citation omitted)); see generally Vasquez v. Gomez, 7 Misc. 3d 958, 796 N.Y.S.2d 869 (Sup. Ct. Bronx County 2005); Bouilland v. Angulo, No. 114116-01, 2004 WL 2941569, at *1 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. New York County Sept. 27, 2004); 160 Siegel’s Practice Review, Late Summary Judgment Motion, at 4 (Apr. 2005). 85 95 N.Y.2d 124, 126-27, 733 N.E.2d 203, 204-05, 711 N.Y.S.2d 131, 132-133 (2000). 86 Cf. N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.21(d) (2005) (where party is prevented from filing note of issue and certificate of readiness because of reasons beyond her control, court, upon motion supported by affidavit, may permit party to file note of issue upon such conditions as court deems appropriate); see also Certified Elec. Contracting Corp. v. City of New York, 23 A.D.3d 596, 598, 804 N.Y.S.2d 794, 796 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (order of court stayed parties from moving for summary judgment pending completion of disclosure after filing of note of issue). 87 Gonzalez, 711 N.Y.S.2d at 134. In Espejo v. Hiro Real Estate Co., 19 A.D.3d 360, 361, 796 N.Y.S.2d 162, 163 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005), the court determined that, although defendant established good cause for its failure to move for summary judgment during the initial 120-day period following the filing of the note of issue, good cause for a late motion was lacking because defendant offered no excuse for the ensuing five-month delay between obtaining the necessary disclosure and moving for summary judgment. Espejo relied on Gonzalez, in which the motion was made “shortly” after the essential disclosure was complete. Id. See Perini Corp. v. City of N.Y., 789 N.Y.S.2d 29, 31 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2005). In light of Espejo and Perini it is clear that a dilatory 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1551 atypical, but its facts established grounds for good cause in a case involving the common problem of delayed disclosure. 88 In Kunz v. Gleeson, which also involved disclosure obtained after the filing of the note of issue, the defendant moved for summary judgment approximately two weeks after the deadline set by the court. 89 The Second Department determined that defendant established good cause for the “slight delay” because the independent medical exams of the plaintiff were not conducted until after the note of issue had been filed. 90 This delayed disclosure, coupled with the fact that the results of the exams provided the evidentiary basis for the motion for summary judgment, established good cause to entertain the late motion. 91 Similarly, in Cooper v. Hodge, disclosure was not yet completed at the time of the filing of the note of issue. 92 Rather than moving to vacate the note of issue, defendant sought an extension of the 120-day period in CPLR 3212(a) until after disclosure was complete. 93 Defendant labored under the belief that he had obtained the extension, but the trial court ultimately rejected the motion as untimely. 94 The Fourth Department reversed, noting that the attorneys for both sides believed the court had granted an extension of time to move for summary judgment and concluding that defendant established good cause to entertain the motion. 95 Despite this Appellate Division caselaw, parties planning to move for summary judgment on the basis of delayed disclosure after CPLR 3212(a)’s limitation period has expired are asking for trouble on several fronts if they have not attempted to vacate the note of issue. In Gonzalez, the defendant promptly moved to vacate the note of issue and identified the significance of the outstanding disclosure. Although the trial court did not grant the requested relief, it expressly permitted the outstanding disclosure to be completed, movant must account for the entire period of delay (i.e., demonstrate good cause) when making a belated summary judgment motion. 88 Cf. Orenstein v. Brum, __ A.D.3d __, 811 N.Y.S.2d 644, 2006 WL 722167 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2006) (finding good cause for delayed motion because defendants could not know precisely what claims they would be moving against until the motion to amend plaintiff’s complaint was decided). 89 9 A.D.3d 480, 481, 781 N.Y.S.2d 50, 51 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004). 90 Id. 91 Id. 92 787 N.Y.S.2d 551, 552 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2004). 93 Id. 94 Id. 95 Id. 1552 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 thereby laying the groundwork for establishing good cause to extend CPLR 3212(a)’s time frame. 96 Conversely, a party who fails to timely move to vacate the note of issue faces substantial difficulties on at least two fronts. If an adversary will not cooperate and provide disclosure after the filing of the note of issue, the party may be required to establish that “unusual or unanticipated circumstances” have developed since the filing to secure a court order requiring the disclosure. 97 Finally, and most significantly, if the party seeks to move for summary judgment after obtaining the materials through delayed disclosure, CPLR 3212(a)’s time periods will likely have expired, requiring a showing of good cause. In this regard, Kunz 98 and other cases have held that delayed disclosure can only constitute good cause where the evidence forming the basis for the motion for summary judgment was acquired after the filing of the note of issue. 99 96 Cf. Certified Elec. Contracting Corp. v. City of New York, 18 A.D.3d 596, 597, 795 N.Y.S.2d 325, 326-27 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (good cause existed for late motion and cross-motion for summary judgment where court stayed all parties from moving for summary judgment pending the completion of discovery, and note of issue was conditioned upon completion of discovery); Quizhpi v. Lochinvar Corp., 12 A.D.3d 252, 252, 785 N.Y.S.2d 431, 431 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2004) (good cause existed for allowing late motion for summary judgment “where the court acquiesced in, and had actual knowledge of, ongoing discovery subsequent to the filing of the note of issue”); Ramirez v. Wyeth Laboratories, Inc., 179 Misc. 2d 764, 768, 686 N.Y.S.2d 602, 605 (Sup. Ct. New York County 1999) (stating that “because the note of issue was filed prematurely largely due to the directions of the court, it cannot be said that [defendant] has failed to establish good cause for the late filing of the summary judgment motion”). 97 N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.21(d) (2005). See, e.g., Gomez v. N.Y. City Trans. Auth., 19 A.D.3d 366, 366, 795 N.Y.S.2d 909, 910 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005); Candray v. Eicher, 19 A.D.3d 352, 352, 795 N.Y.S.2d 908, 908 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005); Esteva v. Catsimatidis, 4 A.D.3d 210, 210-11, 772 N.Y.S.2d 267, 268 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2004); Karakostas v. Avis Rent A Car Systems, 306 A.D.2d 381, 382, 761 N.Y.S.2d 283, 283 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2003); Rodriguez v. Sau Wo Lau, 298 A.D.2d 376, 377, 751 N.Y.S.2d 231, 231 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2002); Rinker v. Oberoi, 288 A.D.2d 873, 874, 732 N.Y.S.2d 787, 788 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2001); Di Matteo v. Grey, 280 A.D.2d 929, 930, 721 N.Y.S.2d 182, 183 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2001); Francis v. Board of Educ. of the City of Mount Vernon, 278 A.D.2d 449, 449, 717 N.Y.S.2d 660, 661 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2000); Philpott v. Bernales, 196 Misc. 2d 117, 118, 762 N.Y.S.2d 771, 772 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2003). 98 Kunz v. Gleeson, 781 N.Y.S.2d 50, 51 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004). 99 Brown v. City of New York, 6 Misc. 3d 1017(A), No. 20673-2001, 2005 WL 263964, at *2 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Bronx County Jan. 12, 2005); see Smith v. Nameth, 807 N.Y.S.2d 411, 412 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2006) (affidavit obtained from defendant bus driver constituted “good cause” for delayed motion where it was not wholly duplicative of his deposition testimony and was “necessary for motion”); LoGrasso v. Myer, 16 A.D.3d 1089, 1089, 790 N.Y.S.2d 919, 919 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2005); Gonzalez v. Zam Apartment Corp., 782 N.Y.S.2d 922, 922 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004); Caiola v. Allcity Ins. Co., 277 A.D.2d 273, 273-74, 715 N.Y.S.2d 736, 737 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2000); see 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1553 This required linkage between the disclosure obtained after the filing of the note of issue and the grounds for the summary judgment motion presents dilemmas for the dilatory movant, which should be avoided at all costs. Even if the movant believes the disclosure will strengthen the motion, there is a significant chance that it will prove fruitless. If so, the movant may now be unable to establish good cause to allow for a late motion. Therefore, lawyers in these circumstances may prefer to forego further disclosure, make a timely motion, and simply rely on the proof already obtained. This also avoids the risk of a court determining that the disclosure should have been obtained earlier, foreclosing any finding of good cause. 100 2. Other Potential Excuses Constituting “Good Cause” While issues related to outstanding disclosure have dominated the attention of the courts in addressing good cause under CPLR 3212(a), several other excuses for belated summary judgment motions have also been considered. CPLR 3116(a), governing the procedure for signing a deposition, provides the deponent sixty days, running from submission of the transcript to the deponent, in which to make changes to the transcript. 101 Therefore, occasions will arise where a movant cannot satisfy CPLR 3212(a)’s time frame because she is required to wait for the return of a corrected, signed deposition transcript that will provide the evidentiary basis for the summary judgment motion. 102 The courts have also Espejo v. Hiro Real Estate Co., 796 N.Y.S.2d, 162, 163 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (witness’s testimony was not essential to making motion); First Union Auto Fin., Inc. v. Donat, 16 A.D.3d 372, 373-74, 791 N.Y.S.2d 596, 597 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005); Buckner v. City of New York, 800 N.Y.S.2d 333, 337 (Sup. Ct. New York County 2005). 100 See Czernicki v. Lawniczak, 25 A.D.3d 581, 582, 806 N.Y.S.2d 876, 877 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2006) (noting that no excuse was offered as to why it took plaintiff more than two and one-half years to complete whatever disclosure remained after the filing of the note of issue); Dettmann v. Page, 794 N.Y.S.2d 406, 406-07 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005); Espejo, 796 N.Y.S.2d at 163 (late movant, who had access to witness’s testimony at any time, could not establish good cause for delay). 101 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3116(a) (McKinney 2005). See Connors, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C3116:1 (2005) (discussing caselaw precluding the use of unsigned transcripts in situations where CPLR 3116(a)’s requirements have not been met). “If the witness fails to sign and return the deposition within sixty days, it may be used as fully as though signed.” N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3116(a) (McKinney 2005). See, e.g., Ireland v. Geico Corp., 2 A.D.3d 917, 918, 768 N.Y.S.2d 508, 510 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 2003); Zabari v. City of New York, 242 A.D.2d 15, 17, 672 N.Y.S.2d 332, 333 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1998); Thomas v. Hampton Express, Inc., 208 A.D.2d 824, 825, 617 N.Y.S.2d 831, 832 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1994). 102 This circumstance has been recognized as a valid basis for making a motion on the eve of trial, even before the amendment of CPLR 3212(a). See Kule Res., Ltd. v. Reliance Group, Inc., 427 N.Y.S.2d 612, 613 (N.Y. 1980) (per curiam) (“When 1554 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 been sympathetic to movants in this situation, and have found good cause to entertain belated summary judgment motions. 103 Attorneys facing trying personal situations may also find refuge in the arms of CPLR 3212(a)’s good cause provision. In Stimson v. E.M. Cahill Company, Inc., 104 both the movants’ attorney and the attorney’s secretary had family emergencies occur on the last day on which to make the summary judgment motion, which prevented them from coming to the office. Resultantly, the motion, which had already been prepared, was not served until two days later. 105 The movants sought leave to serve a late motion based upon the circumstances which befell counsel and her secretary. The Fourth Department reversed the order of supreme court, which denied the movants’ motion seeking leave to serve a summary judgment motion, and granted the motion, concluding that the movants had demonstrated “an adequate explanation . . . for the de minimis delay . . . .” 106 the reason for delay is to complete depositions, which as the Appellate Division found was essential to the making of the motion, denial of the motion as untimely is error.” (citation omitted)). If the deposition transcript will not provide the evidentiary basis for the motion for summary judgment, the movant will be unable to establish good cause. See Kunz, 781 N.Y.S.2d at 51; supra notes 90-91 and accompanying text. 103 See Burnell v. Huneau, 1 A.D.3d 758, 760, 767 N.Y.S.2d 163, 164 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 2003); Fainberg v. Dalton Kent Sec. Group, Inc., 268 A.D.2d 247, 248, 701 N.Y.S.2d 41, 42 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2000). See also Gaffney v. BFP 300 Madison II, LLC, 18 A.D.3d 403, 403, 795 N.Y.S.2d 579, 579 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2005). The party moving for summary judgment should do so promptly after the expiration of the sixtyday period. Any significant delay beyond the expiration of the sixty-day period in CPLR 3116(a) will likely foreclose a party from establishing good cause under CPLR 3212(a). Espejo, 796 N.Y.S.2d at 163 (court determined good cause under CPLR 3212(a) was lacking because defendant did not move for summary judgment “shortly” after obtaining necessary disclosure). 104 8 A.D.3d 1004, 1004, 778 N.Y.S.2d 585, 585 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2004). 105 Id. at 585. Service, not filing, marks the point at which a motion is made. N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2211 (McKinney 2005). See Siegel, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C2211:4 (1991); SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 243; supra notes 36-43 and accompanying text. 106 Stimson, 778 N.Y.S.2d at 585 (quoting Luciano v. Apple Maintenance & Servs., Inc., 289 A.D.2d 90, 91, 734 N.Y.S.2d 153, 154 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2001) (emphasis added)). See Centeno v. Metro. Transp. Auth. Long Island Bus, 193 Misc.2d 617, 619, 749 N.Y.S.2d 704, 706-07 (Sup. Ct. Nassau County 2002) (illness and hospitalization of movant’s attorney’s mother constituted good cause for late summary judgment motion); see also Newsday, Inc. v. Nelkenbaum, 8 Misc. 3d 1005(A), No. 303823-03, 2005 WL 1490263, at *1 (N.Y. Civ. Ct. Kings County June 23, 2005) (“Defendant’s motion for summary judgment was timely filed [the Notice of Trial is dated September 21, 2004, and the motion was made on January 4, 2005]. Defendant’s counsel’s illness constitutes good cause for not having his motion heard on its original return date, and because of the circumstances, this Court is considering the instant motion, with all the same papers, nunc pro tunc.”). 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1555 Another example of good cause is found in Trump Village Section 3, Inc. v. New York Housing Finance Agency. 107 In Trump, the First Department excused a belated motion for summary judgment, made on renewal, 108 which was premised on a subsequent appellate determination in the case that could not have been timely raised in the original moving papers. 109 Moreover, the appellate decision addressed a potentially determinative issue in the case. Trump presents a compelling example of good cause, but it is not one that a lawyer can rely on in advance. Can a movant’s efforts at attempting to secure a discontinuance of the action excuse her delay in making a timely summary judgment motion? Maybe, 110 maybe not. 111 Regardless of support in the caselaw for this excuse, the safest practice would be to promptly make the motion, as it can be withdrawn if efforts to obtain a discontinuance later prove successful. 112 Similarly, litigation strategy should not constitute good cause, as demonstrated by McNeill v. Menter. 113 In McNeill, defendant moved for summary judgment more than four months after the expiration of CPLR 3212(a)’s time period. 114 Defendant argued that there was good cause for the delay because she was waiting for the expiration of plaintiff’s 107 307 A.D.2d 891, 893-94, 764 N.Y.S.2d 17, 20 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2003), leave to appeal denied, 1 N.Y.3d 504, 775 N.Y.S.2d 780, 807 N.E.2d 893 (2003); see also Bullard v. St. Barnabas Hosp., __ A.D.3d __, 810 N.Y.S.2d 78 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2006) (finding good cause to entertain late summary judgment motion where arguments of issue preclusion and law of the case could not have been raised until after order dismissing action against codefendants). 108 A motion for renewal, or for leave to renew, is the procedural device whereby a party seeks to alter a prior order disposing of a motion by injecting additional proof not submitted on the initial motion. N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2221(e) (McKinney 2005). See SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 254. 109 Trump, 764 N.Y.S.2d at 20-21. Trump also concluded that because the motion addressed a “threshold, potentially determinative issue, its consideration in advance of trial was in the interest of judicial economy.” Id. at 21 (citation omitted). This ground can no longer establish good cause in light of the Court of Appeals’ subsequent holding in Brill. See supra notes 25-28 and accompanying text. 110 Lawrence v. Kuo, No. 26597-01, 2004 WL 2683632, at *1 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Queens County Aug. 16, 2004). 111 Bouilland v. Angulo, No. 114116-01, 2004 WL 2941569, at *2 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. New York County Sept. 27, 2004). 112 Cf. SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 56 (where parties are engaged in pre-action settlement talks, plaintiff should commence action as precautionary measure to avoid running afoul of statute of limitations). The party could also seek leave to serve a late motion for summary judgment in advance of the expiration of the time period in CPLR 3212(a). See supra note 76 and accompanying text. 113 797 N.Y.S.2d 230, 231 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2005). 114 Id. at 230-31. 1556 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 time to appeal from an order that had already granted summary judgment to two other defendants. 115 This tactic, better known under the rubric of letting sleeping dogs lie until it is too late, did not support a late motion. 116 Even ignorance has formed the basis of a good cause determination under CPLR 3212(a). In Koloski v. Metropolitan Life Ins. Co., 117 the preliminary conference order required summary judgment motions to be made within sixty days of the filing of the note of issue. The movants’ attorney, who was substituted as counsel after the preliminary conference, was unaware of this requirement. 118 Operating under the assumption that she had one hundred and twenty days from the filing of the note of issue to make the motion, she made the motion on the one hundred and twentieth day. 119 The court concluded that this error was sufficient to constitute good cause because the delay was “minimal.” 120 The holding in Koloski should be contrasted with the rather harsh and somewhat more prevalent approach in Greenfield v. Gluck, 121 where the court determined that ignorance of CPLR 3212(a)’s deadline was insufficient to establish good cause, despite the fact that the movants were pro se litigants. 115 Id. Id. at 231. The court noted that the motion of the other two defendants was argued approximately one month after the expiration of CPLR 3212(a)’s time frame. 117 5 Misc.3d at 1028(A), 799 N.Y.S.2d 161, No. 600231-02, 2004 WL 2903626, at *1 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. New York County Nov. 3, 2004). 118 Id. 119 Id. at *2. 120 Id. See Neuberger v. Barron, N.Y.L.J., Mar. 30, 2005 at 22 (Sup. Ct. New York County) (current counsel’s unawareness of 60-day deadline for making of summary judgment motions constituted “law office failure,” and, under the circumstances, good cause for belated motion). Similarly, “good cause” has been established in cases predating Brill where the movant was never served with the note of issue. Cibener v. City of New York, 268 A.D.2d 334, 701 N.Y.S.2d 405 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2000). See also Brunetti v. City of New York, 286 A.D.2d 253, 728 N.Y.S.2d 665 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2001) (holding that plaintiff’s claimed violation of CPLR 3212(a) was not supported with satisfactory proof of dates of filing and service of note of issue). 121 No. 2002-1092 K C, 2003 WL 1961333, at *1 (N.Y. App. Term. 2d & 11th Jud. Dists. 2003); see Singh v. Deopaul, No. 46334-01, 2005 WL 1774139, at *2 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Kings County July 12, 2005) (law office failure, consisting of counsel’s erroneous diary entry for the summary judgment deadline, insufficient excuse to constitute good cause); Istrefovic v. Santos, No. 554-2002, 2004 WL 3245351, at *1-2 (N.Y. Civ. Ct. Bronx County Oct. 4, 2004) (after action was transferred to New York City Civil Court pursuant to CPLR 325[d], attorney mistakenly moved for summary judgment in supreme court; court found absence of good cause for late motion in New York City Civil Court). 116 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1557 3. “Good Cause” – CPLR 3212(a) vs. CPLR 2004 The ignorance excuse proffered by movants’ counsel and accepted by the court in Koloski 122 resembles “law office failure,” a ubiquitous phrase in New York caselaw discussing time extensions. CPLR 2005, which directly addresses law office failure, allows a court to excuse delay or default resulting from law office failure when relief is sought to extend the time to appear or plead, to compel acceptance of an untimely pleading, 123 or to vacate a judgment or order on the ground of excusable default. 124 Law office failure may also constitute “good cause” under CPLR 2004, which allows a court to “extend the time fixed by any statute, rule or order for doing any act, upon such terms as may be just and upon good cause shown, whether the application for extension is made before or after the expiration of the time fixed.” 125 Although CPLR 3212(a) and CPLR 2004 both employ the phrase “good cause,” the caselaw interpreting CPLR 2004 instructs courts to consider factors such as length of delay, the reason given for the delay, any prejudice to opposing parties caused by the delay, whether the moving party was in default before seeking the extension, and whether an affidavit of merit was proffered. 126 Therefore, in light of Brill’s creed that the absence of prejudice and the merits of an untimely motion for summary judgment are not part of the equation in calculating good cause under CPLR 3212(a), 127 122 Koloski, 2004 WL 2903626 at *1-2; see Neuberger, N.Y.L.J., Mar. 30, 2005, at 22. 123 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3012(d) (McKinney 2005) (“Service of pleadings and demand for complaint, Extension of time to appear or plead.”). 124 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 5015(a) (McKinney 2005) (“Relief from judgment or order, On motion.”). See Alexander, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C2005, at 703 (1992). 125 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2004 (McKinney 2005); Tewari v. Tsoutsouras, 75 N.Y.2d 1, 12-13, 550 N.Y.S.2d 572, 577, 549 N.E.2d 1143, 1148 (1989); In re Estate of Burkich, 12 A.D.3d 755, 755, 785 N.Y.S.2d 137, 138 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 2004); Brusco v. DavisKlages, 302 A.D.2d 674, 674-75, 754 N.Y.S.2d 725, 735 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 2003); Scritchfield v. Perry, 245 A.D.2d 1054, 1054, 667 N.Y.S.2d 584, 585 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 1997). CPLR 2004, one of the most commonly cited provisions in civil practice, is employed to extend the time fixed to perform a myriad of acts, including, among other things, the making of a motion pursuant to CPLR 4404 to set aside a verdict. See, e.g., Johnson v. Suffolk County Police Dep’t, 245 A.D.2d 340, 341, 665 N.Y.S.2d 440, 440-41 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1997); Alexander, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C2004, at 692 (1997). 126 See, e.g., Tewari, 550 N.Y.S.2d at 577; In re Estate of Burkich, 785 N.Y.S.2d at 138; Saha v. Record, 762 N.Y.S.2d 693, 695-96 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 2003). See also Grant v. City of New York, 793 N.Y.S.2d 35 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2005). 127 Brill v. City of New York, 781 N.Y.S.2d 261 (N.Y. 2004). 1558 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 lawyers must be cautious when applying decisions interpreting good cause under CPLR 2004 and other provisions to timeliness issues arising under CPLR 3212(a). The elements for establishing good cause under CPLR 2004 are distinct from the factors considered in determining good cause under CPLR 3212(a). In any event, the courts have expressed reluctance to accept perfunctory claims of law office failure as good cause under CPLR 3212(a). 128 VI. EXTENSION OF TIME PERIODS ESTABLISHED BY COURT RULE OR ORDER All three of the cases decided by the Court of Appeals concerning CPLR 3212(a)’s deadlines have involved the 120day period for making summary judgment motions. 129 Courts are now struggling with the related issue of whether Brill’s constraints also apply when they have set their own deadlines for moving for summary judgment. In a somewhat anomalous decision, one court has held that court imposed deadlines can be extended absent good 128 See Breiding v. Giladi, 15 A.D.3d 435, 435, 789 N.Y.S.2d 449, 449-50 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (“defendants’ perfunctory claims of unspecified clerical inadvertence and reassignment of counsel were insufficient to constitute good cause for the delay” in making their summary judgment motion); DiFusco v. Wal-Mart Discount Cities, 255 A.D.2d 937, 937, 680 N.Y.S.2d 377, 378 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 1998) (movant’s attorney’s excuse that he was too busy to make timely motion was inadequate); Barracks v. Metro North Commuter R.R., No. 122591-2, 2005 WL 1919100, at *1 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. New York County Mar. 18, 2005) (movant’s attorney’s excuse that case became “unwieldy” due to the number of defendants involved and that record was voluminous was insufficient to demonstrate good cause); Gutierrez v. State of New York, No. 107946, (Ct. Cl. Sept. 22, 2004), available at http://court.acmenet.net/lpBin21/lpext.dll/ Claims_2004/b8a9 (last visited Feb. 3, 2006) (claimant’s perfunctory excuse for failure to move for summary judgment within time frame ordered by court does not establish good cause); cf. Hosp. for Joint Diseases v. Elrac, Inc., 11 A.D.3d 432, 433, 783 N.Y.S.2d 612, 614 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004) (defendant’s motion to vacate default judgment entered against it granted where plaintiff, among other things, established reasonable excuse for the default; defendant submitted the affirmation of counsel which provided detailed explanation of the affirming counsel’s oversights that led to the default); Goldman v. Cotter, 10 A.D.3d 289, 291, 781 N.Y.S.2d 28, 31 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2004) (plaintiff’s motion to vacate order entered on default granted where plaintiff, among other things, established reasonable excuse for default; affidavit of plaintiff’s counsel specified occurrences of law office failure that led to default); Leader v. Maroney, Ponzini & Spencer, 276 A.D.2d 194, 195, 718 N.Y.S.2d 374, 378 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2000), aff’d 97 N.Y.2d 95, 761 N.E.2d 1018, 736 N.Y.S.2d 291 (2001) (plaintiff’s counsel’s error in concluding that original version of CPLR 306-b applied to action did not constitute “good cause” to extend time for service under CPLR 306-b). But see Neuberger v. Barron, N.Y.L.J., Mar. 30, 2005, at 22; Koloski v. Metro. Life Ins. Co., No. 600231-02, at *2, 2004 WL 2903626 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. New York County Nov. 3, 2004). 129 Brill v. City of New York, 781 N.Y.S.2d 261, 263-64 (N.Y. 2004); Miceli v. State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins., 786 N.Y.S.2d 379, 380 (N.Y. 2004); Gonzalez v. 98 Mag Leasing Corp., 711 N.Y.S.2d 131, 132-34 (N.Y. 2000). 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1559 cause. In Hernandez v. 620 West 189th Ltd. Partnership, the local uniform rules imposed a 60-day deadline for making summary judgment motions pursuant to the authority vested in CPLR 3212(a). 130 The court in Hernandez concluded that it had discretion to extend its own court-imposed deadline, even in the absence of good cause. 131 The legislative policy supporting the enactment of the 120-day maximum in CPLR 3212(a) is, the court reasoned, not applicable with respect to court-imposed deadlines for making summary judgment motions. 132 Thus, Hernandez held that courts have the discretion to disregard a self-imposed deadline for making a summary judgment motion to “accommodate a genuine need,” 133 and could extend their own deadlines in the absence of good cause so long as they do not exceed the 120-day ceiling. 134 Where, as in Hernandez, the court has imposed its own deadline for moving for summary judgment, CPLR 3212(a)’s language is somewhat awkward. A literal reading of the statute indicates that the ability to extend the time for making a summary judgment motion for good cause only pertains to the 120-day period imposed in the absence of a court rule. The sentence authorizing the court to set its own deadline for making summary judgment motions does not contain a clause authorizing the extension of such a period. 135 This problem appears to be a drafting oversight. The legislative history supporting the 1997 amendment to CPLR 3212(a) refers to both a court-imposed deadline and the 120day period, concluding that “[e]ither date could be extended by 130 Hernandez v. 620 W. 189th Ltd. P’ship, 792 N.Y.S.2d 822, 823 (Sup. Ct. New York County 2005). See N.Y. COUNTY SUPREME COURT CIVIL BRANCH, R. 17, available at http://www.courts.state.ny.us/supctmanh/uniform_rules.htm (last visited Jan. 25, 2006). 131 Hernandez, 792 N.Y.S.2d at 823. But see Bouilland v. Angulo, No. 11411601, 2004 WL 2941569, at *1-2 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. New York County Sept. 27, 2004) (applying Brill’s good cause constraint to 60-day deadline set by court). 132 Hernandez, 792 N.Y.S.2d at 824. 133 Id. 134 Id. Ultimately, the court refused to exercise its discretion to extend the sixty day limitation. Id. See also Keskeny v. 409 E. 87, LLC, 10 Misc. 3d 1057(A), No. 116755-03, 2005 WL 3369351 (Sup. Ct. New York County 2005) (rejecting strict interpretation of sixty day court rule). 135 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3212(a) (McKinney 2005). The sentence authorizing a court to set its own time frame for making summary judgment motions requires that the parties be allowed at least thirty days from the filing of the note of issue for the making of the motion, but no maximum. Id. Apparently a court could, if it so desired, set a date outside 120 days from the filing of the note of issue. Id. 1560 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 the court upon a showing of good cause.” 136 Additionally, as noted above, courts have the express authority under CPLR 2004 to extend the time fixed by any court rule or order. 137 This authority can be exercised before or after the time period has expired, “upon such terms as may be just and upon good cause shown.” 138 Although the statutory history of CPLR 3212(a) and CPLR 2004 support Hernandez’s conclusion that a court can extend its own deadline for making summary judgment motions, this authority does not allow for extensions absent good cause, as Hernandez held. 139 Hernandez’s holding is also difficult to reconcile with language in several Court of Appeals cases emphasizing the importance placed on adhering to court-imposed deadlines. As 136 Memorandum in Support of Amendment from Chief Administrative Judge Jonathan Lippman 1 (June 25, 1996) (on file with author); REPORT OF THE ADVISORY COMMITTEE ON CIVIL PRACTICE, supra note 13. 137 See supra notes 125-26 and accompanying text. 138 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2004 (McKinney 2005). See, e.g., Tewari v. Tsoutsouras, 550 N.Y.S.2d 572, 576-77, (N.Y. 1989) (CPLR 2004 extension may be granted only upon showing of “good cause”); Zamir v. Hilton Hotels Corp., 304 A.D.2d 493, 494, 758 N.Y.S.2d 645, 646-47 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2003) (court erred in denying defendants’ cross-motions to strike “corrections” to plaintiff’s deposition transcript as untimely; plaintiff failed to establish “good cause” to extend time to return deposition); Aretakis v. Tarantino, 300 A.D.2d 160, 160, 751 N.Y.S.2d 481, 482 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2002) (no extension of time to move for dismissal of complaint pursuant to CPLR 3211(e) absent showing of “good cause”); Horn v. Boyle, 260 A.D.2d 76, 78, 699 N.Y.S.2d 572, 575 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 1999) (highlighting necessity that “good cause” support application to extend time limit); Conch Assocs. Inc. v. Mercury, Inc., 245 A.D.2d 538, 539, 666 N.Y.S.2d 499, 500 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1997) (defendant not entitled to extension of time to post bond given its failure to demonstrate “good cause”); Coutrier v. Haraden Motorcar Corp., 237 A.D.2d 774, 777, 655 N.Y.S.2d 660, 663-64 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 1997) (plaintiff’s belated CPLR 4404 motion properly denied absent “good cause”); Casey v. Slattery, 213 A.D.2d 890, 841, 623 N.Y.S.2d 942, 943 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 1995) (same); De Cuyper v. Gonzales, 214 A.D.2d 764, 765, 624 N.Y.S.2d 653, 654 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 1995) (plaintiffs’ request for extension of time to answer defendants’ summary judgment motion properly denied given plaintiffs’ “failure to allege a sufficient basis for the extension”); Thermo Spas Inc. v. Red Ball Spas & Baths Inc., 199 A.D.2d 605, 606, 604 N.Y.S.2d 337, 338 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 1993) (trial court did not err in failing to consider defendants’ tardy papers in opposition to plaintiff’s motion pursuant to CPLR 3126 to strike defendants’ answer given defendants’ failure to offer “valid excuse for [their] delay”); Tesciuba v. Cataldo, 189 A.D.2d 655, 655, 592 N.Y.S.2d 326, 326 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1993) (trial court did not abuse its discretion in denying plaintiff additional time within which to make a post-trial motion for a new trial pursuant to CPLR 4404, there being no explanation from plaintiff showing “good cause” for his lengthy delay of more than two years in seeking such an extension); Alexander, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR 2004, at 692 (1991); see also, McCoy v. Feinman, 99 N.Y.2d 295, 300, 785 N.E.2d 714, 718, 755 N.Y.S.2d 693, 696-97 (2002) (noting that courts have discretion to waive certain time limits under CPLR 2004 for good cause); Grandinetti v. Metro. Transp. Auth., 74 N.Y.2d 785, 787, 543 N.E.2d 737, 738, 545 N.Y.S.2d 94, 95 (1989) (same). 139 Hernandez v. 620 W. 189th Ltd. P’ship, 792 N.Y.S.2d 822, 824 (Sup. Ct New York County 2005). 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1561 the Court stated in Kihl v. Pfeffer, “[i]f the credibility of court orders and the integrity of our judicial system are to be maintained, a litigant cannot ignore court orders with impunity.” 140 Although Brill and Miceli involved violations of the legislatively imposed 120-day rule, the Court equated them with violations of “court-ordered time frames.” 141 The Court has also cautioned that both legislative and judicial deadlines “are not options, [but] are requirements, to be taken seriously by the parties.” 142 In light of these statements, it is difficult to justify the different standard outlined in Hernandez for extending court-imposed deadlines for making motions for summary judgment. The Court of Appeals is likely to impose the same good cause standard enunciated in Brill and Miceli on parties moving for summary judgment after a court-imposed deadline has expired. 143 Several Second Department decisions have implicitly rejected Hernandez’s holding and concluded that good cause must support a motion made after the expiration of a court’s deadline for making motions for summary judgment. In Milano v. George, the supreme court set a 90-day deadline for moving for summary judgment, running from the filing of the note of issue. 144 A defendant’s motion for summary judgment, made on the ninety-first day, was deemed untimely because of the failure to establish good cause for the delay. 145 In First Union Auto Finance, Inc. v. Donat, plaintiff’s motion and defendant’s cross-motion failed to comply with Rule 13 of the Uniform Civil Trial Rules of the Supreme Court, Kings County, which 140 94 N.Y.2d 118, 123 722 N.E.2d 55, 58, 700 N.Y.S.2d 87, 90 (1999). See Andrea v. Arnone, Hedlin, Casker, Kennedy and Drake, Architects and Landscape Architects, P.C., 5 N.Y.3d 514, 521, 806 N.Y.S.2d 453, 457, 840 N.E.2d 565, 569 (2005) (stressing importance of adherence to court deadlines). 141 Miceli v. State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co., 3 N.Y.3d 726, 726, 819 N.E.2d 995, 996, 786 N.Y.S.2d 379, 380 (2004). 142 Id. 143 See generally 158 Siegel’s Practice Review, More on Time to Move for Summary Judgment: Court Can Allow Motion Made After Court-Set Time Expires, as Long as Motion is Made Within the Statutory 120 Days, at 1 (Feb. 2005). Without predicting how the Court of Appeals would go on this point – predictions here are perilous in view of what appears to be shaping up as a Court of Appeals crusade against dilatory conduct in litigation – the Hernandez case seems a fair compromise. It’s pretty clear that it doesn’t offend the statute, but it’s an open question whether it would offend the Court of Appeals. Id. 144 145 792 N.Y.S.2d 906, 907 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005). Id. 1562 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 requires summary judgment motions to be made within sixty days of the filing of the note of issue. 146 The Second Department held that the supreme court erred in considering the merits of the motions because “no good cause for the delay was shown.” 147 Additionally, a Supreme Court Justice sitting in New York County, the same court that decided Hernandez, has expressly declined to follow the “rule” enunciated in Hernandez. 148 VII. THE AFTERMATH OF BRILL In Brill, the Court of Appeals also gave direction to lower courts regarding the disposition of a case in which a meritorious motion for summary judgment could not satisfy the timeliness requirements in CPLR 3212(a). 149 The Court reversed the order granting summary judgment in Brill and returned the case to the trial calendar. 150 The Court observed that the defendant, now deprived of the remedy of summary judgment, could make a motion to dismiss after plaintiff rests, or make a request for a directed verdict during the trial. 151 146 791 N.Y.S.2d 596, 597 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005). See also Bevilacqua v. City of New York, 21 A.D.3d 340, 798 N.Y.S.2d 909 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005). 147 First Union, 791 N.Y.S.2d at 597. Prior to the holdings in Milano and First Union, a trial court in Kings County concluded that Brill did not apply where the motion was made within 120 days from the filing of the note of issue, but after the expiration of Rule 13’s sixty-day period. See Florczyc v. Stahal, No. 25129-99, 2005 WL 119739, at *2 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Kings County Jan. 3, 2005). In Florczyc, the court expressly declined to determine whether the movant had established good cause. Id. Milano and First Union appear to reject Florczyc’s rationale. See Kunz v. Gleeson, 781 N.Y.S.2d 50, 51 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004) (implicitly recognizing applicability of Brill, court holds that merits of motion made approximately two weeks beyond date set by court order were properly considered upon showing of good cause). Additionally, a Supreme Court Justice sitting in New York County, which has an identical local rule requiring all summary judgment motions to be made within sixty days of the filing of the note of issue, has expressly declined to follow Florczyc. See Buckner v. City of New York, 800 N.Y.S.2d 333, 337 (Sup. Ct. New York County 2005). 148 Buckner, 800 N.Y.S.2d at 337. See Clermont-Lundy ex rel. Lundy v. Zimbalist, 10 Misc. 3d 1056(A), No. 4950-03, 2005 WL 3309753, at *7 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Kings County Oct. 5, 2005) (holding that Brill’s “good cause” requirement “applies whether the moving party is untimely pursuant to either a statutory time frame or one that has been ordered by the court”). 149 Brill v. City of New York, 781 N.Y.S.2d 261 (N.Y. 2004). The Court was apparently prompted by Professor David Siegel, who observed, “we’d think better of judicial decisions that absolutely refuse to extend the time for meritorious summary judgment motions if they would tell us what is to happen in the case.” 79 Siegel’s Practice Review, Time Limit on Summary Judgment, at 2 (Jan. 1999). See 51 Siegel’s Practice Review, Strict Time Limit Placed on Motion for Summary Judgment, at 1 (Nov. 1996); SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 279. 150 Brill, 781 N.Y.S.2d at 265. 151 Id. CPLR 4401 permits any party to move for judgment “after the close of the evidence presented by an opposing party with respect to [a] cause of action or issue, 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1563 The dissent in Brill criticized this result, noting that “the time of the litigants, jurors, lawyers, the judge, and other court personnel should not be wasted in going through the motions of a trial which has no merit and must be dismissed. . . .” 152 The dissent surmised that the trial ordered by the majority will provide “futile hope to the litigants” and that the case will ultimately be dismissed “[o]nce the parties make an opening statement or plaintiffs put in their case indicating that the appropriate notice was not given.” 153 The majority in Brill answered the dissent’s concerns with the following observation: Hopefully, as a result of the courts’ refusal to countenance the statutory violation, there will be fewer, if any, such situations in the future, both because it is now clear that “good cause” means good cause for the delay, and because movants will develop a habit of compliance with the statutory deadlines for summary judgment motions rather than delay until trial looms. 154 Despite the majority’s hope in Brill, and, given the adventuresome nature of a healthy segment of the bar, it appears that the problem of late summary judgment motions will persist in the foreseeable future. Brill continues to be cited in reported trial court and appellate decisions on a frequent basis. 155 One can also safely assume that there is an equal or at any time on the basis of admissions.” N.Y. C.P.L.R. 4401 (McKinney 2005). This issue is explored infra notes 200-04 and accompanying text. 152 Brill, 781 N.Y.S.2d at 266 (G.B. Smith, J., dissenting). 153 Id. Although the dissent appears to contemplate that a motion for a directed verdict could be made immediately after opening statements, this is not likely. CPLR 4401 generally permits the motion for a directed verdict only “after the close of the evidence presented by an opposing party with respect to [the] cause of action or issue” moved upon. N.Y. C.P.L.R. 4401 (McKinney 2005). This issue is explored infra notes 201-203 and accompanying text. 154 Brill, 781 N.Y.S.2d at 265. In response to the dissent’s suggestion that monetary sanctions and preclusion may offer effective remedies against a tardy movant, the majority noted that “[p]reclusion on the merits may, as a rule for the future, be wholly disproportionate to the violation. Without considering whether we may impose sanctions against a municipality for violating a statute, six of us conclude that denying summary judgment—simply not considering the merits of an unexcused, untimely motion—is not only the correct remedy under the law but also will most effectively bring an undesirable practice to an end.” Id. at 265 n.4. 155 See supra note 22 and accompanying text. A substantial number of the reported decisions from the appellate courts involve cases that were decided by a trial level court before Brill was handed down. Many of these decisions warranted reversal because they were based on the law prior to Brill, which allowed the merits of the motion to be considered in analyzing good cause under CPLR 3212(a). See, e.g., Dettmann v. Page, 794 N.Y.S.2d 406, 406-07 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005); Hayes v. New York City Trans. Auth., 16 A.D.3d 551, 551, 790 N.Y.S.2d 886, 887 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005); First Union Auto Finance, Inc. v. Donat, 791 N.Y.S.2d 596, 597 (App. Div. 2d 1564 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 number of unreported instances in which courts are confronted with a timeliness problem under CPLR 3212(a). As of this writing, there is not yet a reported decision addressing how a case was handled after it was sent back for trial pursuant to Brill’s command. Although the majority in Brill provided some direction to courts and litigants as to how a case should proceed after it is determined that a summary judgment motion is untimely, many unresolved questions remain. This section of the article will identify several problems that judges and lawyers will confront in cases in which a summary judgment motion is denied as untimely. We’ll address the issues from two separate perspectives: (A) “What Does the Plaintiff Do Now?,” and (B) “What Does the Defendant Do Now?” A. What Does the Plaintiff Do Now? In Brill, the Kings County Supreme Court and the Appellate Division, Second Department reached the merits of defendant’s summary judgment motion. 156 Both of these courts determined that the City of New York established its prima facie entitlement to judgment as a matter of law by demonstrating it did not receive written notice of the defect in the sidewalk at the location where plaintiff fell. 157 Plaintiffs produced a “Big Apple” map to establish prior written notice, but it only contained descriptions of defects in the sidewalk adjacent to the area of the accident and did not provide notice of the defect where plaintiff fell. 158 Therefore, both lower courts dismissed plaintiff’s lawsuit based on the prior written notice requirement in section 7-201 of the Administrative Code of the City of New York. 159 In ruling that these courts should not have Dep’t 2005); Breiding v. Guladi, 789 N.Y.S.2d 449, 449-50 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005). Many cases decided after Brill continue to pose timeliness issues, however. 156 Brill v. City of New York, 781 N.Y.S.2d 261, 263 (N.Y. 2004) (noting that the Kings County Supreme Court “decide[d] the summary judgment motion on the merits”); Brill v. City of New York, 305 A.D.2d 525, 526, 759 N.Y.S.2d 346, 346 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2003). 157 Brill, 759 N.Y.S.2d at 346; Brill, 781 N.Y.S. 2d at 263. The Appellate Division also concluded that the City demonstrated it did not create the allegedly defective condition. Brill, 759 N.Y.S.2d at 346. 158 Id. 159 Section 7-201(c)(2) of the Administrative Code of the City of New York states that no civil action shall be maintained against the City of New York for personal injuries sustained as a result of a sidewalk defect unless it appears that written notice of the defective condition was actually given to the New York City Commissioner of Transportation or any person or department authorized by the 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1565 considered the merits of defendant’s motion because of a failure to establish compliance with the timeliness provision in CPLR 3212(a), the Court of Appeals expressly stated it was not “consider[ing] the merits of the City’s motion.” 160 Despite the Court’s deference, there is certainly a dark cloud hanging over the merits of plaintiffs’ claims. This poses several problems for the plaintiffs in moving forward with the case, which this article will explore below. 1. Search for Additional Proof In the countless number of personal injury cases similar to Brill in which prior written notice of a defect is required, an untimely summary judgment motion may place plaintiff on notice of a specific defect in the proof necessary to establish all of the elements of the claim. Brill’s direction that these cases proceed to trial provides the plaintiff with additional time to gather the proof necessary to satisfy all elements of the claim. Although the period in which to obtain disclosure on notice through CPLR Article 31’s machinery expires with the filing of the note of issue, 161 the plaintiff facing a dilemma similar to the one met in Brill could attempt to seek disclosure through a court order or informally gather information without using the disclosure devices. 162 Similarly, in cases where a belated Commissioner to receive notice. N.Y. ADMIN. CODE § 7-201(c)(2) (McKinney 2005). Similar provisions in several statutes and municipal codes also require written notice of a defect to maintain a suit. See, e.g., N.Y. GEN. MUN. §§ 50-g, 71-b (McKinney 2005); N.Y. HIGH. § 139 (McKinney 2005); N.Y. TOWN § 65-a (McKinney 2005); N.Y. VILLAGE § 6-628 (McKinney 2005). See also, 1B NEW YORK PATTERN JURY INSTRUCTIONS – CIVIL § 2:225(I) (3d ed. 2005) (“Duty and Notice”). Where a prior written notice requirement is applicable, the plaintiff must plead and prove compliance with the requirement as a condition precedent to suit. Katz v. City of New York, 87 N.Y.2d 241, 243, 638 N.Y.S.2d 593, 661 N.E.2d 1374 (1995); Vargas v. City of New York, 4 A.D.3d 524, 772 N.Y.S.2d 381 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004); Farnsworth v. Village of Potsdam, 228 A.D.2d 79, 651 N.Y.S.2d 748 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 1997). The prior written notice requirement is separate and distinct from the obligation to serve a notice of claim on the municipal entity within ninety days after the claim arises. N.Y. GEN. MUN. § 50-e(1)(a) (McKinney 2005). A court may extend the time to serve a notice of claim, upon motion. Id. § 50-e(5). For a discussion of the pitfalls encountered by lawyers commencing actions against municipal entities, see Harris v. Niagara Falls Bd. Of Educ., 6 N.Y.3d 155, 844 N.E.2d 753, 811 N.Y.S.2d 299 (2006) (plaintiff failed to properly commence action against municipal entity when he used same index number from prior special proceeding, which granted order to serve a late notice of claim); see also Connors and Gleason, Problems at the Starting Gate, N.Y.L.J., Jan. 12, 2006, at 3. 160 Brill, 781 N.Y.S.2d at 263 n.2. 161 See Connors, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C3102:3, at 493-94 (2005); supra notes 83-84 and accompanying text. 162 See Niesig v. Team I, 76 N.Y.2d 363, 372, 558 N.E.2d 1030, 1034, 559 N.Y.S.2d 493, 497 (1990) (recognizing value of “avenues of informal discovery of 1566 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 summary judgment motion exposes a lack of medical proof to establish a “serious injury” 163 or “grave injury,” 164 the plaintiff or third-party plaintiff will have additional time to obtain it for trial. 165 2. The Prospect of Sanctions If Ona Brill and her counsel search for proof that the City of New York had prior written notice of the defect, but cannot uncover it, the possibility of sanctions looms. CPLR 8303-a and Part 130 of the Rules of the Chief Administrator of the Courts are both relevant in this context. CPLR 8303-a has limited application, 166 but would govern in Brill and the many other personal injury cases in which timeliness issues under CPLR 3212(a) have arisen. CPLR 8303-a(a) applies in cases seeking damages for personal injury, 167 property damage 168 or wrongful death. 169 It provides that if “such an action or claim is commenced or continued by a plaintiff . . . and is found, at any time during the proceedings or information that may serve both the litigants and the entire justice system by uncovering relevant facts”); see also Federal Freedom of Information Act, 5 U.S.C. § 552 et seq. (2000) (providing for public access to governmental records of the federal government and its administrative agencies); Freedom of Information Law, N.Y. PUB. OFF., art. 6 (McKinney 2005) (statutory scheme providing for public access to governmental records of State of New York and localities, and their administrative agencies); M. Farbman & Sons, Inc. v. New York City Health and Hosps. Corp., 62 N.Y.2d 75, 78, 464 N.E.2d 437, 438, 476 N.Y.S.2d 69, 70 (1984) (party to litigation may pursue governmental records of adverse party through CPLR Article 31 disclosure devices or FOIL methods). 163 N.Y. INS. § 5102(d) (McKinney 2005) (defining several categories of “serious injury”). 164 N.Y. WORKERS’ COMP. § 11 (McKinney 2005) (requiring third-party plaintiff to plead and prove “grave injury” in common-law indemnification or contribution action against plaintiff’s employer). 165 If the additional proof requires the plaintiff to call an expert witness at trial, the plaintiff will also have to satisfy the disclosure requirements in CPLR 3101(d)(1)(i). The courts have been inconsistent, and rather lax, in imposing these obligations, especially with respect to the timing of the disclosure. See Connors, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, C3101:29A, at 59-79 (2005). 166 See SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 414A; Alexander, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, C8303-a, 77-78 (Supp. 2005). 167 See N.Y. GEN. CONSTR. § 37-a (McKinney 2005) (“‘Personal injury’ includes libel, slander and malicious prosecution; also an assault, battery, false imprisonment, or other actionable injury to the person either of the plaintiff, or of another.”). 168 See N.Y. GEN. CONSTR. § 25-b (McKinney 2005) (“‘Injury to property’ is an actionable act, whereby the estate of another is lessened, other than a personal injury, or the breach of a contract.”). 169 CPLR 8303-a(a) also applies to “an action brought by the individual who committed a crime against the victim of the crime.” See N.Y. EST. POWERS & TRUSTS § 5-4.1 (McKinney 2005) (“Action by personal representative for wrongful act, neglect or default causing death of decedent”). 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1567 upon judgment, to be frivolous by the court, the court shall award to the successful party costs and reasonable attorney’s fees.” 170 Accordingly, CPLR 8303-a authorizes a court to award costs and reasonable attorney’s fees against a party who has commenced or continued to prosecute a frivolous personal injury, injury to property, or wrongful death action. In contrast to CPLR 8303-a, Part 130 is not limited to any particular category of action and applies in virtually all civil litigation in New York State. 171 It authorizes a court to award “costs in the form of reimbursement for actual expenses” and sanctions against a party who has engaged in frivolous conduct. 172 Conduct is defined as frivolous if, among other things, it is “completely without merit in law” 173 or it “asserts material factual statements that are false.” 174 In determining whether conduct is frivolous, the court must consider, among other things, “whether or not the conduct was continued when its lack of legal or factual basis was apparent, should have been apparent, or was brought to the attention of counsel or the party.” 175 A court has far broader power under Part 130 than 170 Id. CPLR 8303-a(a) additionally applies to a frivolous counterclaim, defense or cross claim. The costs and attorney’s fees imposed under CPLR 8303-a are capped at $10,000. Id. See Marcus v. Bressler, 277 A.D.2d 108, 109, 716 N.Y.S.2d 395, 396 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2000) ($10,000 maximum sanction applicable to each frivolous cause of action); Entm’t Partners Group, Inc. v. Davis, 155 Misc. 2d 894, 901, 590 N.Y.S.2d 979, 984 (Sup. Ct. New York County 1992), aff’d 198 A.D.2d 63, 64, 603 N.Y.S.2d 439, 440 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1993) ($10,000 maximum sanction does not apply to whole case, but to each prevailing party and each individual claim). 171 Part 130 does not apply in certain lower courts. N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 130-1.1(a) (2005). In addition, Part 130 does not apply to requests for costs or attorneys’ fees subject to CPLR 8303-a. 172 N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 130-1.1(a) (2005). Costs are paid to the opposing party or her attorney. Sanctions are paid to the State. Id. See N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 130-1.3 (2005). See also SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 414A; 133 Siegel’s Practice Review, Both Kinds of Sanctions Applied: Frivolous Claim and Frivolous Conduct Bring Both Compensatory and Punitive Sanctions, at 2-3 (Mar. 2003). The maximum sanction permissible for a single occurrence of frivolous conduct is $10,000, while costs and reasonable attorney’s fees are not capped. N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 130-1.2 (2005). 173 N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 130-1.1(c)(1) (2005). 174 N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 130-1.1(c)(3) (2005). 175 N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 130-1.1(c) (2005). “An award of costs or the imposition of sanctions may be made either upon [a] motion in compliance with CPLR 2214 or 2215 or upon the court’s own initiative, after a reasonable opportunity to be heard” has been accorded the offending party. N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 130-1.1(d) (2005). In making an award of costs and/or imposing sanctions pursuant to section 130-1, the court must issue a written decision setting forth the conduct on which the award and/or imposition is based, the reasons why the court found the conduct to be frivolous, and the reasons why the court found the amount awarded and/or imposed to be appropriate. N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 1568 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 under its statutory sibling, CPLR 8303-a. While a court may only impose a penalty pursuant to CPLR 8303-a if it finds that a party has asserted or maintained a frivolous cause of action, counterclaim, cross-claim or defense, a court may punish any frivolous conduct that occurs during the course of litigation under Part 130, including the making of a frivolous motion. 176 In Brill, for example, although the motion for summary judgment was ultimately denied as untimely, the plaintiffs were placed on notice that there was a critical deficiency in the proof necessary to establish a cause of action against the City. 177 If the plaintiffs continued to prosecute the case through trial without any proof that the City was on written notice of the defect, a strong argument could be made that the plaintiffs and their attorney should be subject to sanctions under CPLR 8303-a or Part 130. 178 In these circumstances, the plaintiffs 22, § 130-1.2 (2005). An award of costs and/or the imposition of sanctions is entered as a judgment of the court. Id. 176 See SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 414A. See also Testa v. Koerner Ford of Syracuse, Inc., 261 A.D.2d 866, 868, 689 N.Y.S.2d 818, 821 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 1999); Harley v. Druzba, 169 A.D.2d 1001, 1002-03, 565 N.Y.S.2d 278, 280 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 1991). 177 Although the Court of Appeals did not consider the merits of the City’s motion, two courts did, and found that plaintiffs failed to establish that the City had prior written notice. Brill v. City of New York, 781 N.Y.S.2d 261, 263 (N.Y. 2004); see supra notes 156-60 and accompanying text. In light of the mandate of Brill and its progeny that the merits of an untimely motion are not to be considered absent good cause, supra notes 25-28, it is unlikely that such pre-trial findings will be expressly made in future cases in which a movant fails to comply with CPLR 3212(a). 151 Siegel’s Practice Review, Sanction Against Plaintiff for Continuing Action in Which Summary Judgment for Defendant Was Warranted, but Was Denied for Lateness?, at 34 (July 2004). There will, however, be many instances in which the supporting proof submitted by defendant with an untimely motion will place the plaintiff on notice that her allegations lack a reasonable basis. In addition, there will be instances in which an appellate court reverses a finding of “good cause” and remands the case for trial pursuant to Brill’s direction. See supra notes 150-51 and accompanying text. In these circumstances, it may be apparent that the plaintiff will be unable to establish a necessary element of the cause of action. 178 See Mitchell v. Herald Co., 137 A.D.2d 213, 218-19, 529 N.Y.S.2d 602, 60507 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 1988) (plaintiff and his counsel sanctioned under CPLR 8303-a because they had a duty to act in good faith to investigate claims and promptly discontinue action where inquiry would reveal that claims lacked reasonable basis). N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 130-1.5 (2005) states that Part 130-1.1 will not apply “to requests for costs or attorneys’ fees subject to the provisions of CPLR 8303-a.” See Entm’t Partners Group, Inc. v. Davis, 590 N.Y.S.2d 979, 984 (Sup. Ct. New York County 1992), aff’d, 603 N.Y.S.2d 439 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1993); Alexander, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, C8303-a, at 89-92 (Supp. 2006). See also Testa, 689 N.Y.S.2d at 821; 1051 Enters., Inc. v. DeBeer, 230 A.D.2d 731, 732, 646 N.Y.S.2d 57, 58 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1996); Harley, 565 N.Y.S.2d at 280; Guevara v. Jocara Realty Co., No. 2002-1510, 2003 WL 21704397, at *1 (N.Y. App. Term, 2d & 11th Jud. Dists. 2003); Forstman v. Arluck, 149 Misc. 2d 929, 932-33, 566 N.Y.S.2d 462, 463-64 (Sup. Ct. Suffolk County 1991). 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1569 would have been placed on notice of the absence of a necessary element of their cause of action and yet continued, knowing that it lacked merit. 179 3. Voluntary Discontinuance Although the City was denied summary judgment in Brill, the plaintiffs were placed in a rather difficult position. If proof of prior written notice could not be obtained, the plaintiffs had the option of voluntarily discontinuing the action under CPLR 3217(a)(2). This subdivision allows a party to discontinue an action prior to its submission to a court or jury by, among other methods, filing a stipulation with the clerk of the court. 180 The court could also sign an order of discontinuance upon such terms and conditions it deems proper. 181 If the plaintiffs in Brill decided to voluntarily discontinue their action, it would likely be without prejudice to commence a new action. 182 The statute of limitations would, however, likely bar any future action. In Brill, the plaintiffs’ 179 See Mitchell, 529 N.Y.S.2d at 605-06 (“The bad faith of plaintiff and his counsel was compounded by their failure to discontinue the action after being specifically advised by defendant’s attorney that the claim was baseless.”). See also N.Y. CODE OF PROF’L RESPONSIBILITY DR 7-102(A)(2) (McKinney 2005) (a lawyer shall not “knowingly advance a claim that is unwarranted under existing law”). 180 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3217(a)(2) (McKinney 2005). The stipulation must be in writing signed by the attorneys of record for all parties. Id. See also N.Y. C.P.L.R. 2104 (McKinney 2005) (stating requirements for valid stipulation). The stipulation must be filed with the county clerk by the defendant, requiring the payment of a fee. N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3217(d) (McKinney 2005) (listing fees); N.Y. C.P.L.R. 8020(d) (McKinney Supp. 2006) (same). See Certified Elec. Contracting Corp. v. City of New York, 804 N.Y.S.2d 794, 796 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (plaintiff never executed stipulation of discontinuance and never filed it with the court). CPLR 3217(a)(2) cannot be used if one of the parties is an infant, incompetent person or conservatee or if a person not a party has an interest in the subject matter of the action. N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3217(a)(2) (McKinney 2005). CPLR 3217(a)(2) allows the parties to discontinue the action without a court order. Id. 181 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3217(b) (McKinney 2005). If the case has been submitted to the jury or court, “the court may not order an action discontinued except upon the stipulation of all parties appearing in the action.” Id. CPLR 8020(d) imposes a $35 fee for the filing of all discontinuances in actions pending in supreme and county courts. N.Y. C.P.L.R. 8020(d) (McKinney Supp. 2006). Pursuant to CPLR 3217(d), all discontinuances in actions pending in supreme and county court must be filed with the clerk of the court by the defendant. Id. See 137 Siegel’s Practice Review, Administrative Problems for Courts and Procedural Pitfalls for Parties Abound as Fees are Imposed for Making Motions and Cross-Motions, and Filing of Settlements is Made Mandatory (Part II), at 3 (July 2003). 182 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3217(c) (McKinney 2005). If the party seeking to voluntarily discontinue the action has not obtained such relief in the past, the discontinuance is generally without prejudice. Id. The notice, stipulation or order of discontinuance could, however, provide otherwise. Id. 1570 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 cause of action, which sounded in negligence, accrued on February 15, 1998 when Ona Brill tripped and fell on a sidewalk in Brooklyn. 183 Their action was commenced on June 4, 1998, 184 within the one year and ninety days after the fall. 185 The period within which to commence an action expired in May 1999. 186 Therefore, a discontinuance would have had to have been accomplished, so as to permit a timely second action, long before the summary judgment motion in Brill was made. 4. Ethical Obligations To Client New York State’s civil caseload is comprised largely of personal injury cases. 187 In an overwhelming majority of these 183 See, e.g., SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 40 (“In the personal injury case predicated on negligence, the applicable . . . period starts at the moment of injury.”). 184 An action or special proceeding is commenced in New York’s superior courts (i.e., supreme and county courts) when the initiatory papers related to the action or proceeding are filed with the appropriate clerk. See, e.g., N.Y. C.P.L.R. 304 (McKinney 2005); Harris v. Niagara Falls Bd. Of Educ., 811 N.Y.S.2d 299 (N.Y. 2006); Mendon Ponds Neighborhood Ass’n v. Dehm, 98 N.Y.2d 745, 746-47, 781 N.E.2d 883, 883-84, 751 N.Y.S.2d 819, 819-20 (2001); Peace v. Zhang, 15 A.D.3d 956, 957, 789 N.Y.S.2d 362, 363 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2005); SIEGEL, supra note 36, §§ 63, 77. Effective September 8, 2005, in the New York City Civil Courts, District Courts and City Courts, a “filing” system has replaced the prior procedure in which actions were commenced by service of process. 2005 N.Y. Sess. Laws page 1332 (McKinney). For a discussion of the new filing system in these lower courts and a discussion of various distinctions with the commencement system in Supreme and County Court, see 164 Siegel’s Practice Review, Basic Change in Practice in Civil, District, and City Courts: “Filing” System Adopted; Summons Service No Longer Deemed “Commencement” Part I, at 1-4 (Aug. 2005); 165 Siegel’s Practice Review, Basic Change in Practice in Civil, District, and City Courts: “Filing” System Adopted; Summons Service No Longer Deemed “Commencement” Part II, at 1-4, (Sept. 2005). 185 N.Y. GEN. MUN. LAW § 50-i(1)(c) (McKinney 2005) (action against a city for personal injury must be “commenced within one year and ninety days after the happening of the event upon which the claim is based”). In addition, a plaintiff in these circumstances must serve a notice of claim upon the municipal entity “in compliance with section 50-e of this chapter.” Id. § 50-i(1)(a). The plaintiff must also plead that at least thirty days have elapsed since the service of the notice of claim and that “adjustment or payment” of the claim has been refused. Id. § 50-i(1)(b); supra note 159. 186 N.Y. GEN. MUN. LAW § 50-i(1)(c) (McKinney 2005). 187 See generally 26TH ANNUAL REPORT OF THE CHIEF ADMINISTRATOR OF THE COURTS OF THE STATE OF NEW YORK, at 11-12 (indicating that 189,306 requests for judicial intervention were filed in actions pending in supreme court for the calendar year 2003, and that 42% of these cases involved torts [i.e. cases involving motor vehicle accidents – 24%, medical malpractice – 2%, and “other tort[s]” – 16%]); 25TH ANNUAL REPORT OF THE CHIEF ADMINISTRATOR OF THE COURTS OF THE STATE OF NEW YORK, at 11-12 (indicating that 189,921 requests for judicial intervention were filed in actions pending in supreme court for the calendar year 2002, and that 43% of these cases involved torts [i.e. cases involving motor vehicle accidents – 24%, medical malpractice – 2%, and “other tort[s]” – 17%]); 24TH ANNUAL REPORT OF THE CHIEF ADMINISTRATOR OF THE COURTS OF THE STATE OF NEW YORK, at 11-12 (indicating that 184,490 requests for judicial intervention were filed in actions pending in supreme court for the calendar year 2001, and that 43% of these cases involved torts [i.e. cases involving motor vehicle accidents – 24%, medical malpractice – 2%, and “other tort[s]” – 17%]); 23RD ANNUAL 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1571 cases, the plaintiff is represented on a contingent fee basis. 188 Based on these two facts, it is reasonable to anticipate that the Court’s holding in Brill may result in many situations in which a plaintiff’s lawyer no longer has an incentive to vigorously prosecute her client’s case. We can highlight the nature of the problem using the facts and procedural history in Brill as a typical example. 189 As noted above, Brill provides that if an untimely summary judgment motion is made without good cause, the case must proceed to trial. 190 In a case similar to Brill, where two courts have determined that an untimely defendant’s motion has merit, the plaintiff’s lawyer may see the writing on the wall and anticipate the outcome of an inevitable motion to dismiss during trial. 191 Given the significant time and expense necessary to bring a case to trial, 192 and the strong probability of a directed verdict, an attorney representing a plaintiff in these circumstances may decide to devote her attention to other matters. If the case is one in which the lawyer represents the client on a contingent fee basis, there is a strong economic disincentive to bring the case to trial. 193 REPORT OF THE CHIEF ADMINISTRATOR OF THE COURTS OF THE STATE OF NEW YORK, at 11-12 (indicating that 183,391 requests for judicial intervention were filed in actions pending in supreme court for the calendar year 2000, and that 42% of these cases involved torts [i.e. cases involving motor vehicle accidents – 23%, medical malpractice – 2%, and “other tort[s]” – 17%]). 188 See N.Y. CODE OF PROF’L RESPONSIBILITY DR 2-106 (McKinney 2005) (discussing fees, including contingent fees, in various circumstances). There are rules in each of the four departments of the Appellate Division governing contingency fees. See N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 603.7 (2005) (rules for the 1st Dep’t); Id. § 691.20 (rules for the 2d Dep’t); N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 806.13 (2005) (rules for the 3d Dep’t); N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 1022.2 (2005) (rules for the 4th Dep’t). 189 This discussion does not reflect or attempt to describe the actual conduct of the lawyers representing the plaintiffs in Brill. The discussion simply uses the facts and procedural history of Brill as an example to demonstrate a perceived problem. 190 Brill v. City of New York, 781 N.Y.S.2d 261, 265 (N.Y. 2004). See supra notes 149-51 and accompanying text. 191 See supra notes 156-60 and accompanying text. 192 See Court of Appeals Addresses Disputed Time Issue on Summary Judgment Motions, N.Y. ST. L. DIG., June 2004, at 1 (“The majority view [in Brill], taken strictly, would therefore require that the plaintiff call her witnesses and put in her case, and that would be an undertaking – if we assume that the case has been ripe for summary judgment all the while – that will indeed impose on all.”). 193 If the lawyer’s fee is contingent on a recovery in the action, the lawyer will obviously not be compensated for her time. See N.Y. CODE OF PROF’L RESPONSIBILITY DR 2-106(D) (McKinney 2005) (prescribing writing in contingent fee matter). In addition, most lawyers in personal injury litigation agree to advance the expenses of litigation, such as court costs, expenses of investigation, expenses of medical examination, and costs of obtaining and presenting evidence. The New York Lawyers’ Code of Professional Responsibility permits a lawyer to reach an agreement of this 1572 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Despite the dark cloud hanging over many cases as a result of Brill’s holding, the lawyer for the plaintiff in such a case still has a duty to zealously represent her client. 194 Therefore, the lawyer has an obligation to attempt to correct any apparent deficiency in the case and prepare for trial. 195 If the lawyer reasonably believes that the deficiency cannot be cured, the lawyer must confer with the client and discuss the possibility of voluntarily discontinuing the action or offering to settle. 196 In addition, the lawyer must discuss the possibility of a court awarding sanctions for frivolous conduct. 197 It is the client, however, who has the ultimate authority to make the decision on how to proceed. 198 If the client in a case similar to Brill rejects the lawyer’s advice and decides to go to trial, the lawyer may need to consider withdrawing from the representation. If the lawyer reasonably believes that the plaintiff’s claims are no longer supported by existing law, and there is no good faith argument nature with a client, “provided the client remains ultimately liable for such expenses.” N.Y. CODE OF PROF’L RESPONSIBILITY DR 5-103(B)(1) (McKinney 2005). Frequently, however, the lawyer is not able to recoup these expenditures from the client in a personal injury action. 194 See N.Y. CODE OF PROF’L RESPONSIBILITY DR 7-101 (McKinney 2005) (“Representing a client zealously”). 195 The lawyer may attempt to accomplish this task by securing new and additional proof. See supra notes 161-65 and accompanying text. 196 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3217 (McKinney 2005). See supra notes 180-86 and accompanying text. See generally N.Y. CODE OF PROF’L RESPONSIBILITY EC 7-8 (McKinney 2005): A lawyer should exert best efforts to insure that decisions of the client are made only after the client has been informed of relevant considerations. A lawyer ought to initiate this decision-making process if the client does not do so. Advice of a lawyer to the client need not be confined to purely legal considerations. A lawyer should advise the client of the possible effect of each legal alternative. A lawyer should bring to bear upon this decision-making process the fullness of his or her experience as well as the lawyer’s objective viewpoint. Id. 197 198 See supra notes 166-76 and accompanying text. See N.Y. CODE OF PROF’L RESPONSIBILITY EC 7-7 (McKinney 2005): In certain areas of legal representation not affecting the merits of the cause or substantially prejudicing the rights of a client, a lawyer is entitled to make decisions. But otherwise the authority to make decisions is exclusively that of the client and, if made within the framework of the law, such decisions are binding on the lawyer. As typical examples in civil cases, it is for the client to decide whether to accept a settlement offer or whether to waive the right to plead an affirmative defense. Id. 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1573 to change the existing law, the lawyer is obligated to make a motion to withdraw from the representation. 199 B. What Does the Defendant Do Now? What can a party, whose motion for summary judgment was denied on the ground that it was untimely, do to ameliorate the loss of the use of summary judgment? The Brill court prescribed several variations of one particular remedy, a motion for judgment during trial pursuant to CPLR 4401. Other remedies may also exist, including a motion to dismiss for failure to state a cause of action pursuant to CPLR 3211(a)(7). Both varieties of remedies – those spelled out by the Brill court and the possible alternatives – will be discussed below. 1. CPLR 4401 – Motion for Judgment During Trial The majority in Brill stated that a defendant who fails to move for summary judgment in a timely manner has two options: (1) move to dismiss the action after the plaintiff rests, or (2) move for a directed verdict during the trial. These options are sanctioned by CPLR 4401, which permits a party to: move for judgment with respect to a cause of action or issue upon the ground that the moving party is entitled to judgment as a matter of law, after the close of the evidence presented by an opposing party with respect to such cause of action or issue, or at any time on the basis of admissions. 200 The dissent in Brill offered a third option ostensibly under CPLR 4401, a motion to dismiss following the parties’ opening statements. As a general rule, a motion for judgment 199 Id. at DR 2-110(B)(2) (requiring lawyer representing a client before a tribunal to make a motion to withdraw if “[t]he lawyer knows or it is obvious that continued employment will result in violation of a Disciplinary Rule”); Id. at DR 7102(A)(2) (preventing a lawyer from “[k]nowingly advanc[ing] a claim or defense that is unwarranted under existing law, except that the lawyer may advance such claim or defense if it can be supported by good faith argument for an extension, modification, or reversal of existing law”). See also id. at DR 2-110(B)(1) (requiring lawyer to move to withdraw from representing client if “[t]he lawyer knows or it is obvious that the client is bringing the legal action, conducting the defense, or asserting a position in the litigation, or is otherwise having steps taken, merely for the purpose of harassing or maliciously injuring any person”); Id. at DR 2-110(C)(1)(iii) (allowing lawyer to withdraw if client “[i]nsists that lawyer pursue a course of conduct which is illegal or prohibited under the Disciplinary Rules”); Id. at DR 7-102(A)(1) (requiring that when representing a client, a lawyer may not “[f]ile a suit, assert a position, conduct a defense, delay a trial, or take other action on behalf of the client when the lawyer knows or when it is obvious that such action would serve merely to harass or maliciously injure another”). 200 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 4401 (McKinney 2005). 1574 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 as a matter of law under CPLR 4401 only lies after the conclusion of the case of the party against whom judgment is sought. 201 However, judgment as a matter of law at this juncture on the basis of an “admission,” such as a statement by a party’s counsel, is only appropriate where, assuming the truth of the facts alleged by the plaintiff, the plaintiff has no case. 202 This occurs when counsel “intentionally states or admits some fact that, in any view of the case, is fatal to the action.” 203 While the various applications for judgment as a matter of law pursuant to CPLR 4401 offer the defendant what she ultimately desires to obtain, i.e., a dismissal of the action, they require the defendant to prepare for and participate in a trial. 204 Other mechanisms may exist that will allow a defendant who has lost the ability to make a summary judgment motion to secure dismissal of an action without participating in a trial. 201 See, e.g., Siegel, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C4401:5 (1992). 202 See, e.g., Siegel, supra note 201, at C4401:2, at 406; see also Cuellar v. City of N.Y., 5 A.D.3d 530, 531, 772 N.Y.S.2d 872, 873 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004) (applications to dismiss after completion of counsels’ opening statements are “disfavored,” and should only be granted where, “from all available indications, the case is doomed to defeat” (citation omitted)); Jones v. Davis, 307 A.D.2d 494, 498, 763 N.Y.S.2d 136, 140 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 2003) (stating that “practice of dismissing a complaint at the conclusion of counsel’s opening statement is disfavored, and should only be done if ‘on the opening it becomes obvious that the suit cannot be maintained because it lacks a legal basis or, when taken in its strongest light, cannot succeed’”(citation omitted)). 203 See Riccio v. De Marco, 188 A.D.2d 847, 849, 591 N.Y.S.2d 569, 572 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 1992) (quoting Hoffman House v. Foote, 172 N.Y. 348, 351, 65 N.E. 169, 169 (1902)). See also Ballantyne v. City of New York, 19 A.D.3d 440, 440-41, 797 N.Y.S.2d 506, 506 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005): A dismissal of the complaint after plaintiff’s attorney’s opening statement is warranted only where “it can be demonstrated either (1) that the complaint does not state a cause of action . . . (2) that a cause of action well-stated is conclusively defeated by something interposed by way of defense and clearly admitted as a fact or (3) that . . . counsel for the plaintiff, in his [or her] opening [statement], by some admission or statement of fact, so completely ruined his [or her] case that the court was justified in granting [a motion to dismiss].” (citation omitted); Gleyzer v. Steinberg, 254 A.D.2d 455, 455, 679 N.Y.S.2d 154, 154 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1998) (same). 204 In the event that a defendant is forced to participate in a trial to vindicate her position, and plaintiff has not offered proof additional to that offered on the late summary judgment motion, the defendant may seek to recover costs and reasonable attorney’s fees. See supra notes 166-76 and accompanying text. 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1575 2. CPLR 3211(a)(7) – Motion to Dismiss The motion to dismiss resides in CPLR 3211. Such a motion is directed at the entire complaint or a particular cause of action therein, based on one or more of the grounds enumerated in the statute. 205 Generally, a motion to dismiss must be made by a defendant prior to the service of her answer. Certain grounds for dismissal may, however, be raised at any time, including the CPLR 3211(a)(7) motion to dismiss for failure to state a cause of action. 206 CPLR 3211(a)(7) permits a party to move for dismissal of one or more causes of action asserted against her on the ground that a “pleading fails to state a cause of action.” In addition to testing the facial validity of a complaint, CPLR 3211(a)(7) allows a defendant to challenge the merits of a plaintiff’s claim or claims. 207 Specifically, where affidavits or other evidentiary materials are submitted by a CPLR 3211(a)(7) movant, the court may elect to treat the motion as one for summary judgment after providing proper notice to the parties. 208 If the court makes this election and the papers and 205 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3211(a) (McKinney 2005). See Siegel, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C3211:5, C3211:6, C3211:9 (2005). CPLR 3211(b) permits a party to seek dismissal of a defense asserted in another party’s pleading. 206 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3211(e) (McKinney 2005). See, e.g., Schel v. Roth, 242 A.D.2d 697, 697, 663 N.Y.S.2d 609, 610 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1997); Siegel, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C3211:28, C3211:52, C3211:58 (2005). 207 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3211(c) (McKinney 2005) (allowing any party to a motion under CPLR 3211(a) to submit any evidence that could be considered on a motion for summary judgment). See, e.g., 150 Siegel’s Practice Review, Is There Any Way Around the Court of Appeals Brill Case, Which Forces to Trial an Action Ripe for Summary Judgment But Not Moved For on Time?, at 1 (June 2004) [hereinafter Is There Any Way Around Brill?]; Siegel, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C3211:23, C3211:25 (2005); SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 265. 208 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3211(c) (McKinney 2005) (stating that “[w]hether or not issue has been joined, the court, after adequate notice to the parties, may treat the motion as a motion for summary judgment”). Courts have recognized three exceptions to the requirement that notice be given of conversion of a motion to dismiss into one for summary judgment: (1) where the action involves no issues of fact, but only issues of law fully appreciated and argued by both sides, (2) when request for summary judgment treatment is specifically made by both sides, and (3) when both sides make it unequivocally clear that they are laying bare their proof and deliberately charting summary judgment course. See, e.g., Four Seasons Hotels Ltd. v. Vinnik, 127 A.D.2d 310, 316, 515 N.Y.S.2d 1, 8 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1987); Int’l Flavors & Fragrances, Inc. v. Royal Ins. Co. of Am., 6 Misc. 3d 1024(A), 800 N.Y.S.2d 347, No. 605910-01, 2003 WL 24013814 (Sup. Ct. New York County 2003). See also Mihlovan v. Grozavu, 72 N.Y.2d 506, 508, 531 N.E.2d 288, 289, 534 N.Y.S.2d 656, 657 (1988) (stating that court, and not a party, must give notice that it is treating a motion as one for summary judgment). 1576 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 proof submitted in support of a motion to dismiss establish that the defendant should be awarded judgment as a matter of law, the complaint may be dismissed. There are, however, several obstacles that may prevent a party from moving under CPLR 3211(a)(7) after the time period in CPLR 3212(a) has expired. Although it may occur on occasion, 209 it will be the rare case in which, after the filing of a note of issue, a party’s pleading still fails to state a cause of action. In addition, a party seeking to use the motion to dismiss for failure to state a cause of action in lieu of a summary judgment motion will be foreclosed from doing so if the party previously made a motion pursuant to CPLR 3211(a). The “single motion rule,” which is a product of CPLR 3211(e), Several courts have also awarded dismissal on a CPLR 3211(a)(7) motion, apparently in the absence of an election under CPLR 3211(c), when plaintiff’s legal conclusions are “either inherently incredible or flatly contradicted by documentary evidence.” Greene v. Doral Conference Ctr. Assocs., 18 A.D.3d 429, 430, 795 N.Y.S.2d 252, 253-54 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005); Asgahar v. Tringali Realty, Inc., 18 A.D.3d 408, 409, 795 N.Y.S.2d 68, 70 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005); Meyer v. Guinta, 262 A.D.2d 463, 464, 692 N.Y.S.2d 159, 161 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1999); see also Guggenheimer v. Ginzburg, 43 N.Y.2d 268, 275, 372 N.E.2d 17, 20-21, 401 N.Y.S.2d 182, 185 (1977) (stating that “unless it has been shown that a material fact as claimed by the pleader to be one is not a fact at all and unless it can be said that no significant dispute exists regarding it, again dismissal should not eventuate”); Williams v. N.Y. City Hous. Auth., 238 A.D.2d 413, 414, 656 N.Y.S.2d 332, 333 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1997) (“Where, as here, evidentiary material is submitted on a CPLR 3211 motion, it may be considered in assessing the viability of a complaint, but unless the defendant demonstrates that a material fact alleged by the plaintiff to be true ‘is not a fact at all’ and that ‘no significant dispute exists regarding it,’ the complaint should not be dismissed.” (citation omitted)). 209 At least one court has granted a CPLR 3211(a)(7) motion to dismiss a complaint where the movant was foreclosed from moving for summary judgment due to its failure to comply with the timeliness provision of CPLR 3212(a). Santana v. City of New York, 6 Misc. 3d 642, 643, 787 N.Y.S.2d 651, 652-53 (N.Y. Civ. Ct. New York County 2004). In Santana, the plaintiff was assaulted by an inmate whom she was visiting at a correctional facility operated by the defendant. The plaintiff subsequently commenced an action to recover damages against the defendant, alleging negligence in the operation of the correctional facility. The defendant’s motion for summary judgment dismissing the complaint was denied by the court, which cited Brill, on the ground that the motion was untimely under CPLR 3212(a). However, the court granted the defendant’s motion to dismiss for failure to state a cause of action, noting that the plaintiff failed to allege that a “special relationship” existed between the plaintiff and defendant, an element of the plaintiff’s case. A motion in limine, which is generally used to test the admissibility of evidence in advance of trial, is an inappropriate device to obtain relief in the nature of summary judgment. See, e.g., Clermont v. Hillsdale Indus., Inc., 6 A.D.3d 376, 377, 773 N.Y.S.2d 901, 902 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004); Downtown Art Co. v. Zimmerman, 232 A.D.2d 270, 270, 648 N.Y.S.2d 101, 101 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1996); George Miller Brick Co., Inc. v. Stark Ceramics, Inc., 9 Misc. 3d 151, 166-67, 801 N.Y.S.2d 120, 134 (Sup. Ct. Monroe County 2005). Accordingly, a party cannot circumvent the timeliness provision of CPLR 3212(a) by labeling her motion as one in limine. Clermont, 773 N.Y.S.2d at 902; George Miller Brick Co., Inc., 801 N.Y.S.2d at 134. 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1577 proscribes multiple motions to dismiss premised on the grounds listed in CPLR 3211(a). 210 Therefore, if a party seeks to make a CPLR 3211(a)(7) motion after the service of her answer, it will not be entertained if she has already made a pre-answer motion to dismiss. 211 If the court elects to “treat the motion as a motion for summary judgment” pursuant to CPLR 3211(c), 212 there are indications that it should be considered a motion for summary judgment under CPLR 3212, rather than one for dismissal under CPLR 3211. 213 If such treatment is afforded a CPLR 3211(a)(7) motion, the timeliness provision of CPLR 3212(a) will likely apply. 214 If a party is allowed to circumvent the timing requirements in CPLR 3212(a) in this fashion, “it could invite wholesale resort to the CPLR 3211(a)(7) motion in any case in which the time for a CPLR 3212 summary judgment motion has expired.” 215 Furthermore, allowing a party to proceed in this fashion will ultimately result in the very problems that CPLR 3212(a) and the Brill decision attempted 210 CPLR 3211(e) states, in pertinent part, that: “At any time before service of the responsive pleading is required, a party may move on one or more of the grounds set forth in subdivision (a) [of 3211], and no more than one such motion shall be permitted.” N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3211(e) (McKinney 2005). See Siegel, Practice Commentaries, McKinney’s Cons. Laws of N.Y., Book 7B, CPLR C3211:55 (2005); SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 273. 211 See McLearn v. Cowen & Co., 60 N.Y.2d 686, 688, 455 N.E.2d 1256, 1257, 468 N.Y.S.2d 461, 462 (1983); Miller v. Schreyer, 257 A.D.2d 358, 683 N.Y.S.2d 51 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1999); Reilly v. Prentice, 141 A.D.2d 520, 520, 529 N.Y.S.2d 343, 344 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1988). 212 See supra notes 207-08 and accompanying text. 213 Rich v. Lefkovits, 56 N.Y.2d 276, 281-82, 437 N.E.2d 260, 263, 452 N.Y.S.2d 1, 4 (1982). 214 See Is There Any Way Around Brill?, supra note 207: CPLR 3211(c) anticipates that the evidence before the court in a given case may be ample enough to support a summary judgment motion. It does this by empowering the court to treat the CPLR 3211 motion as such as long as it gives the parties notice of its intention. An argument that would put a quick end to this possibility is that the court should not ‘treat’ as summary judgment a motion that would now be untimely under the terms of the summary judgment provision itself, CPLR 3212(a). Id. See also Diaz v. N.Y. City Health & Hosps. Corp., 289 A.D.2d 365, 734 N.Y.S.2d 882 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2001) (“Contrary to the defendants’ contention that their motion was addressed to the pleadings pursuant to CPLR 3211(a)(7), the motion was for summary judgment, and therefore it should have been made no later than 120 days after the filing of the note of issue.” (citation omitted)). 215 166 Siegel’s Practice Review, Can a Motion to Dismiss under CPLR 3211 Circumvent the Time Limit on the Motion for Summary Judgment under CPLR 3212?, at 1 (Oct. 2005). 1578 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 to remedy. 216 Accordingly, where a party seeking to circumvent the timeliness provisions in CPLR 3212(a) makes a CPLR 3211(a)(7) motion to dismiss, which is subsequently converted to a motion for summary judgment under CPLR 3211(c), the movant should wind up in the same position: foreclosed from moving for summary judgment absent a showing of good cause. 3. CPLR 3404 & 22 NYCRR § 202.27 – Laxness Dismissals A defendant who has been foreclosed from the use of the summary judgment tool as a result of a violation of the timeliness provision of CPLR 3212(a) may attempt to obtain dismissal of an action pending against her by doing nothing more than diligently pressing for a trial on the very matter that the defendant has insisted contains no triable issue of fact. If the plaintiff fails to appear or is unable to proceed when the matter is set for trial, the defendant may be able to obtain a “laxness dismissal.” 217 22 NYCRR section 202.27 and CPLR 3404 form the core of post-note of issue laxness dismissals, 218 and are the focus of the ensuing discussion. Following the disposition of a summary judgment motion, it is customary for a trial court to conduct a pretrial conference. 219 The purpose of this conference is, among other things, to review the issues to be tried and select a date on which the trial is to commence. 220 Where a defendant’s otherwise meritorious summary judgment motion has been denied due to its untimeliness, plaintiff’s counsel, acknowledging the fact that the action is unlikely to succeed, 216 See supra notes 19, 154 and accompanying text. Cf. Andrea v. Arnone, Hedin, Casker, Kennedy and Drake, Architects and Landscape Architects, P.C., 5 N.Y.3d 514, 521, 840 N.E.2d 565, 569, 806 N.Y.S.2d 453, 457 (2005): [W]hat is undesirable is sometimes also necessary, and it is often necessary, as it is here, to hold parties responsible for their lawyers’ failure to meet deadlines. Litigation cannot be conducted efficiently if deadlines are not taken seriously, and we make clear again, as we have several times before, that disregard of deadlines should not and will not be tolerated. (citations omitted). 217 This phrase is borrowed from Professor Siegel’s treatise. SIEGEL, supra note 36, at 625. 218 With respect to cases in which a note of issue has been filed, care must be taken to avoid reliance on CPLR 3216 (“want of prosecution”) as a ground for dismissal. CPLR 3216 only applies to cases that are in the pre-note of issue stage. E.g., Johnson v. Sam Minskoff & Sons, Inc., 287 A.D.2d 233, 237, 735 N.Y.S.2d 503, 506 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2001); Lopez v. Imperial Delivery Serv., Inc., 282 A.D.2d 190, 194, 725 N.Y.S.2d 57, 60 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2001). 219 See N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.26 (2005). 220 Id. § 202.26(c); see also SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 374. 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1579 may want to dedicate her energies to other matters. 221 Concomitantly, plaintiff’s counsel may elect to skip or lightly forget a pretrial conference scheduled on the matter, or send an attorney to cover the conference who is unfamiliar with the case or without authority to take meaningful actions with respect to the matter. 222 Should this scenario unfold, plaintiff’s counsel will expose the action to a laxness dismissal based on 22 NYCRR section 202.27(b). 223 This rule authorizes a trial court to dismiss an action where plaintiff’s counsel fails to appear for a conference or, upon appearing, fails to announce her readiness to proceed with the conference. 224 Thus, a violation of the rule may provide another alternative for a defendant who can no longer avail herself of a meritorious summary judgment motion, but is still bent on attaining a dismissal. 225 If the trial court invokes § 202.27(b) and dismisses the action, plaintiff must provide a reasonable excuse for the default and demonstrate that her action has merit to successfully vacate the default. 226 If a meritorious summary judgment motion was 221 See supra notes 194-198 and accompanying text. The Uniform Rules require an attorney who appears at a pretrial conference to be “fully familiar with the action and authorized to make binding stipulations or accompanied by a person empowered to act on behalf of the party.” N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 202.26(e) (2005). 223 While Uniform Rule section 202.27 is only applicable to actions in the supreme and county courts, the respective uniform rules of the New York City Civil Court, the City Courts, and the District Courts provide each of these courts with an analogous calendar control device. Id. § 208.14(b) (“Uniform Civil Rules for the New York City Civil Court”; “Calendar default; restoration; dismissal”); Id. § 210.14 (“Uniform Civil Rules for the City Courts Outside of the City of New York”; “Defaults”); Id. § 212.14(b) (“Uniform Civil Rules for the District Courts”; “Calendar default; restoration; dismissal”). 224 See, e.g, Echevarria v. Waters, 8 A.D.3d 330, 331, 777 N.Y.S.2d 724, 724 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004) (dismissing the action pursuant to section 202.27(b) where plaintiff’s counsel failed to appear at pretrial conference); Contractors Cas. & Sur. Co. v. 535 Broadhollow Realty L.L.C., 276 A.D.2d 737, 737, 715 N.Y.S.2d 434, 435 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2000) (striking defendants’ answer and ordering an inquest pursuant to section 202.27(a) where defendants’ counsel failed to appear at pretrial conference); Booth v. Hawk Contractors, Inc., 259 A.D.2d 577, 577, 686 N.Y.S.2d 770, 771 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1999) (dismissing action pursuant to section 202.27(b) where plaintiff’s counsel failed to appear at trial-readiness conference). 225 Presumably a plaintiff’s lawyer would not intentionally skip or lightly forget a pretrial conference for an action that the lawyer believes is meritorious. In any event, if the conference is missed and the action is dismissed pursuant to section 202.27(b), the lawyer may be able to vacate the default. See infra note 226 and accompanying text. 226 See, e.g, Solomon v. Ramlall, 18 A.D.3d 461, 461, 795 N.Y.S.2d 76, 77 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005); Echevarria, 777 N.Y.S.2d at 724-25; Brannigan v. Bd. of Educ. of Levittown Union Free School Dist., 307 A.D.2d 945, 946, 763 N.Y.S.2d 471, 472 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2003); Uddaraju v. City of New York, 1 A.D.3d 140, 141, 766 N.Y.S.2d 222 1580 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 denied solely on the basis of the timeliness provisions in CPLR 3212(a), it may be very difficult for the plaintiff to demonstrate that the default should be vacated based on the merits of the action. In many instances, she may have no incentive to try. 227 In the event that a case similar to Brill is not dismissed 228 or discontinued 229 prior to reaching its turn on the trial calendar, the defendant may avert trial if the plaintiff fails to appear for the commencement of the trial by failing to answer a call at the trial calendar, or appears but is not ready to proceed. 230 Confronted with a plaintiff’s failure to appear for the commencement of trial or failure to be ready to proceed, the trial court has four options. 231 The court has the discretion to: (1) adjourn the case, (2) mark the case “off” or strike it from the trial calendar pursuant to CPLR 3404, 232 (3) vacate the note of issue pursuant to Uniform Rule § 202.21(e),233 or (4) dismiss the action pursuant to Uniform Rule § 202.27. 234 Neither the first nor the third option result in the dismissal of the action. It is unlikely, however, that a court would employ these options to a case resembling Brill, where the merits of plaintiff’s claims are doubtful. The first option, allowing for an adjournment of the case, is the “least drastic course of action” and carries no consequences to the defaulting party. 235 Given that it is the responsibility of the trial courts under the Individual Assignment System 236 to move cases to disposition expeditiously, 237 an adjournment of the trial of a case that has no merit would be inappropriate. 238 Furthermore, 207, 208 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2003); Lopez v. Imperial Delivery Serv., 725 N.Y.S.2d 57, 62 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2001); Contractors Cas. & Sur. Co., 715 N.Y.S.2d at 435; Booth, 686 N.Y.S.2d at 771. 227 See supra notes 194-98 and accompanying text. 228 See supra notes 207-27 and accompanying text. 229 See supra notes 181-82 and accompanying text. 230 See N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3404 (McKinney 2005). 231 Brannigan, 763 N.Y.S.2d at 472; Basetti v. Nour, 731 N.Y.S.2d 35, 41 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2001). 232 See infra notes 242-47 and accompanying text. 233 See supra note 84 and accompanying text. 234 See supra notes 223-27 and accompanying text. 235 Basetti, 731 N.Y.S.2d at 41. 236 Under the Individual Assignment System, which New York adopted on January 6, 1986, a case gets assigned to a single judge who handles the case through its disposition. See SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 77A. 237 Vincent C. Alexander, New Approach to Restoring Cases Marked ‘Off’ the Trial Calendar, N.Y.L.J., Nov. 10, 2001, at 3, 5. 238 Adjournments of trial dates are frequently granted due to the engagement of counsel in another matter before a different court. See generally N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, §§ 125.1, 202.32 (2005). Adjournments are also frequently employed 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1581 the third option of vacating the note of issue would be inappropriate in a Brill situation, unless the certificate of readiness 239 accompanying the note of issue is incorrect in some material respect. 240 The remaining options of marking the matter “off” the trial calendar pursuant to CPLR 3404 and dismissal under Uniform Rule § 202.27 offer the prospect of dismissal of the action, with the latter providing it immediately. CPLR 3404, entitled “Dismissal of abandoned cases,” provides: A case in the supreme court or a county court marked “off” or struck from the calendar or unanswered on a clerk’s calendar call, and not restored within one year thereafter, shall be deemed abandoned and shall be dismissed without costs for neglect to prosecute. The clerk shall make an appropriate entry without the necessity of an order. 241 The statute, which should only be invoked where all parties appear but some circumstance prevents the case from immediately going to trial, 242 affords a dilatory plaintiff one year to restore an action marked “off” the trial calendar. 243 Upon the expiration of the one-year period, the case is automatically dismissed 244 if a motion to restore has not been to accommodate scheduling problems related to witnesses, the illness of counsel, a party or a witness, and personal or family emergencies. 239 See supra notes 83-84 and accompanying text. 240 Basetti, 731 N.Y.S.2d at 41. 241 N.Y. C.P.L.R. 3404 (McKinney 2005). 242 See Basetti, 731 N.Y.S.2d at 41. 243 There is disagreement as to the applicability of CPLR 3404 to actions in the lower courts. See, e.g., Chavez v. 407 Seventh Ave. Corp., 10 Misc.3d 33, 807 N.Y.S.2d 785 (App. Term 2d & 11th Jud. Dists. 2005) (declining to follow prior holdings and concluding that CPLR 3404 is applicable to the Civil Court of the City of New York); But cf. Jeganathan v. O’Reilly, 195 Misc. 2d 197, 199-200, 753 N.Y.S.2d 814, 818 (City Ct. White Plains 2003) (holding that CPLR 3404 is not available as a calendar control device in City Court); SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 376. As to actions in the New York City Civil Court, the City Courts and the District Courts, the individual rules applicable to those courts must be consulted. N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 208.14 (2005) (“Uniform Civil Rules for the New York City Civil Court”; “Calendar default; restoration; dismissal”); N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 210.14 (2005) (“Uniform Civil Rules for the City Courts Outside the City of New York”; “Defaults”); N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 212.14 (2005) (“Uniform Civil Rules for the District Courts”; “Calendar default; restoration; dismissal”). 244 See, e.g., Threatt v. Seton Health Sys., Inc., 277 A.D.2d 796, 796, 715 N.Y.S.2d 791, 792 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 2000) (dismissal of abandoned case accomplished automatically upon passage of one-year period); Meade v. L.A. Lama Agency, Inc., 260 A.D.2d 979, 980, 689 N.Y.S.2d 302, 304 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 1999) (dismissal of action where plaintiff fails to restore within statutory period is self-executing, requiring no further ministerial action); Nunez v. County of Nassau, 265 A.D.2d 312, 313, 696 N.Y.S.2d 217, 218 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1999) (no motion to dismiss by defendant necessary where plaintiff failed to restore action within one-year period, as dismissal 1582 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 made. 245 Restoration within the one-year period is free for the asking and the plaintiff is not burdened with any required showing. 246 If a plaintiff fails to duly restore the action within one year and the action is dismissed, the plaintiff must make a motion to vacate the dismissal. To succeed on such a motion, the plaintiff must establish, among other things, that her action is meritorious, 247 a showing that a plaintiff in a Brill situation will be hard-pressed to make. Accordingly, CPLR 3404 may prove useful to the defendant in a Brill situation, provided that plaintiff’s conduct causes the action to be marked “off” the trial calendar and plaintiff is not inclined to move for restoration of the action within the prescribed period. The final option, dismissal pursuant to Uniform Rule § 202.27(b), 248 is not only the most desirable remedy in the eyes of a defendant in a Brill situation, but is probably the most appropriate. Should the plaintiff in a Brill situation fail to appear for the commencement of trial, or appear but not be ready to proceed, the trial court may dismiss the action pursuant to § 202.27(b). 249 This would remove the one-year grace period offered by CPLR 3404, 250 result in the immediate was automatic); Lee v. Chion, 213 A.D.2d 602, 603, 623 N.Y.S.2d 927, 927 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 1995) (same); SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 376. 245 See, e.g., Ronsco v. Constr. Co. v. 30 East 85th Street Co., 219 A.D.2d 281, 283, 641 N.Y.S.2d 33, 35 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1996); Maida v. Rite Aid Corp., 210 A.D.2d 589, 590, 619 N.Y.S.2d 812, 813 (App. Div. 3d Dep’t 1994). 246 See, e.g., Brannigan v. Bd. of Educ. of Levittown Union Free Sch. Dist., 763 N.Y.S.2d 471, 472 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2003); Basetti v. Nour, 731 N.Y.S.2d 35, 39 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2001); Lopez v. Imperial Delivery Serv., Inc., 725 N.Y.S.2d 57, 62 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2001); SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 376. 247 See, e.g., Basetti, 731 N.Y.S.2d at 39; Lopez, 725 N.Y.S.2d at 62; SIEGEL, supra note 36, § 376. The plaintiff must also establish: (1) a reasonable excuse for the failure to timely restore; (2) lack of intent to abandon the action; and (3) a lack of prejudice to her adversary. Castillo v. N.Y. City Hous. Auth., 6 A.D.3d 568, 568, 775 N.Y.S.2d 82, 82 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2004); Basetti, 731 N.Y.S.2d at 39; Aguilar v. Djonvic, 282 A.D.2d 366, 366, 723 N.Y.S.2d 474, 476 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2001); Lopez, 725 N.Y.S.2d at 62; Bray v. Thor Steel & Welding Ltd., 275 A.D.2d 912, 912, 713 N.Y.S.2d 400, 401 (App. Div. 4th Dep’t 2000); Sanchez v. Javind Apt. Corp., 667 N.Y.S.2d 708, 710 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1998). 248 See supra notes 223-27 and accompanying text. 249 See, e.g., Solomon v. Ramlall, 795 N.Y.S.2d 76, 77 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2005) (dismissing action pursuant to section 202.27(b) upon plaintiff’s counsel failure to appear on date set for jury selection). The defendant should remind the trial judge of any meritorious summary judgment motion that was denied based on untimeliness. See generally Is There Any Way Around Brill?, supra note 207, at 1 (“The trial judge should be apprised of any situation in which the case is ripe for summary disposition, but in which a summary judgment motion was made too late, or – the more likely scenario – was never made at all because the would-be movant recognized its lateness.”). 250 See supra notes 242-47 and accompanying text. 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1583 dismissal of the action, and place the burden on the plaintiff, should she elect to move to vacate the dismissal, 251 to demonstrate the merits of her case. 252 This type of dismissal is warranted in such a case because it will expedite the disposition of the matter, a main objective of the Individual Assignment System. 253 4. Defense Lawyer’s Potential Exposure to Legal Malpractice If a defendant has meritorious grounds for a summary judgment motion, it is obviously in her economic interests to move promptly. Disposing of the case at the earliest possible moment will generally result in a cost benefit to the defendant, who can avoid the continued expense of attorney’s fees and litigation disbursements. If a defendant is precluded from making a meritorious motion for summary judgment based on a failure to comply with CPLR 3212(a)’s time period, 254 it will usually result from a lawyer’s failure to meet the deadline. As the Court of Appeals held in Brill, the case will now have to proceed to trial. 255 This will require a substantial amount of preparation by the lawyers representing the defendant, including the expense of hiring any necessary experts. If the grounds for the untimely summary judgment motion are meritorious, the defendant who is precluded from making the motion because of a failure to comply with CPLR 3212(a)’s time frame may have a legal malpractice claim against her lawyer. A legal malpractice action requires the plaintiff to prove “three essential elements: (1) the negligence of the attorney; (2) that the negligence was the proximate cause 251 The plaintiff in a Brill situation will have little or no incentive to move to vacate a dismissal based on § 202.27. See supra notes 187-93 and accompanying text. 252 See supra note 226-27 and accompanying text. 253 E.g., Basetti v. Nour, 731 N.Y.S.2d 35, 41 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2001) (“[T]he overall purpose of the Individual Assignment System (IAS) [is] to give trial judges greater control over their cases and to move cases to disposition more expeditiously.”); Johnson v. Minskoff & Sons, Inc., 735 N.Y.S.2d 503, 506 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 2001) (stating that “the Individual Assignment System . . . was intended to encourage trial court control of cases and promote the disposition of cases within reasonable periods of time”); Lopez v. Imperial Delivery Serv., Inc., 725 N.Y.S.2d 57, 61 (App. Div. 2d Dep’t 2001) (“Two of the objectives of the IAS were to encourage efficient trial court control of cases and to promote the disposition of cases within reasonable periods of time.”). 254 See Brill v. City of N.Y., 781 N.Y.S.2d 261, 264-65 (N.Y. 2004) (stating that meritorious, nonprejudicial filings, however tardy, cannot be considered in the absence of good cause for the delay); supra notes 25-28 and accompanying text. 255 Brill, 781 N.Y.S.2d at 265. 1584 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 of the loss sustained; and (3) proof of actual damages.” 256 An attorney who agrees to represent a client impliedly warrants that, among other things, she “is familiar with the rules regulating practice in actions of the type which [she] undertakes to bring or defend and with such principles of law in relation to such actions as are well settled in the practice of law.” 257 From the two Court of Appeals cases that specifically address the timeliness requirements of CPLR 3212(a), 258 it is apparent that the dictates of the statute are now well settled. If a lawyer fails to serve a meritorious motion for summary judgment on a timely basis and cannot establish good cause for the delay, a strong argument may be made that the attorney’s conduct constituted negligence. If negligence is established in this context, it will not be difficult to satisfy the second and third elements of a legal malpractice claim. Virtually any subsequent expense incurred during the course of the litigation can be linked to the lawyer’s failure to make the meritorious motion on a timely basis. The proof of actual damages in this scenario will not be difficult to establish, and may take the form of the lawyer’s invoice for any services after the failed motion. 259 The prospect of a legal malpractice claim will only arise in cases where the defendant actually possesses meritorious grounds for a summary judgment motion. A court may volunteer this observation when refusing to entertain a late motion for summary judgment based on CPLR 3212(a)’s timing 256 Prudential Ins. Co. of Am. v. Dewey, Ballantine, Bushby, Palmer & Wood, 170 A.D.2d 108, 114, 573 N.Y.S.2d 981, 985 (App. Div. 1st Dep’t 1991), aff’d, 80 N.Y.2d 377, 590 N.Y.S.2d 831, 605 N.E.2d 318 (1992). 257 1B NEW YORK PATTERN JURY INSTRUCTIONS – CIVIL § 2:152, at 857 (3d ed. 2005). 258 See supra notes 21-28 and accompanying text. 259 The dispute may arise when, after receiving the lawyer’s invoice, the client refuses to pay the lawyer for any services rendered or disbursements incurred after the failed summary judgment motion. Before the lawyer can sue the client for any unpaid fees, she must plead and prove compliance with New York’s Fee Dispute Resolution Program. N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 137 (2005). “An attorney who institutes an action to recover a fee must allege in the complaint: (1) that the client received notice under this Part of the client’s right to pursue arbitration or (2) that the dispute is not otherwise covered by this Part.” Id. § 137.6(b). See Lorin v. 501 Second St. LLC, 2 Misc. 3d 646, 647, 769 N.Y.S.2d 361, 362 (N.Y. Civ. Ct. Kings County 2003) (granting reargument and adhering to the earlier determination that complaint must be dismissed for failure to comply with Part 137’s requirements). Part 137 does not apply, however, to “claims involving substantial legal questions, including professional malpractice or misconduct.” N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 22, § 137.1(b)(3) (2005). 2006] CPLR 3212(a)’S TIMING REQUIREMENT 1585 requirements. 260 Even if a court is silent on the point, if it is apparent that the client was denied the right to have a case dismissed on summary judgment grounds because of the attorney’s failure to comply with CPLR 3212(a)’s time periods, the attorney may have an obligation to disclose the problem to the client. 261 VIII. CONCLUSION CPLR 3212(a)’s timing requirement for summary judgment motions will continue to have a pervasive and significant effect on litigation in New York State courts. This article has attempted to address the rule’s application in a variety of contexts to provide guidance to the bench and bar. As with so many aspects of civil procedure, the rule will gradually settle into place on the landscape and become a noncontroversial part of practice. In the meanwhile, given the large number of cases still addressing CPLR 3212(a)’s requirements, and the dramatic effect of the Court of Appeals’ recent decisions in Brill and Miceli, there will be several more chapters in this saga. 260 In Brill, both the Supreme Court and the Appellate Division concluded that defendant’s motion for summary judgment was meritorious. See supra notes 15659 and accompanying text. The Court of Appeals did not consider the merits of the defendant’s motion. Brill v. City of N.Y., 781 N.Y.S.2d 261, 263 n.2 (N.Y. 2004). 261 N.Y. State Bar Ass’n Comm. on Prof’l Ethics, Opinion No. 734 (Nov. 1, 2000) (opining that an attorney must report to the client a significant error or omission that may give rise to a possible malpractice claim and, depending on the circumstances, may be required to withdraw its representation of the client). 1586 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 POSTSCRIPT Chief Judge Judith Kaye, New York Court of Appeals As the author of Brill v. City of New York, I have several reactions to Professor Connors’ article. First, I am impressed – indeed, dazzled – by the author’s comprehensive treatment of his subject, and by his scholarship. As a CPLR “junkie,” I find all of the pathways to, from, in, out and around Brill downright fascinating. On another level, I feel both elation and dismay. Elation because the Court’s purpose in insisting upon strict compliance with the clear statutory prescription was in part to underscore the seriousness of deadlines and jog a delay-oriented culture (see also Kihl v. Pfeffer 262 ). Thus, elation because the decision sure was noticed! But dismay quickly followed. So much effort, so much lawyer and court time, so much client risk and expense, to avoid simple compliance with a rule requiring that motions for summary judgment be made no later than 120 days after the filing of the note of issue, unless the movant can establish good cause. Professor Connors attributes this to “the adventuresome nature of a healthy segment of the bar,” and provides guidance to the bench and bar in dealing with the timing requirement for summary judgment motions. I can’t avoid offering some guidance of my own: just honor the deadlines, whether statutory or court-ordered. There’s lots of other room for adventure in, and beyond, the law. 262 94 N.Y.2d 118, 123, 722 N.E.2d 55, 58, 700 N.Y.S.2d 87, 90 (1999). The Case for the Retroactive Application of Crawford v. Washington “In all criminal prosecutions, the accused shall enjoy the right . . . to be confronted with the witnesses against him.” U.S. CONST. amend. VI. I. INTRODUCTION The Confrontation Clause, embedded in the Sixth Amendment to the United States Constitution, guarantees all criminal defendants the right to confront their accusers. 1 Described as the “greatest legal engine ever invented for the discovery of truth,” 2 the right of confrontation is considered essential to a fair trial. 3 Indeed, it is one of the “fundamental 1 The full text of the Amendment reads, In all criminal prosecutions, the accused shall enjoy the right to a speedy and public trial, by an impartial jury of the State and district wherein the crime shall have been committed, which district shall have been previously ascertained by law, and to be informed of the nature and cause of the accusation; to be confronted with the witnesses against him; to have compulsory process for obtaining witnesses in his favor, and to have the Assistance of Counsel for his defence. U.S. CONST. amend. VI. (emphasis added). 2 California v. Green, 399 U.S. 149, 158 (1970) (citing 5 Wigmore § 1367). 3 In Kirby v. United States, the Supreme Court referred to the Confrontation Clause as “[o]ne of the fundamental guarantees of life and liberty,” and “a right long deemed so essential for the due protection of life and liberty that it is guarded against legislative and judicial action by provisions in the Constitution of the United States and in the constitutions of most if not of all the States composing the Union.” 174 U.S. 47, 55-56 (1899). Pointer v. Texas declared, “[t]he fact that this right appears in the Sixth Amendment of our Bill of Rights reflects the belief of the Framers of those liberties and safeguards that confrontation was a fundamental right essential to a fair trial in a criminal prosecution.” The Court continued that, “the decisions of this Court and other courts throughout the years have constantly emphasized the necessity for crossexamination as a protection for defendants in criminal cases.” 380 U.S. 400, 404 (1965) (footnote omitted). Moreover, in 1807 Chief Justice Marshall wrote, “I know of no principal in the preservation of which all are more concerned. I know none, by undermining which, life, liberty and property, might be more endangered. It is therefore incumbent on courts to be watchful of every inroad on a principal so truly important.” United States v. Burr, 25 F. Cas. 193 (C.C. Va. 1807) (No. 14,694). 1631 1632 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 guarantees of life and liberty,” 4 and “an essential and fundamental requirement for the kind of fair trial which is this country’s constitutional goal.” 5 In March of 2004, the Supreme Court decided Crawford v. Washington, 6 redefining the landscape of Confrontation Clause jurisprudence. 7 Crawford announced that no testimonial statement may be admitted at trial against a criminal defendant unless the defendant has the opportunity to cross examine the declarant. 8 In short, Crawford significantly reinterpreted the Confrontation Clause’s force and effect. When the Supreme Court promulgates a rule, as in Crawford, criminal defendants with pending litigation gain access to the rule’s application on direct appeal. In order for a criminal defendant who has exhausted all direct appellate avenues, and whose conviction is final, to benefit from a recent Court decision, however, he must attempt to do so on collateral review. 9 If a rule is important enough, courts may apply it 4 Kirby, 174 U.S. at 55; accord Pointer, 380 U.S. at 410 (Stewart, J., concurring) (referring to the right of cross-examination as “[o]ne of the fundamental guarantees of life and liberty,” “one of the safeguards essential to a fair trial,” and, “as indispensable an ingredient as the ‘right to be tried in a courtroom presided over by a judge.’”) (citations omitted). 5 Pointer, 380 U.S. at 405 (emphasis added). 6 541 U.S. 36 (2004). 7 See, e.g., Neil P. Cohen & Donald F. Paine, Crawford v. Washington: Confrontation Revolution, 40 TENN. B.J. 22, 22 (May 2004) (“On March 8, 2004, the U.S. Supreme Court decided Michael Crawford’s appeal from a Washington State conviction for assault and totally revised the modern approach to the Confrontation Clause.”) (citation omitted); Robert P. Mosteller, Crawford v. Washington: Encouraging and Ensuring the Confrontation of Witnesses, 39 U. RICH. L. REV. 511, 511 (2005) (“In Crawford v. Washington, the Supreme Court of the United States radically changed [the] Confrontation Clause doctrine . . . .”); Rene L. Valladares, Crawford v. Washington: The Confrontation Clause Gets Teeth, 12 NEV. LAW. 12, 12 (Sept. 2004) (“The Court’s decision is anticipated to cause rapid and profound changes in how hearsay statements are used against a defendant in a criminal trial. Appellate courts have described Crawford as being a ‘bombshell,’ and a ‘paradigm shift in confrontation clause analysis.’”); John F. Yetter, Wrestling with Crawford v. Washington and the New Constitutional Law of Confrontation, 78 FLA. BAR J. 26, 26 (Oct. 2004) (“The Court erased a body of precedent that was, if not completely favorable to the prosecution, well understood and generally accommodating to the use of hearsay evidence without the necessity of calling the declarant as a witness.”). 8 Prior to Crawford, the Supreme Court case that articulated the governing Confrontation Clause doctrine was Ohio v. Roberts, 448 U.S. 56 (1980). Under Roberts, statements were routinely admitted at trial, without the defendant’s ability to crossexamine the declarant, if they were deemed reliable. Id. at 57. See Part II, infra, for a discussion of Crawford and Roberts. 9 A defendant convicted in state court can seek collateral review using either state or federal procedures. Usually, a state defendant will invoke state collateral procedures before federal collateral procedures, though not required to do so. “After state collateral procedures have been used unsuccessfully, the defendant may try federal collateral remedies, especially federal habeas corpus.” NEIL P. COHEN & 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1633 retroactively on collateral review, thus broadening the rule to reach even those defendants with final convictions. 10 Therefore, if Crawford is deemed retroactive, a defendant with a final conviction may seek collateral review alleging Crawford violations, even if Crawford was decided after the conviction became final. The Supreme Court generally disfavors retroactivity, and accordingly, has fashioned a standard difficult to satisfy. 11 In fact, under the Supreme Court’s current standard no “new” rule has been applied retroactivity. 12 Crawford, however, is a rule of paramount importance. The Constitution guarantees the right of confrontation, yet, prior to Crawford the law ran afoul of that Constitutional mandate. Crawford corrected a serious flaw in the Court’s Confronation Clause jurisprudence, and its rule is so crucial to the legitimacy of criminal proceedings that it must be applied retroactively. Part II of this Note discusses the significance of Crawford’s holding by recapitulating the weaknesses of the pre-Crawford test and describing the improvements made by Crawford. Part III summarizes the high bar set by the Supreme Court’s current retroactivity doctrine, specifically Teague v. Lane 13 and its progeny. More specifically, Part III elaborates on the contours of the second exception to Teague’s DONALD J. HALL, CRIMINAL PROCEDURE: THE POST-INVESTIGATIVE PROCESS CASES AND MATERIALS 805 (2d ed. 2000). The federal habeas statute provides that a federal court “shall entertain an application for a writ of habeas corpus in behalf of a person in custody . . . on the ground that he is in custody in violation of the Constitution or laws or treaties of the United States.” 28 U.S.C. §2254(a) (1982); see also WAYNE R. LAFAVE ET AL., CRIMINAL PROCEDURE 1312 (4th ed. 2004) (“[T]hrough the federal writ of habeas corpus, a state defendant may challenge his state conviction on federal constitutional grounds in the federal courts.”). A defendant convicted in federal court can file a Motion to Vacate Sentence pursuant to 28 U.S.C. § 2255 to challenge the constitutionality of his conviction. “A § 2255 Motion involves virtually the same issues and procedures as federal habeas corpus.” COHEN & HALL, supra note 9, at 848. 10 See LAFAVE, supra note 9, at 1359-61. 11 See, e.g., id. at 1359 (“[T]he second Teague exception is quite restrictive.”); Cohen & Hall, supra note 9, at 843 (“Recent Supreme Court decisions have greatly reduced the chances that a habeas corpus petitioner will be able to get relief based on a recent decision or a novel theory.”). 12 “Beginning with the rule at issue in Teague, the Court has measured at least eleven new rules, or proposed new rules, of criminal procedure against the criteria for the second exception and, in every case, has refused to apply the rule retroactively.” United States v. Mandanici, 205 F.3d 519, 529 (2d Cir. 2000). The Second Circuit proceeded to list a number of cases illustrating this pattern. Id. See also Part III.A, infra, to learn what constitutes a “new” rule. 13 489 U.S. 288 (1989) (establishing the current standard for “new” rule retroactivity). For a further discussion of the Teague standard, see infra Part III. 1634 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 general bar to retroactivity. Part IV argues that the Crawford rule fits within the narrowly construed second Teague exception. It does so by drawing from the Court’s language in Crawford, discussing pre-Teague precedent, distinguishing the previous rules that the Supreme Court has declined to make retroactive, and analogizing the Crawford rule to a rule that achieved retroactivity under Teague in lower state and federal courts. II. BACKGROUND A. Crawford’s Facts and Procedural History On August 5, 1999, Michael Crawford and his wife Sylvia visited a friend, Rubin Richard Kenneth Lee. 14 During the visit Michael Crawford stabbed Lee because Crawford thought Lee sexually assaulted Sylvia. 15 After the police apprehended Michael Crawford, he and Sylvia each gave recorded statements to the police in which they recounted the events that precipitated the stabbing. 16 Their statements differed in one very significant way; Michael said that Lee reached for a weapon of his own before Michael stabbed him, intimating that Michael acted in self-defense, while Sylvia said she never saw Lee with a weapon, intimating that Michael was the lone aggressor. 17 Michael Crawford was then prosecuted for assault and attempted murder. 18 At trial, Michael Crawford claimed self-defense. 19 Sylvia Crawford did not testify because Michael Crawford invoked Washington’s marital privilege, which allowed him to prevent his wife from testifying against him. 20 The prosecution did, however, introduce her tape-recorded statement incriminating Michael, despite the fact that she was not available to be cross- 14 Crawford v. Washington, 541 U.S. 36, 38 (2004). Id. 16 Id. at 38-40. 17 Id. at 38-39 (“Sylvia generally corroborated petitioner’s story about the events leading up to the fight, but her account of the fight itself was arguably different – particularly with respect to whether Lee had drawn a weapon before petitioner assaulted him . . . .”) Michael Crawford said, “I think that he pulled somethin’ out and I grabbed for it and that’s how I got cut,” while Sylvia, when asked if she saw anything in Lee’s hands, said “um um (no).” Id. at 39-40. 18 Id. at 40. 19 Crawford, 541 U.S. at 40 (2004). 20 Id. 15 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1635 examined. 21 Her statement that Lee did not have a weapon was fatal to Michael Crawford’s self-defense claim, 22 and he was convicted of assault. 23 Crawford then challenged his conviction on the grounds that the admission of Sylvia’s statement violated his Sixth Amendment right to confrontation. 24 The Washington Supreme Court, applying the then-controlling United States Supreme Court precedent, Ohio v. Roberts, 25 upheld Crawford’s conviction, concluding that Sylvia’s statement “bore guarantees of trustworthiness.” 26 Crawford then appealed his conviction to the United States Supreme Court. 27 B. Hearsay Statements, like Sylvia’s, made out-of-court and offered as evidence to prove that which they assert are hearsay. 28 The Federal Rules of Evidence 29 generally bar hearsay because hearsay is thought to be unreliable. Underlying the hearsay rule is the idea that if the declarant—the one who made the statement—is not in court there is no way to judge the veracity of the statement; hence, the statement is presumptively unreliable. 30 The Federal Rules of Evidence do, however, 21 Id. In fact, in closing argument the prosecutor referred to Sylvia’s statement as “‘damning evidence’ that ‘completely refute[d] [Crawford’s] claim of self-defense.’” Id. at 40-41. 23 Id. at 41. 24 Id. at 40-41. 25 Crawford, 541 U.S. at 41 (“The Washington Supreme Court . . . conclud[ed] that, although Sylvia’s statement did not fall under a firmly rooted hearsay exception, it bore guarantees of trustworthiness . . . .”). The test from Roberts allowed for the admission of ex-parte testimony if it bore “adequate ‘indicia of reliability.’” Ohio v. Roberts, 448 U.S. 56, 66 (1980). To satisfy that test, evidence had to either fall within a “firmly rooted hearsay exception” or bear “particularized guarantees of trustworthiness.” Id. 26 Crawford, 541 U.S. at 41. 27 Id. 28 FED. R. EVID. 801(c) (“‘Hearsay’ is a statement, other than one made by the declarant while testifying at the trial or hearing, offered in evidence to prove the truth of the matter asserted.”) (adopting the common law definition of hearsay). Michael Crawford was convicted in state court, and hence, the applicable rules of evidence were those of the State of Washington. This Note refers to the Federal Rules to exemplify the law of evidence, and not to imply that they were used at Michael Crawford’s trial. 29 See, e.g., FED. R. EVID. 802 (“Hearsay is not admissible except as provided by these rules or by other rules prescribed by the Supreme Court pursuant to statutory authority or by Act of Congress.”). 30 “[T]he chief goal of the hearsay rule is to enhance the fact-finding process by excluding certain declarations whenever the declarants cannot be subjected to cross22 1636 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 provide for exceptions. In other words, there are situations in which statements, though hearsay, may be admitted nonetheless. 31 These exceptions generally proceed on the notion that some statements, though made out-of-court, are still reliable enough to be valuable as evidence. For example, Rule 804(b)(3) provides that hearsay statements made against the declarant’s interest are admissible. 32 The Rules of Evidence consider statements against interest more reliable than other hearsay because the Rules assume that declarants do not make untruthful statements that are self-incriminating. Sylvia Crawford’s statement was clearly hearsay. It was made out-of-court, and it was offered by the prosecution to prove what it asserted—that Lee did not have a weapon. The court, however, admitted her statement against her husband under Washington’s version of the “statement against interest” exception because, as the argument went, Sylvia implicated herself as an accomplice in the assault, and therefore, she would not have made the statement had it not been true. 33 Accordingly, the court admitted her statement at trial, even though Michael Crawford was unable to cross-examine her. 34 C. The Confrontation Clause The Sixth Amendment’s Confrontation Clause provides criminal defendants with an extra layer of protection against hearsay statements. By guaranteeing the defendant the right to be confronted with the witnesses against him, the Confrontation Clause aims to insure that certain statements, notwithstanding the rules of hearsay, be excluded unless the declarant is cross-examined. Thus, even if a statement fits examination. The rule achieves this goal by permitting the opposing party to object to the use of out-of-court statements that are offered to prove the truth of the matter asserted. Since the use of hearsay can deprive the opponent of an opportunity to challenge the credibility of the hearsay declarant, the rule proceeds on the assumption that cross-examination is vital to assuring the reliability of evidence.” Miguel A. Mendez, Crawford v. Washington: A Critique, 57 STAN. L. REV. 569, 574 (2004). 31 FED. R. EVID. 801(d) (listing statements not included in the definition of hearsay, and thus, not barred by Rule 802), 803 (listing hearsay exceptions that apply even if the declarant is available), 804 (listing hearsay exceptions that apply only if the declarant is unavailable), 807 (providing for the residual exception). 32 FED. R. EVID. 804(b)(3). 33 Crawford, 541 U.S. at 40 (“Noting that Sylvia had admitted she led petitioner to Lee’s apartment and thus had facilitated the assault, the State invoked the hearsay exception for statements against penal interest.”) (citing WASH. R. EVID. 804(b)(3) (2003)). 34 Id. at 40-41. 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1637 within a hearsay exception it will be inadmissible if it runs afoul of the Confrontation Clause. 35 Therefore, insofar as hearsay declarants constitute “witnesses against” a criminal defendant for the purposes of the Confrontation Clause, the Constitution bars admission of the statements. 36 Not all hearsay admitted against a criminal defendant implicates the Confrontation Clause, however, and prior to Crawford the Supreme Court struggled to define exactly what kind of hearsay would trigger the right of confrontation. 37 The Supreme Court first attempted to formulate a workable Confrontation Clause doctrine in Ohio v. Roberts. 38 Roberts articulated a two-part test for the admission of hearsay against the accused, informed by the Court’s pragmatic balancing of society’s interests in law enforcement and finality against an individual’s constitutional right to confrontation. 39 Hearsay was admissible under Roberts if, first, the declarant was unavailable, and second, the hearsay statement bore “indicia of reliability.” 40 If the statement qualified under a “firmly rooted hearsay exception” it was presumptively reliable. 41 Otherwise, a statement could still be admissible if it bore “particularized guarantees of trustworthiness.” 42 In other words, under Roberts, if the declarant was unavailable, and the 35 See, e.g., GEORGE FISHER, FEDERAL RULES OF EVIDENCE STATUTORY AND CASE SUPPLEMENT 394 (2004-05) (“[T]he Constitution is a higher law than the Federal Rules of Evidence, but not necessarily a stricter law. Evidence permitted by the rules of evidence but forbidden by the Confrontation Clause must stay out. Evidence permitted by the Confrontation Clause but excluded by the rules of evidence also must stay out.”). 36 U.S. CONST. amend. VI. 37 See, e.g., FISHER, supra note 35, at 393-94. 38 448 U.S. 56 (1980). Prior to Roberts, “the Court issued a number of ad hoc judgments to resolve particular controversies, but made little attempt to systematize the Confrontation Clause’s impact on the admission of hearsay.” FISHER, supra note 34, at 394. 39 In Roberts, the Court recognized that: [C]ompeting interests, if “closely examined” may warrant dispensing with confrontation at trial. ‘[G]eneral rules of law of this kind, however beneficent in their operation and valuable to the accused, must occasionally give way to considerations of public policy and the necessities of the case.’ Significantly, every jurisdiction has a strong interest in effective law enforcement, and in the development and precise formulation of the rules of evidence applicable in criminal proceedings. Roberts, 448 U.S. at 64 (citations omitted). 40 Id. at 66. 41 Id. 42 Id. 1638 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 statement was deemed reliable, the hearsay was admissible notwithstanding the absence of confrontation. 43 Accordingly, the Washington Supreme Court rejected Michael Crawford’s Confrontation Clause challenge because the court concluded that, under Roberts, Sylvia’s statement bore “guarantees of trustworthiness.” 44 D. Crawford’s Holding On March 8, 2004, however, a unanimous Supreme Court reversed Crawford’s conviction on the grounds that the use of Sylvia Crawford’s statement violated Michael Crawford’s Sixth Amendment right to confront his accusers. 45 Justice Scalia’s majority opinion, joined by six justices, 46 overruled Roberts, 47 and formulated a new standard to govern the admissibility of hearsay statements against a criminal defendant. Under Crawford, the reliability of the statement is irrelevant; the nature of the statement is all that matters. 48 Justice Scalia looked at the text of the Amendment, and determined that the Confrontation Clause concerns only statements made by declarants who bear witness against the accused. Thus, not all hearsay implicates the Constitution, only hearsay statements that are testimonial in nature do. 49 Furthermore, Justice Scalia noted that the Confrontation 43 Id. Crawford v. Washington, 541 U.S. 36, 41 (2004). 45 Id. 46 Justices Stevens, Kennedy, Souter, Thomas, Ginsburg, and Breyer joined Scalia’s majority opinion. Id. at 37. Chief Justice Rehnquist and Justice O’Connor concurred in the reversal, but argued that the result did not require overruling Roberts. Id. at 69. 47 Some lower courts have continued to apply Roberts to non-testimonial statements. See, e.g., Horton v. Allen, 370 F.3d 75, 83-84 (1st Cir. 2004) (noting that unless statements are testimonial “Crawford is inapplicable and Roberts continues to apply”); State v. Rivera, 844 A.2d 191, 200-01 (Conn. 2004) (“nontestimonial hearsay statements may still be admitted as evidence against an accused in a criminal trial if it satisfies both prongs of the Roberts test, irrespective of whether the defendant had a prior opportunity to cross examine the declarant.”). The general consensus, however, is that Roberts no longer has any precedential value. See FISHER, supra note 35, at 431. 48 Crawford, 541 U.S. at 61 (“Admitting statements deemed reliable by a judge is fundamentally at odds with the right of confrontation.”). 49 Id. at 51 (“[N]ot all hearsay implicates the Sixth Amendment’s core concerns. . . . It applies to ‘witnesses’ against the accused—in other words, those who ‘bear testimony.’”) (citing 1 N. WEBSTER, AN AMERICAN DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE (1828)). 44 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1639 Clause does not guarantee reliable evidence; it guarantees a process by which the reliability of evidence is to be judged. 50 Accordingly, the Crawford Court criticized the Roberts test for being both too broad and too narrow. Too broad, argued the Court, because it subjected non-testimonial statements to Constitutional scrutiny, and too narrow because it routinely admitted testimonial statements upon a mere Roberts’s showing of reliability, absent confrontation. 51 “malleable standard,” according to the Court, “often fail[ed] to protect against paradigmatic confrontation violations.” 52 Crawford concluded, therefore, that “[w]here testimonial statements are at issue, the only indicium of reliability sufficient to satisfy constitutional demands is the one the Constitution actually prescribes: confrontation.” 53 Although Justice Scalia and the Crawford Court opted not to define testimonial, 54 clearly, according to the Court, Sylvia Crawford’s statement constituted testimony, and therefore, was barred by the Confrontation Clause. 55 By telling the police that Lee did not have a weapon, and hence did not 50 Id. at 61 (“The Clause thus reflects a judgment, not only about the desirability of reliable evidence (a point on which there could be little dissent), but about how reliability can best be determined.”). 51 Id. at 60 (“First, [the Roberts test] is too broad: It applies the same mode of analysis whether or not the hearsay consists of ex parte testimony. This often results in close constitutional scrutiny in cases that are far removed from the core concerns of the Clause. At the same time, however, the test is too narrow: It admits statements that do consist of ex parte testimony upon a mere finding of reliability.”). 52 Id. 53 Crawford, 541 U.S. at 68-69 (2004) (emphasis added). 54 Id. at 68 (“We leave for another day any effort to spell out a comprehensive definition of ‘testimonial.’”). The Court did, however, offer the following three possible standards, but opts not to chose among them: 1) “‘[E]x parte in-court testimony or its functional equivalent—that is, material such as affidavits, custodial examinations, prior testimony that the defendant was unable to cross-examine, or similar pretrial statements that declarants would reasonably expect to be used prosecutorially’”; 2) “‘[E]xtrajudicial statements . . . contained in formalized testimonial materials, such as affidavits, depositions, prior testimony, or confessions’”; and 3) “‘[S]tatements that were made under circumstances which would lead an objective witness reasonably to believe that the statement would be available for use at a later trial.” Id. at 51-52 (citations omitted). 55 Id. at 68 (“Whatever else the term covers, it applies at a minimum to prior testimony at a preliminary hearing, before a grand jury, or at a former trial; and to police interrogations. These are the modern practices with closest kinship to the abuses at which the Confrontation Clause was directed.”). 1640 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 pose a threat to Michael Crawford, Sylvia Crawford bore witness, or testified, against her husband. Because Sylvia Crawford did not appear at trial, Michael Crawford could not cross-examine her regarding her testimony. Thus, admitting Sylvia’s statement as incriminating evidence against Michael Crawford constituted a paradigmatic Confrontation Clause violation. In summary, with Crawford, “the U.S. Supreme Court radically transformed its doctrine governing the Confrontation Clause of the Sixth Amendment to the U.S. Constitution.” 56 One commentator described the case as “a very positive development, restoring to its central position one of the basic protections of the common law system of criminal justice.” 57 Crawford, however, left many questions unanswered. 58 One such question is whether or not Crawford’s radical transformation 59 of Confrontation Clause interpretation should be applied retroactively to cases on collateral review. 60 In other words, will a defendant with a final conviction based on hearsay evidence admissible under Roberts yet inadmissible under Crawford be able to attack his conviction on collateral review alleging a Crawford violation? Although the Supreme Court has made retroactivity difficult to achieve, 61 certainly a rule that drastically reinterprets 62 a Constitutional guarantee as important 63 as the Confrontation Clause should suffice. III. THE TEAGUE FRAMEWORK FOR RETROACTIVITY ANALYSIS To resolve the question of retroactivity, one must analyze Crawford’s rule under the framework provided by Teague v. Lane. 64 Decided in 1989, Teague articulated the 56 Richard D. Friedman, Adjusting to Crawford: High Court Decision Restores Confrontation Clause Protection, 19 CRIM. JUST. 5 (Summer 2004). 57 Id. 58 Id.; see Mosteller, supra note 7, at 623 (“Crawford leaves many important issues undecided regarding the scope of its application.”). 59 Mosteller, supra note 7, at 511. 60 Richard Alan Ginkowski, Introduction to Friedman, supra note 56, at 5 (“Also unclear is whether the holding may be applied retroactively.”). 61 See supra notes 11-12 and accompanying text. 62 See supra note 7. 63 See supra notes 2-5. 64 489 U.S. 288 (1989). The Teague standard only governs if direct appeal has been completed. New rules apply retroactively to all criminal cases still pending on direct appeal. Schriro v. Summerlin, 542 U.S. 348, 358 (2004); Griffith v. Kentucky, 479 U.S. 314, 328 (1987). 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1641 current governing standard by which retroactivity is to be determined. 65 A. “New” or “Old”? The threshold question under Teague is whether the rule at issue is “new” or “old.” 66 Essentially, “a case announces a new rule when it breaks new ground or imposes a new obligation on the States or the Federal Government,” 67 or “if the result was not dictated by precedent existing at the time the defendant’s conviction became final.” 68 In contrast, a rule is “old” for retroactivity purposes if it is a mere application of In Butler v. McKellar the Court existing precedent. 69 expounded further on the Teague definition of a “new rule,” concluding that a rule is “new” if reasonable minds could have differed about the result of the decision before it was rendered. 70 The great weight of the authority suggests that Crawford announced a “new” rule. 71 Accordingly, this Note treats Crawford’s rule as “new” for the purposes of its analysis. 72 “New” rules trigger Teague scrutiny. 65 LAFAVE, supra note 9, at 1355-61. Teague, 489 U.S. at 301; see also People v. Eastman, 648 N.E.2d 459, 464 (N.Y. 1995) (“The threshold issue in determining whether to apply a constitutional rule retroactively is characterization of the rule as “new” or “old.”). 67 Teague, 489 U.S. at 301 (citing Rock v. Arkansas, 483 U.S. 44, 62 (1987)). 68 Id. (citing Truesdale v. Aiken, 480 U.S. 527, 528-29 (1987) (Powell, J., dissenting)). 69 Id. 70 494 U.S. 407, 417 (1990). 71 Dorchy v. Jones, 398 F.3d 783, 788 (6th Cir. 2005) (“Teague thus prohibits Dorchy from availing himself of the new rule articulated in Crawford.”); Bintz v. Bertrand, 403 F.3d 859, 866-67 (7th Cir. 2005) (“It seems clear that Crawford was a clean break from the line of precedent established by Roberts. Crawford considered and rejected the continuing application of Roberts. . . . Crawford was thus a new rule for purposes of Teague.”); Murillo v. Frank, 402 F.3d 786, 790 (7th Cir. 2005) (“It is obvious to us . . . that Crawford establishes a new rule.”); Bockting v. Bayer, 399 F.3d 1010, 1015-16 (9th Cir. 2005) (“On balance, an analysis of the historical application of the Confrontation Clause cases leads to the conclusion that Crawford announces a new rule . . . .”); Brown v. Uphoff, 381 F.3d 1219, 1226 (10th Cir. 2004) (“Thus, Roberts and its progeny did not dictate the result in Crawford and we conclude that it announces a new rule of constitutional law.”); Mungo v. Duncan, 393 F.3d 327, 335 (2d Cir. 2004) (assuming for the purposes of Teague analysis that Crawford announced a new rule); see also Evans v. Luebbers, 371 F.3d 438, 444-45 (8th Cir. 2004) (applying, in dictum, Teague’s “new rule” framework to the Crawford rule). 72 Some have argued that Crawford announced an “old” rule. For interesting arguments, see Bockting v. Bayer, 399 F.3d 1010, 1023 (9th Cir. 2005) (Noonan, J., concurring) (“Crawford, therefore, does not announce a new rule. Retroactivity is not an issue.”); Murillo v. Frank, 316 F. Supp. 2d 744, 749-50 n.4 (E.D. Wisc. 2004) (“The question is close because although Crawford rejected the application of Roberts to 66 1642 B. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Teague’s “New” Rule Framework Essentially, Teague established a presumptive bar to the retroactive application of “new” rules on collateral review, subject to two exceptions. The first exception allows for retroactivity if the conduct for which the defendant was convicted has become constitutionally protected, and the second, if the “new” rule is a watershed rule of criminal procedure, implicit in the concept of ordered liberty. 73 The first exception certainly does not apply to Crawford since Crawford’s rule does not concern conduct. Therefore, if deemed a “new” rule, Crawford’s retroactivity hinges on whether it fits within the contours of the second exception. In other words, to warrant retroactivity Crawford’s rule must be deemed a watershed rule of criminal procedure implicit in the concept of ordered liberty. C. Teague’s Second Exception as Interpreted by Subsequent Cases Teague’s second exception is decidedly difficult to satisfy. In fact, the exception has grown “exceedingly narrow,” 74 including only a “small core of rules requiring observance of those procedures that . . . are implicit in the concept of ordered liberty.” 75 Indeed, “it is not enough that a new rule is aimed at improving the accuracy of trial, or even testimonial statements, the Court had never explicitly applied Roberts to such statements.’ Thus, it can be argued that Crawford did not announce a new rule at all.”) (citation omitted); Richardson v. Newland, 342 F. Supp. 2d 900, 924 (E.D. Cal. 2004) (“Crawford did not announce a new rule at all but rather is entirely faithful to the Supreme Court’s prior decisions in this area”). If a rule is deemed “old” it is applied retroactively to all cases on collateral review. See Yates v. Aiken, 484 U.S. 211, 216 n.3 (1988) (“[W]hen a decision of this Court merely has applied settled precedents to new and different factual situations, no real question has arisen as to whether the later decision should apply retrospectively.”). Accordingly, only “new” rules are subject to analysis under the Teague exceptions. 73 The standard adopted by Teague originated with Justice Harlan. Justice Harlan, however, advocated a more lenient second exception. Under Justice Harlan’s standard a new rule would be retroactive if the previous rule created “an impermissibly large risk that the innocent will be convicted.” Desist v. United States, 394 U.S. 244, 262 (1969). Thus, according to Justice Harlan “all ‘new’ constitutional rules which significantly improve the pre-existing fact-finding procedures are to be retroactively applied on habeas.” Id. Teague, however, narrowed the second exception, requiring a rule to be a watershed rule of criminal procedure. 74 United States v. Mandanici, 205 F.3d 519, 528 (2d Cir. 2000). 75 Beard v. Banks, 542 U.S. 406, 417 (2004) (quoting Graham v. Collins, 506 U.S. 461, 478 (1993)). 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1643 that it promotes the objectives of fairness and accuracy.” 76 But the adoption of a “new” rule must be a “ground breaking occurrence,” 77 and one that “alter[s] our understanding of the bedrock procedural elements essential to the fairness of a proceeding.” 78 Moreover, the rule must signal “a sweeping change that applies to a large swathe of cases rather than a narrow right that applies only to a limited class of cases.” 79 Notwithstanding the narrowness of Teague’s second exception, however, it must exist for a reason. Therefore, certain rules, like Crawford, must be capable of fitting within its narrow contours. 80 Since Teague was decided in 1989 the Supreme Court has considered twelve “new” rules for retroactive application and has found them all insufficient. 81 The Court recently noted that “it should come as no surprise that [it] ha[s] yet to find a new rule that falls under the second Teague exception.” 82 Additionally, the Supreme Court has declared several times that to achieve “watershed” status a new rule must compare, in terms of significance, with the rule espoused in Gideon v. Wainwright, 83 which confered the right of counsel on indigent defendants. 84 Thus, when the Court considers a “new” rule as a candidate for retroactivity, the Court compares the importance of the new rule to that of Gideon’s rule. 85 No “new” rule has yet prevailed under this analysis. 86 None considered, 76 Mandanici, 205 F.3d at 528 (citation and internal quotations omitted). Caspari v. Bohlen, 510 U.S. 383, 396 (1994). 78 Sawyer v. Smith, 497 U.S. 227, 241-42 (1990) (quoting Mackey v. United States, 401 U.S. 667, 693 (1971)). 79 Mandanici, 205 F.3d at 528 (citation and internal quotations omitted). 80 Bockting v. Bayer, 399 F.3d 1010, 1016 (9th Cir. 2005) (“[T]he bar is not absolute and the Crawford rule meets the Court’s criteria.”). 81 See Mandanici, 205 F.3d at 529 (“[Since 1989, b]eginning with the rule at issue in Teague, the Court has measured at least eleven new rules, or proposed new rules, of criminal procedure against the criteria for the second Teague exception and, in every case, has refused to apply the rule at issue retroactively on habeas review.”). Moreover, since Mandanici the Supreme Court has extended that streak by two, failing to apply the second Teague exception in two more cases. Schriro v. Summerlin, 542 U.S. 348, 355-58; Beard v. Banks, 542 U.S. 406, 419-20 (2004). 82 Beard, 542 U.S. at 417. 83 372 U.S. 335 (1963). 84 Saffle v. Parks, 494 U.S. 484, 495 (1990); see Beard, 542 U.S. at 417. 85 See Gray v. Netherland, 518 U.S. 152, 170 (1996); Saffle, 494 U.S. at 495 (stating that a rule must be of the “primacy and centrality of the rule adopted in Gideon or other rules which may be thought to be within the exception”); Mandanici, 205 F.3d at 528-29 (citing O’Dell v. Netherland, 521 U.S. 151, 167 (1997)). 86 See supra note 12. 77 1644 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW however, has Crawford. 87 IV. carried the constitutional [Vol. 71:4 significance of CRAWFORD IS A WATERSHED RULE OF CRIMINAL PROCEDURE ESSENTIAL TO FUNDAMENTAL FAIRNESS, AND THUS, SHOULD BE MADE RETROACTIVE PURSUANT TO TEAGUE’S SECOND EXCEPTION Since the Supreme Court decided Teague it has not addressed the retroactivity of a “new” rule concerning the Confrontation Clause. Authority suggests, however, that Crawford satisfies Teague’s strictures. Although the Supreme Court, under the Teague standard, has not made a “new” rule retroactive, every rule considered lacked the significance of Crawford’s rule. 88 Indeed, Crawford is more akin to the Gideon rule 89 than any rule that has sought retroactivity before the Court. Moreover, in both Roberts v. Russell 90 and Barber v. Page 91 the Supreme Court gave retroactive effect to a rule implicating the Confrontation Clause. Although these decisions predate Teague, they demonstrate that the public interests that weigh against retroactivity must yield when they conflict with the right of confrontation. 92 Additionally, the Supreme Court’s holding in Cruz v. New York 93 also implicated the Confrontation Clause, 94 and was made retroactive by both the New York Court of Appeals 95 and the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit. 96 Both courts conducted retroactivity analysis under the Teague framework. 97 87 See infra Part IV.A (arguing that Crawford is more significant that the other rules considered for retroactivity under Teague); see also supra note 12. 88 See supra note 89 and accompanying text. 89 Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U.S. 335, 344-45 (1963) (conferring the right of counsel on indigent defendants). 90 392 U.S. 293, 294 (1968) (giving retroactive effect to Bruton v. United States, 391 U.S. 123 (1968), which prohibited the admission, at a joint trial, of a codefendant’s inculpatory extrajudicial confession). 91 390 U.S. 719 (1968). 92 Id. at 294-95. 93 481 U.S. 186, 193 (1987) (barring admission of an interlocking confession of a non-testifying defendant). 94 Id. 95 People v. Eastman, 648 N.E.2d 459, 460 (N.Y. 1995). 96 Graham v. Hoke, 946 F.2d 982, 993 (2d Cir. 1991). 97 See id.; Eastman, 648 N.E.2d at 464-65. 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1645 Accordingly, if ever there could be a rule capable of satisfying Teague’s second exception, surely Crawford, giving new life to an essential and fundamental constitutional guarantee, 98 should be it. A. Crawford is More Significant Than All the Previous “New” Rules That the Supreme Court has Declined to Apply Retroactively The Supreme Court has contemplated the retroactive application of a “new” rule twelve 99 times, and each time determined that the rule at issue failed to satisfy the requirements of Teague’s second exception. 100 None of those rules, however, implicated the Confrontation Clause. The Crawford rule, according to the Supreme Court, corrects an “unpardonable [constitutional] vice.” 101 Crawford is exactly the kind of rule contemplated by the second Teague exception. Indeed, Crawford has “the primacy and centrality of the rule adopted in Gideon,” 102 and must succeed where the others have failed. Of the twelve “new” rules that have failed under Teague, nine concern sentencing, and hence, bear only 98 See discussion supra Parts I, II. Teague itself, while formulating the retroactivity standard, considered the retroactivity of the rule announced in Batson v. Kentucky, 476 U.S. 79 (1986). In Batson the Court held that if a defendant can establish a prima facie case that the prosecutor used peremptory challenges to eliminate members of the jury venire that were of the defendant’s race, the burden shifts to the prosecutor to rebut the inference of discrimination. The prosecutor may rebut the inference of discrimination by showing a neutral reason for challenging the jurors, but if he cannot, the peremptory challenges constitute an Equal Protection violation. Id. at 96-97. The petitioner in Teague sought the benefit of Batson “even though his conviction became final before Batson was decided.” Teague v. Lane, 489 U.S. 288, 294 (1989). Before Teague, however, the Supreme Court in Allen v. Hardy, 478 U.S. 255 (1986), applying the pre-Teague retroactivity standard of Linkletter v. Walker, 381 U.S. 618, 636 (1965), found that Batson was not retroactive. Teague found Allen v. Hardy “dispositive,” and hence, denied the petitioner the benefit of Batson. Teague, 489 U.S. at 296. Accordingly, Teague did not apply the standard it enunciated to the Batson rule, it deferred to Allen v. Hardy’s evaluation of Batson under the then-governing Linkletter standard. Therefore, this Note does not address Teague’s holding with respect to the retroactivity of Batson. 100 See supra note 12; see also Schriro v. Summerlin, 542 U.S. 348, 355-58 (2004) (declining to make a new rule retroactive); Beard v. Banks, 542 U.S. 406, 419-20 (2004) (same). 101 Crawford v. Washington, 541 U.S. 36, 63 (2004). 102 Saffle v. Parks, 494 U.S. 484, 495 (1990). 99 1646 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 tangentially on the accuracy of the trial. 103 These sentencing rules are fundamentally different from, and less important to the truth-finding function than the Crawford rule. Most significantly, sentencing rules affect only the portion of the trial subsequent to the verdict. While the severity of a criminal defendant’s sentence is substantially important to the criminal justice system, Teague requires “new” rules to impact guilt or 103 First, in Schriro, the Supreme Court declined to give retroactive effect to the rule announce in Ring v. Arizona, 536 U.S. 584 (2002). Schriro, 542 U.S. at 355-58. Ring declared that the existence of an aggravating factor which could make a defendant eligible for the death sentence must be proved to a jury rather than a trial judge. 536 U.S. at 609. The defendant in Schriro was sentenced to death under the previous rule, which allowed the trial judge, rather than the jury, to determine the presence of the aggravating factor. 542 U.S. at 350. The defendant, Summerlin, sought the benefit of the Ring rule on habeas review, and his request was denied by a five to four decision of the Supreme Court. Id. at 350, 358. The next two cases, Beard v. Banks, 542 U.S. 406 (2004), and Graham v. Collins, 506 U.S. 461 (1993), the Supreme Court contemplated the retroactivity of “new” rules concerning the ability of the jury to consider mitigating factors in capital sentencing proceedings. In Beard the Supreme Court examined the “new” rule of Mills v. Maryland, 486 U.S. 367 (1988) which declared invalid capital sentencing schemes requiring juries to disregard mitigating factors not found unanimously. Id. at 375. Graham dealt with a proposed rule declaring as unconstitutional jury instructions which disallowed sentencing juries to consider mitigating evidence. 506 U.S. at 464. Both rules fell short of the Teague standard. Beard, 542 U.S. at 419-20; Graham, 506 U.S. at 463. Fourth, in O’Dell v. Netherland, 521 U.S. 151 (1997), the Court held that the rule of Simmons v. South Carolina, 512 U.S. 154 (1994), which entitles a capital defendant to inform his sentencing jury that he is parole-ineligible if the prosecution claims that he is a future danger, id. at 161-62, failed under Teague analysis. O’Dell, 521 U.S. at 167. Fifth, the rule announced in Espinosa v. Florida, 505 U.S. 1079 (1992) (per curiam), also failed under Teague to achieve retroactive application as a “new” rule. Mandanici, 205 F.3d at 529. Espinosa declared “that in certain states where a sentencing judge is required to give deference to a jury’s advisory sentencing recommendation with respect to the death penalty, neither the jury nor the judge is permitted to consider invalid aggravating circumstances.” Id. Sixth, Gray v. Netherland, 518 U.S. 152 (1996), declined to make retroactive a rule that the state’s failure to give adequate notice of some of the evidence it intended to use in the petitioners’ capital sentence proceeding violated due process. Id. at 170. Seventh, Caspari v. Bohlen, 510 U.S. 383, 386, 396 (1994), declined to make retroactive a rule declaring that “twice subject[ing] a criminal defendant to a noncapital sentence enhancement proceeding” violated the Double Jeopardy Clause. Eighth, Saffle, declined to apply retroactively a rule that the trial court’s instruction in the petitioner’s capital sentencing proceeding, “telling the jury to avoid any influence of sympathy, violates the Eighth Amendment.” 494 U.S. at 486. Ninth, Sawyer v. Smith, 497 U.S. 227 (1990), subjected the rule of Caldwell v. Mississippi, 472 U.S. 320 (1985) to Teague analysis, and like the others, the rule failed to satisfy Teague’s strict requirements. Sawyer, 497 U.S. at 241-45. Caldwell’s rule “prohibits the imposition of a death sentence by a sentencer that has been led to the false belief that the responsibility for determining the appropriateness of the defendant’s capital sentence lies elsewhere.” Id. at 233 (citing Caldwell, 472 U.S. at 328-29). 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1647 innocence to warrant retroactivity. 104 Therefore, even a “new” rule of sentencing impacting the imposition of the death penalty—the harshest sentence available—will likely fail under Teague, because sentencing rules simply do not concern the determination of guilt or innocence. 105 In contrast, the Crawford rule interprets the right of confrontation, which is necessary to ferret out truth from an accuser’s testimony. Crawford bears directly on the kind of information that reaches the jury, and it goes to the very heart of the truth-finding process. A rule that implicates the accuracy of the truth-finding process certainly has the likely potential to impact guilt or innocence, as required by Teague. Accordingly, Crawford comports with Teague’s vision of a retroactive rule, while rules concerning sentencing do not. Of the “new” rule retroactivity candidates that did not concern sentencing, none were as important as Crawford. First, in Goeke v. Branch the Supreme Court refused to apply retroactively a rule that prohibited state appellate courts from dismissing the appeal of a recaptured fugitive. 106 The Court aptly observed that since “due process does not require a State to provide appellate process at all, a former fugitive’s right to appeal cannot be said to be so central to an accurate determination of innocence or guilt as to fall within [the second] exception to the Teague bar.” 107 On the contrary, the Constitution guarantees the right of confrontation, and the Supreme Court has incorporated it through the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to apply to the states. 108 Therefore, since Crawford implicates a fundamental constitutional guarantee, it deserves retroactivity more than a rule concerning a non-constitutional right to appeal. 104 Teague v. Lane, 489 U.S. 288, 313 (1989) (“Because we operate from the premise that such procedures would be so central to an accurate determination of innocence or guilt, we believe it unlikely that many such components of basic due process have yet to emerge.”). 105 Id. Since the petitioner in Teague was not under a sentence of death the plurality limited its holding to the non-capital context. The plurality, however, explicitly confirmed that the finality concerns that drove its analysis applied also in the capital context. Id. at 314 n.2. 106 Goeke v. Branch, 514 U.S. 115, 120-21 (1995) (per curiam). 107 Id. at 120 (internal citations and quotation marks omitted). 108 Pointer v. Texas, 380 U.S. 400, 403 (1965) (“We hold today that the Sixth Amendment’s right of an accused to confront the witnesses against him is likewise a fundamental right and is made obligatory on the States by the Fourteenth Amendment.”). 1648 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Gilmore v. Taylor 109 considered the retroactive application of the rule announced in Falconer v. Lane, 110 and the Court again decided that the “new” rule failed to satisfy Teague’s strictures. 111 Falconer declared that “the failure to instruct a jury that it could not return a murder conviction if it found that the defendant possessed a mitigating mental state violates due process.” 112 A jury considers a mitigating mental state, however, only after it finds the facts constituting the underlying offense. Thus, the Falconer rule bears on culpability, not the accuracy of the facts. The Crawford rule, on the other hand, concerns the accuracy of the underlying facts. Crawford provides the jury greater access to information, which significantly increases the likelihood that the jury will arrive at an accurate decision. Butler v. McKellar 113 declined to make retroactive the rule announced in Arizona v. Roberson, 114 which had declared that “the Fifth Amendment bars police-initiated interrogation following a suspect’s request for counsel in the context of a separate investigation.” 115 Butler concluded that “[b]ecause a violation of Roberson’s added restrictions on police investigatory procedures would not seriously diminish the likelihood of obtaining an accurate determination – indeed, it may increase that likelihood – . . . Roberson did not establish any principle that would come within the second exception.” 116 Apparently, the Butler majority operated from the premise that a confession obtained in violation of the Fifth Amendment may be truthful nonetheless, and hence, its admission at trial may in fact conduce to a more accurate fact-finding process. 117 To be sure, the Fifth Amendment’s right not to self-incriminate enjoys comparable constitutional stature to the right to confront one’s accusers; however, the former aims to preserve the individual suspect’s dignity, while the latter aims to insure 109 508 U.S. 333 (1993). 905 F.2d 1129 (7th Cir. 1990). 111 Gilmore, 508 U.S. at 345 (holding that the Falconer rule does not “fall[] into that small core of rules requiring observance of those procedures that . . . are implicit in the concept of ordered liberty”) (internal citations and quotation marks omitted). 112 United States v. Mandanici, 205 F.3d 519, 529 (2d Cir. 2000) (summarizing the Falconer rule). 113 494 U.S. 407 (1990). 114 486 U.S. 675 (1988). 115 Butler, 494 U.S. at 411 (citing Roberson, 486 U.S. at 682). 116 Id. at 416. 117 Id. 110 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1649 the accuracy of the trial. Accordingly, since Teague insists that a retroactive rule impact the determination of innocence or guilt, 118 Crawford is a better candidate for retroactivity than Roberson. The Supreme Court has invoked Gideon v. Wainwright, which conferred the right to counsel upon indigent defendants, 119 to exemplify the type of case capable of satisfying Teague’s second exception. 120 Crawford is of Gideon’s ilk. Gideon declared that a fair trial “cannot be realized if the poor man charged with a crime has to face his accusers without a lawyer to assist him.” 121 One might naturally doubt the utility of a lawyer, however, without the right to face one’s accusers. Skilled lawyers and pro se litigants alike would be unable to mount a defense without the ability to confront adverse witnesses. For example, Michael Crawford was represented by counsel, yet his lawyer was not allowed to cross-examine Sylvia. Had he been extended this “privilege,” he may have inquired as to her vantage point during the incident. In turn she may have replied, truthfully in fact, that her eyes were closed. 122 Indeed, a lawyer is often essential to the fairness of a proceeding, but before a lawyer can be effective the proceeding must comport with Crawford, allowing the defendant to confront testimonial statements. In other words, the right of confrontation preserves and gives content to the right to counsel. Accordingly, since the Court uses Gideon as its retroactivity benchmark, and since Crawford is just as, if not more, important to fairness and trial accuracy, Crawford must be made retroactive. 123 118 See supra note 104 and accompanying text. 372 U.S. 335, 344 (1963). 120 Saffle v. Parks, 494 U.S. 484, 495 (1990) (“Although the precise contours of [the second Teague] exception may be difficult to discern, [the Court] ha[s] usually cited Gideon v. Wainwright, holding that a defendant has the right to be represented by counsel . . . to illustrate the type of rule coming within the exception.” (citation omitted)). 121 372 U.S. at 344 (emphasis added). 122 State v. Crawford, No. 25307-1-II, 2001 WL 850119, at *5 (Wash. App. Div. 2, July 30, 2001), rev’d, 54 P.3d 656 (Wash. 2002), rev’d sub nom., Crawford, 541 U.S. 36 (“Sylvia stated that she shut her eyes during the stabbing. Cross-examination could show that she did not see Lee attack Michael because of this. We conclude that crossexamination could reveal that she lacked knowledge of what happened.”). 123 See Bockting v. Bayer, 399 F.3d 1010, 1019 (9th Cir. 2005) (“Recognizing that bedrock procedural rules are very few in number, it is no leap to conclude that the right of cross-examination as an adjunct to the constitutional right of confrontation joins the very limited company of Gideon.”). 119 1650 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 To be sure, Teague and its progeny make it quite difficult for a “new” rule to achieve retroactive effect. The twelve “new” rules that the Supreme Court has declined to make retroactive exemplify the narrowness of the Teague standard. Nevertheless, no rule as significant as Crawford has yet endured Teague’s scrutiny. The second Teague exception exists so that rules of the magnitude of Gideon and Crawford can achieve retroactive effect, while rules like the ones which hitherto have failed will not upset society’s countervailing interests. The second Teague exception is narrow, but not closed, and Crawford satisfies its requirements. 124 B. The Supreme Court’s Language in Crawford Indicates That the Confrontation Clause is a Bedrock Constitutional Guarantee Essential to a Fair Trial The Supreme Court’s language in the Crawford opinion suggests that its rule is important enough to prevail under a Teague retroactivity analysis. 125 In Crawford, the Supreme Court expressly stated its view that the right of confrontation is a “bedrock procedural guarantee,” 126 and that Roberts constituted an egregious constitutional flaw. Although none of the Court’s language speaks specifically to the retroactivity issue, one can reasonably infer from the Court’s language that Crawford warrants retroactivity. Justice Scalia consulted history, and determined that “the principal evil at which the Confrontation Clause was directed was the civil-law mode of criminal procedure, and particularly its use of ex parte examinations as evidence against the accused.” 127 Moreover, the Court declared that the 124 See, e.g., Valladares, supra note 7, at 12, 16 (“There is a strong argument that Crawford is one of those very rare new rules that is essential to our concepts of fundamental fairness.”). 125 See Bockting, 399 F.3d at 1016 (“That the Crawford requirement is fundamental to our legal regime is beyond dispute. Justice Scalia’s eloquent recitation of the history, purpose, and place of the Confrontation Clause and cross-examination answers this question.”); People v. Watson, No. 7715/90, 2004 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 2133, at *8 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Nov. 8, 2004) (“The language used in the Crawford decision itself also lends support to the view that its declaration of the rule prohibiting the admission of testimonial statements at trial unless they have been subject to cross-examination is watershed.”). 126 Crawford v. Washington, 541 U.S. 36, 42 (2004). 127 Id. at 50 (emphasis added). In particular, Justice Scalia recounted the 1603 treason trial of Sir Walter Raleigh. Raleigh’s alleged accomplice, Lord Cobham, implicated Raleigh in letters. Cobham did not testify, but his letters were read at Raleigh’s trial. According to Justice Scalia, 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1651 right of confrontation is the Sixth Amendment’s “primary object,” 128 and deemed the right a “categorical constitutional guarantee[].” 129 Additionally, the Roberts framework, according to Crawford, was “fundamentally at odds” with the Confrontation Clause 130 and hence, “[did] violence to [its] design.” 131 While Roberts admitted hearsay based on notions of reliability, 132 Crawford declared that the only constitutionally permissible method by which to determine reliability is “testing in the crucible of cross-examination.” 133 Indeed, the Court notes that Michael Crawford’s conviction under Roberts “reveal[ed] a fundamental failure on [the Court’s] part to interpret the Constitution in a way that secures its intended constraint on judicial discretion.” 134 Although Crawford did not contemplate retroactivity, it couched its holding in strong, unequivocal language, intimating that its rule should satisfy Teague. Indeed, to hold otherwise would render Crawford’s language meaningless rhetoric. C. Two Supreme Court Cases, Though Predating Teague, Dictate That Crawford Should Be Retroactive In two cases, Roberts v. Russell 135 and Berger v. California, 136 the Court deemed rules implicating the Confrontation Clause retroactive. Although both cases predate Raleigh argued that Cobham had lied to save himself: “Cobham is absolutely in the King’s mercy; to excuse me cannot avail him; by accusing me he may hope for favor.” Suspecting that Cobham would recant, Raleigh demanded that the judges call him to appear, arguing that “[t]he Proof of the Common Law is by witness and jury: let Cobham be here, let him speak it. Call my accuser before my face . . . .” The Judges refused, and, despite Raleigh’s protestations that he was being tried “by the Spanish Inquisition,” the jury convicted, and Raleigh was sentenced to death. Id. at 44 (internal citations omitted). Justice Scalia then noted, “[O]ne of Raleigh’s trial judges later lamented that ‘the justice of England has never been so degraded and injured as by the condemnation of Sir Walter Raleigh.’” Id. 128 129 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 Id. at 53. Id. at 67-68. Id. at 61. Id. at 68. See supra Part II (discussing the Roberts framework). Crawford v. Washington, 541 U.S. 36, 61 (2004). Id. at 67. 392 U.S. 293 (1968). 393 U.S. 314 (1969). 1652 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Teague, they are persuasive evidence of the high regard in which the Court holds the Confrontation Clause. 1. Bruton v. United States Bruton v. United States 137 concerned Bruton, who had been convicted of robbery. 138 He was tried jointly with his alleged accomplice, Evans. 139 Evans did not testify at the trial, but the prosecution introduced his oral confession, which incriminated Bruton. 140 Bruton challenged his conviction, claiming that the trial judge erred by admitting Evans’s confession in violation of his, Bruton’s, confrontation right. 141 The Eighth Circuit Court of Appeals, however, applying Delli Paoli v. United States, 142 upheld Bruton’s conviction because the trial judge instructed the jury not to consider Evans’s confession when determining Bruton’s guilt. 143 On appeal, the Supreme Court overruled Delli Paoli, and reversed the Eighth Circuit, holding that “despite instructions to the jury to disregard the implicating statements in determining the codefendant’s guilt or innocence, admission at a joint trial of a 137 391 U.S. 123 (1968). Id. at 124. 139 Id. 140 Id. 141 Id. Evans also challenged his conviction and prevailed after the Circuit Court held that Evans’s confession was obtained in violation of the recently decided Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966). Bruton, 391 U.S. at 124, n.1. 142 352 U.S. 232 (1957). Delli Paoli allowed a codefendant’s confession to be admitted at a joint trial if the judge gave limiting instructions. Id. at 239. 143 Bruton, 391 U.S. at 124-25. The trial judge instructed the jury as follows: 138 A confession made outside of court by one defendant may not be considered as evidence against the other defendant, who was not present and in no way a party to the confession. Therefore, if you find that a confession was in fact voluntarily and intentionally made by the defendant Evans, you should consider it as evidence in the case against Evans, but you must not consider it, and should disregard it, in considering the evidence in the case against the defendant Bruton. .... It is your duty to give separate, personal consideration to the cause of each individual defendant. When you do so, you should analyze what the evidence shows with respect to that individual, leaving out of consideration entirely any evidence admitted solely against some other defendant. Each defendant is entitled to have his case determined from his own acts and statements and the other evidence in the case which may be applicable to him.” Id. at 125 n.2 (quoting Evans v. United States, 375 F.2d 355, 362 n.6 (1967), rev’d sub nom., Bruton, 391 U.S. 123) (alteration in original). 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1653 defendant’s extra-judicial confession implicating a codefendant violated the codefendant’s right of cross-examination.” 144 In Roberts v. Russell 145 the Supreme Court applied the Bruton rule retroactively. The Russell Court held that “the error” from Delli Paoli in admitting such statements “‘went to the basis of fair hearing and trial because the procedural apparatus never assured the [petitioner] a fair determination’ With “[d]ue regard for of his guilt or innocence.” 146 countervailing considerations,” the Russell Court concluded that “even if the impact of retroactivity may be significant, the constitutional error presents a serious risk that the issue of guilt or innocence may not have been reliably determined.” 147 Accordingly, the Court determined that the Bruton rule must apply retroactively to cases on collateral review. 148 Although Russell was decided in 1968, twenty-one years before Teague narrowed the scope of habeas review, its holding remains significant even after Teague. Teague relied heavily on the importance of finality and the administration of The Russell Court clearly considered these justice. 149 “countervailing” 150 interests yet concluded that “the impact of retroactivity upon the administration of justice [did] not counsel against retroactivity of Bruton. The element of reliance [was] not persuasive . . . .” 151 Moreover, Teague’s primary departure from existing retroactivity doctrine was the second prong of its second 144 Roberts v. Russell, 392 U.S. 293, 294 (1969). 392 U.S. 293. 146 Id. at 294 (alteration in original) (quoting Linkletter v. Walker, 381 U.S. 618, 639 n.20 (1965)). The Bruton Court elaborated: 145 [T]here are some contexts in which the risk that the jury will not, or cannot, follow instructions is so great, and the consequences of failure so vital to the defendant, that the practical and human limitations of the jury system cannot be ignored. Such a context is presented here, where the powerfully incriminating extrajudicial statements of a codefendant . . . are deliberately spread before the jury in a joint trial. Bruton, 391 U.S. at 135-36 (citations omitted). 147 Russell, 392 U.S. at 295 (emphasis added). 148 Id. 149 Teague v. Lane, 489 U.S. 288, 309 (1989) (“Application of constitutional rules not in existence at the time a conviction became final seriously undermines the principle of finality which is essential to the operation of our criminal justice system.”). 150 Russell, 392 U.S. at 295. 151 Id. (citation omitted) (“Due regard for countervailing considerations— reliance on the old standard of Delli Paoli and the impact of retroactivity upon the administration of justice—does not counsel against retroactivity of Bruton. The element of reliance is not persuasive . . . .” (citation omitted)). 1654 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 exception, 152 which requires a new rule to be “watershed” and to “implicate the fundamental fairness of the trial.” 153 Indeed, Russell, though not constitutionally required to do so (as Teague had not yet imposed the obligation), contemplated this aspect of the Bruton rule, and predicated its holding of retroactivity on the belief that to deny the benefit of the rule would “present[] a serious risk that the issue of guilt or innocence may not have been reliably determined.” 154 Additionally, the Russell Court likened the Bruton rule of Confrontation Clause interpretation to the rule of Gideon v. Wainwright. 155 Courts have often refused to hold “new” rules retroactive because the Supreme Court instructs that a new rule must be comparable to the Gideon rule to warrant retroactivity. 156 Russell cited Gideon to support its proposition that the Supreme Court has “retroactively applied rules of criminal procedure fashioned to correct flaws in the fact-finding process at trial.” 157 Relying on Gideon as authority indicates that the Court believed the right of confrontation to be tantamount to the right to counsel. It thus seems very reasonable to conclude that the Russell analysis, though not controlled by Teague, was just as demanding, and that even under the Teague standard the Russell Court would have applied Bruton retroactively. Since Crawford’s rule is similar to Bruton’s, Crawford deserves equal consideration when subjected to retroactivity analysis. 2. Barber v. Page Likewise, the Supreme Court applied Barber v. Page 158 retroactively in Berger v. California. 159 Barber v. Page declared 152 See supra note 74. Teague, 489 U.S. at 311, 312. 154 Russell, 392 U.S. at 295. 155 Russell, 392 U.S. at 294 (comparing Bruton to Gideon). 156 See, e.g., Beard v. Banks, 542 U.S. 406, 417 (2004); Saffle v. Parks, 494 U.S. 484, 495 (1990). Gideon v. Wainwright conferred on indigent defendants the right to counsel. 372 U.S. 335, 344 (1963). 157 Russell, 392 U.S. at 294 (quoting Stovall v. Denno, 388 U.S. 293, 298 (1967)). 158 390 U.S. 719 (1968). 159 393 U.S. 314, 315 (1969) (“[W]e can see no reason why Barber v. Page should not be given fully retroactive application.”). See generally People v. Watson, No. 7715/90, 2004 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 2133, at *8 n.5 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Nov. 8, 2004) (“[A]t the time that Berger v. California and Roberts v. Russell were decided, the retroactivity of any new rule was determined under the [Linkletter v. Walker, 381 U.S. 618 (1965)] standard, regardless of when the defendant’s conviction became final.”). 153 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1655 that the preliminary hearing testimony of a witness currently outside of the jurisdiction is inadmissible absent a good faith effort by the state to secure the witness’s presence. 160 In deeming the rule retroactive, the Berger Court determined that notwithstanding the state’s “countervailing interests,” 161 the opportunity to cross-examine a witness has a “significant effect on the ‘integrity of the fact-finding process.’” 162 Barber and Crawford alike make it more difficult for the prosecution to use evidence absent confrontation, and both cases stand on the proposition that the Confrontation Clause is essential to fairness. Since Barber was made retroactive, so should Crawford be. In summary, Crawford’s rule is of comparable importance to the rules of Bruton and Barber. All three rules seek to give content to the same “bedrock procedural guarantee,” 163 the Confrontation Clause of the Sixth Amendment. Bruton held that a codefendant’s confession may not be admitted as evidence at a joint trial, regardless of cautionary jury instructions, 164 and Barber made inadmissible statements of non-testifying, out-of-jurisdiction witnesses. 165 Similarly, Crawford held that “testimonial” statements were inadmissible absent the opportunity for cross-examination. 166 Each rule corrected a similar constitutional vice. 167 Since Teague, the Supreme Court has not considered the retroactivity of a “new” rule concerning the Confrontation Clause. Nevertheless, since Berger and Russell imply that Confrontation Clause violations affect the fairness and accuracy of the trial, even under Teague, both rules would 160 Barber, 390 U.S. at 724-25 (“In short, a witness is not ‘unavailable’ for purposes of the foregoing exception to the confrontation requirement unless the prosecutorial authorities have made a good-faith effort to obtain his presence at trial. . . . The right of confrontation may not be dispensed with so lightly.”). 161 Berger, 393 U.S. at 315 (“California’s claim of . . . countervailing interest[s] . . . is most unpersuasive.”). 162 Id. (quoting Linkletter, 381 U.S. at 639). 163 Crawford v. Washington, 541 U.S. 36, 42 (2004). 164 Roberts v. Russell, 392 U.S. 293, 293 (1968) (summarizing Bruton). 165 Barber, 390 U.S. at 724-25. 166 Crawford, 541 U.S. at 68-69 (“Where testimonial statements are at issue, the only indicium of reliability sufficient to satisfy constitutional demands is the one the Constitution actually prescribes: confrontation.”). 167 See Russell, 392 U.S. at 294; Crawford, 541 U.S. at 63 (“The unpardonable vice of the Roberts test, however, is not its unpredictability, but its demonstrated capacity to admit core testimonial statements that the Confrontation Clause plainly meant to exclude.”). 1656 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 deserve retroactivity. 168 Crawford, like Bruton and Barber before it, corrected an error in Confrontation Clause jurisprudence. Accordingly, Crawford, when subjected to Teague’s scrutiny, should be given full retroactive effect. D. The Retroactivity of Cruz v. New York Dictates that Crawford Qualifies for the Second Teague Exception Both the Second Circuit Court of Appeals 169 and the New York Court of Appeals 170 retroactively applied the Supreme Court’s holding in Cruz v. New York. 171 Both courts analyzed retroactivity under Teague, and both concluded that the Cruz rule was sufficiently “watershed” to fit within Teague’s second exception. Since both Cruz and Crawford implicate the Confrontation Clause, and since Crawford is at least as, if not more, necessary to the fundamental fairness and accuracy of the trial, Crawford also deserves retroactive application. Cruz v. New York concerned Eulogio and Benjamin Cruz, who were tried jointly for the felony murder of a gas station attendant. 172 At trial, prosecutors played a taped statement made by Benjamin, which incriminated Eulogio. 173 Benjamin did not testify at trial, and hence was unavailable to Eulogio for cross-examination. 174 The judge, recognizing that Benjamin’s statement was inadmissible against Eulogio, instructed the jury not to consider Benjamin’s statement when determining Eulogio’s guilt. 175 Eulogio had also confessed, but his confession was found inadmissible. The jury returned a guilty verdict against Eulogio despite the lack of admissible 168 One court recently noted that [N]otwithstanding the fact that Roberts v. Russell and Berger v. California were not decided according to the Teague standard, they support the view that the constitutional right to confront witnesses is a watershed rule, because they indicate that a violation of this right implicates the fairness of the trial and the accuracy of the fact-finding process. People v. Watson, No. 7715/90, 2004 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 2133, at *8 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Nov. 8, 2004). 169 Graham v. Hoke, 946 F.2d 982, 983 (2d Cir. 1991). 170 People v. Eastman, 85 N.Y.2d 265, 268 (1995). 171 481 U.S. 186 (1987). 172 Id. at 189. 173 Id. at 188-89. 174 Cruz v. New York, 481 U.S. 186, 188-89 (1987). 175 Id. at 189. 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1657 evidence linking him to the murder. 176 Eulogio’s conviction was upheld on appeal because Eulogio’s own confession, not admitted at trial, “interlocked” with Benjamin’s. 177 In other words, Benjamin’s statement was inadmissible against Eulogio, and Eulogio’s own confession was also inadmissible against Eulogio, but since both statements were similar, or “interlocking,” Eulogio’s conviction was upheld despite the lack of admissible evidence. 178 The Supreme Court, in Cruz v. New York, reversed Eulogio’s conviction because it violated the Confrontation Clause. 179 Specifically, Cruz contemplated “interlocking confessions,” and held that “where a nontestifying codefendant’s confession incriminating the defendant is not directly admissible against the defendant, the Confrontation Clause bars its admission at their joint trial, even if the jury is instructed not to consider it against the defendant.” 180 Before Cruz, statements of this sort were frequently admitted if they were “factually consistent” with or 176 Id. (“At the trial’s end, however, Norberto’s testimony stood as the only evidence admissible against Eulogio that directly linked him to the crime.” But nevertheless, “the jury convicted both defendants.”). 177 The New York Court of Appeals explained “interlocking confessions” as follows, Confessions are “interlocking” if their content is substantially similar. The statements need not be identical, it is sufficient that both cover all major elements of the crime involved and are “essentially the same” as to motive, plot and execution of the crimes. Statements are substantially similar when defendant’s confession is close enough to the codefendant’s with respect to the material facts of the crime charged to make the probability of prejudice so negligible that the end result would be the same without the codefendant’s statement. Confessions do not “interlock,” however, if a codefendant’s confession may be used to fill material gaps in the necessary proof against defendant. People v. Cruz, 66 N.Y.2d 61, 70 (citations omitted). The court concluded that the Cruz brothers’ statements did, in fact, “interlock”: [T]he Cruz brothers agreed, in their separate statements, on the date and target of the crime, the participants in it, the motive of robbery, and the essential facts of how defendant was injured and the station attendant killed. Although Benjamin’s statement was substantially longer, the details included did not contradict or modify the essential elements of defendant’s statement. Id. at 71. 178 Id. at 65. Cruz, 481 U.S. 186, 189 (1987). 180 Id. at 193. “Cruz . . . repudiated the interlocking confession exception to the Bruton rule that the Parker plurality and several Courts of Appeals . . . previously had recognized. . . . Parker commonly was perceived as having endorsed an interlocking confession exception to the Bruton rule.” Graham v. Hoke, 946 F.2d 982, 993 (2d Cir. 1991). 179 1658 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 “substantially similar” to the defendant’s own statement. 181 The Cruz Court, however, declared the use of such statements constitutionally unsound, and in direct conflict with the precedent established in Bruton. 182 Cruz’s author, Justice Scalia, concluded that “[t]he law cannot command respect if such an inexplicable exception to a supposed constitutional imperative is adopted.” 183 Both the Second Circuit Court of Appeals and the New York Court of Appeals applied the Cruz holding retroactively under the second Teague exception. In their analyses, both courts determined that the Cruz rule involved a “bedrock procedural element.” 184 New York’s highest court, in People v. Eastman, proclaimed that “Cruz unquestionably . . . implicates a bedrock procedural element,” 185 while the Second Circuit Court of Appeals, in Graham, announced that “there [could] be little doubt that the decision altered our understanding of a bedrock procedural principle.” 186 Graham continued that “[t]he ‘bedrock procedural element’ implicated in Cruz was the right of confrontation; a right which the Supreme Court long ago referred to as being ‘one of the fundamental guarantees of life and liberty,’” 187 and cited with approval the notion that “[t]he right of cross-examination is more than a desirable rule of trial procedure. It is implicit in the constitutional right of confrontation.” Eastman and Graham then determined that, in addition to implicating a “fundamental procedural guarantee,” application of the Cruz rule is essential to a fair trial. 188 According to the Eastman court, the Cruz rule is necessary in order for “the procedural apparatus of trial . . . [to] assure[] the 181 People v. Eastman, 85 N.Y.2d 265, 273-74, 274 n.4 (1995). Bruton v. United States, 391 U.S. 123, 137 (holding that a defendant is deprived of his Confrontation Clause rights when a codefendant’s incriminating confession is introduced at their joint trial, even if cautionary instructions were given to the jury to disregard the statement). 183 481 U.S. at 193. 184 Graham, 946 F.2d at 993; Eastman, 85 N.Y.2d at 276. Graham did not actually make the determination of whether Cruz announced a “new” or an “old” rule. However, the court reasoned that the rule is retroactive either way. Graham, 946 F.2d at 992 (“[W]e find it unnecessary to categorize the Cruz rule as either a ‘new’ or ‘old’ rule of constitutional criminal procedure. Rather, we . . . believe that regardless of whether the Cruz rule is characterized as a ‘new’ or ‘old’ rule it should be applied retroactively.”). 185 Eastman, 85 N.Y.2d at 276. 186 Graham, 946 F.2d at 993. 187 Id. at 994 (quoting Kirby v. United States, 174 U.S. 47, 55 (1899)). 188 Id. at 993-94; Eastman, 85 N.Y.2d at 276. 182 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1659 defendant a fair determination of guilt or innocence,” 189 and the admission of the types of statements proscribed by Cruz “undermine[s] . . . fundamental fairness.” 190 Similarly, Graham held that the Cruz rule is necessary to “ensure[] a fair proceeding.” 191 Graham concluded that “[t]he Cruz rule . . . satisfies [Teague’s] second exception to the general rule against retroactive application of ‘new’ constitutional rules of criminal procedure,” 192 and that “[e]ven if the impact of retroactivity may be significant, the constitutional error presents a serious risk that the issue of guilt or innocence may not have been reliably determined.” 193 The Crawford rule is analogous to the Cruz rule, and hence, deserves equal treatment for retroactivity purposes. Both rules severely limited the kind of evidence which may be admitted without cross-examination; Cruz rejected “interlocking” confessions, 194 while Crawford rejected all “testimonial” statements. 195 Both corrected flaws in the Court’s Confrontation Clause jurisprudence. 196 In fact, Crawford corrected an even greater affront to the Confrontation Clause than did Cruz. In Cruz, the defendant and codefendant were tried jointly, but the codefendant’s statement was introduced only against the codefendant; the court explicitly directed jurors not to consider the statement in evaluating Cruz’s guilt. 197 Even though the Cruz Court concluded that jurors could not reasonably be expected to obey such an instruction, 198 the resulting Confrontation Clause violation was still indirect. The Cruz trial court recognized that jurors should not consider the testimony at issue, and instructed the jury accordingly. On the other hand, in Crawford, the trial court admitted testimonial hearsay directly against the defendant. Limiting instructions were never given, not even difficult or impossible189 Eastman, 85 N.Y.2d at 276. Id. 191 Graham, 946 F.2d at 993-94. 192 Id. 193 Id. at 994 (quoting Roberts v. Russell, 392 U.S. 293, 295 (1968)). 194 Cruz v. New York, 481 U.S. 186 (1987). 195 Crawford v. Washington, 541 U.S. 36 (2005). 196 Id. at 61 (“Admitting statements deemed reliable by a judge is fundamentally at odds with the right of confrontation.”); Cruz, 481 U.S. at 193 (“The law cannot command respect if such an inexplicable exception to a supposed constitutional imperative is adopted.”). 197 Cruz, 481 U.S. at 189. 198 Id. at 193. 190 1660 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 to-obey ones. 199 The court invited the Crawford jury to consider the ex parte accusatory statement for its truth in deciding whether or not to convict. 200 Therefore, reason dictates that if Cruz twice achieved retroactive effect under Teague, then surely Crawford, correcting an even more egregious constitutional malady, should receive equal consideration. E. Litigation Concerning Crawford’s Retroactivity has Begun, and Lower State and Federal Courts Are in Disagreement Of the five federal circuits that have ruled on Crawford’s retroactivity, only one concluded that Crawford’s rule qualified under Teague’s second exception. 201 Those failing to find Crawford retroactive, however, have done so after only a cursory analysis. 202 Some have flatly stated that Crawford is not “watershed,” effectively assuming that which they should be attempting to prove. 203 Others have chosen to make the fact that Confrontation Clause violations are subject to harmless 199 See Crawford, 541 U.S. at 40-41. Id. at 40. 201 The Ninth Circuit has held Crawford retroactive under the second Teague exception. Bockting v. Bayer, 399 F.3d 1010, 1019-21 (9th Cir. 2005). The Second, Sixth, Seventh, and Tenth Circuits have decided not to make Crawford retroactive. Bintz v. Bertrand, 403 F.3d 859, 867 (7th Cir. 2005); Murillo v. Frank, 402 F.3d 786, 790 (7th Cir. 2005); Dorchy v. Jones, 398 F.3d 783, 788 (6th Cir. 2005); Mungo v. Duncan, 393 F.3d 327, 336 (2d Cir. 2004); Brown v. Uphoff, 381 F.3d 1219, 1227 (10th Cir. 2004). The Eighth Circuit has indicated that Crawford is not retroactive. Evans v. Luebbers, 371 F.3d 438, 444-45 (8th Cir. 2004) (suggesting in dicta that Crawford does not apply retroactively). 202 See, e.g., Bockting, 399 F.3d at 1020 (“The flaw in this analysis [declining to make Crawford retroactive] is that the Second Circuit has substituted its judgment of whether the Crawford rule is one without which the accuracy of conviction is seriously diminished, for the Supreme Court’s considered judgment.”); People v. Watson, No. 7715/90, 2004 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 2133, at *8 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Nov. 8, 2004) (“For the most part, however, with little analysis, these courts have generally held that Crawford . . . did not announce a watershed rule of criminal procedure.” The court continued that, “[w]here explanations have been proffered for this conclusion, these courts have generally pointed to the fact that a Confrontation Clause violation is subject to harmless error analysis.”). 203 See, e.g., Brown, 381 F.3d at 1226; Evans, 371 F.3d at 444-45; Garcia v. United States, No. 04-CV-0465, 2004 WL 1752588, at *4 (N.D.N.Y. Aug. 4, 2004); Hutzenlaub v. Portuondo, 325 F. Supp. 2d 236, 237-38 (E.D.N.Y. 2004); Wheeler v. Dretke, No. Civ.A. 404CV026Y, 2004 WL 1532178, at *1 (N.D. Tex. July 6, 2004); Murillo v. Frank, 316 F. Supp.2d 744, 749 (E.D. Wis. 2004), aff’d, 402 F.3d 786. Some state courts have held similarly. See, e.g., People v. Edwards, 101 P.3d 1118, 1122 (Ct. App. Colo. 2004), aff’d, 129 P.3d 977, No. 04SC565, 2006 WL 320992 (Colo. Feb. 13, 2006); People v. Khan, No. 499-90, 2004 WL 1463027, at *4-5 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. June 23, 2004). 200 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1661 error 204 analysis fatal to Crawford’s retroactivity. 205 The Supreme Court, however, has never indicated that a rule subject to harmless error analysis may not be deemed “watershed” under Teague. 206 In fact, the constitutional error corrected by Cruz was also subject to harmless error analysis, yet it was made retroactive by the New York Court of Appeals and the Second Circuit. 207 Therefore, that a Confrontation Clause violation may not require automatic reversal does not preclude the rule from fitting within the second Teague exception. Two New York Appellate Division cases, citing Eastman, recently found Crawford retroactive under the second Teague exception. People v. Watson 208 and People v. Dobbin 209 both held that since Eastman declared that Cruz satisfied Teague, then so does Crawford. 210 The implicit logic in Watson and Dobbin is clear. Both courts analogized Cruz to Crawford, and concluded that the Crawford rule is at least as, if not more, constitutionally imperative than the Cruz rule. Thus, because Cruz satisfied Teague, Crawford does as well. Since the New York Court of Appeals and the Second Circuit applied Cruz retroactively on collateral review, 211 making Crawford retroactive was the only sensible conclusion. 212 204 Harmless error review means that even if there was a mistake at trial the verdict will stand unless the mistake affected the substantial rights of the parties. See LAFAVE, supra note 9, at 1298. 205 See, e.g., Brown, 381 F.3d at 1226-27; Garcia, 2004 WL 1752588, at *4 (N.D.N.Y. 2004). “These courts have reasoned that because Confrontation Clause errors are subject to harmless error review, new rules altering the clause’s application do not deprive a defendant of his or her fundamental right to due process and, therefore, [Crawford] cannot be considered a watershed rule.” People v. Watson, No. 7715/90, 2004 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 2133, at *8 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Nov. 8, 2004) (citation omitted). 206 Watson, 2004 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 2133, at *10 n.7 (“The Supreme Court has never issued any decision . . . indicating that a rule which is subject to harmless error analysis cannot be considered a watershed rule.”); see also Bockting, 399 F.3d at 1020 (“[W]hether a rule of constitutional law is subject to harmless error review does not answer the question whether it is a bedrock rule of procedure.”). 207 See discussion supra notes 167-91 and accompanying text. 208 2004 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 2133. 209 791 N.Y.S.2d 897 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 2004). 210 Watson, 2004 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 2133, at *9 (“[A]pplying Teague’s teachings, this court finds that the rule announced in Crawford is a ‘watershed’ rule of Criminal Procedure, and thus applies to cases on collateral review.”); Dobbin, 791 N.Y.S.2d at 905 (“[T]he Crawford rule must be applied retroactively on collateral review.”) (italics added). 211 Watson and Dobbin were New York Appellate Division cases. Thus, People v. Eastman, 85 N.Y.2d 265 (1995), decided by the New York Court of Appeals, was 1662 V. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 CONCLUSION With Crawford the Supreme Court corrected an “unpardonable” 213 flaw in its jurisprudence, and restored the Confrontation Clause to its rightful status as a bedrock constitutional guarantee essential to a fair trial. Notwithstanding the high bar set by Teague and its progeny, Crawford deserves to be applied retroactively. As a “new” rule, Crawford’s retroactivity turns on whether it fits within the contours of the second Teague exception. Teague adopted a strict standard for the retroactive application of “new” rules, so strict in fact that the Supreme Court has yet to find a rule capable of satisfying it. The Court, however, has never applied the Teague framework to a rule as significant as Crawford’s. Crawford is more important than, and thus distinguishable from, its “new” rule predecessors, all of which failed under Teague. What separates Crawford from other “new” rules not worthy of retroactivity is its subject, the Confrontation Clause. Prior to Teague, the Supreme Court twice gave retroactive effect to “new” rules concerning the Confrontation Clause, both times concluding that to deprive a defendant of the right of confrontation was to withhold a fundamental constitutional guarantee essential to a fair trial. Furthermore, the New York Court of Appeals and the Second Circuit both applied the Supreme Court’s holding in Cruz v. New York retroactively, demonstrating that even under the strict Teague framework, the importance of the Confrontation Clause outweighs the negative implications of retroactivity. Roberts’s malleable test rendered the Confrontation Clause constitutionally infirm. With Crawford, the Supreme Court resuscitated the right of confrontation, and with it, the legitimacy of criminal trials. The Supreme Court admittedly “[did] violence to [the] design” of the Confrontation Clause binding precedent; Graham v. Hoke, 946 F.2d 982 (2d Cir. 1991), decided by the Second Circuit Court of Appeals, was merely persuasive. 212 Recently the Second Circuit held that Crawford is not retroactive under Teague, yet failed to cite Graham in its analysis. Mungo v. Duncan, 393 F.3d 327, 336 (2d Cir. 2004). Nor did the court make any attempt to distinguish the Cruz rule, made retroactive in Graham, with the Crawford rule. Id. See Part IV.D, supra, for a comparison of Crawford to Cruz, and for an argument that Crawford, in fact, corrected an even more serious constitutional flaw. 213 Crawford v. Washington, 541 U.S. 36, 63 (2004). 2006] RETROACTIVE APPLICATION OF CRAWFORD 1663 when it endorsed the Roberts test, 214 and limiting Crawford to prospective application would exacerbate Roberts’s damage. In summary, neither history nor precedent leaves any doubt that the right of confrontation is crucial to a fair trial, Roberts denied criminal defendants the enjoyment of that right, and Crawford corrected Roberts’s mistake. Only one conclusion follows: Crawford v. Washington must be applied retroactively. Brian Spitser † 214 Id. at 67-68 (“By replacing categorical constitutional guarantees with openended balancing tests, we do violence to their design.”). † B.S. Boston College, 2002; J.D. candidate, Brooklyn Law School, 2006. The author thanks the Legal Aid Society’s Criminal Appeals Bureau, Brooklyn Law Review, his friends, and his family. Fair Use in Trademark in the Post-KP Permanent World HOW INCORPORATING PRINCIPLES FROM COPYRIGHT LAW WILL LEAD TO LESS CONFUSION IN TRADEMARK LAW INTRODUCTION Imagine it is Christmas time, and you are looking for a gift for your nine-year-old niece Suzie. You know that Suzie loves the television show, American Idol, 1 so you resort to the Internet and perform a search for the phrase “American Idol.” This search brings you to the homepage of Constantine Maroulis, a former contestant from the show’s past season. The top of the page reads, “Welcome to the homepage of Constantine Maroulis: A Real American Idol.” The page contains many references to the television show, including screenshots of a few of Constantine’s more memorable performances. You can even purchase Constantine’s debut CD, entitled “A Real American Idol,” as well as a life-size Constantine Maroulis poster if you are so inclined. Suzie is a big fan, so you buy both, but when you give them to her, she starts crying. Suzie screams, “That’s not the real American Idol! Where’s Kelly Clarkson, Ruben Studdard, and Fantasia Barrino?” 2 Failed Christmas presents aside, American Idol has a potential claim for trademark infringement against Constantine Maroulis, since consumers may incorrectly think that the show produced or sponsored Constantine’s CD. Trademarks are designed to protect the trade reputation, or goodwill, of the trademark owner who, through use and advertising, has created an association of his or her product or 1 American Idol (FOX television broadcast 2002-present). Kelly Clarkson, Ruben Studdard, and Fantasia Barrino were the winners from the first three seasons. As winners, American Idol produces and releases their debut album. For more information, see American Idol: About the Show, http://www.idolonfox.com/about (last visited Mar. 13, 2006). 2 1665 1666 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 service with that trademark. 3 For a trademark owner to succeed on a claim of infringement under the Federal Trademark (Lanham) Act, 4 he must show that consumers are likely to be confused as to the source of the junior user’s product. 5 Courts typically look at many factors to determine if a likelihood of confusion exists. 6 On the other hand, Constantine has a good opportunity to assert the statutory fair use defense to trademark infringement, since he is simply describing himself as a real American idol, and to some, this is an accurate description. In defense to a charge of trademark infringement, a defendant can assert the statutory fair use defense of the Lanham Act. 7 To succeed on this defense, a defendant must show that he used the trademark descriptively, not as a trademark, fairly, and in good faith. 8 Until recently, the U.S. Supreme Court had not addressed how courts should handle the fair use defense when faced with a seemingly strong claim for trademark infringement. In other words, can Constantine claim that his use was fair even though consumers are likely to be confused by the origin of the products sold on his website? In 2004, the Supreme Court issued a landmark decision addressing the issue. 9 In KP Permanent Make-Up, Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc. (“KP Permanent”), the Supreme Court held that the statutory fair use defense could succeed even in the face of confusion. 10 Unfortunately, the Supreme Court failed to give any indication as to just how much confusion could defeat the fair use defense. 11 In this Note, I will argue that because of the similarities between the concerns of copyright and trademark protection, trademark law will benefit from incorporating some of the factors from copyright law’s fair use defense as an aid to lower courts being asked to decide whether a use is fair. Although copyright law differs 3 See 1 J. THOMAS MCCARTHY, MCCARTHY ON TRADEMARKS AND UNFAIR COMPETITION § 3:2 (4th ed., 2005). 4 15 U.S.C. §§ 1051-1141n (2000). 5 Id. § 1114(1)(a) (2000). 6 See infra note 32. 7 15 U.S.C. § 1115(b)(4) (2000). 8 Id. 9 See KP Permanent Make-Up, Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc., 543 U.S. 111 (2004). 10 Id. at 122 (holding that “some possibility of consumer confusion must be compatible with fair use”). 11 Id. at 123 (recognizing that while “mere risk of confusion will not rule out fair use, we think it would be improvident to go further in this case”). 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1667 from trademark law in that it protects original works of authorship such as songs or books, there are substantial similarities between the two that justify incorporation. 12 In trademark law prior to KP Permanent, the circuit courts disagreed on the role that confusion played in a fair use defense. 13 The Ninth Circuit, which issued the decision leading to the Supreme Court’s ruling in KP Permanent, allowed confusion to defeat a fair use defense and required the defendant to prove the absence of likely confusion. 14 In opposition to that view, the Second Circuit allowed fair use to succeed even upon a showing of some confusion and did not require a defendant to negate any likelihood of confusion. 15 Other courts fell somewhere in the middle. 16 In KP Permanent, the Supreme Court agreed with the Second Circuit, holding that fair use could exist in the face of confusion, but left open to interpretation just how much confusion would defeat a fair use defense. 17 The Court’s decision effectively left lower courts with a blank check, and those courts have not balked at the ability to write their own rules. 18 Copyright law’s fair use test has given lower courts the clear guidance lacking in trademark law, and similar principles and factors from that test are inherent in trademark law. 19 In copyright law, it is well established that fair use is an affirmative defense to infringement. 20 After decades of judge12 See discussion infra Part III. See discussion infra Part I.C. 14 KP Permanent Make-Up, Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc., 328 F.3d 1061, 1072 (9th Cir. 2003), vacated, 543 U.S. 111 (2004). 15 See, e.g., Cosmetically Sealed Indus., Inc. v. Chesebrough-Pond’s USA Co., 125 F.3d 28, 30 (2d Cir. 1977) (noting that any confusion that results “is a risk the plaintiff accepted when it decided to identify its product with a mark that uses a well known descriptive phrase”) (citing Car-Freshner Corp. v. S.C. Johnson & Son, Inc., 70 F.3d 267, 270 (2d Cir. 1995)). 16 See PACCAR Inc. v. TeleScan Technologies, L.L.C., 319 F.3d 243, 256 (6th Cir. 2003) (finding that a “likelihood of confusion forecloses a fair use defense”); Zatarains Inc. v. Oak Grove Smokehouse, 698 F.2d 786, 796 (5th Cir. 1983) (providing that any likelihood of confusion bars the fair use defense); but cf. Shakespeare Co. v. Silstar Corp. of Am., Inc., 110 F.3d 234, 243 (4th Cir. 1997) (noting that “[t]he fair use defense comes into play only when infringement – including a likelihood of confusion – has been established”); Sunmark, Inc. v. Ocean Spray Cranberries, Inc., 64 F.3d 1055, 1059 (7th Cir. 1995) (holding that fair use could succeed even in the face of likely confusion). 17 KP Permanent Make-Up, Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc., 543 U.S. 111, 116-17 (2004). 18 See discussion infra Part I.E. 19 See discussion infra Part III. 20 See 17 U.S.C. § 107 (2000); see also discussion infra Part II. 13 1668 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 made law, 21 Congress codified the doctrine in section 107 of the Copyright Act of 1976. 22 Section 107 defined four factors that courts should look at to determine if an alleged infringing use is fair. 23 These factors are: (1) the purpose and character of the use; (2) the nature of the copyrighted work; (3) the amount and substantiality of the portion used; and (4) the effect of the use on the potential market for or value of the copyrighted work. 24 While there is no per se formula for what constitutes fair use, certain combinations of these factors will make a fair use defense more likely to succeed. 25 Some judges have already begun to implicitly apply This Note will copyright concepts to trademark cases. 26 demonstrate why these judges are moving in the right direction and suggest further ways to implement this new approach. Part I begins with a history of fair use in trademark, including the circuit split that led to the decision in KP Permanent. This section will also address the Court’s holding in KP Permanent and illustrate the Court’s reasoning for establishing fair use as an absolute defense. This section will conclude by discussing the state of the fair use defense following KP Permanent and the ways in which lower courts have begun to apply the Supreme Court’s holding. Part II will discuss the background of fair use in copyright, and the factors that courts apply to determine fair use. This section will also illustrate typical applications of the copyright fair use test and instances in which courts have upheld or denied use as fair. Part III will look at the similarities between the principles of trademark and copyright protection as well as their respective fair use defenses. In order to suggest that trademark law should incorporate elements of copyright law, this section will illustrate the similar concerns of both areas of the law in granting protection 21 The concept of fair use in copyright first appeared in a judicial opinion in 1841. See Folsom v. Marsh, 9 F. Cas. 342, 344-45 (C.C.D. Mass. 1841) (No. 4,901). The term “fair use” in copyright first appeared in a judicial opinion in 1869. See Lawrence v. Dana, 15 F. Cas. 26, 44 (C.C.D. Mass. 1869) (No. 8,136). 22 17 U.S.C. § 107 (2000). 23 Id. 24 Id. 25 See, e.g., Lish v. Harper’s Magazine Found., 807 F. Supp. 1090, 1096 (S.D.N.Y. 1992) (fair use defense failed even though the fourth factor favored the defendant); see also Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 594 (1994) (while suggesting fair use on the first three factors, the Court remanded to allow the hole in the evidence with respect to the fourth factor to “be plugged on remand”). 26 See infra notes 255-56 and accompanying text. 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1669 and allowing fair use. This section will also address the notion that the scope of trademarks is expanding, which warrants a further examination of their protection. Finally, Part IV will argue that trademark law can borrow specific principles from copyright law to lead to less confusion in the lower courts. This section will demonstrate how borrowing certain aspects of the copyright test and incorporating them into their counterparts in trademark will provide courts with a more consistent approach to fair use in trademark and ultimately lead to less confusion in litigation. I. TRADEMARKS AND FAIR USE A trademark is a designation that identifies and distinguishes a seller’s goods from those of its competitors. 27 By attaching a trademark to its goods, a seller alerts the public that goods bearing this trademark come from that seller and are of a certain quality. 28 For example, when a consumer sees a small insignia of a polo player on a horse on the breast of a man’s shirt, he knows that shirt was manufactured by Polo, 29 and this brand alerts the buyer to a level of quality in the shirt. Trademarks are granted legal protection to safeguard this trade reputation of the trademark owner who has created an association of a product or service with that trademark. 30 When someone other than the trademark owner begins selling goods using a similar name, the trademark owner may succeed on a claim of infringement by showing that consumers are likely to be confused by the similarities. 31 In these cases, courts conduct an intense fact-finding inquiry to determine if a likelihood of confusion exists. 32 27 See 1 MCCARTHY, supra note 3, § 3:1. Id. § 3:2. 29 Polo is a popular brand of clothing, best known for its logo consisting of a horse which often appears on the breast of a man’s collared shirt. For more information, see About Ralph Lauren, http://about.polo.com (last visited Mar. 13, 2006). 30 See 1 MCCARTHY, supra note 3, § 3:2. 31 15 U.S.C. § 1114(1)(a) (2000). 32 See, e.g., Polaroid Corp. v. Polarad Elects. Corp., 287 F.2d 492, 495 (2d Cir. 1961) (defining the factors to consider as: (1) the strength of the plaintiff’s trademark; (2) the degree of similarity between the marks; (3) the proximity of the products or services; (4) the likelihood that the plaintiff will bridge the gap; (5) actual confusion; (6) a defendant’s bad faith in adopting its mark; (7) the quality of the defendant’s product; and (8) the sophistication of the buyers). 28 1670 A. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Statutory, or “Classic,” Fair Use In defense to a charge of trademark infringement, a defendant can assert the statutory fair use defense of the Lanham Act. 33 To succeed on this defense, a defendant must show that he used the trademark descriptively and not as a For example, a trademark, fairly, and in good faith. 34 housecleaning service who advertises that they will “Clean up your Windows” can assert the statutory fair use defense if faced with allegations of infringement by Microsoft. 35 Statutory fair use is also referred to as “classic” fair use, since it existed under the common law of unfair competition prior to the enactment of the Lanham Act. 36 In passing the Lanham Act, Congress codified the doctrine and established that a user accused of infringement can assert the statutory affirmative defense of fair use. 37 The fair use defense, in essence, restricts a trademark owner from exercising exclusive rights over a descriptive term which would prevent others from accurately Specifically, the Lanham Act describing their product. 38 requires that three elements be met to establish the defense: (1) the challenged infringement must not be used as a trade or service mark; (2) the challenged infringement must describe the goods; and (3) use must be fair and in good faith. 39 While the first two factors involve relatively simple factual inquiries, 33 34 15 U.S.C. § 1115(b)(4) (2000). The relevant portion of 15 U.S.C. § 1115 provides: That the use of the name, term, or device charged to be an infringement is a use, otherwise than as a mark, of the party’s individual name in his own business, or of the individual name of anyone in privity with such party, or of a term or device which is descriptive of and used fairly and in good faith only to describe to users the goods or services of such party, or their geographic origin . . . . Id. (emphasis added). 35 Microsoft is a corporation which manufactures computer hardware and software, most notably, the Windows operating system. For more information, see Microsoft Corporation homepage, http://www.microsoft.com (last visited Jan. 22, 2006). 36 See, e.g., William R. Warner & Co. v. Eli Lilly & Co., 265 U.S. 526, 528 (1924) (stating that “[t]he use of a similar name by another to truthfully describe his own product does not constitute a legal or moral wrong, even if its effect be to cause the public to mistake the origin or ownership of the product”). 37 See 15 U.S.C. § 1115(b)(4) (2000). 38 Soweco, Inc. v. Shell Oil Co., 617 F.2d 1178, 1185 (5th Cir. 1980) (permitting fair use “forbids a trademark registrant to appropriate a descriptive term for his exclusive use and so prevent others from accurately describing a characteristic of their goods”). 39 See 15 U.S.C. § 1115(b)(4) (2000). 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1671 the final factor implicates much more subjective analysis, and courts have come to strikingly different conclusions on what constitutes fair use. 40 Before a defendant can assert statutory fair use as a defense to an infringement claim, the plaintiff must first show that its trademark is valid and that defendant’s use of the trademark is likely to cause confusion, mistake, or deception among consumers as to the source of defendant’s goods or services. 41 Once a plaintiff has established both of these elements, a defendant may claim that his or her use is fair as an affirmative defense. 42 In permitting fair use of trademarks, the Lanham Act seeks to prohibit a trademark owner from precluding others from describing their goods. 43 By choosing a potentially descriptive mark, a plaintiff runs a significant risk, because a competitor may want to use those same words to accurately describe his or her product. 44 For example, although Tasti-D-Lite is a registered trademark, a competing ice cream shop may wish to advertise that its ice cream is tasty and delightful. Generally, the law prefers to avoid monopolies, but trademark law often grants exclusive rights, because there is a seemingly endless supply of potential trademarks, and the cost of the monopoly to society is seen as insignificant. 45 In other words, in the Tasti-D-Lite example, a 40 Compare PACCAR Inc. v. TeleScan Technologies, L.L.C., 319 F.3d 243, 256 (6th Cir. 2003) (finding that a “likelihood of confusion forecloses a fair use defense”); Zatarains Inc. v. Oak Grove Smokehouse, 698 F.2d 786, 796 (5th Cir. 1983) (providing that any likelihood of confusion bars the fair use defense) with Shakespeare Co. v. Silstar Corp. of Am., 110 F.3d 234, 243 (4th Cir. 1997) (noting that “[t]he fair use defense comes into play only when infringement – including a likelihood of confusion – has been established”); Sunmark, Inc. v. Ocean Spray Cranberries, Inc., 64 F.3d 1055, 1059 (7th Cir. 1995) (holding that fair use could succeed even in the face of likely confusion). 41 See, e.g., Nabisco, Inc. v. Warner-Lambert Co., 220 F.3d 43, 45 (2d Cir. 2000) (stating that “[t]o prevail on [a claim of] trademark infringement [a plaintiff must] prove that [its trademark] is a protectable trademark and that [defendant’s use] is likely to confuse consumers as to the source of sponsorship of [plaintiff’s] product”). 42 See 15 U.S.C. § 1115(b)(4) (2000). 43 U.S. Shoe Corp. v. Brown Group Inc., 740 F. Supp. 196, 198 (S.D.N.Y. 1990) (allowing fair use “to prevent the trademark rights of one party from being extended to preclude another party from the description of his product to the public” (citing Eli Lilly & Co. v. Revlon, Inc., 577 F. Supp. 477, 486 (1983))), aff’d, 923 F.2d 844 (2d Cir. 1990). A plaintiff choosing a descriptive mark “cannot altogether exclude some kinds of competing uses.” Id. 44 Abercrombie & Fitch Co. v. Hunting World, Inc., 537 F.2d 4, 12 (2d Cir. 1976). 45 U.S. Shoe Corp., 740 F. Supp. at 198 (stating that trademark law permits monopolies “because potential identifying marks exist in virtually inexhaustible supply [and] the cost of the monopoly to society is minimal”). 1672 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 competitor should have no problem using words other than “tasty” or “delightful” to convey the same message without causing unnecessary confusion in the marketplace. Nevertheless, since the cost to society increases if a trademark owner is granted exclusive use of a descriptive trademark, fair use exists in part to help balance the interests in trademark protection and unfair competition. 46 Unfortunately, statutory fair use leaves open the question: at what point is the cost of confusion created by fair use too great for society to tolerate? When a defendant uses another’s trademark in the nondescriptive sense, however, he may still avoid a claim of infringement if his use falls under the nominative fair use doctrine. B. Nominative Fair Use While statutory fair use allows a defendant to use a trademark to describe its own product or service descriptively, nominative fair use allows a defendant to use a trademark to describe the trademark owner’s product or service. 47 For example, an advertising campaign for “Brand X” that claims “If you like Brand Y, you’ll love Brand X” is an example of a nominative fair use. The nominative fair use defense is entirely a product of the judiciary. 48 The leading court in addressing nominative fair use, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, defined three elements required to successfully assert a nominative fair use claim: (1) “the product or service in question must be one not readily identifiable without use of the trademark;” (2) “only so much of the mark or marks may be used as is reasonably necessary to identify the product or service;” and (3) “the user must do nothing that would, in conjunction with the mark, suggest sponsorship or endorsement by the trademark holder.” 49 For example, when former Playboy Playmate of the Year, Terri Welles, used the words “Playmate of the Year” to describe herself on her website, the court upheld the use as fair under the nominative fair use doctrine, because the words sought only “to identify 46 See discussion infra Part III.B. See 2 MCCARTHY, supra note 3, § 11:45 (discussing the distinctions between statutory and nominative fair use). 48 See New Kids on the Block v. News Am. Publ’g, Inc., 971 F.2d 302, 308 (9th Cir. 1992). 49 Id. 47 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1673 Welles as a past . . . ‘Playmate of the Year’” and not to “imply . . . current sponsorship or endorsement by [Playboy].” 50 Nominative fair use appears in many different forms. In addition to the referential use in the Terri Welles case and the comparative advertising in the “Brand X” example, nominative fair use also arises in promotional use and parody. An example of promotional use includes the sale of a t-shirt by a third party bearing a trademark such as a sports team. Danish band Aqua’s infamous song entitled Barbie Girl is a good example of parody. 51 Courts have often wrestled with how to handle nominative fair use claims, particularly in the area of In parody, courts have parody and promotional use. 52 consistently agreed that, in order to be successful, a parody must convey two conflicting messages: that it actually is the original, but also that it is not the original but rather a parody. 53 This creates an obvious conflict in policy, because the more successful the parody, the more confused a consumer will be at first glance. Therefore, nominative fair use raises similar problems as that of statutory fair use in that courts must create their own rules to determine how confusion relates to the fair use defense. The questionable relationship between confusion and the fair use defense created a division of interpretations amongst the circuit courts. 54 C. The Lead-Up to KP Permanent Prior to the Supreme Court’s decision in KP Permanent, the circuit courts disagreed on the significance of likely 50 Playboy Enters. v. Welles, 279 F.3d 796, 800-02 (9th Cir. 2002). AQUA, Barbie Girl, on AQUARIUM (MCA Records 1997). 52 In the promotional use line of cases, there are clearly two schools of thought. One approach finds infringement even when no confusion as to source exists. See Boston Prof’l Hockey Ass’n v. Dallas Cap & Emblem Mfg., 510 F.2d 1004, 1011 (5th Cir. 1975) (holding that patches sold by a sporting goods store bearing the insignia of a professional sports team constituted infringement even though consumers purchased the patches to show allegiance and not because of their source). The other approach to promotional use assesses whether consumers view the use of the trademark as a source identifier to determine whether confusion exists. See Int’l Order of Job’s Daughters v. Lindeburg & Co., 633 F.2d 912, 919 (9th Cir. 1980) (holding that jewelry bearing the trademark of a young women’s fraternal organization did not constitute infringement because purchasers did not see the trademark as identifying source). Parody is equally conflicting. 53 Cliffs Notes, Inc. v. Bantam Doubleday Dell Publ’g Group, 886 F.2d 490, 494 (2d Cir. 1989). (noting that “[c]onflict between . . . policies is inevitable in the context of parody, because the keystone of parody is imitation”). 54 See discussion infra Part I.C. 51 1674 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 confusion as it pertains to a fair use defense. 55 The Second Circuit represented one point of view, holding that fair use is an absolute defense to infringement regardless of the confusion that results. 56 The Ninth Circuit required a defendant to prove the absence of confusion and found that a failure to do so diminished the likelihood of a fair use claim to prevail. 57 Amongst the other circuits, both the Fifth and Sixth Circuits held that any likelihood of confusion bars the fair use defense, 58 while the Fourth and Seventh Circuits held that fair use could succeed even in the face of likely confusion. 59 Under the Ninth Circuit’s approach, the owner of an ice cream shop who advertises that his ice cream is “tasty” cannot succeed on a fair use defense against Tasti-D-Lite unless he or she proves that consumers do not confuse his goods with those from Tasti-DLite. In the Second Circuit, the fair use defense could succeed in this example even if Tasti-D-Lite were able to prove that nearly all ice cream consumers were confused by the other store’s advertisement. Regardless of the circuits’ conflicting interpretations of the relevant provisions of the Lanham Act, the statute gives no indication as to how much confusion is too much. 60 The Supreme Court had yet to address this issue either. In fact, the significance of confusion in a fair use defense provided the Court with its justification for granting certiorari. 61 55 The views of the Ninth and Second Circuits lay at the heart of the circuit split. The Ninth Circuit represented the view that any confusion would defeat a statutory fair use defense. See KP Permanent Make-Up, Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc., 328 F.3d 1061, 1072 (9th Cir. 2003), vacated, 543 U.S. 111 (2004). The Second Circuit opposed this view, finding that fair use is a defense to liability even if there is a likelihood of confusion. See Cosmetically Sealed Indus., Inc. v. Chesebrough-Pond’s USA Co., 125 F.3d 28, 30 (2d Cir. 1977). Although the circuit split that led to KP Permanent did not involve nominative fair use claims, courts have shown equal disagreement with the relationship of confusion in the nominative fair use context. See supra notes 52-53 and accompanying text. 56 Cosmetically Sealed, 125 F.3d at 30 (holding that any resulting confusion from alleged infringement is inherent in the risk that plaintiff took in selecting the descriptive term, and therefore, does not bar the fair use defense). 57 KP Permanent, 328 F.3d at 1072. 58 See PACCAR Inc. v. TeleScan Technologies, L.L.C., 319 F.3d 243, 256 (6th Cir. 2003); Zatarains Inc. v. Oak Grove Smokehouse, 698 F.2d 786, 796 (5th Cir. 1983). 59 See Shakespeare Co. v. Silstar Corp. of Am., 110 F.3d 234, 243 (4th Cir. 1997); Sunmark, Inc. v. Ocean Spray Cranberries, Inc., 64 F.3d 1055, 1059 (7th Cir. 1995). 60 See 15 U.S.C. § 1115(b)(4) (2000). 61 KP Permanent Make-Up, Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc., 543 U.S. 111, 116 (2004) (granting certiorari “to address a disagreement among the Courts of Appeals on the significance of likely confusion for a fair use defense to a trademark infringement claim”). 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1675 In the months before the Court’s decision, scholars speculated about how the Court would rule, and the implications different rulings would create. 62 Most thought that the Court would side with the Second Circuit’s approach in allowing confusion to exist in a fair use defense. 63 Others foresaw the danger a ruling siding with the Ninth Circuit could create. 64 As one scholar noted, by affirming the Ninth Circuit’s holding, “[s]ummary judgment would rarely be granted when a fair use defense is asserted because the defendant would have to disprove likelihood of confusion – a fact-intensive inquiry that is typically part of the plaintiff’s case.” 65 This could either preclude summary judgment altogether or defeat its purpose in avoiding the fact-intensive inquiries of litigation when a defendant asserts fair use. 66 D. The KP Permanent Case 1. Background and Procedural History With the legal landscape ripe for change, the basis for KP Permanent arose as follows. Petitioner KP Permanent Make-Up, Inc. (“KP”) and Respondent Lasting Impression I, Inc. (“Lasting Impression”) both manufactured and sold permanent makeup, “a mixture of pigment and liquid for injection under the skin to camouflage injuries and modify nature’s dispensations,” and in doing so, both used the term “microcolor” in marketing their products. 67 In 1992, Lasting Impression federally registered a trademark with the words 62 See generally Lynda M. Braun, Fair Is Fair, But Is It Enough?, 4 IP LAW & BUS. 54 (2004); Graeme B. Dinwoodie, The Trademark Jurisprudence of the Rehnquist Court, 8 MARQ. INTELL. PROP. L. REV. 187, 208-10 (2004); David S. Welkowitz, The Supreme Court and Trademark Law in the New Millennium, 30 WM. MITCHELL L. REV. 1659, 1697-1700 (2004). 63 See, e.g., Dinwoodie, supra note 62, at 208 (predicting that “the Court will find that the availability of a fair use defense is not conditioned on there being no likelihood of confusion”). 64 See, e.g., Braun, supra note 62 (speculating on the dangers of affirming the Ninth Circuit’s opinion). 65 Id. 66 To disprove confusion, a defendant “would have to conduct a survey and/or go to trial to prove an absence of likelihood of confusion.” Id. This would create suits that are “longer and more costly.” Id. 67 KP Permanent Make-Up, Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc., 543 U.S. 111, 114 (2004). The Court noted that both used the term “as one word or two, singular or plural.” Id. 1676 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 “Micro Colors” written in a small graphic. 68 KP, however, continued to use the word “microcolor” to describe its goods, and, in response to a ten-page advertising brochure put out by KP in 1999, Lasting Impression requested that KP discontinue its use of the term. 69 This led to a lawsuit in which Lasting Impression alleged trademark infringement, among other claims, and KP asserted the statutory fair use defense. 70 The district court granted KP’s motion for summary judgment, finding that KP’s use of “microcolors” was fair, but declined to address the question of whether confusion may result. 71 On appeal, the Ninth Circuit reversed, criticizing the lower court’s failure to address the issue of confusion, and remanded to determine whether a likelihood of confusion existed. 72 The Ninth Circuit also appeared to place the burden of proof as to confusion upon KP. 73 The Supreme Court granted KP’s petition for certiorari to address the disagreement among the circuit courts on the relevance of likely confusion to a fair use defense and to determine which party bears the burden in proving confusion or the absence thereof. 74 2. The Supreme Court’s Decision Justice Souter delivered the opinion for the unanimous Supreme Court, holding that the party claiming fair use does not bear the burden of negating the likelihood of confusion. 75 This did not come as a surprise, since the Ninth Circuit stood alone in suggesting that the defendant bears that burden. 76 In 68 Id. at 114-15. Id. at 115. 70 Id. 71 KP Permanent Make-Up, Inc. v. Lasting Impression, Inc., No. CV-0000276-GLT (C.D. Cal. May 16, 2001). Author’s note: There is some confusion, no pun intended, as to the full name of Lasting Impression. While at the circuit court and Supreme Court levels, they are referred to as “Lasting Impression I, Inc.,” at the district court level, they are referred to as “Lasting Impression, Inc.” 72 KP Permanent Make-Up, Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc., 328 F.3d 1061, 1072-73 (9th Cir. 2003), vacated, 543 U.S. 111 (2004). 73 Id. at 1072 (stating that “KP can only benefit from the fair use defense if there is no likelihood of confusion between KP’s use of the term ‘micro color’ and Lasting’s mark”). 74 KP Permanent, 543 U.S. at 116 (granting certiorari “to address a disagreement among the Courts of Appeals on the significance of likely confusion for a fair use defense to a trademark infringement claim”). 75 Id. at 112 (noting that the Lanham Act “places a burden of proving likelihood of confusion (that is, infringement) on the party charging infringement”). 76 KP Permanent, 328 F.3d at 1072. 69 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1677 answering the more important question of the relationship of confusion to the fair use defense, 77 Justice Souter created, ironically enough, greater confusion for lower courts addressing the statutory fair use defense. 78 The Court did make clear that fair use could prevail in the face of confusion but gave no guidance as to just how much confusion would defeat the defense of fair use. 79 In addition, the Court acknowledged that lower courts may consider likelihood of confusion when determining whether a use is fair. 80 It is also worth noting that the Court did not give any indication as to whether its analysis was applicable to nominative fair use. 81 Given this backdrop, the Court left open the door for the circuit courts to create their own balancing tests for determining the success or failure of a fair use defense when faced with a likelihood of confusion. E. Fair Use in the Post-KP Permanent World In the first year after the Supreme Court’s decision in KP Permanent, only a few courts have addressed fair use claims, and these decisions demonstrate the lack of guidance that the Court’s decision provided for the lower courts. 82 While courts currently recognize that the plaintiff bears the burden in proving a likelihood of confusion and that fair use can exist in the face of confusion, 83 the role that confusion plays in a fair use defense, particularly in the nominative fair use context, 84 has left courts without direction. 77 KP Permanent, 543 U.S. at 120-23. See discussion infra Part I.E. 79 KP Permanent, 543 U.S. at 123 (holding that while “mere risk of confusion will not rule out fair use, we think it would be improvident to go further in this case”). 80 Id. at 115 n.3 (refusing to address nominative fair use because it is not “relevant to the question before us”). 81 For one case which discusses the effect of KP Permanent on a nominative fair use case, see Century 21 Real Estate Corp. v. Lendingtree, Inc., 425 F.3d 211 (3d Cir. 2005). See also discussion infra Part I.E. 82 This note will discuss three cases which provide particularly good examples of the problems created by the Supreme Court’s decision in KP Permanent. See discussion infra notes 85-107 and accompanying text. 83 See, e.g., KP Permanent Make-up, Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc., 408 F.3d 596, 607 (9th Cir. 2005) (recognizing that a defendant raising the fair use defense “has no independent burden to negate the likelihood of any confusion” and that “fair use can occur along with some degree of confusion”) (quoting KP Permanent, 543 U.S. at 123-24); New York Mercantile Exch., Inc. v. Intercontinentalexchange, Inc., 389 F. Supp. 2d 527, 546 (S.D.N.Y. 2005) (same). 84 See, e.g., Century 21, 425 F.3d at 214 (3d Cir. 2005) (addressing a nominative fair use claim after KP Permanent and determining “the extent to which its reasoning applies”). 78 1678 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 On remand, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals reassessed the merits of KP’s fair use claim but again denied their motion for summary judgment. 85 Even after the Supreme Court had vacated the Ninth Circuit’s decision, the lower court came to the exact same conclusion, 86 demonstrating just how much leeway the Supreme Court had left for lower courts to work with. In fact, with regards to how much confusion precludes the fair use defense, the Ninth Circuit expressly recognized that the Supreme Court gave lower courts the authority to determine the relationship between the two. 87 The circuit court then proceeded to address both the likelihood of confusion and the fair use defense 88 and found that the jury should consider likelihood of confusion when addressing the fairness of the use. 89 Therefore, the court again concluded that the district court’s granting of KP’s motion for summary judgment was improper. 90 The Ninth Circuit’s decision creates a great problem for judicial efficiency. Since a plaintiff must prove some material issue of fact as to the likelihood of confusion before a defendant asserts fair use, 91 there will never be an occasion to grant a defendant summary judgment on a fair use claim under this approach. In other words, because a plaintiff has, in theory, already established a genuine issue of material fact as to confusion by the time a defendant asserts fair use, there will always be a genuine issue of material fact in a fair use claim. In another recent case, New York Mercantile Exchange, Inc. v. Intercontinentalexchange, Inc., 92 the Southern District of New York was given the opportunity to offer its interpretation of “classic” fair use after the Supreme Court’s decision in KP Permanent. That case involved, among many claims, 85 KP Permanent, 408 F.3d at 609. Id. 87 Id. at 607 (stating that the issue of how much confusion precludes the fair use defense “was left for the consideration of the Ninth Circuit in this case”). 88 Id. at 608-09. The court held that “the degree of consumer confusion remains a factor in evaluating fair use.” Id. at 609. 89 Id. (finding likelihood of confusion “[a]mong the relevant factors for consideration by the jury in determining the fairness of the use”). 90 Id. Author’s note: The district court has yet to hear this case on remand as of the writing of this note. 91 See supra note 41 and accompanying text. See also KP Permanent MakeUp, Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc., 543 U.S. 111, 120 (2004) (stating that “it is only when a plaintiff has shown likely confusion by a preponderance of the evidence that a defendant could have any need of an affirmative defense”). 92 389 F. Supp. 2d 527 (S.D.N.Y. 2005). 86 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1679 allegations of trademark infringement to which the defendant asserted the classic fair use defense. 93 New York Mercantile Exchange (“NYMEX”), a commodities futures exchange, brought a suit against Intercontinentalexchange (“ICE”), an online competitor, for ICE’s unauthorized use of NYMEX’s service marks. 94 NYMEX asserted that ICE could not claim fair use in the face of confusion, apparently overlooking the Supreme Court’s decision in KP Permanent. 95 Oddly enough, NYMEX had never offered any evidence to allege actual confusion or even a likelihood of confusion. 96 The court granted ICE’s motion for summary judgment due to the lack of confusion, and never reached the merits of the fair use claim. 97 In any event, this opinion still bears some significance on the state of classic fair use following KP Permanent. While the Southern District of New York correctly concluded that fair use could co-exist with confusion, the court seemed to suggest that if a defendant establishes fair use on the merits, any confusion is irrelevant. 98 Finally, in Century 21 Real Estate Corporation v. Lendingtree, Inc., 99 the Third Circuit Court of Appeals offered its interpretation of the Supreme Court’s decision in KP Permanent as it relates to nominative fair use. The Third Circuit adopted an original two-step approach to nominative fair use cases quite similar to the approach followed in the “classic” fair use cases. 100 The first step requires the plaintiff to prove a likelihood of confusion from defendant’s use of the 93 Id. at 529. Id. 95 Id. at 546 (noting that the cases upon which NYMEX relies “predate . . . the Supreme Court’s decision in KP Permanent Make-Up”). 96 Id. (recognizing that “NYMEX has not raised any issue of material fact that a likelihood of confusion exists” and “offered no evidence [of] actual customer confusion”) (emphasis added). 97 Id. 98 See New York Mercantile Exch., 389 F. Supp. 2d at 545 (stating that NYMEX’s assertion that fair use cannot exist in the face of confusion is “wrong as a matter of law”). It is questionable as to how the court would have ruled if faced with evidence of confusion as it did make sure to point out that no confusion was alleged nor did any exist. Id. at 546. Nonetheless, the language in this portion of the opinion suggests that the court had no reservations about upholding a use as fair in the face of confusion. Id. at 545. 99 425 F.3d 211 (3d Cir. 2005). 100 Id. at 222 (“Today we adopt a two-step approach in nominative fair use cases.”). 94 1680 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 mark. 101 Once the plaintiff meets this burden, the defendant can assert fair use, which the court analyzes under the threepronged nominative fair use test. 102 The dissenting judge in this case found the majority’s new test to create too heavy a burden on the defendant, as he would likely bear the burden of negating confusion. 103 This opinion also found critics amongst some of intellectual property law’s foremost legal scholars. 104 J. Thomas McCarthy, author of one of the leading treatises on trademark law and founder of the McCarthy Institute for Intellectual Property and Technology Law at the University of San Francisco School of Law, commented, “I’ve spent many decades studying trademark law, and this is one of the most confusing cases I’ve seen . . . .” 105 Since nominative fair use is entirely judge-made law, these cases provide the sole framework to such claims and bear great significance. The Third Circuit, while well-intentioned, may not have put forth the best approach. The only other case to address nominative fair use after the Court’s decision in KP Permanent did not alter the prior nominative fair use test 106 as defined in the Ninth Circuit. 107 All of these cases following KP Permanent demonstrate the need for the Court or Congress to clarify the relationship between confusion and fair use in trademark law. II. COPYRIGHT AND FAIR USE Similar to trademark law, courts in copyright cases have historically protected certain unauthorized but fair uses of protected material from claims of infringement. 108 Copyright 101 Id. While the plaintiff must show a likelihood of confusion, the court suggested altering the traditional test for likelihood of confusion by eliminating certain factors of the test “that do not ‘fit’ in the nominative use context.” Id. 102 Id. For the three factors of the nominative fair use test, see New Kids on the Block v. News Am. Publ’g, Inc., 971 F.2d 302, 308 (9th Cir. 1992). 103 Century 21, 425 F.3d at 233 (Fisher, J., dissenting) (concluding that the majority’s test “places on defendant the burden of negating likely confusion”). 104 See G.M. Filisko, Trademark Ruling Creates Confusion, 4-43 ABA JOURNAL E-REPORT 2 (Oct. 21, 2005). 105 Id. 106 See Ty, Inc. v. Publ’ns Int’l, Ltd., No. 99-C-5565, 2005 WL 464688, at *6 (N.D. Ill. Feb. 25, 2005) (noting that even after KP Permanent, “[t]he New Kids test provides sound criteria for assessing when nominative use is fair or unfair, despite a likelihood of confusion among consumers). 107 See New Kids on the Block, 971 F.2d at 308. 108 For what is regarded as, perhaps, the first discussion of a fair use claim in copyright, see Folsom v. Marsh, 9 F. Cas. 342, 344-45 (C.C.D. Mass. 1841) (No. 4,901). 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1681 law seeks to protect “original works of authorship” such as a song, a book, or a photograph. 109 The roots of this protection are well-grounded in United States history, as the Constitution empowers Congress “[t]o promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.” 110 In order for a work to be protected, it must consist of some amount of originality and creativity. 111 Copyright infringement requires the exact copying of a protected work or proof of substantial similarity and access to the copyrighted work. 112 The term “fair use” made its first appearance in a copyright opinion in 1869, when an author borrowed material from an earlier publication of a work while scripting a new edition. 113 For over 100 years, the fair use doctrine existed entirely in judge-made law. In the mid-1970s, Congress codified the doctrine of fair use in the Copyright Act of 1976. 114 The Copyright Act permits fair use to operate as an affirmative defense to a claim of infringement if, after looking at four statutory factors and balancing their equities, the court deems the use as fair. 115 The factors to which the court must look are: (1) the purpose and character of the use; (2) the nature of the copyrighted work; (3) the amount and substantiality of the portion used; and (4) the effect of the use on the potential market or value of the copyrighted work. 116 These four factors are not exclusive and often overlap when courts decide whether use is fair. Although there is no prescribed formula to determine fair use, some uses garner a stronger likelihood of success than others in a fair use claim. 117 In Folsom, an author of a biography on President Washington had borrowed material from an earlier work, mainly letters written by George Washington himself. Id. at 343. The court asked “whether this is a justifiable use of the original materials.” Id. at 348. In determining whether the use was fair, Justice Story looked to “the nature and objects of the selections made, the quantity and value of the materials used, and the degree in which the use may prejudice the sale, or diminish the profits, or supersede the objects, of the original work.” Id. 109 17 U.S.C. § 102(a) (2000). 110 U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 8. 111 See Feist Publ’ns, Inc. v. Rural Tel. Serv., Inc., 499 U.S. 340, 345 (1991). 112 Lipton v. Nature Co., 71 F.3d 464, 470-71 (2d Cir. 1995). 113 Lawrence v. Dana, 15 F. Cas. 26, 44 (C.C.D. Mass. 1869) (No. 8,136). 114 17 U.S.C. § 107 (2000). 115 Id. 116 Id. 117 See discussion infra Part II.A and Part II.B. 1682 A. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Purpose and Character of Use Under the first factor of the fair use test, courts look at the purpose and character of the use. 118 Alleged infringing uses can be divided into two sub-categories: (1) transformative or non-transformative use; and (2) commercial or non-commercial use. 119 Courts generally do not extend the fair use doctrine to commercial, non-transformative uses, because such uses contain no originality and seek to reap where one has not On the other hand, if a non-commercial use sown. 120 significantly transforms a work, courts will generally uphold the use as fair. 121 A more difficult situation arises when use is transformative but commercial, or non-transformative but noncommercial, and courts have faced a significantly greater challenge in determining whether use is fair in these situations. In Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc. (“Acuff-Rose”), the United States Supreme Court held that although the rap group 2 Live Crew created a parody of Roy Orbison’s “Oh, Pretty Woman” for commercial gain, they had significantly transformed the song, and therefore, fair use could prevail. 122 The holders of the copyright to the famous Roy Orbison song had sued 2 Live Crew, alleging infringement, suggesting that the commercial use of the song constituted a presumptively unfair use of a copyrighted work. 123 Although the Court of Appeals concluded that the fair use defense was barred by the song’s commercial character and excessive borrowing, 124 the Supreme Court reversed with Justice Stevens writing the opinion for a unanimous Court. 125 118 17 U.S.C. § 107(1) (2000). See 17 U.S.C. § 107(1) (2000) (assessing “whether such use is of a commercial nature”); Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 579 (1994) (stating that in assessing the purpose of the use, courts should also consider “whether and to what extent the new work is ‘transformative’”). 120 See Sony Corp. of Am. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 449 (1984) (noting that if an alleged infringer copied a protected work for commercial gain, “such use would presumptively be unfair”). 121 See Acuff Rose, 510 U.S. at 579 (stating that “the more transformative the new work, the less will be the significance of other factors . . . that may weigh against a finding of fair use”). 122 Acuff-Rose, 510 U.S. at 594. 123 Id. at 572-74. 124 Acuff-Rose Music, Inc. v. Campbell, 972 F.2d 1429, 1439 (6th Cir. 1992), rev’d by, 510 U.S. 569 (1994). 125 Acuff-Rose, 510 U.S. at 594. 119 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1683 In analyzing the first factor of the fair use defense, Justice Stevens drew implicitly upon free speech principles, ignoring the strong sexual content and illicit language in 2 Live Crew’s song. 126 Although the lyrics of 2 Live Crew’s song contained “degrading taunts, a bawdy demand for sex, and a sigh of relief from paternal responsibility” which would surely make the members of the Court cringe, they nonetheless upheld the use as fair. 127 Warning that “[t]his is not, of course, to say that anyone who calls himself a parodist can skim the cream and get away scot free,” Justice Stevens rested the pinnacle of the Court’s holding on the transformative character of the use, since 2 Live Crew “departed markedly” from the lyrics in the Roy Orbison classic. 128 In a similarly murky area of the first factor of the fair use test lies the non-transformative, yet non-commercial use, such as that in Sony Corporation of America v. Universal City Studios, Inc. (“Sony”), which involved the introduction of the home videotape recorder in America. 129 In Sony, copyright holders in the television industry brought a suit against the Since the manufacturers of home videotape recorders. 130 purchasers of such devices could use them to record protected works, the copyright holders opposed the sale of the devices, alleging infringement, based on the non-transformative use. 131 The Court acknowledged that if consumers used the devices to make a profit, the fair use defense would not apply. 132 The Court, however, characterized the use as non-commercial since most purchasers of the device simply sought to watch their favorite programs at different times. 133 Arguably, the Court could have found the use commercial, but chose instead to focus on the time-shifting, 134 which held no commercial purpose. 135 126 Id. at 582 (stating that “[w]hether . . . parody is in good taste or bad does not and should not matter to fair use”). 127 See id. at 583. 128 Id. at 589 (stating that “2 Live Crew not only copied the first line of the original, but thereafter departed markedly from the Orbison lyrics for its own ends”). 129 Sony Corp. of Am. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 417 (1984). 130 Id. 131 Id. at 420. 132 Id. at 449 (stating that “to make copies for a commercial or profit-making purpose . . . would presumptively be unfair”). 133 Id. (characterizing “time-shifting for private home use . . . as a noncommercial, nonprofit activity”). 134 Time-shifting refers to the idea that users of a home video recording device simply shift the time at which they watch programs. Id. at 421. 135 See Sony, 464 U.S. at 449-50. 1684 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Both the Court’s decision in Acuff-Rose and Sony demonstrated the complexity in analyzing fair use claims. The Court indicated that they would not create any per se rules for determining whether use is fair. 136 In Acuff-Rose, even a commercial use could potentially survive a claim of infringement, 137 while in Sony, a non-transformative use had equivalent success. 138 B. The Nature of the Copyrighted Work Under the second factor of the fair use test, courts examine the nature of the copyrighted work. 139 Similar to the first factor, courts divide the copyrighted work into two subcategories: (1) factual or fictional; and (2) published or unpublished. 140 Use of factual, published works, such as the news, garners the strongest likelihood of success on a fair use defense. 141 At the opposite end of the spectrum, use of fictional, published works typically fails on a fair use defense. 142 The question of fair use, however, becomes more difficult when the Court faces factual, yet unpublished accounts. In Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enterprises (“Harper & Row”), authors of the soon-to-be-published memoirs of former President Gerald Ford brought a suit against a magazine that had published portions of the work after receiving an illicit copy from an undisclosed source. 143 Although the District Court rejected the magazine’s fair use claim, the 136 Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 577 (1994) (declaring that fair use “is not to be simplified with bright-line rules”); Sony, 464 U.S. at 448 (referring to copyright fair use as an “equitable rule of reason” (citation omitted)). 137 Acuff-Rose, 510 U.S. at 589. 138 Sony, 464 U.S. at 456. 139 17 U.S.C. § 107(2) (2000). 140 See Stewart v. Abend, 495 U.S. 207, 237-38 (1990) (recognizing the distinction between factual and fictional works as highly relevant to a fair use analysis); Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 564 (1985) (noting that whether or not a work is published or unpublished “is a critical element of its ‘nature’” (citations omitted)). 141 See, e.g., Abend, 495 U.S. at 237 (stating that “fair use is more likely to be found in factual works than in fictional works”). 142 See, e.g., Castle Rock Entm’t, Inc. v. Carol Publ’g Group, Inc., 150 F.3d 132, 143-44 (2d Cir. 1998) (finding that “the scope of fair use is somewhat narrower with respect to fictional works”); see also Twin Peaks Prods., Inc. v. Publications Int’l, Ltd., 996 F.2d 1366, 1376 (2d Cir. 1993) (stating that the second factor “favor[s] . . . creative and fictional work[s]”). 143 Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 542. 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1685 Second Circuit upheld the use as fair. 144 Justice O’Connor, writing for the majority, reversed the decision of the Second Circuit. 145 In analyzing the nature of the copyrighted work, Justice O’Connor recognized the additional concerns when considering a fair use claim dealing with unpublished works. 146 In doing so, she acknowledged the value in the exclusive rights a publisher may have prior to publication. 147 Ultimately, the Court found that the magazine’s unauthorized and “clandestine” use infringed the copyright owner’s interests so much that the Court could not characterize the use as fair. 148 Again, the Court in Harper & Row seemed to focus on the freedom of expression values inherent in copyright law. 149 While the magazine had the right to publish material, such slavish copying was impermissible. 150 In addition, since the original work had yet to be published, the Court implicitly recognized the authors’ freedom of expression rights and the infringement that occurs when one “free-rides” on another’s original work. 151 144 Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 723 F.2d 195, 208 (2d Cir. 1983), rev’d by, 471 U.S. 539 (1985). 145 Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 569. 146 Id. at 564 (stating that “the scope of fair use is narrower with respect to unpublished works”). 147 Id. (noting the importance of “[t]he right of first publication” and “the choices of when, where, and in what form first to publish a work”). 148 Id. (denying the fair use defense since the use “so clearly infringes the copyright holder’s interests in confidentiality and creative control”). 149 For an example of the freedom of expression values found inherent in the fair use defense to copyright infringement, see Wainwright Securities, Inc. v. Wall Street Transcript Corp., 558 F.2d 91, 95 (2d Cir. 1977) (noting that “[c]onflicts between interests protected by the first amendment and the copyright laws thus far have been resolved by application of the fair use doctrine”). The Wainwright court went on further to state that “[w]hat is protected is the manner of expression, the author’s analysis or interpretation of events, the way he structures his material and marshals facts, his choice of words, and the emphasis he gives to particular developments.” Id at 95-96. See also Los Angeles News Serv. v. Tullo, 973 F.2d 791, 795 (9th Cir. 1992) (stating that “First Amendment considerations are relevant in determining whether the purpose of copying a work and the nature of the work copied militate in favor of finding a given use of a particular work to be a ‘fair use’”). 150 Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 565 (stating that “the fact that a substantial portion of the infringing work was copied verbatim is evidence of the qualitative value of the copied material”). 151 Id. (criticizing “the plagiarist who seeks to profit from marketing someone else’s copyrighted expression”). 1686 C. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Amount and Substantiality of the Portion Used The third factor of the fair use defense to copyright infringement requires the court to analyze the amount and substantiality of the portion used. 152 While again, there are no per se rules as to what constitutes too much copying, the courts generally view this factor as heavily related to the purpose and character of the use. 153 The analysis under the third factor differs amongst parodies, books, and other areas in which one asserts a fair use defense. 154 Even the reproduction of an entire work will not preclude a fair use defense in some situations, such as the time-shifting in Sony. 155 Similarly, courts might permit substantial quotations in a book review or a newscast recapping a speech, but not in an exclusive, yet-to-be published work. 156 In parody, the third factor also implicates the fourth factor, 157 since the borrowing inherent in parody may affect the market or value of the copyrighted work. 158 The Court in AcuffRose recognized the difficulty posed by parody, because parody must remind the listener or reader of the original in order to succeed. 159 Therefore, although a successful parody appears to patently fail the third factor of the test, if one “depart[s] markedly” and adds other “distinctive sounds,” a court may characterize a parody as a fair use. 160 152 17 U.S.C. § 107(3) (2000). See, e.g., Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 586-87 (1994) (stating that in analyzing the third factor, “attention turns to the persuasiveness of a parodist’s justification for the particular copying done, and the enquiry will harken back to the first of the statutory factors, for . . . the extent of permissible copying varies with the purpose and character of the use”). 154 See id. (analyzing the third factor in parody by “turn[ing] to the persuasiveness of a parodist’s justification for the particular copying done). But cf. Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 565-66 (analyzing the third factor in both qualitative and quantitative terms in the publishing context). 155 Sony Corp. of Am. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 449-50 (1984) (noting that the full reproduction of protected works “does not . . . militat[e] against a finding of fair use” when involving non-commercial use). 156 Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 564 (noting that “substantial quotations might qualify as fair use in a review of a published work or a news account of a speech”). 157 For a greater discussion of the fourth factor, see discussion infra Part II.D. 158 Acuff-Rose, 510 U.S. at 587 (stating that the third factor “reveal[s] the degree to which the parody may serve as a market substitute for the original or potentially licensed derivatives”). 159 Id. at 588 (stating that “[p]arody’s humor . . . springs from recognizable allusion to its object through distorted imitation”). 160 Id. at 589. 153 2006] D. FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1687 The Effect of the Use on the Potential Market or Value of the Copyrighted Work The final factor of the fair use test in copyright law analyzes the effect of the use on the potential market or value of the copyrighted work. 161 Traditionally, courts have placed the greatest weight on the fourth factor. 162 Courts typically limit fair use to copying which does not significantly affect the market of the copied work. 163 According to the Second Circuit, this fourth factor should strike a balance between the benefits to the public in permitting the use and the personal gains the copyright owner may receive in denying the use. 164 Generally, if an alleged infringing use significantly impacts or “corners” the market, the use will fail the fourth factor. 165 The facts of Harper & Row offered the Court an ideal opportunity to illustrate a use that fails the fourth factor. 166 Following Nation Enterprise’s unauthorized use of Gerald Ford’s soon-to-be published memoirs, Time magazine cancelled its exclusive deal with the publishers and refused to pay the $12,500 to which the two parties had already agreed upon. 167 Presented with this evidence of the direct effect the infringing use had on the market, the Court stated, “[r]arely will a case of copyright infringement present such clear-cut evidence of 161 17 U.S.C. § 107(4) (2000). 4 MELVILLE B. NIMMER & DAVID NIMMER, NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 13.05[A][4] (2005) [hereinafter NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT] (stating that the fourth factor often “emerges as the most important, and indeed, central” factor in fair use cases (citations omitted)). 163 1 id. § 1.10[D] (stating that fair use is limited to “copying by others that does not materially impair the marketability of the work that is copied” (citations omitted)). 164 MCA, Inc. v. Wilson, 677 F.2d 180, 183 (2d Cir. 1981). The MCA court also noted that “[t]he less adverse effect that an alleged infringing use has on the copyright owner’s expectation of gain, the less public benefit need be shown to justify the use.” Id. 165 See, e.g., Iowa State Univ. Research Found., Inc. v. Am. Broad. Co., 621 F.2d 57, 62 (1980) (finding with respect to the fourth factor that “ABC did foreclose a significant potential market . . . monopolized that market . . . [and] usurped an extremely significant market”). 166 See Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 567 (1985). 167 Id. 162 1688 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 actual damage.” 168 In denying Nation Enterprise’s fair use defense, the Court relied heavily on this fourth factor. 169 Although the fair use doctrine requires courts to examine all four factors of the test, courts often imply the potentially dispositive effect of the fourth and final factor, irrespective of the results of the other portions of the test. 170 Courts, however, must still rule on a case-by-case basis and consider all factors. 171 In copyright cases, this test gives courts significant guidance to address fair use claims in various contexts. Trademark law would benefit from similar articulation by the courts. III. WHY TRADEMARK LAW CAN BORROW FROM COPYRIGHT LAW There are distinct differences between what copyright and trademark law actually protect. 172 Similar motivations behind the desire to protect both, however, justify the idea that trademark law can borrow from copyright law. Not only does protection of both of these types of intellectual property seek to curb free-riding, 173 but it also creates economic incentives. 174 In addition, protection attempts to balance the competing public interests in fostering competition with the private interests in 168 Id. See id. at 569 (stating that “a fair use doctrine that permits extensive prepublication quotations from an unreleased manuscript . . . poses substantial potential for damage to the marketability of first serialization rights in general”). 170 See, e.g., Sony Corp. of Am. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 451 (1984) (stating that in the non-commercial context, fair use will fail if a copyright holder demonstrates that the use “would adversely affect the potential market for the copyrighted work”). 171 See, e.g., Lish v. Harper’s Magazine Found., 807 F. Supp. 1090, 1110-11 (S.D.N.Y. 1992) (fair use defense failed even though the fourth factor favored the defendant); see also Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 594 (1994) (while suggesting fair use on the first three factors, the Court remanded to allow the hole in the evidence with respect to the fourth factor to “be plugged on remand”). 172 Copyright protects the more tangible rights in music, books, and works of art. See 17 U.S.C. § 102(a) (2000). Trademark, in contrast, protects the intangible right of goodwill associated with a trademark owner’s product or service. See 1 MCCARTHY, supra note 3, § 3:2. 173 See Lee B. Burgunder, Trademark and Copyright: How Intimate Should the Close Association Become?, 29 SANTA CLARA L. REV. 89, 90 (1989) (stating that intellectual property law is “intended to increase the creative and distributional efficiency of market participants”). 174 See Park ‘N Fly, Inc. v. Dollar Park And Fly, Inc., 469 U.S. 189, 198 (1985) (protecting trademarks “encourages producers to cultivate the goodwill associated with a particular mark”); Stephen B. Thau, Copyright, Privacy, and Fair Use, 24 HOFSTRA L. REV. 179, 180 (1995) (protecting copyrights “create[s] economic incentives for creativity”). 169 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1689 protecting an individual’s property rights. 175 For example, if an individual is granted no protection for a copyright or a trademark, anyone can simply copy an artistic creation or source-identifying word or symbol and share in the success of its creator or owner. To avoid this free-riding, copyright and trademark law grant certain protections to owners of intellectual property. This, in turn, helps create economic The law, however, moves incentives to these owners. 176 cautiously not to over-protect these property rights, because this could inhibit competition or freedom of expression. 177 Therefore, these protections are not limitless. By creating the doctrine of fair use, both copyright and trademark law limit their protections to help safeguard other important societal values. 178 Both doctrines of fair use are heavily intertwined with the First Amendment’s protection of free speech. 179 Additionally, just as protecting intellectual property creates market incentives, 180 limiting protection has a similar economic rationale. 181 In copyright law, a significant part of the fair use defense requires courts to examine the effect the alleged infringing use may have on the potential 175 See ZOE HILDEN & BRIAN T. JAENICKE, FAIR USE OF TRADEMARKS: A LOOK KP PERMANENT MAKE-UP, INC. V. LASTING IMPRESSION I, INC. AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR TRADEMARK RIGHTS AND THE PUBLIC DOMAIN, at 3 (2005) (noting that protecting intellectual property often creates “a struggle between competing public interests – namely, consumer protection and incentives to social progress versus competition and the free flow of information – as well as competing private interests – namely, property rights versus individual free expression”). 176 See supra note 174. 177 See White v. Samsung Elecs. Am. Corp., 989 F.2d 1512, 1513 (9th Cir. 1993) (Kozinski, J., dissenting) (stating that “[o]verprotection stifles the very creative forces [intellectual property is] supposed to nurture” (citations omitted)); see also HILDEN & JAENICKE, supra note 175, at 1 (recognizing that “intellectual property rights [are] an obstacle to free competition [and] a hindrance to the free flow of information and ideas in the public domain as well as to the individual right to free expression”). 178 See 17 U.S.C. § 107 (2000); 15 U.S.C. § 1115(b)(4) (2000). 179 See Robert C. Denicola, Trademarks as Speech: Constitutional Implications of the Emerging Rationale for the Protection of Trade Symbols, 1982 WIS. L. REV. 158, 207 (1982) (noting that “extensions of the trademark monopoly must be tempered by the realization that unlimited control over the use of trade symbols will at times interfere with the exercise of basic first amendment rights”); L. Ray Patterson, Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use, 40 VAND. L. REV. 1, 36 (1987) (arguing that fair use is “the most important and far reaching” free speech constraint on copyright protection). 180 See supra note 174. 181 See Thau, supra note 174, at 186 (arguing that the Supreme Court stresses economic incentives when assessing fair use in copyright); see also HILDEN & JAENICKE, supra note 175, at 7 (recognizing that Congress codified the concept of ‘classic fair use’ “[a]s a means of avoiding the danger that commonplace phrases might be adopted as marks and become the exclusive property of private owners”). AT THE 1690 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 market or value of the copyrighted work. 182 Likewise, in trademark law, fair use allows competitors to use trademarks in good faith in their true descriptive sense to avoid monopolies on descriptive words which inhibit free competition. 183 This section will further explain the rationales behind intellectual property protection and fair use in order to justify incorporating principles of copyright’s fair use test into the realm of trademark fair use. The last part of this section will be devoted to the idea that trademarks, while designed to identify source, have begun to do work they were not originally meant to do. 184 For example, while at one time, a trademark was stitched on the inside of a shirt collar, trademarks are now often found as a part of the shirt itself, such as the Lacoste crocodile, 185 and consumers desire a visible trademark as a sign of status or style. 186 Although trademarks have traditionally been considered a quasi-property right, and not a tangible property right such as a copyright, these shifts might warrant reconsideration of the protections of trademark law. 187 A. Why Does the Law Protect Copyrights and Trademarks? The protection of copyrights and trademarks serves three main purposes: (1) to prohibit free-riding; 188 (2) to create economic incentives; 189 and (3) to balance the competing public 182 See 17 U.S.C. § 107(4) (2000); see also Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 566 (1985) (stating that effect on the potential market is “undoubtedly the single most important element of fair use”). 183 See 15 U.S.C. § 1115(b)(4) (2000). 184 See generally, Alex Kozinski, Trademarks Unplugged, 68 N.Y.U. L. REV. 960 (1993). 185 Most people immediately recognize a Lacoste shirt by the crocodile which adorns the outside of the item. For further illustrations, see the Lacoste website, http://www.lacoste.com (last visited Jan. 28, 2006). 186 See Kozinski, supra note 184, at 961 (recognizing the “growing tendency to use trademarks . . . to enhance or adorn [products], even to create new commodities altogether”). 187 Id. at 966 (arguing that this change should be confronted by amending the Lanham Act). 188 See Burgunder, supra note 173, at 90 (stating that intellectual property law is “intended to increase the creative and distributional efficiency of market participants”). 189 See Park ‘N Fly, Inc. v. Dollar Park And Fly, Inc., 469 U.S. 189, 198 (1985) (protecting trademarks “encourages producers to cultivate the goodwill associated with a particular mark”); see also Thau, supra note 174, at 180 (protecting copyrights “create[s] economic incentives for creativity”). 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1691 and private interests inherent in both. 190 In 1946, Congress enacted the Lanham Act 191 “to secure to the owner of [a trademark] the goodwill of his business and to protect the ability of consumers to distinguish among competing producers.” 192 Although state protections existed previously, 193 Congress felt that national protection was warranted to foster competition and ensure product quality by securing trademark holders with the benefits of a good reputation. 194 At the most basic level, these protections discouraged free-riders. 195 Without these protections, individuals could capitalize on their competitors’ previously established goodwill. For example, if a particular brand of shirt became popular, a competitor could simply attach that name to his shirts and instantly create a market for his goods. These protections also created an economic incentive for a trademark owner to establish a strong trade reputation and economic efficiency for consumers who can easily identify quality through the use of trademarks. 196 Trademark law, however, must avoid overprotection which might limit freedom of speech or hinder competition. 197 Generally speaking, the law disfavors monopolies, and if protection is absolute, competition or free speech can suffer. 198 190 See HILDEN & JAENICKE, supra note 175, at 3 (noting that protecting intellectual property often creates “a struggle between competing public interests – namely, consumer protection and incentives to social progress versus competition and the free flow of information – as well as competing private interests – namely, property rights versus individual free expression”). 191 15 U.S.C. §§ 1051-1141n (2000). 192 Park ‘N Fly, 469 U.S. at 198 (citing S. REP. NO. 1333, 79th Cong. 2d Sess., at 3, 5 (1946)). 193 See Federal Trademark Act of 1905, 33 Stat. 724 (trademark protection was a matter of state concern governed by the common law). 194 Park ‘N Fly, 469 U.S. at 198 (citing S. REP. NO. 1333, 79th Cong. 2d Sess., at 4 (1946)). 195 See 1 MCCARTHY, supra note 3, § 2:1 (stating that trademark is, in part, based on “the plaintiff’s interest in not having the fruit of his labor misappropriated”). 196 See Park ‘N Fly, 469 U.S. at 198 (protecting a trademark “encourages producers to cultivate the goodwill associated with a particular mark”); see also William M. Landes & Richard A. Posner, The Economics of Trademark Law, 78 TRADEMARK REP. 267, 267 (1988) (concluding that “trademark law . . . can best be explained on the hypothesis that the law is trying to promote economic efficiency”). 197 See supra note 190; see also 1 MCCARTHY, supra note 3, § 2:1 (noting that trademark protection “has traditionally been a battleground for competing policies”). 198 See, e.g., In re Morton-Norwich Products, Inc., 671 F.2d 1332, 1343 (C.C.P.A. 1982) (stating that “[o]ne who seeks to register (or protect) a product or container configuration as a trademark must demonstrate that its design is ‘nonfunctional’”); see also Cliffs Notes, Inc. v. Bantam Doubleday Dell Publ’g Group, 886 F.2d 490, 494 (2d Cir. 1989) (construing the Lanham Act narrowly when the First Amendment is implicated). 1692 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 Although copyright law protects a different type of property, namely creative works such as songs or books, 199 the principles behind protection are not all that different from those of trademark law. Copyright law also seeks to curb freeriding “by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.” 200 In doing so, copyright law creates strong economic incentives to create original works by granting authors a bundle of rights. 201 Again, similar to trademark law, copyright law’s protections are not limitless and sometimes yield to the protections of the First Amendment. 202 B. Why Does the Law Limit Copyright and Trademark Protection by Fair Use? Both copyright and trademark law limit protections through their respective doctrines of fair use. 203 In permitting some unauthorized, but fair uses, both areas of intellectual property law use similar economic efficiency 204 and free speech rationales 205 to justify borrowing. In trademark law, when a court determines that an alleged infringing use is fair, they are, in essence, telling the mark owner that this infringement will not cause unwarranted confusion and that barring the use would foster unfair competition and hinder free speech. 206 Similarly, in copyright law, when a court determines that an alleged infringing use is fair, they are telling the copyright holder that the use furthers innovation as it does not intrude 199 17 U.S.C. § 102(a) (2000). U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 8. 201 See 17 U.S.C. § 106(1)-(3) (2000) (granting copyright holders the right to reproduce their works, to prepare derivative works, and to distribute copies). 202 See Patterson, supra note 179, at 4 (arguing that “the copyright clause limits the power of Congress to grant copyright because it embodies free speech constraints”). 203 See 17 U.S.C. § 107 (2000); 15 U.S.C. § 1115(b)(4) (2000). 204 See Thau, supra note 174, at 186 (arguing that the Supreme Court stresses economic incentives when assessing fair use in copyright); see also HILDEN & JAENICKE, supra note 175, at 7 (noting that Congress codified the concept of ‘classic fair use’ “[a]s a means of avoiding the danger that commonplace phrases might be adopted as marks and become the exclusive property of private owners”). 205 See Denicola, supra note 179, at 207 (noting that “extensions of the trademark monopoly must be tempered by the realization that unlimited control over the use of trade symbols will at times interfere with the exercise of basic first amendment rights”); Patterson, supra note 179, at 36 (arguing that fair use is “the most important and far reaching” free speech constraint on copyright protection). 206 See discussion infra notes 208-14 and accompanying text. 200 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1693 too far into the original work and that barring the use would again hinder free speech and have adverse economic effects. 207 In permitting fair use of another’s trademark, the Lanham Act seeks to prohibit a trademark owner from having the exclusive right in a descriptive term which others may use to describe their goods. 208 The Supreme Court has long since acknowledged that an “absolute prohibition” against using another’s trademark would result in undesirable 209 The statutory fair use defense recognizes overprotection. that the public should retain rights in the use of language. 210 The law seeks to carefully balance the monopoly created by trademark protection with the protections of the First Amendment. 211 That is not to say, however, that the protections of the First Amendment alone justify a fair use defense. 212 While trademark fair use certainly intertwines freedom of speech concerns, a trademark owner’s rights need not always cease at the door of the First Amendment. 213 On the other hand, certain situations in trademark law directly implicate the First Amendment. 214 It is behind these driving principles that fair use in trademark exists. Fair use in copyright was derived upon similar principles, although its history runs much deeper. Upon drafting § 107 of the Copyright Act of 1976, Congress 207 See discussion infra notes 215-26 and accompanying text. Soweco, Inc. v. Shell Oil Co., 617 F.2d 1178, 1185 (5th Cir. 1980) (stating that fair use “forbids a trademark registrant to appropriate a descriptive term for his exclusive use and so prevent others from accurately describing a characteristic of their goods”). 209 Herring-Hall-Marvin Safe Co. v. Hall’s Safe Co., 208 U.S. 554, 559 (1908) (noting that such a restriction “would carry trademarks too far”). 210 Park ‘N Fly, Inc. v. Dollar Park And Fly, Inc., 469 U.S. 189, 215 (1985) (Stevens, J., dissenting) (declaring that “[l]anguage, even in a commercial context, properly belongs to the public” (citations omitted)). 211 Denicola, supra note 179, at 207 (stating that “extensions of the trademark monopoly must be tempered by the realization that unlimited control over the use of trade symbols will at times interfere with the exercise of basic first amendment rights”). 212 See Mutual of Omaha Ins. Co. v. Novak, 836 F.2d 397, 402 (8th Cir. 1987) (stating that “the protection afforded by the First Amendment does not give [an alleged infringer] license to infringe [trademark] rights”). 213 Id. (explaining that trademark rights need not “yield to the exercise of First Amendment rights under circumstances where adequate alternative avenues of communication exist” (quoting Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner, 407 U.S. 551, 567 (1972))). 214 Denicola, supra note 179, at 207 (stating that “[w]hen the trademark is utilized as a vehicle for the communication of ideas . . . constitutional interests can no longer be ignored”). 208 1694 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 recognized the judicial doctrine of fair use as “one of the most important and well-established limitations on the exclusive right of copyright owners” and “an equitable rule of reason.” 215 Courts have acknowledged this principle since as early as the nineteenth century when Justice Story declared that “[e]very book in literature, science and art, borrows, and must necessarily borrow, and use much which was well known and used before.” 216 In codifying these longstanding principles, Congress effectively protected an individual’s rights to free expression with limitations. The Supreme Court, in its application of the fair use test, has often evoked principles of free speech. 217 Under the first factor of the fair use test, 218 courts are typically more likely to protect transformative uses, which both foster creativity while at the same time protect free speech. 219 As the Court has recently noted, copyright law must balance the different interests at stake such as promoting creativity while still protecting copyright holders’ rights. 220 Copyright fair use also examines the market effects infringement may have, 221 as the fourth factor of the test requires courts to look at the effect of the use upon the potential market for or value of the copyrighted work. 222 The first and second factors of the test also implicate these concerns. 223 The analysis of the purpose and character of the use looks at whether a use is commercial or non-commercial, 224 215 H.R. REP. NO. 94-1476, at 65 (1976), as reprinted in 1976 U.S.C.C.A.N. 5659, 5678-79. 216 Emerson v. Davies, 8 F. Cas. 615, 619 (C.C.D. Mass. 1845) (No. 4,436). 217 Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 582 (1994) (declaring that “[w]hether . . . parody is in good taste or bad does not and should not matter to fair use”). 218 17 U.S.C. § 107(1) (2000). 219 See discussion supra Part II.A. 220 Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc. v. Grokster, Ltd., 125 S. Ct. 2764, 2775 (2005) (describing copyright claims as “an exercise in managing the trade-off” between “the respective values of supporting creative pursuits through copyright protection and promoting innovation . . . by limiting the incidence of liability for copyright infringement”). 221 See Thau, supra note 174, at 186 (suggesting that many of the Supreme Court’s recent copyright decisions involving fair use “turned on the role that fair use would play in copyright’s scheme of economic incentives”). 222 17 U.S.C. § 107(4) (2000). 223 See id. § 107(1)-(2). 224 See Sony Corp. of Am. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 449 (1984) (stating that “to make copies for a commercial or profit-making purpose . . . would presumptively be unfair”). 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1695 and the nature of the copyrighted work considers whether the work is published or unpublished. 225 Similar to the goals of trademark fair use, copyright fair use balances the interests at stake to determine when infringement is improper. 226 Therefore, it would make sense to examine copyright law when considering how to better analyze trademark fair use claims. C. The Expansion of Trademarks Beyond Source Identification Traditionally, trademarks serve primarily sourceidentifying functions. 227 More recently, however, societal trends have altered the landscape of trademark usage and provided an additional reason for reconsidering the limitations on trademark protection. 228 In today’s society, trademarks not only indicate source, but are also a desirable part of the product itself. 229 For example, some consumers purchase clothing, hats, and bumper stickers to show allegiance to a particular sports team, and the team’s trademark is not a source-identifier at all. 230 Trademarks can also represent status or fashion. Many clothing companies put their trademarks in highly visible places as a selling point for their merchandise. For example, Tommy Hilfiger emblazons their trademark on the outside of almost every item of clothing they sell. The trademark can even become the product itself, such as a rapper wearing a gold Mercedes-Benz hood ornament around his neck. Online retailers sometimes use a competitor’s trademark to generate search engine results or even to trigger 225 See Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 564 (1985) (acknowledging the value in “[t]he right of first publication” and “the choices of when, where, and in what form first to publish a work”). 226 See Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc. v. Grokster, Ltd., 125 S. Ct. 2764, 2775 (2005). 227 See 1 MCCARTHY, supra note 3, § 3:2. 228 See Kozinski, supra note 184, at 962-63 (arguing that these new trends “raise[] questions about whether – and to what extent – the law should protect trademarks”). 229 See Kozinski, supra note 184, at 961 (recognizing the “growing tendency to use trademarks . . . to enhance or adorn [products], even to create new commodities altogether”). 230 When one buys a New York Yankees t-shirt from a vendor in the parking lot at Yankee stadium, it is highly doubtful that he thinks the New York Yankees organization endorses this sale. 1696 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 pop-up advertisements. 231 As the role of trademarks expands, the law should consider what, of these new roles, trademark legislation should protect, and how to effectuate any potential changes. In the realm of fair use, trademark will benefit by expanding the current test and incorporating analogous aspects of copyright fair use and its considerably more comprehensive test. IV. INCORPORATING COPYRIGHT FAIR USE INTO TRADEMARK FAIR USE Given the changing landscape of trademarks 232 as well as the confusion following the Supreme Court’s take on fair use in KP Permanent, 233 courts must facilitate a better approach to assessing trademark fair use. Due to the similarities to copyright law, trademark law would benefit from looking to copyright’s fair use test, which courts have applied more consistently. Copyright fair use applies a significantly more comprehensive test to ascertain whether or not a use is fair. 234 If the factors of that test are analogized to the areas of trademark law which they most resemble, trademark law, too, will have similar consistency in the courts. While a copyright fair use claim involves a careful analysis of the original work, the alleged infringing use, and the market effects, 235 the Lanham Act only requires an analysis of the alleged infringing use to determine if the use is fair. 236 In KP Permanent, the Court suggested that if the alleged infringing use met the elements of the fair use defense, the defense could succeed even when there is consumer confusion. 237 Although the Court indicated that some level of confusion might defeat the fair use 231 See 1-800 Contacts, Inc. v. Whenu.com, Inc., 414 F.3d 400, 403 (2d Cir. 2005) (holding that a search engine’s use of a trademark to trigger advertising does not qualify as “use” of the mark under Lanham Act); but cf. Gov’t Employees Ins. Co. v. Google, Inc., 330 F. Supp. 2d 700, 704 (E.D. Va. 2004) (reaching the opposite conclusion). 232 See discussion supra Part III.C. 233 See discussion supra Part I.E. 234 In addition to the four factor test, the Court has also noted that additional factors can be considered. See Harper & Row v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 588 (1985) (Brennan, J., dissenting) (stating that the four statutory factors “are not necessarily the exclusive determinants of the fair use inquiry and do not mechanistically resolve fair use issues”). 235 See 17 U.S.C. § 107 (2000). 236 See 15 U.S.C. § 1115(b)(4) (2000). 237 KP Permanent Make-Up, Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc., 543 U.S. 111, 121 (2004). 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1697 defense, they gave no suggestion as to how lower courts can come to this conclusion. 238 By failing to give any guidance, the Court ignored one of the pinnacle justifications behind trademark protection: avoiding marketplace confusion. 239 In “classic” fair use claims, courts should consider more than just the nature of the alleged infringing use to better determine how much confusion would bar the defense. As it currently stands, the Lanham Act only requires that courts determine if the trademark is used descriptively, not as a trademark, fairly, and in good faith. 240 In reviewing these considerations, courts, in actuality, only assess the alleged infringer’s conduct and use. 241 This is similar to the first factor of copyright fair use, which looks at the purpose and character of the use. 242 One can only imagine what would become of copyright fair use if it only considered the first factor of the four factor test required by statute. 243 Trademark law also touches on the third factor of the copyright test which assesses the amount and substantiality of the portion used. 244 What the trademark test fails to consider, however, is a trademark owner’s rights, his use of the trademark, and how the alleged infringing use may affect the market. One of the most important considerations in copyright fair use is the fourth factor of the test which assesses the potential economic effects of the alleged infringing use. 245 In fact, both copyright and trademark fair use were constructed around goals of economic efficiency. 246 Without reviewing the trademark itself, its owner’s rights, and the economic effects in permitting or denying a defendant’s alleged infringing use, courts will ignore the primary concerns in creating the fair use defense in the first place. Courts hearing trademark cases should consider both parties’ use of the trademark as well as the respective markets 238 Id. See 15 U.S.C. § 1114(1)(a) (2000). 240 See 15 U.S.C. § 1115(b)(4) (2000). 241 See id. The considerations of the Lanham Act address only how the alleged infringer uses the trademark. 242 See 17 U.S.C. § 107(1) (2000). 243 See 17 U.S.C. § 107 (2000). 244 See id. § 107(3). 245 See id. § 107(4); see also 4 NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT, supra note 162, § 13.05[A][4] (stating that the fourth factor often “emerges as the most important, and indeed, central” factor in fair use cases (citations omitted)). 246 See discussion supra Part III.B. 239 1698 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 in which they sell their products, just as courts hearing copyright cases consider the nature of the copyrighted work as well as economic effects in permitting or denying fair use. In looking at the plaintiff’s use of the trademark, the analysis should not be all that different from a typical likelihood of confusion analysis. 247 Courts, however, should reexamine the likelihood of confusion in light of the fair use claim which may alter their conclusions. Courts can look at the strength of the plaintiff’s trademark as well as when it was registered juxtaposed to the defendant’s use of the trademark. A plaintiff who has had its trademark federally registered and in use for over ten years before a defendant incorporated the words into its advertisement should find itself in a much better position than a plaintiff who has just recently registered a trademark years after a defendant began using the words to market its product. 248 These two different scenarios would create entirely different economic effects, and if trademark fair use is based, in part, around such concerns, these types of facts must be considered. Economic effects cannot be properly addressed by simply analyzing a defendant’s use and bad faith. Copyright law reviews the plaintiff’s work, and in doing so, properly addresses economic issues. There is no reason trademark law should not follow that model for success. Trademark law could also subdivide the factors of its test to achieve more equitable results. In copyright law, certain uses will garner a stronger likelihood of success, such as transformative, non-commercial uses. 249 In trademark law, the Lanham Act does consider the transformative nature of the use by considering whether the alleged infringer uses the trademark descriptively and not as a trademark. 250 The statute, however, does not require that courts assess whether the use is commercial or non-commercial. 251 Trademark law can incorporate this inquiry by examining the relatedness of the goods or services between plaintiffs and defendants. Although courts hearing trademark cases already consider this factor when evaluating the likelihood of confusion, they should 247 See supra note 32. The latter situation is not all that different from the facts of KP Permanent, in which KP had used the words prior to Lasting Impression’s registration. See KP Permanent Make-up, Inc. v. Lasting Impression I, Inc., 543 U.S. 111, 114 (2004). 249 See discussion supra Part II.A. 250 See 15 U.S.C. § 1115(b)(4) (2000). 251 See id. 248 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1699 revisit the issue when assessing fair use. For example, a defendant may use another’s trademark in the sale of goods, which is unquestionably a commercial use. If the defendant sells breakfast cereal, however, and the plaintiff manufactures automobiles, the use might not be considered commercial as it relates to the plaintiff’s business. This additional consideration will speak to economic repercussions as well, since an automobile manufacturer can hardly claim that a cereal maker has adversely affected his business. Similar to copyright law, this additional consideration is not dispositive but simply assists courts in evaluating fair use claims. The dilution of trademarks should also be considered in the post-KP Permanent world as it applies to fair use. 252 Dilution occurs when a famous mark is misappropriated in a way that causes it to lose its distinctive value in the marketplace. 253 Since the Lanham Act requires a distinctive trademark as opposed to a descriptive one to generate a claim of dilution, 254 dilution is not applicable to statutory fair use, but often appears in nominative fair use claims. Some judges have already begun to blend copyright law with trademark law in dilution claims to achieve more equitable results. 255 When Mattel, makers of Barbie, brought a suit against the record companies who produced, marketed, and sold Barbie Girl, a song which poked fun at Barbie, Judge Kozinski of the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals upheld the defendant’s use under the nominative fair use doctrine, but in doing so, cited to a Perhaps Judge Kozinski’s opinion copyright case. 256 foreshadows the future of fair use in trademark law. In the area of nominative fair use, particularly parody, courts must look outside trademark law to find answers. A trademark in parody does not identify source at all, but rather calls the consumer’s attention to the parody through the use of a trademark. 257 Since copyright fair use has successfully and 252 See HILDEN & JAENICKE, supra note 175, at 22 (recognizing that “[i]t remains to be seen what diluting uses will nonetheless be deemed to be fair in the name of fostering free expression”). 253 See 15 U.S.C. § 1125(c) (2000). 254 Id. 255 See Mattel, Inc. v. MCA Records, Inc., 296 F.3d 894, 901 (9th Cir. 2002). 256 See id. at 901 (stating that “[t]he song does not rely on the Barbie mark to poke fun at another subject but targets Barbie herself”) (citing Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 580 (1994) and Dr. Seuss Enters., L.P. v. Penguin Books USA, Inc., 109 F.3d 1394, 1400 (9th Cir. 1997)). 257 Cliffs Notes, Inc. v. Bantam Doubleday Dell Publ’g Group, Inc., 886 F.2d 490, 494 (2d Cir. 1989) (explaining that “the keystone of parody is imitation”). 1700 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 71:4 consistently addressed parody, 258 those cases can provide courts hearing trademark cases with guidance when handling nominative fair use claims. 259 V. CONCLUSION Although some readers might criticize this “incorporation,” this Note does not purport to suggest a merging of copyright and trademark law but rather a consideration of copyright fair use to better facilitate consistent applications of fair use in trademark. The Supreme Court has already rejected a merging of the two areas of intellectual property, 260 but the type of incorporation proposed in this Note is of an entirely different nature. The suggestions of this Note are highly significant in assessing fair use in trademark and upholding the general policies behind intellectual property protection. Although some of this Note’s proposed fair use factors must be proven by the plaintiff, that does not mean that they are not relevant to a court’s inquiry into a fair use claim. Trademark law is based upon multiple policy concerns, and in order to properly address both traditional and new issues that arise with respect to trademark infringement, courts must balance all the interests at stake. 261 As copyright law has similar interests at stake, 262 the adoption of the analogous factors from copyright fair use into trademark law is a natural progression which will benefit the courts as well as both present and future litigants. Both copyright and trademark law have recognized infringing yet fair uses for years, but there are distinct differences in how the courts have interpreted these two doctrines of fair use. Copyright fair use requires a thorough analysis and considers both the original and infringing work as well as the economic repercussions. The trademark test for fair 258 See Acuff-Rose, 510 U.S. at 569. See generally Gary Myers, Trademark Parody: Lessons from the Copyright Decision in Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 59 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 181, 210-11 (1996). 260 See Dastar Corp. v. Twentieth Century Fox Film Corp., 539 U.S. 23 (2003). In Dastar, the plaintiff tried to use the Lanham Act to grant relief in what was essentially a copyright claim, but the work was in the public domain, and no longer protected by a copyright. Id. at 31. The Court denied the plaintiff’s attempt at relief. Id. at 38. 261 See Kozinski, supra note 184, at 977 (properly analyzing trademark rights “requir[es] one to balance interests that point in different directions”). 262 See discussion supra Part III. 259 2006] FAIR USE IN THE POST-KP PERMANENT WORLD 1701 use involves a much simpler inquiry focusing only on the infringing use. Copyright protection, however, has deeper historical roots than trademark, and courts have had more experience in handling copyright fair use claims. As technology blossoms and trademarks flourish, predictability in litigation becomes a necessity to business owners. The state of the law will affect business owners not just in litigation but also in their selection and use of trademarks. Trademark law as it currently stands does not delineate the factors of a fair use claim clearly enough to aid potential litigants. Since both copyright and trademark law share similar goals, it would follow naturally to allow trademark fair use claims to borrow from the principles of copyright fair use and create a clearer, more efficient test. Without better guidelines, both the courts and potential litigants will be wary of how to proceed. By incorporating principles of fair use in copyright, trademark can achieve its ultimate goal of avoiding confusion both in the marketplace as well as within the judicial system. Michael B. Weitman † † B.A., Boston University, 1999; J.D. candidate, 2007, Brooklyn Law School. Thanks to everyone at the Brooklyn Law Review for their endless efforts, Professor Samuel Murumba for helping me get this topic off the ground, Professor Christopher Serkin for his guidance, and my friends and family, especially Emily, for their love and support.