Reservation prices, resistance points, and BATNAs
Transcription
Reservation prices, resistance points, and BATNAs
In Theory Reservation Prices, Resistance Points, and BATNAs: Determining the Parameters of Acceptable Negotiated Outcomes Sally Blount White a n d Margaret A. Neale During the 1980s, bargaining and negotiation garnered considerable attention from researchers and practitioners in a number of different academic disciplines and professions. Much of the research and writing was directed toward improving the effectiveness of negotiators through case studies, theory development, and empirical research. Because a n u m b e r o f authors addressed this issue, o n e resulting difficulty is frequent confusion a m o n g other writers and their students in the translation o f theoretical and empirical concepts. One particular source of confusion is the distinction a m o n g reservation prices (Raiffa, 1982), resistance points (Walton and McKersie, 1965), and BATNAs (Fisher and Ury, 1981). The terms are often used interchangeably by negotiation scholars, and o n the surface, they seem very similar. They all represent the notion o f a lower bound, beyond which the negotiator will not settle. For negotiators in a selling role, that b o u n d translates into the lowest price that is acceptable. For negotiators in a buying role, it represents the highest price that is acceptable. In this article, we argue that, in fact, the concepts are different and that they represent three separate lower bound points that are salient to the focal negotiator at different points in the negotiation. As a starting point, we turn to the original attthors of each of these terms for definitions and examples. Background Resistance point. Research in industrial relations arid collective bargaining has provided many- o f the theoretical underpinnings and perspectives for current negotiation theory and research. A fundamental c o n c e p t taken f r o m this paradigm is the contract zone m o d e l p r o p o s e d by Walton and McKersie (1965). In this model, each party in a negotiation has an aspiration zone o f outcomes within which the final settlement, if" settlement is reached, will fall. A party's range of acceptable outcomes is typically depicted along a unidimenS a l l y B l o u n t W h i t e is a n e g o t i a t i o n s i n s t r u c t o r a n d doctoral c a n d i d a t e at t h e Kellogg G r a d u ate School o f M a n a g e m e n t , N o r t h w e s t e r n University, Evanston, Ill., 60208. M a r g a r e t A. N e a l e is t h e Helen a n d J. L. Kellogg D i s t i n g n i s h e d P r o f e s s o r o f D i s p u t e R e s o l u t i o n a n d O r g a n i z a t i o n s at t h e Kellogg School. 0748-4526/91/1000-037956.50/0 © 1991 Plenum PublistlingCorporation Negotiation Journal October 1.991 379 sionat scale. According to Walton and McKersie (1965), the extremes of the range are b o u n d e d by the party's resistance point, the least favorable o u t c o m e that is needed to satisfy one's constituency, and by the party's target, the best outcome that can be expected. The overlap of the various parties' ranges of acceptable agreements constitute the contract zone. Within this context, the resistance point is often viewed as the most salient aspect. It determines if impasse will occur. By definition, parties will not enter into agreements that fall below their least acceptable outcomes. Alternatively, if a party's target is exceeded, the patty should always agree to the proposal. Walton and McKersie (1965) describe three factors that influence the location o f the resistance point: (1) the lowest subjective utility est'tmate o f what is required by the negotiator's constituency; (2) the most pessimistic assumption about what is possible relative to the other side's objectives; and (3) the least favorable assumptions about the negotiator's bargaJl~ng skill relative to the negotiating opponent. BATNA. In the 1970s, negotiation theorists began to address a broader class o f situations than that o f collective bargaining. Because buyers and sellers in most two-party negotiations can choose their negotiating partners from a broad range of potential bargainers, researchers began to look at situations w h e r e alternative negotiated agreements could be pursued in the event o f impasse. Thus, w h e n Fisher and Ury (1981) wrote their ground-breaking b o o k o n negotiation, they emphasized the importance o f the negotiator's BATNA (Best Alternative To a Negotiated Agreement) in preparing for a negotiation. The key idea o f calculating one's BATNA is to determine, before entering a negotiation, w h a t is the best outcome that the negotiator can h o p e for if the current negotiation results in impasse. In the case o f a job negotiation, it may represent an alternative job offer. In buying a house, it could be an estimate of what a reasonable bid would be o n another house that interests you. A BATNA can also change over time. For example, as the seller of a house, the lowest price that you will accept today, given prevailing market conditions and what you paid for the house, might be higher than what you w o u l d be willing to accept t w o m o n t h s from n o w after placing a successful bid o n y o u r next home. In one-of-a-kind negotiations, such as for the sale o f a valuable painting or vase, a BATNA may simply represent an alternative investment option for your money. Fisher and Ury (1981: 104, 111) write that the BATNA is " t h e standard against w h i c h any proposed agreement should be measured" and that developing y o u r BATNA "enables you to determine what is a minimally acceptable agreement." Reservation price. Shortly after Fisher and Ury's (1981) publication, Raiffa (i982) wrote a b o o k that offered a m o r e analytical framework for conceptualizing negotiations, one that built off the framework that Xgralton and McKersie (1965) had introduced for collective bargaining. W h e n Raiffa (1982) transferred the contract zone model to a broader class o f negotiations, h e replaced the concept o f a resistance point with that o f a reservation price.~ A party's reservation price represents his or her m i n i m u m or m a x i m u m acceptable settlement price within the current negotiation, depending o n w h e t h e r the negotiator is a seller or buyer, respectively. To describe h o w the reservation price is determined, Raiffa (1982: 46) states: In the abstraction...each bargainer knows his or her resezwafion price, but has only probabilistic information about the other party's reset380 White a n d Neale Reservation Prices, Resistance Points, a n d BATNAs ration price. Very often in practice the parties have but an imprecise feel for their own reservation price and make no formal attempt to assess a probability distribution of the other party's reservation price. Further, he asserts that a negotiator's reservation price is influenced b y his o r her BATNA, but does not explicate the relationship b e t w e e n BATNAs and reservation prices. Raiffa (1982) defines the zone of agreement as the area b e t w e e n the parties' reservation prices. In the reservation price model, the likelihood o f settlement within the current negotiation is d e p e n d e n t u p o n the degree to w h i c h the parties' reservation prices overlap. If there is large overlap, the probability of settlement is high, although not guaranteed (Myerson and Satterthwaite, 1983). If there is little or no overlap, the probability o f settlement is low. Synthesis. From these b a c k g r o u n d summaries, it is clear that the BATNA, reservation price, and resistance point are very similar constructs. T h e y e a c h represent the notion o f a lower bound, b e l o w w h i c h the negotiator will n o t settle. A BATNA or reservation price represents a lower b o u n d that is defined relative to the environment surrounding the negotiation (e.g., the prevailing market or alternative investments). A resistance point represents a lower b o u n d , which is influenced by m o r e subjective calculations within the negotiation (e.g., perceptions o f b o t h parties' expectations and assumptions about relative bargaining skills). On the surface, the BATNA and the reservation price s e e m m o s t similar. Thus, in sorting out these concepts, the first question is: W h y should the negotiator not set a reservation price that is simply equal to his or her BATNA? We argue in the next section that in m o s t cases they should not be equal. Reservation Prices versus BATNAs Once a negotiator has entered into a bargaining situation, a value in reaching agreement clearly exists. If n o settlement is reached, the time a n d energy e x p e n d e d to complete the negotiation b e c o m e net losses. A negotiator should, therefore, prefer to complete the current transaction rather than e n d in impasse as long as the settlement price c o m e s within s o m e estimated transaction cost of his or her BATNA. This transaction cost equals the value the negotiator places on the time and energy that he or she w o u l d have to e x p e n d to find a n o t h e r negotiator or to enact s o m e guaranteed alternative outcome. Thus, f r o m a strict cost-benefit viewpoint, negotiators could "rationally" c h o o s e to accept outcomes that fall below their BATNAs in the f o r m o f a transaction-cost-adjusted value. It is this value that the "rational" negotiator should take into the negotiation and below which he or she should not settle. W h a t this reasoning suggests is that b o t h the BATNA and the reservation price are quantities that are fixed o n c e the negotiator enters into a negotiation, and the reservation p r i c e should be equal to the negotiator's BATNA plus or minus an estimated transaction cost, depending u p o n w h e t h e r the negotiator is in a buying o r selling role, respectively. 2 It is at his or her reservation price that the negotiator is truly indifferent between enacting that o u t c o m e and pursuing his or her best alternative agreement. With this clarification in hand, the next question is: In negotiations characterized by the presence o f alternative agreements, is the resistance p o i n t relevant as a construct separate f r o m the reservation price? Data in the following section suggest that, in fact, they are different. In practice, the p r e s e n c e o f a Negotiation Journal October 1991 381 concrete limit o n what negotiators " s h o u l d " accept, if seeking to maximize absolute outcomes, is not the only factor that seems to influence the negotiator's lower b o u n d in actual negotiations. S o m e P u z z l i n g Empirical F i n d i n g s Pinkley, Neale, and Bennett (in press) recently c o n d u c t e d a study to test the extent to w h i c h BATNA levels influence negotiated outcomes. T h e y used a two-party negotiation that required integrative problem solving. T h e y assigned subjects explicit BATNAs, w h i c h were c o n v e y e d in terms o f points that subjects w o u l d be awarded if they c o u l d not reach settlement w i t h their negotiation o p p o n e n t . (Thus, in this case, the BATNAs were set to equal the reservation prices, given negligible transaction costs.) These BATNA levels were varied. It was easier for negotiators w i t h low BATNAs to earn m o r e p o i n t s through settlement than impasse and harder for negotiators with high BATNAs. The results s h o w e d that BATNA levels t e n d e d to influence final settlements. However, they also s h o w e d that a substantial p o r t i o n o f subjects w i t h high BATNAs settled at prices b e l o w their BATNAs. This c h o i c e m e a n t that these subjects preferred settling and obtaining fewer points over declaring impasse and accepting m o r e points. Bazerman, Neale, Valley, Kim, and Zajac (in press) recently f o u n d a different result. In their study, several subjects preferred impasse w i t h zero r e t u r n (i.e., a BATNA of zero) to settling at an agreement that yielded small, positive returns. This study involved a distributive negotiation over the sale o f a house. Buyers were told that their o u t c o m e in the negotiation was equal to the difference b e t w e e n the final settlement price and $230,000, their assigned reservation price. In o n e condition, as m a n y as 11 out o f 88 negotiations resulted in impasse in the presence o f a relatively large bargaining zone. In this case, the negotiators c h o s e a return o f zero points over a positive negotiated settlement. Resistance Points v e r s u s R e s e r v a t i o n Prices Together, the above findings suggest that while BATNAs and reservation prices are prescriptive instruments that negotiators should identify ahead o f time and use, other factors within the negotiation influence actual behavior. If we return to Walton and McKersie (1965), their resistance point concept explicitly incorporates the notion of subjective utility and takes other interactive a.\pects within the negotiation into account (e.g., assumptions about the o p p o n e n t ' s bargaining skills). The findings o f the previous section indicate that negotiators may, in fact, often retranslate explicit reservation prices into perceived resistance points, and it is these resistance points that negotiators act u p o n in actual negotiations. These resistance points may be based u p o n explicit reservation prices, but other factors within the negotiation b e c o m e important as well. To make this distinction clear, consider the following example: Pat budgets to spend $200 o n a new suit and then goes out to the store. Pat tells the salesperson that he is looking for a new suit and w o u l d like to spend n o m o r e than $200. Thirty minutes later, Pat walks out having spent $250. Obviously, Pat was influenced by more than his budget w h e n he decided to buy the suit. Thus, an interesting question for inquiry is: What factors within a two-party negotiation influence the distance a n d direction between a negotiator's reservation 382 White a n d Neale Reservation Prices, Resistance Points, a n d BATNAs price (in this example, Pat's budget; in the earlier examples, the negotiator's BATNA) and the resistance point u p o n which the negotiator bases his or her final actions? The P~gblem with Dollars. The theoretical distinction that we are trying to draw here between reservation prices and resistance points parallels the distinction between outcomes and utilities that economists consider. T h e y assume that decision makers can translate actual outcomes into perceived units o f utility. They then base their analyses u p o n these units o f utility. Within this framework, the reservation price represents a pure o u t c o m e measure (i.e., dollars, points, etc.). The resistance point adds utility concerns to this measure. In practice, the resistance point/reservation price distinction is difficult to untangle for the behavioral researcher, as well as for the practitioner. First, the negotiator may not k n o w his or her reservation price. Often, it is only a vague sense of what alternative negotiations might yield or some targeted range o f outcomes (e.g., "i'd like to get $40 to $50 for my bicycle." ). Second, even if the negotiator does have an explicit reservation price, the negotiator still has to translate any utility concerns into units u p o n which he or she can a c t - - t h a t means that they have to be turned back into dollars. As a consequence, w h e n a negotiator identifies a reservation price (or o n e is assigned, as in the lab), there may be n o way o f telling, a priori, w h e r e the negotiator's resistance point is located relative to his o r her reservation price. One can gain evidence of its location only w h e n the limit imposed by the reservation price is violated--as in the Pinkley, Neale, and Bennett (in press) study, w h e n some negotiators rejected their explicit BKFNAs and instead chose lesser~alued, negotiated outcomes. However, this p h e n o m e n o n is infrequent. In the presence o f a moderately sized, positive bargaining zone between t w o parties, most settlements will fall o n the expected side o f the reservation price. Any variation may be easily rationalized as negotiator error. Thus, negotiation practitioners and researchers may easily overlook the distinction b e t w e e n reservation prices and perceived resistance points. The Social Interaction in Determining Resistance Points Thus far, we have argued that the resistance point is an estimate o f subjective utility, and it is this point u p o n w h i c h the negotiator bases his or her actions. In this section, we go o n to suggest that, while a negotiator may be capable o f calculating his or her BATNA and reservation price objectively, the same negotiator can fall victim to social cognitive biases that pervade the negotiation interaction w h e n determining his o r her resistance point. Just as m a n y researchers (e.g., Neale and Bazerman, 1991) have demonstrated that individual cognitive biases are likely to influence the individual negotiator's performance, we contend that social cognitive biases also affect the negotiation interaction. In this sense, the relationship between a negotiator's resistance p o i n t and his or her explicit reservation price is influenced by the social interchange within the bargaining situation. 3 Further, because o f its inherently interactive nature, the social interchange is affected by social cognitive biases. We present this algument by exploring psychological mechanisms that could explain w h y negotiators might choose either o f two types o f setdements that would appear irrational within a strict profit maximization framework. Such irrational settlements would include a negotiated outcome that results in lower returns than one's reservaNegotiation Journal October 1991 383 tion price or the choice to remain at impasse and accept zero return over the choice to settle and accept a positive return. The Choice to Settle B e l o w One's Reservation Price. T h e social cognitive literature suggests there might be a psychological cost o f uncertainty that negotiators will seek to minimize and m a y lead negotiators to settle b e l o w "rationally" calculated reservation prices. This psychological cost is derived f r o m the individual's need for structure. Kruglanski and Freund (1983) write: The need for structure is the need to have some knowledge on a given topic, any knowledge as opposed to confusion and ambiguity. A need for structure once aroused is assumed to have an inhibiting or freezing influence on the hypothesis-generation process because the generation of alternative hypotheses endangers the existing hypothesis or structure... Indeed, research evidence indicates that time pressure and the need to quickly reach a decision intensify the tendency to seek cognitive closure and to refrain from critical probing of a given seemingly adequate solution to a problem. Thus, the need for structure might lead individuals to focus o n l y o n the current negotiation and accept an o u t c o m e that they might not accept if they were considering the outcome from an internegotiation vantage point. For exampie, imagine the buyer of a house w h o becomes so focused u p o n reaching agreem e n t with the seller o f a particular house that the buyer loses sight o f the fact that there m a y be better values available o n the m a r k e t and ends up overpaying for the property. " I k n o w that I paid a lot for the house," the b u y e r might rationalize, " b u t I wanted a house just like that one, and I did not k n o w if I would ever find another one." The individual's psychological n e e d for structure could also explain a seller's willingness to accept little or n o profit over the uncertainty o f impasse. Many o f us have heard friends w h o have sold used cars say, "I k n o w that I could probably get m o r e f r o m a n o t h e r buyer, but I just wanted to get it sold!" Thus, the n e e d for structure m a y often lead to an irrationally strong desire for settlement. Once a negotiator has entered into bargaining with a strong desire for set° tlement, he or she may then choose behaviors in the belief that these behaviors are those desired by the other p a r t y in order for settlement to occur. Social psychologists refer to this as a process of expectancy confirmation. Expectancy confirmation is often linked to the idea o f a serf-fulfilling prophecy. Darley and Fazio (1980: 869), in writing about expectancy confirmation, assert that " the perceiver's expectation, c o m m u n i c a t e d through his or her action, can actually alter the behavior of the target in such a way that observers judge the behavior to be in accordance with the definition implicit in the perceiver's expectancy." Thus, the process o f expectancy conf'trmation suggests that negotiators w h o strongly desire settlement may, in fact, adjust their behaviors to m a k e settlement occur. These negotiators may seek to act in accordance with the perceiver's (i.e., the other negotiator w h o is less c o m m i t t e d to settlement) expectations. For example, our friend selling the used car might have m a d e a p r e m a t u r e concession o n price because he thought that w h e n the b u y e r did n o t r e s p o n d to his first offer, the buyer was uninterested, rather than simply reticent and thoughtful. In this sense, the n e e d for structure enacted through expectancy confirmation offers o n e explanation for w h y a negotiator m a y c h o o s e to settle below his or her reservation price. 384 White a n d Neale Reservation Prices, Resistance Points, a n d BATNAs The Choice to Accept I m p a s s e over a Positive-Valued Settlement. As ahxrady discussed, both transactional and psychological incentives exist that motivate negotiators to settle within the current negotiation. In the presence o f a positive bargaining zone, why, then, would negotiators ever knowingly c h o o s e impasse over settlement? One simple explanation is that they may not realize that a positive bargaining zone exists. Myerson and Satterthwaite (1983) have proven mathematically that there is "rational" cause for some negotiators to choose impasse based u p o n a probabilistic assessment o f the " t r u e value" the opponent places o n the good being negotiated. This analysis assumes that each negotiator knows his or her o w n "true value" o f the good and that value is unchanging (i.e., not influenced by other events that may transpire). W h e t h e r these assumptions are correct may d e p e n d u p o n the actual negotiation situation. However, adding the uncertainty of not fully knowing one's o w n reservation price to the other assumptions o f their m o d e l would further increase the probability- that the two negotiators might fail to locate a mutually agreeable settlement. While this explanation highlights an important structural aspect o f impasse, a s e c o n d - - a n d perhaps m o r e interesting perspective from a behavioral viewpoint--is the notion that impasse may result because one or m o r e parties knowingly chooses not to settle, even in the presence o f positive settlement gains. A number of researchers studying ultimatum bargaim'ng games (e.g., Guth, Schmittberger, and Schwarze, 1982) have found that many individuals will choose an impasse w h e n they perceive that their o p p o n e n t will get a m u c h better deal than they will. These authors suggest that this behavior is tile result of a violation of a perceived fairness n o r m o f equity or equality. Further, the work of Loewenstein, ]Taompson, and Bazerman (1989) suggests that individuals place lower utilities on the settlement of disputes w h e n they perceive that the o p p o n e n t will get more o f the available resources than they will. As the imbalance becomes greater, the disutility o f settlement (or the attractiveness o f impasse) becomes greater. This effect is heightened w h e n the negotiators do not like the other party. Taken together, the works just cited imply that individuals dislike perceived inequities within bargaining situations. W h e n excessive perceived inequity exists, individuals w h o place especially large amounts of disutility o n inequity may c h o o s e impasse over a positive outcome. The thought process may be, " I f I c h o o s e impasse, at least we both obtain the same outcome--nothing!" With this theoretical argument in mind, we return to Walton and McKersie's (1965) concept of an aspiration zone. Here, in addition to the resistance point, they also identify a target. The target is the best possible o u t c o m e that the negotiator can reasonably expect. We believe that Raiffa's (1982) approach underemphasizes the actual role o f targets in the negotiator's evaluative processes and argue that negotiators probably d o think in terms o f ranges rather than point estimates. For example, "I'd like to get $50 for my bike, but if I have to, I'll settle at $40." Within this context, the target (in this case, $50) is just as important an anchor for the negotiator, if not m o r e so, than the reservation price ($40). The literature o n cognitive anchoring (see Kahneman, Slovic, and Tversky, 1982) argues that individuals will adopt the most salient, available anchor and fail to adjust subsequent judgments adequately away f r o m that anchor. It is easy to imagine that the negotiator's illusions o f optimism and Negotiation Journal October 1991 385 control (Taylor and Brown, 1988), as well as the overconfidence bias (Einhorn and Hogarth, 1978), will lead the negotiator to anchor nlore heavily o n w h a t he or she would like to get (the target) than o n w h a t h e or she is willing to accept (the reservation price). If each negotiator focuses too m u c h o n targets, together they may fail to realize that a middle ground c o m p r o m i s e exists in which both parties will benefit. 4 Within a two-party negotiation, it is conceivable to imagine that o n e p a r t y might enter with a w i d e r aspiration zone than the other, d e p e n d i n g o n economic constraints, desire for settlement, cognitive m a n n e r for processing potential outcomes, etc. This means that one negotiator's entering target for setdement will be farther away f r o m the bargaining zone than the other party's. If we assume that first offers are correlated w i t h initial targets, the negotiator w i t h a wider aspiration zone is likely to make a m o r e extreme first offer. This negotiator is then also m o r e likely to m a k e larger concessions in p r o p o r t i o n to his or her starting offer, because he or she has m o r e space available for m o v e m e n t . The above argument suggests that a negotiator w h o s e aspiration p o i n t is further away from the bargaining zone m a y feel that he or she is m a k i n g m o r e concessions than the o t h e r party. This feeling may, in turn, lead to a perceived violation of fairness n o r m s (e.g., " I ' v e m o v e d $25 and he's m o v e d o n l y $5."). Subsequently, in line w i t h the findings of Guth, Schmittberger, a n d Schwarze (1982), we m a y expect impasse to result. Conclusion As argued above, three separate lower b o u n d points exist that are salient to the negotiator at different points in a negotiation. The BATNA, as Fisher a n d Ury (1981) define it, represents the value o f the negotiator's best alternative to a negotiated agreement. It is the best o u t c o m e that the negotiator can expect if the current negotiation results in impasse. The negotiator's reservation price equals his or her BATNA plus or minus any estimated transaction costs, depending u p o n w h e t h e r the negotiator is in a buying or selling role, respectively. This transaction cost is the value that the negotiator places o n the t i m e a n d energy that would be e x p e n d e d to find another negotiator or to enact a guaranteed alternative outcome. Both the negotiator's BATNA and reservation price values are calculated based u p o n e c o n o m i c considerations and should b e d e t e r m i n e d external to the actual negotiation. T h e y are influenced by prevailing m a r k e t conditions and alternative investment opportunities. The negotiator's resistance point is influenced by his or her reservation price, but it is also affected by m o r e subjective factors. It is this subjective resistance point u p o n w h i c h negotiators seem to base their actions. T h e negotiator's resistance point m a y be located above or b e l o w his o r h e r reservation price, depending u p o n utility preferences for agreement and o t h e r trade-offs. The resistance point m a y also change during the negotiation, d e p e n d i n g u p o n h o w the negotiator processes the interaction. This m o v e m e n t will c o r r e s p o n d to: (t) w h e t h e r the negotiator decides he/she likes his/her o p p o n e n t ; (2) his/her level o f c o m f o r t with uncertainty and n e e d for structure; and (3) his/her perceptions of w h e t h e r the negotiation is proceeding "fairly." Thus, while there are certain conditions u n d e r w h i c h the BATNA a n d reservation p r i c e m a y be close approximations o f o n e another, they m a y at best serve o n l y as initial anchors f r o m w h i c h the negotiator's true resistance point emerges. 386 While a n d Neale Reservation Prices, Resistance Points, a n d BATNAs The adoption o f this tlu°ee-part framework for understanding the negotiator's lower bound has a number o f interesting implications for the negotiations field. First, it provides analytical clarity for behavioral researchers w h o seek to study negotiator behavior. W h e n conducting studies of negotiated outcomes, differences among the concepts of the BATNA, reservation price, and resistance point should be understood and incorporated into analyses. Second, it suggests that practitioners should be aware of situational and interpersonal factors that can lead the negotiator to adjust or ignore his or her "rationally" calculated reservation price during negotiations. These factors include issues such as the need for structure, risk aversion, an interest in fairness, an interest in relationships, etc. Finally, the existence o f the subjective resistance point has theoretical implications in that the utility measures that negotiators use to make decisions are not necessarily ftxed by the environment surrounding the negotiation. While the anchor of a reservation price may be calculated based u p o n structural constraints (such as prevailing market conditions), the final range o f acceptable outcomes that the negotiator considers is influenced by the actual negotiation. This perspective is in direct contrast to current game theoretic analyses and the prescriptive advice of many negotiation scholars and practitioners. Game theoretic analyses assume that negotiator's utilities for outcomes are stable and may be determined in advance. Consequently, prescriptive negotiation models, based u p o n game theory (such as Raiffa, 1982), assume that negotiators can set and implement reservation prices u n h a m p e r e d by psychological factors. Clearly, the evidence presented in this article highlights the need for introducing a more descriptive c o m p o n e n t into both research and prescriptive models. Negotiators are influenced by the negotiation interaction, and it is this descriptive viewpoint that we propose as a next step in negotiations research. NOTES T h e ideas for this article were inspired by early conversations w i t h Robin Pinkley a n d s u p p o r t e d by the Dispute Resolution Research Center at N o r t h w e s t e r n University. T h e a u t h o r s w o u l d like to t h a n k an a n o n y m o u s reviewer for his c o m m e n t s o n a n earlier draft o f this article. 1. This concept is also closely related to theoretical e c o n o m i s t s ' n o t i o n o f a reserwation value (e.g., Nash, 1950). 2. T h e BATNA a n d the reservation prices are fixed p r e s u m i n g that s o m e aspect that defines t h e m does not change during t h e focal negotiation. For example, if I have a n o t h e r offer o n m y house, o t h e r t h a n t h e o n e I a m currently negotiating, b u t s u d d e n l y learn that that b u y e r is n o t financially stable, I w o u l d probably w a n t to adjust m y BATNA, as well as m y r e s e r v a t i o n price. 3. For the p u r p o s e s o f simplicity, this article deals o n l y w i t h situations w h e r e a n explicit reservation price is already k n o w n to t h e negotiator. This c o n d i t i o n allows us to u n t a n g l e t h e process o f reservation price d e t e r m i n a t i o n f r o m resistance p o i n t determination. In actuality, t h e processes are probably closely intertwined. An explicit reservation price m a y take the f o r m o f a guaranteed alternative positive o u t c o m e if settlement is n o t reached, i.e., an explicit BATNA. It m a y also m e a n a zero or negative o u t c o m e in the event of impasse. Each o f t h e s e cases is d e m o n s t r a t e d by t h e t w o earlier examples. 4. tt is possible for targets to c h a n g e d u r i n g a negotiation b a s e d u p o n n e w i n f o r m a t i o n that b e c o m e s available about attainable o u t c o m e s ; howeveL t h e typical n e g o t i a t i o n p r o c e d u r e will likely a n c h o r aspiration levels at o r b e l o w a negotiator's first o r o p e n i n g bid. Negotiation Journal O~-~ober1991 387 REFERENCES B a z e r m a n , M., Neale, Mo, Valley, K., Kim, Y., and Zajac, E. (In press). "The impact of agems and mediators on negotiator behavior," Organization Behavior a n d H u m a n Decision Processes. Darley, J. and Fazio, R. (1980). "Expectanc~¢ confirmation processes arising in the social interaction sequence:' American ~Psychologist 35: 867-881. E i n h o r n , H. and H o g a r t h , R. (1978). "Confidence in judgment: Persistence illusion of walidity." Psychological Review 85: 395-416. Fisher, R. and Ury, W. L (1981). Getting to YES. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Guth, W., S c h m i t t b e r g e r , P., and Schwarze, B. (1982). "An experimental analysis of ultimatum bargaining," Journal o f Economic Behavior a n d Organizations 3: 367-388. K a h n e m a n , D., Slovic, P., and Teersky, A. (1982). J u d g m e n t under uncertainty: Heuristics a n d biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. K r u g l a n s k i , A. and F r e u n d , T. (1983). "The freezing and unfreezing of lay inferences: Effects on impressional primacy, ethnic stereotyping, and numerical anchoring." J o u r n a l o f Experimental Psychology 19: 448-468, Loewenstein, G., T h o m p s o n , L., and B a z e r m a n , M. (1989). "Social utility and decision making in interpersonal contexts." J o u r n a l o f Personality a n d Social Psycholog~y 57: 426-44t. Myerson, R. and Satterthwaite, M. (1983). "Efficient mechanisms for bilateral trading" Journal o f Economic Theory 29: 265-281. Nash, J. F, (1950). "The bargaining problem." Econometrica 18: 155-162. Neale, M. A. and B a z e r m a n , M. H. (1991). Cognition a n d rationality in negotiation. New York: Free Press. Pinkley, R., Neale, M., and B e n n e t t , R. (In press). "Alternatives, reservation prices, and outcomes: The impact of alternatives to settlement in dyadic negotiations," Organization Behavior a n d H u m a n Decision Processes. Raiffa, It. (1982). The art a n d science o f negotiation. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Taylor, S. and B r o w n , J. (1988). "Illusion and well-being: A social psychological perspective on mental health." Psychology Bulletin 103: 193-210. Walton, R. E. and McKersie, R. B. (1965). A behavioral theory o f labor negotiations. New York: McGraw-Hill. 388 White and Neale Reservation Prices, Resistance Points, and BATNAs