Heraclitean Flux and Unity of Opposites in Plato`s
Transcription
Heraclitean Flux and Unity of Opposites in Plato`s
Heraclitean Flux and Unity of Opposites in Plato's "Theaetetus" and "Cratylus" Author(s): Matthew Colvin Source: The Classical Quarterly, New Series, Vol. 57, No. 2 (Dec., 2007), pp. 759-769 Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/27564109 . Accessed: 28/04/2014 18:55 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Cambridge University Press and The Classical Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Classical Quarterly. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 128.95.104.66 on Mon, 28 Apr 2014 18:55:35 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 759 NOTES SHORTER OF AND FLUX AND UNITY HERACLITEAN IN PLATO'S OPPOSITES THEAETETUS CRATYLUS1 flux Heraclitean a large plays in Plato's role Theaetetus and Yet Cratylus. Heraclitus himself did not hold anything like the Flusslehre of these dialogues.2 If this is true, then an explanation of the fact must account for both terms the philosophical of the dialogues and fragments ('How do the two thinkers differ?'), and for Plato's literary depiction of Heraclitus ('Why does Plato treat Heraclitus as he does?'). These are questions because significant subsequent philosophical Aristotle's doctrine of replacement one of notion the has flux played a large in role of the persistence of identity through change. conceptions an underlying to undergo the change?requiring subject its the basic property by opposite?reflects assumption: namely, of if a thing is changing in some way, it cannot also have its identity (idem-?ty) in terms of that change, but time of Aristotle, in terms only some of other that aspect is so deeply this assumption remains the same. By the rooted that in seeking to define a concessive to contrast he uses clause with participial change oo/cet etvat ev Si iSiov r? ravr?v Kal identity: rrjs ovoias fiaXiora ov r v ivavri v efvat to substance 'it is especially that oe/crt/c?v, peculiar ?pidfjLCu one in number, the same it is capable of and contraries' while being receiving one is same' and is another. 'one the (Categories 4al0-ll). Change thing; being substance (ouata) numerical Aristotle had plenty for of precedent this contrast. holds the same assumption. But first, Iwould does we As shall see, Plato's Heraclitus like to establish that the realHeraclitus not. I.HERACLITUS' the point Although has been made DOCTRINE would before,31 to present like of flux in Plato's dialogues for thinking that the conception some new reasons is not derived from Heraclitus not permit the considerable does interaction with literature any Space over Heraclitus' own view the sharp of flux. But since my controversy are two There is about let the following suffice. which Plato, images as examples: uses one B12 is the river, of course It has been (fr. DK)4. discussed in great depth Heraclitus. spawned by main point and antiquity Yet discussions involving in modern of flux?namely, comparison the in all its varying versions, times river that as the never almost of statement the of the two is enough make kvk?ojv, and has been taken both of Heraclitus' reference or to disqualify barley to in flux doctrine. alleged the other main image cocktail (fr. B125 DK). A the idea that the river fragment 1I on an earlier draft, and would for his helpful criticisms like to thank Prof. James Lesher Irwin and Gail Fine for stimulating my thinking on this subject. Profs. Terence 2 I write of G. S. Kirk, Heraclitus: in the minority tradition The Cosmic Fragments2 Heraclitus: Greek Text with a Short Commentary2 (Cambridge, 1962) and M. Marcovich, (Sankt flux for Heraclitus, and is represented preserve 2001). The majority Augustin, opinion would most 'Heraclitus: the river-fragments and their implications', Elenchos 20 strongly by L. Taran, 'On Heraclitus', AJPh 76 (1955), 339-40; W. K.C. Guthrie, 'Flux and (1999), 9-52; G. Vlastos, in Heraclitus', in A. P. D. Mourelatos Logos (ed.), The Presocratics. (New York, 1974); and C. Kahn, The Art and Thought of Heraclitus 1979), 147-53. (Cambridge, 3 Kirk (n. 2), 228. 4 I are spurious. that the other river-fragments agree with Marcovich (n. 2), 194-214 This content downloaded from 128.95.104.66 on Mon, 28 Apr 2014 18:55:35 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 760 SHORTER a flux teaches that is radical (more NOTES than explanatory fundamentally other any of way looking at the river) or global (that is, true of all things, not just rivers) or total (true of every aspect of the river, and if globally applied, then of other things too). Yet in both of the fragments, Heraclitus' language is carefully chosen to point out the of union paradoxical and stability flux: those 'Upon who into step same the different and still different waters flow' and 'The cocktail disintegrates in question is not motion of the two the fragments, unity moved.' flux The In these rivers, unless it is but motion of stability. simply, productive con is the hidden the truth, 'unapparent nection' (d(f)avr)s dppiovir], fr. 54 DK), which it isHeraclitus' self-appointed mission to reveal. The opposition of flux and stability is a starting point patent even to people likeHesiod (fr. 57 DK), to be subverted by the examples of the river and the cocktail. Flux inHeraclitus is always presented along with stability in the service of the unity of opposites; it is not an ultimate principle to which everything else must be reduced; not it does or things go 'all the way to their identity; is that point Without flux and in the case constitutes these is a mere the cocktail flux, down'; indeed, it does not of a threat pose the river them gives of disparate objects, collection and to our the cocktail, their character. respective without ingredients; of knowledge Heraclitus' flux, the river is only two slopes and a ditch: for things like cocktails and rivers, change or motion is what just them makes one 'numerically and the II. PLATO'S FLUX AND COMPRESENCE same'. OF OPPOSITES In Plato, by contrast, flux is not presented as half of a paradoxical unity of opposites; instead, both flux itself and the unity of opposites are considered as phenomena inherent in the nature can rise give the sensibles. two problems, These are nonetheless Plato vocabulary specific epistemological For of to the other), difficulties though clearly distinguished to describe the employs is, one (that each other by and the phenomena related from that arise from them. or sensibles, or forms per in flux (material things objects, in themselves. But this is not obvious. diachronic change of Plato's studies that repeat Aristotle's doctrine explanation Plato, undergoing the many solution although denominated to the problem the doctrine of of the flux of separated Plato had the sensible forms is world,5 indeed T. H. an impossibile) In response Irwin answer of forms are to as a that proposes a problem to was not the succession in mind in of properties saw the compresence that Plato Irwin of opposed Instead, suggests objects.6 as a species in sensible that it is this flux, and not of 'flux', and objects properties to and In which Plato avoid stable forms. immaterial succession, by positing sought 'flux', the flux sensible 5 Metaph. Heraclitean 'From his youth and the a6, 987a29-b7: [Plato] was familiar first with Cratylus that all things are always flowing (?et peovr v) and that there is no opinions about them; and these things he held even later. But Socrates concerned himself with knowledge and sought out the universal and was the ethics, and not at all with the nature of the universe, first to focus his thought on definitions, [Plato] agreed with him, but because of the former (sc. his Heraclitean that this [a d?finition] was of other things, and not of sensibles. doctrine), supposed For it was impossible that the common definition should be of any sensible things, since they are (n. 2), 212-13 may be taken as typical of the always changing (?ei ye perafiaXXovr v).' Guthrie to accept Irwin opposes: the impossiblity of interpretation 'Impressed by this, but unwilling Plato posited a permanent the physical world.' reality outside knowledge, 6 27 (1977), T. H. Irwin, 'Plato's Heracleiteanism', 1-13, especially p. 12: 'Plato's PhilosQ for Forms did not rely, and Aristotle knew it did not rely, on s-change in the sensible argument world.' This content downloaded from 128.95.104.66 on Mon, 28 Apr 2014 18:55:35 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SHORTER responding opposites. Irwin to Irwin, to clarify I hope to diachronic refers change 761 NOTES the nature of of Plato's as properties and flux that 's-change',7 of compresence is suc 'the cession of properties in the same subject over time'.8 This is the brand of flux that the tradition to Cratylus. ascribes not Now, every instance and total; some might properties need be constant of or s-change of succession be intermittent and limited to in the Theaetetus But and Cratylus, this s-change is run out aspects. so that everything is experiencing in this succession and constantly seem not total Constant and succession of properties, does however, respect. what since 'it is discussed in the Theaetetus, thinks about Plato and is sensibles, certain to an extreme, every Irwin suggests that the synchronie Accordingly, terms is understood 'a-change' ('aspect-change'), of flux, the fact that there is not necessarily despite rejected'.9 which he type Irwin is ready to concede that the Theaetetus deals with compresence by Plato any there of opposites, as a and Aristotle to time-dimension s-change, to be and it.10 that Aristotle (Metaph. 1010a) thinks that this sort of flux, if sufficiently severe in degree and rate, is destructive of knowledge. But Plato is not mentioned inMetaph. 1010's critique of Cratylean s-change. knew and Aristotle motivation for the problem with this than that'.12 Irwin it did separated sensibles that for Forms did not 'Plato's argument rely, n in the sensible world.' the Instead, rely, on s-change is the compresence of opposites in sensible forms objects: is that they are never 'no more but always 'just one thing', concludes not with Irwin's is two-fold: of first, mere compresence difficulty explanation seem not to concern to guard his forms does be Plato's from 'flux';13 second, opposites diachronic is different from his concern about the synchronie qualitative change His two of opposite diction makes this difference clear. The compresence qualities. The problems immaterial are not Ibims, the that same in Plato's is no proof mind; that unity both though of opposites may meet is a species their solution in of flux.14 7 Irwin (n. 7), 2. 8 T. H. Irwin, Plato's Ethics 1995), 161. (Oxford, 9 Irwin (n. 7), 10. 10 This is the objection of C. Kahn, 'Plato and Heraclitus', Proceedings of the Boston Area in Ancient Philosophy 1 (1985), 244: 'In Greek as in English, the words for motion and Colloqium change imply a temporal dimension.' 11 Irwin (n. 7), 12. 12 in Republic As is stated, for instance, with its contrast between forms and 475E9-476A7, sensibles on this score. 13 Irwin (n. 9), 161 states that 'We ought not to assume, then, that when Plato speaks of flux he must have succession inmind; and so we ought not to be surprised when he begins by speaking of ... we should and continues compresence by speaking of change simply suppose that he assumes a broad interpretation of flux.' 14 to buttress Gail Fine attempts Irwin's view with the following 'in the Tht. textual evidence: as for example, Plato counts cases of compresence, (152D2-E9), along with cases of succession, ever is, but things are always to be all alike the thesis that "nothing illustrating coming are types of "flux and change" In (152E1), both compresence and succession (yiyverai)." Criticism (152E8).' Cf. G. Fine, On Ideas: Aristotle's of Plato's Theory of Forms, (Oxford, 1995), 55. Yet it is not compresence of opposites that is called 'flux' in Tht. 152D2-E9, but rather, at one point in time, relative to one observer or circumstance, observed presence of one opposite and then the presence of the other opposite observed later in time, relative to another observer or circumstance. This is diachronic flux. The change itself may be relative s-change, garden-variety or absolute. see R. Polansky, On this point, and (so-called 'Cambridge change') Philosophy on Plato's Theaetetus, A Commentary Knowledge: 1992), 95. (Lewisburg, This content downloaded from 128.95.104.66 on Mon, 28 Apr 2014 18:55:35 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 762 SHORTER problems generated by flux in the Theaetetus?unlike The epistemological by generated Phaedo?are synchronie described in explicitly over Theaetetus of opposites compresence not said to be a result of it is marked time'. By Socrates gains motion tional with in the Republic, opposites diachronic Socrates language.15 of compresence to the growing vvv piiv ju, t?a> e?vai, voTtpov The and now, later, less'). relative indeed, NOTES the course same two comparisons the space of a year or becomes 'less' (iv iviavTco... ... I am greater to illustrate is used height, In that dialogue, the compresence described with markers any diachronic the characteristic, in Phaedo 102B1-5.16 is not and flux, an indicator is - the particle of synchronicity, 'at the same dpia, in the Theaetetus is defined in stages. First, k?vttjois not only rota for including but also locomotion, of the concept assent Theodorus' contrast, in place?both of iXaTTOj?'within Si those Timaeus, diachronic removes he changes?then as motion a criterion entirely (orav Si fj piiv iv too avTo)?'whenever a thing be in the same place' 181C9-D1) and admits qualitative change (dXXo?ojois, 181D2) as a sort of Kivinois as well. We might imagine that by abstracting the temporal aspect as well, change could a species of compresence removes since he never be rendered not Plato's, Plato True, discusses and from a process of answer on whatever change, sort, peculiar from aspect every thus"' is flowing into another 'change the compresence and white further pir) is equally colour also white flux, in the Theaetetus. But it is of not the temporal in motion, route: both correct, is accomplished as an example, flux experiences and of supposition, conclusion.17 in his by removing 'if all things "it is thus" gradually gets Theodorus its whiteness, are and "it is not in Theaetetus to agree so a that that a is a there colour' eis dXXrjv xp?av). So far, Plato has got, not (pieTa?oXr) or of but of diff?rents?that and green is, of white opposites, or white a and black less than of white and not-white. He makes of red, move no toward and op?v a circuitous subject uses first Socrates that but 183A). This move (Theaetetus 182D-E. flow opposites and total via even too, radical be our this would aspect, temporal of compresence derived But of opposites. the of compresence ?XXrj and aiodrjois concludes that predication opposites, and subject, is equally anything correct, aXXr) is impossible, follows both in 182E, opposites pir) from aiodrjois. From since words might a contradiction: "it is thus" where and "it is not 'every thus" he specifies op?v Socrates this, and then as well be their own answer, ' . . . This on whatever is a stronger point than the immediate observation Theodorus had made in response to the constant change of colour. He had said that itwould be impossible to give any name to a colour that would 'properly apply to it' (opdeos Trpooayopeveiv). Theodorus grounds this difficulty on the fact that each thing, 'since it is in flux' (are piov), 'moves Naming out from under you while you're speaking' (XeyovTos vireCipxtrai). things that are in flux is like trying to force the Scythians to fight a set-piece 15 G. E. L. Owen, A proof in the 77EP7 IAEQIf, JHS 11 (1957), 103-11 at 108, n. 34, notes that Plato describes the compresence of opposites with the adverbs ajixa (Republic 524E2, 525A4, ovra (Phaedo 74B8 with 102B-C and 523C1, D5) and aet (479B8), and with the phrase raura are any of the words Prm. for flux used, nor is there any 129B6). In none of these passages indication that time must elapse, nor is any Heracliteanism in view. 16 is unlike Simmias Tallness in part because to be tall and short at the same it 'is never willing . .). time' (r? p?yeQos ovS?nore ?d?Xeiv ?pia p?ya Kal opiKp?v e?vai. 17 on this passage Irwin (n. 9), 162, commenting of Theaetetus calls the phenomenon inmy opinion, since he allows that time must pass to bring 'compresence'?confusingly especially ' ... are the result of motion, it about: 'These appearances of compresence change, and mingling (emphasis mine). This content downloaded from 128.95.104.66 on Mon, 28 Apr 2014 18:55:35 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 763 NOTES SHORTER battle.18 Yet if a thing is changing from orange to red, I would be more (?xaXXov) correct in calling it orange than in calling it yellow.19 Such an appellation would not of course apply opdws, but itwould apply better than some others. This sort of flux does not rule out it does not make reference only imprecise. impossible, of opposites, must Socrates 'one further, replacing clarify with and After this modification, 'not-seeing'. 'seeing' to another from one quality but merely nearby, changing approximations; to arrive at unity and 'another colour' In order colour' are the objects from away no longer to the opposite and quality, but en route from opposite of any given name is just one merely changing, that the negation one. Because the changing is, not quale to opposite, Socrates is able to conclude an appellation as correct for a thing as the original name for it. This inference would not have been possible if the change had not been from opposite to opposite. Something that is changing from X to not-X isX in a way, always but also (ov pi?XXov out 'slipping r}).20 This a thing the such is, it is so only to express used of opposites . . . language different facie from the and resulting is 'no more X (itself derived from flux) is prima in a way, difficulty than epistemological observed a few lines earlier, which was expressed by the idea of difficulty Theodorus things the phrase Thus, from the compresence not-X' in a way. Whatever not-X not. equally from under' our words can he While (vne^epx^rai).21 derive the latter difficulty from flux alone, Plato must qualify the flux specifically as involving he before qualities to have compresence opposite possible all, and Plato considers such can of 'no more at arrive X from arising in other dialogues.) compresence having not-X' suffer from from very words, a unity of opposites he this compresence, the difficulties of flux. so that we will need from then flux, and having that such discovers 'Thus' a new and 'not-thus' if we language (It is, of course, at diachronic change any to the results of the second sort: Finally, Plato applies the first sort of difficulty derived not X'. than not opposites also are X than too, to speak at 'no more pu?XXov expressions, 'slip out from under' arrived ov our at all. It is this sort of merely flux-based difficulty, this tendency of things to slip out from under our words (and not the failure of things to be X rather than not-X) that Plato raises also in the Cratylus, a dialogue which is, after all, concerned primarily with naming. At the end of the dialogue, Socrates confronts Cratylus with the difficulties that would arise if all /cat pe?vra>v?439C). such as it is' because the disastrous result things were 'always moving The result is what we should it 'is always in 440A6-D6: slipping away' knowledge, and flowing' (iovr 'the beautiful v arr?vrojv (?et v-n^epx^r the beautiful, ai). Socrates the good, ?et is not expect: always describes etc., would be changing (ixeraninre?) into other things. But because Plato has not here raised the compresence of opposites, the difficulty is expressed by saying that knowledge 'would 18 constant Hdt. 4.120, dealing with the Scythians flight from the Persians, employs vocabulary are similar to Plato's verbs used of the Scythians' of the Persians handling vTreCipxtrai: vtt ^iovt Cf. J. Hartog, The Mirror s, and vneCeXavvovTes. (Berkeley, of Herodotus viretjdyeiv, 'The other company of the Scythians is also ordered to lure the Persians on and lead 1988), 41-2: a day's march them astray, always keeping ahead of them. The verb used is vne?dyeiv, which is carried out surreptitiously through its prefix indicates that this movement 19 R. Bolton, Review 'Plato's distinction between and becoming', Correctly, being of 29 (1975), 71 : 'Plato agrees that there is no absurdity in supposing that some object is Metaphysics no an its place. Equally, arises from supposing that is continuously absurdity changing object its color.' continuously changing 20 cf. P. DeLacy, (ov pi?XXov and the antecedents On this phrase, of ancient scepticism', 3 (1958), 59-71. Phronesis 21 to J.MacDowell, Plato: Theaetetus, Translated with Notes (Oxford, 1973), 180^, attempts derive the 'no more X than not-X' difficulty from flux alone. very This content downloaded from 128.95.104.66 on Mon, 28 Apr 2014 18:55:35 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 764 SHORTER on pass but to a different into not by 'no more are stuck, than knowledge Another than form that we saying these two sorts of epistemological for required els ?XXo etSos (pj^rairLirroi knowledge' at the outset, with words and concepts yvojoeojs), that refer not-knowledge'. difference between time-dimension NOTES the sort flux-based (the is the difficulty out 'slipping from under' problem), but not for the compresence of opposites. This factor is expressed, in both the Cratylus and the Theaetetus, with words indicating time: For if it ever (nore) it is not changing. stays the same, (Cra. it is clear then For as soon as (ajua) the person about to know sort (aAAo /cat aAAo?ov). and of a different The words that or inspection to the next over time. succession it approaches, itwould (Cra. also that Heraclitus established a different become thing, 439E8-440A1) that flux indicates in the Cratylus III. PLATO'S DIALECTICAL CONSTRUCTION HERACLITEANISM Having ), at least, xpov of the flux are aAAo and its compounds, rather than uses the case for compresence). Plato (as was typically to express this sort of change, and that /xera- prefix has to express the sameness of a subject of aet from one denoting opposites and piera?dXXei pierarrirrrei a diachronic use The force. involves r (e/cetvo) the result express negatives occasion that at that time 439E2-3) has a certain of flux, view and Theaetetus OF and that Plato second, has a different view, there remains to show what Plato was doing by employing Heraclitus' name for this quite different sort of problem. In the Theaetetus who ophers Heraclitus' rr)v Theodorus 179C-181B, a flux thesis. These advocate rov (ot 'HpaKXeirov appear 179D4) yE(f>eoov, and Socrates thinkers, or 179D8) iraipoi, as a comic caricature. In discuss certain philos comrades of 'the designated 'the men at Ephesus' the issue of 179D5-8, (ot nepl 'moving being' is depicted as a hot topic of the day, and they are themajor advocates of it: SO: And a battle over it [sc. over the idea that Being is always moving] of no has arisen?one mean size and involving not a few men. THEO: It is far from being small, but around Ionia it is even growing are of Heraclitus the comrades (ot rov huge. For eralpoi) 'HpaKXeirov a campaign for this X?yos very forcefully. conducting ismeant by 'the comrades of Heraclitus'? What term this or 'Stoics'. to refers men These in the 'Heracliteans' are the army same way of Heraclitus It would be a mistake to think that that one might refer to within the larger martial not in the sense that Crito is the iraipos of Socrates (Crito 54D). What are an army Theodorus madmen'. or say, but are which that says There tactics employs that 'you could is in them 'not shoot as their 'full of strange arrows interrogated, and shoot so much 'little turns Their 'strangely name-changed'). in Herodotus Persian 4.120: army both and Heracliteans Scythians when to men who appropriate no more a discussion have of as the enigmatic least bit of phrases' language' (Kaiv is like that strategy crusading them with They (prjpiariGKia s metaphor, ismore, are repose'. 'Epicureans' for they flux. than with do not utter alviypiarojSrj) puerajvopiaoiJieva, of the Scythians literally, the against still for their attackers. Instead, they will not stand answer avoid any close engagement, cryptically arrows at their opponents. This content downloaded from 128.95.104.66 on Mon, 28 Apr 2014 18:55:35 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SHORTER 765 NOTES It is not immaterial in this connection that Socrates and Theodorus have served as Athenian hoplites, and that the Scythians' and Heracliteans' characteristic failure to stand firm in conflict martial or dialectical is, for a hoplite, the mark of cowardice (famously, Archilochus fr. 5West). Recall, too, that the opening of the dialogue saw Theaetetus being transported home from Corinth, wounded and afflicted with re terms him KaX?s Eucleides dysentery. avTov heard others iyKojpiia^?vTOJv irepl Kal and dyad?s tt)v on remarks his pidxrjv?'singing how praises he has over the battle' (142B8). While thismodel of hoplite valour is by no means a pervasive theme in the dialogue, it is a very real component of the Athenian outlook, and thus must of Plato's remarks about Heracliteans. shape our understanding to play the dialectical The Heracliteans' refusal and their game, with Socrates' way of doing style, are thus contrasted unfavourably preferred oracular Plato philosophy. is playing upon the apothegmatic quality of Heraclitus' own prose; upon his famed obscurity of expression; and upon the flux doctrine. All this is plainly enough a caricature Socrates at attributes fun poking that his suppose own of Heraclitus' 'followers' wrote books sharing that perhaps the exasperating suggests this writing; there is no to need style. dart-throwing and avoidance of stable conclusions is only for show; doubtless they have an esoteric doctrine which they teach to their own pupils. But Theodorus remonstrates (180C) that it is not a of masters question and or of pupils, at all: teaching such men one does not become the pupil of another, but pupils, my good man? Among to be inspired, and each each of them happens they sprout up of their own accord from wherever that the other knows nothing. From them, as I was saying earlier, you could never get supposes an explanation or unwilling. We must ourselves take hold of it they be willing (Aoyo?), whether it just as we would a problem and examine (irpo?Xrjpia). What So not these only persons The are Theodorus' are declaration problem' purposes explicitly that levelled complaints said not to constitute the is to be question serves to bracket the question of 'we ourselves the dialogue. must take Since we will it up and nameless against a school.22 taken over for Heracliteans, examination of the flux doctrine's authorship never examine but 'like a for the answer from the Ephesians, get a fixed a problem' it as we would (180C56).23 (There is backhanded humour in the words 'you could never get a X?yos from them' since it is precisely Heraclitus' evangelistic aim to help other men recognize the X?yos.) Taking over 'flux' as a 'problem' (Trpo?X-qpia)should be understood as the opposite of treating it as a X?yos: Theodorus is steering Socrates away from his orig inal intention to examine the words of the Heracliteans themselves.24 That will not work, so the question of change is being taken in hand by Socrates and Theodorus as their own project; the X?yoi of previous thinkers, and their A?yos-doctrines, are put aside. Plato's usage inRepublic 530B6 affords a perfect parallel to our present passage: 22 M. Burnyeat, The Theaetetus 1990), 47-8 and at n. 61 inclines to this of Plato (Indianapolis, as well. conclusion 23 en lOKone?od ai. D. Bostock, Se Set napaXa?ovras Plato's avrovs onep npo?Xr)pia Theaetetus 'This means, presumably, that Plato is not (Oxford, 1988), 99, detects this implication: as Heraclitus to portray the [sc. flux] doctrine himself held it, but to be claiming exactly claim.' examining what seems to him to be itsmost fundamental 24 T roi, a> <f>iXeOeoS pe, p?XXov OKenr?ov Kal e? apx^s, onep avrol vnoreivovrai? as they themselves reason why we ought to examine All the more it from the beginning, put it forward' (Tht. 179D9-E1). This content downloaded from 128.95.104.66 on Mon, 28 Apr 2014 18:55:35 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 766 NOTES SHORTER I said, we shall shall let the things then, Astronomy Xpojp, voi), and we as a to treat flux agreement to particulars. reference without Theodorus' and Socrates' like geometry, using problems pursue (irpo?Xrjpiaoiv in the sky go (r? S' iv r?? ovpavto idoopiev). involves likewise 'problem' the divorce It strengthens about principles reasoning and the flux Heraclitus between true Just as in the Republic here considered. doctrine will put to one so Socrates and Theodorus sensible stars, study to in the writings of others. instances of the flux doctrine agree side any actual They no from 'the ancient inherited but as one treat it, not only as a Trpo?Xrjpia, poets',25 shoe it clear by demonstrating who make 'later men less than from it, so that even do not to apply understand course, Heraclitus' meant many Of to Heraclitus, his with obscure and style his the that complaint his teaching. name in all of in view is still the primary him Plato is using that But is because notwithstanding. poets' (180D3-4). This would be a very odd thing to say if learn their wisdom' makers may it were not does astronomy 'the ancient this, for of purposes still ivSo?a26 rather than because he is engaged in scrupulous history-of-philosophy, less in any interpretation of Heraclitus' words. Aristotle defines ivSo?a as 'reputable that opinions', TovTois or to as he right as an but Kal rrXeioTois ivS?Cois?'to to the most or rj tois oo<j>o?s, Kal all, or to the majority, and notable not as a private definition common to describe attempt it. It applies, knew rj tois Tr?oiv yvcop?piois or to most, I take this description school, dialectic seem r? tois pidXioTa all of them, (Topics 100b21-3). Aristotle's which is, those r? rr?oiv the wise?to also therefore, to Plato. practice To wit: esteemed' posited by Plato in order to serve as one half of a dialectical opposition with total of thesis and notable removes consider As thesis the flux to Parmenides ascribed stability esteemed'. proof, from any and Melissus, two more of of the Eleatics: handling with Heraclitus, association Plato's too-close to peculiar in philosophical thesis the flux is the 'the most just as he lest anyone rather than dialectic investigation of take him to be doing history-of-philosophy to the idea of stability from the philos so distance also takes Plato pains ivSo?a, as he names ophers ovv pir) ovt Ta we XeiTTOjpieda. So a premise require notes, 'The things staked are out which implications SO: in the Theaetetus, I seem things simply Plato avviojpiev, seeks in all ways.'27 changing on the extreme position The other dialogue As Socrates says (184A1): <f>o?ovpiai et7re ttX?ov 7toXv Siavoovpievos Heraclitean that the Theaetetus' be surprised arguments As D. Bostock did not hold. almost Heraclitus certainly Parmenides Of its champions. Xey?pieva not should to extract It is Plato t can only the premise be got from not Heraclitus, who and himself, that has flux. in which Heraclitus Heraclitus ti is introduced ismentioned prominently as a representative to spy (Sokw KaBopav) Heraclitus to myself as old as the days of Cronus and Rhea, which is the Cratylus. of flux: of wisdom, ancient words uttering Homer also says. (Cra. 402A3-6) 25 Tht. v r v r? S? npo?Xr] ?xa aAAo ri napei?rj(f>apev 180C7-D1: per? ?pxai nap? p?v . . . v rovs noXXovs s iniKpvnrop?v noir)oe 26 In Aristotelian term for is used as a technical dialectic Top. 100a), npo?Xrjpa (e.g. Aristotle, and total flux?') to be answered dialectically a question in constant by jumping (e.g. Are sensibles deoe?s such as the off from eVSo^a, 'generally accepted views', which could include paradoxical cf. H. Baltussen, of Peripatetic flux thesis in Plato. For a brief discussion Heraclitean dialectic, in the De Sensibus Dialectic and Plato: Peripatetic the Presocratics (Leiden, Against Theophrastus in Plato's day, it is not of oral dialectic is a literary representation 2000), 34-5. If the Theaetetus to find some of the same terminology being used. surprising 27 Bostock (n. 23), 101. This content downloaded from 128.95.104.66 on Mon, 28 Apr 2014 18:55:35 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SHORTER Again 767 NOTES the flux thesis is older than Heraclitus, and derives from the poets. There a statement probably follows of the in paraphrases, thesis not verbatim fragments,28 of Heraclitus: ' stands Heraclitus that all things flow and nothing says somewhere (X?yei nov Hp?KXeiros) still, and likening the things that are to the stream of a river he says that you could not step twice into the same river. (Cra. 402A8) The nov word mark may verba?as ipsissima as the quotation be expected would given or as a reminiscence inexact, of the vagueness the rather than introduction (Sokco Ka?op?v).29 the next occurence of the flux idea A similarly hyperbolic tone permeates 411B-C, in the Cratylus: SO: And by the dog, I seem to myself . . . I just now noticed mark?what to be prophesying (pavreveodai) not too far from the as a warning serves and to the reader. is ironical, There piavreveodai a jocular in the wise men making themselves of spinning description dizzy. As to these wise men 'No the flux thesis ascribed is radical and extreme: Theaetetus, The word follows single thing is stable or steadfast (pi?vipiov ovSe ?e?aiov), but everything is flowing (pe?v) and moving (c?epeoOai), and full of every kind of motion and constant coming-to-be (yev?oe s ?et).' This is fairly close to the thesis in Theaetetus 18IE that in the Theaetetus is always In fine, with every kind of change'. 'everything changing nor any evidence and Cratylus there is neither of Heraclitus' that any exegesis words, no more Plato has in mind that he than Heracliteans least, any historical (at seriously that Homer thinks a flux-doctrine). teaches Instead, we a radical have theory no with apparent limits to the flux. IV.THE LEGACY OF PLATO'S HERACLITUS a rather to Plato, Thanks we when writers: read a Heraclitean is not even to to hold caricatured the Platonic to hold version of came 'Heracliteanism' and Aristotelian commentators, about or doctrines the X?yos, to call fire to later down we find that to be the element, or are mentioned in certainly opposites?though to be a in all subsequent philosophical writings, to believe is pre-eminently in total, and especially flux. With Heraclitean material, f the exception who in is called of a certain Antisthenes Diogenes HpaKXeireios in 9.6, the epithet Laertius and a Pausanias is applied to no 6.19, 'HpaKXeinorrjs connection person consist with the unity Heraclitus. in all of Greek of these Rather, literature except in his views about flux. This Cratylus. His Heracliteanism is specified by Aristotle is always inMetaph. said to 987a32, 28 So also Kirk (n. 2), 14 and Marcovich (n. 2), 194. 29 This to exegete Heraclitus raises the question of whether Plato was even in a position has been variously Kirk estimated, with the pessimistic directly. The number of direct quotations to fr. 22B82-3 DK (man considered in relation to that only the references giving it as his opinion vov to 22B51 DK 289A,B; ktX.) in god and to ape) in the Hippias Maior (8ia(f)ep?pi oopi^?perai the Sophist 242D, E and Symposium 187A; and to 22B6 DK (the sun new every day) in Republic to flux without 498A are Heraclitus' words. Against this is set the total of references any in the Cratylus in the Phaedo and Theaetetus; 90C, Philebus 43A, and anchoring quotation this assessment S. Mouraviev, Heraclitea 2.A.1 (Sankt Sophist 249B. Cf. Kirk (n. 2), 13-16. With to flux, and 91-4 to all other pages 68-90 agreement, 1999) is in apparent Augustin, devoting and presenting the same passages as Kirk. doctrines, This content downloaded from 128.95.104.66 on Mon, 28 Apr 2014 18:55:35 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 768 NOTES SHORTER where he explains that Plato was familiar 'with Cratylus and the Heraclitean doctrines that all sensible things are flowing and that there is no knowledge about them'. Later, inMetaph. 1010al0-15, Aristotle relates how Cratylus went beyond Heraclitus: 'He found fault with Heraclitus for saying that it is not possible to step into the same river twice; for he thought [itwas possible to do it] not even once.' We thus have two mere than a literary half names Laertius, of On the most depict a topos in oral themselves as Plato.30 are doubtful. historical Heracliteans namely, in Diogenes creation a Cratylus and such slim who evidence, more is probably about speculations It seems likely that the Cratylus and Theaetetus common manifestation dialectic, employed in Plato's of Heracliteanism thinkers by themselves who had day: no to it. allegiance Whether Cratylus himself attributed flux to sensibles only or to other things as well, Aristotle's school probably contributed heavily to that interpretation with De Caelo 298b, where 'all is being generated and is flowing, nothing having any stability one except which thing single said to have come as persists the basis of all these and transformations', 1078b 12-17, where idea-theorists (Pythagoreans and Plato) are also with Metaphysics to their view thus: Those who hold the theory of ideas were led to it because of the truth of they were persuaded the Heraclitean that all sensible things are always in flux, so that if there is knowledge arguments and thought of anything, there must be some other, abiding entities besides sensibles. For there is no knowledge of things that are in flux. With this weight of Aristotelian opinion guiding the characterization of the flux doctrine and of Cratylus, it is no surprise to find that the Aristotelian and Platonic commentators the echo r HpaKXeireios same understandings. They of speak o KparvXos who holds that all things (or sometimes specifically sensibles) are in of ?v Kivrjoei 'their own unstable nature' (?r?vTa etvat) because v so that no thing to the is ever the same 'with respect </>vo i), same rov Kara and the substance' avr? avr?v r? (Kara xp?vov or When the commentators local, say 'flux', they mean physical, vrroKeipievov).31 sort which, when to an alteration of the taken thwarts extreme, qualitative of process change iavr (rfj ?orarrj same time predication. This is not an understanding and Plato of his words, reading in the Theaetetus and sympathetic constructed of Heraclitus but on the that is based on a thorough caricature to suit his Cratylus of Heraclitus dialectical which purposes. CONCLUSION Plato's Heraclitean ologically flux upsetting. is not Heraclitus' Further, Plato's flux, but compresence is far more of opposites radical is also and epistem not Heraclitus' unity of opposites. Why then did Plato select Heraclitus as his representative of instability, and not some other philosopher? The association of the river-saying with flux appears to have been a received commonplace by the time of Plato, perhaps 30 I 'The problem of Cratylus', AJPh 72 (1951), 225-3 and D. N. Sedley, agree with G. S. Kirk, Plato's Cratylus is shown taking his ideas about flux from his 2003) that Cratylus (Cambridge, encounter with Socrates, rather than bringing them to that (historical?) meeting. But contra, cf. D. J.Allan, 'The problem of Cratylus', AJPh 75 (1954), 271-87. 31 inMetaph., Cf. Alexander, inMetaph. 49.21 Hayduck; Asclepius, (987a32), 49.21 Hayduck; in Platonis 10 and 14, all reproduced inMouraviev Proclus, Cratyl. (n. 29), 2.A.I. This content downloaded from 128.95.104.66 on Mon, 28 Apr 2014 18:55:35 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions SHORTER 769 NOTES through Hippias, as Jaap Mansfeld suggests;32 perhaps through Cratylus, as Marcovich hazards. The playful way in which Plato handles Heracliteanism, with comic and hyperbolic imagery, suggests that his audience would have known and altered vented later philosophers its harmonious namely, as a familiar flux Heraclitean recognized This oral dialectic.33 from the context of contemporary theory seems to have pre of Heraclitus' philosophy version from grasping Heraclitus' unity with own intended point about flux: stability.34 MATTHEW Mars Hill Academy, Cincinnati, Ohio COLVIN [email protected] doi:10.1017/S0009838807000705 32 that the sophist building on an idea first put forth by Bruno Snell, suggests Jaap Mansfeld, a handbook of philosophical and poetical commonplaces arranged by theme, Hippias compiled and Homer with the such as 'water', and that this was Plato's source for the linking of Heraclitus der flux doctrine. Cf. B. Snell, 'Die Nachrichten ?ber die Lehren des Thaies und die Anfange und Literaturgeschichte', 96 (1944), Griechischen 170-82, repr. in his Philologus PhilosophiePlato or Gesammelte (Hildesheim, 1966), 119-28 and J. Mansfeld, Schriften "Cratylus 402a-c: 1 (1981), 63-4. in L. Rosetti (ed.), Atti del Symposium Heracliteum Hippias?', 33 or elsewhere, was familiar enough to be fodder for The flux thesis, whether from Heraclitus fr. 170 Kaibel and Plutarch, De comm. popular comedy well before Plato's day. Cf. Epicharmus, ?o?. 44 (1083 A). 34 A lone exception is the use of the river by the Stoic Cleanthes in his physiological flux of the soul constitutes flux in which it as intelligent. Cf. M. Colvin, 'Heraclitean psychology, 28 (2005), 257-72 in Stoic psychology', OSAPh and A. A. Long, 'Soul and body in Stoicism', 27 (1982), 34-57, repr. in id., Stoic Studies Phronesis 1996), 224-59. (Cambridge, THE ASTYNOMOI, PRIVATE WILLS STREET ACTIVITY 1 is an oration Isaeus on the estate of a certain AND seems who Cleonymus, to have taken under his wing his nephews (sister's sons) after their guardian Deinias had died. Cleonymus apparently had feuded with Deinias and during that time wrote up a will transferring his to others property whose exact if any, kinship, with is Cleonymus unknown (4ff.). Cleonymus specifically ignored his nephews despite his own father's wishes that Cleonymus' property devolve on them (5). Cleonymus had his will deposited at the office of the astynomoi, explicitly named in 15 but referred collec tively as irrl ttjv dpxrjv in other sections of the oration (3, 14, 18, 21, 22).l According to the one sent the office 21, speaker who was for someone from 22). The magistrate by testament. on opponents, to confirm of wished the nephews, Cleonymus to carry out of the astynomoi the other terms the law a man In Attic wished?he did not of adoption do reveal 1W. Wyse, The Speeches have that of hand, the will who had claimed (18). Cleonymus' no male heirs (repr. edn. New York, the will and (3, 14, 15, the summoned that Cleonymus a close kinsman, to adopt for a testator frequently adopted of Isaeus to annul his wishes was an adoption bequest he could adopt whomever the cases instance. Although kinsmen, 1979,), especially 185. This content downloaded from 128.95.104.66 on Mon, 28 Apr 2014 18:55:35 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions through