Nasser`s Decision-Making in the 1967 Middle East Crisis: A
Transcription
Nasser`s Decision-Making in the 1967 Middle East Crisis: A
Nasser's Decision-Making in the 1967 Middle East Crisis: A Rational-Choice Explanation Author(s): Ben D. Mor Source: Journal of Peace Research, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Nov., 1991), pp. 359-375 Published by: Sage Publications, Ltd. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/424122 . Accessed: 30/10/2014 05:06 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Sage Publications, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of Peace Research. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions ? Journal of Peace Research, vol. 28, no. 4, 1991, pp. 359-375 Nasser's Decision-making in the 1967 Middle East Crisis: A Rational-choice Explanation* BEN D. MOR Department of Political Science, University of Haifa Nasser's behavior in the 1967 Middle East crisis has been variously explained in terms of decisionmaking deficiencies, personality-related pathologies, and uncontrolled escalation. This paper argues that such accounts are unsatisfactory. They are biased by their use of backward induction, which infers from Nasser's ultimate failure an inevitability to the escalation of the crisis. This inference puts a premium on the evaluation of decisions, rather than on their explanation. It is also inconsistent with Nasser's actual behavior toward the end of the crisis, which strongly suggests an attempt at deescalation. The paper offers an alternative, rational-choice explanation of the crisis. It argues that when the focus of inquiry is shifted from Nasser's failure to his objectives and perception of the strategic context, the crisis decisions of the Egyptian leader can be shown to have been consistent with strategic rationality. Moreover, Nasser's failure was the result not of personality or cognitive deficiencies but rather of Israel's failure to communicate the threshold beyond which she would be compelled to attack. This conclusion underscores the importance of signaling limits to an opponent's escalation so as to facilitate the opponent's learning in crisis. 1. Introduction In May 1967 the status quo in the Middle East changed dramatically as a result of three major decisions made by Gamal Abdoul Nasser in the course of a week: (1) the decision to place the Egyptian army on alert and move its forces into Sinai (14 May); (2) the decision to request the withdrawal of United Nations Emergency Force (UNEF) troops (16 May); and (3) the decision to blockade the Straits of Tiran (22-23 May). In making the third decision, in particular, Nasser appeared to challenge knowingly a repeated Israeli casus belli. Meir Amit, then head of Mossad, the Israeli intelligence service, later recalled that 'until May 23, I thought there was a possibility for maneuvers, that there is a leeway for alternatives. But when Nasser closed the Straits, I said: "This is it, there is no way to avoid war"' (Brecher, 1980, p. 104). Mohamed Heikal, the noted Egyptian * am I grateful to Steven J. Brams, Gideon Doron, and Zeev Maoz for their support, encouragement, and invaluable advice, without which this paper could not have been written. Nils Petter Gleditsch, Daniel Heradstveit, Frank C. Zagare, and an anonymous referee for the JPR also provided helpful comments and suggestions. Needless to say, responsibility for any errors contained in this paper is solely mine. journalist and confidant of Nasser, wrote in Al-Ahram on 26 May that 'Israel cannot accept or remain indifferent to what has taken place', and 'hence, I say, that Israel must resort to arms ... An armed clash ... is inevitable' (quoted in Shamir, 1971, p. 198). After the Tiran blockade, when Israel still failed to attack, Nasser escalated once again by signing the UAR-Jordan Defense Agreement (30 May). Six days later, on 5 June, 1967, Israel launched the pre-emptive strike that began the Six Day War. Given a near-consensus among students of the 1967 crisis that Nasser, at least initially, did not seek armed conflict with Israel, and given the subsequent disaster that befell him, how can his decisions be explained? Studies of the crisis published so far have generated heated controversy with respect to many aspects of Nasser's behavior. Among the important questions that remain open and await further investigation are the following: Did Nasser stumble into the crisis or did he plan his actions in advance? Was he carried away by the unfolding events or did he calculate his moves carefully? Did he possess accurate information about Israeli preferences and capabilities or did he misperceive them? Was he aware of his army's condition or was This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 360 Ben D. Mor he misled by his military advisers to inflate its strength? Did he attempt to de-escalate the crisis or did he escalate until the very last moment? Did his initial successes lead him to prefer war over a diplomatic settlement, or did he prefer the latter option until the end? Did he anticipate an Israeli attack or did he believe he could avert it? In their attempt to provide an explanation for Nasser's behavior, various scholars have supplied different answers to these questions. Consequently, the Six Day War literature is presently flooded with a variety of competing explanations. Still, a review of the studies conducted to date suggests a general convergence on two types of explanations. The first focuses on the psychology of the Egyptian leader. It points to pathologies in Nasser's decision-making, citing the intrusion and influence of irrational factors, inadequate cognitive processing, emotionally biased interpretations of reality, and personality deficiencies. Nasser's disastrous decisions are then variously explained by his cognitive rigidity, his tendency to succumb to wishful thinking, his inability to withstand the pressures of the situation and of his advisers, and his basic passivity and lack of foresight. The second more prevalent type of explanation glosses over the decision-making process itself, concentrating instead on the strategic implications of Nasser's behavior. The pattern that emerges is perceived to conform to the characteristics of a 'brinkmanship crisis' (Lebow, 1981). Nasser's failure is then explained as a case of brinkmanship that went out of control. The contention of this paper is that both accounts of Nasser's decision-making are unsatisfactory. I intend to show that by making the outcome of the crisis the starting-point of their analysis, these accounts produce explanations that are partial and biased. I will offer an alternative explanation of Nasser's behavior by arguing that, contrary to the conventional wisdom on the crisis, Nasser's decision-making was not only rational but strategically so. His failure, moreover, resulted primarily from impediments to crisis learning that were exogenous, and unrelated, to the nature of his decisional process or to loss of control on his part. This paper is organized as follows. Section 2 evaluates the psychological and brinkmanship explanations by juxtaposing them with the available evidence; Section 3 examines Nasser's crisis perception, hypothesizes about his crisis objectives, and argues that his decisions followed the imperatives of strategic rationality; Section 4 analyzes the reasons for Nasser's failure; and Section 5 discusses some of the conclusions that can be drawn from the 1967 case with respect to crisis management. 2. Explaining Nasser's Behavior: The Remaining Puzzles Of the voluminous literature on the 1967 crisis, none is available that deals specifically and exclusively with Nasser's decisionmaking process. There is no equivalent, for the Egyptian side, to those comprehensive studies of Israel's crisis behavior by Brecher (1980, 1975, 1972) or Stein & Tanter (1980). The literature reviewed in this section is thus derived, for the most part, from works that deal with the Six Day War in general and in a variety of contexts. A micro-level comparison of these studies reveals important differences of interpretation on many key issues. At the macro level of comparison, however, most (but not all) studies may be seen as falling into two groups, in accordance with the type of explanatory variables they employ and emphasize. One group focuses on the individual level (i.e. Nasser's psychology), whereas the other is concerned with the interstate level (i.e. the dynamics of brinkmanship). The critical evaluation presented in this section addresses these two kinds of studies. Two caveats are in order before we proceed. First, the division of existing studies into two kinds of explanation is hardly airtight. Few of the works cited below fall clearly in one of the two groups. In fact, most scholars shift back and forth between the individual and interstate levels of analysis.' The second (and related) caveat is that the following discussion is not meant as a This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nasser'sDecision-makingin the 1967Crisis 361 criticism of individual works. The studies mentioned below are not reviewed in their entirety; rather, they are assessed in the context of the two broad explanations to whichthey contributein their analysis. 2.1 ThePsychologicalExplanation A psychological explanation of Nasser's behavior has been offered by two of his foremost biographers. Lacouture (1973) argues that serious deficienciesin Nasser's cognitiveabilitiesand generalcharacterprevented him from correctly assessing the consequences of his decisions. Specifically, he was incapableof distinguishingbetween fact and fantasy and 'seemed not to understand the relation between an act and its consequences,the fall of a hammerand the sound it makes' (p. 310). He was unable to foresee the opponent'sreactionsto his own moves, and succumbedto wishfulthinking, not the least because he 'allowedhimself to be seduced by the gobbledygookdispensed by his own radio ...' (p. 301). These pathologies resulted in serious errors in estimatingIsrael's reaction to the Tiran blockade as well as the USA's ability to restrainits ally from attacking.When the Egyptian hawks (Minister of War Shams Badran and Commander-in-ChiefMarshall Amer) stepped up their pressureon Nasser to escalate, he was forced to make rash moves (p. 305). Nutting (1972), who draws a generally sympatheticportraitof Nasser, nevertheless argues that, during those critical weeks in May and June, he was prone to wishful thinking and resisted all information or advice that seemed to counter his tenaciously held views of the crisis. This cognitive rigidityled him to exclude his Ministers from the decision-makingprocess; in the one case in which his recent decisionswere discussed by the Cabinet, he refused to be drawn into the discussion (p. 410). His unshakenconfidencein his perceptionof the crisis led him to believe, until the end, that Israel would not attack, that if it did, Egypt would prevail, and that the Soviets would support him, 'even if this involved another worldwar' (p. 409). Amos (1979, p. 49) argues that Nasser was drawninto escalation as a result of the charges of cowardice that were leveled against him by the conservative Arab regimes. His own rural origins had made him particularlysensitiveto such insults.He also harbored a paranoid suspicion of the United States, which led him to interpret events andformulatepreferencesin the context of a perceived collusion between the United States and Israel (p. 52). Bar-Zohar (1970) and Kimche & Bawly (1968) argue that the impulsive side of Nasser's personalitytook over as the crisis progressed. Though initially moderate and responsible, the Egyptian leader gradually became intoxicatedwith his own successes. By the time of the Tiran decision, his euphoricconditioncloudedhis abilityto appreciatecorrectlythe directionthe crisiswas taking. The influenceof Nasser'sinitial successes on his subsequentpreferencesand actionsis mentioned in several other studies, including those which generallyespouse a brinkmanship explanation. Safran (1969), for example, suggests that Nasser allowed 'his pridein his tacticalvirtuosityto blindhim to strategicimperatives'(p. 267). Similararguments are made by Laqueur(1969, p. 124) and Dawn (1968, p. 223). Draper (1968) writesthat the Tirandecisionwas influenced by the fact that the Egyptiandeterrentforce concentrated in the Sinai could easily be used to make offensive demandson Israel. The making of these demands was in turn facilitatedby the sheer presenceof the force which, as Heikal reports,dazzledthe Egyptians (pp. 76-77). Lebow (1981) views this effect of the concentrationof force as the primaryreasonfor Nasser's overconfidence in his military power, whichin turnconditionedhis assessment of the risks involved in a more bellicose policy. Stein (1988) argues that Nasser's overestimation of Egyptian military capabilitieswas the resultof motivated error: having committedhimself to a challenge of Israeli deterrence, Nasser and his advisers now engaged in 'wishful thinking andpost hoc bolsteringof their decision'(p. 10). Other scholars cite the influence of the This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 362 Ben D. Mor Arab propaganda machine which fed on Nasser's initial successes. Laqueur (1969) concludes that 'it influenced not only the massesbut also, in the long run, the leaders, whose judgment was likely affected' (p. 107). Dawn (1968), Amos (1979), and Yost (1968) suggestthat the Arab sloganseventually had the effect of limitingpolicyoptions. There are three difficultieswith the psychological explanation. First, it fails to account for Nasser's initial successes because it focuses almost exclusivelyon his subsequentfailure.In fact, the entire course of the crisisis interpretedin termsof its final outcome, and one cannot but conclude that the gains Nasser managed temporarilyto secure were obtainedby luck, or, at best, as a result of Israeli weakness. Lacouture (1973), for example, through a form of backward induction, concludes that even the initialsteps on 14 and 16 May were mistaken (p. 302), thus suggesting that there was an inexorabilityto the course of the crisis. This argumentpresents a methodological difficulty.If one assumesan inexorableand inevitablechainof events, then the explanatory problemreducesitself to identifyingthe first link in the chain. And if, in addition, the final outcome is known to have been disastrous, all subsequent decisions are taken to be a priori mistaken and are explained in terms of 'what went wrong' (see also Lebow, 1981, pp. 91-92). This focus inflates the importance of certain factors by assumption rather than by an examinationof the facts; it puts a premium on the evaluationof decisions, not on their explanation. In addition, there is the implicit assumption that bad outcomes are necessarilythe resultof faultyproceduresor personality-relatedpathologies. The latter factors may or may not be responsiblefor the failure of strategies;this failure, above all, is an empiricalquestion (Herek et al., 1987;Maoz, 1990a). Empirically, too, there is no conclusive evidence to suggest that Nasser's initial decisions sealed the fate of the entire crisis. The facts do not suggest that his mobilization decision, or even his UNEF decision, made war inevitable. In fact, the opportuni- ties to arrestthe crisisexisted throughoutits course, even as late as 30 May, as I argue in Section 4. Therefore, the psychological thesis is unwarrantedin concluding that Nasser's failure lay with his initial decisions.The second difficultyin the psychological explanationconcernsits inabilityto account for the variability over time in Nasser's behavior: Having escalated throughout most of the crisis,why did he stop escalating in June?3Why the sudden caution after 'so many rash moves' (Lacouture, 1973, p. 305)? It is unclear,in other words,why deficiencies in Nasser'scharacterand decisional process led first to impulsive escalatory moves, then to cautionaryrestraint.Neither is it clear why 'this grand master who had triumphedin so manyclose chess mates' (p. 304) fell victimto so many inherentflawsin his personality in the months of May and June, 1967. Why did these same flaws not lead him to reckless escalation in January 1960, when he mobilizedand moved 50,000 troopsand 500 tanksinto Sinaiin reactionto an Israelistrikeagainstthe Syrianvillage of Tawfiq?4 The third difficulty in the psychological explanation relates to Nasser's ability to revise his probability estimates of Israeli attackin responseto incominginformation. The psychologicalexplanation argues that he displayed cognitive rigidity in resisting such revision, despite the availabilityof evidence requiringit (Nutting, 1972, pp. 408410). This explanation suggests that he could not correctlyassess the consequences of his own decisionsand actions in terms of their likely effect on the probability of Israeliattack(Lacouture,1973, p. 310). This argument is again strongly influenced by the knowledge of Nasser's subsequent failure. Working from the known outcome back to the decision, it is clear that at some point something went wrong. In fact, though, Nasser not only revised his probability estimates several times duringthe course of the crisis- as he himself reported in his speech of 23 July 1967 - but his estimates themselves were not far off the mark, as we shall see. Moreover, Nasser's estimates were not groundless- This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nasser's Decision-making in the 1967 Crisis they were based on a certain strategicconception, which Heikal elaborated on in an Al Ahram articlepublishedin Septemberof 1964 (see Safran, 1969, p. 292 and the discussionbelow). 2.2 The Brinkmanship Explanation In contrast to the psychological explanation, the main thrustof the brinkmanship explanation lies not in the idiosyncratic characteristicsof the Egyptianleader, or his decision-makingprocess, but rather in his manipulationof riskand, more generally,in the dynamics of escalation. Yost (1968) arguesthat 'by 17 May the crisishad already acquireda momentumwhich seemed inexorably to sweep all partiestowardand over the brink' (p. 315). Khouri (1968) and Draper (1968) mention Tiran as the critical turning-point,at which the cycle of escalation went out of control. Stein (1988) argues that the deterrent strategiesused by Egypt and Israelwere the catalyst (rather than the solution) to the process of 'miscalculatedescalation'. The success of Nasser's deterrent strategy unleashed a series of demands from his domestic public, and from Arab allies and foes, which he could not resist or control. On the Israeliside, 'the failureof its deterrent strategy dictated a military response, sooner or later' (p. 2; emphasisadded). Amos (1979) points out that at a certain point in the crisis - the removal of UNEF - the localized Egyptian-Syrian-Israeliconflict becameintertwinedwith the intra-Arab conflict, as waged in the Arab media; these two conflicts'beganto cycle together, building up a dynamismof their own' (p. 57). Dupuy (1978), too, writes that both sides blunderedinto the crisis and contributedto its escalation: 'It was a case of tragic, and classic, escalation.. .' (p. 225). The brinkmanshipthesis, then, maintains that as the crisis progressed, the rush of events became an autonomousforce which neither side could control. In terms of Nasser'sdecisions, the argumentappearsto be that by asking for the removal of UNEF, or by imposing the blockade, he inadvertently relinquished control over factors decisive for the subsequent development of 363 the crisis, namelyIsraeliperceptionof available options, and domestic and Arab pressures for furtherescalation. The first problem in the brinkmanship explanation concerns the symmetryof the crisis-dynamicsargument- the contention that both parties were overtaken by events and that both parties, once beyond a certainpoint, could no longer exert control over the cycle of escalation. It is curious that those who advance this argumentalso make abundant simultaneous references to Nasser's psychological shortcomings and to the impact of non-rational (or irrational) elements on his decision-making process. The symmetry of the argument in fact makes idiosyncratic factors irrelevant. If neither Nasser nor Israel's decision-makers could controlthe rushof events afterTiran, then Nasser'sown shortcomingsshould not have mattered - he could no longer avert disastereven if he were a paragonof rationality. Elaboratingon the ways in which he departed from a rational decision-making mode tends to confuse rather than enlighten, because it implies that had another leader been at the helm at this point, the crisis would have ended differently. But if this conclusion is drawn, it necessarily undercuts the force of the 'uncontrollablemomentum' argument and elevates the psychology of the individual leader to the status of the primaryexplanatory factor. The second (and related) difficultyin the brinkmanshipexplanationlies in its failure to document convincingly the thesis that after the UNEF or Tirandecision, the crisis acquiredits own uncontrollablemomentum. Vague as it is, this argumentmustbe at least refutable. Looking at the Egyptian side of the (symmetric)equation, could it be maintained that in making the UNEF or Tiran decisions, Nasser pulled the triggerto war? A negative answercould be given if it were shown that, even at this stage, there was no consensus in the Israeli governmentfor a pre-emptivestrike. I will examine the evidence on this point later. For now, suffice it to say that unwarranted attention to the Israeli casus belli This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 364 Ben D. Mor over Tiran has led several observers to inherentin the post hoc approachthatunderassume on this basis alone that Nasser's lies the prevailingaccountsof the crisis. blockade of the Straits pre-determinedthe Finally, if Nasser'scrisis decisionscan be outcome of the crisis. explained on the basis of strategicrationality, then his failureshouldbe interpretedin a differentlight. This suggestsin turnthat it 3. Nasseras a StrategicallyRationalActor may be necessaryto re-evaluatethe lessons The difficultiesencounteredby the psycho- concerning crisis management that have logical and brinkmanship explanations been drawn to date from this particular suggest that an alternative perspective on case. Most observersagree that Nasser, at least Nasser's 1967 behavior is in order. In the remainderof this paperI develop a rational- initially, did not want war with Israel choice explanation of Nasser's crisis (Dawn, 1968, p. 202; Khouri, 1968, pp. decision-making.This approachis theoreti- 244-245; Yost, 1968, p. 304), nor did he cally attractiveif only for the reason that it think it very likely on the eve of the crisis has not been appliedto this case before and (Safran, 1969, pp. 267-271). Since 1956, he thereby provides a fresh angle on events had continuallyarguedthat the Arabs were that have perhapsbeen overstudiedfrom a not yet readyto undertakean armedconflict cognitive approach.5More importantly,in with Israel. During the Arab summitmeetapplying a rational-choiceapproachto the ings of 1964-65, for example, he decisively study of Nasser's 1967 behavior, one per- opposed a Syrianproposalto launch largeforce proceedsfrom a premisethat has been scale guerrillaattacksagainst Israel, out of repeatedlyrejected: that Nasser's behavior concern that such a strategymight provoke can be explained on the basis of strategic Israelto attack(Safran,1969, p. 273). It is worth noting that Nasser did not rationality. A rational-choice explanation must go intervene when Israel launched a raid beyond the assertion that decision-makers againstthe Jordanianvillage of al-Samuon choose coursesof actionthat maximizetheir 13 November 1966. Neither did he come to values or policy objectives (Allison, 1971). Syria's assistance - despite the EgyptianThe essence of strategicrationalityis that, in Syrian joint defense agreement (in effect choosing a maximizingaction, actors take since November 1966) - when, on 7 April into account the alternatives,preferences, 1967, Israel bombardedSyrianpositions in and possible strategychoices of other rele- the Golan Heights and shot down six Syrian vant actors (Niou et al., 1989). The rele- MIGs (Yaniv, 1987). On 25 September 1964, in an Al Ahram vance of other actors derives from the fact that in an interdependentenvironment,out- article, Heikal described the conditions comes are the result of the interactionof under which Nasser believed Egypt could individualchoices. successfullyengage Israelin war. These conI shall argue that Nasser's 1967 decisions ditions were: 'the concentrationof superior can be interpretedfrom such a perspective. militarypower; the isolationof Israel;Arab This argumentrequires that we reproduce unity' (Safran, 1969, p. 292; see also the strategicenvironment,as it appearedto Draper, 1968, p. 71). None of these conthe Egyptian leader, and understand his ditions obtained on 14 May when Nasser choices in the particularcontext in which decided to mobilize. It is possible to conclude, then, that he thought he was operating. With respect to each of Nasser's decisions, then, the Nasser - at least initially - preferred the question to be asked is not how it contri- statusquo to war. Thus, when rumorsbegan buted to his subsequent failure but rather circulatingtoward mid-Maythat Israel was why it was made at that particularstage in about to launcha strike againstthe Damasthe crisis. By refrainingfrom the use of the cus regime, the alternativesfacing Nasser crisis outcome as the starting-pointof ex- were either to escalate or to refrain from planation, we can avoid the logical pitfalls action (as he had done before).6 Nasser This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nasser's Decision-making in the 1967 Crisis could easily foresee the consequences of the latter strategy: whether Israel in fact attacked Syria or not, Egypt would be faulted for not coming to the assistance of its Syrian ally. This would have constituted a serious personal blow to Nasser; not only had he for a long time now been taunted by his foes in the Arab world for having agreed to the stationing of UNEF troops on Egyptian territory (Draper, 1968, p. 44; Khouri, 1968, pp. 244-245; Yost, 1968, pp. 303304), but his cautious strategy with regard to Israel had also contributed to his decline in prestige in the Arab world (Safran, 1969, p. 282). On the other hand, if Nasser escalated and Israel attacked Syria nevertheless, this would represent a failure of Egyptian deterrence. But Nasser had good reasons to doubt that such would be the outcome of Egyptian escalation. With the assistance of the 1960 Rotem crisis as an analogy (see note 4), he could have estimated that if Egypt signaled its intention to support its ally, Israel would probably prefer to abstain from attacking Syria than risk confrontation on a second front. And, even if the Israelis were not planning to overthrow the Damascus regime, the Egyptian deterrent move would still appear to have been effective. Finally, there was no reason to suppose that Israel, as the status quo power, would be interested in escalating further the situation along the Egyptian-Israeli border. Nasser could have expected, then, that Egyptian mobilization would either deter Israel from attacking Syria or appear to do so (which was just as good), without triggering an actual Egyptian-Israeli confrontation. This was the most desirable outcome for the Egyptian leader. In fact, Israel responded to Nasser's 14 May decision by alerting regular army units and moving some of them to the Sinai border. This was followed (on 16 May) by a limited mobilization of reserves (Brecher, 1980, p. 36). Nasser's crisis behavior after 14 May is more puzzling and raises two questions: (1) Why did he at all consider further escalation as a possible strategy? and (2) Why did he actually choose the escalation strategy after 14 May? The first question requires that we 365 establish a relevance (or means-end connection) between Nasser's objectives in the 1967 crisis and an escalation strategy. The second question requires that we show that Nasser's actual crisis behavior - escalation up to 30 May and de-escalation thereafter was a maximizing means toward his goals. Before these questions can be addressed, it is necessary to examine Nasser's crisis perception after 14 May - in particular, his view of Israel's preferences. Once Nasser made his initial move by mobilizing Egyptian troops, the crisis moved to its second stage. At this point Nasser's main concern was no longer Israel's intentions with respect to Syria but rather her possible reaction to his own future moves. Having changed the strategic picture by his mobilization decision, the Egyptian leader had to consider Israel's preferences anew. But whereas Nasser could estimate Israel's preference structure with relative certainty in the first stage of the crisis, he could no longer do so once in the second stage. This is indicated by his probabilistic estimates of an Israeli attack, which he specified after the war, in his speech at the Cairo University auditorium on 23 July 1967: 1. 'When we concentrated our forces I estimated that the likelihood of war breaking out was 20 per cent.' 2. 'Before we closed the Gulf of Aqabah, we convened a meeting of the Higher Executive Committee ... We discussed the closure of the Gulf of Aqabah. That meeting took place on 22nd May. At that meeting I told them that the possibility of war was 50 per cent.' 3. 'At another [subsequent] meeting I said that the likelihood of war was 80 per cent.' 4. 'Then came the political changes in Israel at the beginning of June. As we followed what was going on there, the probability of war became 100 per cent' (cited in Laqueur, 1968, pp. 197-207). The probability estimates contained in these statements can be interpreted in conditional terms, namely as dependent on the This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 366 Ben D. Mor strategy choices made by both parties to the conflict at each of the different crisis stages. This interpretation follows from Nasser's overall perception of the crisis, as will be argued later. The probability estimates can be seen to imply that Nasser considered two possible sets of Israeli preferences: one which would make the non-attack strategy rational for Israel's leaders, and another which would make the attack strategy rational. Under the first set of preferences, Israel was perceived to prefer some level of escalation along the Egyptian-Israeli border to war between the two countries. This preference reflects the view that Israel was the status quo power, and therefore content with preserving it. Safran (1969, p. 266) writes that 'both Egypt . . . and Israel seemed to be in agreement that full-scale war was not likely as long as the kind of politico-military balance that prevailed during that period continued to exist .'. Nutting (1972, p. 408) recalls that in his conversations with the Egyptian leader during the last days of the crisis, Nasser indicated that 'he could ride out the storm provided he offered Israel no further provocation'. Earlier on, then, he must have believed that Israel was not interested in war with Egypt. In addition, we can speculate that Nasser was aware that political considerations of international sympathy and support were paramount to the Israeli government. (After all, he believed that one of the conditions for the success of an Egyptian military campaign against Israel was her isolation.) Even if Israel subsequently decided to attack, she would prefer war in which she could appear as the defensive party - i.e. the party confronted by escalation - to war in which she would appear as the intransigent aggressor, even if in the former case she would necessarily have to confront a mobilized opponent. For a time, then, Israel would be ready to tolerate some Egyptian escalation - and would choose retaliatory measures short of war - rather than engage in full-scale war. Nasser's experience in the Rotem crisis could only lend additional support to this view. It is reflected in the relatively low probability estimate of Israeli attack that he believed to apply following his mobilization decision of 14 May. However, the fact that Nasser thought of an Israeli attack in probabilistic terms indicates that he considered it possible - and increasingly more probable - that Israel's policy preferences would change. Moreover, in relating his probability estimates of Israeli attack to his own pattern of escalation, Nasser testified to his understanding that Israel's crisis strategy might change in reaction to his own moves. Specifically, it appears that he was concerned with the probability that at some point in the crisis the situation would make it rational for Israel to attack, whether he continued to escalate or not. He understood, in other words, that once a certain level of escalation was reached, Israel would prefer war over any other possible resolution of the crisis. Below this level, Egyptian escalation would succeed; but not knowing where the red line would be drawn, Nasser could choose to face the risk inherent in a gamble or opt out (i.e. stabilize or end the crisis), either by abstaining from further escalation or by de-escalating, as he indicated to Nutting he thought would be possible. Given this strategic context, the question to be asked is whether Nasser's crisis decisions were based on strategic rationality. The answer depends on the crisis objectives the Egyptian leader was pursuing. In the absence of well-grounded empirical data on Nasser's goals, we can only hypothesize about their nature. This hypothesis, in turn, gives rise to a rationalchoice explanation to the extent that: (1) Nasser's crisis decisions can be shown to have been a relevant and maximizing means toward his presumed goals; and (2) other observed aspects of his behavior were consistent with the hypothesized goals.9 The hypothesis suggested here is that in the 1967 crisis Nasser sought to restore his leadership position in the Arab world by avenging his defeat in the 1956 war (hence the crisis objective) and, at the same time, achieve this goal without provoking an Israeli attack (hence the crisis constraint)."' The hypothesized objective meets the relevance: requirement of means-end This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nasser's Decision-making in the 1967 Crisis Nasser did not raise the ante so as to 'manipulate the shared risk of war' (Schelling, 1966, p. 99); if that were the purpose, then any of a number of escalatory moves could have the desired effect. Rather, he sought to challenge very specific arrangements (i.e. the forced stationing of UNEF on Egyptian soil) and commitments (i.e. the Israeli casus belli over Tiran), which he found to be humiliating but had had to endure ever since the 1956 war. And because his humiliation eventually cost him his leadership of the Arab world, he saw an intrinsic value in his final act of escalation the conclusion of the Egyptian-Jordanian defense pact - which signified his newly restored status as undisputed leader. If Nasser's escalatory moves were logically connected to his crisis objective, the question is whether they were also a maximizing means toward this objective, given the constraint of avoiding war. Elsewhere (Mor, 1990) I argue that Nasser's perception of the strategic context and his probability estimates can be used to model the 1967 crisis as a multi-stage game. I reasoned that if Nasser's actual crisis behavior conformed to the mathematical solution of the game, then it can be interpreted on the basis of strategic (i.e. game-theoretic) rationality. The solution to the game indicated that Nasser's crisis behavior was rational (i.e. maximized his crisis objectives under the war-avoidance constraint) if the value he associated with each successive escalatory move - UNEF, Tiran, and the Pact - grew faster than the (increasing) probability of war. This result is understandable, because as Nasser progressed through the crisis, the odds of war (as he perceived them) grew and could be offset only by increasingly higher values associated with successive acts of escalation." It can be argued that Nasser's actual valuation of his escalation moves conformed to this pattern. If the scope of the agenda that Nasser could credibly force upon the Israelis is taken as a criterion, then certainly the valuation of successive escalation moves increased as the crisis progressed: the removal of UNEF and the blockade of the Straits were designed to eradicate the 367 embarrassing remnants of the 1956 war; the Tiran blockade had the additional value of constituting an open challenge to Israel, which considered it to be a casus belli. But whereas UNEF and Tiran were seen as obstacles to the restoration of Nasser's status in, and leadership of, the Arab world - and in this sense were 'negatives' to be removed, or undone - the Pact decision was unrelated to the post-1956 period and could therefore be seen as a major positive achievement. The Pact enabled Nasser through the concentration of Arab power and the show of Arab unity - to open up the possibility of expanding the agenda to include the pre-1956 period, namely the humiliating consequences of the 1948-49 war.12 But Nasser's ability to solidify his considerable gains depended in turn on his ability to stabilize the crisis and force Israel to deal diplomatically with the newly created agenda. Thus, whereas Nasser's valuation of the UNEF, Tiran, and the Pact achievements was sufficiently high to offset the increased probability of war he associated with obtaining them, after 30 May the constraint of avoiding war dictated prudence. (This is also the game-theoretic result: it was rational for Nasser to stop escalating after the Pact decision; see Mor, 1990, for details.) Did Nasser's behavior in the post-Pact period (31 May-4 June) conform to the of strategic rationality? imperatives Whereas observers of the crisis concur that Nasser escalated up to the point of signing the Pact, there is no agreement on the nature of his moves thereafter: Did he escalate the crisis further, or did he attempt to de-escalate it after 30 May? In the early days of June, the Arab military noose around Israel was gradually tightening. In addition to Egyptian, Jordanian, and Syrian troops, Israel now had to confront the presence of Iraqi forces in Jordan, which constituted an Israeli casus belli (Stein & Tanter, 1980, p. 107). On 4 June, Iraq officially joined the Egyptian-SyrianJordanian pact. Whereas Israel's decisionmakers believed that the joint military capabilities of the Arab states would increase This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 368 Ben D. Mor their intent to attack(Stein & Tanter, 1980, p. 236), it appearsthat the militarymoves under Nasser's control were designed for defensive purposes. There is in fact substantialevidence that Nasser attemptedto stabilizethe crisisafter 30 May. Nutting's personal testimony has already been mentioned. In a conversation Nuttinghad with Nasserduringthe last days of the crisis, the Egyptian leader told him that he still believed war could be avoided, provided there was no furtherprovocation (Nutting, 1972,p. 408). Nasseracted on this belief by instructingEgyptianforces in Sinai to abstain from any provocation of the Israelis. Defensive positions were taken despite the objectionsof Badranand Amer, who pressured for a pre-emptive strike.13 According to Bar-Zohar (1970, p. 176), when the EgyptianHigh Commandmet on 2 June, Nasser instructedthat, in light of indicationsthat the crisis was subsiding,no excuse should be given to the Israelis for attacking. Khouri (1968, p. 247), too, arguesthat 'as soon as he had achieved his most immediatepolitical objectives, Nasser was content to sit back and go no further'. There is also the recordof Nasser'sdiplomatic activities during the last days of the crisis:his pledge to Johnson and De Gaulle that Egypt would not be the one to attack (Heikal, 1973;Riad, 1981);his responseto a question put to him (on 2 June) by British MP ChristopherMayhewthat Egypt had no intentionof attackingIsrael;a similarassurance he gave Johnson's envoy, Charles Yost, when the latter visited Cairo at the beginningof June; his decisionto send Vice President Zakaria Mohieddin on a visit to Washingtonon 5 June;and his agreementto a return visit by Vice President Hubert Humphrey(Heikal, 1973;Riad, 1981;Yost, 1968). On 31 May, Egypt's Ambassadorto the United States, El Kony, suggested a formula for a compromise solution to the issue of Tiran(Stephens, 1971, p. 307). What of this was picked up by the Israelis is a different matter. What concerns us here is whether Nasser in fact viewed his public statements as essentially stabilizing. Dawn (1968) argues that although Nasser could not abstain from belligerent rhetoric, he was 'the last to join the campaignof words' (p. 220) and even then took care to emphasize that Egypt would act militarilyonly in response to an Israeliattack.A similarpoint is made by Heikal (1973, p. 245). Heikal'saccountis particularlyinteresting because it revealssomethingabout Nasser's own perception of the role of rhetoric in general. Heikal writes (pp. 237-238) that earlier in 1967, when Sadat returnedfrom Washingtonafter a meeting with Johnson, he brought with him a message from the AmericanpresidentadmonishingNasserfor his open attackson the USA and callingon him to resort to quiet diplomacy. In response, Nasser called in the US ambassador and sent through him a verbal message to Johnson.In this message, Nasserstated that quiet diplomacywould suit the USA, which has 'money and atom bombs, riches and power without limit' but 'would not suit us because I would be cut off from the support of my masses'. Arguingthat 'the main weapon of the Revolution is its masses', he added: 'If I am to be readywith my weapon I must always be ready to talk to the Arab people.' Badeau (1968, p. 98) has also arguedthat 'the Arab world is highly verbal;words are often ends in themselvesand not necessarily forerunnersof action'. In the 1967 crisis, however, suchwas not the perceptionof the Israelis. Cohen (1988, p. 10) notes that Nasserwas 'utterlyobliviousto the yawning culturalgap whichensuredthat his vituperative rhetoricwas taken at its face value by Israel'. His hints of moderationwere 'concealed by a thicket of threateninghyperbole'. 4. TheReasonsfor Nasser'sFailure If Nasser's crisis behavior was strategically rational,then where did he go wrong?If we consider that Nasser chose to de-escalate the crisis after 30 May in the hope of stabilizing the situation, and an Israeli attack occurrednonetheless, then the logicalplace to begin the analysis is with the Pact decision. In Nasser's perception, Israel's preferences after 30 May should have made it This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nasser's Decision-making in the 1967 Crisis 369 rational for her to abstain from attack, tioning in Ismailia when the Israeli attack provided he did not escalate further, which was launched (Bar-Zohar, 1970, p. 176). he didn't. Instead, Israel behaved as if her Dupuy (1978, p. 236) maintains that Nasser's decision to retain Amer as his comdid make an attack strategy preferences rational. Clearly, then, Nasser misperceived mander in chief and first deputy - despite Israel's preferences after 30 May. More pre- deteriorating relations and rumors that the cisely, since he perceived the probability of latter was planning a coup - 'seems ample Israeli attack to be related to his own evidence that he did not expect a war to moves, his failure lay in not realizing that his eventuate in 1967'. Derogy & Carmel (1979) latest escalatory step had, in effect, raised - relying on the testimony of the Soviet diplomat Sakharov, who was stationed in Cairo this probability to certainty. This shifts the attention to Nasser's (1968-70) before defecting to the West decision to sign the Egyptian-Jordanian argue that the Soviets knew of Israel's plan Pact. At this stage of the crisis, his percep- to attack on 5 June, but did not inform tion was that further escalation on his part Nasser of this so as 'to prevent his backing (i.e. the Pact) would raise the probability of out...' (p. 218). On the other hand, in his 23 July 1967 an Israeli attack to 0.80. Given this percepvaluation but his speech Nasser claimed to have correctly tion, more-than-offsetting of the Pact, it was rational for Nasser to assessed the implications of Dayan's escalate, and to conclude logically - when appointment. In the same speech he also Israel once again failed to attack - that he indicated that on 2 June, in a meeting with would get yet another chance to stabilize the senior military officers at the Supreme Comcrisis by de-escalating. In other words, mand HQ, he told his listeners that he Nasser interpreted the Israeli restraint expected an Israeli attack to take place following his 30 May decision as evidence within 48 to 72 hours, and even specified that the outcome of the 'chance event' - the that the attack would begin on 5 June with a signing of the Pact - was in his favor, strike against the Egyptian Air Force. The because it did not trigger an Israeli shift in same account is repeated in Sadat (1977) and Riad (1981). policy preferences. These accounts cannot be easily reconThis analysis conforms with the evidence and further research is required in to staon above Nasser's ciled, attempts presented bilize the crisis after 30 May. Bar-Zohar order to establish the correct picture. But (1970, p. 176) argues that when the Egyp- the evidence is perhaps not as contradictory tian High Command met on 2 June, the as it appears to be at first sight. To begin view of the participants was that Dayan's with, it is possible that Nasser was simply appointment to the post of Defense Minister uncertain about the implications of Dayan's (1 June) was an Israeli domestic matter. appointment. There were, after all, quite a few indicators that the crisis was in fact subTherefore, it 'created no undue excitement'. According to Lebanese press reports, by siding. Primary among them was the US 3 June Egyptian military commanders diplomatic effort, which appeared to be believed that the crisis was over and that gaining momentum with the visits of Robert further alertness in the armed forces was not Anderson and Charles Yost, the imminent necessary (Shamir, 1967, p. 202). This atti- departure to Washington of Moheiddin, and tude of the Egyptian elite may explain why the expected return visit of Humphrey. Barthe deployment of Egyptian aircraft near Zohar (1970, pp. 180-181) provides ample the country's civilian airport was that of 'sit- evidence that around the world the general ting targets for enemy attacks' (Nutting, opinion was that the crisis was in fact over, 1972, p. 416); why on 4 June 'Egyptian and Mansfield (1969, pp. 168-169) writes generals were seen on the tennis courts of that 'many seasoned observers in the Middle Cairo' (Churchill & Churchill, 1967, p. 75); East believed that [Nasser] had got away and why the Egyptian commander of the with it'. It is not surprising therefore - but Sinai front, General Murtaghi, was vaca- somewhat inconsistent with his claim to This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 370 Ben D. Mor have predicted the onset of war - that in the same speech of 23 July Nasser lashed out at the USA for having engaged in deception prior to the Israeli attack. Nasser's statement of 2 June to his military officers may well have been a warning rather than a prediction. Given the officers' over-confidence in the Egyptian army's capabilities and level of preparedness, Nasser may have felt it necessary to jolt them into action. In this he apparently did not succeed, as revealed subsequently by the poor alertness level of the Egyptian forces. Returning to the analysis of Nasser's misperception, the question arises as to whether it in fact came into play on 30 May, when he signed the Pact, or earlier (22 May), when he decided to close the Straits. The answer depends on when Israel's policy preferences actually changed. If the change occurred after 22 May, then the prevalent view in the literature, namely that Tiran was the point of no return, is correct. There are good reasons, however, to doubt this claim. They lie in Israel's perception of the crisis, and of her options, in the period following Nasser's Tiran decision. Eban's (1977) analysis of the crisis suggests that he in fact viewed the Tiran blockade as a point of no return, but not in the sense of rendering war inevitable but rather in the sense of ensuring some form of Israeli resistance. Eban's preference was that this resistance take the form of combined international action, spearheaded by the United States, to open the Straits to Israeli navigation. He argues that Dayan voiced a similar opinion in a Cabinet meeting called by Eshkol on 23 May.14 During that same meeting, according to Eban, 'our military colleagues had made no proposals for immediate military action' (p. 333; see also Brecher, 1980, pp. 117-126). Ezer Weizman (then Chief of Operations) writes (1976, p. 211) that at that point the General Staff 'was perplexed and confused' as well. Its doubts concerning the necessity of an Israeli strike were eliminated only around 26 May (p. 213). Rabin's (1979) memoirs contain a scathing, and revealing, indictment of Israeli hesitation following Nasser's Tiran decision. He recalls (pp. 80-81) a particularly bitter confrontation with Interior Minister Moshe Chaim Shapira on 23 May. The latter, who was adamantly opposed to any military action, accused Rabin (then Chief of Staff) of compromising Israel's security. He repeated his opposition to the military option in a meeting of Cabinet members held by Eshkol on 26 May. Rabin writes that 'Shapira was not the only minister to hold such views, though the others refrained from expressing themselves so bluntly' (p. 90). Even as late as 30 May, when the Pact was signed, Rabin perceived that 'our political leaders remained captive to their illusory hopes that war might be averted' (p. 93). Similar accounts of Israel's hesitation following Nasser's 22 May decision are provided by Kimche & Bawly (1968, pp. 137-138) and Bar-Zohar (1970, p. 119). The reaction to Nasser's signing of the Pact, however, was quite different. Eban (1977, p. 380) writes that 'by his journey to Cairo on 30 May, Hussein made it certain that war would break out and that it would not necessarily be limited to the EgyptianIsraeli front'. Eban understood the significance of the Pact, namely that Israel would now have to fight on three fronts. Accordingly, in a 31 May meeting with heads of departments in the Foreign Ministry, he argued that 'the assumption of two weeks' respite [decided on by the government on 28 May] must now be revised, and that our dialogue with the United States must be modified accordingly' (p. 381). 15 Stein & Tanter (1980, p. 218) write that 'Israel's leaders were stunned by the joint defense pact', but understood its significance. They 'quickly jettisoned the prevailing hypothesis that Arab unity was insufficient to permit an attack . . . and drastically updated their estimate of the likelihood of joint Arab military action' (p. 219). It was in response to this development that Eban, who led the dovish coalition, decided to reopen the 28 May decision to delay military action by two additional weeks (p. 220). Kimche & Bawly (1968, p. 154) argue that, together with the growing evidence that the USA was getting nowhere This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nasser's Decision-making in the 1967 Crisis in its diplomatic efforts, the Pact was decisive in leading to the collapse of 'Eban's antiwar front' (p. 155). At that point, 'there were no more doubters' in the government (p. 154). (See also Dayan, 1976, p. 373, and Churchill & Churchill, 1967, p. 52, on this point.) 5. Conclusion: Teaching and Crisis Management Why did Nasser fail to realize that his Pact decision would trigger the change in Israel's policy preferences? The answer appears to be somewhat paradoxical: Nasser failed because up to that point he had succeeded so well. Despite the odds against him, Nasser managed, within the course of three weeks, to escalate with impunity and secure for himself gains which only a month before appeared to be beyond his reach. All the chance events involved in his escalatory choices turned out in his favor - namely, they resulted in an outcome which permitted him to proceed with his escalation. If learning requires a negative discrepancy between expectations and outcomes (Bandura, 1977; Maoz, 1990a), we may argue that in the case of Nasser in 1967 there was no trigger to learning. The key lies in Israel's reaction to Nasser's moves. Draper (1968, p. 70) argues that 'the evidence is overwhelming that Israel acted exactly as Nasser expected it to act'. This is inaccurate - Nasser had reasons for being surprised. As the odds against him grew and Israel still remained hesitant, Nasser's expectations fell short of the actual outcomes. Thus, there was no reason for him to revise his strategy (or, rather, to revise his probability estimate of Israeli attack and thereby his own strategy). Hence, the strategy which appeared rational at the outset of the crisis remained so until the end (or at least until the beginning of June, when he might have realized his mistake). To recall, Stein (1988, p. 2) argues that 'Egyptian deterrence did not fail but succeeded too well' in that it 'unleashed a set of demands which the president was unable to resist'. The conclusion suggested here is that 371 Nasser's success was in fact at the root of his failure, but for a different reason altogether - it did not permit a trigger to learning, which was required in order for him to reevaluate his strategy. This naturally turns attention to the Israeli behavior. Did Israel in fact fail to 'teach' Nasser that he was approaching the red line, or the point at which the nonattack strategy would cease to be rational? Several participants and observers have argued precisely that. Weizman (1976, p. 215), for example, writes: 'I don't hesitate to number our government's hesitancy and apprehensions as direct causes of Egyptian escalation'. This also appears to be the view of Safran (1969), Cohen (1988), Quandt (1977), Amos (1979), Bar-Zohar (1970), and Yaniv (1987). Cohen (1988, p. 14) writes that 'the measured warnings and unobtrusive military dispositions preferred by Israel either failed to register with the Egyptians or were simply taken as proof of weakness'. Yaniv (1987) argues that in comparison with Ben-Gurion's handling of the 1960 Rotem crisis, Eshkol's defensive actions in 1967 were neither discreet nor decisive enough to convey the correct message. In addition, Eshkol did not enjoy the reputation for toughness and resolve that had been Ben-Gurion's (pp. 118-119). Bar-Zohar (1970, p. 65) argues that in the meeting in which the decision to close the Straits was taken, Nasser's advisers reasoned that even Ben-Gurion took no immediate action when Egypt proceeded to close the Gulf in September 1955. It was hard to believe, therefore, that Eshkol would risk war over Tiran. There was nothing in Israel's behavior during the period thereafter which could have convinced Nasser that he had been wrong. If the conclusion is that the success of Nasser's strategy provided no trigger for revisions, then it appears to be an interesting variant of a more general empirical observation on learning, namely that 'nothing fails like success'. Jervis (1975) discusses this paradox with respect to decisionmakers' learning from history - when analogizing to the past leads to the adoption of a strategy that worked then even if it does not This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 372 Ben D. Mor apply to the present. This study suggests that the paradox may also operate within a given conflict; the mechanism which produces it, however, appears to be somewhat different: the analogy drawn is not from the present to a past event, but rather from the present to some earlier strategic scenario which guides expectations. In Nasser's case, the parallels between the actual events of the crisis and his earlier expectations were strong enough to produce a repetition of the successful strategy. These parallels would have appeared far less reassuring to Nasser had Israel managed the crisis differently. Instead, Israel's behavior could have only convinced him that his earlier estimates were rather conservative. When seen in a broader perspective of crisis escalation in general, this conclusion points to the importance of teaching in crisis. From the perspective of the defender who is interested in preserving the status quo, sharp escalatory moves - such as were initiated by Nasser in 1967 - may appear to be the product of resolve, boldness, or recklessness. In some crises, this is in fact the case, and the defender may then justly perceive that its only alternatives are capitulation or attack. But this study suggests that bold escalation may also be the result of insufficient indicators for strategy revision. This occurs when a challenger's expectations are met, or even surpassed by actual events. If the challenger is simply interested in provoking the defender to attack, then the defender must decide whether to do so or to capitulate. But if the challenger's objective is to achieve a maximal revision of the status quo short of war, then it is paradoxically interested in being 'taught' by the defender about the latter's preferences. If the defender fails to do so, it may bring about an outcome which is inferior for both " parties. Determining what the challenger really wants is not an easy task. Neither is it certain that the challenger will interpret the defender's messages and signals correctly. But the lesson of the 1967 case is that by failing to attempt to teach the challenger where the red line will be drawn, a defender traps itself in an attribution error. It attributes the challenger's boldness to the latter's preferences and concludes therefrom that a defense of the status quo requires nothing less than war. In effect, then, the defender relinquishes the means by which it can evaluate the challenger's objective. NOTES 1. Unfortunately, this practice does not result in explanations that integrate the two levels and specify their interrelationships. One consequence of this is that, within single studies, explanations offered at one level are often inconsistent with explanations offered at another level, as I argue below. 2. One wonders what the historical verdict would have been had the United Nations, or the major powers, taken successful steps to stabilize the crisis. One suspects that Nasser's decisions would have been heralded as the product of an ingenious strategic mind. 3. Both Lacouture (1973) and Nutting (1972) supply ample documentation for Nasser's cautious policy after 30 May. More is said on this point later. 4. For a discussion of the 1960 Rotem crisis and some of its parallels to the 1967 crisis, see Yaniv (1987). That the Rotem analogy influenced Nasser's thinking is suggested by Amos (1979, p. 55), Brecher (1980, p. 46), Dupuy (1978, p. 230), Heikal (1973), Kimche & Bawly (1968, pp. 84-85), Stein (1988, p. 4, fn. 29) and Stein & Tanter (1980, p. 138). Israeli and American decision-makers also shared this perception initially. See Eban (1977, p. 323), Quandt (1977, p. 39), Rabin (1979, p. 68), and Weizman (1976, p. 209). Stein (1988, p. 5) argues that Nasser's restraint in the 1960 crisis was the result of his then secure position at home and abroad. In 1967, on the other hand, he was a weak leader who could not resist the pressures exerted on him. This reasoning is not entirely convincing. It presupposes that insecurity and weakness breed aggression, whereas strength yields restraint. This relationship, however, is not logically necessary: a weak leader may realize that he/she cannot afford to take the same risks that a strong and secure leader can. In fact, despite his weakness, Nasser showed remarkable restraint during the years immediately preceding the 1967 crisis, as well as during the crisis itself, as is argued later. 5. There are, however, rational-choice studies of the crisis from the Israeli perspective. See Stein & Tanter (1980), Wagner (1974), and Zagare (1984, 1981). Maoz (1990b) uses the dollar auction game to analyze the 1967 crisis, which he offers as an instance of 'the paradox of crisis escalation' - confrontations that end in war, contrary to the wishes of the parties involved and despite their efforts to prevent it. This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nasser's Decision-making in the 1967 Crisis 6. The question of Israel's intentions with respect to Syria in mid-May is an intensely debated one in the literature (see, for example, Badeau, 1968, p. 110; Derogy & Carmel, 1979, pp. 207-222; Laqueur, 1968, pp. 74-75; Shamir, 1971, p. 187; and Yaniv, 1987, pp. 115-117). Neither is there agreement on whether Nasser believed the Soviet and Syrian reports of Israeli troop concentrations near the Syrian border. Dawn (1968, p. 209) and Yost (1968, pp. 303-304) argue that Nasser believed an Israeli attack on Syria was forthcoming. I agree with Safran's (1969) view that even if he had doubts about the reliability of the information, 'in a certain particular sense he believed it to be essentially true' (p. 278; emphasis in original). 7. As Safran (1968, p. 291, fn. 19) argues, the 80% estimate, then, must have been made between the Tiran decision and 1 June. There is also no apparent reason to think that Nasser was insincere, or intent on misleading his audience, when he specified these probability estimates in his speech. They do not seem to advance any deceptive purpose on his part, and they are quite consistent with his interpretation of the course of the crisis. It should be noted, though, that Sadat (1977, p. 172), who participated in the 22 May meeting of the Higher Executive Committee, recalls that Nasser said he believed war would occur with certainty if the Straits were closed. This is contrary to Nasser's statement quoted above. If Sadat is correct, then Nasser in effect opted for war when he closed the Straits. Stein (1988) argues, based on the Sadat figure, that Nasser decided to challenge Israeli deterrence because he was led to underestimate Israel's military capability and overestimate his own. There is reason to doubt Sadat's account on this point. Heikal, who on 26 May had written an Al Ahram article arguing that war was inevitable (see quote in the introduction), said to Stephens (1971, p. 481) in July 1969 that this had not been Nasser's view at the time. The testimony of Anthony Nutting (1972; see below) supports Heikal's claim. It also contradicts Badran's account (see Safran, 1969, p. 300, fn. 25) that in a conference held by Nasser on 28 May in the Egyptian General Headquarters, he stated that the probability of war had risen from 80% to certainty. (Note that Badran's account contradicts that of Sadat.) 8. Because we seek at this point to present the crisis from Nasser's perspective, it makes sense to incorporate his own probability estimates into the overall strategic picture. Whether Nasser was in fact justified in generating these particular estimates is a different matter, to be discussed later. 9. This approach to analyzing the crisis follows the 'inference pattern' Allison (1971) specifies for the Rational Actor Model. See in particular his explanation of the Soviet decision to place missiles in Cuba, which involves several hypotheses about Soviet objectives. 10. Although this hypothesis suggests that Nasser was attempting brinkmanship, it leads to an interpretation of Nasser's behavior and failure that differs 373 in several respects from the brinkmanship explanation discussed in Section 2.2. 11. This argument presumes that Nasser was 'riskneutral' (i.e. his attitude toward risk did not affect the expected-value calculation) and that he was uncertain about the outcome of war against Israel. That is, Nasser did not think he would necessarily lose the war but neither did he expect to be necessarily successful in maintaining his crisis achievements if war broke out. 12. Some students of the 1967 crisis have extended their criticism of Nasser's behavior to include the values underlying his preference formation (i.e. pride, personal prestige, and a leadership role). It is therefore important to recall at this point Cohen's (1988) perceptive comment that 'to the Arab leader the fraternal Arab states are what the family is to the individual: the source of his identity and reputation. The revelation of Nasser's impotence [i.e. during the Samu incident of November 1966 and the Syrian-Israeli clash of 7 April 1967] in full view of his peers was an excruciating humiliation which would not go unavenged' (p. 7). 13. Much has been written about the deployment pattern of the Egyptian forces. The best analyses are those of Dupuy (1978) and Stein (1988). This issue resulted in a sharp division of opinion between the Israelis and the Americans during the course of the crisis. Israel argued (through Eban, who on 27 May was in Washington for a meeting with Lyndon Johnson) that the Egyptian deployment suggested a likely attack. The Pentagon, however, did not find evidence for this claim. Later on, when head of Mossad, Meir Amit, visited Washington, he found it difficult to convince Pentagon officials that Israel's estimate of Egyptian intentions was correct. (See Eisenberg et al., 1979, for details on this meeting.) 14. Following the advice of Ya'acov Herzog, the Director-General of the Prime Minister's Office, Eshkol agreed on 23 May to invite leaders of the opposition to participate in the deliberations of the Ministerial Committee on Defense. Dayan took part in the 23 May meeting as a member of the Rafi party. On 1 June he became Defense Minister. Dayan's (1976, p. 378) recollection of the meeting is that although he indicated that a US solution to the Tiran blockade would be acceptable ('I would be very pleased'), he 'did not think anything would come out of it'. Therefore, he recommended to the Committee that following the forty-eight hour respite requested by the USA, Israel should launch a strike against the Egyptians. 15. The Pact decision appears to have changed the perception of the crisis in Washington as well. BarZohar (1970, p. 157) reports that upon hearing of Nasser's move, 'the Americans realized that they had been on the wrong track'; Walt Rostow called Evron, Israel's Minister in Washington, and 'confessed for the first time that he could see no solution'. 16. This conclusion relates to signaling during a crisis. Similar arguments are often raised in connection This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 374 Ben D. Mor with crisis initiation, where the issue is that of effective signaling of commitment to deter challenges to the status quo (see, for example, the discussion of the Korean War in George & Smoke, 1974, and Lebow, 1981). In Israel's case, an interest in conveying to Nasser the limits of Israeli tolerance made sense as long as Nasser did not conclude the Pact with Jordan. But once Israel failed to deter this further escalation of the conflict, and once this development triggered the change in her preferences concerning war, she became interested in keeping Nasser in the dark about her true preferences, so as to maintain strategic surprise. Paradoxically, Israel's earlier failure at signaling may have helped her to project a consistent pattern of moderation even as she was preparing for war: Dayan's press conference of 3 June; the pictures of Israeli soldiers (several thousands of whom had been granted leave) resting on the beaches; and the routine communique issued by the Cabinet on 4 June, made the 'right' impression in Cairo (see Churchill & Churchill, 1967, pp. 74-75, and Brecher, 1980, p. 165). REFERENCES Allison, Graham T., 1971. Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis. Boston, MA: Little, Brown. Amos, John W., 1979. Arab-Israeli Military/Political Relations: Arab Perceptions and the Politics of Escalation. New York: Pergamon. Badeau, John S., 1968. 'The Arabs, 1967', pp. 97-113 in Majdia D. Khadduri, ed., The Arab-Israeli Impasse. Washington, DC: Robert B. Luce. Bandura, Albert, 1977. Social Learning Theory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Bar-Zohar, Michael, 1970. Embassies in Crisis: Diplomats and Demagogues Behind the Six-Day War. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Brecher, Michael, 1972. The Foreign Policy System of Israel: Setting, Images, Process. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Brecher, Michael, 1975. Decisions in Israel's Foreign Policy. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Brecher, Michael, with Benjamin Geist, 1980. Decisions in Crisis: Israel, 1967 and 1973. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Churchill, Randolph S. & Winston S. Churchill, 1967. The Six Day War. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin. Cohen, Raymond, 1988. 'Intercultural Communication Between Israel and Egypt: Deterrence Failure before the Six-Day War', Review of International Studies, vol. 14, no. 1, January, pp. 1-16. Dawn, C. E. 1968. 'The Egyptian Remilitarization of Sinai, May 1967', Journal of Contemporary History, vol. 3, no. 3, July, pp. 201-224. Dayan, Moshe, 1976. Story of My Life: An Autobiography. New York: Warner. Derogy, Jacques & Hesi Carmel, 1979. The Untold History of Israel. New York: Grove. Draper, Theodore, 1968. Israel and World Politics. New York: Viking. Dupuy, Trevor N., 1978. Elusive Victory: The ArabIsrael Wars, 1947-1974. New York: Harper & Row. Eban, Abba, 1977. An Autobiography. New York: Random House. Eisenberg, Dennis; Uri Dan & Eli Landau, 1979. The Mossad: Inside Stories. New York: NAL Penguin. George, Alexander L. & Richard Smoke, 1974. Deterrence in American Foreign Policy: Theory and Practice. New York: Columbia University Press. Heikal, Mohammed Hassanein, 1973. The Cairo Documents. New York: Doubleday. Herek, Gregory M.; Irving L. Janis & Paul Huth, 1987. 'Decision Making During International Crises', Journal of Conflict Resolution, vol. 31, no. 2, June, pp. 203-226. Jervis, Robert, 1975. Perception and Misperception in International Relations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Khouri, Fred J., 1968. The Arab-Israeli Dilemma. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press. Kimche, David & Dan Bawly, 1968. The Sandstorm. New York: Stein & Day. Lacouture, Jean, 1973. Nasser: A Biography. New York: Knopf. Laqueur, Walter, 1968. The Road to Jerusalem. New York: Macmillan. Laqueur, Walter, ed., 1969. The Israel-Arab Reader. New York: Bantam. Lebow, Richard Ned, 1981. Between Peace and War: The Nature of International Crisis. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. Mansfield, Peter, 1969. Nasser. London: Methuen Educational. Maoz, Zeev, 1990a. National Choices and International Processes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Maoz, Zeev, 1990b. Paradoxes of War: The Art of National Self-Entrapment. Boston, MA: Unwin Hyman. Mor, Ben D., 1990. 'Nasser's Decision-Making in the 1967 Middle East Crisis: A Multi-Stage Game Model'. Mimeo, Department of Politics, New York University. Niou, Emerson M. S.; Peter C. Ordeshook & Gregory F. Rose, 1989. The Balance of Power: Stability in International Systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nutting, Anthony, 1972. Nasser. New York: Dutton. Quandt, William B., 1977. Decade of Decisions: American Policy Toward the Arab-Israeli Conflict, 19671976. Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press. Rabin, Yitzhak, 1979. The Rabin Memoirs. Boston, MA: Little, Brown. Riad, Mahmoud, 1981. The Struggle for Peace in the Middle East. London: Quartet. Sadat, Anwar el-, 1977. In Search of Identity. New York: Harper & Row. Safran, Nadav, 1969. From War to War. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill. Schelling, Thomas C., 1966. Arms and Influence. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Shamir, Shimon, 1971. 'The Middle East Crisis: The Brink of War', Middle East Record, the Shiloah This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Nasser's Decision-making in the 1967 Crisis 375 Centerfor MiddleEasternand AfricanStudies,Tel Israel's Experience in 1967 and 1973. New York: Aviv University, vol. 3, pp. 183-204. Jerusalem: Praeger. IsraelUniversitiesPress. Weizman,Ezer, 1976. On Eagles' Wings.New York: Macmillan. Stein, Janice Gross, 1988. 'Deterrenceand Miscalculated Escalation:The Outbreakof War in 1967', Yaniv, Avner, 1987. Deterrence Without the Bomb. paperdeliveredat the AnnualMeetingof the AmeriLexington,MA: LexingtonBooks. can Political Science Association. Washington. Yost, C., 1968.'The Arab-IsraeliWar:How It Began', Stein, JaniceGross& RaymondJanter,1980.Rational ForeignAffairs,vol. 26, no. 2, January,pp. 304-320. Decision-Making: Israel's Security Choices, 1967. Columbus,OH: Ohio State UniversityPress. Stephens, Robert, 1971. Nasser: A Political Biography. New York:Simon& Schuster. Wagner, Abraham R., 1974. Crisis Decision-Making: Zagare, Frank C., 1984. Game Theory: Concepts and Applications.BeverlyHills, CA: Sage. Zagare, Frank C., 1981. 'NonmyopicEquilibriaand the MiddleEast Crisisof 1967',ConflictManagement and Peace Science, vol. 5, no. 2, Spring, pp. 139-162. BEN D. MOR, b. 1956, Assistant Professor, Department of Political Science, University of Haifa, Israel. Research areas: decision-making, international crises, the Middle East, and formal modeling. This content downloaded from 132.74.58.129 on Thu, 30 Oct 2014 05:06:27 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions