The Prehistory of the Autonomy of Science 2mmSemantic
Transcription
The Prehistory of the Autonomy of Science 2mmSemantic
The Prehistory of the Autonomy of Science Semantic Differentiation between Antiquity and Renaissance David Kaldewey Forum Internationale Wissenschaft (FIW), University of Bonn Presentation for the CASTI Workshop in Berlin, Humboldt University, 15-17 June 2015 Socio-Structural and Semantic Definitions of Autonomy • Socio-structural conception: An autonomous space is free from constraints (›negative freedom‹) – Heteronomy = Social structures are »constraining«, they restrict an agent in his freedom of action – Autonomy = Social structures are »enabling«, they provide the agent with possibilities and opportunities • Semantic conception: An autonomous space constitutes its own law (›positive freedom‹) – Which concrete forms of action and communication emerge in a social space that is free from external constraints? – What is meant in a material sense, rather than in a purely formal sense, when one speaks of the »autonomy of science«? Thomas Gieryn’s Definition of Science as an »Empty Space« • »But what is ›science‹? Nothing but a space, one that acquires its authority precisely from and through episodic negotiations of its flexible and contextually contingent borders and territories. Science is a kind of spatial ›marker‹ for cognitive authority, empty until its insides get filled and its borders drawn amidst context-bound negotiations over who and what is ›scientific‹.« (Gieryn 1995: 405) • Gieryn delineates the space of »science« in purely negative terms. He ignores that this empty space (as a semantic space) has a history. • The highlighted »until« implies that first there is a (socio-structural) space, and then it gets filled with (semantic) meaning. The Emergence of an »Empty Space«? Or: An Onomasiological Reconstruction of what Today We Conceptualize as »the Autonomy of Science« Five discoursive contexts and the respective semantic fields are examined: • ›Theoria‹ and ›praxis‹ as forms of life in the Athenian democracy • ›Otium‹ and ›negotium‹ in the Roman republic • ›Catharsis‹ and ›contemplation‹ in Neo-Platonism • ›Vita activa‹ and ›vita contemplativa‹ between Early Christianity and Scholasticism • Differentiation and Secularization of forms of life in the Renaissance Semantic Field I: Theory and Practice in the Athenian Democracy Greek philosophers such as Plato and Aristotle proposed an autotelic life dedicated to philosophy (›bios theoretikos‹) and claimed that this form of life is as valuable and as autonomous as the practical-political life of their fellow citizens (›bios praktikos‹). Semantic Field II: Otium and Negotium in the Roman Republic In the Roman Republic, political philosophers such as Cicero, Sallust, or Seneca valued the the vita activa higher than the vita contemplativa. However, within the semantic space of the political life, they distinguished between ›otium‹ (leisure time dedicated to philosophical studies) and ›negotium‹ (official duties, political affairs). Semantic Field III: Catharsis and Contemplation in Neo-Platonism In Neo-Platonism, contemplation (›theoria‹), understood as the vision of the absolute, is accorded primacy over all other forms of life. The active life is devalued and reconceptualized as mere preliminary stage, a life of purification (›katharsis‹). Semantic Field IV: Vita Activa and Vita Contemplativa in Early Christianity Building on the Neo-Platonic tradition, early Christian theology, patristics, and scholasticsm extensively reflected the relationships between ›vita activa‹ and ›vita contemplativa‹. The two forms of life marked two distinct semantic spaces: The one oriented towards this world (immanence), the other aiming at the hereafter (transcendence). Semantic Field V: Differentiation and Secularization in the Renaissance In the Renaissance, ancient, medieval, and scholastic discourses converged and gave rise to a a new kind of reflection on the value a philosophical life has for society. The ›vita activa‹ experienced a positive revaluation, while the ›vita contemplativa‹ was not devaluated, but transformed, differentiated, and secularized. The Semantic Space of Politics in Diachronic Perspective The Semantic Space of Science in Diachronic Perspective Conclusion I Discourses on Autonomy as »Preadaptive Advances« • The emergence of modern science depended on a previous differentiation of a semantic space in which a quest for truth, relieved of the pressure of practice, and an adequate mode of communication could be consolidated and legitimized. • Thus, in the terminology of evolutionary theory, the discourses on autonomy reconstructed here can be interpreted as »preadaptive advances« in terms of evolutionary theory, that is, as »solutions for problems that do not yet exist« (Luhmann 2005: 219). Conclusion II The Böckenförde Dilemma • Due to the fact that the semantic space of science gained its momentum and its autonomy while it was still embedded in a wider religious semantic field, one can assume that the notion of an autonomous philosophical-scientific quest for truth ultimately benefits from another, older notion of autonomy grounded on the absolute value of the contemplation of God. • Following the political philosopher Ernst-Wolfgang Böckenförde, »the liberal, secularized state is nourished by presuppositions that it cannot itself guarantee. That is the great gamble it has made for liberty’s sake« (1991: 45). – The same goes, as we may now assume, for modern, secularized science: its autonomy is rooted in traditions and in a moral substance that it cannot ensure itself. Conclusion III The Co-Construction of Socio-Structural and Semantic Spaces • None of the discourses on autonomy that have been discussed here can be fully understood in isolation, i.e. detached from the contemporary societal structures and social positions of the respective authors. Thus, we have to conceive of socio-structural and semantic spaces as co-constructed. • It would not be valid, or a materialistic fallacy, to regard the semantics discussed here as merely an effect or representation of social structures; and it would be equally problematic to view all institutions of knowledge simply as materializations of the respective discourses.