Folien - German Grammar Group FU Berlin
Transcription
Folien - German Grammar Group FU Berlin
Verbless Directives Towards a compositional analysis of verbless directives in German 17. HPSG Conference 2010, Université Paris-Diderot Paris VII, 7-10 July Jakob Maché Freie Universität Berlin Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 1/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... structural case in nominalisations I Consider this! Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 2/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... structural case in nominalisations I Consider this! According to Müller (2002), the complements with structural case will surface as genitive NPs – whenever the selecting head is a noun (1) a. Ich korrigiere die Klausuren I correct the.def.acc.pl exams ‘I am correcting the exams’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 2/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... structural case in nominalisations I Consider this! According to Müller (2002), the complements with structural case will surface as genitive NPs – whenever the selecting head is a noun (1) a. Ich korrigiere die Klausuren I correct the.def.acc.pl exams ‘I am correcting the exams’ b. Das [NP Korregieren [NP der Klausuren]] kann the correct-noun the.def.gen.pl exams can ganz schön angestrengend sein very quite exhausting be ‘The correction of the exams can be quite exhausting’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 2/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... structural case in nominalisations II The picture gets blurred, as soon indefinite bare plurals come into play. (2) a. Ich korrigiere Klausuren I correct the.ind.acc.pl exams ‘I am correcting the exams’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 3/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... structural case in nominalisations II The picture gets blurred, as soon indefinite bare plurals come into play. (2) a. Ich korrigiere Klausuren I correct the.ind.acc.pl exams ‘I am correcting the exams’ b. * Das [NP Korregieren [NP Klausuren]] kann ganz schön the correct-noun exams can very quite angestrengend sein exhausting be ‘The correction of the exams can be quite exhausting’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 3/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... structural case in nominalisations II The picture gets blurred, as soon indefinite bare plurals come into play. (2) a. Ich korrigiere Klausuren I correct the.ind.acc.pl exams ‘I am correcting the exams’ b. * Das [NP Korregieren [NP Klausuren]] kann ganz schön the correct-noun exams can very quite angestrengend sein exhausting be ‘The correction of the exams can be quite exhausting’ Lacking a determiner, they cannot be interpreted as embedded NP. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 3/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... structural case in nominalisations III An appropriate interpretation can be obtained, when the complement is introduced by a von-PP (3) a. Ich korrigiere Klausuren I correct the.ind.acc.pl exams ‘I am correcting the exams’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 4/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... structural case in nominalisations III An appropriate interpretation can be obtained, when the complement is introduced by a von-PP (3) a. Ich korrigiere Klausuren I correct the.ind.acc.pl exams ‘I am correcting the exams’ b. Das [NP Korregieren [PP von Klausuren]] kann ganz schön the correct-noun of exams can very quite angestrengend sein exhausting be ‘The correction of the exams can be quite exhausting’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 4/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... structural case in nominalisations III An appropriate interpretation can be obtained, when the complement is introduced by a von-PP (3) a. Ich korrigiere Klausuren I correct the.ind.acc.pl exams ‘I am correcting the exams’ b. Das [NP Korregieren [PP von Klausuren]] kann ganz schön the correct-noun of exams can very quite angestrengend sein exhausting be ‘The correction of the exams can be quite exhausting’ ⇒ structural case in German obviously can also be realised by a PP! Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 4/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Modal verbs with bare directional phrases I One more puzzle! Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 5/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Modal verbs with bare directional phrases I One more puzzle! As shown by Barbiers (2002), Szumlakowski-Morodo (2006, 327) : modal verbs with bare directional phrases do not involve an ellipsis of an infinitive! (4) Wir müssen hier raus! We must here out ‘We have to get out!’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 5/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Modal verbs with bare directional phrases II Szumlakowski-Morodo (2006, 325): if it were ellipsis... (5) Wir müssen hier raus (#gehen / #laufen)! We must here out go run ‘We have to get out!’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 6/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Modal verbs with bare directional phrases II Szumlakowski-Morodo (2006, 325): if it were ellipsis... (5) Wir müssen hier raus (#gehen / #laufen)! We must here out go run ‘We have to get out!’ ◮ ...it should be possible to derive the elided infinitive from discourse Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 6/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Modal verbs with bare directional phrases II Szumlakowski-Morodo (2006, 325): if it were ellipsis... (5) Wir müssen hier raus (#gehen / #laufen)! We must here out go run ‘We have to get out!’ ◮ ...it should be possible to derive the elided infinitive from discourse ◮ ... there should be a verb that can be inserted without any interpretative effect Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 6/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Modal verbs with bare directional phrases III The case of inanimate subjects, see Barbiers (2002) for Dutch and Szumlakowski-Morodo (2006, 327) for German: (6) a. Der Brief muss zur Post (#gehen) The letter must to.the post.office go ‘The letter has to be brought to the post office’ b. Der Brief muss zur Post (#gebracht werden) The letter must to.the post.office brought pas.aux ‘The letter has to be brought to the post office’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 7/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Modal verbs with bare directional phrases III The case of inanimate subjects, see Barbiers (2002) for Dutch and Szumlakowski-Morodo (2006, 327) for German: (6) a. Der Brief muss zur Post (#gehen) The letter must to.the post.office go ‘The letter has to be brought to the post office’ b. Der Brief muss zur Post (#gebracht werden) The letter must to.the post.office brought pas.aux ‘The letter has to be brought to the post office’ ◮ cannot be completed by a motion predicate (lack of animacy) Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 7/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Modal verbs with bare directional phrases III The case of inanimate subjects, see Barbiers (2002) for Dutch and Szumlakowski-Morodo (2006, 327) for German: (6) a. Der Brief muss zur Post (#gehen) The letter must to.the post.office go ‘The letter has to be brought to the post office’ b. Der Brief muss zur Post (#gebracht werden) The letter must to.the post.office brought pas.aux ‘The letter has to be brought to the post office’ ◮ cannot be completed by a motion predicate (lack of animacy) ◮ double ellipsis of past participle + passive auxiliary? Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 7/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Modal verbs with bare directional phrases IV Paul (1968, 320) about bare directional phrases with können, müssen, dürfen, sollen, wollen, mögen, lassen, helfen, wünschen: Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 8/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Modal verbs with bare directional phrases IV Paul (1968, 320) about bare directional phrases with können, müssen, dürfen, sollen, wollen, mögen, lassen, helfen, wünschen: ◮ that much frequent that they cannot be ellipses Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 8/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Modal verbs with bare directional phrases IV Paul (1968, 320) about bare directional phrases with können, müssen, dürfen, sollen, wollen, mögen, lassen, helfen, wünschen: ◮ that much frequent that they cannot be ellipses ◮ er ist weg (’he is away’), er ist nach Rom (’he is (on the way) to Rome’) ⇒ weg and nach Rom are predicates Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 8/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Modal verbs with bare directional phrases IV Paul (1968, 320) about bare directional phrases with können, müssen, dürfen, sollen, wollen, mögen, lassen, helfen, wünschen: ◮ that much frequent that they cannot be ellipses ◮ er ist weg (’he is away’), er ist nach Rom (’he is (on the way) to Rome’) ⇒ weg and nach Rom are predicates ◮ analogously woher hast du das? (’From where do you have that’) Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 8/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... directional phrases and word order I Yet another one! Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 9/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... directional phrases and word order I Yet another one! Steinitz (1989) quoting a talk by Bierwisch (1988): directional phrases occur in the unmarked case at the right periphery. No sentential negation between directional phrase and finite verb (7) a. daß er die Sachen nicht auf den Tisch stellt that he the things neg on the table puts Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 9/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... directional phrases and word order I Yet another one! Steinitz (1989) quoting a talk by Bierwisch (1988): directional phrases occur in the unmarked case at the right periphery. No sentential negation between directional phrase and finite verb (7) a. daß er die Sachen nicht auf den Tisch stellt that he the things neg on the table puts b. # daß er die Sachen auf den Tisch nicht stellt that he the things on the table neg puts Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 9/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... directional phrases and word order II Steinitz (1989) quoting a talk by Bierwisch (1988): no sentence adverbs between directional phrase and finite verb (8) a. Er hat wahrscheinlich das Buch auf den Tisch gelegt He has probably the book on the table put Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 10/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... directional phrases and word order II Steinitz (1989) quoting a talk by Bierwisch (1988): no sentence adverbs between directional phrase and finite verb (8) a. Er hat wahrscheinlich das Buch auf den Tisch gelegt He has probably the book on the table put b. Er hat das Buch wahrscheinlich auf den Tisch gelegt He has the book probably on the table put Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 10/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... directional phrases and word order II Steinitz (1989) quoting a talk by Bierwisch (1988): no sentence adverbs between directional phrase and finite verb (8) a. Er hat wahrscheinlich das Buch auf den Tisch gelegt He has probably the book on the table put b. Er hat das Buch wahrscheinlich auf den Tisch gelegt He has the book probably on the table put c. # Er hat das Buch auf den Tisch wahrscheinlich gelegt He has the book on the table probably put Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 10/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... directional phrases and word order III Steinitz (1989) quoting a talk by Bierwisch: no unstressed particles between directional phrase and finite verb (9) a. Er hat doch die Sachen ins Regal getan He has par the things in.the shelves done b. Er hat die Sachen doch ins Regal getan He has the things par in.the shelves done c. # Er hat die Sachen ins Regal doch getan He has the things in.the shelves par done Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 11/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... directional phrases and word order IV Steinitz (1989) quoting a talk by Bierwisch: no floating quantifier between directional phrase and finite verb (10) a. Wir haben alle unsere Sachen ins Regal gepackt We have all our things in.the shelves packed b. Wir haben unsere Sachen alle ins Regal gepackt We have our things all in.the shelves packed c. * Wir haben unsere Sachen ins Regal alle gepackt We have our things in.the shelves all packed Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 12/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Intonation patterns of directional PPs Finally... Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 13/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Intonation patterns of directional PPs Finally... As recently pointed out by Kratzer and Selkirk (2007) and Truckenbrodt (2010): locative PPs in all-new-sentences behave in mysterious manner: (11) Ich glaube, dass ein JUNGe [PP nach BERlin] fuhr. I think that a boy to Berlin went (12) Ich glaube, dass ein JUNGe eine GEIge [PP an einen Freund] I think that a boy a violin to a friend sent schickte. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 13/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Intonation patterns of directional PPs Finally... As recently pointed out by Kratzer and Selkirk (2007) and Truckenbrodt (2010): locative PPs in all-new-sentences behave in mysterious manner: (11) Ich glaube, dass ein JUNGe [PP nach BERlin] fuhr. I think that a boy to Berlin went (12) Ich glaube, dass ein JUNGe eine GEIge [PP an einen Freund] I think that a boy a violin to a friend sent schickte. ◮ Whenever no direct object present: stress on locative PP possible Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 13/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Intonation patterns of directional PPs Finally... As recently pointed out by Kratzer and Selkirk (2007) and Truckenbrodt (2010): locative PPs in all-new-sentences behave in mysterious manner: (11) Ich glaube, dass ein JUNGe [PP nach BERlin] fuhr. I think that a boy to Berlin went (12) Ich glaube, dass ein JUNGe eine GEIge [PP an einen Freund] I think that a boy a violin to a friend sent schickte. ◮ ◮ Whenever no direct object present: stress on locative PP possible Whenever direct object present: no stress on locative PP possible Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 13/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Outline I Four puzzles... Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Compositional approaches An HPSG analysis Objectives Basic assumptions Resultatives Directional phrases are predicates Word order Intonation Directional complements the ’with’-PP the analysis illocutionary force Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 14/162 Verbless Directives Four puzzles... Outline II directive instances ’wh’-version How does the adressee enter the stage? The Non-finite Head Specifier Scheme Open questions Conclusions Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 15/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality As discussed by Schwabe (1994), Jackendoff and Pinker (2005), Wilder (2008), Jacobs (2008) and Müller (2010), the directional phrase + mit-PP pattern is a challenge for compositionality: (13) [??? [PP In Staub] [PP mit allen Feinden Brandenburgs]]! with all enemies brandenburg-gen In dust ‘Down with all enemies of Brandenburg!’ Heinrich von Kleist, Prinz von Homburg IV, 11, written in 1809-1811 Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 16/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality As discussed by Schwabe (1994), Jackendoff and Pinker (2005), Wilder (2008), Jacobs (2008) and Müller (2010), the directional phrase + mit-PP pattern is a challenge for compositionality: (13) [??? [PP In Staub] [PP mit allen Feinden Brandenburgs]]! with all enemies brandenburg-gen In dust ‘Down with all enemies of Brandenburg!’ Heinrich von Kleist, Prinz von Homburg IV, 11, written in 1809-1811 ◮ Where does the mit (’with’) come from? Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 16/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality As discussed by Schwabe (1994), Jackendoff and Pinker (2005), Wilder (2008), Jacobs (2008) and Müller (2010), the directional phrase + mit-PP pattern is a challenge for compositionality: (13) [??? [PP In Staub] [PP mit allen Feinden Brandenburgs]]! with all enemies brandenburg-gen In dust ‘Down with all enemies of Brandenburg!’ Heinrich von Kleist, Prinz von Homburg IV, 11, written in 1809-1811 ◮ Where does the mit (’with’) come from? ◮ Where does the directive meaning come from? Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 16/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Typological perspective I As Wilder (2008) discusses, these patterns are typologically attested in all Germanic... (14) Into the bag with the money! (15) In die Tasche mit dem Geld! (German) into the-acc bag with the-dat money (16) pengene! (Norwegian) Ned i sekken med money-the bag-the with down into Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 17/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Typolgical perspective II ... and in some Slavic languages. (17) Do pytle s těma! (Czech) into bag with money (18) V šep z denarjem! (Slovenian) in bag with money Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 18/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Schwabe (1994) -Core Grammar vs. Marked Periphery I Already Schwabe (1994, 52) noted that only verbless utterances of the type (19) can be explained in terms of discourse ellipsis. there is no appropriate (empty) predicate that realises its theme-argument as mit-PP. (19) Tasche? Wohin die where.to the-acc bag ‘Where to with the bag?’ (20) Wohin mit der Tasche? where.to with the-dat bag ‘Where to with the bag?’ As for utterances belonging to the type of (20), she assumes that they are part of the marked periphery in terms of Chomsky (1981, 8). Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 19/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Schwabe (1994) – Core Grammar vs. Marked Periphery II IP I′ SpecI wohini I0 e VP V′ SpecV e DP AdvP die Tasche ei V0 e Figure: Analysis by Schwabe (1994, 30) Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 20/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Jackendoff & Pinker (2005) Noncanonical utterance types as PP with NP: (21) Off with his head! (22) Into the trunk with you! Jackendoff and Pinker (2005, 220): A syntactic nut! Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 21/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality A plea for a CxG Analysis I Jacobs (2008, 22): no compositional analysis available! What keeps us from assuming the directional phrase is the head ? Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 22/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality A plea for a CxG Analysis I Jacobs (2008, 22): no compositional analysis available! What keeps us from assuming the directional phrase is the head ? 1. Adverbs never exhibit categorial valency ⇒ they never select mit-PPs Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 22/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality A plea for a CxG Analysis I Jacobs (2008, 22): no compositional analysis available! What keeps us from assuming the directional phrase is the head ? 1. Adverbs never exhibit categorial valency ⇒ they never select mit-PPs 2. in German mood is never expressed lexically ⇒ directive meaning does not come from the directional phrase Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 22/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality A plea for a CxG Analysis I Jacobs (2008, 22): no compositional analysis available! What keeps us from assuming the directional phrase is the head ? 1. Adverbs never exhibit categorial valency ⇒ they never select mit-PPs 2. in German mood is never expressed lexically ⇒ directive meaning does not come from the directional phrase 3. no evidence that the directional phrase is indeed the head Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 22/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality A plea for a CxG Analysis II Jacobs (2008): only a non-compositional analysis might capture these facts: (23) 2 3 Phon /M mit Y/ 4Kat [U Xdir [pp mitP YNP,dat ] ] 5 Sem DIRill (sp,adr,[ GO-END(x,y) & Y’(x) & X’(w)]) Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 23/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Jacob’s (2008) analysis in more detail: Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 24/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Jacob’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ categorial selection of the mit-PP is part of the construction Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 24/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Jacob’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ categorial selection of the mit-PP is part of the construction ◮ directional meaning is part of the construction Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 24/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Jacob’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ categorial selection of the mit-PP is part of the construction ◮ directional meaning is part of the construction ◮ the addresse is semantically encoded Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 24/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Jacob’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ categorial selection of the mit-PP is part of the construction ◮ directional meaning is part of the construction ◮ the addresse is semantically encoded Some shortcomings of the analysis: Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 24/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Jacob’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ categorial selection of the mit-PP is part of the construction ◮ directional meaning is part of the construction ◮ the addresse is semantically encoded Some shortcomings of the analysis: ◮ how does it relate to similar patterns with nonfinite predicates? Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 24/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Jacob’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ categorial selection of the mit-PP is part of the construction ◮ directional meaning is part of the construction ◮ the addresse is semantically encoded Some shortcomings of the analysis: ◮ how does it relate to similar patterns with nonfinite predicates? ◮ empirically not true → also with question meaning! Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 24/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Jacob’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ categorial selection of the mit-PP is part of the construction ◮ directional meaning is part of the construction ◮ the addresse is semantically encoded Some shortcomings of the analysis: ◮ how does it relate to similar patterns with nonfinite predicates? ◮ empirically not true → also with question meaning! ◮ empirically not true → can also be embedded! Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 24/162 Verbless Directives Verbless directives – a challenge for compositionality Jacob’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ categorial selection of the mit-PP is part of the construction ◮ directional meaning is part of the construction ◮ the addresse is semantically encoded Some shortcomings of the analysis: ◮ how does it relate to similar patterns with nonfinite predicates? ◮ empirically not true → also with question meaning! ◮ empirically not true → can also be embedded! ◮ how could these patterns develop diachronically? Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 24/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: Wilder (2008) I ImpP Imp′ PP into the bagi Imp0 VP [Imp] [EPP] V′ PP with the money V0 ti GO Figure: Wilder’s 2008 analysis for English verbless directives Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 25/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: Wilder (2008) II Wilder’s (2008) analysis in more detail: Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 26/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: Wilder (2008) II Wilder’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ Riemsdijk (2002): these cases involve the phonologically empty motion predicate GO. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 26/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: Wilder (2008) II Wilder’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ Riemsdijk (2002): these cases involve the phonologically empty motion predicate GO. ◮ directive interpretation is provided by the ImpP Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 26/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: Wilder (2008) II Wilder’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ Riemsdijk (2002): these cases involve the phonologically empty motion predicate GO. ◮ directive interpretation is provided by the ImpP ◮ theme-argument marked as mit-PP whenever a locative is shifted accross it (As in spray/load-alternation). Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 26/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: Wilder (2008) II Wilder’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ Riemsdijk (2002): these cases involve the phonologically empty motion predicate GO. ◮ directive interpretation is provided by the ImpP ◮ theme-argument marked as mit-PP whenever a locative is shifted accross it (As in spray/load-alternation). Shortcomings for Wilder’s (2008) analysis Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 26/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: Wilder (2008) II Wilder’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ Riemsdijk (2002): these cases involve the phonologically empty motion predicate GO. ◮ directive interpretation is provided by the ImpP ◮ theme-argument marked as mit-PP whenever a locative is shifted accross it (As in spray/load-alternation). Shortcomings for Wilder’s (2008) analysis ◮ empty GO runs into problems whenever modal with inanimate subjects Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 26/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: Wilder (2008) II Wilder’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ Riemsdijk (2002): these cases involve the phonologically empty motion predicate GO. ◮ directive interpretation is provided by the ImpP ◮ theme-argument marked as mit-PP whenever a locative is shifted accross it (As in spray/load-alternation). Shortcomings for Wilder’s (2008) analysis ◮ empty GO runs into problems whenever modal with inanimate subjects ◮ is there compelling evidence for the assumption of GO at all? Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 26/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: Wilder (2008) II Wilder’s (2008) analysis in more detail: ◮ Riemsdijk (2002): these cases involve the phonologically empty motion predicate GO. ◮ directive interpretation is provided by the ImpP ◮ theme-argument marked as mit-PP whenever a locative is shifted accross it (As in spray/load-alternation). Shortcomings for Wilder’s (2008) analysis ◮ empty GO runs into problems whenever modal with inanimate subjects ◮ is there compelling evidence for the assumption of GO at all? ◮ where does the mit come from? Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 26/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: G. Müller 2010 I CP C0 V0 V0 TP C0 V0 T0 VP V′ PP [apass] [•T •] in den Müll VP tV V′ NP (mit) den Klamotten ti tV Figure: verbless directives by G. Müller (2010) Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 27/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: G. Müller 2010 II G. Müllers analysis in more detail: Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 28/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: G. Müller 2010 II G. Müllers analysis in more detail: ◮ involves a covert antipassive morpheme Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 28/162 Verbless Directives Compositional approaches Compositional approaches: G. Müller 2010 II G. Müllers analysis in more detail: ◮ involves a covert antipassive morpheme ◮ involves a phonologically empty verb Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 28/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Objectives Objectives Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 29/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Objectives Objectives ◮ provide a compositional analysis Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 29/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Objectives Objectives ◮ provide a compositional analysis ◮ to reduce the amount of empty categories Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 29/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Objectives Objectives ◮ provide a compositional analysis ◮ to reduce the amount of empty categories ◮ to derive the nature of verbless directives from existing well motivated assumptions Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 29/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Objectives Objectives ◮ provide a compositional analysis ◮ to reduce the amount of empty categories ◮ to derive the nature of verbless directives from existing well motivated assumptions ◮ the mit-PP is an instance of structural case triggered by a directional phrase Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 29/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Objectives Objectives ◮ provide a compositional analysis ◮ to reduce the amount of empty categories ◮ to derive the nature of verbless directives from existing well motivated assumptions ◮ the mit-PP is an instance of structural case triggered by a directional phrase ◮ to discuss ”verbless directives” in abroader context Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 29/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Basic assumptions Basic assumptions Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 30/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Basic assumptions Basic assumptions ◮ motion verbs + directional phrases are subtypes of resultative constructions Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 30/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Basic assumptions Basic assumptions ◮ motion verbs + directional phrases are subtypes of resultative constructions ◮ directional phrases are predicates Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 30/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Basic assumptions Basic assumptions ◮ motion verbs + directional phrases are subtypes of resultative constructions ◮ directional phrases are predicates ◮ the mit-PP is an instance of structural triggered by the environment of a directional phrase Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 30/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Basic assumptions Basic assumptions ◮ motion verbs + directional phrases are subtypes of resultative constructions ◮ directional phrases are predicates ◮ the mit-PP is an instance of structural triggered by the environment of a directional phrase ◮ declarative illocutionary force requires finiteness Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 30/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Basic assumptions Basic assumptions ◮ motion verbs + directional phrases are subtypes of resultative constructions ◮ directional phrases are predicates ◮ the mit-PP is an instance of structural triggered by the environment of a directional phrase ◮ declarative illocutionary force requires finiteness ◮ the addresse is not syntactically encoded Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 30/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Resultatives Directional phrase are resultative predicates The line of reasoning: ◮ Wechsler and Noh (2001, 401): directional phrases are subtypes of resultative predicates ◮ Müller (2002, 210): resultative constructions are complex predicates, they sometime involve a PP ◮ directional phrases are a resultative predicates An objection? Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 31/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Resultatives Directional phrase are resultative predicates The line of reasoning: ◮ Wechsler and Noh (2001, 401): directional phrases are subtypes of resultative predicates ◮ Müller (2002, 210): resultative constructions are complex predicates, they sometime involve a PP ◮ directional phrases are a resultative predicates An objection? ◮ Maienborn (1994, 232) directional PPs cannot be predicates, they are incompatible with copula constructions. ⇒ they have to be arguments Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 31/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Resultatives Already Hermann Paul knew it... Pointing out that directional predicates can be selected by the copula, Paul (1968, 320), explicitly calls them predicates: Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 32/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Resultatives Already Hermann Paul knew it... Pointing out that directional predicates can be selected by the copula, Paul (1968, 320), explicitly calls them predicates: ’[...]er ist weg, er ist nach Rom, die nicht anders aufzufassen sind als er ist in Rom, dh. weg und nach Rom sind als Prädikate zu nehmen ist als Kopula. Desgleichen er ist von Rom, woher ist er? ’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 32/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Directional phrases are predicates! I ’m not the only one! ⇒ independantly motivated by Paul (1968), Barbiers (2002) and Steinitz (1989) ⇒ Implicitly stated by Wechsler and Noh (2001, 401): predicates of motion have optional result state argument see (24) vs. (25): (24) He ran to the store. (25) He ran in place. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 33/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Lexicon entry for a predicate of motion see Wechsler and Noh (2001, 401): (26) 2 ¸ ˙ cat — subcat NPi 2 6 6 6 6relation 6 6 6 6 6cont 6 6 4 4 become Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 3 # 37 7 runneri 77 run-rel 77 7 #7 " 77 locatumi 57 ) 5 ( location-rel " 34/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Directional phrases and word order If directional phrases were predicates... Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 35/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Directional phrases and word order If directional phrases were predicates... → they should behave like other predicates with respect to linearisation. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 35/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Directional phrases and word order If directional phrases were predicates... → they should behave like other predicates with respect to linearisation. All we have to do, is to compare the linearisation rules for directional infinitives discussed by Steinitz (1989) with those of other predicate types (list suggested by Müller (2002)): Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 35/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Directional phrases and word order If directional phrases were predicates... → they should behave like other predicates with respect to linearisation. All we have to do, is to compare the linearisation rules for directional infinitives discussed by Steinitz (1989) with those of other predicate types (list suggested by Müller (2002)): ◮ verbs selecting bare infinitives: modals verbs, AcI,... ◮ verbs selecting past participles: perfect auxiliaries, passive auxiliaries ◮ copula + predicative phrases ◮ subject predicatives, object predicatives ◮ resultative predicates ◮ particle verbs Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 35/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Previous observations: Lenerz (1977) Already since Lenerz (1977, 88) it is known: ◮ that obligatory locative adverbs follow always the direct object, ◮ that free adverbs don’t Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 36/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Directional phrases and word order: Helbig/Buscha (1986) Already Helbig and Buscha (1986, 567 ) suggested that ”directional adverbs” are part of the right sentential bracket – as shown by Müller (2002) the genuin place for predicates in German. (27) Er fährt in diesem Sommer an die Ostsee he rides in this summer to the Baltic Sea ‘He will go to the Baltic Sea this summer’ (28) Sie sieht heute sehr blaß aus. she looks today very pale out ‘She looks very pale today’ As they illustrate those ”obligatory adverbials” take usually the position after freely occuring adverbs, see Helbig and Buscha (1986, 569): Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 37/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Nonfinite predicates and word order: negation I (29) a. daß er die Sachen nicht auf den Tisch stellt that he the things neg on the table puts b. daß sie den Hasen nicht essen kann that she the rabbit neg eat-inf can c. daß sie den Hasen nicht gegessen hat that she the rabbit neg eat-ppp has Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 38/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Nonfinite predicates and word order: negation II no sentential negation between nonfinite predicate and finite verb (30) a. # daß er die Sachen auf den Tisch nicht stellt that he the things on the table neg puts b. # daß sie den Hasen essen nicht kann that she the rabbit eat-inf neg can c. # daß sie den Hasen gegessen nicht hat that she the rabbit eat-ppp neg has Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 39/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Nonfinite predicates and word order: sentence adverbs I (31) a. Er hat wahrscheinlich das Buch auf den Tisch gelegt he has probably the book on the table put b. Sie wird wahrscheinlich den Film sehen dürfen she will probably the movie watch-inf may c. Sie wird wahrscheinlich den Hund erwürgt haben she will probably the dog strangle-ppp have Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 40/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Nonfinite predicates and word order: sentence adverbs II (32) a. Er hat das Buch wahrscheinlich auf den Tisch gelegt he has the book probably on the table put b. Sie wird den Film wahrscheinlich sehen dürfen she will the movie probably watch-inf may c. Sie wird den Hund wahrscheinlich erwürgt haben she will the dog probably strangle-ppp have Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 41/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Nonfinite predicates and word order: sentence adverbs III no sentence adverbs between nonfinite predicate and finite verb (33) a. # Er hat das Buch auf den Tisch wahrscheinlich gelegt he has the book on the table probably put b. * Sie wird den Film sehen wahrscheinlich dürfen she will the movie watch-inf probably may c. * Sie wird den Hund erwürgt wahrscheinlich haben she will the dog strangle-ppp probably have Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 42/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Nonfinite predicates and word order: unstressed particles I (34) a. Er hat doch die Sachen ins Regal getan he has par the things in.the shelves done b. Sie wird doch das Auto verkaufen wollen she will par the car sell-inf want c. Sie kann doch den Dieb gekannt haben she could par the thief know-ppp have Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 43/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Nonfinite predicates and word order: unstressed particles II (35) a. Er hat die Sachen doch ins Regal getan he has the things par in.the shelves done b. Sie wird das Auto doch verkaufen wollen she will the carpar sell-inf want c. Sie kann den Dieb doch gekannt haben she could the thief par know-ppp have Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 44/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Nonfinite predicates and word order: unstressed particles III no unstressed particles between nonfinite predicate and finite verb (36) a. # Er hat die Sachen ins Regal doch getan he has the things in.the shelves par done b. * Sie wird das Auto verkaufen doch wollen she will the car sell-inf par want c. * Sie kann den Dieb gekannt doch haben she could the thief know-ppp par have Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 45/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Nonfinite predicates and word order: floating quantifiers I (37) a. Wir haben alle unsere Sachen ins Regal gepackt we have all our things in.the shelves packed b. Sie wird alle deine Rechnungen bezahlen müssen she will all your bills pay-inf must c. Sie wird alle ihre Freuden verloren haben she will all her joys lose-ppp have Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 46/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Nonfinite predicates and word order: floating quantifiers II (38) a. Wir haben unsere Sachen alle ins Regal gepackt We have our things all in.the shelves packed b. Sie wird deine Rechnungen alle bezahlen müssen she will your bills all pay-inf must c. Sie wird ihre Freuden alle verloren haben she will her joys all lose-ppp have Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 47/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Nonfinite predicates and word order: floating quantifiers III no floating quantifiers between nonfinite predicate and finite verb (39) a. # Wir haben unsere Sachen ins Regal alle gepackt We have our things in.the shelves all packed b. * Sie wird deine Rechnungen bezahlen alle müssen pay-inf all must she will your bills c. * Sie wird ihre Freuden verloren alle haben lose-ppp all have she will her joys Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 48/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Word order Nonfinite predicates and word order: floating quantifiers III no floating quantifiers between nonfinite predicate and finite verb (39) a. # Wir haben unsere Sachen ins Regal alle gepackt We have our things in.the shelves all packed b. * Sie wird deine Rechnungen bezahlen alle müssen pay-inf all must she will your bills c. * Sie wird ihre Freuden verloren alle haben lose-ppp all have she will her joys SUMMARY WORD ORDER: directional phrases and nonfinite predicates behave exactly the same Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 48/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation Intonation: Kratzer/Selkirk (2007) I Kratzer and Selkirk (2007, 105): (40) The Highest Phrase Condition on prosodic spell-out: The highest phrase within the spellout domain of a phase corresponds to a prosodic major phrase in phonological representation. (spell-out domain: sister of the phase head: C0 → TP, V0 → VP) Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 49/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation Intonation: Kratzer/Selkirk (2007) II CP C′ C0 TP T′ dass ein Junge i T0 VP V′ ti V0 VP nach Berlin V0 fährt Figure: Kratzer/Selkirk (2007) (simplified): intransitive verbs + PP Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 50/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation Intonation: Kratzer/Selkirk (2007) III CP C′ C0 TP T′ dass ein Junge i T0 VP V′ ti V0 VP eine Geige V′ an einen Freund V0 schickte Figure: Kratzer/Selkirk (2007) (simplified): transitive verbs + PP Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 51/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation Intonation: Truckenbrodt (2010) I (41) Stress XP: Each lexical XP must contain a phrasal stress Truckenbrodt (2010): if Stress XP is indeed true then: Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 52/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation Intonation: Truckenbrodt (2010) I (41) Stress XP: Each lexical XP must contain a phrasal stress Truckenbrodt (2010): if Stress XP is indeed true then: ⇒ locative PPs cannot be phrasal complement of V Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 52/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation Intonation: Truckenbrodt (2010) I (41) Stress XP: Each lexical XP must contain a phrasal stress Truckenbrodt (2010): if Stress XP is indeed true then: ⇒ locative PPs cannot be phrasal complement of V ⇒ locative PPs are incorporated into the V-head Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 52/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation Intonation: Truckenbrodt (2010) II CP C′ C0 TP T′ dass ein Junge i T0 VP V′ ti V0 VP eine Geige V′ V0 an einen Freund V0 schickte Figure: Truckenbrodt2010: transitive verbs with incorporated PP Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 53/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation Intonation: other types of predicates I According to Müller (2002), a fistfull of lexical items are involved in German predicate complex formation: ◮ verbs selecting bare infinitives: modals verbs, AcI,... (42) ◮ verbs selecting past participles: perfect auxiliaries, passive auxiliaries (43) ◮ copula + predicative phrases (44) ◮ subject predicatives, object predicatives ◮ resultative predicates (45) ◮ particle verbs (46) As shown by Müller (2002, 207): depictive predicates (47) are not part of the predicate complex. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 54/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation Intonation: other types of predicates II prediction: whenever a direct object is present: predicate unstressed Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 55/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation Intonation: other types of predicates II prediction: whenever a direct object is present: predicate unstressed (42) ... dass ein PROFessor eine POLka [INF tanzen] will. that a professor a polka dance-inf wants (43) ... dass ein PROFessor eine POLka [PPP getanzt] hat. dance-ppp has polka that a professor a (44) ist ... dass ein GAST ein exotisches GeRICHT [ADJ gewohnt] accustomed is dish that a guest a exotic (45) ... dass ein MAHLer einen PFOSTten [ADJ schwarz] streicht. paints black pillar that a painter a (46) ... dass ein FÄHRmann einen FAHRgast [PAR über]setzt. that a ferryman a passanger ferry.across Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 55/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation The case of depictive predicates Expectation: since depictive predicates are not part of the predicate complex (Müller (2002)), different intonation should be possible. (47) ... dass ein Rat einen WÄHLer [ADJ NACKT] besucht. that a council a voter naked visits Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 56/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation The case of depictive predicates Expectation: since depictive predicates are not part of the predicate complex (Müller (2002)), different intonation should be possible. (47) ... dass ein Rat einen WÄHLer [ADJ NACKT] besucht. that a council a voter naked visits Depictive predicate is stressed even in the environment of a direct object. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 56/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation The case of depictive predicates Expectation: since depictive predicates are not part of the predicate complex (Müller (2002)), different intonation should be possible. (47) ... dass ein Rat einen WÄHLer [ADJ NACKT] besucht. that a council a voter naked visits Depictive predicate is stressed even in the environment of a direct object. ⇒ for similar observation, see Uhmann (1991, 202) Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 56/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Intonation The case of depictive predicates Expectation: since depictive predicates are not part of the predicate complex (Müller (2002)), different intonation should be possible. (47) ... dass ein Rat einen WÄHLer [ADJ NACKT] besucht. that a council a voter naked visits Depictive predicate is stressed even in the environment of a direct object. ⇒ for similar observation, see Uhmann (1991, 202) SUMMARY INTONATION: directional phrases and (nonfinite/resultative) predicates behave exactly the same Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 56/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Directional complements Verbs with bare directional phrases There is a systematic alternation between nonfinite complements and complements with directional meaning. ◮ verbs selecting bare infinitives: können, müssen, dürfen, sollen, mögen, brauchen lassen, würde gerne, helfen, trauen, haben, sein Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 57/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Directional complements Verbs with bare directional phrases There is a systematic alternation between nonfinite complements and complements with directional meaning. ◮ verbs selecting bare infinitives: können, müssen, dürfen, sollen, mögen, brauchen lassen, würde gerne, helfen, trauen, haben, sein ◮ verbs with past participles: gehören, bekommen, sein, haben Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 57/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Directional complements Verbs with bare directional phrases There is a systematic alternation between nonfinite complements and complements with directional meaning. ◮ verbs selecting bare infinitives: können, müssen, dürfen, sollen, mögen, brauchen lassen, würde gerne, helfen, trauen, haben, sein ◮ verbs with past participles: gehören, bekommen, sein, haben ◮ motion verbs with bare infinitives: kommen, gehen, schicken, senden Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 57/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Directional complements Verbs with bare directional phrases II (48) Bill bekommt (von seiner Frau) Opium geschenkt) Bill gets by his wife opium offeredpas.aux ‘Bill got from his wife opium for present’ (49) Bill bekommt das Opium durch den Zoll. Bill gets the opium through the costum ‘Bill got the opium through the costums’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 58/162 An HPSG analysis Directional phrases are predicates Directional complements Verbs with bare directional phrases II (48) Bill bekommt (von seiner Frau) Opium geschenkt) Bill gets by his wife opium offeredpas.aux ‘Bill got from his wife opium for present’ (49) Bill bekommt das Opium durch den Zoll. Bill gets the opium through the costum ‘Bill got the opium through the costums’ SUMMARY COMPLEMENTATION: directional phrases and (nonfinite/resultative) predicates occur in similar environments Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 58/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis the ’with’-PP mit-PP as structural case ◮ remember the need to assume that also PPs can represent structural case for nominalisation with indefinite bare plural objects! ◮ with-PP is the structural case assigned by directional phrases ◮ it concerns always a THEME argument, an argument that is usually is marked with structural case Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 59/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis the ’with’-PP The Case Principle (modified version) ...adding to the Case Principle along the lines suggested by Meurers (1999), Przepiórkowski (1999) or Müller (2002, 15)a fourth clause captures the fact Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 60/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis the ’with’-PP The Case Principle (modified version) ...adding to the Case Principle along the lines suggested by Meurers (1999), Przepiórkowski (1999) or Müller (2002, 15)a fourth clause captures the fact i. In a list that contains both subject and complements of a verbal head, the first element with structural case is assigned nominative case unless it is raised to a dominating head Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 60/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis the ’with’-PP The Case Principle (modified version) ...adding to the Case Principle along the lines suggested by Meurers (1999), Przepiórkowski (1999) or Müller (2002, 15)a fourth clause captures the fact i. In a list that contains both subject and complements of a verbal head, the first element with structural case is assigned nominative case unless it is raised to a dominating head ii. All other elements of this list with structural case are assigned accusative case. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 60/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis the ’with’-PP The Case Principle (modified version) ...adding to the Case Principle along the lines suggested by Meurers (1999), Przepiórkowski (1999) or Müller (2002, 15)a fourth clause captures the fact i. In a list that contains both subject and complements of a verbal head, the first element with structural case is assigned nominative case unless it is raised to a dominating head ii. All other elements of this list with structural case are assigned accusative case. iii. In nominal environments all elements with structural case are assigned genitive case Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 60/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis the ’with’-PP The Case Principle (modified version) ...adding to the Case Principle along the lines suggested by Meurers (1999), Przepiórkowski (1999) or Müller (2002, 15)a fourth clause captures the fact i. In a list that contains both subject and complements of a verbal head, the first element with structural case is assigned nominative case unless it is raised to a dominating head ii. All other elements of this list with structural case are assigned accusative case. iii. In nominal environments all elements with structural case are assigned genitive case iv. An element with structural case enlisted in a spr-list of a directional predicate is realised as mit-PP unless it is raised into the domain of a dominating verbal head Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 60/162 An HPSG analysis the ’with’-PP the analysis Lexical entry of a directional predicate I Directional phrases are resultative predicates. An analysis along the lines of Müller (2002) is indeed possible: (50) 2in den Staub (’into the dust’) 2 333 2 6 6 6 6 6cat 6 6 6 6 6 6 6 6 6 6cont 6 6 4 6 6head 6 6 6 6 6spr 4 subcat 2 theme 6 4goal move form nonfinite D ˆ ˜ E 77 77 6 4subj np str 1 57 77 77 prep 77 D ˆ ˜ E 77 77 np str 1 57 7 7 hi 7 3 7 7 1 7 7 7 5 7 7 5 Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 61/162 An HPSG analysis the ’with’-PP the analysis Lexical entry of a directional predicate I Some more details: ◮ corresponds to lexical entry of a resultative predicate ◮ the argument of the predicate is represented in both the subj-list and the spr-list ◮ subj is a head feature, could never be saturated by ID-scheme Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 62/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis illocutionary force No declarative illocutionary force without finiteness As noted by Jacobs (2008): never with declarative meaning - only with directive meaning. But see Reis (1985, 307), Schwabe (1994, 52), Reis (1995, 121 Fn 9.), citet[][ 174 Fn. 17]Reis2003: wh-meaning We have to consider at least four cases: ◮ directive directional predicates + with-PP ◮ wh directional predicates + with-PP ◮ embedded directional predicates + with-PP ◮ embedded wh directional predicates + with-PP Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 63/162 An HPSG analysis illocutionary force directive instances Directive directional phrases (51) [??? [PP In Staub] [PP mit allen Feinden Brandenburgs]]! In dust with all enemies brandenburg-gen ‘Down with all enemies of Brandenburg!’ Heinrich von Kleist, Prinz von Homburg IV, 11, written in 1809-1811 properties of the construction: ◮ no particular adressee needs to be present Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 64/162 An HPSG analysis illocutionary force directive instances Other instances of nonfinite directives Infinitives, past participles and directive NPs behave in similar fashion – see Reis (1995, , 117 & 138) and Reis (2003, 171). ◮ allow for directive meanings ◮ allow for a modal wh-interpretation ◮ do not license overt subjects ◮ license a +wh A-Bar Pposition Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 65/162 An HPSG analysis illocutionary force directive instances Other instances of nonfinite directives II External argument is coreferent with adressee: (52) Alle bis auf einen aussteigen! all but of one get.out-inf ’All but one of you, get out!’ (53) Keiner den Raum verlassen! noone the room leave-inf ’Noone leaves the room’ (54) Tiroler Fussball-Miniknaben aufgepasst! Tyrolian football-junior.team listen.upppp Listen up members of football junior teams! Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 66/162 An HPSG analysis illocutionary force ’wh’-version As already known since Reis (1985), Schwabe (1994), Reis (1995), Reis (2003) and Wilder (2008) root directional phrases also are compatible with wh-morphology. As pointed out by Reis (2003, 171), they are closely related to root wh-infinitives: ◮ wh- RIs always have a nonpast, prospective interpretation ◮ wh- RIs always have a modal interpretation ◮ wh- RIs subject interpretation is restricted to the speaker ◮ wh- RIs always are interpreted as speaker oriented not as hearer-directed, information seeking Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 67/162 An HPSG analysis illocutionary force ’wh’-version Root wh-directional phrases: wohin mit and woher mit ⇒ : mainly two instances: wohin: ca. 4400 hits (ca. 870 embedded) woher 5 hits (55) Wohin mit den ”illegalen Einwanderern”? Where.to with the illegal immigrants ‘What to do with the illegal immigrants’ (56) mit dem Geld für die Schönes Projekt, aber woher Beautiful project, but where.from with the money for the Umsetzung? realisation ‘Beautiful project, but how do we get the money for the realisation?’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 68/162 An HPSG analysis illocutionary force ’wh’-version Embedded wh-directional phrases As soon as wh are embedded, they lose their illocutionary force. (57) Die USA wissen nicht, wohin mit ihrem Atommüll The USA know neg where.to with their nuclear.waste ‘The US don’t know what to do with their nuclear waste’ As already pointed out by Reis (1985, 307) Reis (1995, 120) and Reis (2003, 174), mostly embedded by wissen + neg. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 69/162 An HPSG analysis illocutionary force ’wh’-version However, in corpora also other matrix predicates can be found, even if very rare. (58) Österreich hatte keine blasse Ahnung, wohin mit Ball, Austria had no pale idea where.to with ball Spiel und Gegner. game and adversary ‘Austria didn’t have any idea what to do with the ball, the game and the adversary’ (59) auch sagen, wohin Dann sollten die Bildungspolitiker where.to Then should the education.politicians also tell mit den Studenten. with the students ‘In this case the educational politicians should also tell, what to do with the students’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 70/162 An HPSG analysis illocutionary force ’wh’-version Why never declarative? Is directive more basic than declarative? ◮ speculation: in communication more important: directives ◮ Schottel (1663, 548): imperatives often correspond to the verbal root, since they were the first words ◮ Klein (2008): finiteness prerequisite for declarative illocutionary force Reis (1995, 143) and Reis (2003, 183) ◮ directive infinitives contain a modal operator with a bouletic ordering source:(set of possible world consistent with the wishes of the speaker) ◮ declarative speech acts anchor the proposition only to the actual world ◮ finiteness is the expression of that anchoring Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 71/162 An HPSG analysis illocutionary force ’wh’-version A compositional account is possible! ◮ the directional phrase + mit-PP behave like root infinitives ◮ those two types of nonfinite predicates constitute a bigger family (Reis 2003, 196): a compositional analysis is possible for wh-infinitives! SUMMARY ILLOCUTIONARY FORCE: directional phrases and (nonfinite/resultative) predicates behave exactly the same Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 72/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis How does the adressee enter the stage? How does the adressee enter the stage? ◮ Lexically encoded, as suggested by Jacobs (2008)? ◮ Not syntactically encoded see Wilder (2008, 247), Reis (1995, 136) Reis (1995, 136): The infinitive always has a modal bouletic interpretation, it expresses a whish by the speaker. ⇒ the addressee is saturated pragmatically. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 73/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis How does the adressee enter the stage? Imperative operator by Wilder (2008) To bed with you! Into the money! Imperative operator: ”Speaker commands Addresse to bring about p” ◮ p = you (addresse) GO to bed ◮ p = the money GO into the bed Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 74/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis How does the adressee enter the stage? No need to encode the addresse! Another case of bouletic modality - where the hell is the adressee? (60) I would like to have the lobster in butter sauce Another case of directive root infinitive! (61) Zahlen bitte! pay-inf please ‘The bill please!’ Notice, as opposed to most other directive infinitives: external argument ’payer’ is coreferent with the speaker. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 75/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis The Non-finite Head Specifier Scheme Non-finite Head Specifier Scheme I (62) Non-finite-Head-Specifier-Scheme 2 3 synsem — loc — cat — spr hi 2 3 2 3 " # 2 3 2 3 6 7 6 7 form nonfinite 6 7 6 7 head 6 7 6 7 6 7 6 6 7 6 7 6 7 adv-or-prep-or-verb cat 4 57777 6 7 6 6 6 loc ˙ ¸ 6head-dtr 6synsem 6 6 7777 6 7 1 spr 4 5 6 7 6 7 6 6 6 777 6 7 4 5 4 5 2 cont — ind 6 7 6 7 nonloc — slash hi 6 7 6 7 Dˆ E ˜ 6 7 non-head-dtr synsem 1 4 5 non-finite-head-spr-structure Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 76/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis The Non-finite Head Specifier Scheme Non-finite Head Specifier Scheme II The analysis in more details ◮ the argument is selected via the spr-list ◮ the Head Feature Principle prohibits the saturation of the subjlist ◮ the directive meaning is not directly encoded, since a wh-interpretation is also possible ◮ the directive meaning is the unmarked case ◮ declarative meaning is a property of finiteness Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 77/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis The Non-finite Head Specifier Scheme Example (63) in Staub mit allen Feinden Brandenburgs 2phon ˙in Staub mit allen Feinden Brandenburgs ¸ 3 2 33 2 6 7 form nonfinite 6 7 D E 6 6 7 77 6 7 7 6head 6 1 subj 5 4 6synsem — loc — cat 6 7 7 7 6 6 7 6 7 adv-or-prep 5 4 6 7 6 7 spr hi 6 7 ˙ ¸ 6 7 3 2 phon in Staub 6 7 6 7 3 2 2 37 6 6 7 form nonfinite 7 6 6 7 E D 6 6 7 77 6 6 7 6 6 7 77 6cat — head 4subj 1 5 6head-dtr 6synsem — loc 6 7 77 7 6 6 7 7 6 7 6 6 7 5 4 adv-or-prep 7 6 6 7 6 7 5 4 cont 6 7 6 7 6 7 6 ˙ ¸ 2 3 7 6 7 mit allen Feinden Brandenburgs phon 6 7 h i * + " # 6 6 ˆ ˜ 7 7 6 7 6 cat head noun case str 7 6non-head-dtr 7 6 7 1 6synsem — loc 6 7 7 6 4 5 7 cont 6 7 4 5 nonfinite-head-arg-structure Figure: In Staub mit allen Feinden Brandenburgs Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 78/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Open questions Open questions... Are directional phrases always predicates? Some cases are problematic for the predicate account Steinitz (1989, 231 Fn. 11): Problematic class of Verbs, where a predicate analysis fails: (64) blicken, weisen, zeigen, ragen regard point point loom (65) küssen, sehnen kiss long (66) der Weg nach oben the way to up Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 79/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Open questions The last example in Paris... Directional phrases embedded by impersonal predicates: Prediction: Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 80/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Open questions The last example in Paris... Directional phrases embedded by impersonal predicates: Prediction: Since there is no argument position and no structural case available, Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 80/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Open questions The last example in Paris... Directional phrases embedded by impersonal predicates: Prediction: Since there is no argument position and no structural case available, the theme shouldn’t be able to raise into the verbal domain to get [acc]-case. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 80/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Open questions The last example in Paris... Directional phrases embedded by impersonal predicates: Prediction: Since there is no argument position and no structural case available, the theme shouldn’t be able to raise into the verbal domain to get [acc]-case. (67) [Ab [PP mit dir] an die Front]! off with you to the front ‘Get to the front!’ Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 80/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Open questions The last example in Paris... Directional phrases embedded by impersonal predicates: Prediction: Since there is no argument position and no structural case available, the theme shouldn’t be able to raise into the verbal domain to get [acc]-case. (67) [Ab [PP mit dir] an die Front]! off with you to the front ‘Get to the front!’ (68) ’Jetzt geht es [ ab [PP mit dir] an die Front]’, habe ich thought I now goes it off with you to the front, have gedacht ‘Now I will be sent to the front, I thought.’ http://www.oskar-duschinger.de/neu/buecher/maxhuette 2.htm, 15.2. 2010 Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 80/162 Verbless Directives An HPSG analysis Open questions The last example in Paris........ Behave exactly, as predicted by the Case Principle ◮ Also the non-wh-pattern can also be embedded ◮ Whenever the THEME argument fails to raise into the domain of the VP, it will not surface as NP[acc] but mit-PP Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 81/162 Verbless Directives Conclusions Conclusions ◮ Directional phrases are predicates! Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin 82/162 Verbless Directives Conclusions Barbiers, Sjef. 2002. Modality and polarity. In Sjef Barbiers, Frits Beukema and Wim van der Wurff (eds.), Modality and its interaction with the verbal system, volume 47 of Linguistik Aktuell, pages 51–73, Benjamins. Chomsky, Noam. 1981. Lectures on government and binding: the Pisa lectures. Studies in generative grammar, No. 9, Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Helbig, Gerhard and Buscha, Joachim. 1986. Deutsche Grammatik: ein Handbuch für den Ausländerunterricht. Berlin: Langenscheidt, 9. edition. Jackendoff, Ray and Pinker, Steven. 2005. The nature of the language faculty and its implications for evolutions of Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin language, (Reply to Fitch, Hauser & Chomsky). Cognition 97, 211–225. Jacobs, Joachim. 2008. Wozu Konstruktionen? Linguistische Berichte 213, 3–44. Klein, Wolfgang. 2008. On finiteness. In Veerle van Geenhoven (ed.), Semantics in acquisition, pages 245–272, Dordrecht: Springer. Kratzer, Angelika and Selkirk, Elisabeth. 2007. Phase theory and prosodic spellout. The Linguistic Review 24, 93–135. Lenerz, Jürgen. 1977. Zur Abfolge nominaler Satzglieder im Deutschen, volume 5 of Studien zur deutschen Grammatik. Tübingen: Narr. Maienborn, Claudia. 1994. Kompakte 82/162 Verbless Directives Conclusions Strukturen: Direktionale PPn und nicht-lokale Verben. In Sascha Felix, Christopher Habel and Gert Rickheit (eds.), Kognitive Linguistik. Repräsentationen und Prozesse, pages 229–249, Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag. Meurers, Walt Detmar. 1999. Raising spirits (and assigning them case). Groninger Arbeiten zur Germanistischen Linguistik (GAGL) 43, 173–226. Müller, Gereon. 2010. Regeln oder Konstruktionen? Von verblosen Direktiven zur sequentiellen Nominalreduplikation. Ms. Universität Leipzig. Müller, Stefan. 2002. Complex predicates: verbal complexes, resultative Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin constructions and particle verbs in German. Stanford, CA: CSLI. Paul, Hermann. 1968. Prinzipien der Sprachgeschichte. Tübingen, 8. edition. Przepiórkowski, Adam. 1999. On case assignment and ’adjuncts as complements’. In Gert Webelhuth, Jean-Pierre Koenig and Andreas Kathol (eds.), Lexical and constructional aspects of linguistic explanation, volume 1 of Studies in Constraint-Based Lexicalism, pages 231–245, CSLI Publications. Reis, Marga. 1985. Satzeinleitende Strukturen im Deutschen. Über COMP, Haupt- und Nebensätze, w-Bewegung und die Doppelkopf-Analyse. In Werner Abraham (ed.), Erklärende Syntax des 82/162 Verbless Directives Conclusions Deutschen, volume 25 of Studien zur deutschen Grammatik, pages 271–311, Tübingen: Narr. Reis, Marga. 1995. Über infinite Nominativkonstruktionen. In Olaf Önnerfors (ed.), Festvorträge anläßlich des 60. Geburtstags von Inger Rosengren, Sprache und Pragmatik. Arbeitsberichte Sonderheft, Lund: University of Lund. Reis, Marga. 2003. On the form of German wh-infinitives. Journal of Germanic Linguistics 15, 155–201. Riemsdijk, Henk van. 2002. The unbearable lightness of going: the projection parameter as a pure parameter governing the distribution of elliptic motion verbs in Germanic. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics 5, 143–196. Schottel, Justus Georg. 1663. Ausführliche Arbeit von der Teutschen HaubtSprache: worin enthalten Gemelter dieser Haubtsprache Uhrankunft, Uhraltertuhm, Reinlichkeit, Eigenschaft, Vermögen, Unvergleichlichkeit, Grundrichtigkeit.. Braunschweig: Ziliger. Schwabe, Kerstin. 1994. Syntax und Semantik situativer Ellipsen, volume 48 of Studien zur deutschen Grammatik. Tübingen: Narr. Steinitz, Renate. 1989. Vu ,Iy und Iz : Überlegungen zum Prädikativ. In Wolfgang Motsch (ed.), Wortstruktur und Satzstruktur , pages 211–234, 82/162 Verbless Directives Conclusions Berlin: Zentralinstitut für Sprachwissenschaften. Szumlakowski-Morodo, Irene. 2006. ’Ich will weg, wohin musst du’ Modalverben mit Richtungsbestimmung und ohne Infinitiv. Muttersprache 116, 322–347. Truckenbrodt, Hubert. 2010. Effects of indefinite pronouns and traces on verb stress in German. In Toni J. Borowsky, Shigeto Kawahara and Takahito Shinya (eds.), Prosody Matters: Essays in Honor of Lisa Selkirk, London: Equinox Publishing. Jakob Maché 2010, German Grammar, FU Berlin Uhmann, Susanne. 1991. Fokusphonologie, volume 252 of Linguistische Arbeiten. Tübingen: Niemeyer. Wechsler, Stephen and Noh, Bokyung. 2001. On resultative predicates and clauses: parallels between Korean and English. Language Sciences 23, 391–423. Wilder, Chris. 2008. The PP-’with’-DP construction. In Jacek Witkoś and Gisbert Fanselow (eds.), Elements of Slavic and Germanic grammars: a comparative view., pages 235–253, Frankfurt/Main: Peter Lang. 82/162