Scott D. Sagan, Stanford University Benjamin A. Valentino
Transcription
Scott D. Sagan, Stanford University Benjamin A. Valentino
JUST A WAR THEORY? AMERICAN PUBLIC OPINION ON ETHICS IN MILITARY COMBAT Scott D. Sagan, Stanford University Benjamin A. Valentino, Dartmouth College ABSTRACT: To what extent are the American public’s views on the use of force consistent with just war doctrine’s ethical principles? Drawing on an original survey experiment conducted on a representative sample of American citizens, we examine American attitudes towards the jus in bello principles of proportionality, due care and distinction. Consistent with the moral logic of the principle of proportionality, we find evidence that Americans are less willing to inflict collateral deaths on foreign civilians when the military advantage derived from destroying a target is lower. We also find that most Americans are willing to risk of the deaths of some American soldiers to avert a larger number of collateral Afghan civilian deaths, which broadly accords with the principle of due care. Nevertheless, we find that the public’s commitment to proportionality and due care is heavily biased in favor of protecting American lives and national security interests in ways that suggest only limited support for traditional interpretations of just war theory. Moreover, we find little evidence that the public supports the principle of distinction (non-combatant immunity). Under certain conditions, more than two-thirds of the American public was willing to approve of intentional attacks on foreign civilians, and support for large scale killing of civilians did not decrease when the attacks were labeled as intentional with a strategic justification. In addition, contrary to prevailing interpretations of just war doctrine, Americans were significantly more likely to accept the collateral deaths of foreign civilians when those civilians were described as politically sympathetic with the adversary than when they were described as political opponents. The authors would like to thank Benjamin Buch, Jonathan Chu and Anna Coll for their indispensable research assistance on this project. We also thank Seth Lazar, Rachel Stein, David Traven and Allen Weiner for helpful comments on earlier versions of this article. 03/24/2015 DRAFT: PLEASE DO NOT CITE OR CIRCULATE WITHOUT PERMISSION OF AUTHORS Introduction The philosophical and legal doctrine known collectively as “just war doctrine” or “just war theory” is widely acknowledged as the most influential source of ideas about the ethics of war, at least in Western societies (Walzer 2004, Orend 2008). Its principles have been the prime focus of scholarly debate about the ethics of war in the West since its central tenets were first codified by Christian theologian and philosopher St. Augustine in the late fifth century. Just war doctrine also provides the basis for most extant international humanitarian law governing the conduct of war (Roberts and Guelff 2004) and has directly influenced the U.S. military’s official targeting doctrine (Joint Chiefs of Staff 2013, Kahl 2007). Just war principles are frequently cited, explicitly or implicitly, in public debates by both proponents and critics of the use of force to justify their respective positions. Despite the indisputable influence just war doctrine has exerted on the discourse of war among elite jurists, scholars and politicians, however, we know almost nothing about the extent to which the American public’s views on the use of force are consistent with just war philosophy.1 Yet it is far from self-evident that the public’s views of the ethics of war closely correspond to just war principles. Needless to say, most Americans have not studied Grotius or Michael Walzer. Even if they had, as most proponents of just war doctrine acknowledge, the doctrine provides a normative framework for how statesmen and soldiers should act when deciding to use force or when engaged in war, but does not seek to describe how they actually act. Equally important, just war doctrine offers only general guidelines to guide thinking about the use of force. Using the common legal terminology, just war doctrine provides general standards (“do not drive recklessly”) rather than bright line rules (“do not drive above 55 mph”) (Wiener, 2006). Just war doctrine, for example, requires that the use of force should be a last resort, but it provides no simple formula that leaders or the public could use to ascertain exactly when that line has been crossed. Just war doctrine similarly maintains that soldiers and statesmen should not use force in a manner in which the collateral damage to non-combatants is “disproportionate” to the military benefits of the attack, but it provides no strict guideline for how to measure proportionality or disproportionality. Just war doctrine therefore leaves ample room for individual judgment and interpretation, but we have almost no information to help us understand how most people interpret just war principles in For an exploration of Israeli attitudes on just war theory, focusing primarily on just war theory’s assertion of the “moral equivalence of soldiers” see Benbaji, Falk, and Feldman 2014. 1 1 practice. As Walzer (1977, 130) writes, just war principles “don’t explain the most critical of judgments we make of soldiers and their generals. If they did, moral life in wartime would be a great deal easier than it is.” Furthermore, although many of just war doctrine’s central tenets – like the requirement of having a “just cause” for war – likely coincide with the public’s common sense morality of self-defense, others, like the “doctrine of double effect,” are more subtle and controversial, and may be less widely accepted by members of the public, even if they understood them completely. Because just war theory is principally a normative doctrine, whether or not public views on the use of force correspond to just war doctrine should not be regarded as a test of the theory’s validity as a moral doctrine. Understanding the extent to which the public has internalized just war principles, however, is important for at least three reasons. First, even for purely normative scholars, identifying discrepancies between normative prescriptions and our moral intuitions is important because such discrepancies may signal a potential flaw in the normative theory or, at a minimum, require further elucidation (Audi 2005). In this regard, our investigation can be viewed as part of the growing body of scholarship that straddles the line between normative theory and empirical research and seeks to describe and understand the origins of our moral instincts (Green 2013; Haidt 2012). Second, understanding how the public thinks about the ethics of war provides insights into how warfare is likely to be practiced in the real world because, at least in democratic states, the public exerts an important influence over government policies. In turn, understanding how the public interprets and applies just war principles may provide some indication of whether these principles provide any practical limits on war. Third, for normative theorists of war who desire to see certain prescriptive principles implemented in practice, understanding public attitudes on the ethics of war should also help identify the areas in which the public’s views differ from those principles and, potentially, what kinds of arguments might be most effective in changing those views. Just war doctrine encompasses a large and diverse set of ethical arguments and legal precepts. It is not possible to explore all of them in any single paper. We choose to focus on the public’s acceptance of three key moral principles of jus in bello, the body of doctrine that governs the conduct of war. These principles are usually referred to as “distinction” (sometimes called “discrimination” or “non-combatant immunity”), which concerns the killing of non-combatants; “proportionality,” which asks military decision makers to weigh the costs to foreign civilians of a particular operation against the operation’s contribution to winning the war; and “due care” which 2 requires that combatants try to minimize collateral damage, including accepting some risk to themselves if necessary. Debates over competing interpretations of these principles remain among the most frequent topics in the literature on the ethics of war and often lie at the center of public discourse about the use of force in the contemporary world. We explore the American public’s views on distinction, proportionality and due care using data collected from three original survey experiments. In each experiment we asked subjects to read a short, hypothetical news story about an American decision to use force against Taliban targets in Afghanistan. The stories were designed to highlight the kinds of moral choices implicated by the principles of distinction, proportionality and due care. By holding most facts about the scenario described in the story constant while manipulating a single feature of the situation relevant to the application of just war doctrine, we can isolate the effect of varying the degree of distinction, proportionality or due care on each subject’s approval of the use of force. We report three main findings. First, we find evidence that the American public accepts the general moral logic of the principles of proportionality and due care. They are more likely to approve the use of force and accept higher levels of collateral civilian deaths when the military advantage of destroying the target is greater. Most Americans are willing to accept the risk of the deaths of some American soldiers to avert larger numbers of collateral Afghan civilian deaths, which broadly accords with the principle of due care. In these ways, just war theory appears to be more than just a prescriptive theory of how people ought to behave; it describes the moral choices the public claim they would actually make about the use of force. Second, however, we find that the American public’s conceptions of proportionality and due care are heavily biased in favor of protecting American lives and national security interests in ways that suggest at best limited support for most interpretations of just war doctrine. Forty-four percent of the public, for example, supported a U.S. military strike against an explicitly “low level” Taliban target that would have “little effect on the outcome of the war” even though the strike was estimated to kill 200 civilians. The public’s tolerance for risk to American soldiers in order to protect foreign noncombatants is also relatively low. When presented with a choice between two military operations, one of which would entail greater risks for American soldiers but kill fewer foreign civilians and one of which would limit risks to American troops but kill more foreign civilians, a large majority of the public preferred to limit the risks to U.S. troops even when the number of civilians killed was four times greater than the number of U.S. troops who would have died in the risker operation. Third, we found that the public’s attitudes regarding the principle of distinction deviated substantially from just war doctrine. 3 In some conditions, more than two-thirds of the American public was willing to approve of intentional attacks on foreign non-combatants. The public was also significantly more likely to accept the deaths of foreign civilians when those civilians were described as politically sympathetic with the adversary than when they were described as political opponents, a position which does not conform to principles of traditional just war doctrine. The remainder of this paper is divided into five main sections. In the first section we review the principles of distinction, proportionality and due care in just war doctrine and derive from them several testable hypotheses about public attitudes towards the use of force. The second section describes our research methodology for evaluating these hypotheses. In the third section we report the empirical findings of our survey experiments. The fourth section discusses the broader significance of those findings. A final section explores some implications of our research for scholarship and policy. The Principles of Distinction, Proportionality and Due Care in Just War Theory In this paper we explore American attitudes towards three principles of jus in bello, just war doctrine’s guidelines for waging a just war. These principles are usually referred to as distinction, proportionality and due care.2 Simply put, the distinction principle states that military forces may never intentionally target non-combatants. The proportionality principle argues that the harms caused by the use of force must be proportional to the expected benefits of using force. Some scholars also identify a third principle, which figures prominently in international humanitarian law, called “due care” or “precautions in attack.” This principle requires armed combatants take “feasible measures” to avoid killing civilians, even if it means accepting some risk to themselves. Distinction We do not directly examine the jus in bello principle of “necessity.” The principle of necessity means different things to different practitioners and scholars. For example, in April 2012 Obama Administration official John O. Brennan took a minimalist view when stating that U.S. “targeted strikes conform to the principle of necessity, the requirement that the target have definite military value.” (Brennan, 2012) Others argue that the principle of necessity requires that attackers choose the means of attack that causes the minimum amount of harm necessary to eliminate a particular threat. For reviews and critical discussions of the logic of the necessity principle see Lazar (2012) and Statman (2011). Previous experimental studies, have demonstrated that, all else equal, the American public is less likely to approve the use of force when foreign civilian casualties are higher (Gelpi, Feaver and Reifler 2009, 256; Press, Sagan and Valentino 2013). 2 4 The notion that civilians should be spared the violence of war is one of the oldest rules of combat (Kinsella 2011; Slim 2008; van Dongen 1991; Lind 2014). As Michael Walzer notes, one nearly universal rule of warfare points “toward the general conception of war as a combat between combatants, a conception that turns up again and again in anthropological and historical accounts [emphasis original]” (Walzer 1977, 42). Like many just war precepts, the principle of distinction is deceptively simple. As codified in the Geneva Conventions, the principle requires that “persons taking no active part in the hostilities . . . shall in all circumstances be treated humanely” and prohibits “violence to life and person, in particular murder of all kinds” (quoted in Roberts and Guelff 2004, 302). Article 48 of the 1977 Additional Protocol I to the Convention further provides that combatants “shall at all times distinguish between the civilian population and combatants… and accordingly shall direct their operations only against military objectives” (quoted in Roberts and Guelff 2004, 447). The U.S. military’s formal targeting doctrine also clearly specifies that “purely civilian/protected objects or locations may not be intentionally targeted” (Joint Chiefs of Staff 2013, A-2). The general imperative that civilians should be immune from intentional attack during times of war is widely accepted by nearly all just war scholars and jurists, although there is disagreement as to the underlying moral justifications for the prohibition (see Fabre 2009; Arneson 2006; Carpenter 2005).3 Nevertheless, there has been considerable debate about the precise meaning of the term “non-combatant,” which has significant implications for the practical application of this principle. Most just war theorists agree that at least some individuals who are neither armed, nor members of a formal military organization still may be legitimate targets of attack if they contribute directly and significantly to the adversary’s war effort. Civilian mechanics and technicians who repair military equipment or workers in munitions factories, for example, are often cited as possible exceptions to the strict prohibition on targeting civilians. As Hugh Trenchard, Chief Marshall of the British Royal Air Force during the inter-war years famously asked, “Why should the person who made the gun be less a target than he who fired it?” (quoted in Grayling 2006, 133). The Geneva Conventions prohibit attacks against civilians “unless and for such time as they take a direct part in hostilities” (quoted in Roberts and Guelff 2004, 448).4 Walzer (1977, 145-6) reasons that For partial exceptions to the general consensus on strict non-combatant immunity from just war doctrine “revisionists” see Frowe 2014; McMahan 2009; and Overland 2005. For a review of the arguments of some dissenters from just war theory’s conception of distinction, see Fellmeth 2008. 4 The 1977 Geneva Protocol II, which applies to non-interstate conflicts, uses identical language. 3 5 We try to draw a line between those who have lost their rights because of their warlike activities and those who have not… The relevant distinction is not between those who work for the war effort and those who do not, but between those who make what combatants need to fight and those who make what they need to live, like all the rest of us. When it is militarily necessary, workers in a tank factory can be attacked and killed, but not workers in a food processing plant. . . . Although scholars in the just war tradition debate precisely where the line between civilian and combatant lies, most agree that the key moral distinctions rest with how large and direct a contribution civilians make to the war effort (Rodin 2008). When civilians’ contributions are small and infrequent, halting these contributions usually does not justify lethal force. When their contributions are indirect, even if they are significant, they can ordinarily be addressed with means other than military force. As such, most proponents of just war doctrine and the laws of armed conflict concur that factors such as civilians’ nationality or mere political sympathy with the adversary are not sufficient on their own to revoke civilians’ immunity from attack since the activities of regular citizens or even political supporters do not constitute a significant and direct contribution to the war. As Walzer succinctly puts it, “the structure of rights stands independently of political allegiance” (1977, 158). To the extent, therefore, that American public’s views on the use of force are consistent with the principle of distinction, the foregoing discussion suggests the following three hypotheses: Hypothesis 1: Americans should decrease their support for military operations that intentionally target foreign civilians. Hypothesis 2: Americans should increase their support for military operations that intentionally target foreign civilians the more significantly and directly those civilians contribute to the adversary’s war effort. Hypothesis 3: Whether or not foreign civilians politically support or oppose U.S. adversaries should have no independent effect on the willingness of Americans to support military operations in which foreign civilians are killed intentionally or unintentionally. Proportionality: Military Advantage 6 The principle of proportionality constitutes the second major tenet of jus in bello that we examine in this paper.5 In the broadest terms, the proportionality principle requires that the harms of any military attack be outweighed by its benefits (Walzer 1977, 129-133; Hurka 2005). The harms and benefits can include almost any consequences of an attack, but much of the discussion among just war theorists has focused on the question of how to weigh the harm of unintended foreign civilian casualties against the contribution of the attack to winning the war.6 In international law, the proportionality principle compares expected collateral damage to the expected “military advantage” of an attack. The 1977 Additional Protocol I to the Geneva Conventions, for example, prohibits “any attack which may be expected to cause incidental loss of civilian life, injury to civilians, damage to civilian objects, or a combination thereof, which would be excessive in relation to the concrete and direct military advantage anticipated” (quoted in Roberts and Guelff 2004, 453). The principle of proportionality is also reflected explicitly in the U.S. military’s official weapons targeting doctrine.7 Although the principle of distinction strictly forbids the intentional targeting of civilians just war theory permits even the foreseeable killing of civilians during attacks on military targets, as long as certain additional conditions are satisfied.8 These conditions constitute the “doctrine of double effect” and are central to the application of proportionality in the real world.9 According to Walzer (1977, 153), attacks on military targets that are expected to result in “collateral” civilian deaths must meet four key criteria to be permissible under traditional interpretations of the “doctrine of double effect.” First, the attack on the military target must be a legitimate act of war. Second, the direct effect of destroying the military target must be morally acceptable. Third, the attacker must have the intention only of destroying the military target, killing civilians may not be a deliberate objective or an indirect means to achieve a legitimate objective. Finally, the good intended effects of destroying the Proportionality is also a condition for jus ad bellum – which requires that leaders should not embark upon war unless they determine that destructiveness of the war will be outweighed by the good effects the war will achieve. Previous experimental studies, suggest that, all else equal, the American public is less likely to approve the use of force both with respect to starting wars and with respect to specific combat operations foreign civilian casualties are higher (Gelpi, Feaver and Reifler 2009; Press, Sagan and Valentino 2013). 6 It is not clear whether or how the proportionality principle applies to adversary soldiers. As David Hurka (2005, 58) argues “In bello proportionality as standardly understood seems to allow a nation to kill virtually any number of enemy soldiers to save just one of its own soldiers this claim mirrors one from the morality of self-defense, where a person may kill any number of attackers if that is necessary to save his own or another’s life …” 7 The Joint Chiefs of Staff Joint Doctrine for Targeting states that “collateral damage to civilian objects or persons must not be excessive in relation to the concrete and direct military advantage expected to be gained” (Joint Chiefs of Staff 2013, A-5). 8 The U.S. military adopts similar guidelines. 9 For arguments against the doctrine of double effect see Kamm 2004 and Otsuka 1994. 5 7 legitimate military target must outweigh the unintended bad effects of killing the civilians. In other words, the attack must be proportional. In practice, the third and fourth criteria have produced the most academic and legal disputation. Many scholars have questioned what it means for combatants not to have the intention of killing civilians even if they are certain that civilians will die in an attack anyway (McKeogh 2002; Conway-Lanz 2006; Crawford 2013). Others have asked how many civilians is it permissible to kill unintentionally in the service of particular military goals and how much risk to the success of the mission attackers must accept to minimize civilian deaths (Hurka 2005; Bohrer and Osiel 2013; Porat and Bohrer 2014). Despite these differences, however, there is widespread agreement among just war theorists that, all else equal, the greater the military importance of the target, the greater the number of collateral civilian deaths that may be permitted in destroying it. Hypothesis 4: Americans should increase their willingness to accept collateral deaths among foreign civilians the greater is the military advantage of destroying the target for the outcome of the war. Due Care Some scholars of just war theory also identify a separate principle of “due care,” which focuses on the question of how much personal risk soldiers should be expected to assume in order to reduce the risk that military operations might kill or injure foreign civilians or civilian property.10 In international law, the principle is related to “precautions in attack.” Article 57 of the 1977 Additional Protocol I to the Geneva Convention stipulates that, “in the conduct of military operations, constant care shall be taken to spare the civilian population, civilians and civilian objects,” (quoted in Roberts and Guelff 2004, 452) though it does not specify whether soldiers should take risks themselves to provide constant care. The principle of due care emerged from the concerns of some just war theorists that the principles of proportionality and distinction alone are too permissive, allowing soldiers to too easily inflict collateral damage when targeting legitimate military targets by claiming that the damage was unintentional and less than the benefits of destroying the target. Because soldiers are trained and expected to assume risks during times of war, the due care principle requires that combatants 10 Seth Lazar (2012) argues that due care is better understood as part of the broader principle of necessity. 8 willingly shoulder at least some risk in order to minimize risk to non-combatants (Margalit and Walzer 2009).11 As Walzer (1977, 155-6) writes, simply not to intend the deaths of civilians is too easy; most often under battle conditions, the intentions of soldiers are focused narrowly on the enemy. What we look for in such cases is some sign of a positive commitment to save civilian lives. Not merely to apply the proportionality rule and kill no more civilians than is militarily necessary... Civilians have a right to something more. And if saving civilian lives means risking soldier’s lives, the risk must be accepted… Exactly how far they must go in doing that is hard to say… It is best, I think, to say simply that civilians have a right that “due care” be taken.”12 David Luban concurs that the laws of war “never explicitly address the question of how much risk soldiers must assume to minimize ‘collateral’ civilian casualties. International humanitarian law requires soldiers to do everything feasible to avoid unintended civilian casualties, but it never defines ‘feasible’” (Luban 2014, 279). Luban terms the ratio of acceptable foreign civilian deaths to one’s own military deaths the “risk transfer ratio” (Luban 2014, 279). Scholars and international lawyers disagree about what value the risk transfer ratio should take or what additional considerations should affect the balance. Some, like Asa Kasher and Amos Yadlin (2005), argue that combatants have a right to weigh the lives of their own soldiers more highly than the lives of foreign civilians, suggesting a risk transfer ratio greater than one. Others, like Thomas Hurka (2005, 64), argue that “our soldiers’ and enemy civilians’ lives count roughly equally. While a nation may prefer its own civilians’ lives to those of enemy civilians, it may not do the same with its soldiers’ lives. Instead, it must trade those off against enemy civilians’ lives at roughly one to one.”13 Still others, including Avishai Margalit and Walzer (2009), argue that “By wearing a uniform, you take on yourself a risk that is borne only by those who have been trained to injure others... You should not shift this risk onto those who haven’t been trained, who lack the capacity to injure.” As such, they assert, soldiers must bear a greater burden of risks than civilians and soldiers should be instructed to Although the principle of providing due care to protect civilians is usually seen as a special moral duty for professional soldiers, in practice it can also be linked to the principle of proportionality. After all, when soldiers assume greater personal risks to themselves in order to protect adversary or neutral civilians, they can increase the costs of the war to their own side and reduce, at least to some extent, their chances of successfully completing their mission and thus contributing to winning the war. These costs to the war effort presumably must be weighed against the costs of collateral damage according to the principle of proportionality. 12 See also Lee (2012, 213). 13 For a similar argument see Dunlap (2000). 11 9 “conduct your war in the presence of noncombatants on the other side with the same care as if your citizens were the noncombatants.”14 This implies a risk transfer ratio of less than one. Although these disagreements are significant, there is a broad consensus among scholars in the just war tradition that states have the right to impose at least some risks on foreign civilians (keeping in mind that civilians may never be intentionally targeted) in the effort to reduce the risks to their own soldiers. The exact value of the risk transfer ratio remains disputed, but most just war theorists would probably accept that military commanders should be permitted to launch an airstrike against an important enemy military base if doing so would save 1,000 soldiers from dying if the base had to be attacked by a ground assault – even if the airstrike was expected to kill one civilian who happened to be visiting the base. Conversely, most just war theorists would probably reject the attack if it would avert the death of a single soldier but cause the deaths of 1,000 foreign civilians. If the public accepts the underlying logic of due care, therefore, this suggests the following related hypotheses: Hypothesis 5: Americans should be willing to risk the lives of some U.S. soldiers to prevent collateral deaths of foreign civilians in U.S. military operations. Hypothesis 6: Americans should increase their willingness to accept collateral deaths among foreign civilians in U.S. military operations the greater the number of U.S. soldiers’ deaths that will be averted by such operations. Research Design Perhaps the most obvious way to explore public attitudes about the ethics of war would be to draw upon data from existing public opinion polls on actual military operations to gauge public support for various forms of military action (for example, see Eichenberg 2005). Over the past 30 years, numerous polls have inquired about the public’s views on the killing of foreign civilians in various conflicts and whether American soldiers should take more or less risks to protect those civilians. Unfortunately, most public opinion polls suffer from two common problems that severely limit their utility in understanding public attitudes about just war theory principles. First, very few poll questions are specified clearly enough to identify views about these specific principles. A 2011 Luban adopts a similar position, arguing that we have an obligation to “treat civilians on the other side in a way that would be minimally acceptable even if they were our own” (Luban 2014, pp?). See also Christopher (1999). 14 10 poll conducted by Gallup, for example, found that 49% of Americans agreed that it was “sometimes justified” “for the military to target and kill civilians” (Gallup 2011).15 The question, however, did not define the word “civilian” (e.g., whether civilians referred to munitions workers or children or both), nor did it specify the purpose of the killing (e.g., would the civilians be targeted with the intent to kill them or because they were collocated with legitimate military targets) or whether killing those civilians might avert even greater harms to other civilians. Yet as described above, the answers to these questions are critical for the application of just war doctrine. Polls that focus on public attitudes about specific military operations in the real world also face a second limitation. For example, a CNN poll conducted in July 2014 found that 55% of Americans believed that “the amount of military force that Israel has used in Gaza against Hamas and the Palestinians” had been either about right or too little, compared to 39% who said Israel had used “too much” military force (CNN/ORC 2014). In comparison, a poll taken in April 2003, 87% of Americans indicated that they believed that the United States had used the right amount or too little force in Iraq, with only 6% saying we used too much (CBS 2003). Despite the clear differences in responses, however, it is not possible to infer from these two polls whether Americans believed the war in Iraq was more proportionate than Israel’s war against Gaza. Direct comparisons of this kind are confounded by the influence of countless case-specific factors that distinguish the conflicts (e.g., the different interests at stake, differences in public attention to the two wars, the different means of military forces used, etc.). As a result, we cannot use this information to determine which factors have the greatest impact on the public’s assessments of the ethics of the use of force. To test the hypotheses above, therefore, we chose to conduct three related survey experiments on a large, representative sample of American citizens over the age of 18. Unlike public opinion data drawn from real-world instances of the use of force, a survey experiment allows us to construct a hypothetical scenario in which we can hold most relevant facts about the scenario constant (e.g., the broader conflict context, the effectiveness of using force, or the kinds of weapons used) while varying only one aspect of the situation (e.g., the ratio of foreign civilian to U.S. military deaths, the “culpability” of potential civilian victims, whether the killing of civilians was intentional or not, or the military importance of the target). This design enables us to isolate the effects of distinction, proportionality, due care on public attitudes about the use of force. 15 U.S. support for targeting civilians was the highest among all 131 countries polled. 11 To conduct this survey we contracted with YouGov, an internet polling and experimental research firm. YouGov utilizes a technique called “sample matching” to approximate a representative sample. This sampling technique is still relatively new compared to traditional equal probability random sampling, but it is becoming increasingly popular for use in academic research applications, and its performance has been shown to meet or exceed that of surveys based on more traditional telephone polling techniques (Berrens et al. 2003; Sanders et al. 2007; Yeager et al. 2011; Ansolabehere and Schaffner 2014) We devised three separate experiments with a total of 12 experimental conditions (five conditions in experiment 1, four conditions in experiment 2 and three conditions in experiment 3), each focusing a different aspect of just war theory. In each experiment, subjects were randomly assigned to read a different news story about a hypothetical U.S. military crisis in Afghanistan. Approximately 150 subjects were assigned to each condition. Subjects were told to read the story carefully and urged to “imagine how you would feel about these events if they were happening in the real world today.” To increase the realism of the experience, the stories were constructed to look like typical newspaper stories with an Associated Press byline. The key elements of each of the three experiments are summarized in Table 1. The full stories are included in the appendix at the end of this paper. We chose to focus our stories on the conflict in Afghanistan since it was the most significant ongoing American military operation at the time the survey was administered. We believe this maximizes the external validity of the experiment and makes a direct contribution to contemporary policy debates. Of course, because all of our scenarios are drawn from the Afghan war, we cannot explore whether or how specific features of the Afghan conflict affect our findings and, therefore, whether American attitudes about just war principles might vary in different conflicts. Perhaps the most significant concern in this regard is the public’s relatively low support for the war in Afghanistan in 2014. Indeed, averaging across all our conditions, 68% of respondents said they “opposed” the war in Afghanistan. Similarly, a poll administered by the Pew Research Center in January 2014 reported that 52 percent of Americans had already concluded that the U.S. had “mostly failed in achieving its goals in Afghanistan” with only 37% saying it had mostly succeeded.16 It is difficult to say how these dynamics might affect our findings. On the one hand, the perception of failure in Afghanistan might make the public less willing to inflict civilian casualties there, since 16 http://www.people-press.org/2014/01/30/more-now-see-failure-than-success-in-iraq-afghanistan/2/ 12 Americans may conclude that doing so is unlikely to help win an unwinnable war. On the other hand, perhaps Americans have become desensitized to civilian deaths in Afghanistan or are more willing to inflict casualties in the hope of snatching a victory from the jaws of defeat. Afghanistan also differs from many other conflicts because most Afghan civilians are not clearly allied with America’s adversary, the Taliban insurgents, and much of the official rhetoric justifying the war has focused on improving the lives of Afghan civilians. This seems likely to decrease tolerance for civilian casualties compared to classic interstate wars, in which foreign civilians are often presumed to be supporters of the adversary’s government. Future research could explore the interaction of these or other factors and attitudes towards killing foreign civilians. Nevertheless, because the conflict in Afghanistan remains America’s longest and most significant ongoing war, we believe it represents a highly relevant place to explore public attitudes about the use of force. In each story in our experiment, subjects read that the United States had identified a Taliban target in an Afghan village and was considering various options to attack it. Across all three experiments we attempted to describe legitimate military targets that most Americans would agree constituted a threat, but not such a critical threat that it might justify the invocation of “supreme emergency,” which some scholars have argued might justify an exemption from just war principles.17 Experiment 1, which we refer to as the “distinction/culpability experiment,” was designed to examine views about the principle of distinction. In this story the U.S. had discovered a chemical weapons facility in the village, which American officials believed the Taliban was using to produce weapons for use “against U.S. military forces and civilian personnel in Kabul, Afghanistan.” The story reported that the Chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff had prepared a report to the President describing two airstrike options for attacking the target. The first option, called the “small-scale strike” would target three cruise missiles against the facility. The report estimated that the strike had a 45 percent chance of destroying the target. Because the village was “densely populated” the strike would also kill an estimated 20 Afghan civilians living in the village. The large scale strike would use 20 cruise missiles, doubling the chances of destroying the target to 90 percent, but increasing the Afghan collateral civilian fatalities in the village to 500. The report stated that no U.S. military deaths were expected in either operation. 17 For a critical review of these arguments see Toner 2005. 13 Each of the five experimental conditions then varied the information that subjects received about the political attitudes or behavior of civilians in the village and whether or not the United States was intentionally targeting the civilians.18 In condition A, subjects were told that although the village was under Taliban control, “almost all of the residents of the village strongly oppose the Taliban and the chemical facility.” Condition B specified that “almost all of the residents of the village strongly support the Taliban and the chemical facility.” Both conditions clearly indicated, however, that “the villagers have not fought for or provided food or weapons” to either the Taliban or U.S.-allied forces. In other words, in both conditions the villagers met the definition of noncombatants under just war doctrine and international law since they did not make a direct or significant contribution to the Taliban’s war effort. Condition C parallels condition B, but adds that “many” villagers “voluntarily work in the chemical facility” assisting the Taliban, thus raising the possibility that the villagers were making a significant contribution to the Taliban’s war effort and might be liable to attack under just war doctrine. Condition D also parallels condition B, but adds that the large-scale strike would be “targeted against the chemical weapons lab as well as civilian houses in the surrounding village,” which the report concludes would “send a strong message to Afghans in surrounding villages not to support the Taliban.” Condition E parallels condition D, but adds that “many” villagers “voluntarily provide food and shelter for Taliban fighters.” Note that the conditions in experiment 1 are not fully crossed, so it is not possible to experimentally compare each condition to every other condition in the experiment (e.g., it is not possible to compare condition A with condition E, or condition C with condition D). Experiment 2, which we refer to as the “due care experiment,” was devised to explore Americans’ willingness to transfer risks from American soldiers onto foreign civilians. In this experiment, subjects again read that the U.S. had discovered a Taliban chemical weapons laboratory in an Afghan village. A report from the Chairman of the Joint Chiefs to the President described two options for destroying the facility. In the first option, several thousand U.S. troops would “surround the Taliban controlled town and deploy specially-trained Army Ranger units to locate and destroy the chemical weapons components and laboratories.” The report noted that large numbers of troops would need to search the village “house-to-house,” which would place them “at much greater All three experiments employed experimental manipulations in several of the following locations in the story: the headline, the head- lead, a pull quote, several sentences throughout the story, and in a table summarizing the comparisons between the options being considered. 18 14 risk.” Because “American troops would only shoot when fired upon,” however, the door-to-door operation would “avoid any Afghan civilian casualties.” In the second option described in the report, the “troops would remain outside the town and use long-range artillery strikes to destroy suspected Taliban buildings.”19 The report noted that the artillery strikes “would remove the risk to U.S. military forces, but because the chemical weapons components and facilities are dispersed in a residential area, Afghan civilian fatalities would be ‘dramatically higher’ compared to the house-tohouse option,” resulting in an estimated 200 civilian deaths.20 The report emphasized that “both operations have a 90% chance of success.” The four experimental conditions then varied the estimated number of U.S. military deaths in the house-to-house option from 5, to 50, to 200, to 250 while holding Afghan civilian casualties and all other features of the story constant.21 Experiment 3, which we have labeled the “proportionality/military advantage” experiment, was designed to explore the trade-off between adversary civilian casualties and the military advantage of destroying the target. In this experiment, subjects read that the United States had received warning of a meeting of Taliban leaders in an Afghan village. As in experiment 1 (distinction), subjects read that the Chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff had presented the President with the choice between a large-scale strike and small-scale strike, both using unpiloted cruise missiles. The small-scale strike had a 45% chance of destroying the target and was estimated to result in 20 Afghan collateral civilian deaths. The large-scale strike increased the chances of destroying the target to 90% but also increased civilian casualties ten times to 200. In each scenario the story emphasized that “the military will attempt to minimize Afghan civilian deaths,” but some deaths were inevitable in either strike option because the village was densely populated. The three conditions in experiment 3 vary the military advantage of destroying the target. In condition A, subjects read that the strike would target “20 low-ranking Taliban officials” who commanded a “local network of fighters” who carried out attacks in the area around the village. The report from the Chairman of the Joint Chiefs of Staff concluded that eliminating the 20 leaders would “contribute to the success of U.S. operations against the Taliban in the local area, but would We chose an artillery strike instead of an airstrike to avoid varying the number of ground troops involved in the attack, which could influence subjects’ approval of the two options. 20 The “house-to-house” and “artillery assault” scenarios were deigned to closely parallel the hypothetical “Close Engagement” and “Distant Engagement” scenarios employed by David Luban (2014) to illustrate arguments about risktransfer and proportionality. 21 A 5th condition, not described here presented subjects with a range of U.S. fatalities from 0 to 10, which might be a more realistic representation of the way people would receive estimates of fatalities in military operations. The results of this condition were not significantly different from the condition with 5 U.S. military fatalities, however. 19 15 have little effect on the outcome of the war.” In condition B, the target was “20 high-ranking Taliban officials” in charge of a “national network” carrying out national attacks. Eliminating the high-ranking leasers was expected to “contribute to the success of U.S. operations against the Taliban nationwide and would have a major effect on the outcome of the war.” Condition C replicates condition B, adding the group was “planning attacks against the U.S. homeland” and that eliminating them would also “greatly reduce the group’s ability to launch attacks against U.S. targets.” Immediately after reading the news stories, subjects were prompted to respond to a series of approximately 50 survey questions. The first set of questions included manipulation checks and focused on the subjects’ immediate reactions to the news story – including their preferences for different attack options and their views of the ethicality of each option. Subjects then proceeded to answer some more general questions regarding their attitudes towards the use of force and civilian casualties in war. Results The findings reported in figure 1 show the results of experiment 1, which focused on attitudes regarding the principle of distinction. The figure shows subjects’ responses to two key questions, disaggregated across the five conditions. Subjects were asked: (1) “If you had to choose between the two U.S. military options described in the article, would you prefer the small-scale or the large-scale airstrike?” and (2) “Regardless of which option you preferred, how ethical or unethical do you think it would be if the United States decided to launch the large-scale airstrike in this situation?”22 Figure 1: Distinction Most questions in our survey utilized used a 6-point response scale (ranging from strongly agree/approve/prefer, to strongly disagree/disapprove/do not prefer). In this paper we present dichotomized results for ease of interpretation. There were no substantive differences in our results using the full 6 point response scale. 22 16 The results show that subjects were significantly more likely to prefer launching the largescale strike (killing 500 Afghan civilians instead of 20) when the civilians were described as political supporters of the Taliban (thus failing to support hypothesis 3). 65 percent of subjects preferred the large-scale strike when the victims were Taliban supporters (condition B), compared to 50 percent who preferred it when the victims were Taliban opponents (condition A).23 Interestingly, although a somewhat greater percentage of subjects (53% vs. 48%) were willing to describe the large-scale strike as ethical when the civilian deaths would fall among Taliban supporters, the difference was much smaller than the differences in preferences for the attack and not statistically significant. This might suggest that Americans may have internalized the ethical principles of distinction, but not strongly enough to alter their preferences in decisions about the use of force when faced with a real world dilemma like the one we asked them to consider. Indeed, 52% of subjects across all the conditions in experiment 1 agreed that “The United States must protect its most vital national interests even if that sometimes requires doing things that are morally wrong.”24 Although the civilian fatalities in both conditions were described as collateral effects of the attack on the military target (and thus do not fall strictly under the concept of distinction), these preferences run contrary to traditional understandings of just war theory, which hold that the mere political affiliation of noncombatants is not morally relevant in targeting decisions. 24 48 percent of subjects agreed with this statement when the civilian villagers were described as Taliban supporters (condition B) compared to 59 percent who agreed when the victims were described as opponents (condition A). This difference, however, was only marginally significant at p= .08. 23 17 The results also indicate that the degree of direct civilian involvement in the war effort has surprisingly little effect on Americans’ willingness to inflict fatalities among foreign non-combatants (failing to support hypothesis 2). Subjects were no more likely to prefer the large-scale strike when civilian supporters in the village were described as voluntarily assisting the Taliban in making chemical weapons (condition C) than when they were only political sympathizers (condition B). However, subjects were significantly more likely to say the large-scale strike was ethical (53% to 63%) when the villagers were working in the Taliban facility. Again, this reinforces the conclusion that the public’s ethical views and policy preferences about the use of force may sometimes diverge, causing at least some Americans to support policies that they acknowledge may be ethically questionable. Finally, we did not find evidence to support that the majority of the public has internalized the distinction principle’s clear prohibition on the intentional targeting of non-combatants (failing to support hypothesis 1). Subjects were no less likely to prefer the large-scale strike when the strike would target civilian supporters directly (conditions D and E), deliberately targeting civilian dwellings in addition to the chemical facility to “send a strong signal” to other villages, than they were when the civilian deaths were anticipated solely as the side effect of the attack on the chemical weapons facility (condition B).25 Nearly two out of three Americans preferred the large-scale strike even when it deliberately targeted civilians (condition D).26 Although it is possible that the additional military benefit gained by “sending a message” to the Taliban could have offset subjects’ opposition to intentionally killing civilians in condition D, the fact that the subjects actually rated the intentional attack as more ethical (62% in condition D compared to 53% in condition B) makes this explanation implausible.27 In any case, since intentionally targeting civilians in wartime is frequently undertaken in the effort to intimidate or coerce foreign civilians, our experimental comparison also represents the choices military and political leaders face in the real world. Interestingly, we also found no significant difference in subjects’ preference for or ethical judgments of the large-scale strike when the civilians who would be intentionally targeted were described as simply political supporters of the Taliban (condition D) or when the civilians actively assisted the Taliban by providing them with food and shelter (condition E). For many Americans, in Although the large-scale strike would also destroy the chemical weapons facility in conditions D and E, recall that the doctrine of double effect prohibits attacks in which killing civilians in among any of the intended benefits of the attack. 26 The percentage rises to nearly 70% in the intentional targeting conditions when subjects were asked whether they would “approve” of the strike, regardless of which option they preferred. 27 This difference was not significant, however (p=.12). 25 18 other words, civilians who provide political support for the adversary are judged to be just as liable to attack as those directly contributing to the adversary’s war effort. Indeed, at least some subjects appeared to reason that political supporters of the adversary are not “civilians” at all. Only 58 percent of subjects who read that the Afghan villagers were political supporters of the Taliban (condition B) agreed that these villagers should be “considered civilians,” compared to 88 percent who agreed when the villagers were described as opponents of the Taliban (condition A).28 In condition C, where villagers were described as actively assisting the Taliban to build chemical weapons, the proportion of subjects agreeing that the villagers should be considered civilians only dropped by 5%, a level statistically indistinguishable from condition B. We do not have clear hypotheses about whether individual-level traits influence the degree to which subjects’ preferences accord with just war doctrine. Nevertheless, our research design allows us to explore whether specific subgroups of the American public reacted differently to our experimental stimuli. To examine this, we estimated a logistic regression equation with the subject’s preference for the large-scale attack as the dependent variable and separate interactions between the treatment condition and measures of the subject’s political party affiliation (republican or democrat), current or prior military service, gender, age and college education as the independent variables.29 We also included an interaction between a dummy variable for Catholicism and the treatment condition to explore whether Catholics, who might be more familiar with just war principles, would respond differently to our stimuli. Overall, we found few significant interactions. In experiment 1, only military service had a significant interactive effect on subjects’ preferences – substantially increasing the preference for the large scale strike when the villagers were described as opponents of the Taliban (condition A).30 We found somewhat stronger evidence that Americans beliefs about the use of force were consistent with the logic of due care. Figure 2 shows the results of experiment 2, which focused on Americans’ willingness to protect foreign civilians at the cost of risking the lives of American soldiers. As in experiment 1, subjects were asked about their preference between two military options – in this case, an artillery strike, which would kill 200 Afghan civilians, and a house-to-house That difference is statistically significant at p < .001. The full wording of the question is: “In your opinion, should the Afghan villagers described in the article be considered civilians or not?” 29 Due to space constraints this model is not reported. All the independent variables were dummy measures, with the exception of age, which was continuous. 30 70% of subjects with current or prior military service preferred the large scale strike in condition A, compared with 47% of subjects with no military service. 28 19 assault, which would kill only 20. They were also asked whether they agreed that the artillery strike was ethical. We found that significantly more subjects (74% vs. 49%) preferred the artillery strike when doing so would avert the deaths of 50 American troops in the door-to-door operation (condition B) than when it would avert only 5 U.S. military deaths (condition A). Subjects were also much more likely (67% vs. 39%) to say the artillery strike was ethical when the door-to-door assault was expected to result in 50 American military deaths than when 5 U.S. military deaths were expected. These findings support hypotheses 5 and 6. Figure 2: Due Care Although these results suggest that most Americans recognize that American soldiers should accept at least some risk in order to protect foreign civilians, they also suggest that Americans’ “risk 20 transfer ratio” is much higher than many proponents of just war theory would likely endorse. Even when the artillery strike would avert the deaths 5 American soldiers at the cost of 200 Afghan civilian deaths (condition A), a ratio of 40:1, only a bare majority (50.5%) preferred the more discriminating door-to-door assault. When the artillery strike would allow the United States to avoid 50 military deaths, however, the preference for the artillery strike increased to nearly three-quarters of the population. Interestingly, although support for the artillery strike remained high when the expected American losses in the door-to-door operation increased to 200 (condition C) or 250 (condition D) fatalities, it did not significantly increase compared to condition B. This suggests that, among those who were influenced by due care concerns at all, the risk transfer ratio must be greater than 4:1 and for nearly half of all Americans, the ratio must be greater than 40:1 (200 civilian deaths to avert 5 American military deaths). Using the same technique and measures described above for experiment 1, we examined whether age, party-ID, military service, gender, education and Catholicism significantly influenced subjects’ responses to our stimuli. In experiment 2, only gender had a significant interaction with the treatment – with men’s preference for the artillery strike rising much more quickly between condition A and B than women’s. These results are especially compelling because, in contrast to some conditions in experiment 1, subjects in experiment 2 were not told that the Afghan civilians who would be killed were supporters of the Taliban. Indeed, as we noted above, unlike many traditional interstate conflicts, in which foreign civilians can be assumed to be supporters of the adversary, in Afghanistan many civilians support the United States. Most of our subjects seemed to recognize this. 68 percent of subjects in experiment 2 agreed that the Taliban villagers described in the article were either opponents of the Taliban or neutral. In light of the results from experiment 1, therefore, it seems probable that Americans might prefer even higher risk transfer ratios in military operations in which the potential civilian victims are perceived as politically sympathetic to the adversary. In experiment 3, we found evidence that American attitudes are generally consistent with the moral logic of proportionality. This experiment focused on how the public’s willingness to accept collateral civilian fatalities varied with the military advantage expected to be gained by destroying the target (in this case, a meeting of Taliban leaders). The main results from this experiment are reported in figure 3. As in experiment 1, subjects were asked whether they preferred a large-scale missile strike, which offered a higher chance of success (90%) but would result in 200 collateral 21 Afghan civilian deaths or a small-scale strike, which would kill fewer civilians (20 deaths) but offered only a 45% chance of success. Figure 3: Proportionality - Military Advantage The results indicate that Americans do appear to weigh foreign civilian deaths against the military importance of the target (providing support for hypothesis 4). While 68% of Americans preferred the large-scale strike on the meeting of high-ranking Taliban leaders (condition B), only 44% preferred it when the leaders were described as low ranking (condition A). Indeed, when asked whether they would have approved “if the United States had decided not to strike the Taliban meeting at all,” 54 percent of subjects in the low-level condition agreed, compared to 35 percent of those in the high-level condition.31 Interestingly, subjects were no more likely to prefer the largescale strike in condition C, in which subjects read that the high-level Taliban leaders were also planning attacks against the U.S. homeland. This suggests that among subjects whose support for the large-scale strike was influenced by the military importance of the target at all, the chance to eliminate 20 high levels leaders was sufficient reason to prefer the large-scale strike. In this experiment, military service was, again, the only individual-level trait for which we found a significant interaction with the stimuli. Subjects with military service were almost twice as likely to prefer the large-scale attack against the “low level” meeting in condition A as the rest of the population (70% vs. 39%), causing their preference for the large-scale attack to rise less sharply between conditions A and B. 31 That difference is significant at p<.01 22 As in experiment 2, however, it is worth emphasizing that although Americans appear to have followed the logic of proportionality, a very significant minority (44%) was nevertheless willing to accept the deaths of 180 additional Afghan civilians in order to increase the chances of eliminating a threat that American military leaders explicitly stated “would have little effect on the outcome of the war.” Again, this suggests that although most Americans accept the basic moral intuitions that undergird the principle of proportionality, the public’s commitment to the principle is relatively shallow and easily outweighed by the desire to advance even secondary American national security interests. Discussion These empirical findings point to three broad conclusions about the degree to which the American public’s policy preferences regarding the use of military force are consistent with the jus in bello principles of just war theory. First, at a most basic level, the public does appear to recognize and accept the moral logic of the principles of due care and proportionality. They are willing to sacrifice at least some American soldiers to spare the lives of larger numbers of foreign civilians. They are less willing to tolerate civilian collateral civilian fatalities and are more willing to accept a lower chance of success in military operations when destroying the target of the operation would achieve relatively less military advantage. These findings suggest that considerations of proportionality and due care are present in most Americans’ moral intuitions and can shape their policy preferences about the use of force. Whether just war theory has evolved to reflect our preexisting intuitions on these questions or whether hundreds of years of western legal, ethical and religious tradition have shaped our moral views is not possible to discern from this study. Second, however, the public’s commitment to these principles seems relatively fragile and grants a degree of preference to American lives and national security interests far above what most proponents of just war doctrine would likely endorse. To avert the death of 5 American soldiers, nearly half of the American public (49.5%) would be willing to tolerate the collateral deaths of at least 200 foreign civilians. Large minorities of the public are willing to accept hundreds of foreign civilian deaths to increase the chances of success of strikes that even American military commanders acknowledge will provide relatively little military advantage. These findings strongly suggest that Americans have not internalized the most “cosmopolitan” versions of just war theory. Rather, their views are closer to those of scholars like Kasher and Yadlin (2005, 18) who argue that “a combatant is a citizen in uniform… His blood is as 23 red and thick as that of citizens who are not in uniform. His life is as precious as the life of anyone else.” Under this view, the state’s primary interest during combat is in protecting the lives of its own citizens and only secondary consideration is owed to the adversary’s civilians whose protection is the responsibility of the adversary. Pooling across all the subjects in the three experiments described above, 60% agreed that “protecting the lives of U.S. soldiers” ought to be “more important” than “protecting the lives of foreign civilians” in times of war. Only 7% percent thought that the lives of foreign civilians ought to be more important (33% said they should be equally important). Third, our results provide much less evidence that public views on the use of force are consistent with the principle of distinction, perhaps the most fundamental concept of jus in bello. A large proportion of the public supports the intentional targeting of foreign civilians “to send a message” to other civilians not to support the adversary – the kind of “terror bombing” explicitly rejected by most just war proponents and strictly prohibited by international law. Americans are also more willing to accept collateral foreign civilian deaths in U.S. military operations when the civilian victims were viewed as politically sympathetic with the adversary (although few seem to believe that killing political supporters is more morally justified than killing opponents). Many Americans appear to deem that being a political supporter of the adversary is sufficient to cause individuals to lose their status as “civilians” along with the protections that come with that status. Conclusions Some readers may be tempted to conclude from these findings that Americans lack strong ethical principles when it comes to war and that the public simply favors any action that seems to benefit the United States. In contrast, we believe the U.S. public’s moral intuitions seem to follow an alternative “revisionist” view of the ethics of war, one supported by a small, but growing number of revisionist scholars. This perspective rejects just war theory’s clear moral distinction between soldiers and non-combatants in favor of a view that depends on judgments of moral responsibility and liability to attack. In this understanding, noncombatants are not always morally innocent and soldiers are not always legitimate targets in times of war.32 As a result, according to these revisionists, traditional just war considerations of distinction, proportionality and due care must be amended. Under certain conditions, revisionists argue, it may be ethically permissible to target 32 We examine the moral equivalence of soldiers in a separate experiment. 24 civilians directly if they are morally responsible for unjust wars or to trade the lives of culpable civilians to protect the lives of morally innocent soldiers. As Jeff McMahan (2009, 218), perhaps the most prominent just war revisionist scholar writes, “there are ways in which civilians can be accessories to the fighting of an unjust war, and in that way share responsibility for the war. Responsible civilians are therefore potentially liable to certain forms of action that might be necessary to prevent or correct the wrongs involved in the war.” McMahan argues that civilians can become liable not only by working directly for the war effort (e.g., building weapons) but also if they help to “arouse support for the war” or possibly even if they simply fail to take reasonable measures to protest the war. McMahan is careful to clarify that not all such actions should increase civilians’ liability to be killed, but he does suggest that there may be circumstances in which even the intentional targeting of civilians might be morally justified (McMahan 2009, 221-224). Helen Frowe (2014, 187), another revisionist scholar, argues even more directly that “we ought to reject the idea that the Principle of Non-Combatant Immunity picks out any morally significant feature of non-combatants, and with it the idea that it is always morally impermissible for just combatants to attack non-combatants on the unjust side of the war.” These kinds of arguments are reflected in the attitudes and choices of the American public in our experiments. In experiment 1, for example, 60% of subjects agreed that the “Afghan civilians in this village must bear some responsibility for the civilian fatalities caused by the U.S. strike described in the news story” when the villagers were described as political supporters of the Taliban (condition B), compared to less than 20 percent when the villagers were described as opponents of the Taliban (condition A).33 In fact, as noted above, in that experiment 42 percent of Americans asserted that political supporters of the Taliban should not be considered civilians at all. It is well beyond the scope of this paper to attempt to resolve the complex philosophical debate between just war traditionalists and revisionists. Our results do have important implications, however, regarding the practical application of ethical principles on the use of force. As noted above, traditional just war theory is not simply a moral philosophy, but has long served as a practical guide for the conduct of war, shaping international laws and national military doctrines on the use of force. In this sense, traditional just war theory is not intended to codify our existing moral intuitions about the use of force, but serves as a check on those intuitions when, in the strange and terrifying 33 This difference is significant at P<.001. 25 circumstances of war, they might lead us to justify terrible acts. Our results reinforce the urgent need to maintain such a check. As most revisionist scholars seem to recognize, their arguments on the “deep ethics” of war are not a feasible guide for the practice of war. McMahan, for example, acknowledges that his contention that it may be morally permissible to target civilians intentionally is “of limited practical significance,” because the conditions that would need to be satisfied to justify the intentional targeting of civilians “are impossible to satisfy in virtually all actual cases of military attacks against civilians” (McMahan 2009, 224-225). In most cases, he argues, few civilians make a contribution to the war significant enough to justify killing them and even if they did, killing some culpable civilians would usually involve killing many innocent ones who just happen to live nearby. The results of our study suggest that Americans appear to accept the revisionists’ argument that “responsible” civilians may be liable to attack, but not the revisionists’ qualifications that usually render such attacks impermissible in practice. Nuanced judgments about moral culpability and innocence are difficult enough to render in a philosopher’s thought experiments, but almost impossible to make consistently and objectively given the complexity of the real world and the exigencies of war. With no impartial, international judicial body capable of enforcing judgments on parties who make competing moral claims, it seems likely that we will much too often choose to judge ourselves and our countrymen innocent and our adversaries culpable. As McMahan (2009, 109) concludes, a rule that “permitted all combatants to attack civilians in certain specified conditions… would be exploited by the unjust and inevitably abused by the just, leading to greater violence” than a rule that simply banned such attacks categorically. We find this concern amply validated in our results. Indeed, the same logic that subjects in our experiment seem to have employed to justify attacks on civilian political supporters of the Taliban has been employed by enemies of the United States to justify attacks on American civilians. This mode of reasoning was explicit, for example, in Osama Bin Laden’s 2002 “Letter to America,” in which he articulated his justification for the attacks of September 11, 2001. After claiming that Al Qaeda’s attacks were warranted in response to numerous alleged acts of aggression that the United States had committed against Muslims around the world, Bin Laden attempted to preempt his critics, writing, You may then dispute that all the above does not justify aggression against [American] civilians, for crimes they did not commit and offenses in which they did not partake… This argument contradicts your continuous repetition that America is 26 the land of freedom... Therefore, the American people are the ones who choose their government by way of their own free will; a choice which stems from their agreement to its policies… The American people have the ability and choice to refuse the policies of their Government and even to change it if they want. The American people are the ones who pay the taxes… So the American people are the ones who fund the attacks against us, and they are the ones who oversee the expenditure of these monies in the way they wish, through their elected candidates… This is why the American people cannot be innocent of all the crimes committed… against us (quoted in Guardian 2002). As a result of concerns about enabling arguments such as this, McMahan (2009, 109) concedes that, as a matter of practice, the laws of war and the ethics of war should remain separate and he accepts that current just war guidelines provide a reasonably sound basis for such laws. Our results suggest, however, that the American public does not appear to recognize this subtle but critical distinction between revisionist ethics and practice. Many Americans are willing to substitute just war doctrine’s bright line between soldiers and civilians in favor of relatively crude views of moral culpability. Both traditional just war theorists and revisionists, therefore, should consider these findings disturbing and regrettable. 27 Table 1: Summary of Experimental Conditions EXPERIMENT 1 DISTINCTION/CULPABILITY TARGET SCENARIO DESCRIPTION Taliban chemical weapons lab U.S. must choose between a largescale or small-scale airstrike. The large-scale strike kills more Afghan civilians than the small scale strike (500 vs. 20) but is more likely to destroy target (90% vs. 45% chance of success). Conditions vary the “culpability” of Afghan civilians. CONDITION A villagers politically oppose Taliban CONDITION B villagers politically support Taliban CONDITION C villagers politically support Taliban and work in weapons factory CONDITION D villagers politically support Taliban and the U.S. intentionally targets civilians. CONDITION E villagers politically support Taliban and provide food to the Taliban and the U.S. intentionally targets civilians. EXPERIMENT 2 DUE CARE EXPERIMENT 3 PROPORTIONALITY Taliban chemical weapons lab U.S. must choose between a house-to-house assault or an artillery strike. The house-tohouse assault will result in more U.S. military deaths, but fewer Afghan civilian deaths. Conditions vary ratio of U.S. military deaths to Afghan civilian deaths. House-to-house fatalities: 5 US mil. / 0 Afghan civ. Artillery fatalities: 0 U.S. mil/ 200 Afghan civ. Meeting of Taliban leaders U.S. must choose between a largescale or small-scale airstrike. The large-scale strike kills more Afghan civilians than the smallscale strike (200 vs. 20) but is more likely to destroy target (45% vs. 90%). Conditions vary importance of Taliban leaders. House-to-house fatalities: 50 US mil. / 0 Afghan civ. Artillery fatalities: 0 U.S. mil. / 200 Afghan civ. House-to-house fatalities: 200 US mil. /0 Afghan civ. Artillery fatalities: 0 U.S. mil. / 200 Afghan civ. high level, national Taliban leaders House-to-house fatalities: 250 US mil. /0 Afghan civ Artillery fatalities: 0 U.S. mil./ 200 Afghan civ. 28 low level, local Taliban leaders high level, national Taliban leaders planning attacks on U.S. homeland Appendix: Experimental Treatments EXPERIMENT 1/CONDITION A 29 EXPERIMENT 1/CONDITION B 30 EXPERIMENT 1/CONDITION C 31 EXPERIMENT 1/CONDITION D 32 EXPERIMENT 1/CONDITION E 33 EXPERIMENT 2/CONDITION A 34 EXPERIMENT 2/CONDITION B 35 EXPERIMENT 2/CONDITION C 36 EXPERIMENT 2/CONDITION D 37 EXPERIMENT 3/CONDITION A 38 EXPERIMENT 3/CONDITION B 39 EXPERIMENT 3/CONDITION C 40 Works Cited Ansolabehere, Stephen and Brian F. Schaffner. 2014. “Does Survey Mode Still Matter? Findings from a 2010 Multi-Mode Comparison.” Political Analysis 22(3): 285-303. Arneson, Richard J. 2006. “Just Warfare Theory and Noncombatant Immunity.” Cornell International Law Journal 39: 663–88. Audi, Robert . 2005. The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Benbaji, Yitzhak, Amir Falk and Yuval Feldman. 2014. “Commonsense Morality and the Ethics of Killing in War: An Experimental Survey of the Israeli Population.” Forthcoming in Law and Ethics of Human Rights. Berrens, Robert P., Alok Bohara, Hank Jenkins-Smith, Carol Silva, and David Weimer. 2003. “The Advent of Internet Surveys for Political Research: A Comparison of Telephone and Internet Samples.” Political Analysis 11 (1): 1–22. Bohrer, Ziv and Mark Osiel. 2013. “Proportionality in Military Force at War’s Multiple Levels: Averting Civilian Casualties vs. Safeguarding Soldiers.” Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law 46(3): 747-822. Brennan, John O. 2012. “The Ethics and Efficacy of the President’s Counterterrorism Strategy,” address at the Woodrow Wilson Center for International Scholars, Washington, DC. April 30. http://www.wilsoncenter.org/event/the-efficacy-and-ethics-us-counterterrorism-strategy Carpenter, Carli. 2005. “Women, Children and Other Vulnerable Groups: Gender, Strategic Frames and the Protection of Civilians as a Transnational Issue.” International Studies Quarterly 49(2): 295334. 41 Christopher, Paul. 1999. The Ethics of War and Peace: An Introduction to Legal and Moral Issues. Upper Saddle River, N.J.: Prentice-Hall. CBS News Poll. April 2003. Retrieved Oct-19-2014 from the iPOLL Databank, The Roper Center for Public Opinion Research, University of Connecticut. http://www.ropercenter.uconn.edu/data_access/ipoll/ipoll.html CNN/ORC International Poll. 2014. Retrieved Aug-19-2014 from the iPOLL Databank, The Roper Center for Public Opinion Research, University of Connecticut. http://www.ropercenter.uconn.edu/data_access/ipoll/ipoll.html Conway-Lanz, Sahr. 2006. Collateral Damage: Americans, Noncombatant Immunity, and Atrocity after World War II. New York: Routledge. Crawford, Neta C. 2013. Accountability for Killing: Moral Responsibility for Collateral Damage in America’s Post-9/11 Wars. Oxford. Oxford University Press. Dunlap, Charles J. 2000. “Kosovo, Casualty Aversion, and the American Military Ethos: A Perspective.” Air Force Journal of Legal Studies 10(99): 95-107. Eichenberg, Richard C. 2005. “Victory Has Many Friends: U.S. Public Opinion and the Use of Military Force, 1981–2005.” International Security 30 (1): 140–77. Fabre, Cécile. 2012. Cosmopolitan War. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fabre, Cécile. 2009. “Guns, Food, and Liability to Attack in War.” Ethics 120(1): 36-63. Fellmeth, Aaron Xavier. 2008. Questioning Civilian Immunity. Texas International Law Journal 43(3): 453-497. Frowe, Helen. 2014. Defensive Killing. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 42 Gallup 2011. Views of Violence <http://www.gallup.com/strategicconsulting/153623/BRIEF-ViewsViolence.aspx> Gelpi, Christopher, Peter D. Feaver, and Jason Reifler. 2009. Paying the Human Costs of War: American Public Opinion and Casualties in Military Conflicts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Grayling, A. C. 2006. Among the Dead Cities: The History and Moral Legacy of the WWII Bombing of Civilians in Germany and Japan. New York: Walker & Co. Greene, Joshua David. 2013. Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason, and the Gap Between Us and Them. New York: Penguin Press. Guardian. 2002. “bin Laden’s ‘letter to America’” November 24. <http://www.theguardian.com/world/2002/nov/24/theobserver> Haidt, Jonathan. 2012. The Righteous Mind: Why Good People are Divided by Politics and Religion. New York: Pantheon Books. Hurka, Thomas. 2005. “Proportionality in the Morality of War.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 33(1): 3466. Joint Chiefs of Staff. 2013. Joint Publication 3-60: Joint Doctrine for Targeting. Washington, D.C.: Department of Defense. Kahl, Colin. 2007. “In the Crossfire or the Crosshairs? Norms, Civilian Casualties, and U.S. Conduct in Iraq.” International Security 32:7-46. Kamm, Francis M. 2004 “The Failures of Just War Theory: Terror, Harm and Justice.” Ethics 114(4):650-692. Kasher Asa and Amos Yadlin. 2005. “Military Ethics of Fighting Terror: An Israeli Perspective.” Journal of Military Ethics 4(1): 3-32. 43 Kinsella, Helen. 2011. The Image before the Weapon: A Critical History of the Distinction between Combatant and Civilian. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Lazar, Seth. 2012. “Necessity in Self-Defense and War.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 40(1):3-44. Lee, Steven P. 2012 Ethics and War: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lind, Gunner, ed., 2014. Civilians at War. Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum Press. Luban, David. 2014. “Risk Taking and Force Projection.” In Reading Walzer, eds., Yitzhak Benbaji and Naomi Sussmann. New York: Routledge. Margalit, Avishai and Michael Walzer. 2009. “Israel: Civilians and Combatants.” New York Review of Books 56(8) < http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/2009/may/14/israel-civilianscombatants/> McKeogh, Colm. 2002. Innocent Civilians: The Morality of Killing in War. New York: Palgrave. McMahan, Jeff. 2009. Killing in War. Oxford: Clarendon Press Orend, Brian. 2008. “War.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/war/>. Otsuka, Michael. 1994. “Killing the Innocent in Self-Defense.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 23(1): 7494. Øverland, Gerhard Esben. 2005. “Killing Civilians: On the Immunity of Civilians in War.” European Journal of Philosophy 13(3): 345–363. 44 Porat, Iddo and Ziv Bohrer. 2014. “Preferring One’s Own Civilians: May Soldiers Endanger Enemy Civilians More Than They Would Endanger Their State’s Civilians?” forthcoming in the George Washington International Law Review. Press, Daryl, Scott Sagan, and Benjamin Valentino. 2013. “Atomic Aversion: Experimental Evidence on Taboos, Traditions, and the Non-Use of Nuclear Weapons.” American Political Science Review 107(1): 188-206. Roberts, Adam and Richard Guelff, eds.. 2004. Documents on the Laws of War. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rodin, David. 2008. “The Moral Inequality of Soldiers: Why Jus in Bello Asymmetry is Half Right,” in Just and Unjust Warriors, eds., David Rodin and Henry Shue. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 44–68. Sanders, David, Harold Clarke, Marianne C. Stewart, and Paul Whiteley. 2007. “Does Mode Matter for Modeling Political Choice?” Political Analysis 15 (3): 257–85. Toner, Christopher. 2005. “Just War and the Supreme Emergency Exemption,” The Philosophical Quarterly 55(221): 545-561 van Dongen, Yvonne, The Protection of Civilian Populations in Time of Armed Conflict. Amsterdam: Thesis Publishers. Yeager, David S. et al. 2011. “Comparing the Accuracy of RDD Telephone Surveys and Internet Surveys Conducted with Probability and Non-Probability Samples.” Public Opinion Quarterly 75(4):1-39. Walzer, Michael. 1977. Just and Unjust Wars. New York: Basic Books. Walzer, Michael. 2004. Arguing about War. New Haven. Yale University Press. 45 Weiner, Allen S. 2006. “The Use of Force and Contemporary Security Threats: Old Medicine for New Ills?” Stanford Law Review 59: 415-504. 46