Rosario 1 Are Yahweh and Allah One and the Same - prosario-2000

Transcription

Rosario 1 Are Yahweh and Allah One and the Same - prosario-2000
Rosario 1
Are Yahweh and Allah One and the Same God?
by
Pedro Rosario Barbosa
Recently I received this e-mail from a friend, titled “I Believe We
Worship the Same God – G. W. Bush”. I don't know who wrote it, but it
states the following:
Asked about Muslim God vs. Pres. Bush's God, Bush's Answer:
''I believe we worship the same God'' Source: White House
Press Release, Thu Nov 20,2003 -http://www.whitehouse.gov/news/releases/2003/11/20031120
-3.html (towards the end of the transcript)
Q
Thank
you,
Mr.
President,
Mr.
Prime
Minister.
Mr.
President, when you talk about peace in the Middle East,
you've often said that freedom is granted by the Almighty.
Some people who share your beliefs don't believe that Muslims
worship the same Almighty. I wonder about your views on that.
And, Mr. Prime Minister, as a man also of faith, I'd like to
get your reaction to that.
PRESIDENT BUSH: I do say that freedom is the Almighty's gift
to every person. I also condition it by saying freedom is not
America's gift to the world. It's much greater than that, of
course. And I believe we worship the same God.
Note: I think we have an answer about whether Bush is a
Rosario 2
Christian or just greatly deceived. Very sad day for America
if that is his true belief.
+++++
Many Christians accept the Muslim claim that we both worship
the same God. They claim that they call him Allah, while we
call him God. It is not unusual to hear Christian leaders make
such statements. Bible societies have even gone so far as to
use the name Allah in the Bibles they produce for Arab
Christians.
The problem with this is two-fold. First, history and
archeology show clearly that Allah was worshiped as a pagan
moon god long before Mohamed came on the scene. Robert Morey,
author of The Islamic Invasion, explains:
"Islam's origins have been traced back by scholars to the
ancient fertility religion of the worship of the moon god
which was always the dominant religion of Arabia. The moon
god was worshiped by praying toward Mecca several times a
day, making an annual pilgrimage to the Kabah which was a
temple of the moon god, running around the Kabah seven times,
caressing an idol of a black stone set in the wall of the
Kabah, running between two hills, making animal sacrifices,
gathering on Fridays for prayers, giving alms to the poor,
etc. These were pagan rites practiced by the Arabs long
before Muhammad was born."
Rosario 3
"What religion today practices the pagan rites of the moon
god? Islam! This explains why the crescent moon is the symbol
of Islam. It is placed on top of mosques and minarets and
displayed on hats, flags, rugs, amulets and even jewelry.
Every time you see the Muslim symbol of a crescent moon, you
are seeing the ancient symbol of the moon god."
Second, if you read the Qur'an's description of Allah, and
read the Bible's description of God, it becomes obvious you
are reading about two different persons. Allah orders his
followers to kill those who deny Islam, while God instructs
us to love our enemies. Allah had no son while God sent His Son
to die for sinful men. Allah is "unknowable" while God seeks a
personal relationship with His creation, man.
The spirit behind Islam is an entirely different spirit... a
spirit that denies the deity of Jesus Christ. Any Christian
who accepts the notion that Allah is God creates an
impossible situation. Since the Qur'an contains our only
revelation about Allah, they will be forced to look there as
their authority. The Qur'an specifically denies the deity of
Christ! All Christian witness ends right there.
Usually from a Christian point of view, it is very easy to contemplate
this statement as completely legitimate. However, I wish to offer
various points of view, specially anthropological and philosophical
of why things are not so simple as it is said in this e-mail.
Rosario 4
I wish to state that this is not a defense of G. W. Bush, I don't
like him very much. However, that doesn't mean that this particular
statement he made is false. And my argument will center in two main
arguments. First one is an anthropological analysis on the Christian
religion practically sending the message: “Why do you observe the
splinter in your brother's eye and never notice the great log in your
own?” (Matt. 7,3). Secondly, I wish to demonstrate that the
discrepancy is not so much the entity being worshiped, but the
properties or definite descriptions of that entity about what did He
say or has He done.
I.
First of all, one of the things I wish to point to is at the fact that
the essay continually speaks about the pagan background of the Muslim
religion. For example we quote it saying the following:
The problem with this is two-fold. First, history and
archeology show clearly that Allah was worshiped as a pagan
moon god long before Mohamed came on the scene. Robert
Morey, author of The Islamic Invasion, explains:
"Islam's origins have been traced back by scholars to the
ancient fertility religion of the worship of the moon god
which was always the dominant religion of Arabia. The moon
god was worshiped by praying toward Mecca several times a
day, making an annual pilgrimage to the Kabah which was a
Rosario 5
temple of the moon god, running around the Kabah seven
times, caressing an idol of a black stone set in the wall of
the Kabah, running between two hills, making animal
sacrifices, gathering on Fridays for prayers, giving alms
to the poor, etc. These were pagan rites practiced by the
Arabs long before Muhammad was born."
"What religion today practices the pagan rites of the moon
god? Islam! This explains why the crescent moon is the
symbol of Islam. It is placed on top of mosques and minarets
and displayed on hats, flags, rugs, amulets and even
jewelry. Every time you see the Muslim symbol of a crescent
moon, you are seeing the ancient symbol of the moon god."
This statement seems to assume that Islam has a pagan background,
while Christianity doesn't. That in reality Muslims adore Allah as the
moon god, an ancient pagan god. Christianity and Christian symbols
(such as the cross) on the other hand are free of all pagan influence. I
want to show that Christianity and Judaism, both, have absorbed pagan
symbols and backgrounds and even symbols from foreign deities,
religious customs and philosophies that have become part of the JudeoChristian notion of God.
For starters, the final form of the Pentateuch and many books of
the Old Testament was not written until after the Jews came back from
Babylon. Some may argue that the Pentateuch was written by Moses, but
thorough studies which can date as back as the XI century, have shown
Rosario 6
conclusively the impossibility of Moses having written it. Scholars
have concluded that the Pentateuch was the result of very different
traditions. Most of these traditions have a pagan background. For
example, archaeologists have found that approximately during the XI
to Xth century BC or so, the Jewish people were not the only people
there. There were lots of Canaanites worshiping a god called "El"
whose representation was a golden calf. This is the real background
for the word "God" in Hebrew. The word "El" in Hebrew means "God", and
many names in Hebrew are exactly based on this word, for example:
"Isra-el" (Strong with God), "Beth-el" (House of God), "Micha-el"
(Who is like God), "Rapha-el" (God's Healer), etc. However, the Old
Testament uses the word "Elohim" to refer to God. "Elohim" is nothing
more than "El" in its plural form (the ending "im" is used as
indication of plural in Hebrew). So, the Old Testament itself refers
to God using a derivative word of the name of an ancient pagan god.
This may be surprising to many because of the fact that Yahweh,
God, frequently denounces the religion of the Canaanites (Deut.
12,29-31), but the linguistic evidence is undeniable. Furthermore,
this explains something that perplexes Jews and Christians alike:
that Jeroboam chose the Golden Calf to represent the God that took them
out of Egypt (1 Kings 12,26-33). This surprises in the sense that
during the condemnation by the Shilo priests, they don't mention at
all the earlier episode of Moses and the people of Israel with the
Golden Calf (Exod. 32; 1 Kings 13, 1-19). The reason is very simple,
Rosario 7
scholars have reached the conclusion that the story of the Golden Calf
was written by the Shilo priests to denounce precisely what Jeroboam
was doing, this view is reinforced by the fact that the author of the
story of the Golden Calf, probably a Shilo priest, placed in the
people's mouth more or less what Jeroboam stated when he established
the cult (Exod. 32,4; 1 Kings 12,28). But the Golden Calves do not
represent other gods; according to Aaron's own words, the Golden Calf
represents Yahweh himself, because after constructing the Golden
Calf, Aaron says that a feast should be made for Yahweh (Exod. 32,5).
This is not strange in the light of the evidence I have presented now.
"El" and "Yahweh" were one and the same God in the North of Israel
before the Schism, and the link is so powerful, that even when the
Shilo priests want to get rid the images of the golden calves and
denounce them, they cannot get rid of the term "Elohim" to refer to
God. I wish to add that the ancient the cult to "El" considered its god
as being the god of the moon. It is interesting to see that the feasts
of the Golden Calves were the 15th day of the 8th month, because for the
Mesopotamians the cult to the moon god (represented by a young calf)
worshiped also the 15th day of the month as a holy day (1 Kings 12,3233).
For
more
information
on
this
subject
you
can
http://www.bibleorigins.net/GoldenCalfnotEgyptian.html.
go
to:
So,
in
this aspect, apparently Judeo-Christianity's God (Elohim-Yahweh) and
the Muslim Deity (Allah) seem share more pagan background than
Christians have imagined.
Rosario 8
However, this absorption of pagan cults and words into JudeoChristianity doesn't end here. For example, other pagan images were
used, like the Cherubims. The Old Testament uses the images of
Cherubims all over it. You can see them protecting the tree of life in
the Garden of Eden (Gen. 3,24), they are placed on the Ark of the
Covenant (Exod. 37,7-8), they are placed at the entrance of the Santa
Sanctorum of the Temple (1 Kings 6,23-30), and Ezekiel has a vision of
Cherubims (Ezek. 1, 4-27). The word "cherubim" comes from the Assyrian
word "karibu" which were gods that served to protect Assyrian (pagan)
holy places and buildings. Their exact shape was that of the head of a
man, the body of a lion, the legs of a bull and the wings of an eagle.
Isn't an amazing coincidence that Ezekiel describes the cherubims
this way?: "They were of human form. Each had four faces, each had four
wings [. . .] all four had human face, and a lion's face to the right,
and all four had a bull's face to the left, and all four had an eagle's
face" (Ezek 1,10). This also inspired the author of Revelations when
he talked about the four beings praising God constantly before Him,
one had the shape of a man, another the shape of a bull, another the
shape of a lion, and the other of an eagle (Rev. 4,7). So, even the New
Testament is influenced by ancient pagan creatures, the karibu. Later
Christianity went a bit further and made each one of these beings the
symbols of the four evangelists: Matthew (Man), Mark (Lion), Luke
(Bull) and John (Eagle).
Other pagan objects came into play, for example, the famous
Rosario 9
bronze serpent, called Nehushtan, which was also a pagan symbol, but
was also a significant symbol for the Jews.
According to the Old
Testament, Moses commanded a bronze serpent to be built to heal the
Israelites from the poison caused by snake bites (Numbers 21,4-9).
Paradoxically, it also appears as the evil snake that tempts Eve to eat
from the fruit of knowledge of good and evil (Gen.3,1-23).
This
happens to be a symbol of Sumerian god Enki (Ea), the giver of
knowledge of humanity, and his symbol was a snake crawling up a tree or
a stake. The same symbol was used in ancient Greece to denote
Aesculapius, the Greek god of healing, and this symbol is still being
used today as a symbol for cure and medicine. You can look at it in the
hospitals and ambulances. In John's Gospel, Jesus uses the bronze
serpent as the symbol of salvation (John 3,14).
There are many other examples I can give that are from pagan
origins: stellas (Gen. 28,18.22; Jos. 24,26), the style of the Song of
Songs which imitates the poetry styles of people of other countries in
which they celebrated the unions of Osiris and Isis in Egypt and Tamuz
and Ishtar in Babylon. However, with the examples I have given is more
than enough.
Christianity as a religious movement is no exception to this
pagan influence. St. Paul particularly was influenced by Middle
Platonism and Stoicism which were regarded by many Jews as being
pagan, since it was inspired by foreign philosophies. But St. Paul was
very familiar with them, and even openly debated with Stoics and
Rosario 10
Epicureans (Acts 17,16-32). He was evidently familiar with a
philosopher called Philo of Alexandria (20 BC-50 AD), a Middle
Platonist, who wanted to view the Old Testament from the point of view
of the Greek philosopher Plato. For him, God created the world out of
chaos as Genesis stated, but he wanted it to agree with Plato's
Timaeus. According to him, God created a world of forms, but the whole
entity of these world of forms is what he called the Logos. Philo had
interesting names for this Logos: Son of God, the First-Born of God,
the Light of the World, the Mediator between God and his creation, etc.
Since the Logos contains in itself all the intelligible forms or
essences, these perfect entities from which the material world
participates from, then all creation was made through the Logos. This
would prevent, for example, that a perfect being like God would enter
in contact with something like corruptible matter. Since the Logos is
the Image of God, he says, he made man and woman after the Logos, since
the Bible says that God created man and woman after the “Image of God”.
St. Paul, in the authentic Pauline letters (Romans, 1 and 2 of
Corinthians, Galatians, Philippians, 1 Thesalonnians and Philemon)
gives us a hint about this conception of Jesus as the Logos, even
though he is not too explicit. For example, according to St. Paul,
Christ existed before creation: "Make your own the mind of Christ
Jesus: Who, being in the form of God, did not count equality with God"
(Phil. 2,6), "Though there are so-called gods, in the heavens or on the
earth -- and there are plenty of gods and plenty of lords -- yet for us
Rosario 11
there is only one God, the Father from whom all things come and for whom
we exist, and one Lord, Jesus Christ through whom all things come and
through whom we exist" (1 Cor. 8,5-6). Often some Christians ask why
God needed angels (messengers) to mediate between God and humanity as
St. Paul states clearly at one moment (Gal. 3,19-21), the Old
Testament makes clear that God speaks directly to Moses, for instance,
or God speaks to his prophets, or that God makes this or that
extraordinary phenomena (like a pillar of fire), etc. St. Paul,
however, seems to be implying Philo's philosophy of God needing a
mediator between Himself and the world, and from Christ (who he
implies is the Logos) on, then Jesus Christ becomes our mediator (Gal.
3, 22-28). There is still another likening between St. Paul and Philo
of Alexandria. For Philo, to have faith in the Logos makes a man be a
son of God, because the Logos is the first-born of all creation. It is
interesting that St. Paul states exactly the same thing (Rom. 8,11.1415.28-30). The Post-Pauline letters, letters attributed to St. Paul
even though he didn't write them, exploit more the notion of the Logos
and its relation to Christ: Christ is the light (Eph. 5,4), God clearly
made all things (metaphysical and physical) through Christ (Col.
1,15-17),
It was not until the end of the first century, when the Gospel of
John as we know it was finished, that there is an explicit doctrine
linking the Logos and Jesus Christ:
"In the beginning was the Logos, the Logos was with God and
Rosario 12
the Logos was God. He was with God in the beginning. through
him all things came into being, not one thing came into
being except through him. What has come into being in him
was life, life that was the light of men; and light shines in
darkness, and darkness could not overpower it. [. . .] The
Logos was the real light that gives light to everyone; he
was coming into the world. He was in the world that had come
into being through him, and the world did not recognise him.
He came to his own and his own people did not accept him. But
to those who did accept him he gave power to become children
of God, to those who believed in his name who were born not
from human stock or human desire or human will but from God
himself" (John 1, 1-5.9-13).
The only difference between the Logos of St. John and the Logos of
Philo of Alexandria is that for the latter, the Logos was not God, but a
divine creature, the first-born and most perfect of all creation, and
he remained a divine being. However, for St. John, the Logos is God and
he became human (John 1,14).
So, we see a great influence of non-Jewish philosophy in
Christianity, and this was a constant source of conflict between the
Jewish Christians and the Gentiles. The book of Acts, as well as Paul
letter to the Galatians, as well as many apocrypha, and even the letter
of St. James in the New Testament, give testimony of the constant
source of conflict between both the Jewish and the Gentile view of
Rosario 13
Christianity.
However,
this
absorption
of
non-Jewish
(pagan)
philosophies was just the beginning of a whole process of adopting
pagan rituals. For example, Middle Platonism evolved into NeoPlatonism, and St. Augustine, a great theologian and philosopher by
the way, was one of the great representatives of that branch of
philosophy. Often he is called the Christian Plato.
We have to add the fact that also in the New Testament we see
imagery derived from pagan religions, such as the representation of
the woman clothed with the sun in Revelations 12. Her clothing, her
crown, the moon at her feet, etc. are arranged exactly the way it is
represented in many Mother Goddesses at that time. The stars, the
moon, etc. are all symbols also found in the Old Testament, but the way
it is arranged in that text resemble exactly the Mother Goddesses of
ancient Egypt, of Greece, of Babylon, among many others.
Another fact is that very few people know really why Constantine
made Sunday a weekly holiday for the Empire. Most people base
themselves on Eusebius' account in his Life of Constantine (IV,18), in
which Constantine is said to have legislated because Sunday was the
day of Christ's resurrection. However, when one looks at the actual
legislation made by Constantine, and was compilated in the Theodosian
Code, we find the following:
"Imp.
Constantinus
videbatur,
diem
a.
solis,
elpidio.
sicut
veneratione
indignissimum
sui
celebrem,
altercantibus iurgiis et nixiis partium contentionibus
Rosario 14
occupari [. . .]" (Imperatoris Theodosiani Codex, 2.8.1)
Translation: "Simply, because it seems to us the most
inappropriate that in the Day of the Sun, which is
celebrated for His own honor, we be occupied in juridical
complaints [. . .]".
So, he favors Sunday being a weekly holiday because it is the day of the
Sun, the Sol-Invictus. There is plenty of evidence that Constantine
was inclined to the devotion of the Sol-Invictus, most of his coins
allude to it. In the Arch of Constantine, with which he remembered the
attack on the Milvian Bridge, alludes to the Sol-Invictus. He even
made a statue of himself as the Sol-Invictus. This has led many people
(including myself) to conclude that Constantine was not really a
Christian, but a worshiper of the Sun who was a strong ally of
Christianity, because it was a very powerful influence, but he was not
a Christian himself. It was not until after his death, that the bishop
Eusebius of Cesarea falsified many of the facts to make him look like a
Christian. The cult of Sol Invictus was closely linked to Mithraism,
which considered the god Mithra as the god of light. In some ways it
also fused with the worship of the Sol-Invictus, it had Sunday also as
the weekly day of worship. Also both religions shared the same day of
yearly celebration of the Sol Invictus or Mithra: December 25. Sounds
familiar? But wait... there's more! Where did the clothes that the
bishops come from? It certainly didn't originate in the land of
Palestine
during
first
century
Christianity.
If
Constantine
Rosario 15
worshiped the Sol-Invictus and this cult was deeply related to
Mithraism, this can explain why bishops today wear one modality of the
Phrygian caps, which was used by high leaders of Mithraism and the Sol-
Invictus,
and
was
widely
used
by
political
ministers
during
Constantine's rule. This cap is called "mitre", and it is not called
"mitre" (Mithra) for nothing.
Also, the symbolism used by other mysteric religions were
incorporated within Christianity, such as the cross and the crucifix,
which were also used by solar cults, and also the cults to the god
Orpheus, specially the image of Crucified Orpheus. Also we have to
take into account that many symbols widely used in images of mother
goddesses were also very much incorporated to the imagery of the
Virgin Mary.
It can even go as far as inventing legends based precisely on
pagan customs. For example, most historians are definitely convinced
that St. James (the son of Zebedee) did not visit Spain during his
lifetime, and there is plenty of evidence of that. Despite this, to
counteract the force of the Moslems who invaded Spain. Interestingly,
Christian chose sites that were considered sacred by the ancient Celts
on northern Spain to build Temples, and invented stories about how St.
James visited Spain and went throughout those sites and later was
buried there. This is what was called "El Camino de Santiago" (The Way
of St. James). This created and incredible economic incentive in Spain
that led to have enough force to displace the Moslims out of Spain
Rosario 16
during the Reconquer of those lands.
So, we Christians cannot say in any way that our religion is free
from pagan influence, and also it cannot say that the Judeo-Christian
God is not related in any way to the Moslem God, Allah.
II.
This section is more a philosophical foundation of why I don't
think some Christians have a case in saying that the Judeo-Christian
God is not the Moslem God. This has to do with philosophy of language,
specially with the issue of proper names. In here, I wish to make a
difference between a "proper name" and "definite descriptions". For
the effects of this discussion, I will call "proper name" those names
like "Aristotle", "Martin Luther King", "Peter", "John", etc.
"Definite descriptions" gives us the senses (meanings) with which we
refer to objects,such as "the best known of Plato's disciples", "the
leader of the civil rights movement", etc., in this aspect I will
follow Bertrand Russell's terminology to make this distinction.
Usually, for me, names have a meaning, that is "he who is called X",
however, we will treat names here another way. Though I don't agree
with Saul Kripke concerning proper names as rigid designators, I think
his philosophy can be fruitful in our discussion, specially at the
end.
We are questioning, whether an entity that Jews and Christians
call "God" is the same entity that Moslems call "Allah". The basis for
Rosario 17
establishing the difference between both entities is mainly because
the Christian who wrote the essay says that because Judeo-Christian
God has P property, and the Moslems state that Allah has G property,
such difference in property implies a difference in entity. For
example, the Moslem God has the property of being based on pagan
practices, and the Judeo-Christian God doesn't have this property.
Since we have shown that definitely this argument has been refuted, we
have to turn to other of their arguments to see if what some Christians
say is true.
However, we must ask in principle if we can make the allegation
that Judeo-Christian God and the Moslem God are one and the same God
based on the definite descriptions of P and G. Here we enter into the
aspects of intensionality and extensionality in logic and semantics.
A focus on intensions makes us realize a difference between identity
and equality. We will call "equality" between two entities iff two
entities share some properties or definite descriptions. For example,
men and horses are equal in the aspect that they are both mammals.
However, we will call "identity" when both or more entities share all
properties. An example of this is when the Declaration of Independence
state that all men are equal, however this doesn't mean that all men
are identical, since men are all different when accounting for all of
their properties. This difference between equality and identity had
been established by Leibniz, also assumed by Edmund Husserl, and from
Husserl, Rudolf Carnap adopted this difference when he made the
Rosario 18
difference between equivalence and L-equivalence. Most recently Ruth
Barcan Marcus, a modal logician, adopts a position of assuming
different degrees of equivalence in her famous philosophical work
Modalities.
This has been discussed deeply in Philosophy and Linguistics
extensively, for example, Claire Ortiz Hill, Ruth Barcan Marcus'
disciple, and deep admirer or Edmund Husserl, basing herself on the
difference
between
equality
and
identity,
looks
at
examples
questioning, if we can establish an identity just based on few
definite descriptions.
A few years ago in Jerusalem courtroom found a retired Ohio
autoworker named John Demjanjuk guilty of being Ivan the
Terrible, the murderer of hundreds of thousands of Jews.
Throughout
his
fourteen
month
trial,
Demjanjuk
had
insisted he was a victim of mistaken identity. For the
Jerusalem courtroom that condemned him to death the only
thing that mattered involved determining whether or not he
was the same man who had operated gas chambers at Treblinka
during World War II, any of the innumerably many other
things that could be truthfully predicated of him were
beside the point. Their reasoning was of the form: F(x), and
if F(y), then x = y. Killing hundreds of thousands of Jews was
true of Ivan the Terrible and if the same were true of John
Demjanjuk, then he would be Ivan the Terrible -- and liable
Rosario 19
to hanging. (Hill and Rosado 9).
Drawing attention to some undesirable consequences of
failing to distinguish between identity and lesser forms of
equivalence
in
the
medical
sciences
is
one
way
of
illustrating Marcus's concerns and of demonstrating the
real need for consciously trafficking in intensional
notions in order to control confusion and draw the fine
distinctions that are both germane and indispensable to
many
scientific
undertakings.
Strong
extensional
principles may prove appropriate in certain contexts,
e.g., in criminal investigations or juridical proceedings
where a person's guilt or innocence may be the sole
determinant
factor,
but
relying
on
them
could
have
disastrous consequences in other contexts. For instance,
in medical research and practice, extensional notions
could unnecessarily complicate situations and generate
confusion and even make the difference between life and
death, sickness and health.
Consider this example. Doctors at Toronto's Hospital for
Sick Children have discovered that the immune system of
certain diabetics identifies a protein present on the
surface of their insulin-producing cells as being the same
as a protein present in cow's milk with which it is in many
respects almost identical. Unable to distinguish between
Rosario 20
the two proteins, the immune system stimulates the body to
attack and destroy its own insulin-producing cells in the
pancreas, causing juvenile onset diabetes, which may lead
to blindness, kidney failure and heart disease (Hill 5152).
Of course, this is not the case concerning our issue on God. We want to
establish not that if two names of entities that have the same property
are in reality one sole entity. What we have here, for example, is the
issue of whether two names with different properties associated with
them, can designate one entity. Ortiz Hill gives us an example of a
case like this:
For instance, is a person in an irreversible coma following
an accident who is entirely dependent on machines to
sustain her bodily functions identical to the person she
was
before
the
accident
took
place?
Think
of
the
innumerable things that could be have been predicated of
her before that are no longer true, and the truly macabre
propositions that could result from substitution rules
that do not take sufficient account of the difference
between equality and identity. Her family surely would
never have considered depriving her of the minimum means
necessary to support her life before she was in a coma (Hill
45).
So, one entity can have some set of properties at one moment, and at
Rosario 21
another moment an entirely other set of properties. For example, one
woman can have the property of being able to walk, but later after an
accident she doesn't have that property any longer. So we can talk
about
the
same
entity
having
completely
different,
and
even
contradictory definite descriptions.
However, how would this fit into the situation of JudeoChristian God and the Moslem God? In reality not very well. For
example, in the case of a woman we have the criterion of time as an
important factor in stating two contrary definite descriptions of the
woman in a comma. We don't state that the woman "is able to walk" and
"is not able to walk" simultaneously. And we cannot state, for
instance God "is a Trinity" and "is not a Trinity" which is what
diverse religious groups assume God to be. These two definite
descriptions of God are totally incompatible. So, we are back to
square one. At least if we deal with this issue ontologically,
semantics won't get us anywhere.
III.
If this is true, then we will have to move to another
philosophical level, which is the epistemological level of the
discussion, and try to see adequate semantics that will enable us to
deal with the subject of this essay. As in all epistemological
subjects the main subject we must ask is: "how do I know?" or "how do we
know?" In this case the question is: "How do I know that the Judeo-
Rosario 22
Christian God and the Moslem God are two different entities or one and
the same entity?"
Epistemological considerations are difficult, since in great
measure confirmation of statements depend greatly on the theoretical
framework we approach objects. However, there is a level of "common
sense" in which we can all agree on certain aspects of our own
theoretical frameworks, at least enough to make a point. For example,
let's say that John and Peter are arguing if Mary is a secretary or not.
John states that Mary is a secretary, however Peter says that she
isn't. So, both have four alternative scenarios concerning Mary:
(1) That Mary was a secretary before and is no longer a secretary now.
(2) That Mary was not a secretary before, and she is a secretary now.
(3) That John and Peter are talking about different Mary's.
(4) That John and Peter are talking about the same Mary, but one of them
doesn't know her that well.
(3) and (4) will serve for the purpose of our discussion. (1) and
(2) include temporal considerations which we have rejected before and
cannot be applied to the case of God. (3) and (4), however, resemble
better to the dilemma between Judeo-Christians and Moslems.
Number (3) contemplates the possibility that because John and
Peter are giving two different definite descriptions of Mary, the Mary
that John talks about is not the Mary that Peter is talking about.
However, epistemological states can complicate this semantically.
Evidently the fact that John and Peter give two contradictory definite
Rosario 23
descriptions doesn't necessarily mean that they are talking about two
different Mary's. Number (4) is still a possibility. To decide between
(3) and (4), Peter and John can use various strategies.
(a) The first one would be to go visit the Mary(s) they are
talking about and find out if she (they) is (are) indeed a
secretary or not.
(b) To continue looking for other definite descriptions for
Mary, for example: "she is the wife of Charles Menendez", "she
has 3 children", "she is a sweet person", "she lives in
Virginia", "she is studying business management", etc. If they
both can agree on all of these or at least the vast majority, it is
most likely that they are both talking about the same Mary.
Now, let's focus on the issue of God. Can we go to God to ask him if
He is indeed a Trinity or not? It is highly unlikely. First, we don't
know where God is located, and secondly we are talking about a being
Who doesn't express himself very much in a perceptible manner. Of
course, both, the Judeo-Christians and the Moslems will argue that
they can go to their respective sacred books (the Bible and the
Qur'an), and look to what they say as evidence that God is or not a
Trinity. The epistemological difficulty of this strategy is that
actually none of them can prove that their sacred book is indeed God's
Word. All that these religions do is assume (by blind faith) that they
are the Word of God, and what is accepted as faith, is by definition,
not shown to be true neither by science nor by logic alone. Of course,
Rosario 24
both will say how "God speaks to their hearts", but this is too
subjective. Judeo-Christians will argue that God has told in their
hearts that He is a Trinity, while Moslems will argue that God has told
them in their hearts that He is not a Trinity. There is no reason to
doubt the religious sincerity of both groups, but subjective
experiences cannot be shared objectively, and that is a significant
epistemological hindrance. So we cannot use (a) as a way to determine
if God is a Trinity or is not a Trinity.
So (b) seems to be the only alternative to find out if the JudeoChristian God and the Muslim God is one and the same. The Christian who
wrote the essay we are trying to refute listed a number of differences
concerning the Judeo-Christian God and the Muslim God. However,
epistemologically
speaking,
is
this
enough
to
establish
the
difference between "both" "Gods"? Let me give an example of what I
mean. If one looks at Galileo's observations of Jupiter, you will find
that he states that it has 4 moons. If one looks at a textbook that
discusses Jupiter's moons at the end of 1999, it will say that it has 18
moons. Obviously the definite descriptions "it has 4 moons" or "has 18
moons" contradict each other. Either Jupiter has 4 or 18. However, it
would be a complete fallacy to state that because both definite
descriptions contradict, that they don't refer to one and the same
planet Jupiter.
The same here. Evidently if one reads the Bible and one reads the
Qur'an, one will notice definite differences, but also we can look at
Rosario 25
strong similarities between the God of the Bible and the God of the
Qur'an. And in fact, they can be far more similar, than this Christian
is able to accept.
IV.
Let us examine in detail the definite descriptions that the e-mail
states distinguishes the Christian God from the God of the Muslims.
1) The cult to Allah is based on paganism and the cult to the JudeoChristian God isn't.
2) Allah orders to kill anyone who denies the truths of Islam, while
the Judeo-Christian God wants us to love our enemies.
3) Allah is "unknowable" while the Judeo-Christian God is a personal
God.
4) Allah has no Son, while the Judeo-Christian God does have a Son.
5) Muslims deny Jesus' divinity, while Jesus is also the JudeoChristian God.
We have refuted (1) so we won't spend time refuting it again.
Let us go to (2). Allah does say in various parts of the Qur'an to
kill other people who don't want to follow the path of Islam, but
obviously not "just because". For example, the Qur'an orders to have a
war against those who attack Muslims. And the Qur'an explicitly states
that if enemy stops attacking them, then Allah would be merciful
toward the enemy, and it also invites not to precipitate in the
killing, and to do good to their enemy once the persecution is over
Rosario 26
(Qur'an 2, 186/190-191/195). Now, is this not true also for the JudeoChristian God? The simplistic answer given is that Jesus invites us to
love our enemy. But what about all the wars God ordered throughout the
Bible? If the Christians fail to remember, maybe I can make them recall
quoting these passages:
●
Moses commands Levites to kill all of those who are infidels and
worshiped the golden calf. This killing was practically the main
reason why the Levites held the priesthood (Exod. 32,25-29).
●
The capture of Hormah (Num. 21,1-3).
●
The conquest of Transjordan (Num 21, 21-35).
●
God commands the killing of the Midianites (Num. 25,16-18; 31,112), I wish to point out that also God commands the slaughtering
of women (Num 31, 13-24)
●
The capture of Jericho (Josh. 6).
●
The conquest of Ai (Josh. 7).
●
The Conquest of Canaan (Josh 10-12).
●
Saul's war against the Amalekites (1 Sam. 15,1-7)
●
Battle of Mount Gilboa (1 Sam. 31, 1-13)
●
Battle against the Aamonites (2 Sam. 10,4-19)
●
Continuous campaigns against the Philistines (2 Sam. 21,15-22)
●
Elijah orders the killing of ALL of Baal's prophets (1 Kings 18,
20-40)
These are just very few examples of what one might find in the Old
Testament. The New Testament, specially the book of Revelation is
Rosario 27
practically no different. So, how can anyone argue that Yahweh and
Allah are not one and the same God on these basis? Some people might
state that the God of the New Testament teaches love, but the Qur'an
does also in many lovely passages, and teaches love and compassion
also.
It can be argued, for instance, that the Qur'an does show a
continuous hatred toward Jews and Christians. But the Qur'an has more
quotes inviting them to convert to Islam, and it states that as a
result of no-conversion comes condemnation. Haven't Christians said
the same thing throughout history, and aren't some Christians even
still saying this today? In the Bible we can find passages of hatred of
Christians toward the Jews. The author of St. John's Gospel places in
Jesus' mouth words that practically cannot be more hateful toward the
Jews of the time. At one instance, Jesus states that the Jews have the
devil as their father (John 8,44). We can also find passages in the New
Testament which were post-pauline additions to his letters stating
how well-deserved is their punishment by God (1 Thes. 2,15-16),
obviously referring to the Emperor Titus' measures against the Jews
and the Temple. This has been practically one of the basis for the
Christians' hatred toward Jews throughout history. And, with some
reason, the Jews hated Christians throughout history . . . no big
mystery. I wish to add that the Catholic and Protestant churches
didn't hesitate at all to use violence to "convert" other people to its
own religion, or to reconquer lands, not only in mere self-defense. Of
Rosario 28
course, this is not true of all Christians. We can find St. Francis of
Assisi and others who saw how this was contrary to the Gospels. Still,
if violence of the God of Islam is the basis to distinguish Him from the
Judeo-Christian God, unfortunately this criterion seems to make them
more alike than different.
Of course, some Jews and Christians will argue that some of the
battles I have just mentioned were carried out in self-defense, or
that attacks were made against those who "deserved it" because those
"pagans" refused to believe in the one true God. But, I was careful to
exclude self-defense kind of wars. For example, many of those wars
were precisely to conquer lands (the Promised Land), and this
inevitably led to a lot of violence, others were not because of land or
anything, but just for power or other accidental reasons. Why then are
we Christians criticizing Moslems for the same thing?
So, (2) is now refuted. Let's go to (3). Allah is unknowable,
while the Judeo-Christian God can be known. Well, that's a big problem
for Judeo-Christians to hold. For example, in many ways in the Old
Testament God states very clearly that many aspects of Him cannot be
known by anyone. At least in Judaism, God remains transcendent. In
Christianity God became flesh. Is the Judaic God different from the
Christian God? It would be a countersense to say yes, because it is
assumed that the God of the Old Testament is the same one as the God in
the New Testament. Some Christians have gone as far as stating that
Jews worship the wrong God, but would this be consistent with the
Rosario 29
Bible? I don't think so. Why then use this as a justification to say
that Islam worships a different God, just because he doesn't have a
Son, or it is not a personal God, etc. Many Jews believe this way also.
So here we haven't refuted (3) only, we have refuted also (4) and (5).
They all suffer from the same implicit premises.
V.
This is the final section in which I discuss why I believe that
the God of Judeo-Christianity it is the same God of the Moslems.
First of all, Allah, the God of the Moslems, attributes to
himself practically the creation of Adam and Eve (Qur'an 7,18/1924/25), He talks about Cain and Abel (Qur'an 5,30/27-34/31), about
Abraham (Qur'an 2,118-134; 6,74-84.162; 7,71-74.115; among many
other passages), Isaac (Qur'an 2,127-134; 6,34; 11,74; 19,50;21,72;
37,99-112), Jacob (Qur'an 2,127-134; 6,84; 11,74; 19,50; 21,27; 37,
99-112). It attributes to Himself the liberation of the Israelites by
Moses (2,48-68,81; 4,152, 5,23; 6,84-91; etc.), among many other
prophets (Qur'an 4,161). So, at least concerning the Jews there is an
allegation that the Jewish God and the Muslim God are one and the same.
Obviously some things about the facts may differ.. but the allegation
that the Qur'an is making is that Allah was the one who created the
world, who instructed Adam and Eve not to eat the forbidden fruit, who
condemned the serpent, who condemned Cain for killing Abel, who made
the promises to Abraham, who was the God of Isaac and Jacob (Israel),
Rosario 30
who freed the Jews from Egypt's slavery. If all of this is correct,
then what it is evident is that Yahweh and Allah are one and the same
God, at least in the Muslim religion.
Now, about the Christian God, he affirms its relation to Mary,
and its relation to Jesus, and even calls Jesus the Word (Logos) of
God. However, it accuses Christians of overreacting concerning Jesus,
since Jesus was a prophet, he was not God himself. They also deny that
Jesus died on the Cross (Qur'an 4, 155.156-156/157), probably as the
result of the influence of ancient docetic doctrines.
As far as we have seen. The thing is that there is no doubt about
which "Jesus" Muslims are talking about, there is no problem with the
IDENTITY of Jesus himself, the differences are about the facts of what
happened to Jesus.
Using Kripkean semantics of proper names, we see that the problem
is not ontological, we have no doubt about who is the Jesus, or the
Moses, or the Abraham that Muslims are talking about. The problem is
about what they did, about the facts themselves, and there seems to be
a disagreement between the three groups about this subject. So, the
problem is cognitive: how do I (or we) know who did what and why. If
this is true of all the proper names used in the Qur'an and the Bible,
then we return to the question of the identity of the Muslim God, and
without a doubt we are talking about the Judeo-Christian God also. The
disagreements between religions are cognitive: how do we know which
definite descriptions or properties of God are true of God? Some may
Rosario 31
turn
to
historical
aspects,
and
how
one
is
historically
or
archaeologically consistent with one or the other. But there are
questions about Jesus' divinity, what God said to Abraham, etc. in
which the answers go far beyond history or archeology. Each one will
allude
that
their
respective
texts
are
proof
enough,
but
epistemologically speaking they aren't. Most people believe in the
Bible or the Qur'an by faith, and faith itself by definition is not a
proof, it is something someone assumes to be true and which has no way
of being verified or confirmed in the sensible world.
In here I assure that the Judeo-Christian God and the Moslem God
are one and the same God. "Yahweh", "Allah", "Elohim", etc. are
nothing more but names with which we designate one entity. So, I think
that in the very few things I can agree with President Bush, even
though I'm very liberal, is that the Moslems and the Judeo-Christians
worship one and the same God.
One final note:
My intention is not here to bash Judaism nor Christianity, and in
fact the absorption of some pagan symbols and practices for me are not
defects in those religions, but a virtue. I think that in the case of
Christianity, it has been possible to be more effective spreading the
Gospel changing the meaning of old pagan symbols and customs. If
Christianity didn't do that, most probably most Christians wouldn't
have their Bibles today with them.
My message here is this: Before judging harshly other people's
Rosario 32
religion, first look into your own. Just because we use symbols of
goddesses in the images of the Virgin Mary doesn't mean that Catholics
venerate or worship mother goddesses. The same goes for Islam, just
because Muslims kept some pagan practices, that doesn't mean they
worship the moon god. They worship Allah, the same God Jews and
Christians worship, but under another name.
For the rest all I can say is that if we point to the sins of the
Muslims, let us Christians look at our actions also, and see if we have
a moral ground to denounce what they do without taking into account our
own sins of the past.
Sources
Alarcón, Rafael H. A la sombra de los Templarios. Barcelona: Ediciones
Martínez Roca, 1986.
- - -. La última Virgen negra del Temple. Barcelona: Ediciones
Martínez Roca, 1991.
Atienza, Juan G. La ruta sagrada. Barcelona: Robin Book, 1992.
Buckhardt, Jakob. The Age of Constantine the Great. 1949. Berkelay and
Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1983.
Castro Américo. La realidad histórica de España. 1954. México:
Editorial Porrúa, 1987.
Chadwick, H. The Early Church. Hammondsworth, 1978.
Cross, F. L. (ed.) The Oxford Dictionary of the Christian Church.
Oxford University Press, 1957.
Rosario 33
Crystal,
Ellie.
Mithraism.
2001.
November
6,2001.
<http://www.crystalinks.com/mithra.html>.
David, Rosalie. Ancient Egyptian Religion, Beliefs and Practices.
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1982.
Eusebius of Cesarea. The History of the Church. 1965. Baltimore,
Maryland: Penguin Books, 1967.
- - -. Life of Constantine. Paul Halsall (ed.). Fordham University
Center for Medieval Studies: Internet Medieval Sourcebook,
January
8,
2000.
August
18,
2001.
<http://www.fordham.edu/halsall/basis/vitaconstantine.html>.
Farvardyn.
Mithraism.
2001.
January
21,
2002.
<http://www.farvardyn.com/mithras.htm>.
Friedman, Richard Elliot. ¿Quién escribió la Biblia? Trans. Joseph M.
Apfelbaume. Barcelona: Ediciones Martínez Roca, 1989. Trans
from: Who Wrote the Bible?.
Gibbon, Edward. Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire. 7 vols. London:
1909.
Goodenough, E. R. Jewish Symbols in the Greco-Roman Period. vol XII.
NY, 1953
Halbsberghe, Gaston H. The Cult of Sol Invictus. Leiden: E. J. Brill,
1972.
Hill, Claire Ortiz. Rethinking Identity and Metaphysics: On the
Foundations of Analytic Philosophy. New Haven and London: Yale
Rosario 34
University Press, 1997.
Hill, Claire Ortiz and Gillermo E. Rosado Haddock. Husserl or Frege?
Meaning, Objectivity and Mathematics. US: Open Court, 2000.
Imperatoris Theodosiani Codex. George Mason Univesity. September 15,
2001.
<http://www.gmu.edu/departments/fld/CLASSICS/theod.html>.
Kee, Alistair. Constantine vs. Christ. London: SCM Press, 1982.
Kripke, Saul. Naming and Necessity. 1972. Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1980.
Mithraism.
May
14,
1998.
December
3,
2001.
<http://www.mithraism.erudition.net>.
The New Jerusalem Bible. NY; London; Toronto; Sydney; Auckland:
Doubleday, 1990.
Pagan Religions. The Mystery of Jesus Pages. November 28, 2003.
<http://www.askwhy.co.uk/awmob/awpagan/pag240RELOtherSaviour
s.html>.
Plato. Dialogues. 2 vols. NY: Random House, 1937.
Secco Ellauri, Oscar and Pedro Daniel Baridon. Historia universal Roma. 1941. Buenos Aires: Kapelusz, 1991.
Sellers, Jane B. The Death of Gods Ancient Egypt. London: Penguin
Books, 1992.
Tollinchi, Estéban. La metamorfosis de Roma: espacios, figuras y
símbolos. Río Piedras: Editorial Universidad de Puerto Rico,
1998.
Rosario 35
© Copyright 2004, Pedro Rosario Barbosa
This
essay
is
available
under
the
Creative
Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 2.0.
Commons
License:
You are free to copy,
distribute, display and perform the work, under the following
conditions: (1) You must give the original author credit; (2) You may
not use this work for commercial purposes; (3) You may not alter,
transform or build upon this work. For any reuse or distribution, you
must make clear to others the license terms of this work. Any of these
conditions can be waived if you get permission from the author. Your
fair use and other rights are in no way affected by these dispositions.
A copy of the legal code of this license is included at the end of the
essay.
Rosario 36
Creative Commons
Legal Code
Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 2.0
CREATIVE COMMONS CORPORATION IS NOT A LAW FIRM AND DOES NOT PROVIDE
LEGAL SERVICES. DISTRIBUTION OF THIS LICENSE DOES NOT CREATE AN
ATTORNEY-CLIENT RELATIONSHIP. CREATIVE COMMONS PROVIDES THIS
INFORMATION ON AN "AS-IS" BASIS. CREATIVE COMMONS MAKES NO WARRANTIES
REGARDING THE INFORMATION PROVIDED, AND DISCLAIMS LIABILITY FOR
DAMAGES RESULTING FROM ITS USE.
License
THE WORK (AS DEFINED BELOW) IS PROVIDED UNDER THE TERMS OF THIS
CREATIVE COMMONS PUBLIC LICENSE ("CCPL" OR "LICENSE"). THE WORK IS
PROTECTED BY COPYRIGHT AND/OR OTHER APPLICABLE LAW. ANY USE OF THE
WORK OTHER THAN AS AUTHORIZED UNDER THIS LICENSE OR COPYRIGHT LAW IS
PROHIBITED.
BY EXERCISING ANY RIGHTS TO THE WORK PROVIDED HERE, YOU ACCEPT AND
AGREE TO BE BOUND BY THE TERMS OF THIS LICENSE. THE LICENSOR GRANTS YOU
THE RIGHTS CONTAINED HERE IN CONSIDERATION OF YOUR ACCEPTANCE OF SUCH
TERMS AND CONDITIONS.
License
1.
Definitions
a.
b.
"Collective Work" means a work, such as a periodical issue,
anthology or encyclopedia, in which the Work in its
entirety in unmodified form, along with a number of other
contributions, constituting separate and independent
works in themselves, are assembled into a collective whole.
A work that constitutes a Collective Work will not be
considered a Derivative Work (as defined below) for the
purposes of this License.
"Derivative Work" means a work based upon the Work or upon
the Work and other pre-existing works, such as a
translation,
musical
arrangement,
dramatization,
fictionalization,
motion
picture
version,
sound
recording, art reproduction, abridgment, condensation, or
any other form in which the Work may be recast, transformed,
or adapted, except that a work that constitutes a
Collective Work will not be considered a Derivative Work
for the purpose of this License. For the avoidance of doubt,
where the Work is a musical composition or sound recording,
Rosario 37
c.
d.
e.
f.
the synchronization of the Work in timed-relation with a
moving image ("synching") will be considered a Derivative
Work for the purpose of this License.
"Licensor" means the individual or entity that offers the
Work under the terms of this License.
"Original Author" means the individual or entity who
created the Work.
"Work" means the copyrightable work of authorship offered
under the terms of this License.
"You" means an individual or entity exercising rights under
this License who has not previously violated the terms of
this License with respect to the Work, or who has received
express permission from the Licensor to exercise rights
under this License despite a previous violation.
2.
Fair Use Rights. Nothing in this license is intended to reduce,
limit, or restrict any rights arising from fair use, first sale or
other limitations on the exclusive rights of the copyright owner under
copyright law or other applicable laws.
3.
License Grant. Subject to the terms and conditions of this
License, Licensor hereby grants You a worldwide, royalty-free, nonexclusive, perpetual (for the duration of the applicable copyright)
license to exercise the rights in the Work as stated below:
a.
b.
to reproduce the Work, to incorporate the Work into one or
more Collective Works, and to reproduce the Work as
incorporated in the Collective Works;
to distribute copies or phonorecords of, display publicly,
perform publicly, and perform publicly by means of a
digital audio transmission the Work including as
incorporated in Collective Works;
The above rights may be exercised in all media and formats whether now
known or hereafter devised. The above rights include the right to make
such modifications as are technically necessary to exercise the
rights in other media and formats, but otherwise you have no rights to
make Derivative Works. All rights not expressly granted by Licensor
are hereby reserved, including but not limited to the rights set forth
in Sections 4(d) and 4(e).
4.
Restrictions.The license granted in Section 3 above is expressly
made subject to and limited by the following restrictions:
a.
You may distribute, publicly display, publicly perform, or
publicly digitally perform the Work only under the terms of
this License, and You must include a copy of, or the Uniform
Resource Identifier for, this License with every copy or
phonorecord of the Work You distribute, publicly display,
publicly perform, or publicly digitally perform. You may
Rosario 38
b.
c.
d.
not offer or impose any terms on the Work that alter or
restrict the terms of this License or the recipients'
exercise of the rights granted hereunder. You may not
sublicense the Work. You must keep intact all notices that
refer to this License and to the disclaimer of warranties.
You may not distribute, publicly display, publicly
perform, or publicly digitally perform the Work with any
technological measures that control access or use of the
Work in a manner inconsistent with the terms of this License
Agreement. The above applies to the Work as incorporated in
a Collective Work, but this does not require the Collective
Work apart from the Work itself to be made subject to the
terms of this License. If You create a Collective Work, upon
notice from any Licensor You must, to the extent
practicable, remove from the Collective Work any reference
to such Licensor or the Original Author, as requested.
You may not exercise any of the rights granted to You in
Section 3 above in any manner that is primarily intended for
or directed toward commercial advantage or private
monetary compensation. The exchange of the Work for other
copyrighted works by means of digital file-sharing or
otherwise shall not be considered to be intended for or
directed toward commercial advantage or private monetary
compensation, provided there is no payment of any monetary
compensation in connection with the exchange of
copyrighted works.
If you distribute, publicly display, publicly perform, or
publicly digitally perform the Work, You must keep intact
all copyright notices for the Work and give the Original
Author credit reasonable to the medium or means You are
utilizing by conveying the name (or pseudonym if
applicable) of the Original Author if supplied; the title
of the Work if supplied; and to the extent reasonably
practicable, the Uniform Resource Identifier, if any, that
Licensor specifies to be associated with the Work, unless
such URI does not refer to the copyright notice or licensing
information for the Work. Such credit may be implemented in
any reasonable manner; provided, however, that in the case
of a Collective Work, at a minimum such credit will appear
where any other comparable authorship credit appears and in
a manner at least as prominent as such other comparable
authorship credit.
For the avoidance of doubt, where the Work is a musical
composition:
i.
Performance Royalties Under Blanket Licenses.
Licensor reserves the exclusive right to collect,
Rosario 39
whether individually or via a performance rights
society (e.g. ASCAP, BMI, SESAC), royalties for the
public performance or public digital performance
(e.g. webcast) of the Work if that performance is
primarily intended for or directed toward commercial
advantage or private monetary compensation.
ii.
e.
Mechanical Rights and Statutory Royalties. Licensor
reserves the exclusive right to collect, whether
individually or via a music rights agency or
designated agent (e.g. Harry Fox Agency), royalties
for any phonorecord You create from the Work ("cover
version") and distribute, subject to the compulsory
license created by 17 USC Section 115 of the US
Copyright Act (or
the equivalent in other
jurisdictions), if Your distribution of such cover
version is primarily intended for or directed toward
commercial
advantage
or
private
monetary
compensation.
Webcasting Rights and Statutory Royalties. For the
avoidance of doubt, where the Work is a sound recording,
Licensor reserves the exclusive right to collect, whether
individually or via a performance-rights society (e.g.
SoundExchange), royalties for the public digital
performance (e.g. webcast) of the Work, subject to the
compulsory license created by 17 USC Section 114 of the US
Copyright Act (or the equivalent in other jurisdictions),
if Your public digital performance is primarily intended
for or directed toward commercial advantage or private
monetary compensation.
5. Representations, Warranties and Disclaimer.
UNLESS OTHERWISE MUTUALLY AGREED BY THE PARTIES IN WRITING,
LICENSOR OFFERS THE WORK AS-IS AND MAKES NO REPRESENTATIONS OR
WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND CONCERNING THE WORK, EXPRESS, IMPLIED,
STATUTORY OR OTHERWISE, INCLUDING, WITHOUT LIMITATION, WARRANTIES
OF TITLE, MERCHANTIBILITY, FITNESS FOR A PARTICULAR PURPOSE,
NONINFRINGEMENT, OR THE ABSENCE OF LATENT OR OTHER DEFECTS,
ACCURACY, OR THE PRESENCE OF ABSENCE OF ERRORS, WHETHER OR NOT
DISCOVERABLE. SOME JURISDICTIONS DO NOT ALLOW THE EXCLUSION OF
IMPLIED WARRANTIES, SO SUCH EXCLUSION MAY NOT APPLY TO YOU.
6.
Limitation on Liability. EXCEPT TO THE EXTENT REQUIRED BY
APPLICABLE LAW, IN NO EVENT WILL LICENSOR BE LIABLE TO YOU ON ANY LEGAL
THEORY FOR ANY SPECIAL, INCIDENTAL, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
EXEMPLARY DAMAGES ARISING OUT OF THIS LICENSE OR THE USE OF THE WORK,
EVEN IF LICENSOR HAS BEEN ADVISED OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGES.
7.
Termination
Rosario 40
a.
b.
This License and the rights granted hereunder will
terminate automatically upon any breach by You of the terms
of this License. Individuals or entities who have received
Collective Works from You under this License, however, will
not have their licenses terminated provided such
individuals or entities remain in full compliance with
those licenses. Sections 1, 2, 5, 6, 7, and 8 will survive
any termination of this License.
Subject to the above terms and conditions, the license
granted here is perpetual (for the duration of the
applicable copyright in the Work). Notwithstanding the
above, Licensor reserves the right to release the Work
under different license terms or to stop distributing the
Work at any time; provided, however that any such election
will not serve to withdraw this License (or any other
license that has been, or is required to be, granted under
the terms of this License), and this License will continue
in full force and effect unless terminated as stated above.
8. Miscellaneous
a.
b.
c.
d.
Each time You distribute or publicly digitally perform the
Work or a Collective Work, the Licensor offers to the
recipient a license to the Work on the same terms and
conditions as the license granted to You under this
License.
If any provision of this License is invalid or
unenforceable under applicable law, it shall not affect the
validity or enforceability of the remainder of the terms of
this License, and without further action by the parties to
this agreement, such provision shall be reformed to the
minimum extent necessary to make such provision valid and
enforceable.
No term or provision of this License shall be deemed waived
and no breach consented to unless such waiver or consent
shall be in writing and signed by the party to be charged
with such waiver or consent.
This License constitutes the entire agreement between the
parties with respect to the Work licensed here. There are no
understandings, agreements or representations with
respect to the Work not specified here. Licensor shall not
be bound by any additional provisions that may appear in any
communication from You. This License may not be modified
without the mutual written agreement of the Licensor and
You.
Creative Commons is not a party to this License, and makes no warranty
whatsoever in connection with the Work. Creative Commons will not be
liable to You or any party on any legal theory for any damages
Rosario 41
whatsoever, including without limitation any general, special,
incidental or consequential damages arising in connection to this
license. Notwithstanding the foregoing two (2) sentences, if Creative
Commons has expressly identified itself as the Licensor hereunder, it
shall have all rights and obligations of Licensor.
Except for the limited purpose of indicating to the public that the
Work is licensed under the CCPL, neither party will use the trademark
"Creative Commons" or any related trademark or logo of Creative
Commons without the prior written consent of Creative Commons. Any
permitted use will be in compliance with Creative Commons' thencurrent trademark usage guidelines, as may be published on its website
or otherwise made available upon request from time to time.
Creative Commons may be contacted at http://creativecommons.org/.