55 U. Fl. L. Rev. 1 (2003)
Transcription
55 U. Fl. L. Rev. 1 (2003)
Florida Law Review Founded 1948 Formerly University of Florida Law Review VOLUME 55 JANUARY 2003 NUMBER 1 CLUSTER I LATCRITICAL ENCOUNTERS WITH CULTURE, IN NORTHSOUTH FRAMEWORKS Pedro A. Malavet* I. INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 II. THE CONFERENCE CONTEXTS: THE ARTICULATION AND THEORETICAL PERFORMANCE OF LATCRIT . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6 A. The Opening Roundtable . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6 B. Plenary Panel I: Implications of Indigenous Activism . . . . 18 C. The TWAIL/NAIL Concurrent Panel . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24 III. CONTINUING LATCRITICAL ENCOUNTERS WITH CULTURE IN COMPARATIVE NORTH-SOUTH FRAMEWORKS . . . . . . . . . . . 31 IV. CONCLUSION: BIENVENIDAS/OS, AMIGAS/OS AMERICANAS/OS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38 I. INTRODUCTION Latina/o Critical Race Theory (LatCrit) is an academic enterprise that owes much to prior theoretical schools,1 but it is most especially and * Associate Professor, The University of Florida Fredric G. Levin College of Law; J.D., LL.M., Georgetown. I am grateful to the Levin College of Law for allowing me to use a Summer Research Grant and part of a sabbatical to work on this project. I would like to thank Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Guadalupe T. Luna, Ediberto Román, and Kevin R. Johnson for their helpful comments on an earlier draft of this Essay. 1. “LatCrit theory follows and in some ways stems from the historical experience with Critical Legal Studies, Feminist Legal Theory, Critical Race Theory, Critical Race Feminism and Queer Legal Theory.” Francisco Valdés, Poised at the Cusp: LatCrit Theory, Outsider Jurisprudence and Latina/o Self-Empowerment, 2 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 1, 4-5 (1997). I would 1 2 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 clearly a re/orientation of Critical Race Theory (CRT).2 LatCrit is outsider jurisprudence,3 often postmodern4 in style, and mostly, though not exclusively, pursued by academics of color who seek to center the Latina/o experience5 in the legal mainstream of the United States.6 The principal add that Critical Legal Studies (CLS) was the heir to American Legal Realism and the unwitting catalyst for Critical Race Theory (CRT). See generally AMERICAN LEGAL REALISM (William W. Fisher, III et al. eds., 1993); MARK KELMAN, A GUIDE TO CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES (1987) (providing background of CLS); Symposium: Critical Legal Studies: Roll Over Beethoven, 36 STAN. L. REV. 1 (1984) (describing the movement and presenting examples of its scholarship); Cornel West, Foreword, in CRITICAL RACE THEORY: THE KEY WRITINGS THAT FORMED THE MOVEMENT xi, xxii-xxvii (Kimberlé Crenshaw et al. eds., 1995) [hereinafter THE KEY WRITINGS] (outlining background on initial relationship and eventual split of CLS and CRT). 2. While definitions are often dangerous, if not impossible, see Francisco Valdes, Under Construction: LatCrit Consciousness, Community, and Theory, 85 CAL. L. REV. 1087, 1089 n.2 (1997), reprinted in 10 LA RAZA L.J. 1, 3 n.2 (1998) (noting that defining LatCrit is difficult), I like this one: Critical Race Theory is the most exciting development in contemporary legal studies. This comprehensive movement in thought and life—created primarily, though not exclusively, by progressive intellectuals of color—compels us to confront critically the most explosive issue in American civilization: the historical centrality and complicity of law in upholding white supremacy (and concomitant hierarchies of gender, class, and sexual orientation). THE KEY WRITINGS supra note 1, at xi; see also Angela P. Harris, Foreword: The Jurisprudence of Reconstruction, 82 CAL. L. REV. 741 (1994) (providing introduction to a symposium devoted entirely and specifically to CRT). 3. See Mari J. Matsuda, Legal Storytelling: Public Response to Racist Speech: Considering the Victim’s Story, 87 MICH. L. REV. 2320, 2323-24 (1989) (discussing how “outsider jurisprudence” is scholarship produced by and focused on outsider perspectives, communities, and interests, i.e., going beyond the dominant group). Other forms of outsider jurisprudence include Asian-American Legal Theory, Critical Race Feminism, Feminist Legal Theory, and Queer Legal Theory. 4. Although I find his treatment of postmodernism overly harsh, there are some helpful descriptions in David West’s essay, The Contribution of Continental Philosophy, in A COMPANION TO CONTEMPORARY POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 39 (Robert E. Goodin & Phillip Pettit eds., 1993): Postmodernism proposes a last desperate leap from the fateful complex of Western history. Anti-humanism, with its critique of the subject and genealogical history, has shaken the pillars of Western political thought. Heidegger’s “dismantling” of metaphysics and Derrida’s deconstruction carry the corrosion of critique to the fundamental conceptual foundations of modernity. Id. at 64. West adds later in the essay: “Postmodernists seek to disrupt all forms of discourse, and particularly forms of political discourse, which might encourage the totalitarian suppression of diversity.” Id. at 65. 5. LatCrit has and will continue to have a fundamental intellectual link to CRT, but it represents a re/orientation of CRT to “center” outsider groups other than African Americans. The realization of the need for a separate space for this change in focus was not an easy process. While 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 3 products of the LatCrit enterprise, both oral and written, are mostly associated with the annual LatCrit conferences.7 This Symposium issue I am not suggesting that there is a monolithic CRT experience, or that the CRT workshop (the annual meeting of Race Crits) either represented the entire field of CRT, or that it lacked the capacity to grow, the dynamics of the workshop unfortunately appear to have generated a sense of exclusion(s). See Valdés, Poised at the Cusp, supra note 1, at 3 n.5 (noting that the CRT workshop in 1995 had about forty participants, only two of which were Latina/o, Trina Grillo and Frank Valdés); Comments of Sumi K. Cho, Panel: Multiplicities and Intersectionalities: Exploring LatCrit Diveristies: Essential Politics, 2 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 433, 454 n.44 (1997) (condemning the “ritualistic ‘violence’ against gay and lesbian race crits in recent years at the [CRT] summer workshop”); see also Stephanie L. Phillips, Mapping Intellectual/Political Foundations and Future Self Critical Directions: The Convergence of the Critical Race Theory Workshop with LatCrit Theory: A History, 53 U. MIAMI L. REV. 1247, 1249 n.4 (1999) (conceding, as a member of the original workshop organizing committee, that, despite best of intentions, the workshop “replicat[ed] troubling hierarchies . . . in particular, the privileging of African American experience and of heterosexuality”). See generally Phillips, supra (describing history of the CRT workshop; explaining its “invitation only” policy, and suggesting that the workshop and LatCrit Conference had similar memberships and intellectual goals, and that they could and should be coordinated). 6. Francisco Valdés, one of the founders of this new movement, explains: LatCrit theory is an infant discourse that responds primarily to the long historical presence and general sociolegal invisibility of Latinas/os in the lands now known as the United States. As with other traditionally subordinated communities within this country, the combination of longstanding occupancy and persistent marginality fueled an increasing sense of frustration among contemporary Latina/o legal scholars, some of whom already identified with Critical Race Theory (CRT) and participated in its gatherings. Like other genres of critical legal scholarship, LatCrit literature tends to reflect the conditions of its production as well as the conditioning of its early and vocal adherents. Francisco Valdés, Theorizing “OutCrit” Theories: Comparative Antisubordination Experience and Subordination Vision as Jurisprudential Method, (citations omitted), available at http://personal.law.miami.edu/~fvaldes/latcrit/overview.html (last visited Oct. 12, 2002). 7. Naturally, this Symposium issue is the most recent installment in LatCrit scholarly discourse, Symposium, LatCrit VI: Latinas/os and the Americas: Centering North-South Frameworks in LatCrit Theory, 55 FLA. L. REV. 1 (2003); but there has been a symposium issue for each of the annual LatCrit conferences. See generally Symposium, LatCrit V: Class in LatCrit: Theory and Praxis in a World of Economic Inequality, 78 DENV. U. L. REV. 467 (2001); Symposium, LatCrit IV: Rotating Centers, Expanding Frontiers: LatCrit Theory and Marginal Intersections, 23 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 751 (2000); Symposium, LatCrit III: Comparative Latinas/os: Identity, Law and Policy in LatCrit Theory, 53 U. MIAMI L. REV. 575 (1999); Symposium, LatCrit II: Difference, Solidarity and Law: Building Latina/o Communities Through LatCrit Theory, 19 CHICANO-LATINO L. REV. 1 (1998); Symposium, LatCrit I: LatCrit Theory: Naming and Launching a New Discourse of Critical Legal Scholarship, 2 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 1 (1997); Colloquium, LatCrit: Representing Latina/o Communities: Critical Race Theory and Practice, 9 LA RAZA L.J. 1 (1996); Colloquium, International Law, Human Rights and LatCrit Theory, 28 U. MIAMI INTERAM. L. REV. 177 (1996); see also Joint Symposium, LatCrit Theory: Latinas/os and the Law, 85 CAL. L. REV. 1087 (1997), reprinted in 10 LA RAZA L.J. 1 (1998) (noting that this was a “standalone” symposium, not directly connected to one of the LatCrit conferences). 4 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 partly memorializes the Sixth Annual LatCrit Conference, which represented an important milestone because it reached out and empowered the voices of the Southern part of our hemisphere.8 The essays in the cluster addressed in this Essay are the product of this cooperative process of giving voice to the native9 scholars from the Southern Americas, while seeking to expand our voice within the North American academy. The initial challenge in writing this cluster introduction was to articulate the thread of unity in the themes covered by the authors and the 8. The Substantive Program Outline described it as follows: Saludos! This year, the LatCrit Annual Conference will take the long foreshadowed step of affirmatively and self-consciously exploring the links that bind Latina/o Communities in the United States to their homeland societies, cultures and economies and how the impact of such globalization informs an articulation of LatCrit theory and discourse. As many LatCritters have repeatedly commented, the articulation of an inclusive vision of intra-and intergroup justice has for too long been paralyzed by the conflation of citizenship and geography in popular discourse and legal theory. These links help to explain why Latinas/os in the United States constitute transnational groups and communities, typically retaining strong material connections to, and cultural identifications with, their homelands’ traditions, issues, concerns, hopes and aspirations. These links, while oftentimes noted in prior LatCrit programs and texts, have yet to be explicitly thematized and explored in a programmatic way; this year, we take up this pending challenge collectively. The LatCrit VI planning committee has made an affirmative effort to structure the program to center specifically inter-American approaches to social and legal issues. Our hope is to undertake some comparative critical studies of “domestic” issues and their counterparts throughout the Americas, using one or more of the following five lenses or categories which have been employed in prior years’ conference themes: (1) Latina/o pan-ethnicity and multiracialism, including intraLatina/o issues of sameness and difference as well as non-Hispanic Latinas/os, including mestizaje, Indianess and blackness in Latina/o communities and societies; (2) identity—religion, culture, gender, sexuality and heteropatriarchy; (3) immigrations, migrations, and citizenships; (4) coalition, democracy, and community; (5) class and economic equity, including trade, labor, and environment. The basic concept is to encourage critical inquiry of these five broad areas in ways that illuminate and elucidate the North-South character of Latina/o transnationality. Underscoring the inter/national nature of LatCrit theory to date, this year’s conference planners generally hope to turn the gains and insights of the past five years toward a better collective understanding of the diverse hemisphere we share: the Americas. Sixth Annual LatCrit Conference, Substantive Program Outline, at http://personal.law.miami.edu/ ~fvaldes/latcrit/lcvidocs/lcvisubstantiveprogram.html (visited June 6, 2002) [hereinafter Substantive Program Outline]. 9. “Native” is used here to refer to people who are autochthonous to the Americas, not as a reference to Native American, “Indian,” or indigenous identity. See also infra note 58 and accompanying text. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 5 panels in which they initially presented their ideas during the Sixth Annual LatCrit Conference. After all, they were located in different geographic and, seemingly, different intellectual sites within the conference.10 But this cluster of essays, individually and collectively, effectively captures the overall theme of LatCrit VI: Latinas/os and the Americas: Centering North-South Frameworks in LatCrit Theory.11 Specifically, every one of the essays in this section focuses on Latin American legal systems and cultures.12 The methodology may be theoretical or practical, philosophical or sociological, legal or interdisciplinary, but all these works address the challenges posed by the legal systems and cultures that co-exist within the nations of Latin America in 21st century academic legal discourse. This Essay will first discuss how the essays fit within or challenge the themes of the specific roundtable, plenary, or workshop in which they were presented. It will then locate the cluster within the present and the future of LatCrit Theory generally, and LatCritical praxis13 in particular. 10. Hugo Rojas and Mauricio García-Villegas participated in the Opening Roundtable: Encountering Latin America: Exploring the Parameters and Encountering Latin America: Exploring the Parameters and Relevance of LatCrit Theory In and Through a Regional Rotation. Susan Scafidi participated in Plenary Panel One: Implications of Indigenous Activism. Jorge Esquirol and Michael Wallace Gordon participated in the third concurrent panel, titled TWAIL/NAIL: Latin American Legal Theory. 11. See Substantive Program Outline, supra note 8. 12. “Culture” is used here to describe complex social constructs. The negative forms of culture include the essentialized development of dominant ones, and the imposition of negative stereotypes by the dominant culture on social outsiders. See infra notes 104-06 and accompanying text. The positive forms of culture include communitarian, empowering self constructs. See infra notes 107-09 and accompanying text. 13. “LatCritical” describes the LatCrit approach to legal theory. Francisco Valdés has written about praxis in the LatCrit enterprise: Following from the recognition that all legal scholarship is political is that LatCrit scholars must conceive of ourselves as activists both within and outside our institutions and professions. Time and again, the authors urge that praxis must be integral to LatCrit projects because it ensures both the grounding and potency of the theory. Praxis provides a framework for organizing our professional time, energy and activities in holistic ways. Praxis, in short, can help cohere our roles as teachers, scholars and activists. The proactive embrace of praxis as organic in all areas of our professional lives thus emerges as elemental to the initial conception of LatCrit theory. Praxis therefore serves as the second LatCrit guidepost. Valdés, supra note 1, at 53. 6 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 II. THE CONFERENCE CONTEXTS: THE ARTICULATION AND THEORETICAL PERFORMANCE OF LATCRIT This part of the Essay will address each presentation, the specific conference context(s) in which it was delivered, and how the essays produced by the presenters develop these ideas. A. The Opening Roundtable Hugo Rojas and Mauricio García-Villegas participated in our opening roundtable discussion: Encountering Latin America: Exploring the Parameters and Relevance of LatCrit Theory In and Through a Regional Rotation.14 14. This was described in the Substantive Program Outline as follows: The focus of this opening discussion marks a new trajectory for the LatCrit practice of rotating centers, by challenging inherited categories that would otherwise map the world’s regions in racial terms. In this inherited framework, the world is divided into racialized regions: Latin America is Hispanic, Africa is Black, Europe and North America are White, and Asia is (no surprise) Asian. By centering Latin America in LatCrit theory, this kick-off discussion seeks to challenge these essentialist constructions. Latin America, like the United States, and indeed, all regions of the world, is multiethnic, multilingual, multicultural, and multiracial. It is inhabited by individuals and groups marked by differences of gender, class, national origin, sexual orientation, and religion, as well as by the historical articulations of white supremacy, colonialism, and the expansion of international capitalist processes and social formations. Against this background, the opening plenary explores how focusing LatCrit antiessentialist, antisubordination perspectives on the particularities of Latin American realities might inspire new theoretical insights and enable new coalitional possibilities among subordinated groups, both within Latin America and across other regions. How, for example, do questions of group identity and the role of law in the production of inter-group justice map across the realities of ongoing civil war, politicized military institutions, dictatorial cultural traditions, an interconnected church and state, resurgent indigenous nations, imported jurisprudence and civil law systems? How are these realities reflected in the structure and substance of Latin American legal institutions and norms and, with what implications for the process of social transformation? Put differently, what does LatCrit theory have to offer Latin American legal scholars and social activists, and conversely what do they offer LatCrit theory? This opening plenary seeks to engage these important questions by convoking a diverse group of legal scholars, educators, and social scientists from Colombia, Cuba, Mexico and the United States to share their critical perspectives on the realities confronting Latin America and their relevance to Latinas/os and other outsider groups within the United States. Substantive Program Outline, supra note 8. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 7 Mauricio García-Villegas, a Colombian-born and trained academic, engages LatCrit in a critique of what he describes as the Legal Consciousness Studies Movement,15 a subset of Law and Society.16 Professor García-Villegas uses a linguistic style and structure that to the United States observer might appear to be related to university disciplines other than law. However, his writing must be contextualized in the Colombian system of legal education, which is more analogous to our undergraduate system of college education in methodology, if not necessarily in content. Moreover, Colombia, like most Civil Law systems, approaches legal education as a more interdisciplinary endeavor than the traditional United States law school curriculum.17 Professor García-Villegas aims high, and thus purposely chooses language that might be inaccessible in any other context. Reaching the proper balance between the critical exploration of language and its abuse—its use in hurtful and negative ways—is often a challenge, and critical race scholars have often been accused of language abuse.18 While the attacks on CRT all too often are essentialist19 attempts to silence 15. He explains that [s]tudies of legal consciousness bring together, with variants, essential parts of both the “Law and Society” and the critical traditions. From Law & Society they have taken the idea that empirical research is essential to make sense of the way that law functions in the society. From the critical tradition they have adopted the aspiration that sociolegal studies should serve not only to describe how law operates in society but also and above all to contribute to the transformation of society and the defense of the excluded. Mauricio García-Villegas, Symbolic Power Without Symbolic Violence?, 55 FLA. L. REV. 157 (2003). 16. The “Law and Society Association, founded in 1964, is a group of scholars from many fields and countries, interested in the place of law in social, political, economic and cultural life.” The Law and Society home page, at http://www.lawandsociety.org (last visited Oct. 12, 2002). For a critical analysis of the Law and Society Movement, see Trubek, infra note 82. 17. See generally Richard J. Wilson, The New Legal Education in North and South America, 25 STAN. J. INT’L LAW 375 (1989) (containing a dated but still largely accurate description of legal education in South American countries, including Colombia); THE CIVIL LAW TRADITION: EUROPE, LATIN AMERICA AND EAST ASIA 841-91 ( John Henry Merryman et al. eds., 1994) (providing a brief introduction to legal education in the civil law world generally) [hereinafter CIVIL LAW TRADITION]. 18. Compare Dennis W. Arrow, Pomobabble: Postmodern Newspeak and Constitutional “Meaning” for the Uninitiated, 96 MICH. L. REV. 461 (1997), with Ronald J. Krotoszynski, Jr., Legal Scholarship at the Crossroads: On Farce, Tragedy, and Redemption, 77 TEX. L. REV. 321 (1998). 19. “Essentialism adopts the view that all members of a group are alike and share a common ‘essence.’” Cho, supra note 5, at 433 n.1. As it is used herein: The concept of essentialism suggests that there is one legitimate, genuine 8 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 different voices,20 the intentional misuse of language simply for the sake of showing off or of being exclusionary can be hegemonic21 and, more simply, ineffective.22 But, in the LatCrit context, deconstructionist postmodern analysis, such as that undertaken by García-Villegas, clearly demands a careful approach to language which allows scholars properly to explore the hidden complexities of its subjects.23 The LatCrit use of universal voice that speaks for all members of a group, thus assuming a monolithic experience for all within the particular group—be it women, blacks, latinas/os, Asians, etc. Feminists of color have been at the forefront of rejecting essentialist approaches because they effect erasures of the multidimensional nature of identities and also collapse multiple differences into a singular homogenized experience. Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Constructing LatCrit Theory: Diversity, Commonality, and Identity: LatIndia II—Latinas/os, Natives, And Mestizajes—A LatCrit Navigation of Nuevos Mundos, Nuevas Fronteras and Nuevas Teorías, 33 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 851, 862 n.26 (2000) (citations omitted); see also FEMINIST LEGAL THEORY: FOUNDATIONS 335 (D. Kelly Weisberg ed., 1993) (discussing gender essentialism); Angela P. Harris, Race and Essentialism in Feminist Legal Theory, 42 STAN. L. REV. 581, 588 (1990) (discussing gender and racial essentialism). 20. See Pedro A. Malavet, Performing LatCrit: Literature and the Arts as Antisubordination Praxis: LatCrit Theory and Cultural Production: The Confessions of an Accidental Crit, 33 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 1293, 1297-1306 (2000) (discussing the debate over the use of narrative in legal scholarship). 21. For example, abuse of language can be nothing more than a self-indulgent attempt to develop a secret speech that sets your little clique apart, both in private and in public. In her critique of the excesses of literary criticism, Barbara Christian explains the real dangers of such language abuse: For I feel that the new emphasis on literary critical theory is as hegemonic as the world which it attacks. I see the language it creates as one which mystifies rather than clarifies our condition, making it possible for a few people who know that particular language to control the critical scene—that language surfaced, interestingly enough, just when the literature of peoples of color, of black women, of Latin Americans, of Africans began to move to “the center.” Barbara Christian, The Race for the Theory, in MAKING FACE, MAKING SOUL: HACIENDO CARAS: CREATIVE AND CRITICAL P ERSPECTIVES BY FEMINISTS OF COLOR 335, 338 (Gloria Anzaldúa ed., 1990). 22. Here I refer to the forced use of overly complicated language simply for the sake of making an exaggerated pseudo-intellectual display, rather than to write effective scholarship. Barbara Christian again articulates the problem well: “And as a student of literature, I am appalled by the sheer ugliness of the language, its lack of clarity, its unnecessarily complicated sentence constructions, its lack of pleasurableness, its alienating quality. It is the kind of writing for which composition teachers would give a freshman a resounding F.” Id. at 339. 23. For example, LatCrit scholarship challenges the traditional civil rights discourse in law by thoroughly exploring the weaknesses of the Black/White binary paradigm of race. See Ian F. Haney López, Race, Ethnicity, Erasure: The Salience of Race to LatCrit Theory, 85 CAL. L. REV. 1143 (1997), reprinted in 10 LA RAZA L.J. 57 (1998); Juan F. Perea, The Black/White Binary Paradigm of Race: The “Normal Science” of American Racial Thought, 85 CAL. L. REV. 1213 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 9 language in legal scholarship is thus exciting, intellectually stimulating, and effective.24 García-Villegas acknowledges that his work is abstract to a level that his “critique is not suitable to all authors interested in legal consciousness.”25 However, in typical LatCrit form, García-Villegas introduces a provocative theoretical paradigm that will enrich LatCrit Theory. Using the language of postmodernism, Professor García-Villigas explains how the Legal Consciousness Movement fails to adequately account for the effects of structural power hegemonies within a particular legal culture, thus undermining its practical effectiveness as a viable theoretical school. Legal Consciousness Theory might be described as Legal Realism from a different frame of reference: that of the client or party, rather than that of the judge or attorney. The “client,” moreover, is usually a marginalized person, an “other.”26 (1997), reprinted in 10 LA RAZA L.J. 127 (1998) [hereinafter Perea, The Black/White Binary Paradigm of Race]; Juan F. Perea, Ethnicity and the Constitution: Beyond the Black and White Binary Constitution, 36 WM. & MARY L. REV. 571 (1995). This challenge to the binary can be traced back to the very first LatCrit colloquium in Puerto Rico. See generally Colloquium, Representing Latina/o Communities: Critical Race Theory and Practice, 9 LA RAZA L.J. 1 (1996); see also Robert S. Chang, The Nativist’s Dream of Return, 9 LA RAZA L.J. 55 (1996) (stating that Asian-Americans do not fit within the “comfortable binary” of the Black/White paradigm of race); Rachel F. Moran, Neither Black Nor White, 2 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 61 (1997) (finding that Latinas/os are not adequately represented in American civil rights debate because they do not fit within the paradigm); Neil Gotanda, “Other Non-Whites” in American Legal History: A Review of Justice at War, 85 COLUM. L. REV. 1186, 1188 (1985) (book review) (explaining that “foreignness” and the construction/imposition thereof establishes many U.S. citizens, especially Asian-Americans and Latinas/os, as a permanent underclass); Deborah Ramirez, Forging A Latino Identity, 9 LA RAZA L.J. 61, 63 (1996) (explaining a personal experience that required her to challenge the paradigm in order to properly assist a local Latina/o community); Francisco Valdés, Latina/o Ethnicities, Critical Race Theory, and Post-Identity Politics in Postmodern Legal Culture: From Practices to Possibilities, 9 LA RAZA L.J. 1, 20-24 (1996) (discussing various authors’ challenges to the Black/White binary). 24. Of course, a demanding use of language is essential to critical scholarship. More generally, mastering language is an essential skill for a lawyer or academic, and challenging the language skills of any audience can have strong pedagogical effects. But teachers and scholars should be offended by the notion that simple language is a sign of simple-mindedness. For example, popular cultural narratives may sometimes be spoken in plain and simple language and are still perfectly able to transmit complex ideas that constitute antisubordination praxis. (I do not mean to imply that popular culture is always “plain and simple” in language. In fact, popular culture is incredibly complex and textured. However, on occasion, the popular artist uses plain and simple language to make very complex messages accessible to everyone in their community.) Additionally, the capacity to present complex concepts in language that make them accessible to students and to persons outside our field takes a great deal of talent. Moreover, making our work accessible to uninitiated audiences is part of our educational mission and is essential to LatCrit praxis. 25. García-Villegas, supra note 15, at 159. 26. In general, as used herein, “other” and being “othered” mean to be socially constructed 10 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 García-Villegas provides an important warning about shifting the focus of law too much towards the micro-level, and about the methodology of symbolism. He explains that “the absence of a macrosociological lens lessens the capacity to ‘see’ and analyze genuinely efficacious emancipatory options for the excluded.”27 This, García-Villegas explains, is the result of practical contradictions created by attempts within the Legal Consciousness Movement to maintain theoretical coherence in its use of the symbolic. This “exigency of theoretical coherence,”28 prevents the Legal Consciousness theorists from leading us into effective legal reform. The solution, García-Villegas suggests, is to develop a proper balance between the “micro/macro terrain” presented by any complex functioning society and nation. The symbolic theoretical vision of any critical theory that aspires to effective praxis must also be able to produce “a theory of the symbolic strategy as a political instrument, whether it be of domination or of social emancipation.”29 García-Villegas’ work fits within previous comparative legal discourse about the differences between hortatory (exhortative) and prescriptive (compulsory or coercive) legal systems.30 Additionally, Critical Race theorists long ago identified the tension, and sometimes the disjunction, between theory and praxis.31 as “not normative.” See, e.g., Cathy J. Cohen, Straight Gay Politics: The Limits of an Ethnic Model of Inclusion, in ETHNICITY AND GROUP RIGHTS 572, 580 (Will Kymlicka & Ian Shapiro eds., 1997). Much of the material exclusion experienced by marginal groups is based on, or justified by, ideological processes that define these groups as “other.” Thus, marginalization occurs, in part, when some observable characteristic or distinguishing behavior shared by a group of individuals is systematically used within the larger society to signal the inferior and subordinate status of the group. Id. (citing ERVING GOFFMAN, STIGMA: NOTES ON THE MANAGEMENT OF SPOILED IDENTITY (1963)). However, I will also use the term “other” as a relative term. See infra note 111 and accompanying text. 27. García-Villegas, supra note 15, at 187. 28. Id. at 188-89. 29. Id. at 189. 30. See, e.g., MARY ANN GLENDON, ABORTION AND DIVORCE IN WESTERN LAW 5-8 (1987) (indicating that classical Greek vision in which “the aim of law is to lead the citizens toward virtue, to make them noble and wise,” comparing it to the U.S. and England where laws take the forms of “prescriptions” intended to rule actual conduct rather than to persuade and educate subjects into compliance therewith). 31. See Harris, supra note 2, at 751 (noting that there is a tension between the deconstructionist theoretical bent of CRT that attacks entrenched power hegemonies, and the design of an affirmative program of racial “emancipation” which she labels “reconstruction”); Harlon L. Dalton, The Clouded Prism, 22 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 435, 436-37 (1987) (discussing the split between CLS practitioners and theorists); Robert L. Hayman, Jr., The Color of Tradition: Critical Race Theory and Postmodern Constitutional Traditionalism, 30 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 57, 69-70 (1995) (arguing postmodern theory cannot produce a reform project); Patricia J. Williams, 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 11 Accordingly, LatCrit Theory has always tried to ensure that its theoretical work is capable of contributing to praxis.32 Therefore, García-Villegas’ work fits within the LatCrit enterprise, which seeks to empower the marginalized through effective praxis, while maintaining a coherent theoretical paradigm. Hugo Rojas challenges the traditional construct of Chilean society as representing a single mixed race and a homogeneous national culture.33 LatCrit has studied a similar racialized demand for assimilation into a normative,34 homogeneous White culture in the United States.35 LatCrit Alchemical Notes: Reconstructing Ideals From Deconstructed Rights, 22 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 401, 404-06 (1987) (noting CLS’ rejection of rights makes reform difficult). 32. As discussed above, praxis is one of the essential guideposts of LatCrit Theory. See Valdés, supra note 1 and accompanying text; see also Adrien Katherine Wing, Critical Race Feminism and International Human Rights, 28 U. MIAMI INTER-AM. L. REV. 337, 341 (1996) (“[W]hile [Critical Race Feminism] is concerned with theoretical frameworks, it is very much centered on praxis and attempts to identify ways to empower women through law and other disciplines.”). 33. Hugo Rojas, Stop Cultural Exclusions (in Chile)!: Reflections on the Principle of Multiculturalism, 55 FLA. L. REV. 121 (2003). 34. Normative means the dominant societal paradigm, that is, what is considered “normal” in a given sociological context. See Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Borders (En)gendered: Normativities, Latinas and a LatCrit Paradigm, 72 N.Y.U. L. REV. 882, 891 (1997) (noting that “knowledge is socially constructed,” therefore, the “normative paradigm’s dominance” defines “normal”). 35. In the United States there is a legal and social mythology of two racial groups, Blacks and Whites, which LatCrit has labeled the “Black/White binary paradigm of race.” See supra note 23. Within the binary, Whiteness, and the privilege associated with it, implies full assimilation into the U.S. body politic, and Blackness implies exclusion from the normative society. Moran, supra note 23, at 69 (arguing “Latinos receive the message that they are supposed to adapt to American life as earlier generations of White ethnic immigrants did, [or] instead they will remain an isolated and unassimilable population like Blacks”). In addition to fighting against the White supremacist nature of the paradigm, LatCrit scholarship has studied and debated why Latinas/os are denied full citizenship, despite our legal classification as White. See, e.g., Ian F. Haney Lopez, supra note 23 (examining U.S. legal and social racial categorizing, concluding that Latinas/os are legally classified as White, but socially racialized as “other”); Ian F. Haney Lopez, Retaining Race: LatCrit Theory and Mexican American Identity in Hernandez v. Texas, 2 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 279 (1997) [hereinafter Lopez, Retaining Race] (responding to Professor Perea, arguing that Latinas/os are denied full citizenship despite legal Whiteness because they are socially constructed as belonging to an inferior non-White race); George A. Martinez, The Legal Construction of Race: MexicanAmericans and Whiteness, 2 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 321, 326-29 (1997) (noting that U.S. courts recognized Mexicans as White for purposes of the naturalization laws—which only allowed Whites to become U.S. citizens; census also classified Mexican Americans as White); Juan Perea, Five Axioms in Search of Equality, 2 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 231 (1997) (arguing that Latinas/os are excluded from full citizenship because of “ethnicity”) [hereinafter Perea, Five Axioms]; Perea, The Black/White Binary Paradigm of Race, supra note 23 (arguing that Latinas/os are “racialized,” leading to our marginalization). See also Kevin R. Johnson, “Melting Pot” or “Ring of Fire”?: Assimilation and the Mexican-American Experience, 85 CAL. L. REV. 1259 (1997), reprinted in 10 LA RAZA L.J. 173 (1998) (positing that the U.S. myth of assimilation acts as a “ring of fire” that 12 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 seeks to empower the “other” within all societies and challenges the notions of an assimilationist culture that imposes a homogenized normativity. Rojas does just that in the very specific Chilean context by explaining the need for multicultural citizenship generally. But he is specially concerned with the marginalization of indigenous peoples within Chilean culture, and the accompanying deprivation of political rights under the Chilean Constitution.36 Rojas once again brings into LatCrit focus the distinction between imposed racialized37 constructs of cultural citizenship38 and legal/political citizenship.39 must burn away “non-U.S.” cultural identity, and resistance thereto makes Latinas/os unassimilable); Rachael E. Moran, What If Latinos Really Mattered in the Public Policy Debate?, 85 CAL. L. REV. 1315, 1344 (1997), reprinted in 10 LA RAZA L.J. 229 (1998) (“Latinos are forcing America to revisit conventional wisdom about immigration and civil rights by reconsidering popular assumptions about citizenship and identity as well as processes of assimilation and pluralism.”). 36. In the United States, critical theorists, including LatCritters, have written about the need for a multicultural, constitutional definition of citizenship. See, e.g., Mari J. Matsuda, Voices of America: Accent, Antidiscrimination Law, and a Jurisprudence for the Last Reconstruction, 100 YALE L.J. 1329, 1401-03 (1991) (taking the position that “radical pluralism,” entitlement to cultural independence, is constitutionally justified, and perhaps even required by the U.S. Constitution); Enid Trucios-Haynes, The Role of Transnational Identity and Migration, 28 U. MIAMI INTER-AM. L. REV. 293 (1996) (arguing that “transnational identity” leads to “transnational multiculturalism” within the U.S. borderlands, which deserves legal recognition and protection). See also Kenneth L. Karst, Citizenship, Race and Marginality, 30 WM. & MARY L. REV. 1 (1988); Kenneth L. Karst, Paths to Belonging: The Constitution and Cultural Identity, 64 N.C. L. REV. 303 (1986); Gerald Torres, Local Knowledge, Local Color: Critical Legal Studies and the Law of Race Relations, 25 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 1043 (1988). 37. LatCrit scholarship has noted that the social and legal construction of Latinas/os in the United States is fundamentally a racialized process. For example, Ian F. Haney Lopez explains that while race and ethnicity are not essentially different; on the contrary . . . race and ethnicity are largely the same. [But they] should not be conflated because these two forms of identity have been deployed in fundamentally different ways. The attribution of a distinct ethnic identity has often served to indicate cultural distance from Anglo-Saxon norms. Left unstated but implicit, however, is a claim of transcendental, biological similarity: ethnics and Anglo-Saxons are both White. The attribution of a distinct racial identity, on the other hand, has served to indicate distance not only from Anglo-Saxon norms, but also from Whiteness. Racial minorities are thus twice removed from normalcy, across a gap that is not only cultural, but supposedly innate. López, Retaining Race, supra note 35, at 283 (footnotes omitted). 38. LatCrit scholars have paid special attention to the social construction of “foreignness,” with its inherent denial of “citizenship,” that is often imposed on Latinas/os and other groups—such as Asian-Americans—in the United States, despite our legal citizenship. See Neil Gotanda, AsianAmerican Rights and the “Miss Saigon Syndrome,” in ASIAN AMERICANS AND THE SUPREME COURT: A DOCUMENTARY HISTORY 1087, 1096 (Hyung-Chan Kim ed., 1992). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 13 Rojas identifies independence, secession, and regional autonomy, while remaining within a single federal government, as alternatives to empower indigenous peoples.40 These are certainly sensible choices when a [In] the United States, if a person is racially identified as African American or white, that person is presumed to be legally a U.S. citizen and socially an American. . . . [But] these presumptions are not present for Asian Americans, Latinos, Arab Americans, and other non-Black racial minorities. Rather, there is the opposite presumption that these people are foreigners; or, if they are U.S. citizens, then their racial identity includes a foreign component. Id.; see also Juan Perea, Los Olvidados: On the Making of Invisible People, 70 N.Y.U. L. REV. 965, 966 (stating “Latino invisibility” is defined as “relative lack of positive public identity and legitimacy” caused by our foreign ethnicity). Language has also been an important theme in LatCrit scholarship. See, e.g., Steven W. Bender, Direct Democracy and Distrust: The Relationship Between Language Law Rhetoric and the Language Vigilantism Experience, 2 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 145, 146 (1997) (discussing “language vigilantism,” how “individuals speaking a language other than English [mostly Latinas/os] have increasingly come under attack [from normative Anglos] in their schools, their workplaces, and even in their homes and places of leisure”); Juan F. Perea, Demography and Distrust: An Essay on American Languages, Cultural Pluralism, and Official English, 77 MINN. L. REV. 269, 350-73 (1992) (analyzing “official English” legal proposals);. 39. The distinction and disjunction between cultural and political citizenship has been a strong theme in CRT generally and LatCrit Theory in particular. See, e.g., Guadalupe T. Luna, Chicana/Chicano Land Tenure in the Agrarian Domain: On the Edge of a “Naked Knife,” 4 MICH. J. RACE & L. 39 (1998) (detailing how Mexican-Americans in the Southwest had their land taken away in spite of their legal citizenship—and their property rights); Pedro A. Malavet, Puerto Rico: Cultural Nation, American Colony, 6 MICH. J. RACE & L. 1 (2000) (describing Puerto Ricans as an identifiable culture that lacks a legal citizenship, and how they are deprived of real political power because of their legally second-class U.S. citizenship); Robert Westley, Many Billions Gone: Is it Time to Reconsider the Case for Black Reparations?, 40 B.C. L. REV. 429 (1998) (advocating reparations to bring African-Americans to full political citizenship in the U.S.); Eric K. Yamamoto, Racial Reparations: Japanese American Redress and African American Claims, 40 B.C. L. REV. 477 (1998) (containing a critical review of reparations for the internment of U.S. citizens of Japanese descent during the Second World War). The alien represents a body of rules passed by Congress and reinforced by popular culture. It is society, often through the law, which defines who is an alien, an institutionalized “other,” and who is not. It is society through Congress and the courts that determines which rights to afford aliens. Kevin R. Johnson, The Social and Legal Construction of Nonpersons, 28 U. MIAMI INTER-AM. L. REV. 263, 268 (1996). See generally Symposium, Citizenship and its Discontents: Centering the Immigrant in the Inter/National Imagination, 76 OR. L. REV. 207 (1997); Ibrahim J. Gassama et al., Foreword, 76 OR. L. REV. 207, 209 (1997) (“The papers in this Symposium investigate the aporectic relations among the nation-state, liberal understandings of citizenship, and problematic constructions of race and ethnicity as they are applied to immigrants.”). 40. Every one of these alternatives falls under the rubric of autonomous regimes under 14 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 combination of an identifiable indigenous group and a definable territory can be found.41 However, it is not a general solution to the problems of a multicultural modern state in which co-existence within the same territory is a practical necessity. Such a factual situation requires a different theoretical paradigm.42 Rojas’ deployment of the work of Will Kymlicka must be viewed with some care. Kymlicka is a staunch defender of liberalism, and in fact favors the “toleration” model of the liberal state as a solution to the challenges of multiculturalism.43 This is a result of Kymlicka’s stance as a modern International Law. See generally Natsu Taylor Saito, Considering “Third Generation” International Human Rights Law in the United States, 28 U. MIAMI INTER-AM. L. REV. 387 (1996) (arguing that international human rights, such as the right to self-determination, can help to inform LatCrit Theory and to implement its praxis). 41. “All peoples have the right of self-determination. By virtue of that right they freely determine their political status and freely pursue their economic, social and cultural development.” International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, G.A. Res. 2200A, U.N. GAOR, 21st Sess., Annex Supp. No. 16, at 52, U.N. Doc. A/6316 art. 1 § 1 (1966) (entered into force Mar. 23, 1976); International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, G.A. Res. 2200A, U.N. GAOR, 21st Sess., Supp. No. 16, U.N. Doc. A/6316 art. 1 § 1 (1966) (entered into force Jan. 3, 1976). 42. Adeno Addis explains: As a general response to diversity in political units, however, separation seems as impractical as it is dangerous. It is impractical partly because not all groups that believe themselves to be marginalized and excluded from the social and political life of the polity live in a defined territorial unit. In such circumstances, secession will not be a viable answer to the problem of exclusion and discrimination. Indeed, the notion of separation under these conditions is likely to lead to a process of ethnic cleansing. It is also true that not all groups that have grievances against a dominant majority want to secede, even if that were practically possible. They simply wish to participate equally and fully in the life of the political community. Adeno Addis, On Human Diversity and the Limits of Toleration, in ETHNICITY AND GROUP RIGHTS 112, 113 (Will Kymlicka & Ian Shapiro eds.,1997) (emphasis added) (footnote omitted) [hereinafter ETHNICITY]. 43. Kymlicka presents important objections to the multicultural/communitarian critiques of liberal theory that challenge the critics to prove the shortcomings of liberalism or to admit that they are using liberal theory to construct a new paradigm for a more complicated world. Kymlicka, for example, would argue that recognition of community and culture is a process of the evolution of liberalism, rather than a competing paradigm that requires the rejection of liberalism. See WILL KYMLICKA, LIBERALISM, COMMUNITY, AND CULTURE (1989). “Considering the nature and value of cultural membership not only takes us down into the deepest reaches of a liberal theory of the self, but also outward to some of the most pressing questions of justice and injustice in the modern world.” Id. at 258; see also MICHAEL WALZER, ON TOLERATION 111-12 (1997). The centrifugal forces of culture and selfhood will correct one another only if the correction is planned . . . . [T]he political creed that defends the framework, supports the necessary forms of state action, and so sustains the modern regimes 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 15 liberal.44 However, it is important to emphasize that liberalism is not an inherently progressive political theory,45 it requires a multicultural lens to produce a form of citizenship that truly empowers cultural minorities.46 Rojas then properly uses the work of Jürguen Habermas, providing a coherent political theory that applies to resolve the problems of minority groups within the multicultural state.47 Habermas argues that it is possible to respect multiculturalism in a modern democratic society. Individual and group cultural differences can exist, and the State can thrive, if the citizens exercise what he calls “constitutional patriotism.” Under constitutional patriotism, individuals are free to develop their own personal or group culture48 as long as they share legal/political citizenship and a common of toleration—is social democracy. If multiculturalism today brings more trouble than hope, it does so in part because of the weakness of social democracy (in this country, left liberalism). But that is another, longer story. Id. 44. In his works, Kymlicka maps himself as a modern liberal scholar, a la Ronald Dworkin. KYMLICKA, supra note 43, at 10 (“[H]op[ing] to show how my Kymlicka’s arguments are related to the political morality of modern liberals from J.S. Mill through to Rawls and Dworkin”). See also RONALD DWORKIN, LAWS EMPIRE (1989); RONALD DWORKIN, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY (1986). 45. “[Liberalism] is not always a progressive doctrine, for many classical liberals are skeptical about the average human being’s ability to make useful advances in morality and culture, for instance.” Alan Ryan, Liberalism, in A COMPANION TO CONTEMPORARY POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 293 (Robert E. Goodin & Philip Pettit eds., 1993). 46. See generally Malavet, supra note 39, at 75-96 (describing the failure of liberal citizenship as a model that truly empowers minorities within the multicultural state, and articulating a reformed liberalism with a multicultural sensibility). 47. See Jürgen Habermas, Citizenship and National Identity: Some Reflections on the Future of Europe, in THEORIZING CITIZENSHIP 255 (Ronald Beiner ed., 1995). One’s own national tradition will . . . have to be appropriated in such a manner that it is related to and relativized by the vantage points of the other national cultures. It must be connected with the overlapping consensus of a common, supranationally shared political culture . . . . Particularist anchoring of this sort would in no way impair the universalist meaning of popular sovereignty and human rights. Id. at 264 (emphasis added). 48. “Culture” as used by Habermas does not mean the stereotypes that are often used by the normative society to discriminate against certain groups discussed above. Rather, Habermas refers to positive cultural self-constructs. See infra note 109 and accompanying text. 16 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 political culture.49 Rojas will surely apply this type of scholarship in further development of his own work. Accordingly, Rojas will benefit from the sophisticated critiques of liberalism and exposition of postmodern alternatives thereto that are common in LatCrit scholarship.50 Conversely, LatCrit will benefit from his development of these theoretical foundations, and from his discussion of the specific context of Chilean society, a matter that he begins in his essay, and which we can only hope he continues to develop within the LatCrit enterprise. Both García-Villegas and Rojas engaged the conference in precisely the type of discussion that the opening roundtable, the overall conference, and LatCrit jurisprudence intended to foster. They both “centered” their nations to our South (Colombia and Chile respectively) in LatCrit discourse. Moreover, both García-Villegas and Rojas challenged theoretical and social constructs of Latin American nations and their citizens as constituting a single, mixed, Latina/o “race.” One might argue that the construct of Latina/o as a racial category encompassing people of White, indigenous, and African heritage, misses the point that Latinas/os are not a race; rather, we are a cultural/ethnic group encompassing persons of many different races. To put it more simply, phenotypically or anthropologically, some Latinas/os are White, Black, Indigenous, Asian, Arab, something else, or of mixed heritage. On the other hand, many Latinas/os embrace the concept of a “sociedad o raza india, española y africana” (an Indian, Spanish, and African society or 49. See Habermas, supra note 47. [E]xamples of multicultural societies like . . . the United States demonstrate that a political culture in the seedbed of which constitutional principles are rooted by no means has to be based on all citizens sharing the same language or the same ethnic and cultural origins. Rather, the political culture must serve as the common denominator for a constitutional patriotism which simultaneously sharpens an awareness of the multiplicity and integrity of the different forms of life which coexist in a multicultural society. Id. at 264. 50. See generally Jean Stefancic, Latino and Latina Critical Theory: An Annotated Bibliography, 85 CAL. L. REV. 1509 (1997), reprinted in 10 LA RAZA L. J. 423 (1998) (critiquing liberalism is one of the basic themes of LatCrit Theory). See, e.g., Enrique R. Carrasco, Intersections Between LatCrit Theory and Law and Development Studies, 28 U. MIAMI INTER-AM. L. REV. 313 (1996) (critiquing neo-liberal development theory); Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol & Sharon Elizabeth Rush, Foreword: Culture, Nationhood, and the Human Rights Ideal, 33 U. MICH. J. L. REFORM 233, 246-51 (2000) (critiquing liberalism using international legal principles); Daria Roithmayr, Deconstructing the Distinction Between Bias and Merit, 85 CAL. L. REV. 1449 (1997), reprinted in 10 LA RAZA L. J. 363 (1998) (using critical theory to deconstruct the liberal myth of an incompatible merit/bias binary). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 17 race).51 But, of course, these shifting constructions of Latinidad (Latina/oness) only help to reinforce the LatCrit tenet that race is a social construct,52 and as such varies according to lens.53 The racialization of Latinas/os as a single-non-White race produces our marginalization within the United States borderlands. However, in the nations of Latin America the “single-mixed-race” construct enforces White Supremacy by denying the existence of socially constructed racial differences and enforced racial privilege(s). As Hugo Rojas points out, this reduces racial minorities, such as indigenous peoples, to invisibility, and thus leaves them powerless within the legal/political system. García-Villegas underscores the concept that critical theorists can only empower the diverse members of their societies by focusing both on the individual and on his/her legal/political/social location within the nation as a whole. These two essays balance each other quite well. García-Villegas wants to empower the marginalized “other,” but warns that this can best be accomplished within the national social and legal structure. Rojas begins to explore how liberalism, with a multicultural sensitivity, might provide true constitutional citizenship for Chilean indigenous peoples. Both authors fully capture the anti-essentialist nature of LatCrit Theory. In particular, García-Villegas focuses “LatCrit antiessentialist, antisubordination perspectives on the particularities of Latin American realities [that] might inspire new theoretical insights and enable new coalitional possibilities among subordinated groups, both within Latin America and across other regions.”54 This is precisely what the panel was intended to bring to the forefront of our conference. Rojas, likewise 51. This is a common image in Latin-American popular culture. See, e.g., LA SONORA PONCEÑA, DESCENDENCIA, BIRTHDAY PARTY (“Somos latinos, somos la esencia de Puerto Rico, quien me discute ese honor . . . Orgulloso de mi cantar, latina, yo siempre estoy, . . . Mezcla de español, africano y taino.” (emphasis added). Author’s translation: “We are Latinos, we are the essence of Puerto Rico, who argues/challenges this honor? . . . Proud of my singing, Latin, I always am, . . . A Mixture of Spaniard, African, and Taino.”). 52. “Race is social, in the sense that the groups commonly recognized as racially distinct have their genesis in cultural practices of differentiation rather than in genetics, which plays no role in racial fabrication other than contributing the morphological differences onto which the myths of racial identity are inscribed.” Lopez, Retaining Race, supra note 35, at 281; see also L. LUCA CAVALLI-SFORZA ET AL., THE HISTORY AND GEOGRAPHY OF HUMAN GENES (1994) (discussing the lack of biological basis for racial categories); MICHAEL OMI & HOWARD WINANT, RACIAL FORMATION IN THE UNITED STATES: FROM THE 1960S TO THE 1980S (1986); Ian F. Haney Lopez, The Social Construction of Race: Some Observations on Illusion, Fabrication, and Choice, 29 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 1 (1994). 53. See Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Indivisible Identities: Culture Clashes, Confused Constructs and Reality Checks, 2 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 199, 207 (1997) (suggesting imposed social constructs are dynamic and tend to change based on the racialized, gendered frame of reference of the actor). 54. See Substantive Program Outline, supra note 8. 18 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 working within the context of the panel, challenges the single-race construct of Latin America, to remind us all of the strong but marginalized indigenous element in the Americas. B. Plenary Panel I: Implications of Indigenous Activism Susan Scafidi, who participated in Plenary Panel One:55 Implications of Indigenous Activism,56 argues that the legal construction of indigenous 55. Generally, the plenaries were intended to: [R]eflect a delicate balance between the need to revisit issues of fundamental and continuing importance to our multiply diverse communities and the need to chart new directions, center particular struggles and integrate new issues and perspectives into evolving LatCrit social justice agendas. Both are crucially important in deepening the theoretical insights and expanding the solidaristic commitments already achieved through the collective discourse and communitybuilding efforts of prior LatCrit conferences. Id. 56. The plenary was described in the Substantive Program Outline as follows: In our theorizing about identity, U.S. Latinos/as have focused on naming and analyzing the superordinant practices of White culture and examining relations among ourselves . . . as well as our relations to and with other subordinated groups within the U.S. . . . As LatCrits, we are just now exploring the political and economic benefits of a pan-ethnic Latina/o identity while learning of the complex experiences that both connect and divide the different populations that fit within the Latina/o umbrella. The rest of the continent is witnessing seismic changes in the struggles associated with ethnic identities. . . . At least eight Latin American nations—Bolivia, Colombia, Ecuador, Guatemala, Mexico, Nicaragua, Peru, and Paraguay—now recognize the ethnic pluralism of their societies by including specific constitutional provisions granting varying degrees of autonomy to the indigenous groups within the national borders . . . . This identity, asserted by indigenous peoples, is as distinct from the mestizo/a majority as it is from the criollo/a minority (i.e., the White European elites) . . . . What does this hemispheric dialogue and struggle mean for U.S. Latinas/os? How is the Latina/o struggle for voice, vote, and power in the U.S. understood south of our borders? What does this struggle mean for LatCrit theory and practices? What can we learn when such concepts as mestizaje and hybridity are challenged and then revived by Latin American theorists . . . ? Latin American theorists, . . . are drawing on concepts such as performativity, mimicry, and national myths to deepen the understanding of the construction of national identities in Latin America. LatCrit theory can be strengthened and broadened by exploring its links to this new theorizing about the identities that define the various groups in Latinas’/os’ countries of origin and that also define ethnicity as a concept and by extension give the “Lat” in LatCrit more specific meanings. Id. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 19 peoples in the former Spanish Americas, mostly influenced by Juan de Solórzano Pereira,57 is flawed because the European-Spanish legal culture in which the original rules developed was markedly different from the colonial Spanish-Indigenous culture imposed in the Americas. Moreover, the difference between the more “homogeneous” Spanish culture in the Iberian peninsula and the more racially and culturally diverse SpanishIndigenous culture(s) in the Americas, is one of the reasons for the continued subordination of the Latin-American indigenous peoples. Scafidi correctly diagnoses the result: the legal construction of “indians”58 in the Americas that was imposed by the Spanish conquistadores (conquerors) was flawed and has left the indigenous peoples as a permanent underclass in the new nations of the Americas. Scafidi argues that the subordination of the indigenous peoples is the product of a failure to adapt Spanish laws, which were developed in the context of a relatively homogeneous Spain in the 17th century, to the more complex social realities of the Americas. Scafidi’s analysis suggests that the development of the Leyes de las Indias (the Laws of the Indies, the Spanish Americas) was a legal blunder—a failed comparative experiment—rather than an affirmative attempt legally to control the indigenous peoples. However, rather than failing properly to analogize, perhaps Solórzano achieved exactly what he set out to do: to justify, through law, the colonial occupation of the Americas and the subordination of the indigenous peoples to the Spanish colonizers. The indigenous peoples are still subordinated because one mostly White, Spanish-speaking, Christian postcolonial dominant group has replaced a White, Spanish-speaking, Christian colonial dominant group. Now, like then, the “White” (male) elite also benefits from continuing the subordination of the indigenous peoples. Therefore, the reason for the continued subordination of the indigenous peoples is not some fundamental failure of analogy or comparative methodology to bridge the cultural gap between Spanish and colonial cultures.59 The real problem is that Spanish Leyes de las Indias 57. Susan Scafidi, Old Law in the New World: Solórzano and the Analogical Construction of Legal Identity, 55 FLA. L. REV. 191 (2003) (indicating that her “essay examines the efforts of seventeenth-century Spanish jurist Juan de Solórzano Pereira to clarify Native American legal identity within the Spanish social order through the use of legal analogy”). 58. Both generally and in law, Spanish conquistadores referred to the new colonies of the Americas as the “Indias” (Indies) and to the indigenous inhabitants thereof as Indios (Indians). See IV DICCIONARIO ENCICLOPÉDICO DE DERECHO USUAL 389 (1998) (explaining that use of Indias was due to Columbus’ error in mistaking the islands of the Caribbean and the Eastern coast of the Americas with the Eastern coast of the Indian subcontinent); see also id. at 392 (noting that “Indio” refers to indigenous peoples of what the Spanish called the Indies). 59. Most comparativists accept the necessity of “bridging the cultural gap” when doing any transnational work. See, e.g., Roger J. Goebel, Professional Qualification and Educational Requirements for Law Practice in a Foreign Country: Bridging the Cultural Gap, 63 TUL. L. REV. 20 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 intentionally replicate the essentialized normativities of 13th century60 Spanish society: moros (Moors, Muslims), Jews, and cristianos (Christians).61 By focusing on the 17th century Spanish society in which Solórzano performed his duties, Scafidi perhaps misses the real analogy intended by Solórzano, between 13th century moros (Muslims) and Jews in Spain on the one hand, and 17th century indias/os in the Americas, on the other. Re/viewed in this manner, the conquistadores merely duplicated the social hierarchies they had at “home” in Spain in their newly 443, 444-54, 508 (1989). Accordingly, the “cultural, social, political and economic systems” in which the law must be applied are essential when instructing a client on the “relevant considerations” of international legal transactions. Id. This matter is discussed further below in Part III, infra notes 99-102 and accompanying text. 60. The 13th century might make a better historical frame of reference because this is the period during which the Partidas, the most important “national” code in Spain and its colonies, were produced, starting in 1265. It is also important to note that this is a period of the Reconquista, the process through which the Catholic kingdoms defeated and expelled Muslims and Jews from the Iberian Peninsula. II DICCIONARIO DE LA LENGUA ESPAÑOLA 1743 (2001) (defining “Reconquista,” in upper case, as generally referring to “the recovery of the Spanish territory invaded by the Muslims . . . the culmination of which was the taking of Granada in 1492” (author’s translation)). 61. The Código de las Siete Partidas has been described as “a work generally known as a medieval legal treatise and called ‘the first extensive compilation of western secular law since Justinian.’” MARILYN STONE, MARRIAGE AND FRIENDSHIP IN MEDIEVAL SPAIN 1 (1990) (citing Charles Sumner Lobingier, Introduction, in ALFONSO EL SABIO, LAS SIETE PARTIDAS vi (Samuel Parsons Scott trans., 1931)). They were drafted under the patronage and probably the supervision of King Alfonso X, El Sabio, of Spain during the thirteenth century. Id. at 1-22. Some experts believe that the Partidas did not become effective law until the 1348 Ordenamiento de Alcalá, see, e.g., RENÉ DAVID & JOHN E. C. BRIERLEY, MAJOR LEGAL SYSTEMS IN THE WORLD TODAY: AN INTRODUCTION TO THE COMPARATIVE STUDY OF LAW 57 (3d ed. 1985), but others hold that they “were being used extensively as a book of reference by royal judges before 1348.” STONE, supra at 10 (citing EVELYN S. PROCTER, ALFONSO X OF CASTILLE, PATRON OF LITERATURE AND LEARNING 51 (Reprint 1980)). Francisco Martínez Marina, author of a prominent essay about the history of Spanish legislation, claimed that the large number of Partida manuscripts with marginal notes in existence during the eras of Alfonso X, Sancho IV, Fernando IV and Alfonso XI suggests that the provisions of the Siete Partidas were discussed in universities and debated by lawyers and judges prior to 1348. Id. (citing Francisco Martínez Marina, Ensayo histórico-crítico sobre la legislación y principales cuerpos legales de los reinos de Leon y Castilla especialmente sobre el código de las Siete Partidas de don Alfonso el Sabio, in OBRAS ESCOGIDAS DE DON FRANCISCO MARTÍNEZ MARINA 194 (1966)). There is strong historical evidence that the Spanish nobility objected to the Partidas because they appeared to limit the nobility’s power and importance, both during the reign of Alfonso X, and that of Alfonso XI two generations later. Id. at 17. The noblemen appeared to regard some of the objectionable rules as the product of non-Spanish thinking imported from the Paris and Bologna schools. Id. This may account for the debate regarding their effective date. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 21 conquered territories, it is just that the haves are essentially the same, and the have-nots are of slightly different shades and religions. Nevertheless, regardless of the historical and social frame of reference, Scafidi engages us in an important discussion about the legal construction of the indigenous peoples of the Americas that was imposed by the Spanish conquistadores.62 The “noble savages” Columbus encountered in the Caribbean have collectively become known as the Taino people.63 The “cannibals” that Columbus warned of were the island Caribs, who posed the most consistent indigenous military challenge to Spanish control of the Caribbean.64 To these, of course, one must add the large indigenous cultures of the continental Americas who were conquered by the Spanish because, unlike the Taino and Caribs, these cultures were not totally exterminated during the process of conquest. They are thus the principle objects of the laws that Scafidi studies. She deftly points out how the Spanish political culture used juridical concepts that had a long history within the Christian Spanish legal order and, by analogy, developed a system to apply to the newly conquered indigenous peoples of the Americas.65 This system is based on the natural inferiority of the colonized indigenous peoples relative to the White Spanish conquistadores. However, it also reflects a paternalistic charity towards these wretched wards66 that is comparable to the medieval Catholic Canon Law and its ratione personarum jurisdiction over “wretched persons” and its “protection” of Jews.67 The seemingly 62. Scafidi, supra note 57. 63. Id. at 198. 64. “Columbus encountered Tainos throughout most of the West Indies. . . . A second peripheral group, the Island-Caribs, lived on the islands from Guadeloupe southward, separating the Tainos from South America.” IRVING ROUSE, THE TAINOS: RISE & DECLINE OF THE PEOPLE WHO GREETED COLUMBUS 5 (1992). The Caribs and the Spanish fought a type of “guerrilla” war during the early 16th Century, with many raids on Puerto Rican soil, and military response from the Spanish. FEDERICO RIBES TOVAR, A CHRONOLOGICAL HISTORY OF PUERTO RICO 30-99 (1973). By the end of the century, the Caribs were no longer raiding. Id. The Taino on the other hand, were enslaved in the encomiendas, and by the 18th century, were almost completely gone. See infra note 68. 65. Scafidi, supra note 57, at 198. 66. Id. 67. In Catholic Canon Law, the church law and ecclesiastical court jurisdiction was divided into jurisdiction over certain kinds of persons (ratione personarum, “by reason of persons”) and jurisdiction over certain types of conduct or relationships (ratione materiae, “by reason of subject matter”). The church claimed “personal jurisdiction” over: (1) clergy and members of their households; (2) students; (3) crusaders; (4) personae miserabiles (“wretched persons”), including poor people, widows, and orphans; (5) Jews, in cases against Christians; and (6) travelers, including merchants and sailors, when necessary for their peace and safety. 22 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 “charitable” language of the laws masked a horrible reality.68 Like all social and legal constructs that are based on the alleged “natural” superiority of one group over another, the Spanish colonial model has left the personas nativas/os americanas/os (persons native to the Americas) as a permanent underclass within the new nations of this hemisphere. Scafidi indicates that Critical Legal theorists attack analogical approaches to law69 because they are “incapable of yielding just results in a heterogeneous society.”70 She focuses on the legal construction of Harold J. Berman, Law and Revolution: The Reformation of the Western Legal Tradition, in CIVIL LAW TRADITION, supra note 17, at 298. 68. For example, the encomienda (to entrust) system was supposedly a benign process of putting the indigenous persons of Puerto Rico to work and to educate them into Christianity. In reality, it was brutal slavery. On December 20, 1503, Queen Isabella of Spain issued a Royal order instructing the Governor of Puerto Rico to “compel and force the said Indians to associate with the Christians of the island and to work on their buildings, and to gather and mine the gold and other metals, and to till the fields and produce food for the Christian inhabitants and dwellers of the said island.” THE PUERTO RICANS: A DOCUMENTARY HISTORY 18-19 (Kal Wagenheim & Olga Jiménez de Wagenheim eds., 1994). The edict itself identified the problem that it was trying to resolve as follows: “We are informed that because of the excessive liberty enjoyed by said Indians they avoid contact . . . with the Spaniards to such an extent that they will not even work for wages, but wander about idle, and cannot be had by the Christians to convert to the Holy Catholic Faith . . . .” Id. While the Tainos were ostensibly considered “free” men under the edict, the reality was that they were enslaved. Id. at 19-22. By the 18th Century most of the Tainos native to Puerto Rico were almost completely gone. PEDRO MALAVET-VEGA, HISTORIA DE LA CANCIÓN POPULAR EN PUERTO RICO (1493-1898), at 96 (1992) (noting that in 1509, 60,000 Tainos were given into the encomiendas; only 14,636 were left by 1515; 1,537 were left by 1530; by 1778, only 2,302 Tainos were counted as living mostly in the central mountains of Puerto Rico). 69. For example, Trina Grillo and Stephanie Wildman have described “the dangers inherent in . . . analogizing sex discrimination to race discrimination.” See, e.g., Trina Grillo & Stephanie M. Wildman, Obscuring the Importance of Race: The Implication of Making Comparisons Between Racism and Sexism (or Other–isms), in CRITICAL RACE THEORY: THE CUTTING EDGE 566 (Richard Delgado ed., 1995). Grillo and Wildman explain that comparing sexism to racism perpetuates patterns of racial domination by marginalizing and obscuring the different roles that race plays in the lives of people of color and of whites. The comparison minimizes the impact of racism, rendering it an insignificant phenomenon—one of a laundry list of–isms or oppressions that society must suffer. Id. 70. Scafidi, supra note 57, at 202. This claim raises complex questions. As Grillo and Wildman explain: Given the problems that analogies create and perpetuate, should we ever use them? Analogies can be helpful. They are part of legal discourse, as well as common conversation. Consciousness raising may be the beginning of knowledge. Starting with ourselves is important, and analogies may enable us to understand 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 23 subordination for the indigenous peoples of the Americas.71 Scafidi’s project fits within the LatCrit enterprise and its goal of helping to empower the marginalized. Like Scafidi, LatCrit seeks to identify the continuing subordination of entire groups and classes in any country, but most especially in the real or imagined Latina/o “homelands”72 at the start the oppression of another in a way we could not without making the comparison. Instead of drawing false inferences of similarities from analogies, it is important for whites to talk about white supremacy, rather than leaving all the work for people of color. Questions remain regarding whether analogies to race can be used, particularly in legal argument, without reinforcing racism/white supremacy. There are no simple answers to this thorny problem. We will have to continue to struggle with it, and accept that our progress will be slow and tentative. Grillo & Wildman, supra note 69, at 570. 71. As discussed above, Scafidi argues that 17th century Spanish society was relatively heterogeneous and that it was therefore an error to apply the laws of that heterogeneous society to the multicultural Americas. Nevertheless, while the Spanish society of the 17th century was indeed socially constructed as heterogeneous, after a long process of Reconquista and internal persecution, the laws that Scafidi critiques had their origin in the diverse Iberian peninsula of the 13th century. Therefore, I believe that she has chosen an example that does not support the claim that analogy cannot produce adequate or progressive results in a heterogeneous society. Rather, Spanish colonial laws are an example of the replication of privilege to marginalize the “other,” with essentially the same privileged group (White, Christians), and a different “other” (indigenous peoples). See Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, The Latindia and Mestizajes: Of Cultures, Conquests, and LatCritical Feminism, 3 J. GENDER RACE & JUST. 63, 77 (1999). [In] New Spain (Mexico) where the Spanish were a white minority, Spanish attitudes toward the Native population paralleled the Spanish xenophobic expulsion of Jews and Arabs from Spain . . . . [T]he Spaniards in Mexico (as well as in other places) established a complex system of racial categorization that included the prohibition of public office holders from having a “taint” of Indian, Arabic, or Jewish blood. Id. (footnotes omitted). 72. The term “homeland” is loaded with positive and essentialized meanings, depending on lens. Compare Pedro A. Malavet, The Accidental Crit II: Culture and the Looking Glass of Exile, 78 DENV.U. L. REV. 753, 763 (2002) (“For me, ‘home’ is Ponce, Puerto Rico. No matter how far away from it I may go, my personal, professional and emotional travels always lead me back to Ponce.”); with Perea, Five Axioms, supra note 35, at 240 (“‘National origin’s’ focus on ancestral lands and traits outside the United States facilitates the attribution of foreignness to Latinos/as, our ‘symbolic deportation’ from within these borders. Thus we are removed from our full and constitutive role in a plenary conception of American identity.”). Robert Chang explains that Latinas/os and Asian-Americans share the imposition of the essentialized normativities of nativists who construct their fellow U.S. citizens of color as foreign. Chang, supra note 23, at 58. The nativists then dream of the “return” of the “foreign” “other” to the imaginary homeland imposed by the nativist, or at least that the “foreigner” never will realize full citizenship within the U.S. “Where are you from,” is quickly, albeit often impliedly, followed by “When are you going back?” Id. (citation omitted). For discussion of cultural nationhood, see also infra notes 110-11 and accompanying text. 24 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 of the 21st century. LatCrit thus seeks to understand how subordination, such as that described by Scafidi, is accomplished, because that is a necessary prerequisite for its antiessentialist mission. LatCrit Theory will benefit from proper historical analysis of the legal construction of identity perpetrated by the Spanish colonizers on the nations of Latin America because such constructs have enduring influence on the identity of Latinas/os even here in the United States.73 Moreover, because the process of legal/social construction of subordination discussed by Scafidi is similar to the social construction of race in the United States,74 this work also offers us yet another perspective on how to tear down existing power hegemonies that will be relevant to LatCrit praxis within the United States borderlands. C. The TWAIL/NAIL Concurrent Panel Jorge Esquirol and Michael Wallace Gordon participated in the third concurrent panel, titled TWAIL/NAIL:75 Latin American Legal Theory.76 73. For example, colonial racial hierarchies often become part of Latina/o identity and constitute internalized oppression(s). See infra note 106 and accompanying text. 74. See supra notes 37, 52 and accompanying text. 75. Elizabeth Iglesias has defined TWAIL/NAIL: “Third World Approaches to International Law” (TWAIL) and “New Approaches to International Law” (NAIL). Elizabeth Iglesias, Out of the Shadow: Marking Intersections in and Between Asian Pacific American Critical Legal Scholarship and Latina/o Critical Legal Theory, 40 B.C. L. REV. 349, 372 n.65 (1998). 76. The panel was described as follows: The other two sets of concurrent sessions this year features [sic] four concurrent panels each. Like the plenary panels, these concurrent sessions reflect the desire for continued attention to matters of recurring significance and the effort to mark new terrain for anti-subordination critique. The concurrent panels, as indicated more fully in the attached Program Schedule, address issues ranging from continuing LatCrit efforts to engage and incorporate critical perspectives on international and comparative law, to explorations of the current day consequences of Cubans’ identities within and outside the patria, Puerto Rico’s colonized history, and the political economies of culture, desire and latinas’ bodies. As in prior LatCrit conferences, both the concurrent panels and the concurrent workshops are crucial and integral events that enable conference participants to join in relatively intimate small-group settings to carry forward ideas from prior LatCrit conferences, or from conversations begun in plenary sessions during the conference, or to break new ground that may serve as points of programmatic follow-up in future LatCrit conferences. We hope you will take advantage of, and contribute to, the synergies that are so often produced by the blend of plenary and concurrent programming and so clearly evident in the Symposium proceedings that have resulted from these blends at prior LatCrit conferences. Substantive Program Outline, supra note 8. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 25 Michael Gordon focuses on the many mis/conceptions about Latin American legal culture among United States’ legal practitioners and academics. He correctly attributes these false constructs both to United States legal/cultural imperialism and to a failure to apply real comparative methodology. Because he is one of the preeminent comparativists in the United States today,77 Gordon acts as an important intellectual bridge between North and South America, especially between the United States and the nations south of the Rio Grande. In his all too brief remarks, Professor Gordon provides a series of illustrations of the anglo-saxon, male, protestant, pro-common law American vision of a peculiarly legal form of cultural imperialism that displaced Spanish law from those parts of what are today the United States, but were Spanish prior to the Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo.78 However, Gordon provides a more optimistic view of the present and hopefully the future, particularly in the area of Public International Law. He specifically cites the North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA)79 as reflecting a more pluralistic vision of law and legality that 77. See generally RALPH H. FOLSOM ET AL., INTERNATIONAL BUSINESS TRANSACTIONS IN A NUTSHELL (2000); RALPH H. FOLSOM ET AL., INTERNATIONAL TRADE AND INVESTMENT IN A NUTSHELL (2000); RALPH H. FOLSOM ET AL., INTERNATIONAL BUSINESS TRANSACTIONS: A PROBLEM-ORIENTED COURSEBOOK (1999); INTERNATIONAL BUSINESS TRANSACTIONS: A READER (Ralph H. Folsom ed., 1997); MARY ANN GLENDON ET AL., COMPARATIVE LEGAL TRADITIONS IN A NUTSHELL (1999) [hereinafter GLENDON ET AL., NUTSHELL]; MARY ANN GLENDON ET AL., COMPARATIVE LEGAL TRADITIONS: TEXT, MATERIALS AND CASES ON THE CIVIL AND COMMON LAW TRADITIONS (1994). 78. Michael Wallace Gordon, Legal Cultures of Latin America and the United States: Conflict or Merger, 55 FLA. L. REV. 115 (2003). As a result of the Treaty, the U.S. acquired “present-day Texas, California, Arizona, New Mexico, Nevada, and parts of Utah, Colorado and Kansas.” JUAN F. P EREA ET AL., RACE AND RACES, CASES AND RESOURCES FOR A DIVERSE AMERICA 253 (2000); see also Treaty of Peace, Friendship, Limits, and Settlement Between the United States of America and the Mexican Republic, Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo, May 30, 1848, U.S.-Mex., art. IX, 9 Stat. 922, 930 [hereinafter Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo]. On the Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo, see generally THE LEGACY OF THE MEXICAN AND SPANISH-AMERICAN WARS: LEGAL, LITERARY AND HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE (Gary D. Keller & Cordelia Candelaria eds., 2000); RICHARD GRISWOLD DEL CASTILLO, THE TREATY OF GUADALUPE HIDALGO: A LEGACY OF CONFLICT (1989); Symposium, Understanding the Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo on its 150th Anniversary, 5 SW. J.L. & TRADE AM. 1 (1998). LatCrit scholar Guadalupe T. Luna has written extensively about the Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo. See, e.g., Guadalupe T. Luna, Chicanas/os, “Liberty” And Roger B. Taney, 12 U. FLA. J.L. & PUB. POL’Y 33 (2000); Guadalupe T. Luna, “This Land Belongs To Me:” Chicanas, Land Grant Adjudication, and the Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo, 3 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 115 (1999); Guadalupe T. Luna, Beyond/Between Colors: On the Complexities of Race: The Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo and Dred Scott v. Sandford, 53 U. MIAMI L. REV. 691 (1999); Guadalupe T. Luna, En El Nombre De Dios Todo-Poderoso: The Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo and Narrativos Legales, 5 SW. J. L. & TRADE AM. 45 (1998). 79. On the Treaty, see generally RALPH FOLSOM ET AL., NAFTA: A PROBLEM-ORIENTED COURSEBOOK (2000); RALPH H. FOLSOM ET AL., HANDBOOK OF NAFTA DISPUTE SETTLEMENT (1998). 26 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 better respects the different legal systems of its member states: Mexico’s civil law system, Canada’s partially hybrid common law/civil law tradition, and the common law rules of the United States. Specifically, he points out that the dispute-resolution provisions of the agreement adopt the substantive legal rules and standards of review of each member state.80 The NAFTA has been the subject of LatCrit discussion, not all of it positive,81 but it is clearly an important area for LatCrit study. Jorge Esquirol challenges the “Law and Development” scholarly view of Latin America.82 This law and development model has endured well past the shelf-life of that discredited movement. Professor Esquirol refers 80. Gordon, supra note 78, at 118-19. 81. See, e.g., José E. Álvarez, Critical Theory and the North American Free Trade Agreement's Chapter Eleven, 28 U. MIAMI INTER-AM. L. REV. 303, 312 (1997) (“NAFTA investment chapter [overly] reflects U.S. laws and perspectives.”); Elizabeth M. Iglesias, Human Rights in International Economic Law: Locating Latinas/os in the Linkage Debates, 28 U. MIAMI INTER-AM. L. REV. 361, 369-71 (1996) (critiquing the “labor accord portion of the NAFTA”). 82. Jorge L. Esquirol, Continuing Fictions of Latin American Law, 55 FLA. L. REV. 41 (2003). David Trubek has provided a thorough, critical analysis of law and development: The law and development movement was a sort of export branch of Imperial legal culture. In the 1960’s American legal academics, encouraged by massive grants from foundations and government agencies, turned to the study of the role of law in Third World “development.” . . . The law and development movement took the value of modern law to be self evident. “Modern law” usually meant the codes or new statutory enactments which third world governments had imported from other, presumably more advanced, nations. Usually, these codes or statutes set forth norms that had little relation to everyday life in the countries of Africa, Asia, and Latin America. Law and development scholars assumed that adoption and implementation of these (often imported) modern laws marked development or progress. And they treated as a “problem” the fact that social relations in Third World countries did not conform to these newly enacted norms. This equation of legal standards with progress, and the definition of non-compliance as a problem, led these scholars to spend a considerable amount of time thinking about how we could develop a way to measure—and thus increase—the “penetration” of so-called modern law. Compressed in that single word are a whole set of assumptions and attitudes that have come under attack. Critics have challenged the following assumptions: that any body of law contains a single set of principles or rules whose impact can be unproblematically measured; that law emanates from some central source and then is implanted in society; that modern law (whatever that is) is normatively desirable or historically inevitable; and, finally, that the social scientific task of measuring “penetration” is a progressive task. It does not require much sophisticated feminist analysis to see how the use of the term “penetration” crystalized the hegemonizing, dominating, and patriarchal nature of imperial legal culture in the 1960’s. David M. Trubek, Back to the Future: The Short, Happy Life of the Law and Society Movement, 18 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 4, 37-38 (1990) (footnotes omitted). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 27 to developmentalism and developmentalists to describe, respectively, the Law and Development scholarship of the 1960s and 1970s, and the United States academics who produced it.83 Comparativists in the United States, and elsewhere, have long recognized many of the shortcomings of law and development.84 Professor Esquirol thus engages us in a well-crafted, strong discussion and critique of the legal form of cultural imperialism perpetrated by the North upon the nations of Latin America. Esquirol argues that the developmentalist view endures in the United States’ memory because it fits in with American stereotypes about “corrupt” and, more generally, inferior Latin American cultures.85 This essentialized view in turn affects how Americans86 interact with Latin America. Additionally, the construct is embraced by existing dominant groups in Latin America who thus protect their privilege and continue to subordinate their own people. This marginalization from outside and from within, especially in and through law, serves only to perpetuate essentialized normativities—even within a culture that to the North American eye is an “other.” 83. See generally Esquirol, supra note 82. 84. For a succinct, critical note on law and development, see CIVIL LAW TRADITION, supra note 17, at 36-37. 85. Elizabeth Iglesias has described this phenomenon: By the term development discourse, I refer to a cluster of arguments and representations that organize our understandings of the causes and cures of Latina/o economic and political subordination around accounts linking subordination to underdevelopment and underdevelopment to the persistence of social practices, relations, and expectations that are represented as elements of Latin [American] culture. Iglesias, supra note 81, at 377-78. 86. Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol explains the irony of using the term “American” to refer only to citizens of the United States of America: I use the designation United States for the United States of America. Many, if not most or all of the other authors use the terms United States and America interchangeably. I decided not to alter the authors’ choice of language in that regard. I do find it necessary to comment thereon, however, because I find it ironic that in a book on imperialism the imperialistic practice of denominating the United States as “America” remains normative. Indeed, America is much larger than the U.S. alone; there is also Canada [and Mexico] in North America, and all of Latin America and the Caribbean, (some locations commonly referred to as Central America, some as South America). Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Introduction, in MORAL IMPERIALISM: A CRITICAL ANTHOLOGY 15 n.5 (Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol ed., 2002). 28 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 A new paradigm is needed that promotes full—both legal and economic—desarrollo (development). This paradigm should reject the assumption of the irrelevance of the official legal system as a positive element in the daily lives of the americanas/os (the people of the Americas). To the contrary, the new approach should embrace the official legal system as a catalyst for change that has the capacity to empower the marginalized. Accordingly, the process of reform should not be designed to bypass the local legal system and supplant it with a supranational alternative; rather, the end-goal should be to allow formerly marginalized peoples to participate fully in the national legal system. Reform, rather than replace the national systems; advise and empower the citizens of Latin American nations; do not presume to impose and thereby control those systems and citizens. Esquirol provides a critical defense of the legal cultures of the nations of Latin America through a well-researched and thoughtful critique of the law and development movement as well as its more contemporary cousin, modern developmentalism. He articulates that both the shortcomings of this movement and its demise are too often constructed in culturally imperialistic ways that underestimate or totally ignore the strength and nature of individual Latin American legal systems.87 Yet, Esquirol does not ignore the negative forces and existing hegemonies within Latin American societies. Rather, he explains how these forces are an altogether ignored element that led to the failure of law and development theory and its attempted implementation as a single model for an entire continent.88 This provocative and powerful critique captures the theme of the conference, and engages LatCrit in developing a theoretical blueprint to empower the nations of the Americas, with a progressive approach to legal reform and to law more generally. Esquirol captures the spirit and purpose of LatCrit by reconceptualizing the law and society movement, and removing it from the previously United States-centric, paternalistic view, and placing it in the context of the diverse legal systems of the nations of Latin America. The central theme of his critique is that by accepting the “duality,” the separation between the formal legal system and the so-called informal social/legal sector,89 critical theorists are abandoning the field of 87. The plural is especially important because it is the national, that is, local identity of law that Esquirol explains defines the individual legal systems of the Americas. Hence, he challenges the homogenized notion that “Latin America” is a single territory or a single legal system. Esquirol, supra note 82, at 43. 88. Id. at 80. 89. In a work referenced by Esquirol, Hernando de Soto describes “informality” as a formally illegal process “designed to achieve such essentially legal objectives as building a house, providing a service, or developing a business.” HERNANDO DE SOTO, THE OTHER PATH: THE INVISIBLE REVOLUTION IN THE THIRD WORLD 11 (June Abbott trans., 1989). The “problem” that produces the informal economy is the state, concludes de Soto: “We can say that informal activities burgeon 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 29 formal law to the traditionalist, conservative power brokers that are thought to control it. In so doing, progressives are giving up any chance of effective legality, because informality—the conduct of trade outside the official legal system—90will not work as a long-term, predictable legal system.91 Esquirol articulates a solution, a progressive form of “legal nationalism” that conceives of “formalism . . . as the autochthonous mode of legal interpretation in the region.”92 Here, Esquirol’s work is reminiscent of the debate in comparative law over the effect of “certainty” as a positive legal principle in fascist Italy and Nazi Germany.93 “Sophisticated dichotomists,” according to Esquirol, breath new life into the duality’s construct of a dichotomy between the formal and informal legal sectors in all the nations of Latin America by recognizing the existence of the separation without neglecting the official legal system as when the legal system imposes rules which exceed the socially accepted legal framework—does not honor the expectations, choices, and preferences of those whom it does not admit within its framework—and when the state does have sufficient coercive authority.” Id. at 12. Accordingly, there is a duality, a disjunction, between the formal legal system and the informal sector. 90. Hernando de Soto further explains the activities of the informal sector as follows: The concept of informality used in this book is based on empirical observations of the phenomenon itself. Individuals are not informal; their actions and activities are. Nor do those who operate informally comprise a precise or static sector of society: they live within a gray area which has a long frontier with the legal world and in which individuals take refuge when the cost of obeying the law outweighs the benefit. Only rarely does informality mean breaking all the laws; most individuals disobey specific legal provisions . . . . Id. 91. Esquirol presents LatCrit with a real challenge to its convictions. See generally Esquirol, supra note 82. Progressive social and cultural consciousness are positive forces, but he questions whether the theoretical paradigm makes it impossible for praxis to work. While not discounting the dangers of legal pluralism in the hands of a repressive reactionary regime, Esquirol nonetheless challenges progressives in and out of the Americas to re-engage with the official legal system and formalist legal scholarship. Id. at 95. While the field is an inherently dangerous one, it is also the only possible source of a long-term solution to the problems of informality in the nations of the Americas. Id. Accepting informality is not the solution. Rather, we progressives must bridge the gap between the formal legal system and the pluralistic legal cultures within the nation states of the Americas. Id. at 96-97. 92. Id. at 107. 93. The long-held perception is that the formal use of certainty to oppose fascism allowed Italian judges to become a force against the excesses of the Mussolini regime, whereas the abandonment of it in Germany turned the German judiciary into a willing tool of Hitler’s regime. See CIVIL LAW TRADITION, supra note 17, at 998-1004 (comparing the ability and willingness of judges in Germany and Italy to resist their respective country’s fascist dictatorships by using or abandoning the principle of certainty in the law). 30 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 part of any sensible solution.94 In other words, the duality is not a necessary part of the legal cultures of Latin America, it is rather a problem that prevents everyone within those cultures from working within an effective, pluralistic formal legal system. Esquirol thus challenges the notion that Latin American cultures are by nature lawless or chaotic. His work, and the scholarship he studies,95 may provide us with the tools for a paradigmatic shift96 in the discourse of Latin American legal cultures. One that must seek to bridge the gap between formal and informal rules, and create a single pluralistic legal culture within each Latin American nation.97 Both Gordon and Esquirol urge LatCrit to engage the cultures of the nations of Latin America from a position of knowledge. This requires real 94. Esquirol, supra note 82, at 108. 95. Esquirol specifically discusses the work of Hernando de Soto, which identifies a lack of anarchy in the informal economy, that is, the informal sector is not a completely lawless sector, nor is it without rules, it is rather a marginalized group that has found it necessary to bypass the formal legal system. It is however important to note that laws, substantive legal rules, are part of both the formal and the informal legal system. See generally DE SOTO, supra note 89. 96. Philosophical paradigm shifts can be analogized to a process of religious conversion because they are fundamentally subjective processes. [A] scientific revolution occurs when one paradigm is replaced by another. Paradigm shifts cause scientists to view the world in new and different ways. During scientific revolutions, then, scientists experience perceptual shifts. According to Kuhn, the transition from one paradigm to another is a conversion experience that cannot be compelled by logical argument. George A. Martínez, Philosophical Considerations and the Use of Narrative in Law, 30 RUTGERS L. REV. 683, 701 (1999) (footnotes omitted). Therefore, Professor Martínez concludes “[s]ince racial divisions are founded in something other than reason—i.e., deeply held prejudices and sentiments—perhaps it can only be undone by techniques, such as narrative, that do not depend on reason.” Id. at 705 (footnotes omitted). Or are those calling for paradigm shifts simply appealing to common sense? See BOAVENTURA DE SOUSA SANTOS, TOWARD A NEW COMMON SENSE: LAW, SCIENCE AND POLITICS IN THE PARADIGMATIC TRANSITION 518-19 (1995). My objective, therefore, was not to present the blueprint of a new order, but merely to show that the collapse of the existing order or disorder—which Fourier significantly called “subversive order”—does not entail barbarism at all. It means, rather, an opportunity to reinvent a commitment to authentic emancipation, a commitment, moreover, which, rather than being a product of enlightened vanguardist thought, unfolds as sheer common sense. Id. 97. See Esquirol, supra note 82. While concerned about “foreign modeled realism” Esquirol acknowledges that it does provide voice to traditionally disenfranchised peoples within the formal legal system. Id. at 113. The dangers are that the discourse will not be tailored to the local legal culture and that the colonial crisis of self-confidence will endow foreign models with undue discretion that will create remedies not really effective within the legal systems of Latin America. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 31 comparative study, as Gordon particularly urges, and a non-essentialist legal/political paradigm, as Esquirol writes. Gordon takes LatCrit to the trade perspective on Public International Law, which is clearly an important area for the exercise of LatCrit praxis. However, Esquirol provides an important warning with his extensive and strong critique of the law and development movement, and the enduring negative effects of its inherent construction of the legal systems of Latin American nations, as hopelessly de-linked from informal reality.98 His strong analysis of the theoretical shortcomings of these theories will help to produce a new paradigm, informed by LatCrit Theory, that will result in praxis to empower the “informal” sector, rather than undermine the “formal” legal systems of the Americas. III. CONTINUING LATCRITICAL ENCOUNTERS WITH CULTURE IN COMPARATIVE NORTH-SOUTH FRAMEWORKS These new voices within LatCrit all had a common focus: Latin American cultures—more precisely the legal and social construction of cultures—and their relationship to legal theory and praxis. Because the frame of reference of some of the authors and of members of the audience cut across national borders, this is a comparative legal study of culture. Comparative law is the study of law that is foreign to the observer; thus, it requires a particular methodological/scientific approach.99 The distinction between comparative methodology and comparative legal science100 will depend on the intended use of comparative study. For 98. LatCrit has in fact studied trade issues. See, e.g., supra note 81. See also Colloquium, International Law, Human Rights and LatCrit Theory, 28 U. MIAMI INTER-AM. L. REV. 177 (1996) (noting that many of the articles in this colloquium focused on the intersection between human rights and trade and development). 99. Accordingly, Comparative Law is not a body of rules and principles. Primarily, it is a method, a way of looking at legal problems, legal institutions, and entire legal systems. By the use of that method it becomes possible to make observations, and to gain insights, which would be denied to one who limits his study to the law of a single country. Neither the comparative method, nor the insights gained through its use, can be said to constitute a body of binding norms, i.e. of “law” in the sense in which we speak of “the law” of Torts or “the law” of Decedents’ Estates. Strictly speaking, therefore, the term Comparative Law is a misnomer. It would be more appropriate to speak of Comparison of Laws and Legal Systems . . . . RUDOLPH B. SCHLESINGER ET AL., COMPARATIVE LAW 1 (5th ed. 1988) (footnotes omitted). 100. To the French, for example, comparative law (droit comparé) “is not a branch of the law, but very specifically a part of the science of law (science du droit).” JEAN-LUC AUBERT, INTRODUCTION AU DROIT 55 (5th ed. 1992) (author’s translation); see also DAVID & BRIERLEY, 32 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 example, the practitioner of comparative legal science can assist persons in other fields of the law to adopt the comparative method, either to avoid the problems created by the misunderstanding of different legal cultures, or to illuminate effective courses of action that are based on a real understanding of those cultures. Comparative law is, in this context, an effective and sophisticated system of legal translation and education, because “[l]aw, taken alone and considered only in its strict theory, would give a false view of the way in which social relations, and the place therein of law, really operate.”101 A comparative legal theorist looking across national borders ought to provide a full understanding of the law and its underlying theory in their proper practical context.102 Analogously, LatCrit is a jurisprudential school that seeks to illuminate legal praxis, and in this particular conference it focused on the cultural context of law across international boundaries.103 The cultures of the nations of the Americas are the products of physical and intellectual colonization,104 which requires LatCrit to further develop supra note 61, at 2-3, 11-13. 101. DAVID & BRIERLEY, supra note 61, at 14. 102. Goebel, supra note 59, at 447-48. Professor Goebel notes that this is not a universally accepted tenet, id. at 454, but concludes, in my opinion correctly, that this is an important, even essential requirement for properly carrying out our professional duties to our clients. For a general discussion of the importance of understanding a legal system in its proper context, see generally DAVID & BRIERLEY, supra note 61; GLENDON ET AL., NUTSHELL, supra note 77; CIVIL LAW TRADITION, supra note 17, at 113-115; JOHN HENRY MERRYMAN & DAVID S. CLARK, COMPARATIVE LAW: WESTERN EUROPEAN AND LATIN AMERICAN LEGAL SYSTEMS: CASES AND MATERIALS (1978); SCHLESINGER ET AL., supra note 99, at 1; KONRAD ZWEIGERT & HEIN KÖTZ, 1 INTRODUCTION TO COMPARATIVE LAW: THE FRAMEWORK 68 (Tony Weir trans., 2d ed., 1987). 103. LatCrit seeks to be heard by and to assist our colleagues from the South but, in seeking to hear other voices, LatCrit is also enriched by learning to look at itself from a different frame of reference. This is a process similar to a traditional comparativist turning the study of a foreign legal system into a critical look at their own rules and procedures. The comparative method will give a national scholar “a better understanding of his own law, assist in its improvement, and . . . open[] the door to working with those in other countries in establishing uniform conflict or substantive rules or at least their harmonisation.” DAVID & BRIERLEY, supra note 61, at 11-12. 104. Homero Manzi put it as follows: Nuestra pobre América, que comenzó a rezar cuando ya eran prehistoria los viejos testamentos . . . cuando la historia estaba llena de guerreros, el alma llena de místicos, el pensamiento lleno de filósofos, la belleza llena de artistas, y la ciencia llena de sabios . . . Todo lo que cruzaba el mar era mejor y, cuando no teníamos salvación, apareció lo popular para salvarnos. HÉCTOR GAGLIARDI, P OR LAS CALLES DEL RECUERDO 5 (1970) (emphasis added). Author’s translation: Our poor America (meaning the continents, not the one country), which started to pray when the testaments where pre-history . . . when history was full of warriors, 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 33 the paradox of the colonized: that the society that this process left behind after the end of the colonial period is both for better and for worse, the product of the mixture of people, cultures, and laws brought together by the colonization process. Accordingly, postcolonial societies often fall victim both to external cultural imperialism105 and to internalized oppression.106 The former colonized peoples intellectually and culturally colonize themselves and prey upon each other by adopting and perpetuating the essentialized hierarchies of the former colonial power. As a result of this process, the peoples themselves are the colonizers and the colonized. the soul full of mystics, thinking was full of philosophers, beauty was full of artists, and science was full of wise men . . . . Everything that crossed the sea was better and, just when we were beyond salvation, the popular [culture] appeared to save us. Id. I realize that this quote is told from an Eurocentric perspective that might be read to exclude the Native American contribution, but the Native American is a crucial element in the Latin-American popular cultures that distinguishes us from the conquistadores peninsulares (peninsulares is a reference to persons born on the Iberian Peninsula). 105. Carla Freccero explains that: Imperialism can [occur] on different levels and usually involves territorial annexation, economic and political annexation, juridical (legal) annexation, and ultimately ideological and cultural annexation; these latter are often referred to as cultural imperialism . . . . [C]ultural or mental decolonization [is] a “literature/criticism that is participatory in the historical processes of hegemony and resistance to domination rather than (only) formal and analytic.” Collective and concerted resistance to programmatic cultural imperialism thus comes to be called “cultural” or “mental” decolonization. CARLA FRECCERO, POPULAR CULTURE: AN INTRODUCTION 68 (1999) (citations omitted). 106. The internalization of oppression occurs when a group that is oppressed by the normative society replicates some forms of oppression to marginalize members of its own community along lines of discrimination that parallel those of the normative group. For example, women might be subordinated by the men within the group, and among African Americans, lighter skin hues are considered more desirable. Oliva Espín explains the paradox of a group that is the object of discrimination marginalizing members of its own community: The prejudices and racism of the dominant society make the retrenchment into tradition appear justifiable. Conversely, the rigidities of tradition appear to justify the racist or prejudicial treatment of the dominant society. These “two mountains” reinforce and encourage each other. Moreover, the effects of racism and sexism are not only felt as pressure from the outside; like all forms of oppression, they become internalized . . . . OLIVA W. ESPÍN, WOMEN CROSSING BOUNDARIES: A P SYCHOLOGY OF IMMIGRATION AND TRANSFORMATION OF SEXUALITY 8 (1999). 34 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 In its Latin American variant, the best challenge to the process of selfcolonization is the development of the “popular,” the home-grown forms of culture in all its variations, including recognizing that the dominant popular Latin American cultures co-exist with subordinated (mostly indigenous) systems, thus re/creating patterns of colonialism. The Sixth Annual LatCrit Conference, and the essays included in this cluster, are part of the process of challenging existing power hegemonies by recognizing the real and vibrant legal cultures of the nations of Latin America, albeit from a critical perspective. Together, they adopt a philosophically communitarian,107 cultural studies108 view of the term “culture,” meaning that culture is a whole way of life (ideas, attitudes, languages, practices, institutions, structures of power) and a whole range of cultural practices: artistic forms, texts, canons, architecture, mass-produced commodities, and so on. Culture means the actual grounded terrain of practices, representations, languages, and customs of any specific historical society. Culture, in other words, means not only “high culture,” what we usually call art or literature, but also the everyday practices, representations, and cultural productions of people and of postindustrial societies.109 107. The communitarian concept of citizenship views the “citizen as a member of a community.” Herman Van Gunsteren, Four Conceptions of Citizenship, in THE CONDITION OF CITIZENSHIP 36, 41 (Bart van Steenbergen ed., 1994). “This conception strongly emphasizes that being a citizen means belonging to a historically developed community. Individuality is derived from it and determined in terms of it.” Id. Moreover, “identity and stability of character cannot be realized without the support of a community of friends and like-minded kindred.” Id. 108. Carla Freccero explains that the term “cultural studies” covers a range of theoretical and political positions that use a variety of methodologies, drawing on ethnography, anthropology, sociology, literature, feminism, Marxism, history, film criticism, psychoanalysis, and semiotics. Cultural studies is anthropological, but unlike anthropology, it begins with the study of postindustrial rather than preindustrial societies. It is like humanism, but unlike traditional humanism it rejects the distinction between socalled low culture and high culture and argues that all forms of culture need to be studied in relation to a given social formation. It is thus interdisciplinary in its approaches. Cultural studies “has grown out of efforts to understand what has shaped post World War II societies and cultures: industrialization, modernization, urbanization, mass communication, commodification, imperialism, a global economy.” FRECCERO, supra note 105, at 14 (footnotes omitted). 109. Id. at 13. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 35 LatCrit encourages the development of the concept of cultural nationhood or citizenship to differentiate the colonized peoples from their colonial oppressors110 because it can be used as a source of empowerment, consciousness, and pride.111 But, this cultural exploration might produce legitimate concerns over the dangers of nationalism112 and cultural imperialism. Accordingly, LatCrit Theory illuminates the proper balance between identifying cultural faultlines that require reform, and the imposition of cultural imperialism that seeks a homogenized normativity that only perpetuates the supremacies promoted by the colonial power. As all the essays in this cluster indicate, the post-colonial cultures of the Americas are the result of the racial, gender, and political mix created by the colonizer.113 The Spaniards effectively designed the blueprint for the gender, cultural, religious, ethnic, and racial mix in the Spanish Americas by conquering and destroying the indigenous peoples, raping the indigenous women,114 bringing in settlers, allowing immigration, and importing African slaves.115 The Spanish then used law to define and organize their practically constructed local societies. LatCrit takes a critical look at those cultures and recognizes and celebrates their strengths. But it also criticizes their shortcomings and provides the theoretical vision to resolve them. Thus, LatCrit, as a premier 110. See, e.g., Malavet, supra note 39 (explaining that the Puerto Ricans are culturally distinct from the normative U.S. society). 111. Hence, “othering” can be used as a subversive force that empowers marginalized colonial peoples. See Addis, ETHNICITY, supra note 42, at 127. 112. In speaking of the dangers of nationalism, Ronald Beiner ponders “[e]ither fascism is a uniquely evil expression of an otherwise benign human need for belonging; or there is a kind of latent fascism implicit in any impulse towards group belonging.” Ronald Beiner, Introduction, in THEORIZING CITIZENSHIP, supra note 47, at 19. 113. Adeno Addis, in arguing against secession, identifies the need for co-existence: “Whether the multiplicity is the ‘unintended’ consequence of colonialism or the organizing principle, the defining feature, of the particular nation-state, the uncontroverted fact is that most nations are indeed multiethnic and multicultural.” Addis, supra note 111, at 113. 114. I am not entirely comfortable with the use of the term “rape” here. As Margaret Montoya explains: “Choosing the right word [to describe ‘sexual relations between the Spanish conquistadores and the indigenous women of the Americas’] is difficult . . .; perhaps rape is the accurate term, but it denies agency to all the indigenous women in the past who were involved in cross-racial relations.” Margaret E. Montoya, Academic Mestizaje: Re/Producing Clinical Teaching and Re/Framing Wills As Latina Praxis, 2 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 349, 351 n.3 (1997). The concept of “agency” implies that people can be the objects of action or its subjects, the performers of acts, i.e., the agents of action. When one is a subject, one acts as an agent for some purpose, hence, one is exercising agency. MICHAEL WALZER, ON TOLERATION xi (1997). When a person lacks the power/capacity to take action, s/he is deprived of agency. 115. For descriptions of the process of construction of the Spanish colonial cultures in the Americas, see Hernández-Truyol, supra note 71, at 76-79 (providing a general description with specific examples regarding Mexico and Cuba); Malavet, supra note 39, at 12-20, 55-74 (describing the development of Puerto Rican culture). 36 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 example of the current deconstructionist postmodern age, rejects the idea of liberal universalism as being “merely a cover for an imperialistic particularism.”116 Postmodernism also points out the theoretical shortcomings of current philosophical movements, and warns against the mistakes of extremism at any end of the philosophical spectrum.117 This is especially true when one in engages in cultural studies, particularly legal/comparative cultural studies, such as those included in this Symposium. LatCrit contends that the peoples of Latin America must be able to develop “shared identities”118 within their own community as political and cultural citizens of their respective republics —or within the United States community that is most familiar to LatCritters—as political citizens of the nation who have their culture respected by the normative society. The alternative, to construct any people as cultural “citizen[s] of the world,”119 116. Beiner, supra note 112, at 9. “Appeals to universal reason typically serve to silence, stigmatize and marginalize groups and identities that lie beyond the boundaries of a white, male, Eurocentric hegemon. Universalism is merely the cover for an imperialistic particularism.” Id. 117. Beiner, for example, describes what he calls the “universalism/ particularism conundrum,” as: “[t]o opt wholeheartedly for universalism implies deracination—rootlessness. To opt wholeheartedly for particularism implies parochialism, exclusivity, and narrow-minded closure of horizons.” Id. at 12. 118. Addis explains: By “shared identity” I mean to refer to an identity that bonds together, partially and contingently, minorities and majorities, such that different cultural and ethnic groups are seen, and see themselves, as networks of communication where each group comes to understand its distinctiveness as well as the fact that distinctiveness is to a large degree defined in terms of its relationship with the Other. Viewed in this way, the notion of shared identity is not a final state of harmony, as communitarians would claim. It is rather a process that would allow diverse groups to link each other in a continuous dialogue with the possibility that the life of each group will illuminate the conditions of others such that in the process the groups might develop, however provisionally and contingently, “common vocabularies of emancipation,” and of justice. I think Seyla Benhabib is right when she observed that “[t]he feelings of friendship and solidarity result . . . through the extension of our moral and political imagination . . . through the actual confrontation in public life with the point of view of those who are otherwise strangers to us but who become known to us through their public presence as voices and perspectives we have to take into account.” Addis, supra note 111, at 127 (footnotes omitted). 119. MARTHA C. NUSSBAUM, FOR LOVE OF COUNTRY: DEBATING THE LIMITS OF PATRIOTISM 5 (1996). Nussbaum advocates cosmopolitan citizenship thusly: The accident of where one is born is just that, an accident; any human being might have been born in any nation. Recognizing this, [Diogenes’] Stoic successors held, we should not allow differences of nationality or class or ethnic membership or 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 37 would constitute an imposed homogeneity. Critical scholars should reject the notion that being Mexican, Puerto Rican, Cuban, Columbian, Chilean (or American, or Irish) first and a citizen of the World second is morally questionable or irrelevant.120 Nationalism, or as the authors discuss, national consciousness and sensibility, may be deployed as a positive force,121 as long as it is limited by a pluralistic communitarian consciousness.122 In this context, the peoples of the Americas should be able to choose to be patriots of their chosen nation,123 more generally, even gender to erect barriers between us and our fellow human beings. We should recognize humanity wherever it occurs, and give its fundamental ingredients, reason and moral capacity, our first allegiance and respect. Id. at 7. 120. Once someone has said, I am an Indian first, a citizen of the world second, once he or she has made that morally questionable move of self-definition by a morally irrelevant characteristic, then what, indeed, will stop that person from saying, as Tagore’s characters so quickly learn to say, I am a Hindu first, and an Indian second, or I am an upper-caste landlord first, and a Hindu second? Only the cosmopolitan stance of the landlord Nikhil—so boringly flat in the eyes of his young wife Bimala and his passionate nationalist friend Sandip—has the promise of transcending these divisions, because only this stance asks us to give our first allegiance to what is morally good—and that which, being good, I can commend as such to all human beings. Id. at 5 (emphasis added) (referring to THE HOME AND THE WORLD, a novel by Tagore). 121. Michael Walzer describes this type of nationalism: The quality of nationalism is also determined within civil society, where national groups coexist and overlap with families and religious communities (two social formations largely neglected in modernist answers to the question about the good life) and where nationalism is expressed in schools and movements, organizations for mutual aid, cultural and historical societies. It is because groups like these are entangled with other groups, similar in kind but different in aim, that civil society holds out the hope of a domesticated nationalism. In states dominated by a single nation, the multiplicity of the groups pluralizes nationalist politics and culture; in states with more than one nation, the density of the networks prevents radical polarization. Michael Walzer, The Civil Society Argument, in THEORIZING CITIZENSHIP, supra note 47, at 153, 166. 122. In other words, nationalism does not have to be inherently fascist. See supra note 112. 123. Richard Rorty urges Americans, especially the American left, not to disdain patriotism as a value, and indeed to give central importance to “the emotions of national pride” and “a sense of shared national identity.” Rorty argues that we cannot even criticize ourselves well unless we also “rejoice” in our American 38 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 peoples of the world should be able to choose a national affiliation. While nationalism cannot become dogma,124 cultural sovereignty within a supranational political culture that empowers the marginalized125 would allow the nations of Latin America—and the Estados Unidos de Norteamérica (the United States of America)—to live up to the ideal of a diverse “political culture” that exercises “constitutional patriotism.”126 IV. CONCLUSION: BIENVENIDAS/OS, AMIGAS/OS AMERICANAS/OS LatCrit VI, and this issue, have brought to the forefront new voices in legal scholarship. This is part of the process of resisting the suppression of scholars of color within the United States legal academy.127 But it is more importantly about expanding the LatCritical exploration of law, theory, and praxis within a newly-enriched United States legal scholarship. The essays in this cluster are a major contribution to creating a link between the existing LatCrit emancipatory theory and praxis, and the existing and developing academic environment in North and South America. This part of the Symposium issue presents new voices and new discourses that develop, expand, transform, and enrich LatCrit Theory. These essays collectively provide an important lens to re/view the multicultural and multiracial Latin American societies, and thus to challenge the inherited racialized constructs of the nations of the world generally, and those of Latin America in particular. The fundamental paradigmatic shift that brings all the authors together is the denial of the identity and define ourselves fundamentally in terms of that identity. Rorty seems to hold that the primary alternative to a politics based on patriotism and national identity is what he calls a “politics of difference,” one based on internal divisions among America’s ethnic, racial, religious, and other subgroups. He nowhere considers the possibility of a more international basis for political emotion and concern. NUSSBAUM, supra note 119, at 4. 124. J.G.A. Pocock uses the French Revolution as an example to describe the terrifying results of citizenship becoming dogma which justifies the destruction of your “enemies,” that is, outsiders. The French revolution went from an uprising of citizens against the ancien regime, to the terror of citizenship being deployed to justify the destruction of the enemy. Virtue became terror. See J.G.A. Pocock, The Ideal of Citizenship Since Classical Times, in THEORIZING CITIZENSHIP, supra note 47, at 29, 50. 125. See Jürgen Habermas, supra note 47, at 264. 126. Id. 127. To do otherwise, of course, would again create the incongruity identified by Richard Delgado in the Imperial Scholar that the civil rights discourse in legal scholarship is being dominated by the normative voices of White males and, thus, is fundamentally incomplete. See Richard Delgado, Comment, The Imperial Scholar: Reflections on a Review of Civil Rights Literature, 132 U. PA. L. REV. 561 (1984). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 39 colonial myth of a single mixed race for Latinas/os, by pointing out that those constructs in fact create internalized oppressions that deprive the same marginalized persons, especially dark-skinned African descendants and indigenous peoples, of voice within the national discourse (as emphasized particularly by the work of Hugo Rojas and Susan Scafidi). Additionally, as García-Villegas, Gordon, and Esquirol point out, serious analysis of, and engagement with, the national legal systems of the Americas is essential to the success of any movement that wishes to empower the americanas/os. LatCrit theory and praxis were well served by the oral presentations made by these authors at LatCrit VI, and the growing permanent record of LatCrit scholarship, memorialized in this Symposium issue, is enriched by it. ¡Bienvenidas/os! CONTINUING FICTIONS OF LATIN AMERICAN LAW Jorge L. Esquirol* I. THE 1960S-1970S LAW-AND-DEVELOPMENT PARADIGM . . . . . 46 A. Social Theory of Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49 B. Gap Between Law and Society . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53 C. Arcane and Formalist State Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 57 D. Legal Informality as an Argument for Development Politics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62 II. BRIDGING THE EVER-PRESENT GAP: THE DEVELOPMENT ATTEMPT . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 66 III. ROLLING UP THE BRIDGES (ACROSS THE GAP) . . . . . . . . . . . . . 69 IV. CRITIQUES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 81 A. Critique of Latin American Duality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 81 B. Critique of an Identity Approach to Latin American Law . . 83 C. Critique of “Exoticized” Latin American Law . . . . . . . . . . 86 D. Critique of the Hyper-Social . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 89 V. TRADITIONAL LEGAL DISCOURSE REINFORCED . . . . . . . . . . . . . 92 VI. FROM THE SIDELINES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 98 A. The Politics of Autochthonous Social Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99 B. Abandonment of Progressive, Counter-Dominant Law . . . 101 C. Foreclosing the Potential for a More Pragmatic Legal Discourse . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 104 VII. SOME WAYS OUT OF THE DEVELOPMENTALIST BIND . . . . . . . 106 A. Unapologetic Formalists . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 107 B. Sophisticated Dichotomists . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 108 C. Foreign-Modeled Realists . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 111 VIII. CONCLUDING THOUGHTS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 113 * Professor of Law, Florida International University College of Law. My deep gratitude to Charles Donahue, David Kennedy, Máximo Langer, Liliana Obregón, Clara Sandoval, and the May 9, 2001 participants of the Harvard Law School S.J.D. Colloquium for their wonderful comments and suggestions. 41 42 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 Law in Latin America is routinely the target of systemic criticism by U.S. commentators. Marked by underdevelopment and corruption in the region, national legal systems are considered part of the problem and not the solution. As a result, numerous reform proposals advocate the internationalization of traditionally national legal domains. International competence in the form of the Inter-American system, NAFTA, a free trade area of the Americas or World Bank intervention in national judiciaries will not, however, supplant most of the hemisphere’s law. Whatever expectations the global arena may hold, local law will continue to play a substantial role. In addition, internationalizing reforms may actually undermine the general goal of expanding democratic participation. Distancing the operation of law from local reach is likely to reinforce the very anomalies already perceived in the region. In this light, we should reexamine our settled understandings of “Latin American law” and the latter’s widely-noted limitations. This Essay advances the task of rethinking some of the basic background beliefs. The most substantial body of U.S.-based, legal writing on the region remains the development scholarship of the 1960s and 70s. At the time, many U.S. legal scholars turned their attention to promoting economic development through law reform. With respect to Latin America, their diagnosis was that excessive legal formalism constituted the main stumbling block to growth and the redistribution of wealth. State law, the sum of official rules and regulations, was seen as operating quite separately from the needs and characteristics of Latin American societies. The image of a wide gap was used to characterize the distance separating the written law, sanctioned by the State, and the living law—the actual rules which people follow. Moreover, the perceived disconnection of Latin American peoples from their legal institutions was, in turn, taken as reflecting a host of societal and cultural particularities unmet in the law. These same critiques and images continue to be expressed today: “antiquated Latin American law is insufficient to meet the needs of developing societies and economies”; “legal techniques are unresponsive to the societal goals of development, efficiency and rationality”; and “judicial administration is arcane and ineffective.” Moreover, these same core beliefs can be expected to influence the structure of hemispheric trade agreements and to inspire more program proposals by non-governmental organizations. Development scholars sought to address these same dysfunctions several decades ago by proposing a range of remedies, especially in the area of access to the courts and legal education. The legal culture, it was argued, should better square with modernization and its priorities. New legislation was suggested in furtherance of economic activity; new methods were introduced to make the legal process more accessible; and, a different conception of the role of law in society was advanced as crucial. Latin American lawyers and legal operators were urged to exchange their 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 43 professional tools for more pragmatic implements. While never really attaining much impact in Latin America, the Cold War project of law-anddevelopment quickly succumbed to its critics, not the least of whom were some of its very practitioners. For many, the end was the result of authoritarian Latin American governments and the manipulation of wellintentioned reforms. Development-style legal pragmatism, it seemed, simply lent credibility to the then reigning military rulers in the region, with its malleable conceptions of law and legitimacy. The traditional legal formalism of Latin America at least appeared to offer a way of holding an intractable law, with whatever protections and guarantees it offered, over authoritarian states and illegitimate regimes. For others, developmentalism failed because of the shortcomings of its proponents. Armed with an insufficient understanding of the workings of Latin American law, these early scholars are viewed in retrospect, by some, as not sufficiently attuned to local legal cultures. Notably, today’s neo-developmentalists stress this latter explanation for earlier failings and are quick to note, as a course correction, their now extensive collaboration with Latin American legal scholars and institutions and their current advisory rather than directing roles. In any case, while its immediate goals may have been foiled, the scholarship of developmentalism and the framework it erected for thinking about law in Latin America continue to have far-reaching effects. The images it created remain well-entrenched in the minds of U.S. academics and policy planners. First, while claiming to offer a realistic diagnosis of the failings of Latin American legal systems, developmentalists pressed a commonplace argumentative strategy. The gap between law and society, or the discrepancy between social and legal spheres, is a common trope throughout jurisprudence. Development experts pressed this image, though, as a way to usher in a series of broad-scale reforms. Purporting to align the legal system with social needs, they were able to launch changes in substantive law, legal education, and litigation, which would have in all likelihood been more difficult if introduced piecemeal and debated on their own merits through more open processes. Second, developmentalism’s deployment of social incongruity as the basis for its intervention has produced a sort of legal orientalism. That is, it has generated a depiction of law and society in Latin America which is quite indefensible as pure description: Law is presented as qualitatively distinct from social relations. In this same vein, Latin America is purported to be the site of more, and more divergent, legal pluralism than one would find elsewhere. This strategic portrayal of Latin America, more than just shoddy empiricism, has a perverse effect. It continually discredits Latin American legal institutions by calling for a different legal model, projected and idealized as truer to economic and social realities. Repeated iterations of these notions as empirical description have lodged these images as a 44 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 special peculiarity, or identity, of Latin American law. That is, the significant focus and writing on Latin America during the high period of developmentalism has had a profound influence on commonly-accepted notions about Latin American law and legal systems. More than at any other time, U.S. law reviews constructed the picture of a Latin American legality. Their central images, part of a rhetorical strategy, cemented the notions of an abnormal, Latin American gap between law and society and a culturally or socially distinct normativity peculiar to Latin American peoples. In this background way, 1960s developmentalism and its aftermath have structured the politics of law in Latin America for subsequent generations. Highlighting the dissonance between state law and social practice, as developmentalists did, has over time entrenched a deep skepticism as to the relevance and desirability of the former. Specifically, and here one of the main points of this Essay, it has led to increased disengagement by progressives with official legal discourse, especially with respect to struggles over the meaning of legal norms. And, it has skewed debates over the appropriate mix of regulatory versus informal mechanisms of societal governance. Progressives are led to advocate automatically and reflexively for the informal end of the equation, putting all stock in social-based solutions, understood as reflecting a distinct, identity-based normative system. By contrast, state law is identified with illegitimate elites and portrayed as mere ideological cover for the ruling classes. It is argued that a more effective and appropriate law should take its place—characterized as a more autochtonous law or, alternatively, modern law, the U.S. legal model, or transnational law. As such, engagement with state law is projected as a sterile endeavor, relegated to the ministrations and concerns of Latin American elites. In its place, attention is drawn to autochtonous social spheres of normativity or, alternatively, a foreign model. As a result, questions over informality or non-state intervention in certain areas of the economy and society are displaced, never taken up as issues of political and economic interests directly, but rather as matters of essentialist legal identities outside state law. The impact of developmentalism was also significant in other unexpected ways. Clearly, the call for a renegotiation of existing social and economic arrangements fell on deaf ears among Latin America’s legal traditionalists. They dismissed any such social-based argument and rather, if anything, cast it as political maneuvering and not serious legal reform. Responding to this marginalizing move over time, subsequent generations of progressives have—misdirectedly I argue below—pursued a strategy of separate but equal systems of legality, with social norms as the source of such separate systems and the banner for a populist legal politics. This approach, consisting of an acute emphasis on social practices, a 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 45 qualitatively distinct Latin American conception of law, and the idea of legal particularity across identity groups in the region—taken together, what I call the hyper-social—can be understood as a product of 1960s developmentalism. Its persistence as a progressive legal strategy, as well as its intrinsic marginality, is especially connected to the way in which legal developmentalism was successfully rebuffed. The notion of official law’s social incongruity, beyond just a formula for promoting the law-and-development program in the 1960s, has retained a special appeal in Latin America. Indeed, its general acceptance as uncontroversial diagnosis, for both the right and the left in legal politics terms, is a central topic of this Essay. The notion’s persistence might, at first blush, be seen as an open challenge to traditional Latin American jurists, a constant reminder of the fragility of national legal systems as against the overwhelming weight of divergent social forces. And indeed, neo-developmentalists continue to play on this image in just this way. Images produced by progressives in the 1960s serve just as well to push for a neoliberal renovation of Latin America’s discredited legal systems today; this time following the logic of the market rather than state-directed growth and redistribution. For progressives still operating under this same “development” framework, the usefulness of this strategy has long come to an end. It has induced new generations to engage in a prolonged and unfruitful search for the actual substantive content of Latin American social normativity. Instead of challenging traditionalist interpretations of official law, and openly questioning which sectors benefit from informality, demands are premised on a separate social code, typically posited and sought outside the official legal realm. Countless efforts have been expended in confirming the existence and substance of these separate codes. At the same time, the degree to which the Latin American gap between law and society is greater than elsewhere is repeatedly accentuated, and the static character and social irrelevance of state law reinforced. Official legal discourse, of course, remains central to the distribution and maintenance of economic, political and social power. It serves as a significant locus of societal struggle. State law’s interpretation and potential re-conceptualization, even if performed in outwardly opaque fashion, is a chief mode of social governance. It remains the site for advancing governance alternatives and cementing existing configurations. It is constitutive of the economy and society, and most importantly of sectors remaining outside direct state involvement. Furthermore, its role in structuring access to the global arena, by local interests and popular forces, while by no means exclusive, will surely remain considerable. Thus, to the extent developmentalism has swayed progressives to abandon their engagement with official legality, the effect has been to concede significant power. Freed of such academics and activists, traditional jurists can more 46 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 easily dominate legal interpretation. All the while, this dichomotization reinforces traditionalism’s monopoly over official law and its claims to a non-politicized legality—and thus to law, tout court. In this connection, a legacy of 1960s developmentalism is a more undemocratic legal discourse in Latin America. The effects mentioned above work a great disservice to the understanding of law in the region as well as to progressive intervention in this field. Abandoning official law to the most conservative actors within Latin America reinforces, if not produces, the very notion of its exclusivity to elite sectors. Furthermore, normalizing as fact a pathological disconnection between official law and local society undermines the legitimacy of law generally within popular consciousness, without any qualitatively better or less problematic substitute. Social normativity as an operational system, even if elevated to the rank of official law, cannot avoid on-going societal struggles over political conservatism, elite monopolies, and discursive hegemonies. None of these can be magically sidestepped. At most, social normativity offers a different terrain for these same battles. Moreover, the social field as deployed by progressives today does not serve them well. On the contrary, the discredit heaped on national legal systems has mostly worked to open the door to—or at least make it more difficult to resist—frequent proposals for transplants of foreign law or foreign models. While legal imports may not embody a determinate political valence (either multi-nationals or barrio dwellers might be benefitted in a particular instance), they typically do deprive local actors of transparent engagement with the political choices inherent in lawmaking. And, they fail to solve the proffered problem of legitimacy, said to consist of the current system of non-participative and mystified lawmaking, by replacing it with more of the same. In this Essay, I focus on the ideas about law in Latin America embedded in law and development scholarship of the 1960s and 1970s. I criticize the particular way in which these ideas have subsequently been given content. Additionally, I highlight their impact on legal thinking in and about Latin America. Finally, I describe alternative ways to conceive of the relationship between society and law in the region. While a significant body of neo-development scholarship has been produced in the last two decades, my aim is not to describe developmentalism over time, but rather to highlight the particular legacy of its earlier variety and the reactions it provoked in Latin America. I. THE 1960S-1970S LAW-AND-DEVELOPMENT PARADIGM My focus in this Part is to highlight the key ideas of the 1960s and 1970s law-and-development movement. Numerous theories about law’s relation to the economy and to society have been advanced throughout the 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 47 past century, including various theories finding favor within Latin America. Some of these overlap with the notions identified here.1 To the extent they coincide, this Essay then speaks to potentially multiple intellectual traditions. However, my line of analysis is U.S. law-anddevelopment. Different attempts have already been made at articulating its central paradigm.2 These have mostly focused on identifying the conceptual models and political forces that influenced developmentalists.3 My approach is quite different. It examines the rhetorical structures used by development scholars, the images drawn upon, and especially the framework they offer us for thinking about, and acting in relation to, Latin American law.4 Rather than characterizing “legal development” as some sort of system or model (even a highly variegated or multiply-defined one) in which the central question is its acceptance or rejection (even if this is considered in light of deeply local variables), I examine legal developmentalism as a set of argumentative structures, deployed at a moment in time by a group of legal professionals, to achieve their specific aims. The latter, simply put, consisted of exporting a part of U.S. legal discourse under the assumption it would support both economic growth and social justice. My objective in this Essay is to highlight the generic legal strategies that inform developmentalists’ “diagnosis” of Latin American law, to note 1. For example, the “alternative uses of law” movement within the Italian judiciary or the “Critique du droit” scholars in France, both important in the 1970s, present a number of complementary ideas about law. The specific contours of these and the uses made of them in Latin America are, however, subjects for other work. 2. See JAMES A. GARDNER, LEGAL IMPERIALISM: AMERICAN LAWYERS AND FOREIGN AID IN LATIN AMERICA (1980); Richard Bilder & Brian Z. Tamanaha, Book Review and Note Review Article, 89 AM J. INT’L L. 470 (1995) (reviewing 2 LAW AND DEVELOPMENT: LEGAL CULTURES (Anthony Carty ed., 1992) and LAW AND CRISIS IN THE THIRD WORLD (Sammy Adelman & Abdul Paliwala eds., 1993)). 3. See generally GARDNER, supra note 2 (presenting legal development as a system or model–a U.S. one–which was sought to be transferred to Latin America). Gardner’s account describes the failure of this project on the basis of the inherent vulnerabilites of the U.S. model and its manipulation “in tropic, authoritarian climates.” Id. at 11. Concededly, his account contains a nuanced description of the “model” and an contextualized account of the local, political, and legal culture. The approach here, however, offers an alternative way of understanding developmentalism and its failures. It resists characterizations of the development project as the U.S. legal model, as well as, it resists characterizing its non-favorable reception in Latin America as the result of Latin American legal or political culture. Instead, I present an account of the actors within legal and political circles who deploy cultural and legal arguments for and against different projects. 4. An immediate objection, and a routine one, to the notion “Latin American” or more specifically “Latin American law” is its imprecision. Indeed, the existence of any such thing is highly debated. Still, the concept has been used historically, as either referring to the identity of law in the region or to a particular political project (of course, these two are not by any means mutually exclusive). The analysis here is intended precisely to dismantle the specific meaning of “Latin American law” resulting from development scholarship. 48 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 their deployment of these arguments as empirical description of law and society in the region, and to remark on the effect that the continued acceptance of these ideas, as part of the nature of Latin American law, have on legal politics within Latin America. As a result, my analysis is concerned more with development scholarship than with particular projects proposed or implemented in Latin America. Of course, these are interrelated, as much of this scholarship describes then current or past projects. Another focus of my analysis is the reaction of traditional Latin American legal scholars to the project of developmentalism, as well as the lasting consequences of the development effort. Accordingly, I draw into consideration the reactions of Latin American jurists, as active interlocutors, and not simply as accepting or resisting of foreign aid. The demise of developmentalism in the 1970s cannot be explained solely in terms of cuts in assistance funding or political debates occurring in the United States—although these are important—but depends on the appeal and receptivity of the project in the legal political context of Latin America. This is quite different than saying that legal development or that a “U.S. model” was manipulated by Latin American dictators, thereby causing the project’s failure,5 or that Latin American legal culture is of a different quality—whether socially or culturally—rendering antiformalism or pragmatism impracticable. It highlights, instead, how Latin America’s legal intelligentsia reacted to an attempt to change the rules of the game. Law and development is more important, in Latin America, because of its failure than because of any significant impact of its programs. And, the end of developmentalism is meaningful because of the role it played within Latin American legal politics and because of the impact of its scholarship on persisting rhetorical constructions. Law-and-development was, for the most part, a politically progressive movement within the U.S. legal academy. Riding on the coattails of development economics, legal developmentalism went hand-in-hand with reformist approaches to social justice and the redistribution of wealth in Latin America. Political stability and economic growth were understood as inter-connected. Achieving both was U.S. policy in the 1960s, an 5. See GARDNER, supra note 2, at 5. The author blames the failings of developmentalism on the shortcomings of the U.S. legal model, but especially on the manipulability of U.S. style antiformalism in the Latin American context. See id. The analysis in both parts of the volume suggests that the American legal models carried abroad had built-in flaws and vulnerabilities, and that these surfaced and were clearly illuminated in the harsh exposure of the Third World. As shown in the case studies, the American legal models demonstrated a vulnerability to authoritarian ordering and abuse. Id. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 49 attempt to counter more revolutionary appeals such as the Cuban Revolution of 1959. Of course, developmentalists can be found in varying stripes.6 The movement became quite radicalized at both ends of the spectrum. On the right, economic progress turned into a justification for military governments and the systematic repression of social demands. Pinochet’s Chile is a bold example. It is mostly this version of developmentalism which survived through the 1980s. Right-wingers ultimately turned to private markets, instead of the military, as the discipline to produce economic growth. On the left, the promise of economic development came to be seen as illusory, the relationship between developed and underdeveloped countries more static and symbiotic than collaborative and evolutionary. Dependency theory drove these points home.7 Today, the progressives that are engaged in economic development debates work mostly from a defensive posture: arguing for some continuing role for the state over the market and highlighting the human toll of an unbridled economic logic. My portrayal of law-and-development scholarship here draws mostly from the progressive middle, and from the first wave of developmentalism, which constitutes the bulk of writing about Latin America in U.S. law reviews and reflects the most enduring images. Notably in the 1960s and 1970s, several legal casebooks were published in the United States, specifically on Latin America.8 They contain excerpts from various development scholars of the period in addition to their authors’ own views. These materials, as well as additional works cited, provide the basis for my analysis here. A. Social Theory of Law 6. See id. at 8. Gardner estimates that U.S. $5 million went to Latin American legal development from a variety of public and private sources, and that approximately fifty American legal professionals worked in Latin America. Id. 7. See, e.g., ESSAYS IN HONOR OF ANDRÉ GUNDER FRANK: THE DEVELOPMENT OF UNDERDEVELOPMENT (Sing C. Chew & Robert A. Denemark eds., 1996). 8. See HENRY P. DE VRIES & JOSÉ RODRIGUEZ-NOVÁS, THE LAW OF THE AMERICAS (1965) (containing information mostly on the subject of the Inter-American legal system, but dedicating a third to descriptions of law in Latin America); KENNETH L. KARST, LATIN AMERICAN LEGAL INSTITUTIONS: PROBLEMS FOR COMPARATIVE STUDY (1966); KENNETH L. KARST & KEITH S. ROSENN, LAW AND DEVELOPMENT IN LATIN AMERICA: A CASE BOOK (1975); JOHN H. MERRYMAN, THE LAWS OF WESTERN EUROPE AND LATIN AMERICA (1976) (including some development writing, however, responding to a very different tradition of scholarship about Latin America and fitting more traditionally within the project of depicting Latin American law as an extension of European law, which I have written about elsewhere.). See generally Jorge L. Esquirol, The Fictions of Latin American Law (Part I), 1997 UTAH L. REV. 425 (analyzing the role of “Europeanness” within Latin American law). 50 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 In the law-and-development movement, like any area of scholarship, its participants espoused a range of approaches to scholarship and to legal theory.9 In the main, however, the imprint of social-based approaches is unmistakable.10 Many development scholars were contemporaneously engaged in law-and-society groups, particularly active during that time.11 As such, a general description is possible. It is not an exhaustive description nor can it capture the complexity of any single scholar. Still, it conveys the most operational ideas of this moment in legal scholarship. That being said, some brief comments about social theories of law, in general, are in order. Evidence of the richness of legal theory, sociolegal discourse in some form is a significant complement to most modern 9. See Lawrence M. Friedman, On Legal Development, 24 RUTGERS L. REV. 11, 12 (1970) (arguing that, for the most part, developmentalists had no theory; “when the lawyer goes abroad, he sails into a vacuum. He takes with him nothing that can reasonably be called a careful, thought out, explicit theory of law and society or of law and development–nor does he find one at his destination.”). 10. See, e.g., Thomas M. Franck, The New Development: Can American Law and Legal Institutions Help Developing Countries?, 1972 WIS. L. REV. 767, 790. The precise role of lawyers in a given country emerges from the interaction of a variety of forces affecting that country, and, therefore, the kinds of roles lawyers play in national development ought to be viewed as a sociopolitical choice which each nation must make for itself . . . . [T]he means towards those ends employed by lawyers, laws, and legal institutions must be constantly updated to accord with the specific society, in all its multivarious complexity, and with each intricate, delicately balanced system of national goals and values. Id.; see also Dennis O. Lynch, Review Essay: Hundred Months of Solitude: Myth or Reality in Law and Development?, 1983 AM. B. FOUND. RES. J. 223, 226 (finding developmentalists’ inspiration in Karl Llewelyn’s lawyer as a social engineer: “He [Llewelyn] had an anthropological view of law, which argued that lawyers and judges should examine how behavior in actual social circumstances reflected societal values that should be incorporated into the legal order as working legal rules to guide future behavior.”). 11. See, e.g., Friedman, supra note 9, at 53 (stating “[t]he theory of law and development is only a special case, or corollary, of the theory of law and society.”); Lawrence M. Friedman, Legal Culture and Social Development, 4 LAW & SOC’Y REV. 29, 34, 43 (1969) (defining the “legal system” to mean the living law, “under the influence of external or situational factors, pressing in from the larger society”) [hereinafter Legal Culture]. Friedman considers the effectiveness of such a system as its ability to process demands for change while maintaining stability. See id. In this connection, he calls for more empirical study of the legal culture as the main factor determining effectiveness: “What is the living law of the provinces, or the streets, or the corporation, in comparison to the law on the books?” Id. at 43; see also Kenneth L. Karst, Law in Developing Countries, 60 LAW LIBR. J. 13, 16 (1967) (highlighting the unevenness of law’s application in developing countries (based on class membership) as contrary to a “development-conducive state of mind.”). Karst sees law’s role in development as principally one of “legitimating change” needed to effect the social transformations required to apply law equally to all. See id. at 16. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 51 conceptions of law.12 While no single generalization captures the variety of theories on the nexus of law and society, the familiar dualism offers a ready source of legal authority. It signifies a separate field of societal interaction whence organic norms can be unearthed.13 It may also be used to draw into consideration, within the context of legal decisionmaking, the formal law’s practical effects on society.14 In both cases, the purported link to popular society provides an ostensibly democratic justification for its relevance. Expanding legal decisionmaking, in this way, to include social aspects enlarges the set of technologies available to legal operators beyond the traditional modes of conceptualism and deductivism or naturalism and positivism. Also significant, social-based theories offer a way to challenge existing rules or interpretations of rules. An account of prevailing social realities may, for example, be introduced within legal analysis to argue the obsolete nature of current legal rules. It may be used in favor of a new policy direction, arguably more in keeping with societal needs, over others. Or, it may be used to marshal images of societal ill-adaptedness and thus an explanation for the failure of conventional legal formulas. Of course, the method can also be deployed to uphold the underlying legitimacy of existing laws. Images of society can also be produced to justify the seamlessness and cultural coincidence of legal norms and societal practices. Social accounts of law are actually quite standard within most modern legal systems. As such, they often stand for nothing more than the dominant understanding. Thus, while social argument can often be an 12. Clearly, sociolegal discourse is also often directed at debates within sociology, generally speaking. This Essay is limited to considering sociolegal debate within the traditional field of law and not as a basis for intervention in the social sciences. 13. See, e.g., EUGEN EHRLICH, FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE SOCIOLOGY OF LAW 119-20 (Walter L. Moll trans., 1936) (defending a theory of social and economic associations as the basis for legal as well as extra-legal norms). Ehrlich demonstrates how it would be quite impossible to understand legal rules without reference to this underlying realm of “facts of the law.” Id. And every new development which arises for new purposes, and which stands the test of time, is added to the treasure of social norms, and serves to guide later associations. There is an endless and uninterrupted process of adaptation to new needs and situations, in which is embodied, at the same time, the development of the human race and of its norms. It may suffice to instance the great number of new norms, not only of law, but also of morals, ethical custom, honor, good manners, tact, and perhaps, at least in a certain sense, etiquette and fashion . . . . Id. 14. While both formulations taken together may seem contradictory, in terms of law as either a dependent or independent variable, Lawrence Friedman describes that even scholars considering law a secondary aspect of society, such as Marxists, believe that once law acquires an independent existence, it may exert reflex influence upon the foundation. See Friedman, supra note 9, at 54. 52 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 effective tool for reform, it is just as often part of the legitimating rhetoric of established positions. Scholars of the 1960s and 1970s were clearly interested in the question of development.15 While the term came to encompass a range of meanings, key to its understanding was more, and more equitable, economic growth.16 Working from the discipline of law, legal developmentalists struggled with the relationship between economic and other sorts of development and the legal system.17 Convinced that a link existed, they charged ahead with projects of legal reform with the objective of promoting economic as well as political development.18 Their writing about Latin America, the focus of this Essay, built a consensus of sorts on the ills of then contemporary systems of Latin American law.19 These ideas, sketched out below, inform most writing about Latin America, and they continue to do so today. They influence the type of legal reforms often insisted upon by international organizations and foreign governments for the region. They also condition 15. See Carl A. Auerbach, Legal Development in Developing Countries: The American Experience, 63 PROC. AM. SOC’Y OF INT’L L. 81 (1969). 16. See Franck, supra note 10, at 772-73 (describing “new” development (the 1960s and 1970s kind) as interested in social welfare and popular participation; “popular participation makes for better development than does elitist autocracy–better qualitatively and, ultimately, better quantitatively.”); see also Friedman, supra note 9, at 13-14 (stating, “‘[D]evelopment’ . . . refers to any process of growth or change; and at the same time it means a special kind of favorable growth, on the model of the so called developed countries.”). 17. See Auerbach, supra note 15, at 82 (stating “legal scholarship in our country has contributed little upon which to build a theory of ‘legal development’ or to offer advice as to how legal institutions may be used to foster the modernization process . . . legal scholars are beginning to pay attention to the problem of legal development; those who have worked in developing nations are reflecting upon their experiences and writing about them”); see also L. Michael Hager, The Role of Lawyers in Developing Countries, 58 A.B.A. J. 33, 33 (1972) (stating “the neglect of law in development studies reflects uncertainty as to its ultimate contribution. The question for some observers is not simply a matter of degree but whether the law is an ally of development or an enemy.”). 18. See Franck, supra note 10, at 788. Of course, we have recognized the role played by law and lawyers in facilitating development in the United States. We would also accept the assertion that law is everywhere an essential instrument of government. But good law aids development; archaic law hinders it. Good lawyers help, bad lawyers do not. Id. 19. My use of the term “Latin American law” is subject to much debate. It suggests a common system of law throughout Latin America or, at a minimum, a view of law’s key characteristics as consisting of transnational similarities. Indeed, facile use of this phrase may signal complicity in the strategic use of the idea of transnational law, which I attribute to the dominant Latin American legal discourse (principally by reference to a transnational European law) and which I have criticized elsewhere. However, my use of the term here simply reflects the historical fact of the category and attempts to explore the strategic uses to which it has been put. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 53 the types of projects supported by non-governmental organizations in their efforts to promote change. Most importantly, they impact the legal strategies available for progressive positions. B. Gap Between Law and Society Developmentalists were in accord that a wide rift existed in Latin America between state law as enacted and the way people behave.20 The relationship between law and society, law-and-development’s central premise even if not fully understood, thus consisted of a vast disconnection between the two in Latin America. This discrepancy is central to a range of scholarship on agrarian reform,21 economic regulation,22 urban squatter settlements,23 legal aid services,24 legal education,25 and the legal culture.26 20. See Marc Galanter, The Modernization of Law, in MODERNIZATION: THE DYNAMICS OF GROWTH 153 (Myron Weiner ed., 1966). Galanter—not focusing on Latin America in particular in this piece–describes the law-and-society shibboleth of a “dualistic legal situation.” See id. The innovation is not the discovery of a gap between lawyers’ law and popular law (or law in books and law in action); gaps exist in most systems of law. See id. at 157-58. The interesting point, according to Galanter, is the particular way which “modern law” attempts to deal with this gap and the underlying local, legal tradition it evidences. See id. at 158-65. In his estimation, it is to suppress and replace it: “[o]ur model pictures a machinery for the relentless imposition of prevailing central rules and procedures over all that is local and parochial and deviant.” Id. at 157. “The law on the books does not represent the attitudes and concerns of the local people. . . . The law in operation is always a compromise between lawyers’ law and parochial notions of legality.” Id. at 162. [L]aws were frequently imported from foreign legal systems without consideration of their appropriateness to Brazilian society, and in a good many areas, laws are so out of touch with social reality that the society is able to function at all only by ignoring the law or on the basis of the jeito, a highly prized national institution for bypassing the formal legal structure. Keith S. Rosenn, The Reform of Legal Education in Brazil, 21 J. LEGAL EDUC. 251, 254 (1969). 21. See Joseph R. Thome, The Process of Land Reform in Latin America, 1968 WIS. L. REV. 9, 22. But if the legal system and its institutions are to play an effective role in the process of reform, then the lawyers who shape its form and susbstance must become painfully aware of the actual social and economic conditions they would change. Only then will they realize that traditional legal methods may actually frustrate the process of reform, and that the legal process, at least in this area, may have to take strange and unfamiliar but yet effective and equitable forms. Id. 22. See Dale B. Furnish, The Hierarchy of Peruvian Laws: Context for Law and Development, 19 AM. J. COMP. L. 91 (1971). 23. See generally Kenneth A. Manaster, The Problem of Urban Squatters in Developing Countries: Peru, 1968 WIS. L. REV. 23, 61 (praising the 1961 Peruvian Barriadas Law: “The kind of pragmatic, imaginative adaptation of old legal concepts to new problems which we see in this 54 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 Without attempting an exhaustive description of all these works, the key throughout is that official law is out of step with society. A formalistic and ritualistic legal tradition, based on foreign, European models, is determined to be a key obstacle to development, if not an outright bulwark of the status quo. Additionally, the actual social practices of Latin Americans are presented as reflecting a distinct realm, separate and distinguishable from state law. The disconnectedness of law to society was highlighted, within developmentalist writings, to demonstrate the ineffectiveness of state legal systems. In their place, a modern law capable of promoting development was proposed. Developmentalist efforts spanned a broad range, including both formal and informal strategies. Legislation for agrarian reform programs and urban settlements was advanced. Antitrust and securities law regimes were devised. Legal education, especially, was targeted. Some scholars emphasized the mentality of development. Setting proper incentives and drawing from local codes of conduct—development from the bottom—were highlighted. The prominence of the informal sector was studied. Informality provided a gauge on the motivations and values of local actors. It was also typically characterized as the by-product or result of an ill-functioning formal legal sector. A more effective modern law, or law is the kind of first step which Peru and many other countries must take if they wish to begin to confront the squatter crises effectively, peacefully, and fairly within the framework of legal systems which are both progressive and just.”). 24. See Barry Metzger, Legal Services to the Poor and National Development Objectives, in COMMITTEE ON LEGAL SERVICES TO THE POOR IN THE DEVELOPING COUNTRIES, LEGAL AID AND WORLD POVERTY: A SURVEY OF ASIA, AFRICA, AND LATIN AMERICA 10 (1974) (stating “the formal legal systems of most developing nations are derived from Western models imperfectly adapted to distinctive local conditions. Not surprisingly, this has resulted in the failure of certain laws to function as intended and in large gaps between popularly accepted behavior and legal norms.”). 25. See, e.g., Jorge Witker, Derecho, desarrollo y formación jurídica, 24 REVISTA DE LA FACULTAD DE DERECHO DE MÉXICO 659, 670 (1974) (giving, as an example of the gap between law and society, the supposition in the law which is “not empirically proven, that the family in Latin America is structured in general by way of the marriage tie. Sporadic studies of legal sociology in small communities have detected the existence of a multitude of extra-legal unions, which lack any legal provision regulating them.”). Statements such as these can be made of any place at any time. The “gap” here is merely an argumentative device, which can in this same fashion be deployed in most any setting. Here, it is used to argue for a change in legal education and more social and economic policy-oriented judicial decisionmaking. 26. See Frank Griffith Dawson, Labor Legislation and Social Integration in Guatemala: 1871-1944, 14 AM. J. COMP. L. 124 (1965). Dawson describes how Guatemalan labor legislation is starkly at odds with Indian goals, values, and traditional hierarchy. See id. Dawson seems to argue against this destruction of “pluralism” by the state. See id. Indeed, his characterization of a cruel and oppressive official system makes this point. See id. Yet, in a footnote he states “[d]espite [its] perils, however, the demise of pluralism is to be welcomed.” Id. at 142 n.86. For him, it is in this way that Latin American states will become national societies. See id. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 55 the promise of it, was by contrast a way of legitimizing the political and economic proposals advanced by developmentalists.27 By contrast, references to social or informal legality encompassed a variety of different meanings across the range of development writing. When filling a relatively minor role in specific work, the notion of the social order generally refers to a source of additional norms, derived from observable social interactions, social values, and attitudes28—themselves derived from morality,29 religion, community, and other systems of coercion.30 Under this formulation, the claim is that the formal law does not satisfactorily describe, and could not describe, the entire legal system.31 27. See, e.g., Legal Culture, supra note 11, at 43-44 (stating “[n]o community or group is truly lawless. But if law is defined as the formal law of the capital or the rulers, then in every country there are lawless groups and territories . . . . Pluralism . . . is not merely a structural matter. It rests on cultural differences.”); see also generally Hager, supra note 17. 28. See, e.g., Kenneth L. Karst & Norris C. Clement, Legal Institutions and Development: Lessons from the Mexican Ejido, 16 UCLA L. REV. 281 (1968) (focusing on the specific economic decisions confronting ejido (community-held land, which is parceled out to individual farmers to work) members in Mexico and arguing for legal reform, to better secure land tenure, based on the “small-scale” perspective of the ejido farmer’s social and economic constraints). While the authors recognize the political interests aligned against reform and the legal arguments they invoke, they do not address them directly or suggest direct engagement to counteract them. See generally id. Instead, they advance their argument by urging the “small-scale” perspective as better suited to development. See id. at 302-03. 29. See, e.g., Norman S. Poser, Securities Regulation in Developing Countries: The Brazilian Experience, 52 VA. L. REV. 1283, 1294 (1966) (stating “[t]he developmental purpose of the program and the gap between business morality and the standards that are necessary for the existence of mature capital markets create special difficulties in formulating and enforcing these standards”). 30. See, e.g., Kenneth L. Karst, Rights in Land and Housing in an Informal Legal System: The Barrios of Caracas, 19 AM. J. COMP. L. 550, 569 (1971) (describing the customary or informal law of the urban barrio in Caracas). Karst’s analysis is an example of the use of a separate social sphere as a source of alternative legal norms. See generally id. He argues that “barrio law” should be considered as official law. See id. at 569-70. His argument is explicitly directed at those, within Venezuela or outside, who believe that barrios are simply an example of a legal void, where official law has yet to penetrate. See generally id. His rationale is that this informal, barrio law provides for land tenure stability for urban squatters, which has the effect of promoting investment in their dwellings and thus promotes development. See id. at 569. Of course, the official property regime also has the same objective of providing for stability. Solely on the principle of stability required for development, arguments can be made either for or against barrio law. In fact, barrio law’s purported guarantee of stability is predicated on the government’s decision not to enforce official laws because of political reasons, thereby keeping barrio law and urban squatters in a precarious position even if they feel secure as a matter of their “state of mind.” According to Karst, however, “the security that is relevant to development is the state of mind of the developmental decisionmaker.” Id. 31. See, e.g., Friedman, supra note 9, at 29. [Legal culture] includes all the relevant social values and attitudes that influence 56 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 Simply enough, other criteria must be considered. These may, alternatively, supplement existing laws, provide for other better rules, or assist in understanding the causes for official law’s breakdown. In other works of development, the social law plays a larger role. In these cases, the social field signifies a thickly populated set of autonomous cultural norms. Qualitatively different from state law, this notion of social law designates an alternative system more organically connected to the societal group.32 Under this formulation, the claim is that social groups hold such norms irrespective and possibly independent of state law. In its strongest terms, social law is presented as a potential substitute for the state. The scale of legal diversity identified also varies within development scholarship. It may refer to particular norms of a group or community within a specific area. Some development and development-paradigm studies, in fact, focused on systems of normativity within smaller-scale communities: urban barrio dwellers,33 rural localities,34 indigenous settlements, and others. Alternatively, it may refer to the vastly different levels of state presence throughout one country or in Latin America as a whole. In the aggregate, nonetheless, these works offer the picture of a broadly plural social sphere. Every Latin American country has a large body of formal national law on the books—and has had, at least from the mid-19th Century. Still, the vertical segmentation highlighted by Wiarda [i.e.,“a number of corporate elites and intereses”] persists, stubbornly resisting the establishment of truly national legal universalism. The moral communities, in other words, are national communities only with respect to a relatively limited number of kinds of transactions and relationships. A perspective that emphasizes participatory development, however, permits us at least to speculate that a “horizontally” oriented idea of community may grow at a grass-roots level, with legal institutions playing their expected role: defining communities, providing channels for law but cannot be deduced from its structure and substance. These include respect for law or the lack of it, whether people readily use their courts, their officials, or prefer informal ways of solving problems, and attitudes and demands upon law posed by different ethnic groups, races, religions, occupations and social classes. Id. 32. See, e.g., Keith S. Rosenn, The Jeito: Brazil’s Institutional Bypass of the Formal Legal System and its Developmental Implications, 19 AM. J. COMP. L. 514, 515 (1971). 33. See Karst, supra note 30, at 569-70; see generally also Manaster, supra note 23, at 61. 34. Karst & Clement, supra note 28, at 282-302. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 57 group effort, providing training in cooperation and leadership.35 This diverse society is consistently presented as sharing one commonality, its radical distinctness from the official legal culture. C. Arcane and Formalist State Law In terms of existing law, developmentalism emphasized the ineffectiveness of Latin American legal systems, alien to the social particularities of Latin American peoples.36 Rather than emphasize the multiple and competing governance projects at work in the arena of state law, drawing on both formalist and antiformalist methodological discourses,37 developmentalists painted with a broader brush. They depicted official legality as simultaneously anachronous, malfunctioning, and marginal. They presented the picture of an unredeemably dysfunctional legal system, and they drew on a variety of images to do so. The charge raised by developmentalists has the effect of drawing into question the conventional repertoire of Latin American legal technologies. It questions its capacity to represent, and perform, legal decisionmaking in transparent, rational, and accessible forms. Latin American legal discourse indeed reflects a relatively complex argumentative style.38 Drawing on European scholars and foreign models, legal operators frame their arguments in outwardly circuitous and arcane elocutions. In general, the dominant mode of legal reasoning advances specific legal positions on the basis of foreign authorities and legislative developments in Europe and North America, that is to say, on interpretations of foreign jurists and characterizations of international developments. This does not mean that legal argument is necessarily any less strategized nor reflective of particular local interests. Foreign authorities are sufficiently abundant, and their interpretations sufficiently pliable, to provide a basis for multiple positions. 35. KARST & ROSENN, supra note 8, at 675 (footnote omitted). 36. See id. 37. See, e.g., Rosenn, supra note 32, at 533-34. Rosenn readily accepts that formalism, as a legal methodology, may be marshaled to frustrate social change; however, he does not recognize that it can also be the basis for projects of nation-building and even economic development. See id. 38. See Diego E. López Medina, Comparative Jurisprudence: Reception and Misreading Transnational Legal Theory in Latin America (2002) (unpublished S.J.D. Dissertation, Harvard University) (on file with the author) (Demonstrating this complexity, foreign legal authorities must be marshaled and aligned with an advocate’s position. Sources concerned with vastly different issues and particularities in their own countries must be refitted to provide the rule for the case at hand. Additionally, the typical legal argument contains a hodge-podge of cites, seeking to win the battle of foreign authorities.). 58 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 It does raise the question, however, which will be discussed further below, of the outward effects of this dominant mode of legal reasoning. Even if the array of local political choices may be fully represented, the need to marshal European precedents or transnational jurists in their defense may undermine, in the aggregate, a system of democratic law. Law is mystified by being presented as beyond local agency and individual objectives. The different outcomes in question are eclipsed by discussions of foreign jurists. Additionally, certain interests may more easily trump others absent a more transparent, democratic discourse. The quite indeterminate discourse of juristic authority, paradoxically, makes it easier to defend idiosyncratic results. Furthermore, allocating societal goods without reference to social consequences or local equities relieves the decision-maker of a level of democratic constraints, even if the constraint is only to craft the decision within the discourse of democratic constraint. Not so attuned to the intricacies, however, developmentalists mostly depicted the official Latin American legal systems as a hold-over from formalism of an earlier era. The legal system was pictured as a relic, not unlike classical legal formalism at the turn of the twentieth century in the United States. Albeit, Latin American formalism was understood as reflecting civilian rather than common law forms. Typical common law prejudices about civilian legal systems were raised. For example, ideas about the rigidity of code law and the isolation of the deductive method from social reality were added to the causes of Latin America’s anachronistic law.39 Historical narratives were introduced to support claims of the region’s tradition of ineffective legality. The mass of colonial laws and regulations, unassimilable and contradictory, were used to show the parallel with contemporary forms.40 Sociological narratives, today quite suspect, were raised to argue the characteristics of societies impacted by Spanish and Portuguese mores, and thus to explain Latin Americans’ predispositions to circumvent official law.41 Somewhat understandably, legal technique in Latin America reinforced this perception. Clearly, legal discourse consisting of citations to foreign 39. See KARST & ROSENN, supra note 8, at 45-47, 61-62. 40. See, e.g., DE VRIES & RODRIGUEZ-NOVÁS, supra note 8, at 161-73. The colonial heritage of Hispanic America with its special techniques of adjustment to harsh measures persists in the present-day civic irresponsibility, if not outright evasion of obligations to the community . . . . The Hispanic American legal tradition is a blend of formal adherence to representative democracy and respect for written law isolated from social factors . . . . Id. at 168. “[T]hough the forms of constitutional government have long been present, the sociological basis for effective implementation of written words is often lacking.” Id. at 172. 41. See id. at 161-71. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 59 jurists and transnational legislative developments recalls an outdated theory on the nature of law. The notion of Latin American law’s foreignness is also supported by the traditional comparative law scholarship on the region.42 The legal systems of Latin American countries are generally described as faithful imitations of continental European models. Particularly in terms of private law, the resemblance between Latin American legal codes and legislation and their European counterparts is well noted. Continental legal sources and juristic authorities are understood as the bases of legal argument within Latin America. Additionally, the United States is generally recognized as the source of most of the region’s constitutional law. These characterizations of imitativeness or transplantedness are not, however, intended as criticism. Many comparativists and Latin American jurists, on the contrary, laud the transnational commonality and, indeed, point to it to justify the legitimacy and objectivity of the region’s laws. In addition, much comparative scholarship about Latin America reinforces the idea of the region’s official legality as merely a brand of legal formalism. The eminent, Austrian jurist Hans Kelsen is often presented as a sufficient and exhaustive description of Latin America’s legal consciousness. Mainstream analyses signal the larger-than-life impact of this European jurist.43 For many commentators, after citing Kelsen no more need be said. For them, Kelsen is a shorthand for describing a system of positive law formalism, essentially a belief in the hierarchical sources of legal authority—from regulations to statutes to constitutions—and the law as a relatively autonomous system—the pure theory of law. Kelsen, coupled with a Spanish, scholastic past often constitutes the extent of explanation of Latin America’s official legality. Its natural law and deductive logic tradition is simply understood to be updated by reference to Kelsen’s theory of graduated legal sources and the autonomy of law from other spheres of social life. Other analyses demonstrate a more varied picture. Despite Kelsen’s great influence, other figures have been instrumental.44 And, more importantly, Kelsen himself has been used to stand for many different propositions and many different interventions within legal argument and 42. See generally MERRYMAN, supra note 8. 43. See, e.g., Furnish, supra note 22, at 92. Furnish gives pride of place to Hans Kelsen. Id. He in fact wholly adopts this framework to describe the workings of Peru’s administrative law structure: “The lawyer interested in law and development should follow that trail to see laws in action, for in Peru and other developing nations the most important source of developmental policy is the Executive.” Id. at 111. Furnish adopts both the “gap” metaphor and the notion of official law’s Kelsenianism at face value. See generally id. 44. See, e.g., CARLOS S. NINO, INTRODUCCIÓN AL ANÁLISIS DEL DERECHO (1983). 60 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 legal politics.45 Attempting to understand Latin American law solely through one’s view of Kelsen would be unsatisfactory and misleading. Kelsen does not describe the full workings of Latin American legal systems. Rather, much legal argument and legal projects citing Kelsen as authority for myriad propositions are but some of the elements of Latin American legal reasoning. In any case, whether or not Latin American law can be unproblematically characterized as a transplant from other political societies or the spitting image of Kelsen is part of the same argumentative repertoire. The affirmative side of the debate, it is worth noting, generally upholds a view of law as a coherent whole, capable of being transported to different locations while working in much the same way. Even modified versions of this point, where foreign laws are said to be adapted to the Latin American context, reinforce the same notion that law is mostly autonomous of local actors. By contrast, Latin American law may be understood quite differently. Its foreign borrowings may respond to different political or strategic motivations. Use of those materials may be intimately tied to local interests and cultural politics. Outwardly foreign sources may be used quite differently and for different reasons in local settings. This debate, however, makes little sense in the abstract. Both sides are already sufficiently well-known terrains. Either vision can offer the background scenario for or against a particular political position within some specific debate.46 What is relevant to this discussion, however, is that 1960s/1970s developmentalists deployed the characterizations of foreignness and formalism. And, they pressed them as system-wide critiques. The formal legal system was presented in two ways. It was portrayed as ill-fitting and anachronous, adrift in stultified European (and old U.S.) models.47 This imported law was contrasted to the very different lived realities of actual Latin American peoples. At the same time, official law was identified as reflective of the interests of a small elite within these countries. This latter point would seem to show the opposite, its local ties, notwithstanding the unsurprising fact that the legal system benefits some at the expense of 45. See BORDA KELSEN, EN COLOMBIA (1991). 46. At the risk of getting ahead of myself, I simply make a cursory note here: One of the points of this Essay is that the particular form of traditional legal discourse in Latin America rejects part of this argumentative repertoire. It reinforces necessitarian univocalism by disqualifying arguments that openly acknowledge the multiple positions and interpretations available from traditional legal materials, that is, from citations to foreign jurists and foreign sources. 47. See, e.g., Dale B. Furnish, Chilean Antitrust Law, 19 AM. J. COMP. L. 464 (1971) (decrying the irrelevance of anti-trust laws as a result of Chile’s social and economic realities). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 61 others. The contradiction, however, is downplayed by the suggestion that Latin American elites (or those benefitted) are foreign just as well.48 In any case, developmentalists criticized the legal system’s economic effects and attributed this to an operational incapacity to align judicial decisions with national, social, and economic policy. In an era of changing economic measures, policy enthusiasts were loathe to be frustrated by local judges. Absent legal decisions aligned with the development consensus, however, local judiciaries threatened the effective implementation of national economic objectives. In this regard, the dominant legal technologies, it was argued, were insufficiently calibrated to assure the survival of development policies. As such, the technologies were slated for reform. Developmentalism embraced the prescription of updating Latin American legal theory.49 Introducing pragmatism to law schools and the courts, as mentioned already, was the goal. It was assisted by claims of improving access to the social norms of Latin American peoples; better reflecting the social realities and cultural identity of the nation; and embodying the internal conceptions and choices of local society. Developmentalists—most of them faithful believers in the sociological underpinnings of law—were quick to demonstrate the influence of society on law and vice versa. The whole of their project was based on the belief that development could be engineered through law. Yet, this truism turned out not to be a belief about all legal systems. Legal systems might be a product of their societies, and then again they might not. In Latin America, the sociological truth marshaled by developmentalists was that the legal system was not.50 There, the mass of law was presented as unmoored from 48. This point is reinforced by the role ascribed within dependency theory to Latin America’s comprador class, essentially local elites identified with the economically powerful in the developed world, or unscrupulous intermediaries in the incessant siphoning of wealth from the undeveloped to the developed world. See DAVID LEHMANN, DEMOCRACY AND DEVELOPMENT IN LATIN AMERICA: ECONOMICS, POLITICS AND RELIGION IN THE POST-WAR PERIOD 20-26 (1990). In a footnote, Lehman explains “the term seems to have originated in South-East Asia where it refers to nonindigenous merchant groups with a distinctive ethnic (Chinese, Indian, European) identity.” Id. at 26 n.21. 49. This prescription is not limited to 1960s law and development. Recent writings by the head of the World Bank’s legal division, Ibrahim Shihata, prescribes the same remedy not only for Latin America but around the world. See, e.g., Ibrahim F.I. Shihata, The Role of Law in Business Development, 20 FORDHAM INT’L L.J. 1577, 1577-78 (1997). Shihata advocates a turn to legal realism by local judiciaries. See id. at 1581-83. The rationale clearly stated is that realist judges will be better able to implement national economic goals at the micro level. See id. at 1582-83. 50. See, e.g., GARDNER, supra note 2, at 267. Although there is oversimplification in this analysis of a single and impedimental role of the exported formal legal system, it illuminates a particular “law-againstlaw” conflict, in this case between the formal legal system on the one hand and the informal law of the society or the instrumental laws of emerging states on the 62 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 the mass of society. Depictions of urban barrios, peasant communities, and other “informal” sectors, by contrast, were used to demonstrate both the truth of this assertion and, for some scholars, the alternative resources within society (or informal law) available to development planners, including economic incentives and goal-setting values of social groups. Of course, the unproblematic way in which the law-and-society dichotomy was expressed, as both irreconcilable and necessarily symbiotic, signals the strategic use made of this formula. D. Legal Informality as an Argument for Development Politics The characterization of a gap between law and society is not peculiar to Latin America nor is this notion particular to law and development. On the contrary, it is a methodological convention which boasts a long history. The notion of a different lived experience of the law is highlighted and instrumentalized for purposes of legal reform. In the Anglo-American tradition, it is generally attributed to sociological jurisprudence, spearheaded by Roscoe Pound before World War I.51 The most common association with the concept is embodied in the slogan: “law in the books and law in action.”52 According to Morton Horwitz, it was originally employed for the purpose of criticizing nineteenth and early twentieth century orthodox legal thought.53 The underlying notion, that law can become disconnected from social reality, was also the springboard for American legal realism.54 A more controversial version of progressivism than sociological jurisprudence,55 realism had an indelible influence on other. In these conflicts the law and development movement did not find the formal legal system uniformly on the side of developmental change; on the contrary, legal formalism again demonstrated a considerable capacity to complicate social relationships and to delay and inhibit broader social change. Id. 51. See MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW 1870-1960: THE CRISIS OF LEGAL ORTHODOXY 169-71 (1992). Horwitz downplays the controversy typically cited between sociological jurisprudence and legal realism; on the contrary, he suggests “both intellectual movements should be understood as sub-categories of pre- and post-World War I Progressive legal thought, and Legal Realism needs to be seen primarily as a continuation of the reformist attack on orthodox legal thought.” Id. at 171. 52. See Roscoe Pound, Law in Books and Law in Action, 44 AM. L. REV. 12 (1910). 53. See HORWITZ, supra note 51, at 188. 54. See id. at 187-88. 55. See id. Indeed, it was the very slogan, “law in books and law in action,” which became the target for legal realists in the 1930s. One of the principal figures of American legal realism, Karl Llewelyn, rose to prominence by critiquing the unfulfilled potential of sociological jurisprudence to reform the “law in books.” See id. at 170-82. Pound’s handiwork for all its reformist pedigree and potential had by the 1930s “a tendency toward idealization of some portion of the status quo at any given time.” Id. at 174. Realism, according to Horwitz, presented a real threat to the then 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 63 U.S. legal thought. In fact, one is hard pressed to describe legal consciousness in this country without reference to its main tenets. For lawand-society scholars, as direct heirs to realism, “gap” studies were central to their work. Measuring the relative distance between formal law and societal behavior was instrumental in calibrating law as a tool of social engineering. It is thus not surprising that 1960s developmentalists, many of them North Americans, highlighted the relatively “unrealist” cast of Latin American legal culture and the wide gap between law and society: In Latin America, however, governmental administration has, from the very beginning, been incorporated into the prevailing system of patronage. Nepotism, for example, which seems almost sinful in the Anglo-American world, is widely regarded in Latin America as a social duty. Monopoly privilege is at least as old as the Conquest; Queen Isabella sought from the outset to limit the exploitation of the New World to her own subjects—not even to Spaniards generally, but to subjects of Castile. In Latin America, it is sometimes said, mercantilism never died. Given this history, it has been argued that the very idea of “rights” in Latin America is meaningful largely in terms of group privileges, as distinguished from individual rights. Legal universalism is thus seen as a dream—and perhaps a North American dream at that—rather than even a potential reality in Latin America.56 It is also this “informal” feature which they invested with great significance.57 The Director General of the International Labor Office, Wilfred Jenks, speaking in Costa Rica in 1972, was rather clear about it: The most renown legal thinkers in Latin America in recent times, men of the stature of Luis Recaséns Siches, Carlos Cossio y Eduardo García Maynez, have been essentially philosophers of the tradition of Kelsen rather than architects and engineers of social change through the legal process in the fashion of Roscoe Pound. There has not been a contemporary Andrés Bello, with the universal scholarity of legal system’s self-sustaining tropes of principled deduction and legal objectivity. See id. at 187-92. Sociological jurisprudence ultimately became a way to defend the even-handedness of legal rules by pointing to their source as observable human interaction as opposed to questionable human logic or doubtful neutrality. 56. See, e.g., KARST & ROSENN, supra note 8, at 639 (footnotes omitted). 57. See, e.g., DE VRIES & RODRIGUEZ-NOVÁS, supra note 8, at 193. “Particularly in codes containing a high proportion of terse, abstract statements of principles rather than detailed rules, the power to interpret becomes, in practice, the power to create ‘law in action.’” Id. 64 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 a grand humanist conceiving of law as, essentially, a branch of the art of statesmanship. What is required are public figures of their stature in order to place law as an effective instrument of social change at the center of thought and practice in Latin America.58 This discussion, among other things, highlights the “methods reform” advanced by legal developmentalists. Methods reform is a shorthand way of describing a range of proposals advanced by various scholars of this period. In the aggregate, their proposals not surprisingly suggest emulating U.S-like legal reasoning.59 Latin American legal operators were urged to adopt the United States’ particular form of legal discourse (or what developmentalists understood that to be).60 Describing the characteristics of this latter notion would obviously be the subject for a body of scholarship in its own right. However, one element of this discourse, which 58. Wilfred Jenks, El derecho y el cambio social en el pensamiento y la práctica de América Latina, in REVISTA DE CIENCIAS JURÍDICAS 307, 310 (1972) (author’s translation). Jenks also relates that: In this respect [i.e. providing for change within law as a response to social conflict], a large measure of change has been produced in the content and primordial tendencies of Latin American law during the preceding generation. “Social law” has become a part of unceasingly growing importance in law as a whole . . . . So transformed to its social function, [law] enjoys a positive potential for social change of vast reach, which earlier generations would have doubted with profound skepticism. Id. at 313 (author’s translation). 59. See GARDNER, supra note 2, at 34. The end result was a law and development movement that lacked many of the preconditions for direct legal transfer and turned instead to the task—the difficult task—of indirectly transferring abstract American legal models and concepts that were neither invited nor imposed, but rather infused, through American legal assistance. Id. 60. See, e.g., KARST & ROSENN, supra note 8, at 646. But in our zeal to be realistic, we should not overlook the obvious and central fact that an enormous portion of every legal system in the “developed” world is exceedingly coherent and knowable. (Our own legal education, which still centers on developing analytical skills, is misleading in this respect, for it consistently focuses on problem situations, while most transactions and relationships are “easy cases.”) Consider, in contrast, . . . Brazil. Id. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 65 can be safely asserted, is that there is no, or at least need not be, overarching theory encompassing all legal reasoning. On the contrary, legal reasoning is, above all else, grounded in local social realities and discrete policy objectives. To this end, developmentalists were active in promoting a new curriculum for Latin American law schools.61 Changing legal methods and reasoning habits required modifying them at their source.62 Take for example, Edward Laing, speaking of Colombia: 61. See Rosenn, supra note 20, at 255 n.9 (reflecting on the obstacles to law school reform, “[i]t may be that something akin to American legal realism cannot thrive in a society where so many disputes are resolved by extra-legal measures, or where those charged with enforcing the law are accustomed to reinterpret it without particular regard to statutory language.”). Rosenn construes American legal realism too narrowly. It is precisely these same phenomena that many legal realists reveal in the U.S. context. Elsewhere, Rosenn notes that “this prevailing attitude towards law and law study—that it comes hermetically packed like tennis balls and that deductive analysis is the key to open the can—is at least partly responsible for the great disparity between law and practice in Brazil.” Id. at 272. See Henry J. Steiner, Legal Education and Socio-Economic Change: Brazilian Perspectives, 18 AM. J. COMP. L. 39 (1971); see also Edward A. Laing, Revolution in Latin American Legal Education: The Colombian Experience, 6 LAWYER AM. 370, 372-73 (1974). Whether they were the cause or the effect of the tendencies to be presently described is a matter of speculation. But the Colombian (and the Latin-American) law school and university helped to produce and perpetuate the class distinctions and social cleavages which were earlier mentioned . . . . Traditionally, therefore, conservatism has been a feature of the law and society. In law and legal education the tendency has been to stress historicism and positivism as cardinal features of law, the teaching of which was designed to produce “jurists” cast in the traditionally exegetical mold by a system which eschewed intellectualism (unless traditionally endowed) and creativity, and which extolled professionalism . . . . The system we have described contributed to professional attitudes resistant to change, the retention of outworn techniques and to an inwardlooking and resilient law school organization and internal structure, with outmoded curricula and methodologies. Id. (footnotes omitted). 62. See, e.g., Karst, supra note 11, at 19 (stating “[l]awyers in the older of the developing countries . . . e.g., in Latin America . . . have not been trained in a policy-oriented legal science. . . . A radical re-ordering of legal education seems essential to change these patterns of thought”). See also Thome, supra note 21, at 22. [If] the legal system and its institutions are to play an effective role in the process of reform, then the lawyers who shape its form and substance must become painfully aware of the actual social and economic conditions they would change. Only then will they realize that traditional legal methods may actually frustrate the process of reform . . . . Id. 66 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 The following are illustrations of these failings [of traditional legal education]: (i) Absence of courses on the social sciences (and the relation of law to society), on economic law and on forensic deontology or professional ethics. (ii) Failure to provide the student with practical exercises and the opportunity to see law in operation and some of the byproducts of the legal process, such as prisons. (iii) The disregard of decided cases (jurisprudencia) in the teaching of law.63 Additionally, development-minded reformers supported the expansion of legal services to the poor and public interest litigation.64 Beside the direct benefit in terms of assistance to low-income groups, these services offered a way to reallocate economic resources by means of the legal system. II. BRIDGING THE EVER-PRESENT GAP: THE DEVELOPMENT ATTEMPT One of the paradoxes of Latin American legality is that “social” argument is not a routine part of mainstream legal discourse. That is, arguing on the basis of social particularities and perceived realities is not, in fact, unproblematically available as a legitimate mode of legal argumentation. Understandably then, attempts at its introduction underlie the strategy of presenting, emphasizing, and constructing a separate social or informal sphere of normativity. As it has been configured, however, the latter course has been and continues to be ineffective to produce change. To explain, the mainstream conception of law in Latin America (with all the caveats that such a general reference to very diverse phenomena must entail) is that answers to legal questions are singular; there is but one correct response for any legal question under the law. This conception is supported by a host of different legal theoretical positions and approaches. Naturalism, positivism, and sociology have all in one way or another been pressed into service in furtherance of this dominant idea. Moreover, arguments premised on other than accepted legal materials are deemed illegitimate and inapposite as legal reasoning. As such, it is understandable 63. Laing, supra note 61, at 374 (footnotes omitted). 64. See Metzger, supra note 24, at 7. Except under the most exceptional circumstances, an effective legal services program can contribute only marginally to eliminating the economic poverty of lower-income groups. Its contribution is more toward distributive justice—toward the nondiscriminatory operation of institutions with which citizens deal—which is increasingly being recognized as a development goal complementary to but independent of economic development. Id. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 67 that different waves of social reformers have sought to position “social reality” as an alternative source of law and to insist on the formulation of rules that follow its recognition. Such an argumentative move reconceptualizes legality as plural, that is, of permitting potentially multiple solutions under potentially multiple presentations of social reality. This characterization is not intended to describe an essential quality of law in Latin America. Surely, law and legal discourse are the product of the motivations and idiosyncracies of its participants. Throughout Latin America, these are mostly organized at the national level. As such, this Essay admittedly presents broad ideas and hypotheses calling to be enriched by more detailed accounts of country-specific or even community-specific usages. Still, past political projects mobilizing the conception of a unified Latin American legal identity (either as explicitly Latin American or essentially European) have had an impact on legal discourse throughout the region. It is the collective impact of these projects which is described here as a common element and thus renders it sensical to discuss on a regional level of analysis. It depends on nothing other than the historical fact of “Latin American” (or European) identity-based projects pursued in law. Thus, this description of a Latin America-wide state of affairs is neither an attempt to reinforce some past identity project nor does it seek to mobilize a new identity characterization of its own. Rather, it describes the commonalities produced historically by the advancing by some, and resisting by others, of projects of transnationality. A by-product of those struggles, and achievement of those emerging victorious, happens to be the rejection of social-based legal argument. Mainstream Latin American jurisprudence, thus, has consistently drawn a sharp line between law and politics, and placed social argument firmly within the latter camp. In this discursive economy, social argument is the antithesis of law. It threatens the above-politics authority of legal rules. Curiously, a wide spectrum of legal politics has effectively acquiesced in this state of affairs. As such, consolidating the social realm as a source of law remains an activity relegated to the margins, if not completely outside, of national legal discourse. Characterized as political discourse, it is rejected by mainstream jurists. As such, the tried and true method of legal renewal through invoking social considerations is rendered ineffective. In this light, the inordinate efforts of progressive scholars of the social, in particular, become more understandable. In the face of a legal culture apparently impervious to transformation on the basis of social needs, the strategy has been to redouble efforts. The exclusion heightens the motivation to defend and construct a separate social sphere, as a concrete sociological reality, to render it undeniable for arguing for legal reform. The gap between law and society is magnified and the coherence of a separate sphere of social normativity is re-emphasized. Thus, in order to make way for quite conventional social arguments, many progressives have 68 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 dedicated themselves to the vast enterprise of defending social alternity. Identifying and making concrete the potential of a social source of norms offers the hope of strengthening their hand. Real transformation, however, seems always postponed until the social is sufficiently articulated, through empirical study, sociological research, or maybe only after a revolution. This state of affairs within Latin American legal culture is indeed problematic. Instead of a routine use of social-based argument within national legal discourse, this technique has been rendered for the most part unavailable or illegitimate. Clearly, social argument is not new (it was not new in the 1960s) nor is it a deeply counter-institutional mode of legal argument, often quite the contrary. Yet, its deployment in Latin America, as a reforming catalyst against traditionalism within the official legal system, has not worked. This apparent unavailability of the social, however, is no more an intrinsic particularity of Latin American legal systems than is the figure of a lawless gap between state normativity and social conduct. Historical accounts demonstrate that Latin America is not immune to cross-national currents in legal theory. Latin American jurists provide testamentary proof of the pervasive influence in the region of social theories in scholarship as well as decision-making. Yet, there is admittedly a perceived absence of social argument within Latin American legal reasoning. It is deeply eclipsed, and when it is raised, it is quickly challenged as illegitimate. Additionally, this is not a result of a time lag in general jurisprudence—such as a movie that might not have yet reached our southern neighbors. Quite differently, the arrival of social argument in law is not late but, rather, has been repeatedly re-inscribed as an innocuous reaffirmation of the existing legal system or as a political question to be kept off the table. Thus, its reformist, transformative potential has been repeatedly blunted. Nonetheless, this same strategy of calling on the social, employed by law-and-development scholars, continues to be relaunched and given new life by subsequent generations of progressive scholars.65 As it has been 65. As noted earlier, taking up other historical examples of this phenomenon is beyond the scope of this Essay. However, by way of brief reference, Wanda Capeller tells the story of French “Critique du Droit” influence in the late 1970s in Latin America, in the way suggested by the analysis here. See generally Wanda de Lemos Capeller, Entre o ceticismo e a utopia: A sociologia jurídica latino-americana frente ao debate europeu, in SOCIOLOGÍA JURÍDICA EN AMÉRICA LATINA (1991). Capeller identifies military dictatorships in the 1970s with legal formalism (just as developmentalists did with then existing legal regimes), subsequently challenged by critics, deploying “Critique du Droit,” who saw the French ideas as an “‘ideological option’ in opposition to North American theoretical models.” (Rather than legal realism, they wandered toward materialism.) See id. Still, its proponents failed, according to Capeller, because of insufficient connection with social research and social reality, making it impossible to effectuate any real transformation (reinforcing the subsequent move by progressives toward the hyper-social, discussed 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 69 given shape, it consists of projecting and defending a qualitatively different and dense field of social particularity from which to argue for change, a field of social reality and difference that cannot be denied, which is what I call the hyper-social. Consequently, it entails arguing an ever bigger and deeper gap between law and society. Law-and-development’s rejection by Latin American traditionalists, however, has already marked the marginality of this enterprise. Specifically, the defenses and arguments raised against methods reform in the 1970s, inscribed this antiformalist, progressive strategy as non-legal discourse. Indeed, the way this skirmish took place, discussed below, helps to explain the current state of play of Latin American legal politics. In passing, I have referred to neo-developmentalism in Latin America. Direct heirs to the tradition of social-legal duality, these newer reformers employ essentially the same ideas and strategies to promote a marketoriented overhaul of the legal system. They respond to the objections, the same ones directed at 1960s developmentalism, by differentiating their approach. Objective economic incentives and market logic, it is argued, guide their efforts and thus, it is claimed, are not as easily manipulable as social engineering and political redistribution goals. Furthermore, neodevelopmentalists defend their agenda as the product of collaboration with and consent by Latin Americans. With theses explanations, the new wave of developmentalists are satisfied to pick up where past efforts left off—if not with the same content at least with the same overall analysis and framework. My concern here, though, rather than tracing the impact of neodevelopmentalism and discussing its parameters, is the impact on progressive legal politics remaining in the wake of earlier developmentalism. In this connection, the specific ways in which developmentalism was rebutted in Latin America are important. III. ROLLING UP THE BRIDGES (ACROSS THE GAP) Aligning the law with economic development and social justice was not in the abstract very controversial. Latin American leaders were anxious to receive the new technologies associated with modernization. Especially in the areas of law and economics and business law, Latin American professionals were eager to tool up. Latin American jurists as well were enthusiastic about the renewed attention and resources targeted to legal institutions. The year 1959 marked the first of five regional conferences of Latin American law schools to reconsider their curriculum.66 While framed below in text). Id. at 94-95. 66. See GARDNER, supra note 2, at 56 (confirming that the first conference in Mexico City consisted of more than two hundred and fifty Latin American delegates from forty law schools in 70 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 in broad and somewhat vague terms, the need to adjust law to its social setting was an articulated goal.67 The value of these conferences, according to Edward Laing, lay in “the spiritual coming together and the widening of horizons [, and these] were worthwhile achievements notwithstanding the ‘flagrant discordance’ between the accords of the conferences and their application in each law school.”68 Yet, the division between reformers and traditionalists was quite plain. In a prepared presentation for a subsequent Latin American law school conference, scheduled in Argentina but not held, Héctor Fix-Zamudio traced the dividing lines: Due to this traditional exaggeration of our exclusively theoretical juridical studies, a path is opening among Latin American treatise writers worried about the abuses of “dogmatism,” [demonstrating] an inclination for the socalled “empirical” studies, following the example of a sector of Anglo-American treatise writers, especially those from the United States, who have signaled the need to reduce the predominance of those labeled pejoratively as “bookteachers.”69 eighteen countries, with no North Americans in attendance). 67. See Laing, supra note 61, at 379. Laing highlights the following points: [E]merging from the first conference was the recommendation, made in connection with curricula suggestions, that legal education should be adjusted to the social needs of the community and be related to its needs and those of the rest of Latin America. This was repeated at the third conference, while the fourth conference suggested some specific programs for law schools to follow in fostering the social and economic welfare of the community and its members [for example, free legal assistance and centers for legal information]. Id.; see also Héctor Fix-Zamudio, Docencia en las facultades de derecho, 3 BOLETÍN DEL COLEGIO 2 (1973). 68. See Laing, supra note 61, at 382. DE ABOGADOS DE MÉXICO For its basic activities ARED [national Colombian association for legal education reform] has received some financial assistance from the Ford Foundation. . . . Despite the fact that these, and other activities could only have been beneficial, there has been some reluctance of other law schools to join ARED, and teachers using the modern methodologies have experienced considerable student resistance and been accused of brainwashing and conducting unwholesome Yankee practices. Id. at 387-88. 69. Fix-Zamudio, supra note 67, at 15 (author’s translation). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 71 The 1960s and 1970s also saw much localized, national interest and debate on reforming legal education, such as in Argentina, Brazil,70 Chile, Colombia,71 Peru, and various Central American states.72 In short, the political environment offered an opening for reform. Furthermore, developmentalism was supported by a worldwide focus on issues of economic progress and the backing of powerful international agencies and their resources. Not surprisingly, Latin American legal operators were receptive. Indeed, there was a ready segment of Latin American reformers, as evidenced by the regional and national conferences on Latin American legal education, whose agenda developmentalists directly reinforced.73 70. See, e.g., Cláudio Souto, Sociology of Law: A New Perspective in Brazilian Legal Education, 1972 ARCHIV FEUR RECTHS UND SOZIALPHILOSOPHIE 237 (1972). Souto describes the introduction of sociology of law courses and an institute at the University of Recife law school. See generally id. He credits William D. Macdonald of the University of Florida College of Law with the following. Id. at 243. The more general and important of these applied studies [within the institute] was research initiated . . . under a topic suggested by William D. Macdonald . . . [which] attempts mainly to survey opportunities for socio-juridical research in connection with the reform of Brazilian legislation—opportunities for research that could or should be carried out whether before or after the new codes are put into effect. Id. at 243. Souto was interested in framing a qualitative definition of the “living law” (beyond the quantitative “high-frequency behavior”) which could form the basis for the expansion of societies and of their problems of sociability, the increase of internal and external communication, the needs of international life. All this seems to demand a type of social control capable of adaptation to our modern society: a social control less formal and less dogmatic and more flexible, more dynamic, corresponding to the rapid change of the particular societies and the nature of the international society, which remains, to a great extent, an informal one. Id. at 245. 71. See Laing, supra note 61, at 383. 72. Id.; see, e.g., Mario Quiñónez Amézquita, El estudio del derecho y sus metodos de enseñanza, 1 BOLETÍN DEL COLEGIO DE ABOGADOS DE GUATEMALA 2, at 4, 16 (1974) (“[P]odemos afirmar que son las Facultades de derecho las más conservadoras y reacias a la implementación de reformas . . . . Nosotros hemos considerado que Guatemala necesita un abogado con miras al desarrollo, que conozca el Derecho de su país, la realidad del mismo.”); Antonio Vivanco, Enseñanza e Investigación en el Derecho Agrario, 1 REVISTA JURÍDICA DEL PERÚ 151 (1974). 73. Of course, it is not clear how far Latin American-based reformers were willing to go. The words of a leading figure in legal education in Colombia, Dr. Fernando Hinestrosa of the Externado de Colombia, leaves room for doubt, stating that law is not simply a science or a mere technique, nor speculative knowledge, nor a vulgar method of doing things. But, as in its classical Roman ancestry, Law continued to be an art and, require[d] a solid theoretical conception, a simple and direct method 72 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 While the formula—essentially antiformalism—was not new to Latin America, developmentalists had their own way of articulating it.74 An emphasis on policy, pragmatism, and realism was surely a new turn within Latin American legal discourse. Yet, it was no more than old wine in new bottles. It represented a challenge to dominant legal discourse in much the same way that other social-based efforts had attempted in the past. It did so, specifically, by drawing authority from social and economic imperatives and proposing different legal arrangements to attain them. In any case, defenders of the traditional system did not wait long to react.75 The potential of non-traditional argument as proposed by developmentalists was soon undone.76 One mode of rejecting reform and supporting traditionalism was to emphasize the importance of Roman law of reasoning and decision and an universal criterion, with a clear humanist flavor . . . . Laing, supra note 61, at 386. Then again, legal mystification is not necessarily a proxy for lack of reformist intent. 74. GARDNER, supra note 2, at 57-58. The American legal assistance programs which later emerged had little apparent memory or knowledge of the Latin American reform endeavor—a striking omission in the American law and development literature on Latin America in the early and middle 1960s, and an instructive comment on the American origins of the reforms subsequently launched. Id. 75. See, e.g., id. at 62-63 (describing the resistance in Brazil to legal education reform, where an independent center in 1965 was created “largely because the Brazilian law schools were, in fact, unreceptive to American notions of reform . . . .”). 76. A quite theoretical treatment of the tensions presented is the work of Eduardo García Máynez of Mexico. Eduardo García Máynez, El derecho en el order del ser y como sector del orden social, 19 REVISTA DE LA FACULTAD DE DERECHO DE MÉXICO 525 (1969). García Máynez reinforces the traditional conception of law, and argues against “psychological” or “legal consciousness” ideas about legality, in the following way. See generally id. In other words, the execution of acts of consciousness in an individual or a plurality of subjects does not constitute, rather it confirms or recognizes legal objects. There is no doubt that the existence of these is found in the psychological ambit, in conscience and individual feeling, but it does not depend on such connection, nor is it limited by it. Id. at 528 (author’s translation). García Máynez grounds law in the social order, but for him the social order fixes the minimum requirements for co-existence. It is inter-subjective, rather than collective, yet rises above individual will. When participating in society, individuals submit their individuality to its pre-existing dictates. As such, in his work, the social order is not a source for substantial change, rather it is already present and the source of existing legal rules. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 73 to the Latin American legal curriculum.77 Roman law is still a basic, required course within most Latin American law schools. The course is generally offered over a full year, and possibly more than any other discipline firmly propounds the membership of Latin American legal systems within the family of a European transnational law—the mainstay of legal legitimation in Latin America.78 In 1967, the first Inter-American Congress on Roman Law was held in João Pessoa, Brazil79—in effect, the counter-conference to those mentioned above, targeting “pragmatic” curricular reform. A few years later in 1973, at another such event, César José Ramos Sojo of the Universidad Central de Venezuela captured the sentiment of these meetings: It is also worthwhile to observe that the crisis in higher education is part of a more general crisis of culture. It is not so much a determinate discipline which is questioned, but rather the proper finality of studies imparted, the values that until now have been represented, the concrete ideal which is sought to be created. In what concerns the studies of Law, we see widely disseminated the persuasion that the interest lies in forming, along the way more able manipulators of procedures and competent drafters of acts and legal documents. It is then, as 77. See, e.g., Maria do Socorro Bezerra da Costa et al., Atualiçazão do ensino do direito romano, 23 REVISTA DE LA FACULTAD DE DERECHO DE MÉXICO 53 (1973). In no instance should the importance and utility of the study of Roman law be placed in doubt, as it has come to conform a true legal consciousness through above all legislation and case law. It is valid to consider it not a dead law that should be forgotten. It is a living law, acting, and impregnating o amago as the essence of other Laws. Id. See also César José Ramos Sojo, Necesidad de una actualización de la enseñanza del derecho romano, 23 REVISTA DE LA FACULTAD DE DERECHO DE MÉXICO 67 (1973). The author argues that [t]he frequency with which we find the questioning of the modern study and teaching of Roman law, inside and out of law schools, could have us believe that it is a phenomenon exclusively of our times. As well it has been observed about France, this attitude is more than 200 years old . . . . Notwithstanding this observation by Accarias (“Roman law courses . . . are in actuality rejected by students and attacked by reason of an undue suspicion by part of the peoples of the world.”) the study and teaching of Roman law was conserved in the curriculum of studies of Roman law in France, without transcendental reform. And what is valid for France, can be said as well for our countries. Id. at 67-68 (author’s translation). 78. See Esquirol, supra note 8, at 427 n.2, 431-32 n.14. 79. See Bezerra de Costa et al., supra note 77. 74 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 a logical consequence, that Roman law and other disciplines are not appreciated within such conception of scholastic education. From this cannot be excluded the utilitarianism of many who register at law schools. According to the pragmatism, by them maintained, only what can be translated into economic gain and purchasing power should be the object of study, fast and easy, within professional practice. For them, creative activity, the attainment of order and the intuition of the normative, [and] the social mission of the jurist of condere et interpretare ius do not matter.80 Also, for example, Nina Ponnsa de la Vega de Miguens from Argentina argues in the same symposium proceedings, published by the Universidad Autónoma de México Law Review: Other specialties, like for example sociology and economics, approach their study with a prospective criterion and projections toward the future. The mental training of those that think in law is moved by the present and by an objective field which is at the same time axiomatic, with the concern to know and obtain juridical values whose nucleus is justice . . . . Roman jurisprudence has meant an always current truth, applied today in different fields of law . . . . It is evident that legal education has as its principal end to configure the mentality and way of thinking, in such a way that the student acquires a certain logico-juridical habit that is adapted to the normative system of his time . . . . It is desirable the fact that the study of Roman jurisprudence be every day more extensive and deep, despite that its learning require the study of rules and prescriptions that are frequently permitted and inapplicable in actuality. Its specific objective is the training of scientific jurisconsults armed with a special and necessary logic for the interpretation and application of laws, which is acquired fundamentally through the jurisprudence of the Romans.81 Other approaches and theoretical frameworks were also marshaled against substantial curricular reform—essentially arguing against changing the “European” identity of Latin American law.82 The new methods, to the 80. Sojo, supra note 77, at 70. 81. Nina Ponnsa de la Vega de Miguens, Necesidad de una actualización en la enseñanza del derecho romano, 23 REVISTA DE LA FACULTAD DE DERECHO DE MÉXICO 21, 22-23, 25 (1973) (author’s translation). 82. Cf. Victor Tau Anzoátegui, Importancia y estado actual de la enseñanza de la Historia 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 75 extent they were actually introduced, were quickly undermined.83 Their lack of success has been attributed, by certain scholars, to insufficient resources and unsustained attention directed at curricular change; and lethargy and inertia, or both, on the part of Latin American legal professionals and law students.84 Yet, considering that legal developmentalism’s main product was conceptual (an idea about the nature of law and its application), its open resistance by Latin America’s legal mainstream and the discursive forms this took, I maintain, is a significant part of the explanation. Dominant Latin American jurists and defenders of the traditional order rejected the developmentalist opening and its democratizing potential.85 Introducing new variables within legal reasoning would, at a minimum, require a different way of justifying settled divisions of power and distributions of resources within society. Developmentalist methods, del Derecho, 130 REVISTA JURÍDICA ARGENTINA “LA LEY” 976 (1968). 83. See, e.g., GARDNER, supra note 2, at 83. Opposition surfaced [at PUC in Rio de Janeiro, Brazil], for example, in the form of persistent faculty criticism that the new reform program—especially the Development Law branch—was not law but social science. Eventually, after intense intrafaculty struggles, the CEPED group and the dean were replaced by a dean in the more traditional and conservative mold. Id. 84. See, e.g., id. at 231-35. 85. See, e.g., Francisco Serrano Migallón, El derecho y la ley, 5 EL FORO 53 (1969) (arguing that order is not a social norm, rather order is the goal of state law, as opposed to ideal justice or the common, social good). In his view, state law can only achieve some rough measure of the ideal of justice while providing peace for society to pursue its common good. Absent law, “una sociedad sin orden sería un mundo donde reinase como única Ley el bajo instinto del egoïsmo y las insanas pasiones humanas.” Id. at 54. But cf., Ambrosio Romero Carranza, A los cincuenta años de la creación de una cátedra de derecho, 1973JURISPRUDENCIA ARGENTINA: DOCTRINA 287, 287 (arguing against the tendency in Argentine law schools to marginalize the study of political law; “[e]n la actualidad el conocimiento del derecho político se ha impuesto como una necesidad urgente e indispensable para el progreso de la vida social”); see also Sojo, supra note 77, at 77-78. It is necessary to safeguard against the iconoclastic current of breaking all links with the legal tradition in which we are inserted and which signals our common destiny, Kischaker highlighted the contribution of Roman law in Europe, its active participation as a constructive, harmonious and pacific element, of the sole city, beyond national differences. Codifications of the French, Italian, and German type, as works of Romanists, reveal the phenomenon of a common descent and a common place of understanding. The codifications derived from the same cannot be subtracted from the influence of Roman law which remains the fundamental juridical datum, at the base of our social organization, a factor of unity. Id. 76 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 moreover, might go further. They could disrupt the long-settled accommodations reached by the legal system. Accepting policies such as the then widely-touted goals of economic progress and social equity, as part of legal decisionmaking, could open to renegotiation the old bargains struck. The lurch to the left, represented by dependency theory’s critiques of the development model,86 further exacerbated the perceived dangers of a substantial renegotiation, under the mantle of a “periphery-centered” development. In order to derail this possibility, traditional legal operators emphasized the dangers of instrumentalism.87 Policy, rule-skepticism, and antiformalism were all tarred with the same defect: legitimating arbitrary laws. The focus on policy and social reality was associated with unlimited deference to the government in power.88 To sharpen the point, following this thinking, in a left-wing government antiformalism means the end of private property and the rule of law; in a military dictatorship, it means repressive norms of social control and autocratically-derived public policies.89 By interpreting development methods as leading to these results, traditional jurists called upon the fears of political extremism; the new methods could just as easily legitimate arbitrary state action by undemocratic governments. Traditionalists sought refuge in their conventional role as defenders of the status quo, containing the unruly masses on the one hand and 86. See ANDRE GUNDER FRANK, LATIN AMERICA: UNDERDEVELOPMENT OR REVOLUTION (1969). 87. See GARDNER, supra note 2, at 117. When, therefore, the OAB [Brazilian Bar Association] president, Faoro, discussed “formalism” and “instrumentalism,” he in effect turned the legal models of American legal assistance inside out. Rather than criticize legal formalism as antiquated, for example, the movement perceived in legal formalism the “dorsal fin” of liberal constitutionalism. Rather than encourage rule skepticim and state instrumental law, the movement advocated formal rules and the rule of law. Id. (footnote omitted). 88. An interesting example is the reaction of the Chilean Supreme Court to the legal interpretations espoused by the Allende administration in the early 1970s. A significant amount has already been written about the Chilean Court’s exceptionally activist stance and consequent delegitimation of legally valid, yet non-traditionally interpreted and applied, governmental programs and enforcement actions. But see Velasco, The Allende Regime in Chile: An Historical Analysis 9 LOY. L.A. L. REV. 480 (1975-76) (sustaining that Allende’s actions were illegal, if not in the letter, in the spirit of the law, thereby precipitating the Court’s justifiable stance); Neal Panish, Chile Under Allende and the Decline of the Judiciary, 9 LOY. L.A. INT’L & COMP. L.J. 693 (1987) (also attributing the Court’s actions to Allende’s violation of the separation of powers doctrine). 89. See David M. Trubek & Marc Galanter, Scholars in Self-Estrangement: Some Reflections on the Crisis in Law and Development Studies in the United States, 1974 WIS. L. REV. 1062, 107084. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 77 restraining autocratic leaders on the other. The balance was maintained, however, by defending against any deep transformation of the existing order. Social-based legal argument presented such a potential disruption, upsetting the balance enshrined by conventional legal reasoning. Accordingly, traditional jurists helped rechannel, defeat, or otherwise disable the transformative potential of this legal technology. The specific outcome of a development-inspired attempt at transformation in the 1960s and 1970s is significantly illustrative of this occurrence. Developmentalists, on their part, allowed themselves to be cowed. Faced with the very real abuses of political extremists at the time, it appeared Latin America was not ready for policy or pragmatic legal decisionmaking.90 At least it was not so at the cost of reducing democracy or progressive aims. Take for example James Gardner’s “terminal” review of the Brazilian legal education reform project presented to the Ford Foundation in 1973: [T]he core of this conceptualization [producing more activist and socially aware lawyers and a more humanistic approach] may become very tenuous if law has, by the very essence of its being, an enduring affinity for the status quo, and if lawyers, by their class background, training, professional reinforcement, etc., are among the more persistent agents of the status quo . . . . Stated baldly: even to the extent that [the grant] did succeed, it may have simply trained up more effective agents of the status quo, and strengthened the institutions which train these agents.91 Even worse, faced with the possibility of supporting dictators or Marxist regimes, developmentalists pulled their own plug.92 Even an insightful and critical scholar such as Gardner, cited above, fell into the belief that 90. See generally PANISH, supra note 88. Panish retreats into “separation of powers” formalism when confronted with a politically-controversial, and for some, unbridled Chilean pragmatism. See id. 91. See GARDNER, supra note 2, at 80-81 (quoting his own report) (second alteration in original). 92. See Bilder & Tamanaha, supra note 2, at 474. The authors discuss the practical end of law and development funding and scholarship after deep doubts were expressed within the U.S. legal academy about exporting instrumental approaches towards law to authoritarian Latin American governments. Id. “Trubek and Galanter did not, however, offer any suggestions about what should replace the Western model.” Id. I agree with the authors’ views on the error of imploding law and development but for very different reasons. The authors argue that its demise was a result of purely “homegrown” U.S. political reasons—the Vietnam War, distrust in government, and the rise of the critical legal studies movement. See id. at 474-76. They, however, underestimate the impact and resistance of powerful sectors of Latin American societies and legal intelligentsia to development-based reforms and to the politics of its proponents. See id. 78 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 American legal assistance and repressive, state instrumentalism were indistinguishable: In summary, well before the arrival of American legal assistance and the establishment of CEPED [the institutional vehicle for legal education reform] in Brazil, that country’s governing technocracy had accepted much of CEPED’s basic perception of law: that formal, doctrinal law is antiquated and is an impediment to development, and that instrumental law is modern and is an important vehicle for social control and social engineering. The governing technocracy [an authoritarian military government] had started the public sector on a forced march to state instrumentalism . . . . And the Brazilian legal profession, as discussed above, was bypassed and generally confused by, and attempted to catch up with, this major jursiprudential change. American legal assistance was not the “cause” of this fundamental breach in Brazil’s traditional legal culture, of course. . . . It was precisely this emerging public sector instrumentalism that conditioned much of the receptiveness to CEPED’s American jurisprudential models.93 Developmentalists especially came to see it this way, if they understood their own project as simply getting law out of the way of the developmentalist state. Up against an obstructionist Latin American legal class resiting developmental policy, their notions of pragamatism, antiformalism, and instrumentalism, which were intended to overcome the resistance, became conflated with simply legitimating state action.94 Their objectives were limited to undoing the separate authority of the traditional legal profession to speak exclusively for the law, rather than providing an alternative legal discourse capable of differentiating between different types of state action. In the belief that the developmentalist state would do the right thing, advocating the legality of its actions was a logical way to align law with development. Once Latin American governments were perceived as not doing the right thing, however, the strategy of undoing the obstructionist power of the legal profession came to be seen as wrongheaded. The backpedaling that marked the end of developmentalism contributed especially to reinforcing—in legal discourse terms—the 93. See GARDNER, supra note 2, at 98-99. 94. See Dennis O. Lynch, supra note 10. In Lynch’s review of Gardner’s book, one criticism stand out: Gardner’s failure to distinguish between positivism and naturalism within Latin American legal formalism, and his failure to differentiate between instrumentalism and pragmatism within North American realism. As a result of this confusion, formalism as natural law thinking appears to offer a basis for resisting authoritarian government decrees: developmentalism as merely instrumentalism appears to offer no brakes. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 79 connection between the independent authority of the legal profession and traditionalist legal positions, the latter consisting of a narrow and undemocratic conceptualization of law as necessitarian and univocal. In any case, the whole legal development project was thus drawn into question. In fact, public self-questioning and self-doubt ultimately prompted the main U.S. and international agencies to withdraw their support. Faced with the choice of either accepting the traditional political settlement under the existing legal system or potentially offering legitimacy to political extremes, they chose the former. This formulation of the options, however, presents a false dilemma. While pragmatism and policy can surely serve as handmaidens of authoritarianism, this discovery does not undermine its ability to articulate critiques or to stand as alternative law supported by the legal class, as a sustainable national legal discourse. Furthermore, in this same way, legal formalism can offer a basis for resisting state action, yet it can also be a singularly effective basis for justifying repression. In any case, developmentalists backed away. They were daunted by the traditionalist stranglehold on the conception of law and by their own dualistic depictions of Latin American legality. As such, developmentalism was shown incapable of providing safeguards against political extremism, the same objection raised against state instrumentalism. Developmentalists seemed to agree that the new methods were in fact prone to legitimating arbitrary action, failing to differentiate among different projects in policy pragmatist terms. Notably, no effective opposition to state authoritarianism was conceived of, if the multiple character of law were to be acknowledged openly.95 The only 95. See id. at 118. [T]he legal engineer and legal instrumental models were in fact engaged as the agents and the instruments of the state, and the models provided no coherent basis for criticism of, or resistance to, an authoritarian state. For this resistance the lawyers—Brazilian and American—turned to the formal legal tradition and the rule of law. Id. About Chile, Gardner asserts [t]he low point [of the legal instrumentalism model as supported by U.S. legal assistance] involved extralegal social action, encouraged by the state, as part of a larger pattern of coercive engineering, beyond the reach of legislative authorization, to force owners to transfer farms or businesses to the state sector. In that situation the already blurred line between “law” and “policy” faded to extinction, purposeful instrumentalism readily became state engineering beyond the reach of legal instruments and judicial review, and the process, if unchecked by legal or political institutions, became little distinguishable from raw state power. In Chile, then, underlying instrumental models again demonstrated a persistent affinity for policy and power—and a vulnerability to executive and state 80 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 strategy apparently available against extremism was a return to univocal, legal dogmatism. Traditionalism often frustrated the implementation of developmental policies; on the other hand, it offered some traction and autonomy against repressive regimes. This turn, however, greatly limits and accepts the fear of political extremism as a valid limit on pluralist legal politics. Acquiescing in necessitarian, univocalism as the lesser of two evils reinforces non-dominant (be it framed as pragmatism, policy, or antiformalism) legal argument as political. Furthermore, it postpones a more democratic legal discourse for another day, for the sake of condemning—with the strongest force of a univocal and unquestionable law—an undemocratic government today. Some recent commentators have criticized the 1970s withdrawal of developmentalists on different grounds.96 They view the internal criticism and ultimate termination of development projects as constituting as much a U.S.-centered and imperialist imposition as the actual development projects to which internal critics were objecting. However, reading either developmentalism or its demise as solely U.S. phenomena presents a picture of Latin American actors devoid of agency and fails as a fuller explanation. The key feature of legal developmentalism was an idea about legal reform through changing legal reasoning techniques. This idea was not new within Latin American legal circles by the time foreign developmentalists arrived, nor was the extensive resistance to it merely the by-product of anti-Vietnam War protesters or intellectual crises over modernization theory. It also reflected the interests of those standing to lose from the reforms, and the discursive struggle that marks its defeat. In this regard, casting social-based argument—including its policy pragmatist version—as illegitimate legal reasoning and reemphasizing the univocality of law by traditionalists played a prominent role. It has also led to an equally forceful counter-strategy by progressives of arguing social particularity and its distinctness from state legal institutions. Here, it is important to differentiate between incorporating social considerations within legal reasoning and, alternatively, claiming a hypostatized field of social interaction deemed particular to Latin America. It is the latter course that many progressives writing about Latin America have followed. The motivations are multifold. As deployed by 1960s and 1970s developmentalists, discussed above, it can be traced to attempts to sweep the decks clear, to make room for a ordering. Id. at 184. 96. See, e.g., César Rodriguez, Globalización, Reforma Judicial y Estado de Derecho en América Latina: El Regreso de Los Programas de Derecho y Desarrollo, EL OTRO DERECHO 25 (2001); see also Tamanaha , supra note 2. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 81 whole new program and set of prescriptions for the legal system. The position is understandable: U.S. academics were not interested in engaging in political struggles through the then existing Latin American legal argumentative conventions nor did they want to be hamstrung by them. Rather, they proposed a whole new playing field and a whole new agenda, ones which they, of course, understood much better. Subsequent generations of progressives, as discussed in more detail below, have gravitated to this position as well. Attracted by the potential of introducing multiplicity or pluralism to legal reasoning, consistently foreclosed in the past, the strategy appears to be mere common sense. However, the resistance of Latin America’s legal intelligentsia played an important role. After the victory over development, reforms premised on social reality, pragmatism, and policy are more clearly off the table, leading progressives to ever more accentuated claims of an excluded and alternative social law. IV. CRITIQUES A. Critique of Latin American Duality The predominant diagnosis advanced by developmentalists quite obviously suffered from an overly reified conception of both Latin American law and Latin American peoples. State law in Latin America is not simply an inert, foreign artifact, nor are Latin American people unique bearers of inimitable social particularity.97 Developmentalists deployed these tropes, rather plainly, in furtherance of their overall project. The legal culture was to be transformed, ostensibly, to encourage the legal system to respond to social needs and policy objectives.98 A new deal was required. 97. See Esquirol, supra note 8, at 461-64. 98. See, e.g., Roger W. Findley, Ten Years of Land Reform in Colombia, 1972 WIS. L. REV. 880, 910-11. Findley attributes, in part, the slow progress of Colombia’s 1961 land redistribution program, enacted out of fear generated by the Cuban Revolution, to resistance by the courts. INCORA [the administrative agency charged with executing land reform] has been particularly hampered . . . by reversals in the Administrative Disputes Courts, some of which appear to be considerably more sympathetic to the interests of large landowners than to the goals of the land reform program. Acquisitions have been invalidated for minute deviations from prescribed procedures. . . . Because of the vagueness of the statute and the latitude which it gives an unsympathetic court seeking a way to upset a finding of inadequate use [the legal standard required], INCORA personnel in expropriation proceedings have been greatly concerned over the possibility of lengthy appeals and, ultimately, reversals. Id. In discussing pending legislation in 1972 to improve the system, he notes that [t]he bill would establish an entirely new system of specialized land courts. These 82 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 To do this, traditional political and economic arrangements enacted through law, and their articulated justifications, had to be undone. The card played was none other than the disconnectedness of official law from social reality. This claim, rather than a sociological or cultural discovery, was a challenge to the political compromises that had been hammered out through the legal system at the time. A systematic overhaul of those settlements could only be effected by re-opening the bases of legal decisionmaking.99 Reforming legal methods and introducing “social law” arguments were crucial. They offered a way of renegotiating the established political and economic deals. Drawing on a social sphere of human interaction has been the tradition within legal theory in both the United States and Continental Europe, as discussed above. It can be traced to calls for undoing the strict positivism of the 19th century.100 It has fueled countless reform efforts against laws perceived as out-of-step with contemporary realities.101 Conversely, it has also assisted in defending state law against delegitimating critiques. Social theories of law are not new in Latin America either.102 In different degrees, the legal culture has assimilated both challenges and affirmations stemming from notions of a separate social source. A comprehensive study of these would be valuable at this point, but is unfortunately beyond the scope of this work. Yet, the courts would have exclusive jurisdiction to hear many of the trials and appeals in expropriation and extinction cases now handled by the administrative and civil courts and would be directed to apply a social philosophy sympathetic to the land reform program. Id. at 921. 99. See, e.g., Wolfgang G. Friedmann, The Role of Law and the Function of the Lawyer in the Developing Countries, 17 VAND. L. REV. 181, 186 (1963). If the lawyer continues to be identified, as he predominantly is at the present time, with the defense of the existing order and of vested interests, against the urgent needs and interests of societies that must lift themselves from poverty and stagnation to a radically higher level of economic and social development, often within a desperately short time, the lawyer will eventually be reduced to an inferior and despised status in the developing nations. Id. 100. See Marie-Claire Belleau, Les Juristes Inquiets (1996) (unpublished S.J.D. dissertation) (on file with the Harvard Law Library); see also FRANÇOIS GÉNY, MÉTHODE D’INTERPRETATION ET SOURCES EN DROIT PRIVÉ POSITIF: ESSAI CRITIQUE (1899). 101. See EHRLICH, supra note 13, at 391-411; see also Rodolfo Sacco, Legal Formants: A Dynamic Approach to Comparative Law (Installment II of II), 39 AM. J. COMP. L. 343 (1991). 102. See generally Medina, supra note 38; see also Liliana Obregón, Nineteenth Century Latin American Internationalism (unpublished S.J.D. dissertation in progress) (draft on file with author). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 83 existing work of Latin Americanists is sufficient to demonstrate prior uses of social theory as a mode of intervening in legal discourse.103 Social alternity, in its sense of otherness from the legal system, is thus not novel within Latin American legal discourse. Simply put, it was also the technique of choice for developmentalists. The introduction of this concept does not serve any new or better understanding of the workings of the legal system. Rather, it is an argumentative move within legal discourse. Highlighting the estrangement between legal and social spheres, simply as a logical matter, may argue in favor of transforming existing laws or possibly assimilating society to the law in place. Both the extensiveness of legal reform or, alternatively, the intensity of legal penetration efforts depend on the objectives of its proponent. In this way, it can be less a claim about a particular reality than an effort to transform that reality. Understood as such, developmentalists’ emphasis on the dichotomy between law and the social order then should not be read as the key, idiosyncratic element or identity of Latin American legal systems. Instead, these writings may best be read as advancing particular political or programmatic objectives, swaddled in the argumentative device of social-legal duality. Developmentalists’ claims then can be viewed as less about the actual functioning of Latin America’s legal systems than about the particular way or particular deals cut under those official systems. Indeed, considering the fact that many developmentalists had little prior familiarity with the region, its languages, and the peculiarities of its various legal systems, it stands to reason that their intervention, in the mode of description, was designed to clear the decks. Advancing the irrelevance of official law, as a matter of fact, gave them a free hand to drive through a broad agenda, unencumbered by the necessity to work from within the existing state of legal play. Their reform objectives, or renegotiation objectives, were assisted by calls reconnecting them with social reality and attuning the legal system to local culture. In fact, of course, Latin American legal systems were already responding to social reality and were inseparable from local culture. The social norms and policies in place, however, were simply different from those advanced by developmentalists. B. Critique of an Identity Approach to Latin American Law The portrayal of informality, and the gap in developmentalist literature often projects this device as a peculiar or especially exaggerated aspect of the local legal culture, cast in terms of the sociological or cultural particularities of Latin Americans in relationship to law. It is this claim which is untenable as an empirical fact peculiar to the region. Such 103. See generally Medina, supra note 38. 84 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 phenomena as gaps and informality are common features of all legal systems. Nonetheless, in one of the better known developmentalist pieces, Keith Rosenn, despite acknowledging the occurrence of informality elsewhere, sustains its cultural dimension in Brazil: Plainly Brazil is not unique in this respect; bending of legal norms to expediency occurs in all countries . . . . But what is striking about Brazil is that the practice of bending legal norms to expediency has been elevated into a highly prized paralegal institution called “jeito.” The “jeito” is an integral part of Brazil’s legal culture, and in many areas of the law it is employed normally rather than exceptionally.104 It is this construction of “paralegal,” sociological, or cultural identity, which the above citation is an example, that this Essay rejects. My claim is that giving a sociological cast to, circumventing administrative red tape through legal fictions, even if they are far-fetched fictions, advances the idea of a qualitatively distinct Latin American conception of law. And yet, legal fictions are a time-honored device of all formalized systems. Furthermore, making a judgment as to the degree of informality and then characterizing it as evidence of a cultural phenomenon leads to a misconception. It downplays the role of resources and political will in effective law enforcement, highlighting instead the social incongruity of the legal system. This mode of arguing for law reform has contributed to the belief—and to the rhetorical construction—of an identity of Latin American law that is essentially discordant with a separate cultural system in place. This particular Latin American situation is typically contrasted to the way law operates elsewhere, especially in developed countries. Advancing cultural reasons for the refracted ways in which official law operates across society creates a picture of multiple and distinct systems of legality at work, each with its own relative degree of legitimacy. Classifying legal informality as cultural or social displaces on to Latin America a common, yet not readily admitted, feature of all modern state law. It preserves, by contrast, an idealization of developed legal systems as able to transfuse the entirety of human society and amply consensual throughout, evidenced by the projection of a uniform internalization. Such a fiction does not hold even among officials of the same state apparatus, much less across whole societies. In any case, its predominant effect is to undermine Latin American legal institutions by highlighting, as extraordinary and pathological, features which are quite common. In the long run, which is my point in this Essay, it has not served progressive causes well. 104. See Rosenn, supra note 20, at 254. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 85 This is not to say that experiences of legal pluralism are wholly invented nor that the term is completely inapposite as a characterization of certain phenomena.105 In fact, legal pluralism is an appealing concept because it is so present everywhere. Even if one differentiates between types of legal pluralism, the notion is deployable in almost any context.106 Furthermore, it has been quite effective both as a conceptual and a political tool for indigenous communities in Latin America.107 Identifying indigenous norms and recognizing them at the level of state law or quasistate law has been, according to its proponents, an effective strategy in recent decades.108 To what extent the outcome has been, in the best of cases, anything other than an aggressive decentralization of dispute resolution functions can be debated infinitely. Regardless, many progressive scholars focusing on indigenous rights laud its potential.109 My analysis and criticism, here, do not extend to these gains. In the context of indigenous groups, legal pluralism may indeed be a politically useful concept. However, in terms of a diagnosis or an intervention in national legal discourse, the notion—often advanced as a corollary of the gap between law and society—has come to be counterproductive to progressive aims, as is discussed below. Furthermore, my argument does not deny that there are identifiable differences between law as enacted and popular sentiment or even local practices. Of course these exist. However, this does not mean that Latin American societies are evidence of this difference any more than anywhere 105. Sally Merry, Legal Pluralism, 22 L. & SOC’Y REV. 869 (1988). 106. See, e.g., BOAVENTURA DE SOUSA SANTOS, ESTADO, DERECHO Y LUCHAS SOCIALES (1991) (sustaining that legal pluralism extends to collectives based on cultural, guild, racial, religious, territorial, and other criteria, which have created their own normativity that regulate various spheres of social life and permit them to resolve their conflicts). 107. See, e.g., RAQUEL YRIGOYEN FAJARDO, PAUTAS DE COORDINACION ENTE EL DERCHO INDIGENA Y EL DERECHO ESTATAL (1999). 108. Id. Note however that the advances in recognizing legal pluralism in Guatemala, as obtained in the peace accords in the mid-1990s, were ultimately defeated by a popular vote in May 1999 against the relevant modifications to the national constitution. 109. The way that separate indigenous law is being conceived by its defenders is, nonetheless, cause for concern and subject to the same critiques levied here against dominant legal traditionalism in Latin America. Defenders of this separate system argue for its stature on a par with state law. Additionally, many argue the incommensurability of its cosmovision and identity with Western law, thus arguing the inability of judging it by human rights principles (or any outside-derived criteria). These advocates, however, run into the error of presenting indigenous law as an arena which can only be understood and observed by outsiders but not in which they can participate. Dangerously, under this framework, outsiders can become anyone in disagreeing with or challenging the hegemonic interpretation of such indigenous normativity. Contra Esther Sanchez Botero, Aproximación desde la antropología jurídica a la justicia de los pueblos indígenas, in EL CALEIDOSCOPIO DE LAS JUSTICIAS EN COLOMBIA (2001); see generally Beatriz Eugenia Sanchez, El reto del multiculturalismo jurídico; La justicia de la sociedad mayor y la justicia indígena, in EL CALEIDOSCOPIO DE LAS JUSTICIAS EN COLOMBIA (2001). 86 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 else. Legal diversity, to some degree, is part and parcel of any application of law. One need only look for it to find it. Specific communities often assimilate generalized rules in idiosyncratic fashion; undocumented immigrants live in a constant state of informality; political dissidents and marginalized groups abide by their particular loyalties; and the various institutions of civil society all produce their own codes of conduct, not all of these always in strict alignment with written law. To the extent Latin America is perceived as any different, in these terms, it is more logically the result of scarce enforcement resources and lack of political will, at any one time, to increase repression. Raising the image of lawlessness or its positively-stated analog, an accentuated social-legal gap, to the level of a deep cultural and historical characteristic is all together a different matter. This is part of the legacy of law-and-development scholarship, as this passage on the gap or extra-legality of market transactions illustrates: Ironically, corruption itself is often a response to conditions of insecurity. If strangers are suspect, then the world of market transactions is cold and forbidding. A bribe turns a t r ansactional r e l a t i o n s h i p i n t o a “ m o r a l ” relationship—although the word “moral” may be jarring in this context—by defining a new particularist moral community. Such a community is functionally analogous to the community created when one person becomes the godparent (padrino) of another’s child, making the two “coparents” (compadres), bound to each other in quasi-familial loyalties that imply, among other things, some forms of economic support.110 The preceding is an example of the curious characterizations sketched by developmentalists, many seemingly riding on an undercurrent of racial or cultural preconceptions. C. Critique of “Exoticized” Latin American Law During the high period of developmentalism, there were of course already existing critiques within the bosom of law-and-society regarding simple distinctions between the legal sphere and the social sphere. Furthermore, there was a growing body of critical literature which took exception to the dichotomies presented by legal sociologists and questioned the motivations of this type of analysis. The apparatus employed by developmentalists in Latin America was already more richly explored within academic circles than the legacy of developmentalism would lead us to believe. The notions of a gap and of separate spheres were 110. See, e.g., KARST & ROSENN, supra note 8, at 638 (emphasis added and footnotes omitted). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 87 contested propositions even as they were being deployed to describe reality in Latin America. Of course, concepts about the law’s social effects and social engineering through law were still common. What is curious is that when depicting Latin America, it was possible to present the dichotomy in the starkest terms possible without raising much of an eyebrow. This aspect of developmentalist writing deserves some attention. Scholarship about the U.S. legal system by U.S. legal scholars could not have drawn such a clean divide between society and law, nor could it have implanted the notion of a systemic gap between the two in such uncontestable ways (of course, the point for most centrist U.S. scholars writing about the United States at the time was precisely to avoid doing so). David Trubek and Marc Galanter approached the phenomenon from this perspective.111 [I]n view of many areas that diverge from the model [liberal legalism], there is little reason to assume that it represents the typical or normal case of legal regulation in this [U.S.] society. The gap between the law on the books and the law in action has been discovered innumerable times (in race relations, divorce, school prayers, and criminal justice, for example) but the implications of this discovery depend on one’s picture of what is normal and typical in our legal system. Within the received paradigm, each instance of the gap tends to be dismissed as an exception—something atypical, peripheral, and transient. Awareness of such discrepancies does not induce professionals to relinquish their model of the legal system, for the persistence of the paradigm is powerfully supported by the training and intellectual orientation of the profession.112 While this is undoubtedly so, in the contrasting case of Latin America, forceful pre-existing beliefs assisted. There, the gap was starkly presented as between the official law as a whole and a separate social sphere. The plausibility of this notion is no doubt reinforced by popular ideas about Latin American lawlessness. The easy acceptance of a systemic breach between law and societal behavior dovetails with widely popularized images of Latin Americans. The figure of the “bandido” or the outlaw possibly comes into play. The unreflective assumption of Latin Americans as law breakers makes the academic diagnosis of the same appear rather unproblematic. Exoticizing these societies, indeed characterizing them as somehow beholden to different conceptions of the meaning of law, plays a large role. In this milieu, individual scholars’ observations, or even 111. See generally Trubek & Galanter, supra note 89. 112. Id. at 1082 (footnote omitted). 88 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 scientific studies if you will, about Latin Americans’ lack of attention to traffic lights or strategic manipulation of bureaucratic obstacles come to constitute evidence of a different, qualitative idea about the nature of law. This is not to say that proponents of gap analysis in Latin America harbored racist designs. That would obviously be an exaggeration. Some rather unfavorable images, however, part of the collective background, do support the relative plausibility of developmentalists’ assertions. Conservatives may have found it only natural that Latin America was fraught with lawlessness. Progressives, among them many developmentalists, relativized the differences as cultural. The move of aligning moral authority with societal behavior—rather than with official legality—was then but a short step. That is, the norms to be valued and upheld were to be found within society and not within the state, at least some of them. In any case, this framework reinforces the belief that the actual norms accepted and internalized by the people of Latin America are quite different, sociologically, from European or Western counterparts. State law by contrast stands either as an objectionable imposition of power or, in the best case, a quixotic concoction of Latin American elites. Ironically, law-and-development’s diagnosis, by pressing this image of social alternity, entrenches the notion as a dominant understanding of Latin American law as well as an increasingly accepted self-understanding by Latin Americans. The repeated representations of systemic lawlessness, or “gap,” between law and society, a debatable proposition at best about underlying reality, has a more insidious effect. It contributes to the actual internalization of this notion as part of Latin American legal identity. Clearly, my use of cultural ideas in this context does not adhere to a view of culture as an independent variable. Rather, it views culture as the aggregate of a dynamic panoply of images and devices, deployed in furtherance of myriad political projects in competition within society. As such, culture is created and given content by influential intellectual work, such as law and development scholarship, at times by claiming merely to represent an already existing reality. My point is that the claim to reality, here, is strategic—consciously or not. It is not a serious empirical claim. It is rather an argumentative commonplace, routinely deployed within modern legal discourse to challenge or support a particular position. In any event, law and development scholarship marshaled the proposition that Latin America experiences a larger degree of discrepancy between law and society, even if other legal systems may also experience divergences.113 Cataloguing these divergences has, in fact, occupied a great many Latin Americans who have taken the point seriously. This type of 113. See, e.g., Rosenn, supra note 20, at 267 (stating “[i]n Brazil, to a greater degree than in many countries, much of the ‘living law’ bears little resemblance to the law on the books”). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 89 academic work continues to attract even progressive scholars. The framework etched by developmentalists thus continues to dominate Latin American law scholarship today. D. Critique of the Hyper-Social The motivation of developmentalists and others following in their tracks, manifestly, is often (although not only) to stake an alternative, authoritative position from which to challenge dominant legal positions, clearly a valid aim. Take for example, the proposal of Jorge Witker, law professor at the Universidad Autónoma de México, who in 1974 spliced together the law-and-development framework, depicted here, and “French sociological jurisprudence” to argue in favor of bridging the gap between positive law and the law in action.114 Specifically, he suggested how such a move could be operationalized in Latin America: For example, the majority of our [Latin American] legal orders possess open institutions such as the concept of good customs, the concept of the moral, that admits for connotations that are not necessarily individualist, and the public order [which is] of a vast generality in which the social or collective interest may prevail over an absolute liberal will. Lastly, the “so-called legal lacunae” that permit, fundamentally, the judge to operate with flexibility and breadth even within legal dogmatism. In synthesis, even positivist state norms whose range of observance is limited in our societies and whose conceptual structure is essentially static, permits, overcoming the until now prevailing criteria, to search for the necessary harmony between effectiveness and validity of the norm and its efficaciousness or concrete normativity.115 In the specific context of 1960s and 1970s law and development, the alliance between international advisors and legal reformers in Latin America may have consisted of nothing more than an interest in better articulated legal decisions, requiring different considerations to be incorporated as part of accepted legal reasoning.116 114. See Jorge Witker, V., Derecho, desarrollo y formación jurídica, 24 REVISTA DE LA FACULTAD DE DERECHO DE MÉXICO 659 (1974). 115. See, e.g., id. at 663. 116. See, e.g., Carlos Gaviria Díaz, La enseñanza del derecho en nuestro medio, 27 ESTUDIOS DE DERECHO: ORGANO DE LA FACULTAD DE DERECHO Y CIENCIAS POLÍTICAS DE LA UNIVERSIDAD DE ANTIOQUIA 5 (1968). Gaviria rails against the hodge-podge, “historical” reasoning methods of mainstream Colombian jurists, which he maintains lead to legal dogmatism: 90 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 The legacy of law and development, however, is of a different order. It set the framework for subsequent reform efforts. It also catapulted forward claims about a distinct and isolated social order. In its wake, numerous attempts have sought to prove the substantiality of a dense, alternative legality existent in Latin America. As the argument goes, the formal legal system is not only politically insensitive to social interests but, moreover, is unreflective of genuine local normativity. It is this approach, deployed by developmentalists and legal sociologists alike, which continues to frame separate social and legal spheres in Latin America. However, in the wake of traditionalist critiques of social methods and arguments as non-law or as social science, to offer some traction the social field required reconstructing, not as a normal and routine source of legal renovation, but as a substantial, different, and irrepressible contrast to the accepted conception of the formal legal sphere. As such, development scholars and, more so, others following in their footsteps propose that social realities—whether characterized as modern law or a societallyderived code—must be introduced within Latin American legal systems. For many Latin American progressives, loyal to the concept of sociallyconnected law, this approach then entails the articulation of a separate and available social normativity. And, as mentioned already, considerable resources have been expended on identifying—effectively attempting to create—such a justifiable, norm-producing social content. My criticism here of this hyper-social field, in addition to rejecting the particular existence of social-legal disconnection or its purportedly extraordinary degree in Latin America, is to take objection with its extensive effects. The paradigm entrenched by development scholars treats behavioral divergences from the official legal system as evidence of a separate sphere of society. The official legal system is then presented as malfunctioning because it does not sufficiently mirror the social side. Demonstrating the content of different social behavior is taken as proof of this malfunctioning. It presents the justification for changing the formal legal system. It also suggests that “social legality,” “modern law,” or some such other better suited system take its place. These efforts by legal scholars were, and continue to be, misplaced if not outright The fear that legal formalism is instilled in many does not come from its taking part in favor or against the existing status, rather from its remaining neutral and not committing to the preservation of a cracked system nor to the struggle to replace it by one judged better. In place of a theory of that type, [they] prefer to conserve devalued doctrines or even better [doctrines] withdrawn from circulation in the scientific world, which fulfills nonetheless the ideological function assigned by the moment. Id. at 8. In its place, he argues for scientific criteria which can be demonstrated objectively as suitable to a given situation. See generally id. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 91 counterproductive. They reify the notion that a separately defensible social arena, more legitimate than the legal order, exists. In this way, it may be believed, social specificity can be more easily invoked for particular reform efforts. However, this tactic of appealing to the hyper-social, as I explain, should not be necessary. The social sphere is already part of the conventional repertoire of legal technique, even within the sources of legal authority cited by traditionalists themselves. Moreover, the vast efforts at inscribing social-based reform with authentic or organic value is counterproductive, considering the widespread skepticism with which these notions are held. Statements about social norms of this type may, in the end, be actually more easily dismissed as incapable of fulfilling their own claims. In any case, the quintessential legal reform strategy of the last century—law’s disconnectedness to society and reality—is repeatedly replayed within the Latin American context, without much effect. Continuous frustration with these failed efforts leads to larger and larger claims about an excluded social content. Additionally, a separate social normativity is presented as an option to state law. New legal techniques—often empirical ones—are said to hold the promise of introducing external society within formal legal discourse or of replacing it all together. The impetus for reform hinges on accentuating the discrepancy between state law and the social sphere. The greater the gap the more untenable the traditional system and the greater the urgency for reform. Yet, success has been misunderstood as requiring the articulation and defense of a distinct social sphere in fact. In short, developmentalists and their progeny have assisted in transforming the argumentative device of “invoking the social” as an identity-based progressive political project in opposition to the identity of the official state system. The acquiescence in this move by many progressives has resulted in substantial work directed at the project of identifying and defending such a social normativity—all with the underlying purpose ultimately of standing side-by-side or even replacing the official legal orthodoxy. Such efforts are unnecessary—as well as misguided—since interventions in official legality based on social reality can be accommodated, and exist as a routine device within modern legal systems. Ironically, it is the very work-product of legal sociologists today that continues to reinforce the notion of separateness between law and society and attempts to construct a never-sufficiently-well-articulated social alternative, situated outside legal institutions. It is this latter course which, rather than offering a promising alternative to Latin American traditionalists, falls into their hands. In effect, with the aim of forcing the consideration of social conditions within legal discourse by arguing their irrepressibility and undeniability, progressives accept the thick demarcation between legal and social realms. And, they pre-construct 92 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 the social field—deep and dense—as different from law. Moreover, these characterizations are often given the form of sociological or cultural traits. The emphasis on a marked social identity typically coincides with the vesting of Latin American informality, legal pluralism, and social practices with a scientific, sociological flavor. Yet, this quadrant or strategy of political legal struggle is already effectively preordained as non-law by traditionalists, responding to the first wave of developmentalist reform efforts.117 The implications of my claim here extend to examples and periods beyond the scope of this Essay.118 However, my hypothesis points to repeated instances in which the critical edge of social argument in Latin American legal discourse has been blunted; its traction undone by defenders of the existing legal bargains. While this Essay obviously can only begin to examine this phenomenon, the circumstances surrounding the law-and- development movement are an apt example. This is not to say that the category of social argument was rendered problematic solely because of developmentalism. This would be an overstatement. Nonetheless, the use of social argument has been rendered more problematic at various historical junctures where proponents attempted to make significant use of the device. Tracing the circumstances surrounding these other moments is a topic for additional work. The study of developmentalism here presents some significant, preliminary insights. V. TRADITIONAL LEGAL DISCOURSE REINFORCED Conventional jurists, plainly enough, maintain the political status quo by cloaking it with the authority of law. This authority is upheld through the primacy of dominant legal discourse and the discipline of accepted modes of legal reasoning. Admitting a different or more expansive, yet similarly authoritative, mode of legal reasoning would require new justifications or rationalizations for the existing political bargains. This opening could, in effect, result in the striking of different social and 117. See, e.g., SOCIOLOGÍA JURÍDICA EN AMÉRICA LATINA (Oscar Correas ed., 1991). Writing the foreword on a collection of articles on legal sociology in Latin America, Correas notes the wide divergences of these academic practices across the countries of Latin America. He notes, however, their one common feature is their politicization. He comments on the “First World perception,” in his view, that this is an inferior practice as compared to the First World’s “scientific” legal sociology. He notes the difficulty of Latin American legal sociology to get beyond politics, and he also champions the case that this political position is due to the injustices that continue to afflict Latin America (as opposed to the White world). Under my framework, Correas’ observations more than anything else reflect his condition, the marginalization (and self-marginalization) of legal sociology as political, not because of some knowledge deficiency on their part, but as is explained in the text of this Essay. 118. See generally Esquirol, supra note 8 (discussing another example in which the critical edge available through French socio-historicism was also blunted). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 93 political arrangements. It is precisely this new deal that was, in reality, the original goal of developmentalism. Progress would be achieved through incremental changes within the political economy, driven in part by the legal system, which would enlarge the class of enfranchised citizenry. This was the goal of 1960s Latin American reformism, as opposed to a more radical, revolutionary break. In effect, the notion of alternative legal techniques has the very purpose of re-dealing the cards. However, it is also this renegotiation which traditional jurists highlighted as a way to intimidate progressive reformers. The fear invoked was a disruption of the delicate political balance established through law. Absent traditional legal limits, a free-for-all could ensue. Specifically, extremist political tendencies in Latin America might not be kept in check. The political aim of developmentalists’ interventions, in this case, would be completely reversed. Rather than offer room within the legal system to pursue progressive aims, developmentalist methods could be just as easily, if not more easily, used to justify repressive regimes. Particularly, if the developmentalists in question believed in the vast malleability of law, this danger loomed large and real. Furthermore, even if a new political bargain could be struck, it would not henceforth have recourse to the unquestionable authority of law to preserve it. The legal sphere would be indelibly compromised, undermining its ability to justify a new political bargain, while also admitting its past role in legitimating the old order. The end of developmentalism offers some clues to understanding the failure of other historical attempts at introducing social reality, pragmatism, policy, or generally antiformalism within Latin American legal discourse.119 Considering the political leanings of most development lawyers, the risks presented were obviously too great. However, the choices presented were, I argue, unjustifiably limited. Reformism was too quickly defeated by the fears of its own proponents. Chiefly, that fear was made all too real as a result of underlying perceptions of Latin American political culture. The reality of autocratic, military governments and rightwing coups reinforced the plausibility of a potentially more reactionary 119. See, e.g., Bilder & Tamanaha, supra note 2, at 475-76. I would suggest that, in a remarkable contradiction, the implication of Trubek/Galanter’s objection to instrumental attitudes toward law is in direct conflict with the thrust of their argument and with their legacy to the field: what is needed in a developing country—to protect against the dangers of a purely instrumental view of law—is an established and functioning, formalistic-oriented rule-of-law system! Id. Bilder and Tamanaha fall into this false dilemma as well. They address the alternative pole, legal formalism. This is precisely the argument made by Latin American traditionalists. Formalism represented the discursive practice under the latter’s control. 94 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 political deal as a result of a shift in the legal status quo. In addition, at least for developmentalists, social norms were not in reality a democratic check on state law. Traditionalists, and chastened developmentalists, understood Latin American societies as lacking these constraints.120 The perception of such lawlessness is, in fact, what makes the ultimatum so compelling. Legal traditionalists, at least, offered the possibility of keeping right-wing rulers to some account. If belief in the unquestionability of law was somehow shaken, then the legal establishment would be at a loss to reestablish authority. Undemocratic autocrats would be able to wield their power freely.121 This conundrum has played a repeated role in dismantling reformist legal projects in Latin America. The choice facing reformers is, on the one hand, to uphold the sanctity of law with its existing trade-offs, or, on the other, to do without the legal system as a tool of social governance. They must either withdraw from reform efforts or risk losing the support, and cover, of traditionalist forces. By their rejection of social-based legal discourse, traditionalists in effect refuse to agree to law’s standing as unquestionable authority if it means legitimating a new political deal ushered in by social reformism.122 This places reformers in the position of potentially winning the battle, but at the price of losing the war. Any gains achieved would stand precarious as a result of the compromised nature of 120. Bilder and Tamanaha argue that a debilitating critique, stopping “1970s developmentalism” in its tracks, was the charge of ethnocentrism associated with liberal legalism. Id. at 481-83. My argument is that this is a rather secondary point if not an all together irrelevant concern—a red herring for both those making the claim and those rebutting it—at least in the Latin American context. Traditionalist Latin American legal discourse emphasizes its membership within the Western family of law. Thus, transplanting further aspects of Western liberal legalism is not much of an objection at all. Additionally, the entire critique of ethnocentrism is built on the dualism of law and society. Specifically, the sociological claim of a separate and autochthonous law is upheld by contrasting it with an essential and contrasting development identity. This Essay offers a different framework from which to conceptualize this dualism, and the claims and critiques that spring from it. 121. Indeed, for Gardner, for example, the Allende project of “revolution through law” consisting essentially of dusting off old laws and finding loopholes in existing laws to push through radical reforms (not in fact contemplated by the formal legal materials) demonstrates how legal instrumentalism is most effective the more authoritarian or non-democratic a government is. See GARDNER, supra note 2, at 179. Gardner’s argument basically boils down to the point that Allende’s brand of legal instrumentalism did not work in the end because he retained (did not close down) democratic legal institutions (unlike in Brazil) and arrogated legislative power to himself. See id. Under this framework, the more authoritarian the better legal instrumentalism, and thus U.S. legal models will work to legitimate whatever is said to be law. See id. 122. See, for example, Jorge Witker’s description of the conservative Chilean Supreme Court’s systematic undermining of President Salvador Allende’s social program, leading to his delegitimation and the ultimate overthrow of democratic government. Witker, supra note 115, at 66769. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 95 legal authority, sabotaged by traditionalists threatening that any social reformist success would be the product of a politicization of law. Reformism foreclosed, the option left would involve a system-wide, revolutionary rejection of official law. This was exactly the turning point for developmentalism. With few options for progressive reform that would preserve legal authority, proponents would have to reject the entire system, in terms of its foreignness or social disconnectedness, and then follow through with the conclusions. The choice, under this state of affairs, soon becomes radicalized: reject official law and draw on other social constraints as a system of governance or desist from social reform through the legal system. My argument is not in favor of either of these options. It is rather to argue against the necessary nature of this limited choice. In its place, I am advancing social-based argument within national legal discourse through to its ultimate conclusions, notwithstanding the threats of traditionalists.123 Furthermore, my analysis urges progressive reformers to re-take their engagement with official law, broadening the field of political struggle and debate over the meanings of texts and policy. My approach proposes a more democratic legal discourse, expanding both the terms and transparency of legal debate, rejecting necessitarian univocalism without foreclosing the above-political authority of law. It is not a very revolutionary or paradigm-shifting proposal, but in the Latin American context it challenges a true bottleneck choking political reform. Failing to address it only leaves a much more extreme choice, in which the only alternative is advocating the overthrow of Latin American states’ legality with little hope of achieving any better social arrangements. To clarify, my claim is not that social-based argument is a panacea for progressive reform. Like any legal technology, it has its limits and its reversals. Still, as part of the conventional repertoire of democratic legal systems, it opens a channel for alternative interpretations and positions available under state law. As such, it is a significant part of a democratic, 123. Various commentators, as well as several references in this Essay, note the specific Chilean experience from 1970 to 1973, under the socialist Salvador Allende government. It is commonly accepted that Allende’s reform strategy of “revolution through law” consisted of legal instrumentalism in relation to already existing laws. The maneuver was the design of a small circle, not enjoying the support of most of the legal profession. To the extent that combining pragmatism and state law is understood as exemplified (and exhausted) by the Allende experiment, it should be noted that the actual form that it took in Chile is quite different from my own proposal here. Allende’s legal loopholes strategy was generally perceived as an intentional misreading, or exaggeration, of often outdated legal sources by a few close collaborators. My proposal here refers to the inherent mulitiplicty comfortably available through legal interpretation and legal decisionmaking, which includes reliance on social argument. It does not seek to defend a system whereby ostensibly contrived meanings to laws-on-the-books are pushed through to justify state action. 96 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 or democratically-oriented, system of law. It is quite telling that traditional Latin American jurists have, in numerous instances, rejected and marginalized socially-based techniques. Possibly fearing class revolt, or substantial renegotiation, their objective has been to narrow the discipline of legal methods. Eliminating one of the sources of the regeneration of legal systems and their ability to respond to popular forces is, in the end, grave. The more limited the possibilities for addressing popular and democratic demands, the more vulnerable and precarious are state legality and the underlying political deal it preserves. At a minimum, even if we understand socially-based legal decisionmaking to mean merely the discourse of democratic participation and accountability, resisting it aggressively will surely backfire. Traditionalists may believe that they have much to lose by allowing for social decisionmaking, and on a personal level this may very well be. The class of jurists now exercising near exclusive ability to speak for the law would be unable to retain their monopoly. Legal discourse, at a minimum, would be democratized. Yet, from a conservative political perspective, social-based reasoning may in the long run actually be more effective. It could reinforce the authority of the legal class and foster more support for the political bargains which may be reached. Of course, those political bargains would have to be, at least discursively, struck differently. This may lead to some tangible sought-after renegotiations in certain circumstances. And, at a minimum, it would extend democratic considerations—to the extent this expanded legal discourse can provide them—throughout more of the institutions of the state. By contrast, the shibboleth of law versus society, reinforced by developmentalism and its demise, has erected a zero-sum game for thinking about Latin American law. Its legacy makes available two potential political stances, roughly speaking. Either one joins the project of making the state more like the people, or one joins the project of making the people more like the existing state. Regardless, the task remains under the discipline of this framework to champion one identity over the other. Conservative approaches to this problem describe the issue as one of the penetration of state law into popular sectors. That is, the perceived gap between law and society is to be addressed by redoubling efforts at social transformation through the legal system.124 In the main, this is the underlying blueprint for legal traditionalists in Latin America. The call for 124. See, e.g., Rosenn, supra note 32, at 543-49. Rosenn uses the notion of the Brazilian jeito to capture, in his view, an extra-legal social device to circumvent an obsolete legal system. See id. Yet, he does not argue in favor of rebuilding the legal system on the basis of the jeito. See id. Instead, he advocates for legal penetration by the formal legal system “reasonably attuned to the times and culture, a high degree of obedience to the rule of law, and impersonal, efficient administration of the laws” which would make resort to the jeito unnecessary. Id. at 548-49. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 97 legal penetration reinforces the project of strengthening the official legal system and re-making society in its image. From a progressive perspective, this project is merely the perpetuation of control by legal elites and enforcement of the traditional political deal. Legal penetration, in this view, would not be neutral. It would not merely promote the harmonization of a common national culture of legal coercion. Instead, the inherent hierarchical tilt within state law would be more effectively imposed across national society. For more progressive commentators, highlighting the discrepancy between law and society offers an indictment of the class-control and cultural insularity of state law in Latin America.125 Interventions are thus directed at offering substitutes. Progressive efforts highlight alternatives to state legality, arguing they are better attuned to local, social activity. The discrepancy between law and the social order is presented as a diagnosis of the Latin American situation. The social order is offered as an alternative to the formal legal system—although, as discussed in the case of developmentalism, without much chance of success. By accepting this duality, progressives are brought to heel. They eschew direct engagement with state law because they reject its central project of imposing the traditional political deal on society. They embrace social law as pertaining to a sphere outside the formal legal system. Yet, the latter can never be attained, or fully implemented, because it would come only at the price of renouncing the special status of law. Traditionalists can sustain this threat as long as progressives do not revisit the underlying duality premise. By shunning “formal” yet social-based argument and interpretation within national legal discourse, and not rebutting threats about law’s politicization, progressives leave open the field of state law to traditionalists. As such, they can only argue for reform from the sidelines. Progressives have in this way miscalculated the potential for intervention. By insisting on challenges from the sidelines, they have implicitly accepted the ultimatum put to them. Accepting the premise of social-legal dualism and its substantive difference reinforces the traditionalist monopoly of national legal discourse. The latter remains as the sole way of defending legal authority autonomous of the state. Like everyone else, progressives fear undermining law as a separate source of power. However, the room for progressive positions is self-selectedly peripheral if traditionalists alone are left to speak for the (national) law – no matter how much discredit is heaped from the margins in terms of class 125. See, e.g., Leopoldo Munera Ruiz, La justicia es p’a los de ruana, in SOCIOLOGÍA JURÍDICA EN AMÉRICA LATINA 45 (1991) (discussing how the alternative uses of law strategy in Colombia is based—in part as the result of a nine year reading group of social law scholars in Bogota—on an essentially materialist view of the primacy of social relations in the determination of law). 98 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 bias, social disconnectedness, and the multiplicity of other normative systems. Furthermore, progressives have not appreciated the full workings of legal discourse. Maintaining a monopoly over legal power requires continuous reinforcement of dominant rhetorical constructions. Organized interests within society—much as any good lawyer—deploy the full range of legal argument, encompassing formalism, antiformalism, pragmatism, necessitarianism, and almost any other legal technology. However, accepting the identity of official Latin American law as distinct from social life works in effect to stabilize, as long as such identity holds, the monopoly of currently dominant interests. Vesting the legal system with essentialist characteristics, accepted across the spectrum of legal politics, leads to the perceived impermeability, and thus consequently-produced impermeability, of traditionalist interpretations of law. In that order, oppositional projects in legal politics come to be conceivable, exclusively in contrasting identity terms. VI. FROM THE SIDELINES This Part focuses principally on the route taken by scholars of social law within Latin America. As noted above, development scholarship attributed the disconnection to a state law apparatus far removed from the lives of local inhabitants. To the extent state law is brought into focus, it is depicted as legal formalism, cut from a civilian mold, operated by legal elites. In addition to the differences of class it designates, the existence of a popular social law highlights the cultural, even racial, identification of Latin America’s state law. Specifically, state law stands for Latin American assimilation to the broader culture of the foreign law it emulates. In consequence, it privileges European cultural forms over local practices. In these terms, the agenda for political progressives appears to follow, as a matter of course, to recuperate the cultural and social particularity of governance norms among Latin American peoples. Ultimately, these would then take the place of an exclusionary, entrenched legal culture reproduced by and for elites. My argument is that the reaction to law and development, and the latter’s defeat, lead to, once again, a missed opportunity for reform. Rather than introduce a more democratic and pluralist legal discourse, it merely reinforced the power of traditionalist positions as the sole embodiment of law and independent check on state action. The effort’s demise, actively sought by Latin America’s legal intelligentsia, perversely provided another occasion to link social-based legal argument with political maneuvering. At the same time, it further cemented the framework of divergent social and official normativities as the central paradigm. In this way, the demise of law and development, along with other attempts to introduce reformist 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 99 techniques within Latin American legal thinking, has contributed to the current state of play and the range of positions and strategies deployed by progressives within Latin America. A. The Politics of Autochthonous Social Law Local community norms may be no more progressive than state law. Indeed, localized legality may harbor some quite troubling convictions regarding minorities, punishment, and the vulnerable. While their study may indeed offer a clearer picture of actual community sentiment, it is not necessarily a treasure trove of progressive politics. Moreover, once enshrined as organic law, local norms are less amenable to dynamic reform. Indeed, attempts to champion the rights of women or minorities are resisted by reference to long-standing community standards. And, in fact, if community legality is precisely the source of law advanced by social scholars, then it is its very particularity and deep-rooted nature that must be respected. Intervention from the outside or even by reformist elements of the local community would suffer a formidable presumption favoring tradition—however it becomes defined. The term legal pluralism, in the sense of different systems of legality, is often used to describe this project.126 It invokes alternative normative orders existing throughout society. Through this medium, community and group norms may not only enjoy comparable standing to state law, they may also offer a better description of internalized coercion within the locality. This first presupposition of scholars of the social law is based on the notion of an alternative legal code. It is a key notion as it informs the diagnosis of a misalignment of law and society in Latin America. It offers a non-racist yet often racialized explanation of the relative “irrelevance” of official law perceived in Latin America. It is not that there is a social or cultural deficiency in terms of abiding by legal obligations. Instead, the 126. See, e.g., Boaventura de Sousa Santos, Los paisajes de la justicia en las sociedades contemporáneas, in EL CALEIDOSCOPIO DE LAS JUSTICIAS EN COLOMBIA 85-150 (Boaventura de Sousa Santos & Mauricio García-Villegas eds., 2001) (noting “until recently the subject of legal pluralism was centered on the identification of local legal orders, infra-state, that coexisted in different ways with national official law”). Santos proposes a more complex notion of legal pluralism that would encompass the hybridity and inter-legality of local and national as well as global legal orders, “each one of these has its own normativity and legal rationality as a result of which relations among them are many times tense and conflictive.” Id. While Santos proposes a porous and hybrid conception, the central image is of multiple identities colliding or coming together. See generally id. My analysis suggests that this approach repeats the pitfalls and dead-ends of identity-based analysis, although it does address simplistic Manichean dualism. See also Capeller, supra note 65, at 100 (stating “[i]n this way, legal research at a local level demonstrates that pluralism and interlegality are key concepts for a post-modern conception of law”); see generally Gabriel Ignacio Gómez, Justicia comunitaria en zonas urbanas, in EL CALEIDOSCOPIO DE LAS JUSTICIAS EN COLOMBIA (1991). 100 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 point is that Latin Americans, or at least some of them, march to the beat of a different drummer. If only we could find the tune being played, the legal system could be realigned with society’s previously formed legal commitments. Additionally, legal pluralism of this type has had a popular political effect. It signifies respect for historically marginalized groups. Research agendas on particular groups’ internal orderings offers the potential of political empowerment. Armed with their own law, proponents may then expect economic and other resources to follow close at hand. Promoting norms coming from within the particular group offers a better chance for legal compliance and more respect for enforcement efforts. Thus, not only would a people’s law suggest more effective law enforcement, it would be more democratic. Again, this broad category of thinking about law is premised on the existence in Latin America of an alternative conception of law. Thus, the task at hand appears as one of uncovering the content of such alternative conception. In terms of the actual content of any such social law, the scholarship is varied.127 Of course, no coherent ready-made alternative to state law has been revealed. It should be clear that most proponents of legal pluralism and social law do not claim, which would be a large claim, an alternative legal order of the same stature waiting in the wings to be uncovered and implemented. Rather, in its most typical meaning, the notion of social law boils down to two beliefs: (1) particular legal rules exist which are more authentic (to particular groups) than state law, and (2) instances of dispute resolution are available which are more attuned to the local culture than the state. However, much of Latin American sociological jurisprudence is bogged down in endless theorizing over the type of relationship existing between law and society.128 Rummaging through a multiplicity of theories and theorists occupies scholars rather removed, striving more for a convincing blueprint of legal and social interconnectedness than those attempting to operationalize an alternative justice. In any case, there are, by way of support, sufficient development-era studies confirming the informalism with which ordinary people conduct their “legal” affairs. Informality, social norms, and the gap between law and society all dovetail in reinforcing the same duality claim. Yet, we would expect nothing different from ordinary citizens in any society. We would not expect that they conduct their interpersonal interactions as magistrates or advocates before a court of law. Nor would legal concepts or legal categories be assimilated strictly or even understood as jurists would understand them. The prevalence of an informal sector or an 127. See generally EL CALEIDOSCOPIO DE LAS JUSTICIAS EN COLOMBIA (Boaventura de Sousa Santos & Mauricio García-Villegas eds., 2001). 128. See generally SOCIOLOGÍA JURÍDICA EN AMÉRICA LATINA (1991). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 101 informal version of state law is thus far from evidence of the separate identity of social law. On the contrary, it is evidence of the commonality of legal practices. Informal or disparate application is part and parcel of any system of law and of any system of coercion, as discussed above. Additionally, arguing for a particular option on the basis of its immanence in society is not uncommon within any system of law, for several centuries now. It is not, it should be noted, a legal device leading to one type of interpretation. Differing views of a socially-based rule may be advanced; in such case, the same technology can advance different outcomes. Moreover, legal reasoning of this type also advances conservative positions, positions which can reinforce the status quo on social and political issues. This is not to say that norms or notions drawn from particular social groups may not be a valuable intervention. On the contrary, a main point of this Essay is to argue for the permeability and openness of state law to these sources of law. For the sake of clarity, however, advancing alternative, socially-inflected norms distinct from traditional interpretations is quite different than claiming autochthonous sites of norm generation which necessarily trump other positions. The latter is nothing other than a decentralizing political project, riding on a preference for more “local tradition-based” decisionmaking and the reinforcement of group identities. More than pointing out the downsides to this latter approach, my focus here is its impact on traditionalist dominance of legal discourse. B. Abandonment of Progressive, Counter-Dominant Law The appeal of “informal law” is another of the legacies of the law-anddevelopment movement for progressive scholars. Rather than devote energies to challenging traditionalist legal positions, numerous scholars have focused instead on studying the particularities of social groups within Latin American politics.129 Indeed, a significant portion of law and development scholarship and its aftermath, focuses on the law of the barrio, the law of the urban slum, the law of the armed forces, the law of the guerrillas, the law of particular indigenous groups, and the law of any plausibly identifiable social grouping.130 129. See DE SOUSA SANTOS, supra note 106; EL CALEIDOSCOPIO DE LAS JUSTICIAS EN COLOMBIA (Boaventura de Sousa Santos & Mauricio García-Villegas eds., 2001); RAQUEL YRIGOYEN FAJARDO, PAUTAS DE COORDINACIÓN ENTRE EL DERECHO INDÍGENA Y EL DERECHO ESTATAL (1999). 130. See Gómez, supra note 126. Gómez’s work, for example, is an update on developmentera studies of urban barrios. See generally id. In it, he describes how recent attempts by the Ministry of Justice to “informalize” (used to mean “decentralize”) local dispute resolution by regulating “conciliation in equity” (community justice) programs have mostly failed. See generally id. He describes the failure as one of trivializing the social. See id. at 269. 102 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 By siphoning off progressives, the emphasis on social law has thinned the ranks of counter-dominant legal discourse. While this claim is impossible to quantify, it is clear that many progressive Latin American legal thinkers adhere to sociological frameworks and empirical research agendas. By contrast, many fields of official law are thoroughly dominated by traditional, conservative scholars. Indeed, it is often difficult to find the full range of legal and political positions, afforded by the ordinarily available, multiple interpretations of legal materials. Often, a juristic orthodoxy is capable of capturing and univocally interpreting entire fields of law.131 Of course, in some cases this is assisted by the hierarchical arrangement—also part of the legal profession—which prizes some traditional academic voices over others. But, beyond this admittedly uneven playing field, many times progressives have simply not articulated the quite plausible, formal counter-arguments.132 They may disdain engaging the official materials believing they lack legitimacy. As such, the According to this perspective, the new state proposals of community justice are limited to creating uniform models of regulation and control of “small” conflicts according to which the reality of the social micro-stages and daily relations must adapt, even at the expense of the group identity in which they emerge. Id. Thus, even when the state takes an informal social approach, its performance is evaluated in the context of a “more real” social identity conflicting with an intrinsically formal legal system unwilling to share power with informal systems. See id.; see also Consuelo Acevedo et al., Justicia comunitaria en zonas campesinas: Los casos de los municipios de Caparrapi y Arcaya en Cundinamarca, in EL CALEIDOSCOPIO DE LAS JUSTICIAS EN COLOMBIA (Boaventura de Sousa Santos & Mauricio García-Villegas eds., 2001). 131. See, e.g., Jorge L. Esquirol, Can International Law Help? An Analysis of the Colombian Peace Process, 16 CONN. J. INT’L L. 23 (2000). 132. For example, Rodrigo Uprimny manifestly struggles to defend (in keeping with his professed conviction in favor of legal pluralism) the recent Colombian legislation newly instituting “justices of the peace” to administer community justice at the local level. Uprimny finds comfort in the fact that justices of the peace may be able to function as the “hinge” between state law and community norms, integrating the two. He leaves the job of constructing an “integrated” legal discourse to the newest, most vulnerable, and least resourced legal professions—these newlyformed, mostly rurally-located legal officials. No doubt opening more judicial offices, decentralizing, and making dispute-resolution available are rather positive developments. However, most studies of these state-sponsored community justice efforts (even in the same volume in which Uprimny is published) note that they are grossly hamstrung by the formal logic of state law and are much less effective (influential) than home-grown dispute-resolution structures. In short, the democratic opening that justices of the peace (as well as other judges) may make use of cannot be utopically projected as the result of de-centralization or procedural legal pluralism (and the physical contact of judges with the social), rather it is a process of construction of a national legal discourse in which progressives must take an active and engaged part. Contra Rodrigo Uprimny, Yepes ¿Justicia comunitaria en contextos violentos y antidemocráticos?, in EL CALEIDOSCOPIO DE LAS JUSTICIAS EN COLOMBIA 309 (Boaventura de Sousa Santos & Mauricio García-Villegas eds., 2001). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 103 calculation is to invoke instead “extra-legal” arguments based directly on political or social expediency. The predominant effect has been the abandonment of state law by many progressive scholars. Rather than direct their political intervention—whether it be in terms of wealth redistribution or enfranchising marginalized groups—faith has been placed in endorsing alternative, sometimes highly local, notions of legality.133 Yet, in terms of results, it has been noted already that no unproblematic or coherent alternative emerges. Instead, the social field simply presents the project of reconstructing a different legality, and the opening of a different playing field not necessarily more progressive or just. By shifting energies to constructing an ideally imagined social field, however, scholars have left most other legal battles open to more conservative colleagues.134 Whatever one’s position is as to state law or law generally, the fact remains that official legality is central to democratic governance.135 No doubt, perceptions of law’s ineffectiveness and low levels of enforcement undermine the appeal of engaging dominant legal discourse. Yet, to the extent that these make engagement seem inconsequential or irrelevant, they 133. Interestingly, in response to the rhetorical question that Boaventura de Sousa Santos asks himself as to why social practices should be thought of as separate systems of normativity, he answers, “[p]ut in these terms, this question can only be answered by another question: Why not? Why should the case of law be any different than religion, art or medicine?” See DE SOUSA SANTOS, supra note 106, at 138. My analysis here ventures a response. 134. See generally Carlos María Cárcova, Teorías Jurídicas Alternativas, in SOCIOLOGÍA JURÍDICA EN AMÉRICA LATINA, 25 (1991). In accord with the central proposition here, Cárcova puts it this way: The field of legal theory is abandoned: “Given that the traditional models do not work to account for the relation law/society, (we should) migrate toward the more productive terrains of sociology and (we should) do legal sociology.” With that, the theoretical categories organized by the traditional thinking of jurists is maintained undisturbed and the legal sociologists worry neither essentialists nor positivists. Id. at 30. 135. See Wanda de Lemos Capeller, Entre o ceticismo e a utopia: A sociologia juridica Latino-americana frente ao debate europeo, in SOCIOLOGÍA JURÍDICA EN AMÉRICA LATINA 75 (1991). Capeller recognizes the centrality of state law, and cites Boaventura de Sousa Santos for the same proposition. However, she attempts to explain the marginality of sociological jurisprudence in Brazil as a structural phenomenon, using the center/periphery metaphor; as a peripheral state, Brazil’s sociological jurisprudence is therefore “peripherical.” I think she takes the metaphor too far. My own focus is much less to attempt a comparative description of the place and role of sociological jurisprudence in Latin America versus Europe in broad structural terms. Rather, my analysis here describes an historical attempt to use this technology as part of a specific political project by a certain group of individuals. Only as a consequence, and by hypothesizing about other such possible projects, a picture of the marginalization of sociological methods can be outlined. 104 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 are deceptive. For in fact, legal argument is a significant medium of political organization, with undeniable effects throughout the polity. Thus, the question cannot be reduced to whether or not Latin Americans are respectful of traffic rules or whether or not land registries are effective in enforcing property rights. As in any legal system, there are discrepancies between the letter of the law and how it is carried out. Possibly, even, in countries with fewer resources those discrepancies are more evident. However, in terms of allocations of political and economic power, state law is a significant player even if its role at a particular point in time is to divest itself of such authority. Clearly, this is not to say that its power is equitably exercised or democratically executed. Quite the contrary, Latin American legal authority over a number of areas has been captured by a small number of personalities, typically quite circumspect about redistributing power. Such figures are conservatives by definition, they oppose undermining their own source of authority. Law thus continues to be defended as univocal and impervious to alternative interpretation. In this way, the societies’ respected legal experts are often in the position to speak for the law, effectively unopposed. This aspect of the Latin American legal profession, while not in any structural way preempting progressive reform, does in fact make it more difficult. My hypothesis, in this connection, is that the situation would be different if Latin America’s scholars of the social turned more of their attention to contestatory legal debate, especially at the national level. Offering alternatives to official positions, captured by conservative colleagues, would provide the opening of the legal system which is much desired not on the basis of an alternative conception of a coherent legality, much less in terms of a different cultural quality of law that must be recuperated or integrated. Instead, an amplified legality—more democratic and responsive to Latin America’s diverse populations—lies in challenging orthodox views of Latin America’s jurists as to what the law requires. C. Foreclosing the Potential for a More Pragmatic Legal Discourse A separate by-product of social scholars’ forays into law in Latin America is also negative. It bears repeating that this is not a comment as to any necessary implication of a social approach. It does, however, describe the way in which a social approach, in the aggregate, has operated in Latin America and what remains as its lingering effects. To the point, the hyper-social ideas reinforced by developmentalism have effectively foreclosed the exercise of a progressively-inflected pragmatism within the region. The particular history of law-and-development offers some insight on this particular point. A mainstay of this particular social approach to legal legitimacy involved de-linking state law from purely formal concepts. In other words, 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 105 to make room for alternative legality within the state, law-anddevelopment scholars found themselves in opposition to the traditional operators of Latin American legal systems. In part descriptive, in part evaluative, the operators of the traditional system were characterized as formalists. While this latter concept has many meanings, the most significant one for development scholars, however, was the rigidity of legal interpretation. In an environment where one group or class controls, the legal system is impervious to democratically responsive modes of interpretation. In other words, the legal elite is thoroughly in control and in the singular position to speak for the law. Key to changing this state of affairs was the introduction of an alternative mode of legal decisionmaking. The first target was the univocality of legal interpretation. The push for reform in legal education and broader access to courts, characteristic of law-and-development, was tailored to meet this objective. However, as was alluded to earlier, the political climate of the time made an apparently more fluid conception of law a dangerous instrument. In the hands of reactionary politicians, legal plasticity could just as easily sanction repressive measures as the more humanist goals sought by developmentalism. Once law and development scholars came around to see it this way, many withdrew their efforts. The upshot was that alternative legality, pluralism, and pragmatism became more firmly associated with particular politics, either of the far right or the far left. Consequently, it came to be seen that only in a progressive political environment could social or pragmatic notions of law thrive. In a reactionary environment, legal formalism—universal and univocal—was a better ally against arbitrary action. While no doubt this was a plausible reading of the situation at the time, it reaffirms the perception that alternative legal discourse is political while traditionalism is not. The fear of legitimating dictators surely cannot be discounted. Pushing for a transition in legal discourse which has this effect is certainly not appealing. However, desisting and furthermore characterizing the project of legal pragmatism, within the context of law and development, as an openly political calculation has left broader effects. It has reinforced the connection between the pragmatic (or social) and the non-legal, either in the form of state instrumentalism or, alternatively, cultural particularity.136 136. See, e.g., Acevedo et al., supra note 130. Presenting the still-current dualism, the authors contrast state legal organs in rural communities with the more personal interactions of campesinos with respect to conflict resolution (specifically, based on their perception of official justice as a last resort and their idiosyncratic application of official norms). The latter is conceptualized as a separate system, “la justicia de acá” in which “[i]t is the pragmatism of campesino rationality which makes possible the incorporation within their culture of this know-how (i.e. more localized justice), with concrete solutions deriving from knowledge of its causes and experience, applied by one of 106 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 The line between law and politics is further embedded, with the law on the side of only traditionalist interpretation. This configuration describes the twin fears reinforcing objections to a more open legal discourse in Latin America. Latin American jurists have traditionally been preoccupied with defending state institutions from the onslaught of unruly Latin American societies. Indeed, even sociallycommitted scholars have questioned the feasibility of liberal democratic states in Latin America. Faced with illiberal societies, the worry thus arises that states may fall prey to openly undemocratic forces. The rule of law has thus been identified with a very particular mode of legal discourse. This is not to say that the range of potential legal outcomes available under more pragmatic approaches would be excluded under Latin America’s brand of legal debate. As a discursive practice, it is not outcome-determinative per se. However, this mode of discourse does distance legal authority from the reach of local society and, clearly, legal progressives. In this way the potential range of political volatility is to be narrowed. The objective of Latin America’s legal elites is an above-politics/above-social source of authority. Their mode of doing so is a well-patrolled discourse of singular legal options. In any case, some challenges have been waged against this straightjacketting of Latin American legal reasoning. A case in point is the law-and-development attempt outlined in this Essay. To repeat, its chief means was to highlight the incongruity between social and legal orders. Progressive heirs of this strategy have further attempted to erect a social order that could rival traditional law. By reinforcing the conception of a deep social sphere, however, social pluralists’ efforts have not gotten very far. It has caused the further abandonment of progressive engagement with the official legal system, leaving orthodox jurists freer reign. Moreover, its promised rewards are always delayed until after the reconstruction of an alternative social sphere. Rather minimal, its more immediate gains have consisted of establishing exceptions to state law. As such, it has only further undermined the routine and ordinary argumentative use of “social” interpretation and argument throughout national legal discourse. VII. SOME WAYS OUT OF THE DEVELOPMENTALIST BIND This Part traces, in cursory fashion, part of the legacy of failed developmentalism in the 1960s and 1970s. It catalogues the main strategies and frameworks deployed by Latin American legal progressives today. This is but a brief sampling of the very rich legal debate currently taking place in many Latin American countries. Several of my examples draw their own.” Id. at 284. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 107 from Colombian legal scholarship, which has especially experienced a boom in recent years. These works demonstrate a variety of reactions to the limitations of the law and development paradigm. Faced with the dichotomy expressed by developmentalism, these examples reveal attempts struggling with the resultingly reinforced, dominant framework. They also offer some options for reformism and progressive intervention within Latin American legal discourse. A. Unapologetic Formalists Some progressive scholars have reclaimed the tradition of formalist legal interpretation as their own. That is, championing a sort of legal nationalism, formalism is conceived as the autochthonous mode of legal interpretation in the region.137 This is a curious turn of the meanings earlier ascribed to formalism and authenticity. Whereas formalism was perceived as the concoction of elites, informalism signified the genuine law of the people. More recent defenses of formalism attempt to turn this critique on its head. Scholars of course are careful not to justify their defense of formalism purely in terms of the authentic. Notions of authenticity have been widely debunked already. Therefore, the claim is based in terms of tradition or some such other. Formalism by extension is a significant part of Latin American legal tradition. It need not be ejected, the argument goes, in favor of some foreign vogue for pragmatist antiformalism. This is a compelling argument. It rejects the false dualism of social law and state law. It also adopts a sophisticated interpretation of authenticity. Furthermore, it acknowledges the indeterminate nature of formalism. In other words, progressive objectives need not require pragmatic legal methods. Formal interpretation, while generally associated with conservative legal decisionmaking, can serve quite well. Conversely, pragmatism or realism is no more a guarantor of an enlightened social order. This latter insight comprehends the fear experienced by development scholars. As mentioned above, development scholars placed much stock in pragmatism and the social as a way of democratizing Latin American legal systems and promoting progressive political objectives. They desisted when their methods proved equally amenable to promoting conservative goals and further entrenching military dictators. Defenders of formalism attempt to advance beyond the limitations of developmentalists. They do so by claiming formalism as their own. Additionally, this position also attempts to capitalize on the perceived strengths of formalism. That is, it is more clearly defensible as a source of 137. See, e.g., Medina, supra note 38; see also IMER FLORES, INTEGRATED JURISPRUDENCE (2001) (pre-publication text on file with author). 108 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 authority beyond the reach of sheer political power. Making law unreachable from the play of society and politics enhances its perception of objectivity and neutrality. Jurists are thus in a stronger position to interject the law as a limit on governmental power. Some of the weaknessess with this approach have to do with the relatively nontransparent and undemocratic way in which this technology works. Discussion of this point is contained above in reference to traditional modes of Latin American legal discourse. An additional weakness is that it underestimates the effect of normalization of traditional positions deploying the same type of technologies. Thus, while legal devices may be instrumentalized for a variety of positions, certain positions can become dominant through their continual repetition by the dominant legal community. In other words, in any particular legal debate, formalist arguments may be less convincing in the hands of progressives when a “formalist” interpretation has already been authoritatively advanced by traditionalists and accepted across the legal profession. As such, it may be hard to beat them at their own game. In any case, the articulation of alternatives using these same technologies is a valuable exercise, even if such positions are not immediately likely to prevail. It challenges the assumptions of necessitarianism and univocality associated with Latin American law. B. Sophisticated Dichotomists Some scholars have continued in the tradition of critiquing the discrepancy between formal state law and the workings of society. These critiques are not merely a rehashing of the distinction articulated since at least the times of Roscoe Pound. Such scholars attempt to bring new insight to the dichotomy.138 New linguistic and cultural studies theories are brought to bear on the subject. For example, some scholarship taking the existence of the duality as established analyze the reasons for its persistence. One very welldeveloped treatment of the topic pursued the symbolic power of law in Latin America. Mauricio García Villegas’ La eficacia simbólica del derecho draws on much contemporary deconstructivist theory to analyze the role of law in Colombia.139 Analogizing much of law to the preamble of many modern constitutions, the symbolic work performed is highlighted. In a certain respect, scholarship of this nature clearly provides a deeper analytic approach and genuinely wrestles with the question of ineffective law enforcement. Assuming the diagnosis is correctly identified, then, this work attempts to understand the appeal of the existing 138. See, e.g., HERNANDO DE SOTO, THE OTHER PATH (June Abbott trans., 1989). 139. See, e.g., MAURICIO GARCÍA-VILLEGAS, LA EFICACIA SIMBÓLICA DEL DERECHO (1993). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 109 situation; that is, the preference for symbolic as opposed to effective enforcement. Furthermore, this type of scholarship recognizes that the formal legal system has a function. It may not be the function desired. Nonetheless, it identifies the relevance or connection between state law and society at large. In its most extreme rendition, the gap between law and society is described in terms of an inorganic state law—quite unconnected to the local citizenry. Symbolic power, for example, signals the ordering potential of state law, even if such ordering depends on cognitive dissonance as its basis. Another excellent example, in line with neoliberal neodevelopmentalism, however, is the work of Hernando de Soto in Peru.140 In his much acclaimed, The Other Path, de Soto draws on the descriptive dualism of formal and informal sectors in Peru.141 The formal sector, in his view, consists of the legal system, official institutions, and traditional social groups such as industry associations, labor unions, and pressure groups.142 The informal sector consists of mostly peasant migrants to urban areas operating in the shadow economy.143 For de Soto, it is not a sociological or cultural difference which gives rise to the difference; rather, it is the economic inefficiency of formal legal rules.144 In his words: Let us take the invasion of state waste land as an example. What explanation can we find for this phenomenon, if we view it from a cultural or social standpoint? Is it an age-old practice which reflects Peruvians’ partiality for getting together and invading other people’s property? Of course not . . . . From a legal standpoint, on the other hand, the explanation is perfectly clear . . . . If the red tape were reduced, there might still be people who would prefer to invade land and risk all the adverse consequences, but they would be a minority . . . . Although no one denies the relative importance of social, cultural, or ethnic factors, we simply have not found any evidence to bear out the theory that they explain why a large sector of the population operates outside the law.145 140. 141. 142. 143. 144. 145. See, e.g., DE SOTO, supra note 138. See id. at 80. See generally id. See generally id. See id. at 185. Id. at 185. 110 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 De Soto’s thesis is that the legal system discriminates against “informals”—as such they have no choice but to bypass official law.146 The consequences of his view are that the formal legal system has lost social relevance. Alternatively, formalizing the mix of motivation and incentives, observable in the informal sector, would align the legal system with economic growth.147 De Soto’s analysis retains the dichotomy between law and society. He portrays it, however, as the product of economic inefficiency rather than a different Latin American conception of the nature of law.148 He bases his claims on empirical research of Peru’s extensive bureaucratic costs related to industry, housing, and transport.149 It is hard to read de Soto’s work without drawing a parallel to illegal aliens in the United States. These informals also constitute a substantial population excluded from the official legal system, systematically repressed and denied constitutional rights. Moreover, a case can be made that all groups or individuals—and their identifying activities—may claim the quality of “informals” when disfavored by official law. Adopting economic efficiency analysis may improve their lot, then again it might not. What de Soto proposes is, in effect, to renegotiate societal conflicts by the lights of economic efficiency.150 If his proposal were adopted, and the criterion of efficiency were paramount within legal decision-making, then the winners and losers would indeed look different. In this way, his proposal is much like the developmentalist one of a shift in legal methods as a mode of triggering broad-scale reform. Unlike earlier developmentalists, however, de Soto limits his method to the logic of economic gain while developmentalists placed social justice and redistribution of wealth at the top of their list. This is not to say that this argument is a dead letter. Quite the contrary, the argument that the duality, produced by the formal legal system, is economically inefficient has had a receptive audience. Neoliberals have 146. See generally id. 147. Id. at 187. It is simpler and cheaper to bring the formals and informals together by changing the law than by trying to change the characteristics of the people. To show the informals how the existing laws operate, or to try to convince them that they will increase their social standing by accepting the mercantilist system inherited from Spain, would be to alter their culture drastically. It makes more sense to adapt the law to reality than to try to change everyone’s attitudes, for the law is the most useful and deliberate instrument of change available to people. Id. 148. See generally id. 149. See generally id. 150. See generally id. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 111 embraced the point as a reason for stronger property and contract rights, in the place of current law, situated beyond the reach of shifting political deals.151 They claim that legal rules premised on the logic of efficiency are better suited to promote development than the current, formal system riddled with bureaucratic costs. Whether or not this new attempt at overhauling the traditional legal deal is actually successful remains to be seen. Neoliberalism in any case has some very diverse supporters. From a more progressive perspective, deeper analyses of the gap between law and society run parallel to developmentalism and neodevelopmentalism. They offer once and again the argument for systemwide reform, but in the name of social justice rather than economic efficiency. Surely, the distance between law on the books and law in action is a plausible object of study. However, raising this question as the essential problem with Latin American law, or as the best strategy for progressive reform, is misguided. The error stems from insisting on an already defeated 1960s strategy. The notion is that effective social reform can be achieved through informal law-led projects of social, economic, and political transformation. That is, that elite power in Latin America, exercised through official law, can be upset by a competing popular or social law. To the extent that reformminded progressive scholars continue in this belief, and thus continue to call for informal law, they forego the potential for any actual effective reform of the overall state. They in fact continue to reinforce the identity of the gap and continue to cast their lot in the losing role. C. Foreign-Modeled Realists A new outcropping of legal scholarship has attempted to champion legal pragmatism. Its basis of authority is a tried and true technique within Latin American legal discourse. Foreign authorities are marshaled in support of particular positions.152 In this version, various Latin American 151. Id. at 180. One passage is particularly illuminating: It should be pointed out that the costs of informality also affect formals and particularly increase the uncertainty of the costs of remaining formal, for there is no property right, contract, or extracontractual liability which can be regarded as constant when the state can use the legal system arbitrarily. Id. While de Soto deploys the intellectual framework of developmentalism, i.e., social/legal duality, his argument is not dependent on the differences between the formal and informal sectors (essentially they are both inefficient save the informal sector is more inefficient) and is chiefly a plea in favor of raising economic efficiency, in his reading co-terminous with strong property and contract rights, as the guiding principle of legal reform over and above local political debate. 152. See Oscar Mejía, Cesar Rodríguez, and Isabel Cristina Jaramillo (articles on file with author). 112 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 scholars have been particularly attracted to U.S. academics, but also to some Europeans, writing in the field of constitutional law, especially.153 I will focus my discussion on the general profile of this vein of scholarship. Curiously, even relatively conservative sources are marshaled as authority for progressive positions in Latin America. Defenders of the legitimacy and objectivity of the existing U.S. and common law systems are often called upon to fulfill quite a radical role. Figures such as Ronald Dworkin and John Rawls are cited to support notions such as the multiplicity of textual interpretations and the legitimacy of social considerations. In their home terrain, these scholars are understood as defenders of the system’s built-in constraints on decisionmaking. Indeed, they reinforce the legitimacy of legal decisionmaking, by reason of its qualitative difference from political or other social influences. The tactic becomes more understandable, however, in light of the suppression of social argument within dominant Latin American legal discourse, as discussed above. Instead of crafting an empiricallydemonstrable social sphere, foreign-modeled realists rely on traditional jurists from other locales. In this way for example, a U.S. jurisprudence of constraint in decision-making, which nevertheless recognizes the pliability of interpretation and the primacy of policies and principles as tie-breakers, offers Latin American progressives the room they need. Moreover, this authority is claimed as deriving from within the legal system itself, that is, as legal and not political. As such, legal operators pursuing this approach are driven to engage the formal legal materials directly. Some of the drawbacks of this strategy are parallel to its strengths. Calling upon foreign authority is a well-known mode of legal argument within Latin America. Therefore, proclaiming the genius and relevance of particular foreign scholars is likely to be effective. Judging by recent citations within constitutional decisions in some Latin American countries, this strategy is already somewhat effective. However, it harbors the dangers of ossifying a certain notion of the social, not as the dynamic interplay of local societal interests and values, but rather, as some foreignbased determination which may only be accessed by reference to foreign legal materials or foreign scholars. In other words, the effectiveness of social argument may be limited by reading it as narrowly inherent in foreign sources, and possibly as transnational law. In this way, social decisionmaking can be undermined and rendered unresponsive to local conditions, instead of merely allowing for arguments based on “social” developments in countries with similar constitutions or other legal materials. Of course, this is only conjecture. Then again, it is based on the 153. See, e.g., Sandra Morelli, Universidad Externado de Colombia (article on file with author). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 113 uses made in the past of foreign authority within Latin American legal discourse. Whether foreign-modeled realism may “bridge the gap between law and society” remains to be seen. Additionally, foreign-based realism harbors an additional pitfall. It presents the dilemma of marshaling foreign traditionalists for the purpose of local, reformist objectives. To the extent that foreign traditionalists subscribe to sociolegal discourse, however, this is not really an issue. It may pose particular questions for comparativists immersed in the legal discourse of both the United States (or Europe) and Latin America. However, the conservative pedigree of the foreign model can only stand to reinforce the Latin American reformer’s position. The difficulty is that these same authorities do not offer much beyond rhetorical uses of sociolegal discourse. At some point, some of the very same critiques levied against U.S. traditionalists, for example, would become relevant. In other words, supporting foreign model realism may merely foist the limitations of U.S. legal liberalism on Latin America. These limitations, as amply demonstrated by critical scholars, are a serious concern. However, the authority of the U.S. mainstream within contemporary Latin American legal discourse, as discussed above, serves a very different purpose. It provides expression for recurrently-repressed social-based discourse within the formal legal system. Possibly at some point such social-based discourse will be normalized in such a way that it may need to be challenged. At this point in time, however, this reformist “liberal” intervention can be quite a progressive move in certain fields. VIII. CONCLUDING THOUGHTS Developmentalist writing on Latin America has drawn some of the enduring images that we continue to hold about law in the region. This body of scholarship emphasized the looming disconnection between law and the social particularities of Latin American peoples. Another legacy of developmentalism is that its end in the mid-1970s is linked to the propensity of social-based methods to politicize law. More than just any set of images, this construction has had far-reaching effects. Specifically, it has reinforced the opposition against social transformation through the legal systems of Latin America. By accepting the ultimatum posed by traditionalists in Latin America, development scholars accepted their inability to challenge the existing political deal. Cowed by fears of lawless societies out of control, absent a well-maintained formal discourse of law’s above-politics authority, developmentalists desisted. They accepted the traditional deal cut by Latin American jurists over the potential loss of the authority of law. Additionally, they inspired a generation of Latin Americans and Latin Americanists to pursue marginally-situated projects of reform. Accepting 114 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 the framework of a more legitimate social normativity, heirs to this tradition remain busily crafting the bases for a substitute to state law. This, however, will likely not come. By definition, it is relegated to the dimension of society and minority politics—no matter how many empirical studies and research projects are conducted. By contrast, traditional jurists preserve official legal discourse against projects that threaten reform or militate in favor of a reevaluation of the traditional political deal. In part defending the political status quo, in part defending their own quite singular authority to speak for the law, traditional Latin American jurists have prevented the legal system from responding to widespread social demands. As such, rather than defuse political grievances, they aggravate them. The state as a whole becomes open to challenge and the legal system subject to charges of irrelevance. Perceived gaps between legal and social spheres and the relative unavailability of reformist social-legal discourse within Latin America are not, however, particularly useful descriptions of intrinsic features of the system. Rather, they are observations about the political projects and actors who have dominated legal discourse in the region. Making the mistake of accepting these as truths about Latin American law undermines the chances for reform and the strategies available to achieve it. LEGAL CULTURES OF LATIN AMERICA AND THE UNITED STATES: CONFLICT OR MERGER Michael Wallace Gordon* When I joined the U.F. law faculty thirty-three years ago to teach, among other subjects, seminars on law and development in Latin America and trade and investment in Latin America, I was told by Professor Bill Macdonald that an anonymous donor made available a rather attractive cash prize each year for a paper based on the theory of “how Latin Americans would be better off if they would only adopt U.S. legal institutions.” I had come to this institution largely because of my affection for “things” Latin, and the reputation of its Center for Latin American Studies. It seemed a little strange to me that we would want to impose upon Latin American legal culture characteristics that had a very confined origin—the “felt necessities of the times” arising from incidents of a battle in 1066 on Senlac Hill just north of Hastings. I had taught Comparative Law at the University of Connecticut for two years—the first such course offered there. My students enrolled believing that comparative law would mean comparing Connecticut law with Rhode Island law. France to them meant Bordeaux, as in wine, and Germany meant war movies and helmets worn by scruffy Americans who rode Harley-Davidsons. We struggled through the terms with new concepts of puissance publique, usafruct and delicts, preclusion and exequatur. But we soon found the materials wanting—they dove headlong into substantive law with not a moment to think about the legal culture of France or Germany. The Spanish legal system was not ever referred to. After all—we were “ingleses” and had won the battle of the Armada—and so much for Spain. I am uncertain about how LatCrits think about the legal cultures of Latin America and the United States, and what I might possibly add to this collection of America’s preeminent group of LatCrits. Perhaps what might be useful is to draw upon my thirty-five years of teaching law to note some examples where the two cultures have come in conflict or have merged. One might wish to know who “won,” or better, what survived, when they came in conflict or merged. An example of the former is when new states of this union in the 1800s were presented with an opportunity to choose the legal system for the state—civil or common law. An example of the latter is the more recent adoption of the North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA),1 when choices had to be made about legal processes. Let me * Chesterfield Smith Professor of Law, University of Florida, Levin College of Law, J.D., 1963, University of Connecticut; M.A., 1968, Trinity College; B.S. 1957 University of Connecticut. 1. North American Free Trade Agreement Implementation Act, Pub. L. No. 103-182, 107 115 116 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 begin with the former. Much of the current United States was under the influence of Spanish legal culture prior to the Treaty of Guadalupe in 1848.2 In 1850, the California Senate published a report on civil and common law.3 The Bar of San Francisco petitioned the committee on the judiciary, which considered the future jurisprudence for the state as “the most grave and serious duty which the present Legislature will be called upon to perform.”4 The report considered various characteristics of the civil and common law.5 The legal tradition of the area had been Spanish and, more recently, Mexican civil law. It did not take long for the committee to disclose its preferences and prejudices. It stated that: The Common Law is that system of jurisprudence which, deducing its origin from the traditionary customs and simple laws of the Saxons, becoming blended with many of the customs and laws of the Normans, enriched with the valuable portions of the Civil Law, modified and enlarged by numerous Acts of the English Parliament, . . . has grown up, . . . under the reformed religion and enlightened philosophy and literature of England, and has come down to us, amended and improved by American Legislation, and adapted to the republican principles and energetic character of the American people.6 This statement is incorrect—the common law did not absorb the valuable portions of the civil law. The reception of Roman law on the continent did not extend to England. The report also suggests that the Spanish and other forms of the civil law were based on unenlightened philosophy and literature, and a legal culture unimproved by legislation and attributable to a less than energetic people.7 The report considered several differences between the two systems. Did it do so fairly? Consider these comments: The Civil Law regards husband and wife . . . disunited in person, and with dissevered interests in property. It treats their Stat. 2057 (1993). 2. Treaty of Peace, Friendship, Limits, and Settlement With the Republic of Mexico, July 4, 1848, U.S.-Mex. 9 Stat. 922, 1948 WL 6374. 3. Report on Civil and Common Law, 1 Cal. 588, 588 (1850). 4. Id. 5. See id. 6. Id. at 592. 7. Id. at 592-93. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 117 union in the light of a partnership, no more intimate or confiding than an ordinary partnership in mercantile or commercial business. Whereas, the Common Law deems the bond which unites husband and wife, so close in its connection, and so indissoluble in its nature, that they become one in person, and for most purposes one in estate. . . . The result is, that in no country has the female sex been more highly respected and better provided for—nowhere has woman enjoyed more perfect legal protection, or been more elevated in society; and nowhere has the neptial [sic] vow been more sacredly observed, or the nuptial tie less often dissevered, than in the Common Law countries—England and the United States.8 I am not a historian of the comparative role of women in Spanish and English legal cultures, but I sense that these comments would not be fully affirmed. If the nuptial tie is more often dissevered in civil law cultures, there cannot be many married couples in Latin America. The report next comments on the male and majority. The Civil Law holds the age of majority in males, for most of the ordinary purposes of life, at twenty-five years. . . . This system retains man in a continued state of pupilage and subordination from earliest infancy, until, in some cases, his locks become hoary with age. But the Common Law absolves the age of twenty-one from parental restraint, and clothes it with the complete panoply of manhood. It bids the youth go forth into the world, to act, to strive, to suffer—an equal with his fellow man—to put forth his energies in the service of his country, or in the eager strife for the acquisition of wealth or the achievement of renown. Hence, under the latter system, the activity, the impetuosity, the talents of early manhood, stimulated by fresh aspirations of ambition, or love of gain, are, at the earliest period, put under requisition and brought into exercise, in developing the resources, and adding to the wealth and glory of a State; whilst, under the former, they stagnate for lack of sufficient inducement to action, and are to a great degree lost.9 This is a marvel of overstatement, if not misstatement. The report goes on to mention other “obvious” benefits from the common law.10 I end with one I can relate to better from my experience with commerce. 8. Id. at 594. 9. Id. 10. Id. at 594-96. 118 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 The Civil Law holds, under the doctrine of implied warranty, that where one article eventually proves to be of different material from, or of inferior quality to, that which the purchaser intended to buy, and supposed he was buying, he may require the vendor to refund the whole or a portion of the consideration received . . . . On the other hand, the Common Law more wisely says, that if B wished to guard against the contingency of a possible defect, he should have made it a part of the contract of sale, that A gives his express warranty of the merchantable quality of the goods. Its doctrine is caveat emptor; . . . the Civil Law looks upon man as incapable of judging for himself . . . .11 Has not the commercial law of the common law system changed its opinion about caveat emptor, and has not the civil law notion of implied warranty become an essential feature of modern society, whether civil or common law based? I will not dwell upon this aged report longer, nor repeat its less than generous specific comments about Mexico, which we must remember we had just been at war with for invading its own territory. There were good reasons for absorbing and preferring the common law in these Southwestern states, but they did not usually include such uncertain distinctions as related above. In reality, the Spanish legal culture was and continued to be part of the legal culture of these states, in both substantive law (e.g., real property) and procedural law (e.g., civil procedure). How interesting might these states be today had the opportunity to truly merge the best of two legal cultures been addressed. It is that issue of merger which I would like to comment on with regard to the adoption of NAFTA.12 The modesty of NAFTA, in contrast to the European Union, has not presented many opportunities to debate and select or merge legal concepts. Much of NAFTA is influenced by the earlier rules established in the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) in 1947.13 But there are several dispute resolution mechanisms in NAFTA where the legal cultures presented conflicts. For example, Chapter 19 was created to establish a binational panel review of specific agency decisions in each of the parties.14 The parties might have adopted a common standard of review, but they instead preserved the standards of review of each 11. Id. at 595. 12. See supra note 1. 13. General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade, Jan. 1, 1948, T.I.A.S. No. 1,700. 14. United States-Canada Free-Trade Agreement Implementation Act of 1988, PL 100-449, 102 Stat. 1851 (1988). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 119 nation.15 Thus, in a case I will soon sit on with one other American and three Mexicans to review the correctness of a dumping decision (involving fertilizer exported from the United States to Mexico), our panel must apply Mexican law and review the decision just as a Mexican tribunal would do.16 This is in contrast to another NAFTA dispute panel I am currently sitting on challenging not a Mexican agency decision, but a decision of the United States Department of Commerce. Two Mexicans, two other Americans, and I will determine whether the U.S. agency properly applied U.S. law. NAFTA could have adopted the United States standard of review for all hearings, or that of Mexico or Canada. I think that the experience I am having, as are other Americans and Mexicans, is valuable. We are looking at the same concepts and sitting once to apply the standards of Mexican law, and sitting another time to apply the standards of U.S. law. When the Free Trade Agreement of the Americas (FTAA)17 is adopted, there will very likely be a dumping dispute process. Will a single standard be adopted? If so, there will be some rich experience to make a better judgment than was made by the legislature in California a century and a half ago. Time prevents me from further comments on these areas, although much could be said. I do not fully understand the LatCrit movement, but I think that some of what it wishes to achieve is not unlike what I have been talking about to my students for many years, such as the comments earlier about the California report, which I have been using since I first taught Comparative Law to my University of Connecticut students in the fall of 1966. It has never made much sense to me to continue to do something my way solely because it is my way, when my neighbor’s way seems better. That is certainly appropriate when my neighbor is making Paella and flan and I am having a hot dog and jello. It also seems true when my neighbor’s legal culture has characteristics that seem more appropriate than my own. Unfortunately not many of our students are touched by comparative legal culture in the usual curriculum, but this old gringo may be a little bit of a LatCrit, or maybe more a “CivCrit,” when he continues to teach about amparo, courts of cassation, and prescripción and exequatur. Thanks for including me—if only just for a day. 15. Id. 16. Dumping involves the sale of goods by a company, for example a U.S. fertilizer company, for less in the exporting country (the United States) than in the importing country. Such sales are said to be for Less Than Fair Value (LTFV). 17. See generally Free Trade Area of Americas (Proposed Official Draft 2001), available at http://www.ftaa-alca.org/ftaadraft/eng/draft_e.doc. [Rule 12.8.5 for proposed draft]. STOP CULTURAL EXCLUSIONS (IN CHILE)!: REFLECTIONS ON THE PRINCIPLE OF MULTICULTURALISM Hugo Rojas* I. INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 122 II. DESCRIPTION OF THE RESEARCH PROJECT “MULTICULURALIDAD Y DERECHOS DE LOS PUEBLOS INDÍGENAS EN CHILE (PIMDPI-CHILE)” . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 123 III. DEFINITION AND ELEMENTS OF THE PRINCIPLE OF MULTICULTURALISM . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 127 A. Cultural Diversity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 130 B. Multicultural State . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 131 C. Multicultural Citizenship . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 133 D. Territory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 137 E. Recognition of Cultural Human Rights . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 137 F. Minimum Rights of the Principle of Multiculturalism . . . . 137 IV. MINIMUM RIGHTS OF THE PRINCIPLE OF MULTICULTURALISM . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 137 A. The Right of Self-Determination . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 139 B. The Right of Cultural Identity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 144 C. Special Rights of Representation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 147 V. CONCLUSIONS AND COMMENTS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 148 VI. FINAL COMMENTS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 150 VII. RESUMEN EN ESPAÑOL (SUMMARY IN SPANISH) . . . . . . . . . . . 152 In Chile, as in other regions, long-lasting cultural ghettos segregate society. A cultural and economic minority enforces the social codes, consumer habits, modes, values, and principles that the rest of the population, implicitly or explicitly, must follow. The social thinking of this minority (un)consciously embraces: (1) moral conservatism and Catholicism, (2) neoliberalism, (3) urban separation between social classes, (4) a strong political belief in order and authority, (5) a concept of nation as a synonym for unity between equal mestizos—diminishing cultural * Visiting Scholar at Duke University and University of North Carolina (2001). 121 122 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 diversity inside its territory, (6) assimilationist public policies, and (7) the control of the media, and, therefore, of public debate. This Essay tries to explore new arguments to present the principle of multiculturalism in legal academia. This legal-political principle is a key feature in transforming the concept of the state in Chile because it is urgent to improve the legal status of the indigenous peoples, gender minorities, religious minorities, gypsies, immigrants, and other marginalized identities. The principle of multiculturalism is an essential legal-political principle of the multicultural-state, and an orienting principle of law that: (1) values the cultural diversity of every social group that inhabits a given territory; (2) stimulates individual and collective freedom to maintain, favor, and share the patrimony and their own cultural identity; (3) encourages intergroup participation, respect, and exchange; and (4) promotes the development of the different collective identities from the moral and legal arenas, favoring mutual comprehension and the resulting inter-cultural creativity.1 I. INTRODUCTION Considering the efforts of a part of the Chilean legal academia to open a space for meaningful debate on multiculturalism, the following document can be considered as a theoretical starting point for beginners and for those who are engaging this topic for the very first time: a new proposal in the conceptualization of the principle of multiculturalism. I hope that this Essay is received as one more argumentative work aimed at producing a final modification of the political system that currently exists in Chile under the Political Constitution of 1980 imposed by Pinochet’s dictatorship. More specifically, the essence of this proposal is to collaborate in the urgent transformational process that is necessary to overcome the old model of nation-state, and to establish the foundations for a transition to a multicultural-state that, in my view, will be able to guarantee human rights and to mediate tensions among the different cultural groups and peoples that co-exist in the Chilean territory. Part I presents an overview of the Proyecto de Investigación Multiculturalidad y Derechos de los Pueblos Indígenas en Chile (PIMDPIChile). This Essay includes a brief description of the objectives of this 1. Two initial comments: (1) As the debate about multiculturalism is just starting in Chile, the legal academia faces a tremendous challenge and a great opportunity to learn from comparative experiences and theories without neglecting domestic realities and perspectives; (2) North American scholars could easily disagree with the use that some concepts and constitutional guarantees receive in these pages, mainly because legal reasoning is connected to personal meanings and views of the world. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 123 project, its importance given the current structure of the Chilean legal culture, its initial hypothesis, its alternative structure, and its methodology. The second part of this Essay presents the definition of the principle of multiculturalism as a superior and orienting criterion of the political-legal system. Each of its main elements are presented and explained: (1) cultural diversity, (2) multicultural state, (3) multicultural citizenship, (4) territory; (5) cultural human rights, and (6) minimum or fundamental rights of the principle of multiculturalism. Third, the Essay presents the minimum rights of the principle of multiculturalism: (1) the self-determination rights, (2) the cultural identity rights, and (3) the special rights of cultural representation. It is important to mention that the legal nature of these three minimum rights corresponds to a category of collective rights which classical liberal tendencies are unwilling to recognize. Finally, this Essay presents the more significant ideas that can be derived from the theoretical construction of the principle of multiculturalism, including some final comments relating to Chilean legal culture that warrant further study and contrast. II. DESCRIPTION OF THE RESEARCH PROJECT “MULTICULTURALIDAD Y DERECHOS DE LOS PUEBLOS INDÍGENAS EN CHILE (PIMDPI-CHILE)”2 The PIMDPI-Chile is an attempt to answer two questions: (1) Is it possible to reconcile legally, on the one hand, the existence and protection of a project of national integration and, on the other, the recognition of the different cultural identities that co-exist in Chile?; and (2) Is our legal system prepared to mediate the growing and complex social multiculturalism of a country that is situated in an ever more globalized world order? Contrary to what I originally believed, my research has led 2. See generally HUGO ROJAS, EL P RINCIPIO DE LA MULTICUTURALIDAD UNA PROPUESTA JURIDICA PARA PROMOVER Y PROTEGER NUESTRA DIVERSIDAD CULTURAL (2002). See also Hugo Rojas, El Principio de la Multiculturalidad, in DOCUMENTOS CULTURALES 67-145 (Bárbara Negrón ed. 2001); Hugo Rojas, El Principio de la Multiculturalidad Un aporte a la protección de los derechos humanos culturales, in 18 ANUARIO DE FILOSOFÍA JURÍDICA Y SOCIAL 451-71 (Chile) (2000). Special thanks to: Arzobispado de Santiago, Corporación Nacional de Desarrollo Indígena, Corporación Tiempo 2000, Duke University School of Law, Fundación de Documentación y Archivo de la Vicaría de la Solidaridad, Latina/o Critical Legal Theory, Inc., Ministerio de Educación, Facultad Latinoamericana de Ciencias Sociales—Chile, Pontificia Universidad Católica de Chile, Sociedad Chilena de Filosofia Jurídica y Social, The Consortium in Latin American Studies at the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill and Duke University, The Ford Foundation, Universidad Alberto Hurtado, Universidad Católica de Valparaíso, University of Dayton, University of Florida Fredric G. Levin College of Law, and University of Miami Center for Latin American and Caribbean Legal Studies. 124 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 me to answer the two questions in the negative. Indeed, given the decades of persistent cultural domination by sectors that support essentialist, hispanic, assimilationist, and monoculturalist doctrines, it turns out to be of the highest importance to counteract these tendencies by strengthening the theoretical core of the multicultural paradigm. The general objectives pursued in this research work are the following: (1) to deal in a comprehensive way with the meaning, importance, content, and legal establishment of the principle of multiculturalism, considering that it is one of the central platforms on which every multicultural-state should be based; (2) to specify and clarify some anthropological concepts and definitions that are highly relevant, but insufficiently addressed in legal dogmata; (3) to criticize the dominant and homogenizing cultural policies that have prevailed in Chile in the two first centuries of its existence as an independent nation-state;3 (4) to contribute with the dynamic nature of the public law when suggesting the incorporation of a new principle that could promote the development of interculturality and that recognizes for all cultural groups and indigenous peoples the right of keeping and protecting their own cultural identity;4 and (5) to make a comparative analysis that 3. The intellectual and symbolic construct nation-state is an association of domination of the institutional type that inside a defined territory controls the monopoly of legal production and legitimate force, regulates the monetary system, stimulates in public policies homogeneous and integrated societies according to nationalism, and even more importantly, disguises exclusionary cultural myths. We have to remember that in Latin America the nation-states seek social unity and uniformity—denying the multiethnic character of societies—using assimilationist policies and educational structures, without dissembling public efforts in the generation of nationalist collective sentiments. 4. Principles of law can be defined as abstract and superior legal criteria that reproduce the supreme cultural values that influence the law’s basis in a country, and that pretend to be accepted by the citizens’ collective conscience. The main dynamic functions of general principles of law are: (1) to control the power of bureaucratic authorities favoring human rights, (2) to inspire legislative work and discussion, and (3) to support legal interpretations, especially in hard cases. An interesting debate that has not been taken into account by the principles of law has to do with the interrelation that occurs when the classical principles of liberty, equality, and solidarity get in touch with the principle of multiculturalism. Those four principles do not necessarily oppose, but they rather complement one another, and that was my statement during Segundo Encuentro Nacional de Formación de Estudiantes de la Congregación de los Sagrados Corazones: La incorporación del Principio de la Multiculturalidad como Principio General del Derecho la realizo a partir de la Tesis de la Complementariedad entre los principios de libertad, igualdad, solidaridad y multiculturalidad. Así como sabemos que en el plano individual la libertad política no tiene sentido si no está íntimamente ligada a la libertad jurídica, en un nivel colectivo las culturas que no ven aseguradas sus libertades fundamentales (o que ven menoscabada su libertad) están en justo derecho de hacer ver los desequilibrios normativos y exigir a las autoridades la reparación del daño causado. Si todas las culturas son libres e iguales en dignidad y derechos, y si en la práctica algunas son más libres e iguales que otras, decretar la igualdad entre desiguales, sin establecer las condiciones que 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 125 could show the level of recognition of multiculturalism in different legal systems.5 The theoretical framework of the PIMDPI-Chile is divided in three parts: (1) to review the bases of the Multicultural Model; (2) to emphasize the importance of multiculturalism in modern times, focusing on the nation-state’s crisis, the globalization/localization phenomena, and the increase of migration; and (3) to analyze in comparative terms the establishment of the Principle of Multiculturalism, for example, in Latin American political constitutions, in North American legal systems, and under public international law and humanitarian law. As in all the intellectual proposals of this sort, this one in particular seeks to deconstruct essentialist representations, combat social and cultural injustice, and transform the legal discourse/structure of subordination/ oppression into an inclusive one by attending the multiple cultural experiences in Chile. First, I wish to set Chile in the phenomenon of compensen en parte las desventajas de hecho, a la larga lo único que logra es profundizar tal desigualdad. De modo que libertad, igualdad y multiculturalidad no se contraponen, sino que se articulan en la compleja misión de dotar a todas las culturas de ciertos derechos básicos colectivos y comunes; pero el cumplimiento de ello implica abrir espacios de debate y de diálogo intercultural en aras de una cultura jurídica respetuosa de todas las representaciones culturales e igualar las condiciones y los planos en los que han de darse tales interlocuciones. Por otro lado, la relación en la que aún falta mucho por hacer es la que debería existir entre el Principio de la Multiculturalidad y el Principio de la Solidaridad: en el evento de tener que reconocer normativamente a la multiculturalidad en calidad de principio, hay argumentos suficientes para sostener que su contenido y sus elementos deben estar indicados en concomitancia con lo que se ha estado avanzando respecto de la consagración jurídica del Principio de la Solidaridad. Esta estrecha vinculación no sólo se origina en un ethos solidario ni en la necesidad de armonizar los principios, sino también porque hemos visto que sólo a partir del reconocimiento de la realidad del otro como hermano-prójimo y de la comprensión sincera de los problemas que le son propios y no entendiéndolos como ajenos, es factible superar etnocentrismos, nacionalismos, chilenismos, esencialismos, etc. (presupuesto sine qua non para declarar que en Chile todos los grupos culturales son libres e iguales en dignidad y derechos). De lo dicho con anterioridad se colige que cualquier variación que se produzca en la consagración normativa de los principios señalados altera para bien o para mal la trama jurídica y, por ende, al Principio de la Multiculturalidad. Hugo Rojas, Address at Segundo Encuentro Nacional de Formación de Estudiantes de la Congregación de los Sagrados Corazones, Santiago (May 2001). 5. It is appropriate to recall that some Latin American political constitutions have valued multiculturalism and have also acknowledged indigenous peoples’ civil rights. Unfortunately, at that level, Chile is not one of those countries and it has forgotten the claims of more than a million indigenous that live in its territory (at least 8% of the population). About international law, let me say that I perceive some optimism on how recent international legal instruments are dealing with indigenous peoples’ rights. 126 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 worldwide globalization (latu sensu) in order to achieve a multicultural citizenship—that is, one that is capable of maintaining and promoting diversity among the different and many cultural identities that co-exist in its territory. Second, the legal situation of indigenous peoples in Chile is highly problematic, especially the conflicts arising from water shortages in the North and the struggle for land and property rights in the South. Nobody can be indifferent when facing the historical violation of human rights of Latin American indigenous peoples, and in our particular case of the aymara, mapuche, rapa nui, atacameños, quechua, colla, kawashkar and yámana o yágan people. I agree with Rodolfo Stavenhagen when he declares that the transgression of the human rights of indigenous peoples does not only take place in material matters—that is, the well documented dispossession and exploitation they have suffered—but also in the systematic denial of the (limited) possibilities that would allow them to preserve and develop their own cultures, including their languages, customs, rules, organizations, beliefs, and different ways of social codes.6 In Chile, de facto and de jure conditions reflect this terrible historical tendency. By absorbing all the indigenous cultures and minorities under an exclusive cultural model and by trapping these groups in cultural ghettos, the only thing dominant social and cultural forces have achieved has been, to paraphrase Bernardo Subercaseaux, the mutilation of our multiculturalism.7 This is why the so called conflicto mapuche cannot be reduced to a private dispute over property rights in land, nor to a simple matter of public disorder that warrants application of the full weight of the law. The investigative hypothesis has been: Incorporating the principle of multiculturalism in Chilean constitutionalism can be a significant and essential contribution for adapting or re-modeling the social system to pressures emerging from globalization, the discourses and movements promoting protection of cultural human rights, and new understandings of the nation-state idea reflected in Latin American panindigenous discourses. If these ideas are proven, it would follow that the “rules of the game” need to be examined and reformed in order to promote respect for diversity, diminish the climate of confrontation, secure greater autonomy for the different cultural groups that co-exist in the Chilean territory and, finally, declare legally and constitutionally the Chilean country as a state composed of many different cultural expressions. Methodologically speaking, the steps designed to accomplish the proposed objectives are: (1) a comprehensive review of the Chilean press 6. RODOLFO STAVENHAGEN, DERECHO INDÍGENA Y DERECHOS HUMANOS EN AMÉRICA LATINA 9 (1988). 7. See Bernardo Subercaseaux, Caminos interferidos: de lo político a lo cultural: Reflexiones sobre la identidad nacional, 73 ESTUDIOS PÚBLICOS 159-64 (1999). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 127 over the last three years, focusing on the ethnic conflicts; (2) planning the research work by identifying the legal problem, defining the general and specific objectives, formulating the initial hypothesis, and designing a program of work; (3) the bibliographic review of documents that have addressed the topics of multiculturalism, ethnic conflicts, human rights, indigenous rights, et cetera; (4) attendance and active participation in seminars, conferences, and debates about the conflicto mapuche, globalization, national reconciliation, the legal response to cultural changes, et cetera (in Chile as well as abroad); (5) interviews carried out by specialists on the topics of multiculturalism, indigenous law, and human rights; (6) writing a first draft; (7) the task of processing all the comments received;8 (8) the synthesis and reduction of the material in the final document; and (9) the design and implementation of the action plan. III. DEFINITION AND ELEMENTS OF THE PRINCIPLE OF MULTICULTURALISM As far as I know, the first time that the term multiculturalism was used was in the Preliminary Report of the Royal Commission on Bilingualism and Biculturalism (produced in Canada in the mid-1960s).9 Recently, people have tried to define, operationalize, characterize, value, criticize, question, or disparage the term. Before sitting down to read a document about multiculturalism, it is worth investigating the personal aspects of the author (verbigratia, the culture to which he or she belongs, the discipline to which he or she is devoted, his or her home country, geographical place, age, gender, political inclination, social class, religion, et cetera). To highlight the controversial character of this matter, it would be enough to pay attention to what Jon Stratton and Ien Ang state: As a discourse, multiculturalism can broadly—and without, for the moment, further specification—be understood as the recognition of co-existence of a plurality of cultures within the nation. Celebrated by some and rejected by others, 8. Comments and contributions made by Leslie Adams, Rodrigo Andreucci, José Aylwin, José Bengoa, Francesca Bignami, Rafael Blanco, José María Bulnes, Michael Byers, Guillermo Caballero, Thomas Clemens, Doriane Lambelet Coleman, Jerome Culp, Jorge Curilen, Fernando de Laire, Nancy Ehrenreich, Arturo Escobar, Rolf Foerster, Edmundo Fuenzalida, Sergio Fuenzalida, María Angélica Garrido, Paulina Gómez, Tibor Gutiérrez, Dadimos Haile, Jan Hoffman French, Elizabeth Iams, Elizabeth Iglesias, William Mace, Jennifer D’Arcy Maher, Jeff Marder, Jorge Montealegre, Bárbara Negrón, Sonia Olea, Alejandro Posadas, Maximiliano Prado, Vernellia Randall, Nelson Reyes, Hugo E. Rojas, Roberto Rosenthal, Pablo Salvat, Lars Schoultz, Andrea Seielstad, Agustín Squella, Carolina Stefoni, Francisco Valdés, Christian Viera, and Steven Wilkinson, among others, improve the project. All errors are mine. 9. See David BENNETT, A PRELIMINARY REPORT OF THE ROYAL COMMISSION ON BILINGUALISM (1965) (Can.). 128 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 multiculturalism is controversial precisely because of its real and perceived (in)compatibility with national unity . . . . Viewed historically, multiculturalism could be understood as the consequence of the failure of the modern project of the nation-state, which emphasised unity and sameness—a trope of identity—over difference and diversity.10 Quid sit. Multiculturalism consists in a group of different social phenomena that are derived from the complex cohabitation or co-existence of people that identify themselves with diverse cultures in the same territory.11 To be more precise, multiculturalism is the situation in which a great variety of cultural tendencies, world views, and explanations of reality cohabit within a territory—none being strong enough to dominate or eliminate the others. The principle of multiculturalism can be understood as an orienting principle of the political-legal code that: values the cultural diversity of every social group that inhabits a given territory; stimulates individual and collective freedom to maintain, favor, and share the patrimony and their own cultural identity; encourages intergroup participation, respect, and exchange; and promotes the development of the different collective identities from the moral and legal arenas, favoring mutual comprehension and the resulting intercultural creativity. This principle is the search for the highest coherence between cultural diversity/plurality and the unity of political integration.12 It can be understood historically as a consequence of the failure of the modernizing/homogenizing project known as the nation-state.13 10. Jon Stratton & Ien Ang, Multicultural Imagined Communities: Cultural Difference and National Identity in the USA and Australia, in MULTICULTURAL STATES: RETHINKING DIFFERENCE AND IDENTITY 135, 138 (David Bennett ed., 1998). 11. See ADELA CORTINA, CIUDADANOS DEL MUNDO: HACIA UNA TEORÍA DE LA CIUDADANÍA 178 (1997). 12. See generally Cynthia Hamilton, Multiculturalism as Political Strategy, in MAPPING MULTICULTURALISM 167-77 (Avery Gordon & Christopher Newfield eds., 1997). See also Bennett, supra note 9, at 89, 222. 13. There are many reasons to support the obsolescence and crisis of the nation-state, among them you can find: (1) the existence of a clear detachment between our reality—plural, multicultural, and multiethnic—and the historic emphasis that the nation-state has given to homogenize society; (2) the growing economic, technological, military, cultural, political, and social interdependence among the different world realities in relation to globalization; (3) the consequent answer and understandable defense by the traditional and local identities, as it happens in the Latin American re-ethnification processes, and the identities, acknowledgment, aspirations, and claims coming from excluded groups or cultures; (4) the actions of human rights movements; (5) the rapid and profound changes in the international system that occurred in the latter half of the twentieth century; (6) the necessity of a minimum global ethic; and (7) the failure of nationalist, ethnocentrist, evolutionist, and diffusionist theories. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 129 Multiculturalism is worthwhile, beneficial, interactive, and interculturally positive if, and only if, we protect the cultural human rights of all the actors and people involved, individually and collectively. When a government adopts and promotes a multicultural policy—active or interventionist—it explicitly accepts the legitimacy of cultural diversity. I will back up this idea quoting a basic book written by Claire Renzetti and Daniel Curran: Multiculturalism emphasizes respect for and appreciation of the cultural contributions, practices, and experiences of diverse groups. Historically, in the United States, the cultural achievements of many segments of the population . . . were downplayed or ignored, while the achievements of other groups, especially of the Anglo-Saxon heritage, were elevated . . . . Critics of multiculturalism say it promotes separatism and intergroup conflict by encouraging people to identify with their “own kind” rather than with what members of society share in common. To a large extent, however, this criticism reflects a fundamental misunderstanding of multiculturalism. The purpose of multiculturalism is not to diminish the accomplishments of the English or Western Europeans or to deny that our contemporary culture owes a great deal to our Anglo-Saxon and Western European heritage. Rather, multiculturalism simply emphasizes that many groups have played a significant role in the cultural development of the United States, and that the historical and contemporary contributions of the many diverse cultural groups that make up the United States today should be recognized and appreciated. Supporters of multiculturalism point out that the U.S. population is becoming more—not less—diverse, and a multicultural perspective is therefore increasingly necessary if the various subcultures are to forge a life together based on cooperation and mutual respect. Moreover, the rapid growth of international business and politics and the development of advanced communications technology mean culturally diverse societies have increased contact and are becoming more interdependent. This, too, should encourage us to adopt a multicultural perspective.14 It is important to strongly support the advantages of the multicultural model because the violent circumstances that have characterized the twentieth century have clearly shown that one of the most demanding collective challenges is to learn to mediate the real or potential tensions that occur when engaging cultural difference (verbigratia, radicalism and 14. CLAIRE RENZETTI & DANIEL CURRAN, LIVING SOCIOLOGY 72-73 (1998). 130 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 unyielding bipolarities). The struggle for social inclusion is not possible if it transgresses the acknowledged aspirations of the large number of cultural groups that feel alienated, excluded, or denied. Let us not forget that when trying to fight for equality or for the recognition and enforcement of their rights, cultural “Others” often find themselves pushed into highlighting their differences—their alteritas in relation to other cultural groups—and on many occasions the emphasis on difference has been misunderstood or has evolved into irreversible processes of fanaticism, fundamentalism, and/or cultural ghettos. The precaution just presented was, in some way, predicted in 1992 by Diego Iturralde when he pointed out that the Latin American Nation-States and the indigenous nations/peoples would face increasing tensions in their relationships, adding that this process would make it necessary to develop political and cultural methods for reorganizing society to create space for diversity and real pluralism.15 Against this background, the voices advocating multicultural public policies in our region are entirely justified. An sit. The ultimate foundation of multiculturalism is, above all, of an anthropological nature. Multiculturalism comes from every human being’s originality and, due to our gregarious nature, it is reflected in every group of individuals that unite and identify themselves culturally. As talking about society entails different points of view and perceptions of reality, the temporal authority must respectfully value and promote, as carefully as possible, all cultures and should refrain from privileging any particular one of them. But be careful. It is not unusual to find cultures that may be unworthy of official respect because they have proven themselves to be intolerant, exclusive, exploitative, cruel, and repressive. However, even members of intolerant cultures must enjoy the freedom to express their points of view, provided their acts do not infringe the human rights of those who do not agree with them. Living in a multicultural society is not easy. The ideal of democracy can help to some extent as a result of its practical and political structures, but it does not necessarily resolve the underlying problem. I turn now to the aforementioned elements of the principle of multiculturalism: (1) cultural diversity, (2) multicultural state, (3) multicultural citizenship, (4) territory, (5) cultural human rights, and (6) minimum or fundamental rights of the principle of multiculturalism. A. Cultural Diversity More than being simply one element of the principle of multiculturalism, a commitment to cultural diversity is a natural and 15. See Diego Iturralde, Los Pueblos Indígenas y Sus Derechos en América Latina, 15 REVISTA IIDH 12 (Costa Rica) (1992). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 131 obvious imperative in creating a social reality in which a plurality of cultures, totally or partially diverse, can co-exist. It is worth repeating an idea formulated by Charles Taylor, “in the current situation all societies are every day more multicultural and, at the same time, are every day more subject to multinational migration.”16 The importance of this element is addressed in a recent article by José Bengoa, in which he states succinctly that a modern indigenous policy must assume: (a) the multiculturalism of society as a principle; and (b) the acknowledgement of the different people that make up multiethnic societies.17 B. Multicultural State The multicultural state can be understood as a kind of state that embraces the political advances achieved in and through the project of modernity—including the effects of constitutionalism—and that, moreover, incorporates the principle of multiculturalism as a pivotal and constituent pillar. In the multicultural state, three kinds of rights are integrally and systematically articulated: the subjective public rights established in domestic law, human rights (from first, second, or third category), and the different collective rights involved in the principle of multiculturalism.18 In other words, in a state where the principle of multiculturalism rules, constitutional rights embrace the universal rights of all individuals regardless of race, ethnicity, religion, and gender, for example, as well as a series of cultural rights belonging to minority groups. Thus, MS = f (PM) MS: Multicultural-State PM: Principle of Multiculturalism 16. CHARLES TAYLOR, EL MULTICULTURALISMO Y “LA POLITICA DEL RECONOCIMIENTO” (1993). 17. See JOSÉ BENGOA, Políticas públicas y comunidades mapuches: del indigenismo a la autogestión, III 2 PERSPECTIVAS 331 (2000). 18. The transformation of the nation-state into a multicultural-state, besides the citizens’ approvals, requires: (1) total protection of civil rights and constitutional guarantees, (2) positive actions that enforce international human rights in the implementation of public policies, (3) legal recognition of individual and collective rights, (4) respect of democratic and truly representative authorities/structures, and (5) a global ethic previously agreed by consensus in a social contract or pactum by social/political actors. 132 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 Any variation in the legal configuration of the principle of multiculturalism reflects a variation in the concept of the multicultural state (that ends ultimately in a variation in the cultural human rights framework applicable to the different cultures that co-exist in a territory). Will Kymlicka explains two cases in which we are in the presence of a multicultural state: (1) if the members belong to different nations or peoples; and (2) if the members have emigrated from different nations, provided that this involves an important aspect of the personal identity and the political life.19 Other authors include a third case: cultural groups, social movements, and minority voluntary associations (although this enlargement can lead us to a concept of multi-subculturalism). Without trying to avoid or close the debate, it is important to record that Multicultural States can also be made up by two or more nations (multinational states) or by diverse ethnic groups (multiethnic states). The pluralist state must create forums and spaces in which disputes can be addressed and resolved in a climate of tolerance, where basic consensus can be reached, and where respect for cultural diversity and the multiple identities that are part of a country can be promoted. As UNESCO has maintained, finding proper ways to reconcile a new plurality with a common citizenship is an unavoidable obligation, and this objective cannot be achieved simply by building a multicultural society.20 It requires also that the state be multiculturally formed. By this, I mean a state that recognizes plurality without diminishing its integrity.21 The Australian example provides a good case in point: Multiculturalism, as government policy, has provided a new status for the state as the site where the overarching ideological principles that legitimise and vindicate the diversity of cultural practices in Australian territorial space are formulated. The state provides an ideological context for the production of the nation, but . . . the nation is not conceived as a cultural expression of the universal ideological principles represented by the state. Rather, the state acts as an institutional container of principles which are instrumental to the encouragement and management of cultural diversity . . . . In 1989, the Australian federal government launched the National Agenda for a Multicultural Australia. The very phrase ‘multicultural Australia’ suggests that ‘multiculturality’ has now been enshrined as a recognised 19. See generally WILL KYMLICKA, MULTICULTURAL CITIZENSHIP: A LIBERAL THEORY OF MINORITY RIGHTS (1996). 20. See generally UNESCO, NUESTRA DIVERSIDAD CREATIVA: INFORME DE LA COMISIÓN MUNDIAL DE CULTURA Y DESARROLLO (1996). 21. See supra note 19. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 133 essence of Australian national identity, understood as an ideal unity-in-diversity.22 C. Multicultural Citizenship When we start talking about the development of a multicultural citizenship, the premise is that the state and society facilitate the right of citizenship as a set of abilities and civic competences for the participation of a person or group in the global community to which he or she belongs. Multicultural citizenship is different from other versions of citizenship because the citizens/actors are willing in their daily lives to tolerate, respect, and incorporate the different cultures of a political community, so that no citizen is ever made to feel as a second or third class citizen. Federico Vázquez has been researching the concept of multicultural citizenship from an emancipationist model, that is to say, from the perspective of the liberation and vindication of individual and collective rights, and he defines it as: [E]l espacio del reconocimiento del Otro, como portador de una multiplicidad de sentidos sociales y culturales . . . . [A]sí la diferencia se concibe de forma relacional dentro de un marco de conflicto y de encuentro . . . . El acceso a la ciudadanía cultural se da a través del reconocimiento de la diversidad sociocultural en la esfera pública, movilizada culturalmente, y donde es posible reivindicar derechos colectivos (protecciones externas), sin el desmedro de la libertad individual (restricciones internas).23 This model, inspired by the development of intercultural ethics, is the absolute opposite of models underlying apartheid regimes (physical separation of the different cultural groups) or the assimilation of minority cultures, as happens in “melting pot” countries. In fact, in modern 22. Stratton & Ang, supra note 10, at 155-56. 23. FEDERICO VÁZQUEZ, UN CONCEPTO DE MUTACIÓN: AVENTURAS Y DESVENTURAS DE LA CIUDADANÍA SOCIAL Y MULTICULTURAL EN AMÉRICA LATINA 209 (2000) The space for the recognition of the Other, as a bearer of a wide variety of social and cultural meanings . . . . So then the difference is conceived in a relational perspective inside an area of conflict and encounter . . . . The access to the cultural citizenship it is given through the acknowledgement of the social-cultural diversity in the public sphere, culturally moved, and where it is possible to vindicate collective rights (external protections), without diminishing the individual freedom (internal restrictions). See id. (author’s translation). 134 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 democratic theory, the notion of citizenship entails a series of rights and obligations that inform its meaning (status) and whose active exercise (roles) is encouraged as much as possible in order to promote the inclusion of discriminated or dispossessed social groups as members of the citizenry. Elizabeth Jelin presents some examples of such opening reactions that might help us to distinguish between collective status and collective roles in a historical perspective: [L]a lucha contra la ‘solución final’ del nazismo, el movimiento de derechos civiles en los Estados Unidos en la década de los sesenta, las luchas contra el Apartheid en Africa del Sur en el presente, las reivindicaciones del feminismo de acabar con todas las formas de discriminación de las mujeres, los reclamos de ciudadanía de grupos étnicos minoritarios, son las manifestaciones internacionalmente más visibles y conocidas de estas luchas sociales por la inclusión, la eliminación de privilegios y la igualdad.24 Interludio. In many situations, I have detected that some authors cast United States citizenship as an example of a multicultural citizenship model. The truth is that, after researching what happens in the United States, I have concluded that at best it would be considered an example of a stagnant multicultural citizenship. We have to remember that the topic of multiculturalism has been methodically studied in the United States since the seventies, and it has been conceived as a possible alternative to the White supremacy that historically has dominated and assimilated other cultures (e.g., NativeAmericans, African-Americans, Hispanic-Americans, Pacific IslandersAmericans, Asian-Americans, Biracial and Multiracial Americans, etc.). That explains why Jamin Raskin stressed in The Eighth Annual Federalist Society Lawyers Convention, Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 24. Elizabeth Jelin, ¿Cómo construir ciudadanía? Una Visión Desde ABAJO, 55 EUR. REV. LATIN AM. & CARIBBEAN STUD. 21, 24 (1993). The struggle against the Nazism final solution, the Civil Rights Movement in the United States in the sixties, the fights against the apartheid in South Africa in the present, the feminist vindications to end with all forms of discrimination against women, the citizenship petition of minority ethnic groups, are the most visible and known international signs of these social struggles for the inclusion, expressions of the privilege elimination and equality. See id. (author’s translation). When I use the expressions “collective status” and “collective roles,” there is a peculiar connection to Ralph Linton’s anthropological theory in THE STUDY OF MAN 11331 (Prentice Hall, 1964). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 135 in 1996, the struggles and the complex gestation of the multicultural model and the subsequent legal reforms: The real glory of the American polity . . . is that we define ourselves not by exclusion, but rather by the struggle against exclusion, by the never-ending demand on the part of oppressed groups for freedom, respect, and equal ability to participate in society. These struggles for inclusion produced the Thirteenth, Fourteenth, Fifteenth, and Nineteenth Amendments. These gains were achieved at the price of much blood and sacrifice . . . . The civilizing struggles of the 1960s and 1970s, the civil rights movement, the women’s movement, the gay and lesbian movement, and the youth movement, have made this country a richer, freer, and more democratic nation than it was thirty-five years ago. And yet, our nation today is in the throes of a blacklash against “multiculturalism,” the progressive and, to my mind, inescapable cultural changes unleashed by the antiauthoritarian movement of the last several decades.25 In articulating the thesis of the U.S. multicultural stagnation, an outsider like me would have to take into account at least some of the following concerns: (1) the long-lasting assimilationist and integrationist policies that are institutionalized in the heart of White supremacy have neutralized, through a phenomenon called Americanization, the limited, though real, possibilities for cultural negotiations; (2) the population’s majority identification with the utilitarianism and individualistic line of thinking has not even allowed the debate over the possibility of protecting collective rights—in other words, individualism is one of the untouchable dogmas on which the American legal net is built; (3) the ironic historicallegal-political distancing between the always protected right of religious freedom and the cultural rights of the different social groups that live in the territory; (4) the stress on federalism and the constitutional democracy as the only supposedly favorable alternatives to assure cultural diversity; (5) the insistence on limiting the public debate over multiculturalism to linguistic or educative matters (probably because of the centripetal forces of the concept of the American Nation); (6) the objective or the mission of the U.S. public education continues to be, more or less, assimilationist and ethnocentrist: form good citizens, English-speaking, who share a common commitment to the Western values on which the nation is purportedly founded, ready to defend patriotically the country’s interests (right or wrong); and (7) the color blindness thesis in the public administration 25. Jamin B. Raskin, From “Colorblind” White Supremacy to American Multiculturalism, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL’Y 743, 744-45 (1996) (footnotes omitted). 136 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 performances is hardly compatible with the practice of the affirmative action thesis. One of the interesting points debated in the United States was emphasized by Tom Tyler in the 2000 Symposium Law, Democracy, and Society:26 when we want to prevent the potential problems that might arise in future relationships among diverse ethnicities, we have to consider that the traditional assimilationist theory that all immigrants faced when they arrived in the United States is no longer shared by all cultural groups: However, not all members of minority groups are interested [now] in assimilating. Instead, they argue for a multicultural model, such as that found in Canada. Such pressures have intensified, since many immigrants from Asian societies and many immigrants from the Spanish-speaking world have strong cultures that they resist abandoning. They support a model of society that accommodates to the moral and cultural values of diverse groups, recognizing their validity and incorporating them into overall societal values . . . . This potential change in American government and social structure has provoked widespread concern about the presumed destructive consequences of moving from a society based on identification with a single set of superordinate values and institutions to a society composed of citizens with strong identifications with their ethnic and racial subgroups—a multicultural or “mosaic” society. Concerns about the transformation of America into a “preservative of diverse alien identities,” that is, a society of “groups more or less ineradicable in their ethnic character” have been expressed by social commentators (Schlesinger, 1992). Underlying these concerns is the question of whether democratic institutions and values diminish among minorities who place greater importance on their . . . affiliation with their own ethnic subgroups than the larger society.27 The previous ideas presented lead me to predict that the social and legal stagnation of American multicultural citizenship can only be overcome if Americans start recognizing in their public policies that creating one common political culture for all citizens does not require that the different cultural groups assimilate to the ways and mores of the dominant culture, a recognition that is per se quite risky to those who benefit from the existing structure of cultural domination under White supremacy. If the demographic and geopolitical reality of multiculturalism is a human 26. Tom R. Tyler, Multiculturalism and the Willingness of Citizens to Defer to Law and to Legal Authorities, 25 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 983 (2000). 27. Id. at 987-88. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 137 struggle for recognition, then a society can be considered multicultural only if the social outsiders, silenced or dominated groups perceive themselves as included in public spaces, and participate and are heard in the building process of public policies, curricula, for example. D. Territory A territory is a physical space where people with different cultural knowledge must cohabit and which is recognized as belonging to one or more states. It is sometimes debated whether this territory must always be physical or whether it can exist symbolically as well. E. Recognition of Cultural Human Rights According to Patrice Meyer-Bisch, in this category we must locate the following rights: respect for the cultural identity, information, education, formation, participation in cultural life, and access to patrimony, including the common patrimony of humanity.28 Luis Polo mentions that cultural rights refer to different aspects of the rights related to knowledge transmission such as: (1) the right to participate in cultural activities, (2) the right of information, and (3) the right of communication and the use of the media. This last of the three is one of the more important rights for disseminating the cultural expressions of different peoples and the recognition of their cultural expressions.29 F. Minimum Rights of the Principle of Multiculturalism The difficulties of introducing these rights in the Chilean Constitution convinced me to dedicate a complete and final section to this issue. IV. MINIMUM RIGHTS OF THE PRINCIPLE OF MULTICULTURALISM The principle of multiculturalism can remain confined in the Chilean academic halls as a minority desire or aspiration, or it can be recognized, implicitly or explicitly, by statutory law. Although the content of these rights are applicable to all cultures (essential aspect) and vary from one place to another (territorial aspect), there is enough literature and empirical evidence to demonstrate that talking about multiculturalism, in different Latin American countries, loses its meaning if the following minimum rights are not recognized in introducing the principle of multiculturalism 28. Patrice Meyer-Bisch, De una sucesión de generaciones a un sistema de los derechos humanos, XIV 1 REVISTA PERSONA Y SOCIEDAD 123-31 (Chile) (2000). 29. Luis Felipe Polo Gálvez, Prospectiva de los Derechos Humanos Desde el Punto de Vista de los Derechos Culturales, XIV 1 REVISTA PERSONA Y SOCIEDAD 115 (Chile) (2000). 138 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 into constitutional hierarchy: (1) the right of self-determination of indigenous peoples, (2) the right of cultural identity, and (3) the right of proper representation, according to cultural parameters. These rights are clearly of a collective nature, because they are situated in a different dimension from individual rights: a constellation of cultural community that is aware of itself. The lack of certainty as well as the lack of cultural and political referents about the future of the social order lead me to conclude that we cannot be satisfied with a regime that focuses exclusively on individual rights and the rights of participation and decision. According to Stavenhagen, there are some situations in which individual rights cannot be completely fulfilled if collective rights are not recognized, or in another words: [D]onde el pleno ejercicio de los derechos individuales pasa necesariamente por el reconocimiento de los derechos colectivos. Así lo entendieron de hecho los redactores de los dos pactos internacionales de derechos humanos ya que el artículo primero de ambos pactos es idéntico y reza así: “Todos los pueblos tienen el derecho de libre determinación”. .... La situación de las diversas minorías étnicas y de los pueblos indígenas en el marco de los Estados nacionales o multinacionales representa otra instancia en la que el pleno ejercicio de los derechos individuales pasa por los derechos colectivos. La ‘igualdad de derechos’ de los individuos no es más que una ilusión si esta igualdad es negada por diversas circunstancias a las colectividades a las que estos individuos pertenecen. Y por el contrario, la igualdad de derechos de las colectividades étnicas resulta entonces condición necesaria (pero tal vez no suficiente) para el ejercicio de las libertades y los derechos individuales.30 But, is it valid to talk about collective rights? What do liberals say about it? Opinions vary on this question. In fact, it has caused prestigious liberals to step back in the global forum when trying to answer whether protecting individual rights (latu sensu) is sufficient or, on the contrary, whether it is necessary to include communities as subjects of law. A diverse group of thinkers, whose work cannot be regarded an alternative 30. Rodolfo Stavenhagen, Los Derechos Indígenas: Algunos Problemas Conceptuales, in CONSTRUIR LA DEMOCRACIA: DERECHOS HUMANOS, CIUDADANÍA Y SOCIEDAD EN AMÉRICA LATINA 151, at 162-63 (Elizabeth Jelin & Eric Hershberg eds., 1996) [hereinafter CONSTRUR LA DEMOCRACIA]. Compare Elizabeth M. Iglesias, International Law, Human Rights and LatCrit Theory, 28 U. MIAMI INTER-AM. L. REV. 177, 207-13 (1997). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 139 to Liberalism, but only a criticism of some of its major flaws (e.g., Alasdair MacIntyre, Michael Sandel, Charles Taylor, and Michael Walzer), favors a state that is committed with the security that a society needs for its daily working and development. Liberal versions after the publication of A Theory of Justice31 sustained the concept of State neutrality in the face of possible cultural perspectives, defining its function strictly in terms of guaranteeing the exercise of individual rights. Some authors can be found halfway between the positions explained. They do not accept the concept of collective rights as an element of a liberal theory, but they urge the importance of recognizing essential rights for the benefit of minority groups so that they can carry on with their lives (e.g., Habermas, Kymlicka).32 On the other hand, if we accept the human rights classification made by Meyer-Bisch in: (a) civil and political rights; (b) social and economic rights; (c) cultural rights; (d) structural rights (about the structural regrouping when applying the principle of indivisibility); and (e) rights of the people in vulnerable conditions;33 there cannot be the slightest doubt that the three rights of the Principle of Multiculturalism are both collective and cultural, though this does not mean they cannot be supported in a complimentary manner by other categories of human rights (e.g., the right to be free of racial, ethnic or gender-based discrimination). A. The Right of Self-Determination Although the right of self-determination of peoples/nations/communities is not the ultimate objective of this research, it is nevertheless a crucial factor in understanding the principle of multiculturalism. This is easily understood if we sociologically envision the peoples’ self-determination rights as a process or complex net of legal and political relations between one nation/people (or nations/peoples) and one State in which they are situated, whose main objective is to facilitate the attainment of certain levels of autonomy that consist of giving the people/nation the means to keep their own identity without depending on central authorities all the time. Now, the self-determination right does not correspond to all minority groups, but to peoples (including indigenous peoples) and to nations that inhabit a historically recognized territory. It does not necessarily entail 31. JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE (1971). 32. This is not the moment to criticize the liberal doctrine of individual rights. An excellent illustration has been given by Pablo Salvat, La Justicia entre Liberales y Comunitaristas (breve esbozo y comentario en torno al Caso Pinochet), XIII 3 REVISTA PERSONA Y SOCIEDAD 165 (Chile) (1999). See also Robert Justin Lipkin, Can Liberalism Justify Multiculturalism?, 45 BUFF. L. REV. 1 (1997). 33. Meyer-Bisch, supra note 28, at 130-31. 140 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 secession or political independence. On the contrary, it is possible to reach political agreements that would enable a people and nation to be part of a sovereign state in return for the recognition of some autonomy in matters of a political-cultural nature, thus allowing the specific group to dictate their own rules on previously agreed subject matters. The objective of the autonomy system is to permit determined groups, with a common tradition and shared social-cultural characteristics, to develop freely their ways of life and heritage, exercise their rights, and be in charge of their own business. This is achieved through the establishment of a special governance regime for certain member communities who choose their own authorities from within the community and exercise the jurisdictional authority legally accorded to them to decide internal community affairs.34 Examples of this are Panama and Nicaragua, but it could possibility be applied in other countries: En Panamá existe una región indígena autónoma. En Nicaragua se solucionó un difícil conflicto al firmar un estatuto de autonomía con los pueblos indígenas de la Costa Atlántica. En ninguno de estos casos autonomía implicó secesión del Estado. De parecida manera, las autonomías indígenas en México o en Perú, si se dan, tendrán que estar pactadas con el gobierno federal y ser promulgadas en la Constitución de la República y en las constituciones de cada estado federal.35 Through the application of autonomy rights, indigenous peoples can peacefully engage in activities that enable them to satisfy different matters/subjects. For example, they can (1) set their own cultural objectives, (2) choose their priorities and preferences, (3) define the rules of inter-group behavior, (4) select the appropriate media, (5) determine the contents of education (multilingual, bilingual or not bilingual), (6) solve internal conflicts, (7) celebrate their own rituals and festivities without interference, and (8) produce and reproduce internal laws. Equality of the human rights and the self-determination of the peoples are part of the group of human and fundamental rights whose recognition is related to the human dignity of the peoples and the principle of liberty. As there is a strong relationship between equality rights, basic human rights, and the right of self-determination, it is clear that the right of selfdetermination is not only essential for the communities but it is one of the most important rights of human rights theory. 34. HÉCTOR DÍAZ POLANCO, AUTONOMÍA REGIONAL: LA AUTODETERMINACIÓN DE LOS PUEBLOS INDIOS 151 (1991). 35. LUIS VILLORO, ESTADO PLURAL, PLURALIDAD DE CULTURAS 95 (1998). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 141 It has often been stated that there is a contradiction between the rights of peoples and individual rights. Authors like Stavenhagen and Villoro openly disagree with this doctrine.36 In this vein, and in supporting a vision of the correct and appropriate complementary nature of these rights, it has been said that: Si el derecho de los pueblos se considera un derecho humano fundamental, en el mismo plano que los derechos individuales [, entonces] no puede [ni debe] haber contradicción entre ellos. Los derechos humanos básicos no fundan su legitimidad en su promulgación por el Estado, se justifican en el reconocimiento de necesidades y valores previos a la constitución de cualquier asociación política. Si el “derecho de los pueblos” ha de entenderse como un derecho humano básico, tiene que fundarse en necesidades y valores supuestos en cualquier asociación política y que no deriven de ella.37 As modern anthropological legal theories have warned, it is impossible to realize individual rights without cultural collective rights. The difficult aspect is to reach peaceful agreement in the elaboration of alternatives that will reduce inter-ethnic tensions (internal and international). For this reason, the plurality of national satisfaction increasingly has been valued, especially if national harmony depends on recognizing the collective interests of social-cultural communities. If, on the one hand, you want to avoid the dangerous fragmentation of the states and, on the other, political negotiation between the parties is paralyzed, it is not always easy to reach this consensus, and the participation of an impartial third party has turned out to be a necessary strategy of recourse (in a few cases this third party has been the United Nations).38 Luis Villoro, who maintains that the indigenous problem can only be solved by legally recognizing the peoples’ autonomy, is in favor of giving self-determination rights only to those minority communities that exactly fulfill the characteristics of “a people.”39 This self-determination can be exercised in two ways by “a people”: (1) claiming for itself the right to make final decisions about its future without accepting any higher legal authority other than itself—in this case the exercise of the selfdetermination leads to a sovereignty statute (this, for example, is the 36. See Stavenhagen, supra note 30; Villoro, supra note 35. 37. VILLORO, supra note 35, at 88. 38. Remember that the Charter of the Organization of American States (OAS) proclaims that all peoples are subjects of inter-American law and subjects of collective rights, such law and right being the principal the self-determination. See Charter of the Organization of American States, Dec. 13, 1951, 119 U.N.T.S. 3 (as amended). 39. VILLORO, supra note 35. 142 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 position taken by nation-states and some nations that aspire to the sovereignty of statehood); and (2) agreeing to be part of a sovereign state, with delimited faculties, competences, and fields in which the autonomy rights could be exercised (this would be the case of indigenous autonomous regions in countries like Canada, Panama, and Nicaragua).40 Stavenhagen calls this kind of self-determination internal (political and economical organization ad intra of a people, without affecting the external relations already stated).41 The assumption is the existence of a superior pactum between the peoples and the sovereign state in which are specified the conditions of the survival and maintenance of the identity (e.g., ways of life protections and cultural reproduction in a territory), development, and education of ethnic groups’ self-government in a multicultural state, for example, the San Andrés Larraínzar Agreement between Ejército Zapatista de Liberación Nacional and the Mexican government. In sum, there are several options for effectuating the second category of self-determination rights, such as federalism, relative or partial independence, political and administrative decentralization, and others. This issue is very complex, and several politicians have failed to satisfy public opinion when trying to suggest alternatives that will promote peaceful solutions for the resolution of inter-ethnic conflicts. At the same time, the legal academy has been alert to the strategic manipulations through which the doctrine of the right of self-determination of peoples has been interpreted. For example, Elizabeth Iglesias has argued that the demise of the interstate system of sovereign nations is a potentially progressive development for the struggle against subordination, and maybe Latin American scholars should explore the implications of her remarks in connection with the Latina/o Critical Legal Theory Third Annual Conference, Miami Beach: Rather than investing further in a bankrupt system of nationstates, LatCrit theory might chart a new agenda to imagine and articulate the kinds of institutional arrangements and rights regimes that can promote the right of selfdetermination, both at the international and sub-national levels where the neoliberal project is, even now, reconfiguring and consolidating new regimes of freedom and compulsion. At an international level, this agenda might take up the pending project of promoting the full recognition of individuals as subjects of international law, for example, through the incorporation of international human rights into the institutional structures, substantive norms, and decisional 40. Id. at 94. 41. Stavenhagen, supra note 30, at 168. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 143 procedures currently regulated by international economic law. At a subnational level, this agenda might begin by rejecting the neoliberal paradigm that confines democracy to the political realm, and pursue the institutionalization of democratic governance structures throughout the inter/national economy as well. Both trajectories provide a meaningful way out of “the stateness problem,” even as they expand the parameters and meaning of democracy in ways that more readily cohere with the anti-essentialist, antisubordination commitments that are the heart of the LatCrit movement.42 If we assume a realistic point of view of the law, trying to be careful with the meaning of social events, then we will have to reintroduce Villoro’s argument directly in relation to the situation currently confronting a majority of Latin American countries: Los pueblos indígenas no han gozado de iguales oportunidades para ejercer sus derechos ciudadanos. Aunque se los declare iguales en derechos, en realidad no lo son. Carecen de las mismas oportunidades que los demás para decidir respecto de sus formas de vida, personales y sociales, y ejercerlas siguiendo su propia cultura, sin interferencias ajenas. La autonomía que reclaman es justamente la facultad de realizar, con la libertad que les confiere su derecho de ciudadanos, sus propias formas de vida. Para ello necesitan que se estatuya ese derecho en la Constitución. Esa garantía no estaría en oposición a los derechos iguales a todo ciudadano, sino, por el contrario, sería la manera de garantizar su ejercicio para los ciudadanos que no han tenido hasta ahora la posibilidad real de disfrutarlos. La autonomía, lejos de propugnar derechos opuestos a la igualdad ciudadana, pretende garantizar su ejercicio efectivo para todos los pueblos que componen la nación y no sólo para el mayoritario. Para asegurar la igualdad, es necesario reconocer 42. Elizabeth Iglesias, Foreword: Identity, Democracy, Communicative Power, Inter/National Labor Rights and the Evolution of LatCrit Theory and Community, 53 U. MIAMI L. REV. 575, 646 (1999) (footnotes omitted). Following this line of thought and after reading some of the LatCrit documents, I firmly believe that it is possible to put in contact the progressive sectors of the Chilean Legal Culture with the pivotal objectives and main postulates of the LatCrit Theory. It is probable that the potential encounters between them may require a lot of previous explanations if there really is a strong desire to take advantage of each other. I suggest, as a very convenient step, we spread the LatCrit Theory all over Latin America, break the ice in some (conservative) circles, and stop the (human rights violations) amnesia in others. 144 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 jurídicamente la autonomía allí donde se impide u obstaculiza su ejercicio.43 B. The Right of Cultural Identity The most conservative position in the Chilean jurisprudence conceives cultural identity as a set of, more or less, fixed, essential and unchanging features, that were made up in the distant past. Others, by contrast, view the national identity as a mutable historical process that is constantly under construction. One also hears skepticism concerning the idea of national identity (e.g., post-modernist theories), suggesting the idea is vague or without content and that it is used for either imaginative or discursive purposes, or both but in the end has no scientific meaning. Nevertheless, for Subercaseaux the richness of the debate that has been held in the last years, at least in Chile, has not been in vain because “it points at the deconstruction of the concept [of national identity], from the field of its historicity and also from the post-modern cultural theory.”44 Leaving aside these interesting controversies, the preliminary results of the PIMDPI-Chile has led me to ratify that the identity of a people is not something inherited or given, but rather an image constructed and projected at all times (past, present, and future). The destruction of a peoples’ identity begins with the denial of its capacity to construct its own self-image, the consequent lack of recognition with, and the cultural expressions aborted or manipulated. In his work, Estado Plural, Pluralidad de Culturas, Villoro explains the essence of a peoples’ identity, confirming the different opinions presented in connection to the vitality and humanity of cultural relativism: Por identidad de un pueblo podemos entender lo que un sujeto se representa cuando se reconoce o reconoce a otra persona como miembro de ese pueblo. Se trata, pues, de una representación intersubjetiva, compartida por una mayoría de los miembros de un pueblo, que constituiría un “sí mismo” colectivo. El “sí mismo” colectivo no es una identidad metafísica, ni siquiera metafórica. Es una realidad con la que se encuentran sociólogos y antropólogos. Los individuos están inmersos en una realidad social, su desarrollo personal no puede disociarse del intercambio con ella, su personalidad se va forjando en su participación en las creencias, actitudes, comportamientos de 43. VILLORO, supra note 35, at 102-03. 44. BERNARDO SUBERCASEAUX, CHILE O UNA LOCA HISTORIA 47 (1999) (emphasis added). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 145 los grupos a los que pertenece. Se puede hablar así de una realidad intersubjetiva compartida por los individuos de una misma colectividad. Está constituida por un sistema de creencias, actitudes y comportamientos que le son comunicados a cada miembro del grupo por su pertenencia a él. Esa realidad colectiva no consiste, por ende, en un cuerpo, ni en un sujeto de conciencia, sino en un modo de sentir, comprender y actuar en el mundo y en formas de vida compartidas, que se expresan en instituciones, comportamientos regulados, artefactos, objetos artísticos, saberes transmitidos; en suma, en lo que entendemos por una “cultura”. El problema de la identidad de los pueblos remite a su cultura.45 It is not enough to give autonomy to groups that do not share the values nor the beliefs of the dominant national majority. It is necessary to recognize the collective identity of the group through a combination of factors that enable its cultural reproduction. Some of these factors include: the validity of common law, an education that would answer the wishes of the community, religious practices, linguistic expressions, family codes, rules for social behavior, and physical spaces. The right to maintain a cultural identity is not limited to the right to maintain peoples’ distinctive cultural features, but rather to maintain its capacity for autonomous decisions that influence the cultural meanings and heritage with which the members of a culture can identify themselves. According to Jorge Larraín, the more significant the role of collective identity in the self-construction of personal identities, the more important become the symbolic meanings and historical narratives through which individuals are called to construct their identities.46 Does the right of cultural identity have limits? Of course, to begin, there are basic rights of all members of society (constitutional and internationally recognized or both), subjective or collective; in addition, the legislature has neither the constitutional nor legal power to define the rules that either will expand the scope of minority group autonomy or restrict the autonomy rights of sub-cultures.47 Finally, in those difficult or complex cases, it is the court’s responsibility to solve the conflict of interest between two or more views of the world or cultures. 45. VILLORO, supra note 35, at 65-66. 46. Jorge Larraín, Elementos teóricos para el análisis de la identidad nacional frente a la globalización, in ¿HAY PATRIA QUE DEFENDER? LA IDENTIDAD NACIONAL FRENTE A LA GLOBALIZACIÓN 75 (2000). 47. See AMITAI ETZIONI, LA NUEVA REGLA DE ORO: COMUNIDAD Y MORALIDAD EN UNA SOCIEDAD DEMOCRÁTICA 237 (1999). 146 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 The ones that accept, negotiate, and implement the details of the cultural rights of Latin American ethnic groups will have to be the states’ representatives and indigenous peoples’ representatives. But it is not enough to identify the particular elements and give expression to them in legislation. According to Enrique Mayer, it is fundamentally important to go beyond the specific contents that can be included or excluded in the declaration of these rights.48 It is also necessary—along with the declaration of these rights—to create the mechanisms of implementation, dispute resolution, and sanction.49 Two important breakthroughs in the comprehension of the right to a cultural identity are first, Article 7, Convention 169, adopted at the General Conference of the International Labor Organization in Geneva, 1989;50 and second the design of the Canadian Multicultural policy in the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms and the Canadian Multiculturalism Act.51 48. Enrique Mayer, Reflexiones sobre los derechos individuales y colectivos: los derechos étnicos, in CONSTRUIR LA DEMOCRACIA, supra note 30, at 171. 49. Id. 50. International Labor Convention (No. 169). Concerning Indigeneus and Tribal Peoples in Independent Countries, June 27, 1989, art. 7, at http://iolex.ilo.ch.1567/cgi_lex/conude.pl?c169. 51. The Government of Canada: (a) recognizes and promotes the understanding that multiculturalism reflects the cultural and racial diversity of Canadian society and acknowledges the freedom of all members of Canadian society to preserve, enhance, and share their cultural heritage; (b) recognizes and promotes the understanding that multiculturalism is a fundamental characteristic of the Canadian heritage and identity and that it provides an invaluable resource in the shaping of Canada’s future; (c) promotes the full and equitable participation of individuals and communities of all origins in the continuing evolution and shaping of Canadian society and assist them in the elimination of any barrier to such participation; (d) recognizes the existence of communities whose members share a common origin and their historic contribution to Canadian society, and enhance its development; (e) ensures that all individuals receive equal treatment and equal protection under the law, while respecting and valuing their diversity; (f) encourages and assists the social, cultural, economic, and political institutions of Canada to be both respectful and inclusive of Canada’s multicultural character; (g) promotes the understanding and creativity that arise from the interaction between individuals and communities of different origins; (h) fosters the recognition and appreciation of the diverse cultures of Canadian society and promotes the reflection and the evolving expressions of those cultures; (i) preserves and enhances the use of languages other than English and French, while strengthening the status and use of the official languages of Canada; and (j) advances multiculturalism throughout Canada in harmony with the national commitment to the official languages of Canada. All Canadian federal institutions shall: (a) ensure that Canadians of all origins have an equal opportunity to obtain employment and advancement in those institutions; (b) promote policies, programs, and practices that enhance the ability of individuals and communities of all origins to contribute to the continuing evolution of Canada; (c) promote policies, programs, and practices that enhance the understanding of, and respect for, the diversity of the members of Canadian society; (d) collect statistical data in order to enable the development of policies, programs, and practices that are sensitive and responsive to the multicultural reality of Canada; (e) make use, as appropriate, of the language skills and cultural understanding of individuals of all origins; and (f) generally, carry on their activities in a manner that is sensitive and responsive to the multicultural reality of Canada. See generally CAN. CONST. (Constitution Act, 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 147 C. Special Rights of Representation The election system is a set of rules or social-political relations that structure the designation process of authorities based on the preferences expressed by the citizens of a given political community.52 This process per se is oriented to the designation of representatives in whom the voters have entrusted the defense of their interests and the orientation on public matters. Additionally, the process itself is a very important element in the institutional architecture of modern states and the functioning of representative democracies. The election system in a democratic culture must be a framework where all later results in the elections (sample) can be as representative as possible of the total citizenry (population). Paraphrasing Josep Vallès and Agustí Bosch, we have to consider the idea of representation-sample in the sense that the group elected can be a representative selection of the voters, or at least of some of their main characteristics,53 having a strong bearing on the social legitimacy of democratic mechanisms. If the design of the election is uninominal (first-past-the-post) or binominal, we take the risk that the positions of minority groups would be ignored and that it would affect their modus vivendi as the country in general. If we have to take sides for one of these positions, it would be recommended that the candidates’ elections could be connected with proportional or distributive criteria. In this vein, there are several representative dimensions of a group of voters, including (1) place of residence, (2) political or ideological orientation, (3) gender, (4) social class, (5) profession or activity, and (6) ethnic or cultural group. The big difference between the positions that have adopted a first-pastthe-post system and the ones that recommend a distributive electoral process design is the different value that they give to representation. Proponents of the first approach reinforce the parliamentary positions of the blocs or the merger of the biggest political parties, whereas proponents of distributive formulas are those who recognize the need to achieve a fair distribution of seats among all the participants.54 Empirical and quantitative analysis of the election results in different countries using 1982) pt. I (Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms); Canadian Multiculturalism Act (1988). Cf. J.W. BERRY & J.A. LAPONCE, ETHNICITY AND CULTURE IN CANADA (1994). 52. JOSEP VALLÈS & AGUSTÍ BOSCH, SISTEMAS ELECTORALES Y GOBIERNO REPRESENTATIVO 33 (1997). 53. See id. at 12. 54. See id. at 133. 148 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 these different processes in the last fifty years reveal that the first-past-thepost and the binominal alternatives show bigger signs of disparity than the distributive system.55 Even experts have mentioned a standard deviation higher than two hundred percent (200%) from the one that used the distributive or proportional approach.56 From a historic point of view, the proportional system has been used as a result of the achievements of minority group movements tired of the postponements and their marginalization in elections that do not allow them to elect representatives under systems of a uninominal disposition. To solve the problems of underprivileged groups in known election processes, Kymlicka has tried to demonstrate that the rights of selfdetermination that could guarantee the correct representation of those groups appeal ultimately to the very basis of a representative democracy.57 The consecration of these rights would be neither undemocratic nor liberal, but it would be: una ampliación plausible de nuestras tradiciones democráticas existentes y en determinadas circunstancias es la mejor manera de asegurar que las minorías puedan expresar adecuadamente sus intereses y sus aspiraciones. Habida cuenta de que resulta vital que las minorías dispongan de procedimientos justos para que se escuche su voz en el proceso político, parece obvio que las propuestas orientadas a lograr la representación de grupo les proporcionan tales procedimientos.58 Diminishing the systematic exclusion of minority groups in the electoral processes during the (unfinished) Transition stage to democracy in Chile requires the complete transformation of the election system that currently is in use. It is significant to add that the designated senators (senadores designados) and life member senators (senadores vitalicios) increase the rates of deviation, undermine the legitimacy of the political system, and distort the concept of democracy. Indeed, the high indexes of deviation in Chile invite efforts to make a high level qualitative turn and establish a temporary system of quotas for the representation of minority groups (defined in the widest sense) for as long as necessary to remedy the lack of minority representation. V. CONCLUSIONS AND COMMENTS 55. See generally ARENO LIJPHARD, ELECTORAL SYSTEMS AND PARTY SYSTEMS: A STUDY 1945-90 (1994). 56. Id. 57. See KYMLICKA, supra note 19, at 207. 58. Id. OF TWENTY-SEVEN DEMOCRACIES 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 149 Our journey has tried to elaborate the structural and theoretical bases of a new legal-political principle of a higher order that allow or contribute to the process, within the democratic system, the challenges, risks, and benefits that will carry out cultural diversity in a context of growing globalization. The detailed study of the principle of multiculturalism is timely because there are voices of worry and skepticism considering the event of having to reconcile national identity (if there is one) with the different cultural expressions that co-exist in a territory. If multiculturalism consists of a group of social phenomena that comes from the complex co-existence of people that identify themselves with different cultures living in a same territory, then we can understand the principle of multiculturalism to be an essential legal-political principle of the multicultural state—an orienting principle of law that: (1) values the cultural diversity of every social group that inhabits a given territory; (2) stimulates individual and collective freedom to maintain, favor, and share the patrimony and the group’s own cultural identity; (3) encourages intergroup participation, respect, and exchange; and (4) promotes the development of the different collective identities from the moral and legal arenas, favoring mutual comprehension and the resulting inter-cultural creativity. When we incorporate the principle of multiculturalism at a constitutional level, we are contributing in part to: (1) better attention to cultural human rights; (2) a modern citizenship with informed and tolerant citizens, who are able to participate in the market’s opportunities and to participate in all public spaces; (3) the possibility of improving pacific systems for conflict resolution, starting with the implementation of multicultural educational projects; (4) the modernization in which social, economic, and cultural inclusion are pursued; (5) the end of the negationexclusion dialectics of the Other by the elites; and (6) positively assuming within our region the trans- and inter-cultural fabric of our condition. When I mentioned each element of the principle of multiculturalism, I paid special attention to the meaning of: (A) cultural diversity, (B) multicultural-state, (C) multicultural citizenship, (D) territory, (E) recognition of cultural human rights, and (F) recognition of the minimum or fundamental rights of the principle of multiculturalism. In relation to the minimum rights of the Principle of Multiculturalism, the peoples’ rights of self-determination that are recognized in international law need not be understood as a right to political separation, but rather as a complex net of legal-political relations between a certain people and the state authorities. Its objective is to ensure the right of peoples to the necessary level of autonomy that would guarantee the support of their own cultural identity, the establishment of priorities by the community’s internal decision-making processes, and the management of 150 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 collective matters by themselves. However, the right to maintain a cultural identity is not limited to the right to maintain peoples’ distinctive cultural features, but rather to maintain its capacity for autonomous decisions (something risky, contingent, doubly contingent, and diachronic).59 If we are talking about special rights of cultural representation, I do not disagree with the idea of temporary quotas to ensure representation in the political institutions, but I would suggest the distributive-proportional election system as a good remedy to the high deviations that the uninominal and binominal systems produce. In all other respects, it is our duty that all cultures have access to fair procedures that allow them to take meaningful part in the political process. You may have noticed that in this research work, several criticisms have been brought against: (1) the nation-state; (2) the strong roots of the dominant and exclusive legal discourse; (3) the genocidal, assimilationist, or integrationist theories, whose effects are still part of some rules and legal doctrine sectors; and (4) the legal delay in the protection of minority groups’ and indigenous peoples’ rights in Chile. The purpose of these criticisms have been none other than to find the legal-political arguments to support the validity and the advisability of: (1) proposing to the country the incorporation of the principle of multiculturalism in our constitution; (2) promoting cultural human rights and cultural diversity through the construction of a multicultural state in Chile; (3) the contributions that global minimum ethics have been producing in these kinds of subject matters;60 (4) our theory of the complementary relationship among the principles of liberty, equality, solidarity, and multiculturalism; (5) the thesis that the principle of multiculturalism is in harmony with international law, its potential consecration in formal sources, and the importance of recent debates about indigenous peoples in the international community; and (6) the processes of ethno-genesis related to the American pan-indigenous discourses. VI. FINAL COMMENTS Chileans have the fortune of living together and sharing in the bowels of a plural society that is not only multicultural, but also, multiethnic. Although we can agree at a discursive level with this statement, boasting of this or simply saying it is not enough. The background and the implications of this statement are honestly immeasurable. When it refers 59. See generally NIKLAS LUHMANN SOCIEDAD Y SISTEMA: LA AMBICIÓN DE LA TEORÍA (1997); NIKLAS LUHMANN, SISTEMAS SOCIALES: LINEAMIENTOS PARA UNA TEORÍA GENERAL (1991). 60. See Adela Cortina, Multiculturalismo y Universalismo, XIV 1 REVISTA PERSONA Y SOCIEDAD 133 (Chile) (2000). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 151 to the legal system’s actors, it comes to be an essential part in the conscious understanding of the legal evolution that we have had in the republican past. It is unacceptable to deny the following declaration: our statutory law has not been able either to avoid or to diminish the huge cultural isolation, nor to alleviate the serious structural imbalances. There is a lot to do to stop the legal structures of domination in Chile. First, scholars (and the media) should concentrate their work against the historical euro-centric, anti-indigenous, and anti-Latina/o discourse. Second, scholars should try to explore and find out more alternatives to reduce political tensions between civil society, the government, and the military, so courts and judges can maintain independence in their mission of finding the truth about human rights violations during Pinochet’s dictatorship. Third, scholars must build an inclusive legal framework that overcomes the inflexible-traditional-essentialist one that is centered on concepts as Nation-State, Chilenidad, patriotism, etc. There is no doubt that, for different reasons, such as the ethnocentrism and the patriotism or passionate nationalism, Chileans have not taken advantage of all the magnificence and shine of the wealth of the community or communities or union of social unions that live in the Chilean territory. Even more, there persists in an important sector of citizenry, especially in the dominant elites, a legal debt to the native peoples that fight: (a) to be socially and constitutionally recognized; (b) to recover a big part of their ancient territories; and (c) to have a better level of political autonomy with the purpose of reproducing their cultures and maintaining their traditions and heritages. The importance of legally recognizing our cultural plurality through the incorporation of this new principle (the one that tends to alter, in a crucial way, the spirit and the organic structure of existing public law) is not only justified for reasons of the preventive order. In fact, given the likely eventuality of consecutive turmoil and inter-cultural conflicts, a system essentially democratic, multicultural, participative, inclusive, and representative is the best means for processing the interests of the ones involved in a context of respect of human rights (and also to pacify fundamentalism). But a second argument comes up with force: considering the new challenges that emerge from the world or the globalization phenomena–for example the rapid rhythms of migratory population movements (permanent, seasonal, or temporary), the force of the media, international investments, and stock market transactions—all make me believe that, as days go by, our society has to be alert to the complex ups and downs in this upward direction to multiculturalism, happening with different intensities, but that reaches all the world. If we want to live together, we will have to incorporate changes in the political system, because if we leave unchanged the current pseudodemocratic structures that offer little participation, our future inevitably 152 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 will be unstable (or not too encouraging). I hope that the solidarity ethos is a top priority when trying to guarantee cultural diversity, plurality of interests, opinions, and values through a participative construction of the multicultural state (until now the only one capable of enabling the existence of the different cultural identities and, if internally agreed on by the members of these cultural groups, the only one capable of contacting these cultural groups to establish mutual recognition). Even though we have awoken to a multicultural country, this multiculturalism remains mutilated in the legal and social areas. As our current legal code is not prepared to process efficiently the growing and irreversible social multiculturalism, it is of the highest importance to debate the proposals directed to assume the compatibility among the unitarian political project and the multiple projects that come from the different cultures. One of those prospective proposals that, I am convinced, will favor the recognition (and tolerant and reciprocal understanding) of the different cultures of Chilean society, is the one that I have presented under the name of the principle of multiculturalism. VII. RESUMEN EN ESPAÑOL (SUMMARY IN SPANISH) No quisiera desaprovechar la oportunidad que Florida Law Review me ha dado, al publicar estas reflexiones sobre el Principio de la Multiculturalidad, para agradecer la hospitalidad de la Escuela de Derecho de la Universidad de Florida y para felicitar al Comité Organizador de la Sexta Conferencia Anual de LatCrit (Gainesville, abril de 2001). Además, me parece del todo apropiado resumir algunas de las ideas que han sido planteadas en este artículo para facilitar o motivar investigaciones similares de académicos de habla hispana.61 Es común apreciar dentro de la historiografía conservadora y esencialista un cierto culto hacia el mito de la Chilenidad, como queriendo destacar que la gran mayoría de los habitantes de la República serían mestizos, hispano parlantes, monógamos, heterosexuales, católicos, sedentarios, occidentales. Sin embargo, la realidad es distinta y las minorías han demostrado ser mucho menos flexibles de lo que superficialmente se piensa o contempla: por una parte sabemos que existe un porcentaje importante de inmigrantes provenientes de las más diversas 61. No haber incorporado esta sección al final del ensayo hubiera sido una clara señal de contradicción con lo que he estado sosteniendo. El multiculturalismo no sólo puede ser visto desde la perspectiva macro-sociológica, sino también en nuestros quehaceres y cotidianeidad, incluyendo nuestras actividades laborales y académicas. Es cierto que el inglés se ha estado transformando en un idioma globalizado que permite a las personas de diferentes culturas utilizarlo como un mínimo denominador comunicacional, pero si se escribe pensando en las dificultades de las latinas y los latinos, anhelando mayores índices de justicia social, lo que a todas luces corresponde es fortalecer y mantener el bilingüismo en las revistas especializadas. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 153 latitudes, también estamos ciertos que más de un millón de personas se identifica con alguno de los pueblos indígenas y que se están generando procesos de etnogénesis, no olvidemos el nomadismo del pueblo gitano, tampoco que las estadísticas muestran cómo en las últimas décadas ha ido descendiendo el porcentaje de católicos en la población y, en contrapartida, ha aumentado el número de fieles de otros credos religiosos. Destinar esfuerzos para demostrar algo tan notorio como nuestra diversidad cultural no sólo sería algo inoficioso sino reiterativo, pues diversas encuestas e investigaciones ya lo han logrado con notable éxito y rigurosidad científica. Por el contrario, el aporte verdadero que se puede realizar desde la academia es ofrecer los marcos teóricos que puedan utilizar los actores sociales y políticos para lograr que el sistema político sea más inclusivo y menos excluyente. Por eso he intentado explicar los nódulos teóricos del Estado-Multicultural de una manera diferente a lo que a la fecha ocurre en las aulas, esto es, identificando a lo que en puridad denomino Principio de la Multiculturalidad. En otras palabras, y tal como fuera señalado en la primera parte de la Introducción, en apoyo de los incipientes esfuerzos que se pueden detectar en parte de la doctrina chilena por abrir un debate profundo sobre multiculturalidad, en este documento se sugiere un punto de partida teórico y que puede ser útil tanto para iniciados como para quienes se acercan por vez primera al tema: una propuesta diferente de conceptualización del novísimo principio de la multiculturalidad. En la primera parte del documento se ofrece una visión panorámica del Proyecto de Investigación Multiculturalidad y Derechos de los Pueblos Indígenas en Chile (PIMDPI-Chile). Se mencionan sumariamente sus objetivos, las sospechas que justifican su importancia (o al menos que debieran llamar la atención de la cultura jurídica chilena), la hipótesis inicial, la estructura y la metodología. A continuación se da a conocer la definición del PM, en cuanto principio superior y orientador del sistema jurídico-político, y se presta atención a cada uno de sus elementos principales: (1) diversidad cultural; (2) Estado-Multicultural; (3) ciudadanía multicultural; (4) territorio; (5) derechos humanos culturales; y (6) derechos mínimos o fundamentales del Principio de la Multiculturalidad: (A) el derecho a la libre determinación de los pueblos; (B) el derecho a la identidad cultural; y (C) los derechos especiales de representación. Por último, como corresponde a todo trabajo de esta naturaleza, se transcriben las Conclusiones más importantes sobre la construcción teórica del PM y se formulan algunos comentarios finales que requieren posteriores estudios y contrastes. En apretada síntesis, el recorrido efectuado ha pretendido acotar en parte las bases estructurales y normativas de un nuevo principio jurídicopolítico de rango superior que permite o contribuye a procesar al interior del sistema democrático los desafíos, riesgos y beneficios que conlleva la 154 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 diversidad cultural y la heterogeneidad social, en un contexto ascendente de globalización. El estudio pormenorizado del Principio de la Multiculturalidad es oportuno puesto que suenan voces de inquietud e incredulidad ante la eventualidad de tener que compatibilizar toda la temática de la identidad nacional (si es que la hay) con las diversas expresiones culturales que coexisten dentro del territorio. Si la multiculturalidad consiste en un conjunto variado de fenómenos sociales que derivan de la convivencia y/o coexistencia compleja de personas que se identifican con culturas diversas en un mismo territorio; es factible entender al Principio de la Multiculturalidad, en cuanto principio jurídico-político esencial del Estado-Multicultural, como aquel valor orientador que: (1°) valora la diversidad cultural de cada uno de los componentes de la sociedad; (2°) promueve la libertad individual y colectiva para mantener y compartir los múltiples patrimonios e identidades culturales propios; (3°) fomenta la participación, el respeto y el intercambio intergrupal; y (4°) promociona el desarrollo de las distintas identidades colectivas desde los ámbitos moral y jurídico, favoreciendo la comprensión mutua y la creatividad resultante. Al pretender consagrar el Principio de la Multiculturalidad en el nivel constitucional se está contribuyendo en parte a: (1) una mejor atención de los derechos humanos culturales, (2) una ciudadanía moderna dotada de ciudadanos informados y tolerantes capaces de intervenir en las oportunidades de los mercados y de participar en todos los espacios públicos, (3) la posibilidad de mejorar los sistemas pacíficos resolutorios de conflictos, partiendo por la implementación de proyectos pedagógicos multiculturales, (4) una modernización en la que se persigue la inclusión social, económica y cultural, (5) la terminación de la dialéctica de la negación-exclusión del otro por parte de las élites, y (6) asumir positivamente en la región nuestra condición de tejido trans e intercultural. En cuanto a los derechos mínimos del Principio de la Multiculturalidad, la autonomía de los pueblos reconocida en el derecho internacional no debe interpretarse como un derecho a la separación política sino más bien como una compleja red de relaciones jurídico-políticas entre un pueblo determinado y la autoridad estatal, cuyo objetivo es alcanzar ciertos márgenes o niveles de libertad que aseguren la mantención de la propia identidad cultural, la fijación de las prioridades de la colectividad y el manejo de los asuntos colectivos por sí mismos. Por otro lado, el derecho a la mantención de la identidad cultural no conduce a la preservación de los rasgos distintivos, sino al mantenimiento irrestricto y sin cuestionamientos de capacidad autónoma de decisión y de cambio desde la retroalimentación de los integrantes de una cultura, produciendo en los individuos los significados e historias con las cuales se puedan identificar (lo que puede cambiar contingente y diacrónicamente). Si de los derechos especiales de representación se trata, los sistemas de cuotas y los sistemas 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 155 electorales proporcionales son buenos paliativos a las altísimas desviaciones de los modelos mayoritaristas. Por lo demás, es un deber que todas las culturas dispongan de procedimientos justos para que se escuche sus voces en el proceso político. Se podrá haber apreciado que en este documento se han esbozado críticas contra: (1) el Estado-Nación; (2) las hercúleas raíces del paradigma jurídico monocultural; (3) las teorías genocidas, asimilacionistas o integracionistas, cuyos resabios aún permanecen en algunas normas y sectores doctrinarios; (4) el atraso jurídico en la protección de los derechos de las minorías y de los pueblos indígenas en Chile. El sentido de tales detracciones no ha sido otro que buscar los argumentos jurídico-políticos para sostener la validez y la conveniencia de: (1) proponer al país la introducción del Principio de la Multiculturalidad en nuestro ordenamiento constitucional; (2) promover los derechos humanos culturales y la diversidad cultural por medio de la construcción del Estado-Multicultural en Chile; (3) los aportes que la ética universal de mínimos ha estado haciendo en este tipo de materias; (4) nuestra teoría de la complementariedad entre los principios de libertad, igualdad, solidaridad y multiculturalidad; (5) la tesis que el Principio de la Multiculturalidad está en armonía con el derecho internacional, su potencial consagración en las fuentes formales y la trascendencia de los últimos debates en Naciones Unidas sobre los derechos de los pueblos indígenas; y (6) los procesos de etnogénesis vinculados con los discursos panindigenistas americanos.62 Por último, los chilenos tenemos la dicha de convivir y compartir en el seno de una sociedad plural, que no sólo es multicultural sino que, además, es multiétnica. El trasfondo y las implicancias a las que conduce tal afirmación son francamente inconmensurables, y en lo que respecta a los actores del sistema jurídico, resulta una pieza esencial en la comprensión conciente de la evolución normativa que hemos tenido en el pasado republicano, pues resulta inaceptable todo intento que anhele reprimir la siguiente autocrítica: nuestro derecho positivo no ha sido capaz a lo largo de los siglos XIX y XX de disminuir (y menos de evitar) las grandes exclusiones culturales ni los serios desequilibrios estructurales que acusan quienes se han sentido discriminados en este orden de materias, incluso a veces la soberbia del legislador ha llevado a actitudes de indiferencia frente a las aspiraciones de las minorías, lo que puede resultar mucho más doloroso de lo que se piensa en la construcción dialógica de las autoimágenes e identidades grupales. Qué duda cabe, por razones de diversa categoría, tales como el etnocentrismo y el patriotismo o nacionalismo pasional, los chilenos no hemos aprovechado en todo su 62. RODOLFO STAVENHAGEN, DERECHO INDÍGENA Y DERECHOS HUMANOS EN AMÉRICA LATINA (Mexico) (1988). 156 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 esplendor y brillo la riqueza de los crisoles y mosaicos que aglutinan la comunidad de comunidades (o unión de uniones sociales) que habita el territorio chileno. Es más, persiste en un sector importante de la ciudadanía, sobre todo en las élites dominantes, una deuda jurídica pendiente con los pueblos originarios que luchan por: (a) ser reconocidos social y constitucionalmente; (b) recuperar gran parte de sus tierras ancestrales; y (c) gozar mayores grados de autonomía política con la finalidad de reproducir sus culturas y resguardar sus tradiciones. A pesar que pestañeamos desvelados en un país multicultural, esa multiculturalidad persiste ‘mutilada’ en los planos jurídico y social. Como nuestro ordenamiento vigente no se encuentra preparado para procesar eficientemente la creciente e irreversible multiculturalidad social, es de la mayor conveniencia debatir propuestas encaminadas a asumir la compatibilidad entre el proyecto político unitario con los múltiples proyectos emanados de las diversas culturas. Una de esas propuestas prospectivas que, estamos convencidos, permitirá favorecer el reconocimiento (y la comprensión tolerante y recíproca) de las diversas culturas de la sociedad chilena es la que acá se ha dado a conocer bajo el nombre de Principio de la Multiculturalidad. SYMBOLIC POWER WITHOUT SYMBOLIC VIOLENCE? Mauricio García-Villegas* ** *** I. LEGAL CONSCIOUSNESS STUDIES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 158 II. ANTI-STRUCTURALISM AND THE CRITICAL STANCE . . . . . . . . 162 III. THE CONCEPTS OF SYMBOLISM IN LEGAL SCHOLARSHIP . . . . 166 IV. SYMBOLIC EFFECTS OF LAW IN BOURDIEU AND IN THE LCS . . 172 V. CONCLUSION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 186 During recent decades social theory has struggled with the attempt to overcome both subjectivist and structuralist conceptions. In this effort, actors have been understood to construct social reality through their practices. Thus, social practices are socially constructed at the same time. Neither subjects nor objects existed prior to this work of construction; the nature of reality is therefore always symbolic, discursive.1 These ideas have been accorded a warm reception in the Law and Society (L&S) Movement, and, in particular, in a current of thought within the movement that is interested in the study of legal consciousness in the everyday life of social actors, here termed “Legal Consciousness Studies” (LCS). In this Essay, I propose to analyze some aspects of the reception of that social theory in these sociolegal studies. The hypothesis that I want to demonstrate is that despite the importance of their contributions to understanding of law, there is a theoretical ambiguity in these studies. This follows from the fact that they adhere to different currents of social theory, which are irreconcilable to the extent that they are premised on different presuppositions about social relations.2 * García-Villegas is a Professor of Law at the National University in Bogota, Colombia, and an Affilliated Scholar at the Institute of Legal Studies, University of Wisconsin Law School. ** A similar but different version of this Essay is being published in a special issue of the International Journal for the Semiotics of Law edited by John Brigham. *** I would like to thank Jane Larson, John Brigham, Sally Merry, Cesar Rodríguez, Diego López, Howard Erlanger, Catherine Albiston, Daniel Lipson, Christine Ruggiero, Ruben Garcia, Oscar Guardiola, Jonathan Graubart, Dan Steard, and Austin Sarat, for the valuable comments they provided on an earlier version of this Essay. 1. For this concept, see ERNESTO LACLAU & CHANTAL MOUFFE, HEGEMONY AND SOCIALIST STRATEGY: TOWARD A RADICAL DEMOCRATIC POLITICS (1985). 2. See generally JEFFREY C. ALEXANDER, TWENTY LECTURES: SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY SINCE WORLD WAR II (1987). 157 158 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 To illustrate this ambiguity, I will contrast the way that the concept of symbolic efficacy is employed in the LCS and in the work of Pierre Bourdieu, who is frequently cited by the new sociolegal studies as an authorized theoretical reference. I will analyze, first, some basic concepts that underpin the sociolegal studies considered here; then I turn to an explication of some notions related to the idea of symbolism in law; finally I concentrate on a theoretical comparison between Bourdieu and the LCS. My hope is to contribute to the French debate on both Bourdieu’s sociolegal theory and the sociology of law in general. I. LEGAL CONSCIOUSNESS STUDIES At the end of the 1980s some prominent members of L&S began to reconceptualize its movement. The aim was to achieve greater critical commitment in opposition to the predominant position, which, according to critics, was politically and epistemologically perverted through the prevalence of an institutional viewpoint and a public policy bias.3 This redirection revived the old realist purpose to attain an empirical sociology of law that was, at the same time, critical. The studies encompassed in this project of renewal can be termed, following McCann and March,4 and Ewick and Silbey,5 “Legal Consciousness Studies.” They include not only those authors referred to in McCann and March,6 but also part of the group of sociolegal researchers—especially what Trubek and Esser have named the “Cultural Anthropology” tendency—partially linked to the Amherst Seminar in Massachusetts. All of these authors base their work in a constitutive theory of social action and beginning from that point, attack 3. See generally Austin Sarat & Susan S. Silbey, The Pull of the Policy Audience, 10 LAW & POL’Y 97 (1988). 4. See generally Michael W. McCann & Tracey March, Law and Everyday Forms of Resistance: A Socio-Political Assessment, in 15 STUDIES IN LAW, POLITICS, & SOCIETY (Austin Sarat & Susan S. Silbey eds., 1995). 5. See generally PATRICIA EWICK & SUSAN S. SILBEY, THE COMMON PLACE OF LAW: STORIES FROM EVERYDAY LIFE ch. 3 (1998) [hereinafter COMMON PLACE]; Patricia Ewick & Susan S. Silbey, Conformity, Contestation and Resistance: An Account of Legal Consciousness, 26 NEW ENG. L. REV. 731 (1992) [hereinafter Legal Consciousness]. 6. McCann & March, supra note 4, at 208-09. In their examination of these sociolegal studies McCann and March concentrate on the following authors: SALLY ENGLE MERRY, GETTING JUSTICE AND GETTING EVEN: LEGAL CONSCIOUSNESS AMONG WORKING CLASS AMERICANS (1990); BARBARA YNGVESSON, VIRTUOUS CITIZENS, DISRUPTIVE SUBJECTS: ORDER AND COMPLAINT IN A NEW ENGLAND COURT (1993); Legal Consciousness, supra note 5; Austin Sarat, “ . . . The Law Is All Over”: Power, Resistance and Legal Consciousness of the Welfare Poor, 2 YALE J.L. & HUMAN. 343 (1990) [hereinafter The Law]; Austin Sarat, Off to Meet the Wizard: Beyond Validity and Reliability in the Search for a Post-Empiricist Sociology of Law, 15 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 155 (1990) [hereinafter Off to Meet the Wizard]; Lucie E. White, Subordination, Rhetorical Survival Skills, and Sunday Shoes: Notes on the Hearing of Mrs. G., 38 BUFF. L. REV. 1 (1990). See generally McCann & March, supra note 4. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 159 instrumentalist visions of law.7 In this sense they are not too dissimilar from the Critical Legal Theorists, although LCS distanced itself from these theorists in its vindication of empirical investigation. I will develop my analysis on these LCS mostly in very general terms, understanding that they belong to what is today a dominant trend in sociolegal studies in the United States. I am aware of the fact that, given this level of abstraction, my critique is not suitable to all authors interested in legal consciousness. The legal phenomenon is seen in LCS as a constitutive element of social reality and not as an official institutional apparatus destined to intervene in this reality.8 Accordingly, the attention of the investigator is directed toward those everyday concrete social practices in which legal rules are perceived as constitutive elements of the reality. This emphasis on the routine instead of the exceptional, on the social in place of the institutional, and on mental representations (the symbolic worldview) instead of a coercive legal system (the instrumental vision) are common elements in this change of optic.9 The concept of legality is central to this perspective. Patricia Ewick and Susan Silbey point out that “(l)egality is an emergent feature of social relations rather than an external apparatus acting upon social life. As a constituent of social interaction, the law—or what we will call legality—embodies the diversity of the situations out of which it emerges and that it helps structure.”10 One can detect three more or less scattered premises in this reconfiguring of L&S: first, a defense of empirical research without implying the adoption of positivist postulates; second, a progressive political position in favor of weak or marginalized social actors; and finally, a perspective that is more open to exploring the complexities of the relationship between law and social change from a constructivist perspective. In the first place, LCS was opposed to the crude positivism of the early years of the L&S Movement.11 There is no objective truth; that is, there is no truth independent of the knowing subject. The significance of knowledge is socially constructed in the relationship between the observer 7. It is worth noticing that there are some legal theorists who apply the constitutive theory to the legal field in rather different terms. See, e.g., JOHN BRIGHAM, THE CONSTITUTION OF INTERESTS: BEYOND THE POLITICS OF RIGHTS (1996); John Brigham, The Constitution of Interests: Institutionalism, CLS and New Approaches to Sociolegal Studies, 10 YALE J.L. & HUMAN. 421 (1998) [hereinafter Constitutions of Interests]. 8. According to Ewick and Silbey, “The ways in which the law is experienced and understood by ordinary citizens as they choose to invoke the law, to avoid it, or to resist it, is an essential part of the life of the law.” Legal Consciousness, supra note 5, at 737. 9. Id. at 741-42. 10. COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 17. 11. McCann & March, supra note 4. 160 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 and the observed.12 However, this proposition has provoked great debate in the North American sociology of law, particularly centered around the Amherst Seminar. Betweeen 1980 and 1995 Amherst, Masschusetts, was home of a discussion group in sociolegal theory called the “Amherest Seminar on Legal Ideology and Legal Process.” For over a decade, the most important intellectuals in North American and European sociology of law were invited to the seminar. There was some affinity between the seminar and the LCS. The seminar’s aim was to reconstruct an empirical sociology that was at the same time critical.13Sociolegal research provides new visions or interpretations of legal phenomena, perhaps more adequate, but without validity or truth being claimed for them.14 Empirical investigation and the research methodology of the social sciences are not sacrificed—and in this regard the empiricist imperative maintains all the vigor of the L&S tradition—although the objectivist postulates typical of positivistic social science are renounced. So, its advocates champion a postempiricism that does not conceive of science as authoritative or conclusive knowledge, but one that “continues to keep alive the hope that science can serve as a tool of persuasion, albeit a limited one, in a world with ‘a multitude of values, knowledge perspectives, and criteria.’”15 Empirical research thus changes its subject of analysis in this new version of L&S. LCS react against a research tradition dedicated to the study of how legal institutions operate, and, in particular, the courts. LCS also interested themselves in judicial work, but not from the perspective of the judge or the judge’s decision, as the earlier work in L&S had done. Instead, they examine judicial work from the perspective of the participating actors. In McCann’s words, they countered the top-down approach with “bottom-up jurisprudence.”16 In these new micro-cultural spaces, ethnographic and anthropological research acquire an overwhelming importance that contrast with other approaches that are more concerned with the structural elements of class or hegemony. 12. See Christine B. Harrington & Barbara Yngvesson, Interpretative Sociolegal Research, 15 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 135, 148 (1990). 13. David M. Trubek & John Esser, “Critical Empiricism” in American Legal Studies: Paradox, Program, or Pandora’s Box?, 14 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 3, 3-52 (1987). In their evaluation of the seminar’s achievements Trubek and Esser state that although the seminar pariticpants were able to leave behind a deterministic and instrumentalist view of legality, the attachment to a conception of empirical science was unchanging, and that created important theoretical problems. For the complete debate, see generally Review Section Debate, 15 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 135, 13580 (1990). 14. See Off to Meet the Wizard, supra note 6, at 166. 15. Id. at 165. 16. MICHAEL MCCANN, RIGHTS AT WORK: PAY EQUITY REFORM AND THE POLITICS OF LEGAL MOBILIZATION 21 (1994). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 161 Additionally, LCS identified themselves politically with the interests of the subjects of their research—the marginalized, the minorities, the excluded, etc.—and then attempted to create alternative social forms through the use of law.17 This Essay affirmatively resolves the debate that arose inside the Critical Legal Studies (CLS) group about the convenience of using the law as an instrument of social emancipation. LCS recognize the possibilities of struggle against hegemony without forgetting that the law can, de facto, work in some cases as an instrument of social domination.18 In this regard, the understanding of the relationship between law and social change is much more complex and elaborate than the approach found in CLS.19 Also, from its origins, those working in LCS joined critics in rejecting the gap studies and, in general, positioned themselves against the instrumentalist views of law predominating in L&S during the 1970s. In contrast to these approaches, they insisted on the indeterminate character of law.20 Legal norms give way to multiple, disparate, and variable social practices that can only be made sense of by investigating empirically the legal consciousness of concrete social actors. This research shows how social actors, despite being limited by social structures, possess a significant creative, constructive capacity. While the notion of determination or lack thereof in critical studies leads to the structuralistMarxist debate on the relations between the state/law and the economy, in LCS the same theme directs emphasis toward the cultural and subjective elements of political domination and thus to the adoption of an “interpretive” social theory.21 Following this perspective, legal consciousness is part of a reciprocal process in which the significance attributed by individuals to their world, and thus to law, “become[s] repeated, patterned, and stabilized, and those institutionalized structures become part of the meaning systems employed by individuals.”22 If legality is a dynamic process of social construction, the instrumentalist approach and determinate character of law lose all explanatory power. In its place arises a concept of law endowed with contingent outcomes that derive from the interaction of individuals and institutions. 17. KRISTIN BUMILLER, THE CIVIL RIGHTS SOCIETY: THE SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION OF VICTIMS (1988); see generally White, supra note 6. 18. Adelaide H. Villmoare, The Left’s Problems with Rights, 9 LEGAL STUD. F. 39, 41-43 (1985). 19. See MCCANN, supra note 16. 20. Legal Consciousness, supra note 5, at 742; see also COMMON PLACE, supra note 5. 21. See generally PETER L. BERGER & THOMAS LUCKMANN, THE SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION OF REALITY: A TREATISE IN THE SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE (1966). 22. Legal Consciousness, supra note 5, at 741. The cultural emphasis in these studies is notorious. On this point, see MCCANN, supra note 16. 162 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 II. ANTI-STRUCTURALISM AND THE CRITICAL STANCE Studies of legal consciousness bring together, with variants, essential parts of both the L&S and critical traditions. From L&S they have taken the idea that empirical research is essential to make sense of the way law functions in society. From the critical tradition they have adopted the aspiration that sociolegal studies should serve not only to describe how law operates in society, but also, and above all, to contribute to the transformation of society and the defense of the excluded. In relation to this latter aspect, as mentioned above, these studies have made extremely important contributions, especially with regard to the complexity of individuals’ legal strategies, whether of accommodation or resistance.23 Despite their critical ambitions, however, a reading of the LCS leave, from the political point of view, a nostalgic taste of lost revolutionary fervor—recognizing that in this they are not alone—and, from the theoretical standpoint, the sensation of “rigor without imagination,” to use one of Pierre Bourdieu’s expressions. This despair appears to be due to the adoption of a type of epistemological approach that neglects the role of political domination in sociolegal phenomena. On this point Trubek and Esser seem to be correct when, analyzing these studies, they relate LCS’ failure to provide a strong political critique to the studies attachment to empiricism.24 According to Trubek and Esser, the Seminar was not able to elucidate the complex relationship between knowledge and politics; perhaps for that reason, their studies lack the political commitment and the moral richness that is often found in critical studies and in feminist work.25 Excessive confidence in social science and in the possibility of understanding a sociolegal reality through empirical investigation limits their critical perspective. The fact that, according to established social science methods, only “verifiable” objects of study are accepted minimizes the possibilities of interpretation and critique. Over-dependence on data derived from empiricism generally limited to local social settings means that the critique loses the force of more comprehensive denunciations.26 I agree with Trubek and Esser on their idea that LCS lack critical dimension, but I take a different argument to explain why that happened. Instead of looking at the way they adopt empiricism, I focus on a tension or even an inconsistency in their theoretical background. 23. See generally MCCANN, supra note 16; McCann & March, supra note 4. 24. See generally Trubek & Esser, supra note 13. 25. Id. at 33-34. 26. See generally Boaventura de Sousa Santos, Room for Manoeuver: Paradox, Program, or Pandora’s Box?, 14 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 149 (1989); Joel F. Handler, Postmodernism, Protest and the New Social Movements, 26 LAW & SOC’Y. REV. 697 (1992). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 163 The contemporary debate on empiricism and criticism, however, is not what it was when Trubek and Esser wrote their influential essay. Over recent decades, sociolegal theory in L&S has joined in with the prevailing tendency in social theory, according to which it is necessary to supersede both objectivist positions (functionalism, structuralism) and subjectivist stances (phenomenology, ethnomethodology, interactionism, etc.).27 This tendency goes by different names, among which the theorie pratique of Pierre Bourdieu and the “structuration theory” of Anthony Giddens are outstanding examples. In LCS, these theoretical positions are generally recognized and adopted under the rubric of a “constitutive theory of law.”28 Despite this theoretical “agreement” around the notion of a constitutive theory of law—an agreement which moreover is proposed in very general terms—the empirical research of the LCS seem to be marked, in practice, by an underestimation of the structural elements privileging individual action.29 In this Essay, I argue that the domestication of critique in the LCS is linked to a certain dissonance between their empirical studies and the theoretical grounding. This dissociation has an explanation not only in a certain geographical division between empirical research with a strong influence of North American empiricist traditions30 and a theoretical bases 27. See, e.g., ADVANCES IN SOCIAL THEORY AND METHODOLOGY: TOWARD AN INTEGRATION (K. Knorr-Cetina & A.V. Cicourel eds., 1981) [hereinafter ADVANCES OF SOCIAL THEORY AND METHODOLOGY], in which articles by Anthony Giddens, Pierre Bourdieu, J. Habermas, Randall Collins, and others are included; MICHAEL BURAWOY ET AL., ETHNOGRAPHY UNBOUND, POWER AND RESISTANCE IN THE MODERN METROPOLIS (1991); Anthony Elliot, Introduction, in THE BLACKWELL READER IN CONTEMPORARY SOCIAL THEORY (Anthony Elliot ed., 1999). 28. See JOHN BRIGHAM, THE CONSTITUTION OF INTERESTS: BEYOND THE POLITICS OF RIGHTS (1996); COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 274; MCCANN, supra note 16, at 303; Harrington & Yngvesson, supra note 12, at 141; Legal Consciousness, supra note 5. For a more general overview of the contributions of this theory in law, see ALAN HUNT, EXPLORATIONS IN LAW AND SOCIETY: TOWARDS A CONSTITUTIVE THEORY OF LAW (1993). Legal consciousness studies (LCS) are not alone in employing this theory, see, e.g., Ruth Margaret Buchanan, Context, Continuity and Difference in Poverty Law Scholarship, 48 U. MIAMI L. REV. 999 (1994). For its theoretical antecedents, see DOUGLAS HAY ET AL., ALBION’S FATAL TREE: CRIME AND SOCIETY IN EIGHTEENTH-CENTURY ENGLAND (Douglas Hay et al. eds., 1975); Owen M. Fiss, Objectivity and Interpretation, 34 STAN. L. REV. 739 (1982); Robert W. Gordon, Critical Legal Histories, 36 STAN. L. REV. 57 (1984); Karl Klare, Lawmaking as Praxis, 40 TELOS 123 (1979). The constitutive theory of law is usually an offshoot of cultural studies, especially drawing on the seminal work of CLIFFORD GEERTZ, LOCAL KNOWLEDGE: FURTHER ESSAYS IN INTERPRETIVE ANTHROPOLOGY (1983) and MICHEL DE CERTEAU, THE PRACTICE OF EVERYDAY LIFE (Steven Rendall trans., 1984) and of postmodernism; see Handler, supra note 26; LACLAU & MOUFFE, supra note 1. 29. Handler, supra note 26. 30. C.G.A. Bryant argues that a positivist approach to the social sciences has predominated U.S. departments of sociology since 1940. CHRISTOPHER G.A. BRYANT, POSITIVISM IN SOCIAL THEORY RESEARCH 133 (1985); see also Alan Sica, Social Theory’s “Constituency,” 20 AM. OF MICRO- AND MACRO-SOCIOLOGIES 164 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 of European origin31 emphasizing critique, but also in a differentiation with political roots as the dissociation between theoretical model and empirical investigation originates in the existence of divergent “theoretical presuppositions”—to employ Alexander’s concept—from which the proposed theoretical models are constructed. Let me explain. One possible division in social theory is that which differentiates between those who study society as a terrain of conflict, stratified and marked by struggle,32 and theorists who, without ignoring the existence of conflict, posit that society is better characterized by features such as interaction and culture. This tension between conflict and consensus in social theory harks back to a debate that exercised functionalist and Marxist scholars during the 1960s and which today is considered to have been superseded.33 In a more general sense, however, this tension continues to have meaning and manifests itself in different ways.34 In short, I hypothesize that there is a dissociation in LCS between two types of theoretical foundations. On one hand, they seem to adhere to a general theory primarily developed in Europe by theorists working within a social conflict tradition.35 This framework is supposedly aimed at nourishing what LCS call a constitutive social theory, by which the structure/agency dichotomy would be overcome. On the other hand, however, empirical research in LCS seems to be grounded in a typically American social theory that we may term, following Collins, microinteractionist. According to this approach, and in opposition to conflict theories, elements linked to agency, like individual consciousness, communication among actors, and symbolic interchanges, prevail. Given the preeminence of empiricism over theoretical analysis in LCS, this dissociation leads to a situation in which actors and their consciousness and practices turn out to be much more important than social structures working to restrict actors. Thus, cognitive matters became central in the analysis, whereas political elements were almost forgotten. Symbolic interchange obscures symbolic violence. In other terms, there seems to be a gap between interpretivist theoretical models—society as constructed—based in assumptions close to the conflict tradition, and empirical investigations associated with a sort SOCIOLOGIST 227, 227-41 (1989). 31. In theoretical matters, North American sociologists of law have been somewhat dependent on European tendencies. See de Sousa Santos, supra note 26; Trubek & Esser, supra note 13. 32. Here I am referring in general terms to all social theories that emphasize conflict, especially between groups and classes, as a central element of social practices and of social theory. 33. See generally ANTHONY GIDDENS, SOCIOLOGY 1 (1993). 34. As Randall Collins reviews in his text, RANDALLCOLLINS, FOUR SOCIOLOGICAL TRADITIONS (1994). 35. Such theorists include Bourdieu, Foucault, Giddens, and Touraine. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 165 of cultural microinteractionism. This dichotomy also appears as a lack of accord between defenders of a cultural perspective on legal practices36 and proponents of a conflict theory.37 The fact that all of these authors share the idea to overcome the dichotomy between structure and agency—which characterizes constitutive social theory—does not seem sufficient to include them under a unitary model. So, the dissociation between the theoretical and the empirical in LCS is also evidenced as a divergence with respect to the use of interpretive social theory: while some employ the idea of the interconnection between structure and agency to show the cognitive importance of social construction premised on agency, others use this supposition to illustrate how domination is originated and produced. In short: I claim that a theory such as that of Bourdieu or Giddens confuses more than it enlightens when it is incorporated into the theoretical model termed “the constitutive theory of law.” This argument is worth developing in more detail. In the cultural vision that underlies LCS the law is seen as a symbolic or discursive object.38 This symbolic vision on law is different from the concept of the symbolic use of law that Bourdieu, among others,39 proposes. While the first concept 36. See, e.g., GEERTZ, supra note 28; PAUL KAHN, THE CULTURAL STUDY OF LAW: RECONSTRUCTING LEGAL SCHOLARSHIP (1999); Susan Silbey, Making a Place for Cultural Analyses of Law, 17 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 39 (1992); Barbra Yngvesson, Inventing Law in Social Settin: Retuinking Popular Legal Culture, 98 YALE L. J. 1689 (1989). 37. See, e.g., PIERRE BOURDIEU, RAISONS PRATIQUES: SUR LA THÉORIE DE L’ACTION (1994); ANTHONY GIDDENS, CENTRAL P ROBLEMS IN SOCIAL THEORY: ACTION, STRUCTURE AND CONTRADICTION IN SOCIAL ANALYSIS (1979) [hereinafter CENTRAL PROBLEMS]; ANTHONY GIDDENS, SOCIOLOGY [hereinafter SOCIOLOGY]. Bourdieu explains the production and reproduction of hierarchical social systems with reference to the way that cultural resources, social processes, and institutions maintain individuals in a continual competition for social dominance. On the adoption of a social theory of conflict in Bourdieu, see DAVID SWARTZ, CULTURE AND POWER: THE SOCIOLOGY OF PIERRE BOURDIEU (1997). Giddens, in turn, argues that all social systems can be studied as incorporating or expressing modes of domination and it is this concept more than any other that provides the focal point for the investigation of power. Social systems that have some regularized existence across time-space are always “power systems,” or exhibit forms of domination, in the sense that they are comprised of relations of autonomy and dependence between actors or collectivities of actors. ANTHONY GIDDENS, THE NATION-STATE AND VIOLENCE 8 (1987). 38. The sociolegal literature alludes to this as “interpretive.” Trubek & Esser, supra note 13, at 13-14. In Europe the term “discursive” is more frequently used. 39. See generally GEORGES BALANDIER, LE POUVOIR SUR SCÉNES (Ballard ed., 1992); JOSÉ EDUARDO FARIA, EFICACIA JURIDICA E VIOLENCIA SIMBOLICA: O DIREITO COMO INSTRUMENTO DE TRANSFORMACAO SOCIAL (1984); Daniéle Loschak, Droit, normalité et normalization, in LE DROIT EN PROCESS (Daniéle Loschak ed., (1983); MAURICIO GARCÍA-VILLEGAS, LA EFICACIA SIMBOLICA DEL DERECHO: EXAMEN DE SITUACIONES COLOMBIANAS (1993). 166 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 refers chiefly to a problem of knowledge,40 the second adds an element of social domination.41 Given the plurality and malleability of the legal symbols in the conception of LCS, and given that the meaning of such symbols is never fixed, law has a social character that is essentially weak and almost random.42 Sarat, for instance, claims43 that disadvantaged citizens do not accept a “myth of rights”;44 individuals in his stories seem able to resist legal symbols. This clearly contrasts with its strong and almost inevitable character, in social and political terms, in the work of Bourdieu and other authors who refer to the symbolic use of law as a political phenomenon working in a hierarchical society. Let me put this in other terms: a constructive or interpretive vision of society entails that the explanation of society is reduced to the relation between agency and structure or between subjects and objects. The social reality is therefore constructed, relational, discursive, and cultural—pure elements outside this relation. If this is the case, the problem here is how to understand law as a discursive or cultural devise. What is the symbolic efficacy of law in a social setting? And it is precisely in relation to these problems that LCS and Bourdieu advance different conceptions of the law as legal practice. I will develop these ideas as follows: first, I will undertake a succinct explication of the concepts of the symbolism in legal scholarship, and I will show its different uses in North America; then I will illustrate how the concept of symbolic uses of law is developed in Bourdieu as contrasted to the concept of symbolic vision in LCS. III. THE CONCEPTS OF SYMBOLISM IN LEGAL SCHOLARSHIP Symbolism is not a way to manufacture meanings, but is rather a modality of textual interpretation.45 It entails not only a presumption of analogy between symbols and objects, but also a fundamental uncertainty in meaning structures. The symbolic relies mainly on what Umberto Eco 40. See CLIFFORD GEERTZ, LOCAL KNOWLEDGE: FURTHER ESSAYS IN INTERPRETIVE ANTHROPOLOGY 21 (1983) (refering to this perspective as “conceiving of social life as organized in terms of symbols . . . whose meaning . . . we must grasp if we are to understand that organization and formulate its principles”). 41. This difference, as we will see below, is not at all clear in the treatment that has been accorded to the symbolic in North American sociology of law. In other words, clarity does not exist concerning the meaning and scope of law understood as a symbol that constitutes and is constituted in these practices. 42. MERRY, supra note 6, at 147. 43. E.g., The Law, supra note 6, at 374. 44. See generally STUART A. SCHEINGOLD, THE POLITICS OF RIGHTS: LAWYERS, P UBLIC POLICY, AND POLITICAL CHANGE (1974). 45. UMBERTO ECO, SEMIOTICA E FILOSOFIA DEL LINGUAGGIO 225 (1984); ROLAND BARTHES, MITOLOGIAS 211, 214, 226 (1980). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 167 calls the “cloudiness of the content.”46 In contrast, metaphors function precisely in terms of meaning. Metaphors “allow us to understand one domain of experience in terms of another.”47 Thus, symbolism involves interpretation and justification in pragmatic contexts. This is called pragmatic understanding of language48 and has had an extraordinary influence on twentieth century theory. It is associated with the elimination of the subject/object dichotomy in social theory,49 with the prevalence of hermeneutic approaches both in the social sciences50 and law,51 with rhetorical approaches in legal theory,52 with the analysis of symbols and symbolism in anthropology,53 and with the study of sociolegal interactions.54 In terms of social action, the symbolic is contrasted with the instrumental. The transformation of social reality through pragmatic measures characterizes instrumental action, whereas actions oriented to the production of meaning in the context of communication and interpretation characterize symbolic actions. Here, as Gusfield has noted, “the goal is reached in the behavior itself rather than in any state which it brings 46. ECO, supra note 45, at 226; see also ROLAND BARTHES, MITOLOGIAS 211, 214, 226 (1980). 47. GEORGE LAKOFF & MARK JOHNSON, METAPHORS WE LIVE BY 117 (1980). 48. Regarding the distinction between semantics, syntax, and the pragmatic, see Charles W. Morris, Foundations of the Theory of Signs, in INTERNATIONAL ENCYCLOPEDIA OF UNIFIED SCIENCE (Otto Neurath ed., 1938). For the pragmatic uses of language, see H.P. Grice, Meaning, 64 PHILOSOPHICAL REV. 337, 377-88 (1957). For the relationship between linguistic pragmatics and power, see BOURDIEU, supra note 37; V.N. VOLOSINOV, MARXISM AND THE P HILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE (1973). 49. PIERRE BOURDIEU, LE SENS PRATIQUE 43 (1980) (“Among all oppositions artificially dividing social science the most unfortunate and ruinous is that established between subject[ ] and object[ ].”); SOCIOLOGY, supra note 37, at 158 (noting that the study of natural languages is central both to the understanding of actions as “meaningful,” and to the process of communication in social interactions); JEAN-FRANÇOIS LYOTARD, LA CONDITION POSTMODERN 67 (1979) (“le lien social est langagier”). 50. SOCIOLOGY, supra note 37, at 149. 51. See RONALD DWORKIN, A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE (1985). See, e.g., Fiss, supra note 28 (explaining judicial work as neither a discretionary nor mechanical activity); see also Gordon, supra note 28. 52. The pragmatic relations between the speaker and audience in the context of legal argumentation have been explored extensively by CHAIM PERELMAN, LOGIQUE JURIDIQUE (1979); CHAIM PERELMAN, LE RAISONNABLE ET LE DÉRAISONNABLE EN DROIT (1984). 53. Classical works include: CLAUDE LEVI-STRAUSS, ANTROPOLOGIA STRUCTURAL (1984); BRONISLAW MALINOWSKI, TEORIA SCIENTIFICA DELLA CULTURA ED ALTRI SAGGI (1949); M. MAUSS, TEORIA GENEEERALE DELLA MAGIA ED ALTRI SAGI (1965). 54. For example, “symbolic interactionism” has been applied to law in different ways. For examples of the various approaches, see JOSEPH R. GUSFIELD, SYMBOLIC CRUSADE: STATUS POLITICS AND THE AMERICAN TEMPERANCE MOVEMENT (1963); Thomas Meisenhelder, Law as Symbolic Action: Kenneth Burke’s Sociology of Law, 4 SYMBOLIC INTERACTION 43, 43-57 (1981); Carolyn R. Miller, Public Knowledge in Science and Society, 3 PRE/TEXT 31, 31-49 (1982). 168 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 about.”55 This distinction is similar to the difference between denotative and connotative discourses: in denotation the focus is on a referent, which is the same for everyone who refers to it; connotative references, by contrast, are inherently ambiguous.56 In legal scholarship, the idea of the symbolic is most widespread in the area of constitutional law,57 but it also has been developed in criminal law,58 labor law,59 and in environmental law.60 Sociolegal scholars have developed different approaches to the symbolic. The significance of this concept varies widely depending on which era or which “school” one looks at; the meaning given to it can even vary with the same author at different times. At least four different approaches can be distinguished. The first approach views the symbolic in terms of the inherent force of legal discourse. In this schema, the law is the authorized language of the State through which its legitimacy is produced and reproduced. No state is able to survive through the use of physical coercion alone. An authorized justification for the use of physical constraints is first needed, and law exists to furnish it. Legitimated power and the law exist in a state of symbiosis: state actions are justified through legal norms and legal norms are effective when they are backed by the state power. Some sociolegal scholars also emphasize this difference. Danièle Loschak argues that the force of law does not reside exclusively in its recourse to authorized physical violence, but also in the fact that it authorizes certain speech acts—and not others—as “true” and “legitimate.”61 In the United States, Sally Merry, for example, has argued that “law works in the world not just by imposition of rules and punishments but also by its capacity to 55. GUSFIELD, supra note 54, at 21. 56. Id. at 170. 57. In the United States there is a large bibliography on the symbolic effects of constitutions; see, e.g., JOHN BRIGHAM, THE CULT OF THE COURT (1987); SCHEINGOLD, supra note 44; Constitutions of Interest, supra note 7; Max Lerner, Constitution and Court as Symbols, 46 YALE L.J. 1290 (1937). For the Latin American context, see MARCELO NEVES, A CONSTITUIONALIZACAO SIMBOLICA (1994); GARCÍA-VILLEGAS, supra note 39. 58. Ronald J. Berger et al., The Dimensions of Rape Reform Legislation, 22 LAW & SOC’Y REV. 329, 329-353 (1988), for example, emphasizes the symbolic dimensions of rape law as an indicator of women’s contemporary legal status, rather than as an instrumental mechanism for the achievement of specific policy goals. Juvenile law is also frequently analyzed in symbolic terms. 59. William J. Moore & Robert J. Newman, The Effects of Right-to-Work Laws: A Review of the Literature, 38 INDUS. & LAB. REL. REV. 571, 571-585 (1985). Moore & Newman have argued that the impact of the right-to-work (RTW) laws on union membership, wages, and industry location is more symbolic than substantive. See id. 60. Pauline Lane, Ecofeminism Meets Criminology, 2 THEORETICAL CRIMINOLOGY 235, 23548 (1998); Pierre Lascoumes, La Formalisation Juridique du Risque Industriel en Matière de Protection de L’environment, 31 SOCIOLOGIE-DU-TRAVAIL 315, 315-33 (1989). 61. Daniéle Loschak, Driot, Normalite Et Normalization, in LE DROIT EN PROCESS 54 (1983). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 169 construct authoritative images of social relationships and actions. . . .”62 This particular property of law may be called symbolic to the extent that it does not operate through instrumentalities, at least in the first instance, but rather through political meaning. Political science,63 constitutional legal studies,64 and even legal theory65 frequently employ this understanding of the symbolic use of law. A second approach focuses on the process of implementation of norms as a matter of public policy. It defines its unit of analysis in terms of an efficacious legal system created and supported by public agencies. The crucial distinction between law-in-action and law-in-books became for many sociolegal scholars a rationale in the search for institutional consistency between both elements, instead of a mechanism for critical analysis. Marginality, contradiction, and indeterminacy, as observed features of the law, are here converted into problems of legal implementation.66 These “inconsistencies” are seen as problems of administration and public adjustment, rather than, for example, mechanisms for the production of political hegemony. From this perspective, the distinction between the symbolic and instrumental effects of law is collapsed into the problem of “dysfunctional law,” which policymakers, aided by sociolegal knowledge, were supposed to solve. The strong link in the early 1970s between academic researchers and state 62. MERRY, supra note 6, at 9. 63. Political science approaches often examine the processes by which government actions shape public beliefs, perceptions, and behaviors. See, e.g., MURRAY EDELMAN, POLITICAL LANGUAGE: WORDS THAT SUCCEED AND POLICIES THAT FAIL (1977); MURRAY EDELMAN, THE SYMBOLIC USES OF POLITICS (1964) [hereinafter SYMBOLIC USES OF POLITICS]; Kitty Calavita, The New Politics of Immigration: “Balanced-Budget Conservatism” and the Symbolism of Proposition 187, 43 SOC. PROBS. 284, 284-305 (1996). 64. The symbolic dimension of a constitution is often seen as an important and necessary political effect which conditions the constitution’s instrumental efficacy. On this view, constitutions have the symbolic function of framing a civic identity for people. See Giorgio Rebuffa, Legality and Illegality, in the Constitution; Legalita e illegalita nella Consituzione, 37 QUADERNI-DISOCIOLOGIA 97, 97-104 (1993). 65. Even the instrumental efficacy of law presupposes this symbolic efficacy. Moreover, the idea of validity in legal theory is very often linked to the symbolic acceptance of the legal system. See H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW (1961). 66. In the U.S., this process of conversion is frequently found in policy analyses. See, e.g., JEFFREY L. PRESSMAN & AARON WILDAVSKY, IMPLEMENTATION: HOW GREAT EXPECTATIONS IN WASHINGTON ARE DASHED IN OAKLAND; OR, WHY IT’S AMAZING THAT FEDERAL P ROGRAMS WORK AT ALL, THIS BEING A SAGA OF THE ECONOMIC DEVELOPMENT ADMINISTRATION AS TOLD BY TWO SYMPATHETIC OBVSERVERS WHO SEEK TO BUILD MORALS ON A FOUNDATION OF RUINED HOPES (1973). For an example of it in the European context, see Simon Charbonneau & Jean G. Padioleau, La Mise En Oeuvre d’une Politique Publique Réglementaire Défrichement Des Bois et Forêts, 21 REVUE FR. DE SOCIOLOGIE 49, 49-75 (1980); J.D. Dellay & L. Mader, Que faire des objectifs dans une étude de mise en oeuvre de la législation?, 7 REVUE SUISSE DE SOCIOLOGIE 385, 385-97 (1981). 170 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 policy reformers67 led these studies to overestimate the identification of the state and official law. The relatively progressive political agenda that was born with the L&S Movement was eventually smothered by the weight of its debt to state policy reform.68 “[T]he alliance between sociolegal scholarship and policy elites of the liberal state,” Sarat and Silbey argue, “is sufficiently strong and subtle that research apparently critical of aspects of American legal institutions works, paradoxically, to reinforce fundamental assumptions of liberal legalism.”69 According to a third point of view, the influence or social efficacy of law should be sought more in the institutional creation of a reified legal consciousness whereby social reality appears as something natural, not constructed70 and not so much in the instrumental determination of social behaviors through rewards and sanctions. This position has been argued by scholars in the traditional CLS. Their lack of agreement with respect to the balance between the cultural and the economic, however, affects the clarity of the movement when it comes to the concept of the symbolic use of law. Let me explain this idea. The rejection of legal instrumentalism is not sufficient to unify the critics. This is because in the 1970s Neo-Marxist debate on the possible autonomy of the state with respect to the economy, an unavoidable tension was latent between the cultural dimension of political legitimation and the structural character of the economy.71 This tension has divided the critics. Some adhered to the position of Poulantzas that state autonomy—and that of law—is only relative and that therefore the legal order is determined “in the last instance” by the structure of the capitalist mode of production. According to this—present in Balbus for example—the possibilities of social emancipation through progressive juridical reforms are practically nonexistent. Others, however, relying on a Marxist analysis with a cultural emphasis,72 argued that the law offers social movements genuine maneuverability derived from the needs that the 67. David M. Trubek, Back to the Future: The Short, Happy Life of the Law and Society Movement, 18 FLA. ST. U.L. REV. 4 (1990), has also pointed to the importance of funding to this uneasy alliance: “[s]ince there was no agency ready to provide adequate financial support for an autonomous ‘discipline’ of law and society, their product was often tailored to meet the needs of government agencies and foundations which had policy goals that might be served by law and society knowledge.” Id. at 29. 68. See id. at 28-30. 69. Sarat & Silbey, supra note 3, at 113. 70. Robert W. Gordon, Some Critical Theories on Law and Their Critics, in THE POLITICS OF LAW: A PROGRESSIVE CRITIQUE 281 (David Kairys ed., 3d ed. 1998) 71. See CLYDE W. BARROW, CRITICAL THEORIES OF THE STATE: MARXIST, NEO-MARXIST, POST-MARXIST (1993). 72. Alan Hunt, The Ideology of Law: Advances and Problems in Recent Applications of the Concept of Ideology to the Analysis of Law, 19 LAW & SOC’Y REV. 11 (1985). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 171 state apparatus has to make concessions in order to maintain or increase its legitimacy. While the first position emphasized the determining character of the economic structure, the second highlighted the state’s need for legitimation. In this respect, James Boyle argues that when this debate began, economic structuralism was dominant, but by the end the subjective dimension predominated.73 The majority of the critical theorists consider that the symbolic effects of law operate only to the benefit of state institutions and their aims of political manipulation.74 However, too much emphasis on the unitary character of state domination led these CLS scholars to a rather simplistic image of law as an institutional mechanism for social control. The strength of state legal domination undermines the possibility—even if often remote—of emancipation from hegemonic structures through progressive norms that were supposed to have only symbolic effects.75 Others, however, more disposed to accept a certain cultural autonomy in the symbolic use of law, consider that while a considerable institutional advantage may exist relative to the possibilities of appropriation and political manipulation of legal meanings, social movements and individuals also can use these meanings in their favor. The concept of hegemony in Gramsci, understood as an arena of struggle for political meaning, is important for the defense of this position.76 In fact, it is not only the critical theorists who hold this idea of the symbolic use of law as a practice of legitimation and domination. Organizational theory both in Europe and in the United States has shown how institutions respond to social problems in such a way that the aim of legitimation and communication predominates over the achievement of the proposed objectives.77 Of course there is a clear rapprochement between this position and the first one outlined above. The difference lies in emphasis: organizational theory insists that institutional legitimation is a 73. See James Boyle, The Politics of Reason: Critical Legal Theory and Local Social Thought, 133 U. PA. L. REV. 685, 779 (1985). 74. Mark Tushnet, An Essay on Rights, 62 TEX. L. REV. 1363, 1392-93 (1984). See generally THE POLITICS OF LAW: A PROGRESSIVE CRITIQUE, supra note 70; Joan Roelofs, Judicial Activism as Social Engineering: A Marxist Interpretation of the Warren Court, in SUPREME COURT ACTIVISM AND RESTRAINT (Stephen C. Halpern & Charles M. Lamb eds., 1982); Duncan Kennedy, American Constitutionalism as Civil Religion: Notes of an Athiest, 19 NOVA L. REV. 909 (1995). 75. See generally Marc Galanter, The Radiating Effect of Courts, in EMPIRICAL THEORIES OF COURTS (Keith O. Boyum & Lynn Mather eds., 1983); MCCANN, supra note 16, at 218. 76. See generally Gordon, supra note 70. 77. On this point, see M. CROZIER & FRIEDBERG, L’ACTEUR ET LE SYSTÈME (1977) in Europe, and, in the United States, see the authors of the school called “new institutionalism” in sociology: P. DIMAGGIO & WALTER POWELL, THE NEW INSTITUTIONALISM IN ORGANIZATIONAL ANALYSIS 8, 112 (1991). A similar perspective from outside this current can be found in, THE SYMBOLIC USES OF POLITICS, supra note 63,where social problems are constructed by institutions in accordance with their need for legitimation. 172 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 strategy, while in the perspective that understands the symbolic as an inherent element of law, legitimation is rather an outcome. A fourth approach to the symbolic use of law can be found in studies emphasizing the cultural aspect of ordinary citizens’ legal consciousness; the law is viewed here as a social practice which “operates . . . as both an interpretive framework and a set of resources with which and through which the social world (including that part known as the law) is constituted.”78 “Law,” argues Sarat, “is both a resource and a constraint.”79 According to this perspective, rather than an external force impressing itself upon social life, the law is an emergent feature of social relations and a socially constructed system of action. Drawing upon reflexively informed social theory, subjects, as products and producers of society, emphasize the symbolic dimension of legal practices. From this point of view, all practices—including legal practices—are analyzed in terms of their degree of symbolic efficacy. The symbolic is seen here as something that characterizes both the perception of reality as well as the practices derived from it. This discursive or interpretive approach to the symbolic contrasts with a descriptive or positivist stance, according to which there is an external reality apart from the subject who knows it. In what follows, I will concentrate on the latter two perspectives: that is, on the critical idea that the symbolic is approached as an institutional strategy—or as an institutional use—destined to serve the aims of legitimation, and the epistemological idea—or that of constitutive social theory—in which the symbolic is understood as a form of cultural consciousness that constitutes and in turn is constituted by the society. I will refer to them with the terms symbolic use of law and symbolic vision of law, respectively. Clarity in the distinction between the two will aid in comprehending the problems that derive from the extant theoretical model in LCS. IV. SYMBOLIC EFFECTS OF LAW IN BOURDIEU AND IN THE LCS Pierre Bourdieu is one of the most respected and most often cited authors in the works of LCS.80 His work is frequently referred to by 78. COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 23. 79. Austin Sarat “. . . The Law is All Over” Power, Resistance, and the Legal Consciousness of the Welfare Poor, 2 YALE J.L. & HUMAN. 343, 377 (1990). 80. E.g., EWICK & SILBEY, COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 39 (when explaining their theoretical framework they state: “[w]e draw on a recent and growing body of literature in sociology that attempts to bridge these dualisms by redefining the relationship between the individual and social structure, reconfiguring what was understood to be an oppositional relationship as one that is mutually defining.” To that end, they cite first Bourdieu and then Giddens, Swidler, Sewell, and Steinberg. In theoretical studies of sociology of law, Bourdieu is frequently cited to justify a theoretical framework). Buchanan, supra note 28; see also McCann & 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 173 sociolegal researchers affiliated with the LCS school as supportive of both a constructive theory of practice of law and a symbolic understanding of social relations. Those belonging to LCS are particularly attracted to his idea that the keys to understanding how social structures are produced and reproduced are found in concrete social practices. The practices constitute the structures as much as the practices themselves are determined by the structures; the structures are socially constructed in the practices of social actors in their everyday lives. The concept habitus is of particular importance in this effort to get beyond the subject/object dichotomy. According to Bourdieu habitus is a system of durable, transposable dispositions, structured structures predisposed to function as structuring structures, that is as principles which generate and organize practices and representations that can be objectively adapted to their outcomes without presupposing a conscious aiming at ends or an express mastery of the operations necessary in order to attain them.81 The empirical dimension of Bourdieu’s postulate82 and the relevance of everyday practices fit well with LCS interests. One could even say that as Bourdieu has the aim to write a general theory of practices, LCS is attempting to write a general theory of legal practices. In both cases there is an underlying question: how are the discourses and social practices produced and reproduced? Bourdieu’s interest in this question is located in the fact that one can obtain, through its elucidation, a better comprehension of political domination in society. In other words, this question suggests another more profound one: how is it possible that hierarchically based systems of domination persist and reproduce themselves through social practices? Bourdieu views society as a stratified and differentiated space in which individuals struggle to defend positions and interests.83 Now, domination, March, supra note 4, at 217; MERRY, supra note 6. 81. PIERRE BOURDIEU, THE LOGIC OF PRACTICE 53 (1990). For an application of this concept to the field of law, see Fréderic Ocqueteau & Soubiran-Paillet, Champ juridique, juristes et régle de droit: Une sociologie entre disqualification et paradoxe, in DROIT ET SOCIÉTÉ 9, 9-26 (1996). 82. It is worth noting that in Bourdieu this does not lead to a positivist outlook on the social sciences. Bourdieu considers erroneous the opposition of theory and practice or that of quantitative and qualitative methods. Both “theoreticism,” understood as speculation divorced from reality and “methodologism” (methods as an end in themselves) have no reason to exist in sociology. See generally Pierre Bourdieu & De San Martin, Le patronat, in ACTES DE LA RECHERCHE SCIENTIFIQUE (1978). 83. SWARTZ, supra note 37, at 63. According to Wacquant, PIERRE BOURDIEU & J. D. WACQUANT, AN INVITATION TO REFLEXIVE SOCIOLOGY 14 (1992), Bourdieu’s work can be interpreted as a materialist anthropology of the specific contributions of the different symbolic 174 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 more than something linked to the use of physical violence, is something articulated through, and experienced through, the use of symbolic violence. The ones who are dominant in society do not achieve that position merely through possession of economic capital. They also attain cultural capital and the close connection between the two forms of capital.84 This articulation operates in such a way that the symbolic systems—through which we establish classifications and determine the essential categories of social inclusion and exclusion—do not have only a cognitive and social structure function,85 but also a political function of domination. The symbolic is also an inherently violent practice to the extent to which it imposes meaning on the world and on social relations in which economic and political power lose their original arbitrary and exclusive connotations and appear as something normal and acceptable. Here Bourdieu’s idea of “misrecognition” is important. Activities and resources gain in symbolic power to the extent that they become separated f r o m u n d e r l yi n g m a t e r i a l i n t e r e s t s a n d h e n c e a r e “misrecognized”—disguised as disinterested forms of activities and resources. The application of this idea to law can be seen in Bourdieu’s article La force du droit.86 Not only is all action interested but much action can be carried out successfully only if its interested character is “misrecognized.” The law is a good example of symbolic violence. The possibility that legal workers have to establish essential classification for the social order—legal/illegal, just/unjust, true/false—entails enormous political privilege. According to Bourdieu, the official law is the privileged space for the production and exercise of symbolic power. The law possesses the “magic effect of nomination.”87 It also has the power to establish the official, the legitimate, and the authorized worldview. Legal authority is the privileged form of power, especially in terms of legitimate symbolic violence—monopolized by the State—which the State both produces and practices.88 The symbolic capital embedded in legal norms creates a type violences on the reproduction and transformation of the structures of domination. 84. SWARTZ, supra note 37, at 136-37. 85. According to Bourdieu, the cognitive structures which social agents implement in their practical knowledge of the social world are internalized “embodied” social structures. See generally PIERRE BOURDIEU, LA DISTINCTION; CRITIQUE SOCIAL DU JUGEMENT (1979). 86. Pierre Bourdieu, La force du driot; elements pour une sociologie du champ juridique, in ACTES DE LA RECHERCHE EN SCIENCES SOCIALES 64 (1986) [hereinafter La force du driot](French version, perferred); Pierre Bourdieu, The Force of Law: Toward a Sociology of the Juridical Field, 38 HASTINGS L.J. 805, 814-53 (1987) [hereinafter The Force of Law](English version). However, I use here the original French version. 87. See sources cited supra note 86 88. Id. at 3. This idea of symbolic power is also usefully explored by BALANDIER, supra note 39; HARRY PROSS, ESTRUCTURA SIMBOLICA DEL PODER (1980); HARRY PROSS, VIOLENCIA SOCIAL 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 175 of force that functions independently of their implementation.89 According to Bourdieu, this type of legal force is defined by its opposition to both the simple non-implementation (failure) of legal norms, and to the implementation of legal norms through sanctions.90 In understanding the symbolic force of law or its legitimizing effect, we must avoid not only those materialistic accounts that see nothing but power relation in the explanation of law, but also those idealistic accounts that explain it through the general recognition of the universal values carried out by its norms. “We can no longer ask whether power comes from above or from below,” says Bourdieu, in a reference to the debate between critical and doctrinal explanations of law.91 Against the materialistic account Bourdieu maintains that, “[w]e need to recover the profound logic of juridical work in its most specific locus . . . .”92 However, this postulate does not prevent him from recognizing that, “given the essential role it plays in social reproduction, the judicial field has a smaller degree of autonomy than other fields, like the artistic or the literary.”93 Symbolic power here is not only an institutional power but also a power that is clearly linked to the economic structure of society. The efficacy of symbolic capital in terms of social differentiation and hierarchy relies on its correspondence with other forms of capital, among which economic capital is primary. In Bourdieu’s words, “[g]iven that symbolic capital is none other than economic or cultural capital when it is known and recognized according to the categories of perception that it itself imposes, the relations of symbolic power tend to reproduce and to reinforce the power relations that constitute the structure of social space.”94 For this reason the schema for perceiving the world are not simply systems of knowledge, they also are systems of social domination that demonstrate the importance of the objective division between social classes.95 Loic Wacquant explains how in Bourdieu “the sociology of knowledge or of cultural forms is eo ipso a political sociology, that is a sociology of symbolic power.”96 (1989). 89. GARCÍA-VILLEGAS, supra note 39. 90. La force du droit, supra note 86, at 14. 91. Id. In the United States this debate was specially intense between CLS scholars and the legal mainstream. 92. La force du droit, supra note 89, at 3-4. 93. Id. at 18. 94. PIERRE BOURDIEU, CHOSES DITES 160 (1987). 95. Social class, according to Bourdieu, does not have an objective reality as Marx thought. See BOURDIEU, supra note 37. What exists is “a space of differences, in which class exists, shall we say, virtually . . . not as a datum but rather as something that is being invented” Id. at 28. 96. BOURDIEU & WACQUANT, supra note 83, at 14. DE LOS SIMBOLOS 176 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 In other words, the symbolic dimension of law is made of two elements. One is the cognitive element, according to which actors give meaning to their practices. The second, the political element, puts the emphasis on the different types of uses of the symbolic in order to improve domination. My argument is that this second aspect is neglected in LCS and it is so because it is an aspect of the symbolic that seems to be relevant only in a conception of society that draws upon a conflict theory, which is strange to LCS. LCS also take an interest in knowing how legal discourse and legal practices are produced and reproduced over time.97 They conceive of the law as a set of concrete practices of ordinary people and not as an institutional discourse that is imposed upon them. The law is seen as a complex repertoire of discursive strategies and symbolic parameters that structure meaning and social practices. Thus, and in opposition to a dogmatic view, the law is a phenomenon characterized by the pluralism, indeterminacy, and contingency of legal practices. The symbolic is a central element of this theory to the extent to which reality is constructed through representations and interpretations and not in concrete realities. However, in contrast to Bourdieu’s work, here the emphasis is placed on the cognitive aspect of the symbolic dimension of law. This explains the importance attributed to legal culture, understood as a complex set of discourses and symbolic frameworks through which individuals give meaning to their legal performances.98 The cultural and constitutive viewpoints can, at times, seem to be the same: “[t]his cultural or constructivist understanding sees legality as an ongoing human production.”99 Structure is conceived of in terms of cultural schema that organize and normalize social interactions. These cultural schema, unlike something external and unitary that is imposed on subjects, are composed of myriad complex interrelated significations that are difficult to disentangle.100 Consciousness, argue Ewick and Silbey, is not an effect of structure but rather an integral part of it. “[It] is participation in the production of structures.”101 Accordingly, ideology is not a set of abstract ideas but a complex process through which “meaning is produced, challenged, 97. Silbey, supra note 36, at 41-42; Legal Consciousness, supra note 5, at 26; COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 45, 247. 98. Critics consider LCS to be “[s]tudies of legal culture.” Susan S. Silbey, Making a Place for Cultural Analyses of Law, 26 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 39 (1992) ; MCCANN, supra note 16, at 15. 99. COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 31. 100. It is difficult to comprehend the meaning of a cultural order according to Clifford Geertz, Ideology as a Cultural System, in IDEOLOGY AND DISCONTENT 47, 56-57 (David E. Apter ed., 1964). Cultural studies are marked by this skeptical position with respect to the possibilities of understanding the structural elements that infringe on agency. ALEXANDER, supra note 2, at 235. 101. COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 224. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 177 reproduced, and transformed.”102 Ideology, they argue, in a somewhat confused way, can be understood to represent an intersection between structure and consciousness. “If we use the term consciousness to name participation in the production of structures, ideology refers to the processes that produce a specific pattern in social structure.”103 Whatever the explanation, the concept of legal ideology is reduced to the level of everyday legal practices as a complex process through which meanings are produced, reproduced, and changed, beginning with the experience of shared power.104 Likewise, Harrington and Yngvesson, are opposed to a modern conception of power grounded in “the distinction between ideology and practice”;105 such a conception places “ideology outside of social relations, and thus creat[es] a two-dimensional world, one part of which (culture, the symbolic, the state, law) is given and constitutes the other.”106 The reconceptualization of these terms—culture, consciousness, structure, ideology—supposes an erasure of their dividing lines; the subsumption of structure in consciousness107 makes the difference between culture, structure, consciousness, and ideology a very subtle one and frequently confusing.108 The “de-materializing” of the concept of ideology and its assimilation to that of consciousness has even been the object of criticism in authors sympathetic to the position argued in LCS. This is the case of Michael McCann. For him “[t]he problem with this conceptual equation is that it obscures, or reduces [the analytic] attention [paid] to . . . the interactive relationship between [the] individual and [the] institutional” and between the institutional and subjectivity.109 Once the institutional dimension of ideology is played down, those social spaces where the poor live are magnified. Not only is resistance overestimated in terms of political practices but also those who suffer poverty are presumed virtuous or their 102. MICHÉLE BARRETT, WOMEN’S OPPRESSION TODAY: PROBLEMS IN MARXIST FEMINIST ANALYSIS 47 (1980), cited in COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 225. 103. COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 225-26. 104. Id. at 225. 105. Harrington & Yngvesson, supra note 12, at 142. 106. Id. 107. COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 225 (stating that “Structure, which in its conventional formulation tends to be understood as largely material and external to the situations it constrains, is now defined so as to encompass ideas as well as resources.”). I admit with McCann, however, that Merry's analysis, MERRY, supra note 6, of this relation is different to the extent that she establishes a distinction between ideology and discourses. 108. See ALEXANDER, supra note 2, at 302-29, on the difficulties of formulating a cultural theory. According to this scholar, following Geertz, the goal of cultural analysis is interpretation and not theory. Id. at 328. 109. McCann & March, supra note 4, at 213. 178 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 actions justified in all circumstances.110 Their practices are presumed to be violence free. But this is an illusion, as Bourdieu has explained: “[a]nd the populist illusion which is nowadays nourished by a simplistic rhetoric of ‘resistance’ tends to conceal one of the most tragic effects of the condition of the dominated—the inclination to violence that is engendered by early and constant exposure to violence.”111 Not only does this perspective not help to distinguish the actions of the excluded according to their merits, but in fact it works actively to obscure the way that powerful groups routinely defy and resist legal norms, which frequently implies a considerable cost for those with whom LCS authors identify.112 Moreover, the idea that the resistance holds is not related to social classes, race, or workplace struggles, but rather to tactical maneuvers against judges, clerks, mediators, administrators, or other state officials.113 The fact that both the collective and the contextual dimension of individual practices are not considered leads these studies to conceptualize resistance as something rather romantic and innocuous. In almost all the narratives chosen by these authors, practices of resistance114 are reduced merely to intentions of resistance that are supposed to be heroic but in fact are mostly useless or ephemeral, even in terms of individual fights. Symbolic power is exerted only with the collaboration of those who undergo it because they help to construct it as such. But nothing would be more dangerous than to stop short at this observation (as idealist constructivism, in its ethnomethodological or other forms, does). This submission is in no way a “voluntary servitude” and this complicity is not granted by a conscious, deliberate act; it is itself the effect of a power, which is durably inscribed in the bodies of the dominated, in the form of schemes of perception and dispositions (to respect, admire, love, etc.), in other words, beliefs which make one sensitive to certain public manifestations, such as public representations of power.115 110. See id. 111. PIERRE BOURDIEU, PASCALIAN MEDITATIONS 233 (Richard Nice trans., Standford Univ. Press 2000, 1997) [hereinafter PASCALIAN MEDITATIONS]. For an explanation of Bourdieu’s opposition against the celebration of resistance, struggles, and creative practices of the dominated, see P. BOURDIEU & LOIC J.D. WACQUANT, AN INVITATION TO REFLEXIVE SOCIOLOGY (1992) [hereinafter INVITATION TO REFLECTIVE SOCIOLOGY] . 112. See PASCALIAN MEDIATIONS, supra note 111, at 219. 113. See generally McCann & March, supra note 4. 114. M. Becker, Towards a Substantive Feminism, in FEMINIST JURISPRUDENCE (Cynthia Grant Bowman & Morrison Torrey eds., 1995). 115. PASCALIAN MEDITATIONS, supra note 111, at 171. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 179 On reading the stories presented by LCS one gets the impression that, despite their own interpretations of practices, the final obstacle actors face in their fight for emancipation is a structural one: race, poverty, education, and so on. It is striking that the authors overlook this element in their analysis.116 In the story of Millie Simpson told by Ewick and Silbey, for instance, it is clear that she—a poor Black women—succeeds in her resistance only when her boss, a powerful White man, decides to help her.117 If this is the case, why then are structural and institutional elements, which undoubtedly are important for the understanding of legal reality and legal culture, so disregarded? I claim that it is because culture, domination, and hegemony are reduced to consciousness. In Bourdieu, conversely, culture cannot be understood outside the economic and cultural conditions in which subjects act. Cultural tastes are never disinterested and can only be understood by starting from a theory of symbolic power.118 Culture is a set of dispositions internalized by individuals through a process of socialization that constitute schemas of perception and understanding of the world. These work only to the extent that there is a certain correspondence with the hierarchical order that they represent. “There is a correspondence between social structures and mental structures, between the objective division of the social world—particulary between dominators and the dominated in the different spaces—and the principles of worldview and classification that agents apply to that world.”119 This correspondence fulfills essential political functions in society. Thus, symbolic systems are not only tools of knowledge but, first and foremost, instruments of domination. Cultural capital works the same way as economic capital and of course is intimately related to it. All cultural production is oriented to the production of dividends, that is, to a reward.120 According to Wacquant’s reading of Bourdieu, the concepts of habitus, capital, and space expand the scope of interests while reducing that of utility and consciousness. The concept of legal consciousness in the LCS does just the opposite. 116. Moreover, some LCS are aware of this fact. Sarat, for instance, insists that the welfare poor do not have a counter hegemonic view of law; neither are they able to challenge the system of legal meaning through which power is exercised and domination maintained. Off to Meet the Wizard, supra note 6, at 377. 117. See COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 3-14. 118. SWARTZ, supra note 37, at 89 (interpreting Bourdieu, “[i]f his theory of practices extends the idea of interest to culture, then his theory of symbolic power extends culture to the realm of interest with the claim that all forms of power require legitimation.”). 119. PIERRE BOURDIEU, LA NOBLESSE D’ÉTAT: GRAND CORPS ET GRANDES ÉCOLES 7 (1989) [hereinafter LA NOBLESSE E’ETAT]; BOURDIEU, supra note 49, at 206. 120. In Bourdieu’s theory there is a search for profit analogous to the quest for economic advantage in the selection or rejection of cultural styles. See BOURDIEU, supra note 37, at 147. 180 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 “A central objective of Bourdieu’s work is to show how cultural and social class correlate.”121 Ideology, for its part, is a tool that operates to disguise social reality and therefore to maintain a certain status quo that allows domination and differentiation among individuals. Ideology is then synonymous with symbolic violence and consists in the capacity of a social and institutional power to impose legitimate meanings, in such a way that the power relations that undergird this power are hidden.122 So the law is an essential element of political domination and its nature is domineering, potent, and almost inevitable.123 In contrast, for LCS law is always polyphonic, contingent, variable, and therefore, weak.124 The studies of legal consciousness tend to neglect the postulate according to which the different schema for perception, interpretation, and action originate in the positions that social actors occupy in the economic sphere. Ewick and Silbey, for example, differentiate three ideal types that aid in the comprehension of this complex reality; they term them: “before the law,” “with the law,” and “against the law.”125 The first, “before the law,” reflects those practices that depend on a reified view of law, understood to be a coherent, majestic institution with all the formal trappings.126 This is the view derived from the history it authorizes, the story it wants to tell.127 The second possibility, “with the law,” comprises a vision of the law as a playing field on which different actors and institutions compete.128 The third, “against the law,” encompasses those attitudes that see the law as a space of confrontation and, at times, emancipatory struggle.129 121. SWARTZ, supra note 37, at 143. 122. Id. at 89. In Bourdieu ideology or symbolic violence is “the capacity to impose the means for comprehending and adapting to the social world by representing economic and political power in disguised, taken-for-granted forms.” Id. In his PASCALIAN MEDITATIONS, however, Bourdieu warns about the concept of ideology: [i]f I have little by little come to shun the use of the word “ideology” this is not only because of its polysemy and the resulting ambiguities. It is above all because, by evoking the order of ideas, and of action by ideas and on ideas, it inclines one to forget one of the most powerful mechanisms of the maintenance of the symbolic order, the twofold naturalization which results from the inscription of the social in things and in bodies. PASCALIAN MEDIATIONS, supra note 111. 123. La force du droit, supra note 86, at 64; BOURDIEU, supra note 94. 124. Off to Meet the Wizard, supra note 6, at 375. 125. COMMON PLACE , supra note 5, at 45. 126. Id. at 47. 127. Id. 128. Id. at 48. 129. Id. at 48-49. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 181 This classification enriches the phenomenon of ordinary people’s legal representations and shows the complexity of the resistance to law that had been oversimplified by some CLS. It does not appear, however, to give sufficient weight to the power of certain material factors to restrict pluralism, contingency, and legal practices. Ewick and Silbey, for example, do not seem interested in investigating why some types of legal consciousness appear to prevail over others and what relationship exists between this tendency and the existence of a hierarchically divided society. In the same Ewick and Silbey research, there is a clear correlation between social marginality and the legal consciousness termed “before the law”; likewise, to have some cultural and economic capital and the representation of law as a game appear to go hand in hand. However this correlation does not show up in their analysis, not even as an interesting element. Because they are interested in what kind of legal consciousness people possess without asking what kind of material conditions make this legal consciousness possible, the concept of domination exists but does not seem to hold a central place.130 For these authors, social practices structure a social reality that, in turn, affects these practices, but the process is not directed toward political domination. Their interest lies in legal consciousness and individual practices of resistance, as they form part of a process in which the meaning given by individuals to their law becomes repeated and stabilized, and those institutionalized structures become part of the meaning systems that are employed by actors.131 But their narration of consciousness and practices of resistance do not explain why, even in their own examples, actors are not only inevitably isolated but also are unable, despite their resistance, to modify their situation of subordination and marginality.132 This is so because they are not interested in exploring the conditions under which an actor’s legal consciousness is produced and reproduced in society.133 Whatever the case, the act of limiting oneself to recounting individual stories of resistance to hegemonic power, without taking into consideration the obstacles to this resistance, obscures the phenomenon of power in society, including that of local power to the extent to which it exists in relation to other powers.134 130. PASCALIAN MEDIATIONS, supra note 111, at 67. 131. Legal Consciousness, supra note 5, at 741. 132. See White, supra note 6, at 21-32 (declaring that the narration of Mr. G’s history leaves the same impression). 133. PASCALIAN MEDIATIONS, supra note 111, at 68. 134. See generally BURAWOY ET AL., supra note 27; BOAVENTURA DE SOUSA SANTOS, TOWARD A NEW COMMON SENSE: LAW, SCIENCE AND POLITICS IN THE PARADIGMATIC TRANSITION (1995). 182 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 In the face of the crushing imposition of official law on individuals’ mental representations and on their practices, Ewick and Silbey speak of “reification”;135 Bourdieu, in comparison, refers to symbolic violence. These are not mere nuances of meaning; they presented and revealed two different theoretical options, one centered in problems of knowledge and the other in problems of power. In one, human agency is privileged, while the other emphasizes the state’s imposition of a worldview. Neither does this refer simply to a question of emphasis; above all it is a difference underlying three essential concepts in a critical legal theory: legal culture, legal consciousness, and legal domination. Both LCS and Bourdieu insistently employ an idea of the symbolic, in opposition to an instrumentalist, view of law. For LCS, however, this notion has an epistemological use that refers to the construction of a legal reality premised on systems of communication and interchange among individuals.136 While in Bourdieu this idea has not only a constitutive connotation (it creates the social world although this world first creates the law), it has, first and foremost, a clear political presentation, because creating and ordering social reality confers a permanence upon it that is typical of things.137 In order not to fall into a sort of radical nominalism à la Foucault, however, Bourdieu sustains that law’s power to name and to create “can function effectively only to the extent that the symbolic power of legitimation (or naturalization) reproduces and heightens the immanent historical power which the authority and the authorization of naming reinforces or liberates.”138 As a consequence, the political function of symbolic legitimation is superimposed on a cognitive or merely creative dimension that the law possesses as constructor of society. Law is seen as an instrument strategically employed by social actors in conflict.139 LCS, conversely, seem to give greater importance to the cultural or constitutive dimension than to the political dimension, or at least they do not center their attention on the latter. This weighting derives from the assumption they adopt, in contrast to conflict theorists, that social actors do not necessarily act in a strategic and self-interested manner. Bourdieu’s critique of phenomenological and ethnomethodological positions in sociology is perfectly apropos here 135. COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 78-79. 136. In opposition to a conception of law as a set of normative institutionalized controls, see generally Galanter, supra note 75, at 117-42. 137. La force du droit, supra note 86, at 13. 138. See id.; BOURDIEU, supra note 49, at 206; BOURDIEU, supra note 94, at 160. 139. According to Swartz, Bourdieu injects the language of strategy to distance himself from strict structuralist forms of determination by stressing the importance of agency. SWARTZ, supra note 37. On the other hand, the concept of strategy does not lead to the acceptance of a rational choice theory. Id. at 99. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 183 while they are right to recall, in opposition to the mechanist vision, that social agents construct social reality, they fail to address the question of the social construction of the principles of construction of that reality which agents implement in the individual and also collective work of construction, and to consider the contribution of the State to that construction . . . . In modern societies, the State makes a decisive contribution towards the production and reproduction of the instruments of construction of social reality.140 LCS accept that violence is exercised through law and that this violence favors hegemonic power; however, and in concordance with the cultural turn prevailing in social theory over the last decade, it appears as if the explanations lodge here and go no further. The relationship between violence and class domination is not developed. For Yngvesson,141 the way law names the world and the way legal professionals construct meanings is hegemonic, but that hegemony assumes plurality: It does not passively exist as a form of dominance. “It has continually to be renewed, recreated, defended, and modified.”142 Sarat explains this accent on resistance stating that “[m]eanings that seem natural, or taken-for-granted, are described as hegemonic, but because the construction of meaning through law is, in fact, typically contested, scholars show the many ways in which resistance occurs.”143 I think that this approach does not take material constraints seriously. In Stuart Hall’s terms, “[it] replaces the inadequate notions of ideologies ascribed in blocks to classes with an equally unsatisfactory ‘discursive’ notion which implies total free floatingness of all ideological elements and discourses.”144 Sympathetic to a discursive approach to social construction, Susan Silbey maintains that the meanings and values held by social actors “are never fixed, nor stable, nor unitary.”145 Silbey recognizes, however, that the possibilities of variation in these meanings and values are limited by 140. PASCALIAN MEDITATIONS, supra note 111, at 174-75. 141. See generally Yngvessson, supra note 36 142. Id. at 1693. 143. Austin Sarat, Redirecting Legal Scholarship in Law Schools, 12 YALE J.L. & HUMAN. 129, 140 (2000); see also MERRY, supra note 6. 144. Stuart Hall, The Problem of Ideology: Marxism Without Guarantees, in STUART HALL: CRITICAL DIALOGUES IN CULTURAL STUDIES 25, 41 (David Morley & Kuan-hsing Chen eds., 1996). A similar critique of culturalist positions is found in Nancy Fraser, Social Justice in the Age of Identity Politics: Redistribution, Recognition, and Participation, in 19 THE TANNER LECTURES ON HUMAN VALUES 22 (Grethe B. Paterson ed., 1998); see also BURAWOY ET AL., supra note 27. 145. Silbey, supra note 98, at 45. 184 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 the specific circumstances in which each individual finds him or herself.146 But is this sufficient? In LCS, the possibilities of social emancipation and competition for the benefits of law appear as probable as the possibilities of social domination. The concept of hegemony becomes malleable and contingent.147 The position of actors in social space, their economic and cultural capital, is given short shrift while concentrating on the possibility that actors oppose or resist power. This almost random account of the values-consciousness-practice trilogy hides some characteristics that frequently accompany hegemonic power, for example its persistence through time, or its success in imposing legitimated social practices in which stability and the absence of critique are characteristic features. Concepts like domination and hegemony are frequently employed in LCS, but they are used in a way that excludes both the ideas of class and the State. The concept of hegemony seems to evoke the image of a dispute among equals and of a fight for different meanings rather than the idea of domination and violence. It is true that occasionally—as Yngvesson has argued148—the exchange among actors is considered to be an unequal one; however, it seems that this is only the starting point of the struggle and that everything could change thereafter. In any case, it is difficult to state the LCS view on this matter because there is only a resounding silence on the question. There is a lack of interest in the elucidation of social asymmetries even as a partial but important source of explanation of the struggle among different meanings. The problem of power is reduced to disembodied symbols as if the cultural dimension of power could be explained by itself. This is why when they develop the idea of symbolic power, they have in mind the idea of a symbolic power without symbolic violence. Indeed, insofar as the social and economic location of the actors in society is not considered, insofar as the socioeconomic hierarchy is not examined, both domination and resistance are equally possible; I am tempted to say they are “equally random.”149 Every practice seems to be reduced to a fight among actors holding different meanings, each of which could eventually win. It seems as if there are no tendencies in this game, no hierarchies, no violence. Even the State seems to be only one more actor playing a game. Every practice is a matter of culture, a matter of 146. Id. at. 46. 147. Handler, supra note 26, at 700. 148. See Yngvesson, supra note 36, 98. 149. MERRY, supra note 6, at 8. See generally, Legal Consciousness, supra note 5. The fact that people go to court, for instance, is considered as a fact of domination: “freedom from the control of the community comes at the price of domination by the State, in the form of the court,” says Sally Merry. MERRY, supra note 6. Given however, their lack of interest in class matters and local positions of actors in society, they are not able to explain when and how this domination by courts actually works. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 185 meaning. The difference between “high” and “low” is therefore erased.150 It is true that agency and meaning are restricted by structures, but these structures are reduced to discourses and this analysis undermines the question of why, in a given social reality, only some discourses are possible. In short, LCS are interested in people who are usually poor or marginalized. However, this is an anthropological interest in symbols and representations rather than a critical interest. Bourdieu is also interested in social marginalization and domination. However, instead of focusing on legal consciousness, he is interested in objective relations between people. ”I could twist Hegel’s famous formula and say that the real is relational: What exist in the social world are relations—not interactions between agents or intesubjecteive [sic] ties between individuals, but objective relations which exist ‘independently of individual consciousness and will’. . . .”151 The disinterest shown by LCS for macrostructural analysis obscures the underlying factors that determine the relative permanence of social hierarchy and domination; they give an image of openness, contingency, mobility, malleability, and indeterminacy to social relations that in fact does not exist in the United States or anywhere else. One does not have to be against the dynamic and omnipresent notion of power in Foucault152—as a critique of the conceptualization of the State as an institution centralizing power and violence—to recognize that a healthy chunk of the power in society circulates through state institutions. It seems to me that domination takes on multiple forms, some of which are efficacious precisely through an invisible or undetectable state. In essence it is common for the State—and for law—to exercise its power through selective doses of intervention or nonintervention in different spaces and times. Or put another way, institutional power also consists of 150. See generally Yngvesson, supra note 36, at 1689. 151. INVITATION TO REFLECTIVE SOCIOLOGY, supra note 111, at 97. 152. A sort of fascination with the concept of power as developed by Foucault in le panoptique, is found in LCS. See, e.g., COMMON PLACE, supra note 5, at 188; Legal Consciousness, supra note 5, at 731; William L.F. Felstiner & Austin Sarat, Enactments of Power Negotiating Reality and Responsibility in Lawyer-Client Interactions, 77 CORNELL L. REV. 1447 (1992). This enchantment seems to be paradoxical to the extent that the opacity, the submission even, of social actors to power structures is so characteristic of Foucault’s thought. What happens is, in North American sociology of law, Foucault’s conception of power is very often taken up only insofar as it is something fluid, variable, and decentralized, and not as it is shown to be an omnipresent structure that determines social action. I question whether it is legitimate to dismember Foucault’s work in this fashion. See Buchanan, supra note 30 (including a more elaborate analysis of Foucault). 186 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 the selection of which social spaces to protect, which to abandon, which to liberate, which to oppress, etc.153 V. CONCLUSION The studies of legal consciousness have the merit of having demonstrated the complexity and creativity of the legal phenomenon in individual and collective spheres that, prior to these studies, were only seen as passive elements of social regulation. It is doubtless that these studies offer a more highly developed and complex view of the sociolegal reality. A close reading, however, reveals the lack of critical energy that some legal studies formerly possessed. A certain domestication of the critical spirit has occurred, probably unintended, that wrests analytic strength and interest from the studies of legal consciousness. To what is this domestication due? More than a decade ago, Trubek and Esser proposed that the attachment to empiricism was affecting the critical force of these studies. Without ignoring the merits to their argument, in this Essay I have attempted to answer this question by following a different line of reasoning. My argument was organized as follows: first, as a critique of the LCS idea of abandonment of both the institutional and the macro-level perspectives in favor of ethnographic local studies; second, as a postulate of inadequacy of the theoretical model that sustains the studies undertaken within this micro-perspective. Concerning the first point, LCS are nourished in the political commitment of the Critical Theorists as well as the empirical aims of the L&S founders. Nevertheless, they distance themselves both from CLS and from the initial tendency of L&S (gap studies). With respect to the first point, LCS reject the disregard for empirical research and knowledge of the concrete sociolegal reality (law-in-action). The distance from the latter is a condemnation of their lack of commitment to a position independent of the dominant political thought and the circles of power. But the way in which LCS achieved this double distancing continues to occasion problems. The excessive emphasis placed on the constituted character of the social world dilutes the distinction between the exterior and interior of subjectivity in such a way that the critique loses its referent. Everything is reduced to a scattered and random set of consciousnesses and social practices that practically explain themselves tautologically. A very high price to pay for the “institutionalist errors” of policy studies: the absence of a macrosociological lens lessens the capacity to “see” and analyze genuinely efficacious emancipatory options for the 153. Boaventura Santos, Bogotá: Uniandes, Siglo del Hombre, in EL CALEIDOSCOPIA DE LAS JUSTICIAS EN COLOMBIA (2001). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 187 excluded. The mental representation of reality leaves aside, or at least underestimates, the ideological influence of state entities on individual consciousness. In this fashion topics such as social action/agency, the fragmentation of power, and individual resistance end up cloaking issues such as class domination, hegemony, and alienation. The constructive nature of social action is so strong that it overshadows its structured dimension; in this way the macro-level of hegemony is hidden and the classist connotation of symbolic violence is cancelled out. In the second place, the study of consciousness and concrete legal practices lacks a sufficiently clear theoretical framework. There seems to be a certain incompatibility between a constructivist or interpretivist theoretical model and empirical research. This disagreement could be based on the fact that the former appears, at least at times, to be grounded in social presuppositions close to those of the conflict tradition, while the latter appears to be associated with a microinteractionist tradition that gives the subject a central role in social organization. In the more specific terms of this Essay, the problem occurs because the theoretical agreement around the notion that the symbolic as an essential element in law hides fundamental differences in the way that this idea is conceived and employed by authors belonging to different sociological traditions. The way that the LCS explain both the concept of “legal consciousness” and the symbolic vision of law fits better in constructivist theoretical models, particularly ethnomethodological theories, than in those developed by Bourdieu, Giddens, or Touraine, where the symbolic is treated not only as “symbolic vision,” but also and especially—due to its affinity with conflict theory—as “symbolic strategy” or “symbolic uses.” Symbolic force—Bourdieu says—that of a performative utterance, and specially of an order, is a form of power which is exercised in bodies, directly and as if by magic, without any physical constraint; but the magic works only on the basis of previously constituted dispositions, which it “triggers” like springs.154 Of course, a certain empathy exists between the explication of the domestication of critique as an effect of empiricism, such as Trubek and Esser argue, and this more general hypothesis of the lack of fit between theoretical model and research. I think, however, that we do not argue the same point and in fact the explanations are not even similar, one being more particular and the other more general. My point is that empiricism in L&S has a conservative character, not because the researchers are conservative or because its use in the explication of reality prevents 154. La noblesse d’etat, supra note 118, at 169. 188 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 investigators from adopting a critical stance, but rather due to the type of empirical investigation prevailing there. This type of research—unlike others155—is linked to a theoretical tradition that concentrates on the creative potential of social action in such a way that the connection between agency and structure violates the spirit claimed by the constructivist model. To sum up, I think that this argument is explained less as an epistemological problem of truth—objectivist versus interpretivist—than as a problem of political presupposition in social theory. In the case of the LCS this problem is manifested in a type of empirical investigation that accentuates aspects related to agency, constructive capacities, and resistance, at the expense of a social theory inclined to put the emphasis on conflict, hierarchy, and structure. It is worth noticing that this difference between conflict theory and constitutive theory exists despite their agreement on the necessity to overcome the agency/structure dichotomy or the objectivism/subjectivism dualism. In other words, I claim that LCS have not succeeded in their purpose to overcome the agency/structure dichotomy and that this is due to the fact that they do not sufficiently consider the analysis of the social reality under which legal consciousness is produced and reproduced in society, the analysis of, as Bourdieu says, the “social construction of the principles of construction of that reality” which is implemented in social practices. The exigency of theoretical coherence in the model adopted, in very vague terms to be sure, by the LCS, posits a dilemma. One possibility is to uphold a constitutive theory of a culturalist stripe–which goes from Clifford Geertz to Paul Kahn—according to which local actors in specific discursive or symbolic social contexts in which plurality, contingency, and indeterminacy engage in practices of social construction. In this case my view is that all reference to authors such as Bourdieu, Giddens, or Touraine should be abandoned. Another possibility is to take seriously the structural aspect in social construction, which means taking on the challenge of both 1) the tension between attempts at social change that 155. For example, those of Bourdieu. See also BOAVENTURA DE SOUSA SANTOS, TOWARD A NEW COMMON SENSE: LAW, SCIENCE AND POLITICS IN THE PARADIGMATIC TRANSITION (1995); PATRICIA WILLIAMS, THE ALCHEMY OF RACE AND RIGHTS (1991) (discussing feminist studies); Menkel-Meadow, Feminist Legal Theory, Critical Legal Studies, and Legal Education or “The Fem-Crits Go to Law School,” 38 J. LEGAL EDUC. 61 (1988); Martha Minow, Interpreting Rights: An Essay for Robert Cover, 96 YALE L.J. 1860 (1987); Robin West, Jurisprudence and Gender, 55 U. CHI. L. REV. 1 (1988). For critical studies of race see, Kimberle Williams Crenshaw, Race, Reform, and Retrenchment: Transformation and Legitimation in Antidiscrimination Law, 101 HARV. L. REV. (1988). For Latino studies, see Margaret E. Montoya, Law and Language(s): Image, Integration and Innovation, 7 LA RAZA L.J. 147 (1994); Francisco Valdes, Theorizing “OutCrit” Theories: Coalitional Method and Comparative Jurisprudential Experience—RaceCrits, QueerCrits and LatCrits, 53 U. MIAMI L. REV. 1265 (1999). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 189 start from individual or collective action and the barriers, sometimes insurmountable, that inhibit those emancipatory endeavors, and 2) the tension between the micro-level of social action and the macro or institutional level. I think that a critical vision of law, such as that attempted in the studies of legal consciousness,156 would have much more chance to prosper on this micro/macro terrain.157 In sociolegal terms, it would be then a question of combining the symbolic vision of law, inherent in all constitutive social theories, and which is not called into question here, with a theory of the symbolic strategy as a political instrument, whether it be of domination or of social emancipation. But clearly this task will not be an easy one and still lies ahead. 156. See McCann & March, supra note 4, at 209. 157. A good example of the theoretical connection between micro and macro can be seen in the concept of the “extended case method,” developed by Michael Burawoy; such a method “attempts to elaborate the effects of the ‘macro’ on the ‘micro.’ It requires that we specify some particular feature of the social situation that requires explanation by reference to particular forces external to itself.” BURAWOY ET AL., supra note 27, at 9; see also ADVANCES IN SOCIAL THEORY AND METHODOLOGY, supra note 27. Concerning socio-legal studies, Santos develops a complex macro/micro framework for the explanation of the role law plays in society as well as for overcoming the dichotomy agency/structure. DE SOUSA SANTOS, supra note 134, at 275. OLD LAW IN THE NEW WORLD: SOLÓRZANO AND THE ANALOGICAL CONSTRUCTION OF LEGAL IDENTITY Susan Scafidi* I. TERRA INCOGNITA LEX . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 192 II. EUROPEAN SOURCES OF LAW . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 193 III. LAW IN THE INDIES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 195 IV. LAW FOR THE INDIANS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 197 A. Historical Debate: Indian Identity and Legal Status . . . . . 198 B. Solórzano’s Synthesis: Miserabiles Personae . . . . . . . . . . 199 V. ON ANALOGICAL REASONING . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 202 VI. CHECKING THE REARVIEW MIRROR . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 204 Over 500 years ago, a small band of Europeans sailed past the borders of the map, encountered a previously unknown land and peoples—and sought legal advice on how to proceed. The initial response, from royal financiers of the voyage and their ecclesiastical supporters, focused on gaining control of the new territory by claiming responsibility for its inhabitants. Despite the juridical consensus surrounding this approach, however, it required a century and a half of experimentation and debate before one jurist was able to classify the identity of these new “subjects” within the expansionist empire. * Assistant Professor of Law, Adjunct Assistant Professor of History, Southern Methodist University. In researching this Essay, a thumbnail sketch of a larger, ongoing project, I have incurred many debts of gratitude: to the Honorable Morris S. Arnold; to University of Chicago Professors Kathleen N. Conzen, R.H. Helmholz, and William J. Novak; to Professor Laurent Mayali and the extraordinary staff of the Robbins Collection, Boalt Hall School of Law, University of California, Berkeley, for generous financial and research assistance (and a memorable birthday celebration); to Assistant Curator and Research Librarian Walter Brem and the staff of the Bancroft Library, University of California, Berkeley; to Professor David Weber and SMU’s William P. Clements Center for Southwest Studies for encouragement and an accompanying travel grant; to Professor Berta Hernandez-Truyol and her colleagues at the University of Florida for coordinating LatCrit VI; to Professors Kevin Johnson, Tayyab Mahmud, Camille Nelson, Ofelia Schutte, and Stephanie Wildman for commenting on my conference presentation; to SMU’s University Research Council and Robert Dedman School of Law for research grants; and to fellow SMU Law Professors William Bridge; Joseph W. McKnight, III; Mary Spector; and especially my esteemed colleague Jeff Trexler. Thank you all. 191 192 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 I. TERRA INCOGNITA LEX1 Modern civic identity in the Western Hemisphere flows from the original fifteenth century collision between Native American2 peoples of the Caribbean and European explorers sailing under the Spanish flag. Shortly after this unexpected event, European legal advisors turned to the familiar language of medieval jurisprudence to assert sovereign control over the previously unknown territory.3 In order to apply these legal principles, the jurists first required a means of bridging the situational gap between the Old World and the New. Just as metaphor provided a vehicle for European explorers attempting to describe an unfamiliar continent, so legal analogy offered an apparent means to equate portions of the established legal order with the newly incorporated elements. Analogical reasoning, designed to expand Spanish influence, thus provided the basis for a new world order, aspects of which continue to inform the relationship between national governments and indigenous peoples.4 The initial sequence of European law’s transplantation to the Americas is fairly straightforward. First contact between Indians and Europeans yielded a series of descriptions intended for the royal financiers of the voyage. The news of potentially valuable lands prompted Spain to stake a legal claim, preferably through arguments sufficient to exclude other European competitors. This claim, while aimed at the territory itself, necessarily included a characterization of Spain’s relationship with the native inhabitants. The ius commune, however, lacked a provision for newly “discovered” peoples. They were neither Christian allies, nor Spanish subjects, nor Muslim infidels. While they might be captured as slaves, such trade would not support Spain’s exclusive claim to the new lands. Medieval experience did allow their designation as objects of missionary activity, with an eye to conquering them should such overtures be refused. Yet even apparently 1. Unknown land, unknown law. 2. At the risk of anachronism, the terms “Native American,” “Indian,” and “native or indigenous peoples” appear interchangeably throughout this Essay to describe the pre-contact inhabitants of the Americas and their descendants. Similarly, as modern scholarship appears to lack a culturally neutral term for the territory explored and occupied by European powers from the late fifteenth century onward, the terms “Americas,” “Western hemisphere,” “New World,” and “Indies” appear throughout the work. 3. See generally ROBERT A. WILLIAMS, JR., THE AMERICAN INDIAN IN WESTERN LEGAL THOUGHT: DISCOURSES OF CONQUEST (1990). 4. See, e.g., Johnson v. M’Intosh, 21 U.S. (8 Wheat.) 543 (1823). While Chief Justice John Marshall does not refer in his decision to European civil law or to the European jurists cited by the parties, his characterization of Native American tribes as “dependent” is strikingly similar to the conclusions of Spanish jurists. Id. at 596. For a useful collection of Latin American constitutional provisions and legislation regarding indigenous peoples, see DERECHOS DE LOS PUEBLOS INDIGENAS: LEGISLACIÓN EN AMERICA LATINA (Gisela González Guerra ed., 1999). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 193 successful conversion seemed insufficient to prompt recognition of these “gentle, naked” people as full-fledged Spaniards. Complicating these attempts at legal classification was European recognition of social classes, and in particular a ruling elite, among Native American groups. As a practical matter, many Spaniards viewed influence over and exploitation of Indian leaders as a strategy for controlling the native population as a whole. Treatment of native elites as equal partners, however, would undermine Spain’s claim to the territory. The problem of Native American legal status under European law remained ambiguous for over a century, despite persistent discussion of colonial exploitation and the periodic appearance of ineffective royal laws prohibiting such behavior. This Essay examines the efforts of seventeenth-century Spanish jurist Juan de Solórzano Pereira to clarify Native American legal identity within the Spanish social order through the use of legal analogy.5 Part II describes Solórzano’s legal education and the sources of law that he brought to bear on the problems of the Americas. In Part III, the Essay follows Solórzano to his Peruvian post and outlines changes in the colonial legal regime. Part IV returns to the discussion of indigenous legal status, outlining the early debates, and then focusing on Solórzano’s use of analogy to identify Indians as “miserabiles personae,” a category including widows, orphans, and other persons similarly in need of special protection under the law. Although this classification of Indians among the dependent members of European society endured through the end of Spanish colonial rule and was consistent with the royal claim to the territory of New Spain, the analogy ultimately proved insufficiently flexible to adapt to actual circumstances. Part V briefly reviews both the attacks of Critical Legal theorists on the validity of analogical reasoning and recent defenses of this venerable method of legal analysis, as well as cognitive bases of metaphor and analogy. Finally, Part VI offers preliminary conclusions about Solórzano’s use of analogical reasoning to construct indigenous peoples’ Western legal status and invites further discussion. II. EUROPEAN SOURCES OF LAW Juan de Solórzano Pereira was born in Madrid in 1575. His mother and father, both Old Spanish petty nobility, were from the university towns of Valladolid and Salamanca, respectively. At approximately age 12, 5. In terms of methodology, this Essay combines a legal history narrative with legal realism’s insights regarding the importance of agency and forms of legal reasoning. Critical Legal Studies, and thus LatCrit, is one of several branches of modern jurisprudence that traces its intellectual lineage to the realists. See NEIL DUXBURY, PATTERNS OF AMERICAN JURISPRUDENCE 435-50 (1995); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW 1870-1960: THE CRISIS OF LEGAL ORTHODOXY 269-72 (1992). 194 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 Solórzano followed his father into the legal profession, enrolling at the University of Salamanca, the peninsula’s most distinguished legal faculty. He graduated in 1599 and began teaching shortly thereafter, receiving the advanced degree of Doctor of Laws in 1608.6 This traditional legal education formed the core of Solórzano’s jurisprudence. When Solórzano was a law student, the standard curriculum covered the ius commune, or law common to all of Europe, rather than local or national Spanish law.7 Although medieval and early modern jurists treated the ius commune in many respects as one system,8 it actually consisted of two distinct branches.9 The first was Roman or civil law, based on the Emperor Justinian’s sixth-century Corpus iuris civilis, a landmark compilation of laws and legal scholarship.10 In the late eleventh century, the legal community rediscovered the Digest, the section of Justinian that excerpted and organized by subject matter the writings of great Roman jurists.11 This rediscovery led to the establishment of law schools across Europe and the rapid diffusion of Roman law.12 So highly regarded was the Corpus iuris civilis, that jurists assumed it to contain sufficient material to resolve any given legal question,13 and centuries later still referred to it as “written reason”—although this reverence for the text did not deter multiple and competing schools of interpretation.14 Indeed, the Spanish government’s attempt, over a century after Solórzano’s graduation, to force universities to replace the Roman law-based curriculum with national law was met with such resistance from professors that the order was ultimately repealed.15 The second branch of the ius commune was canon or ecclesiastical law, which included Biblical passages, statements of Church councils, writings of Church fathers, Papal decisions, and other materials among its 6. For basic biographies of Solórzano, see JAVIER MALAGÓN & JOSÉ M. OTS CAPDEQUÍ, SOLÓRZANO Y LA POLITICA INDIANA 7-40 (1965); JOSÉ TORRE REVELLO, ENSAYO BIOGRÁFICO SOBRE JUAN DE SOLÓRZANO PEREIRA 15-25 (1929). Note that while modern orthography renders his patronymic as “Pereira,” it often appears as “Pereyra” in historical documents. 7. See MANLIO BELLOMO, THE COMMON LEGAL PAST OF EUROPE 1000-1800, at 124-25 (Lydia G. Cochrane trans., Catholic Univ. of Am. Press 1995) (1988) (noting the limited legal curricula of late medieval and early modern universities); 1 ALFONSO GARCIA-GALLO, MANUAL DE HISTORIA DEL DERECHO ESPAÑOL §§ 599-603 (10th ed. 1984) (describing twelfth through seventeenth century universities, with emphasis on the legal curriculum in Spain). 8. PETER STEIN, ROMAN LAW IN EUROPEAN HISTORY 52 (1999). 9. See id. at 49-52. 10. Id. at 35. 11. Id. at 43. 12. Id. at 52-53. 13. Id. at 46. 14. See BELLOMO, supra note 7, at 224-25 (describing various approaches to the study of the ius commune). 15. STEIN, supra note 8, at 106. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 195 authoritative texts.16 In the early twelfth century, a scholar named Gratian attempted to organize this unwieldy mass of material in his Concordia discordantium canonum, or Harmony of conflicting canons, and began to use the volume as a textbook for law students.17 Over the course of the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, scholars updated Gratian’s work with additional compilations, and the resulting authoritative collection of ecclesiastical law became known as the Corpus iuris canonici.18 Although many students, like Solórzano, were not members of the clergy, it nevertheless became common for their university degrees to reflect certification in both civil and canon law.19 While the universities of Solórzano’s era taught the “learned law,” Spanish lawyers conducted the quotidian legal business of the empire according to more localized rules. Collected royal legislation received greatest deference, supplemented by local municipal charters or custom as necessary.20 Only when these sources failed to address a particular issue were lawyers and judges to apply Roman law, preferably by reference to the Siete Partidas, a thirteenth century vernacular text commissioned to introduce Roman and canon law principles into the peninsula.21 The influence of the ius commune was not limited to the interstices of positive law, however, as educated jurists looked to broader currents of European jurisprudence in matters of procedure and interpretation.22 Solórzano’s legal education, while devoid of practical experience, thus prepared him to engage in critical analysis of legal issues according to the highest standards of the seventeenth century European legal community. III. LAW IN THE INDIES In 1609, one year after completing his doctoral degree, Solórzano received a judicial appointment as oidor of the Royal Audiencia of Lima, and the following year set sail for the Americas.23 He remained in that post 16. Id. at 49. For an accessible English-language description of the historical development of canon law and its significance in Western jurisprudence, see JAMES A. BRUNDAGE, MEDIEVAL CANON LAW (1995). 17. STEIN, supra note 8, at 49; BRUNDAGE, supra note 16, at 47-49. Modern scholars express disagreement as to Gratian’s identity, as well as the original date and content of what is often called simply Gratian’s Decretum. See also ANDERS WINROTH, THE MAKING OF GRATIAN’S DECRETUM (2000). 18. STEIN, supra note 8, at 50-51. 19. Id. at 52. 20. CHARLES R. CUTTER, THE LEGAL CULTURE OF NORTHERN NEW SPAIN, 1700-1810, at 3132 (1995). 21. Id. at 32. 22. See STEIN, supra note 8, at 66 (describing the gradual acceptance of the Siete Partidas among professionally trained judges). 23. MALAGÓN & CAPDEQUÍ, supra note 6, at 14-15. For a glossary of terms intended to make 196 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 for eighteen years, during which he married a criolla of a distinguished family and witnessed the birth of eight children.24 This overseas assignment might have proven routine and unimportant; after all, over a century had passed since first contact between Native Americans and Europeans, and many of the major public debates had given way to established institutions. Instead, subsequent changes in the laws of the Indies allowed Solórzano’s Peruvian experience to form the basis for a lasting contribution to Spanish colonial jurisprudence. Upon Solórzano’s arrival in Lima, the system of governance combined the laws of Castile, which exercised claim to the region, with both royal decrees regarding the Indies and local regulations created by European officials and settlers.25 The Spanish legal system also recognized indigenous law and custom, so long as they conflicted with neither Christianity nor European law.26 Solórzano’s position as a judge required consideration of all of these sources of law, as well as facility in determining which to apply. In 1614, however, King Philip III replaced this extant patchwork of peninsular and colonial laws with a decree that only laws formulated specifically for the New World or adopted by the Council of the Indies would have force there.27 The declaration placed Solórzano at the forefront of a major reorganization of Spanish colonial law. Over the course of his career in the royal service, Solórzano became not only an authoritative commentator on the laws of the Indies under Spanish rule, but also a participant in the reorganization of those laws. His first major commentary and legal defense of imperialism, De Indiarum Iure, appeared in 1629, shortly after his return to Madrid; the second volume of this work followed ten years later.28 In addition to this Latin text, Solórzano, in 1647, published Política Indiana, a modified version in Spanish intended for wider distribution.29 Both the Latin and the the history of Latin American law accessible to English-speaking scholars, see M.C. Mirow, Latin American Legal History: Some Essential Spanish Terms, 12 LA RAZA L.J. 43 (2001). 24. MALAGÓN & CAPDEQUÍ, supra note 6, at 16. 25. CUTTER, supra note 20, at 32; GARCIA-GALLO, supra note 7, § 777. 26. CUTTER, supra note 20, at 32; GARCIA-GALLO, supra note 7, § 777. 27. CUTTER, supra note 20, at 32; GARCIA-GALLO, supra note 7, § 777. 28. See ANTHONY PAGDEN, LORDS OF ALL THE WORLD: IDEOLOGIES OF EMPIRE IN SPAIN, BRITAIN AND FRANCE C. 1500-C. 1800, at 98 (1995) (noting that Solórzano’s work offers a defense of imperial ideology grounded in both scholasticism and Roman law). 29. JAMES MULDOON, THE AMERICAS IN THE SPANISH WORLD ORDER: THE JUSTIFICATION FOR CONQUEST IN THE SEVENTEENTH CENTURY 10 (1994). Muldoon notes that Solórzano was ordered to remove certain detailed royal orders against mistreatment of Indians from the manuscript of Política Indiana in order to prevent these official descriptions of mistreatment from drawing the attention of other European powers. Id. (quoting LEWIS HANKE, THE SPANISH STRUGGLE FOR JUSTICE IN THE CONQUEST OF AMERICA 90 (1949)). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 197 Spanish versions of Solórzano’s work circulated widely throughout the New World and were reprinted several times during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries.30 While Solórzano also played a major role in collecting and rationalizing the laws of the Indies following the 1614 decree, that project did not proceed as expeditiously as the publication of his scholarly commentaries. The Council of the Indies, including Solórzano himself, approved an early version in 1636.31 The official text of the Recopilación de leyes de las Indias, however, was not promulgated until 1680, some twenty-five years after Solórzano’s death.32 The fortuitous timing of Solórzano’s judicial appointment, together with a traditional legal education that informed his analysis of colonial jurisprudence, nevertheless secured his position as an influential force in the history of Latin American law. IV. LAW FOR THE INDIANS As Solórzano worked to construct what became the definitive legal argument for Spanish activities in the New World, one of the major unresolved issues was the legal “status” of Native Americans within Spanish society. Despite a century of debate, including significant currents of thought that emerged from Solórzano’s own alma mater, a mass of ad hoc legal enactments governed Indian-European interactions. Diversity among indigenous peoples and changing demographics further complicated the search for a unified legal structure. Lima, for example, was a city of 60,000 people, of whom 30,000 were slaves of African descent, 25,000 were considered Spanish, and a mere 5,000 were Indians.33 While the daily life of an indio compelled to render service to the Spanish state may have been little different from that of an esclavo, Indians were nevertheless a separate group from slaves, who were treated as chattels, and were subject to different rules. Solórzano’s attempts to articulate a precise classification of this distinct minority group within the formalist Spanish legal system formed an important part of his work, and one that may offer insight into the deepest roots of the modern legal identity of indigenous peoples in the Americas. 30. MULDOON, supra note 29, at 10. 31. See GARCIA-GALLO, supra note 7, § 785 (describing the series of efforts that led to the promulgation of the Recopilación). 32. Id. 33. MALAGÓN & CAPDEQUÍ, supra note 6, at 18. 198 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 A. Historical Debate: Indian Identity and Legal Status From Queen Isabella’s frequently quoted reprimand of Columbus for attempting to initiate a slave trade in her Native American “vassals,”34 to the famous debates between Bartolomé de Las Casas and Juan Ginés de Sepúlveda at Valladolid,35 early European attempts to characterize the previously unknown American peoples polarized the empire. The first eyewitness report from the “Indies,” the widely circulated letter attributed to Columbus, enthusiastically described many of the native peoples as gentle, unsophisticated, unclothed, and lacking in any “ill-will [or] treachery.”36 By contrast, the letter also warned against certain islands inhabited by armed cannibals.37 Although simplistic and inaccurate, Columbus’s words laid the foundations for two competing theories regarding the nature of the Indians: either they were “noble savages,” endowed with a wide range of simple virtues, or they were mere “beasts,” greedy, savage, and idolatrous.38 More informed, moderate, and nuanced ethnographic information would gradually inform this national debate, in part through the testimony of indigenous peoples themselves, but the argument’s general parameters influenced royal policy throughout the colonial period. The intensity of the debate might have waned in the decades following first contact between Native Americans and Europeans were it not for the political and theological ramifications of the issue. Spain had predicated its original claim to territory in the New World on a missionary “duty” to subject the Indians to Christian rule and thus convert them. In the 1493 bull Inter caetera, the Pope recognized this claim and assigned a large portion of the region and its inhabitants to Castile. This constructed understanding of the Spanish presence in the Americas led directly to the encomienda system, which entrusted groups of Indians to individual Spaniards who were responsible for their religious and cultural training and protection.39 In practice, the system allowed an encomendero to exact heavy tributes from “his” (or occasionally her) Indians, and fostered many of the abuses of chattel slavery, including removal from home villages and 34. HANKE, supra note 29, at 20. 35. Id. at 11. For the arguments of Las Casas, see BARTOLOMÉ DE LAS CASAS, IN DEFENSE OF THE INDIANS (1992). 36. Margarita Zamora, Christopher Columbus’s “Letter to the Sovereigns”: Announcing the Discovery, in NEW WORLD ENCOUNTERS 1, 4 (Stephen Greenblatt ed., 1993). 37. Id. at 8. 38. See HANKE, supra note 29, at 11-12 (describing the sixteenth century conflict regarding the nature of the Indians). 39. See generally LESLEY BYRD SIMPSON, THE ENCOMIENDA IN NEW SPAIN: THE BEGINNING OF SPANISH MEXICO (1966). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 199 forced labor. Although the crown issued a steady stream of decrees designed to curb the atrocities of the colonists,40 many believed that the Indians’ “brutish” or “barbaric” nature required subjugation through harsh controls.41 Those on the other side of the debate, including the Dominican and former encomendero Bartolomé de Las Casas, supported a policy of converting the “docile and clever” native peoples to Christianity through teaching and persuasion.42 Beliefs regarding the nature and character of Native Americans were thus central to Spain’s Catholic religious identity and exercise of imperial power. In the realm of academia, the sixteenth century debate over the “nature” of the Indians led to a new union of jurisprudence and theology centered at the University of Salamanca. Its leading proponent was the Dominican theologian Francisco de Vitoria, who believed that law should interpret and reflect the divine will apparent in nature, including the unequal status of persons.43 This theory supported both the need for governmental structures and the exercise of power over individuals, such as the encomienda system. Vitoria also argued, however, that the Church did not exercise universal temporal authority over nonbelievers, and that Spain required grounds other than the 1493 papal donation for its claims in the New World—a point of view shared by competing European powers.44 Lawful control over non-Christian lands might instead, in Vitoria’s view, arise from the need to exercise moderate force in order to preach the gospel.45 Since this argument focused on nonbelievers’ receptivity to Christianity, and on the potential use of just war in the service of missionary activity, it once again drew attention to the essential question of the Indians’ character and normative legal status. B. Solórzano’s Synthesis: Miserabiles Personae The value of Solórzano’s treatment of the issue of Native American legal status, and of colonial jurisprudence more generally, lay not in original argument or polemical description but in an orderly approach to harmonizing a century of debate and ad hoc decrees with pre-existing legal structures. His Política Indiana consists of six books, the first of which addresses the threshold question of Spanish title to the Indies, while the second turns to the question of indigenous status. After discussing specific forms of labor and desired conditions, Solórzano concluded “[t]hat the Indians are and should be counted among those persons whom the law 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. 45. See generally RECOPILACIÓN DE LEYES DE LOS REYNOS DE LAS INDIAS 1681 (1987). LAS CASAS, supra note 35, at 11-16. Id. at 362. BELLOMO, supra note 7, at 226-28. HANKE, supra note 29, at 150-52. Id. at 151. 200 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 calls miserables . . . .”46 In this context, the term is categorical rather than merely descriptive. While Solórzano did consider many Indians to be among the “poor and wretched” of the earth, comparing them to Job and other suffering Biblical figures,47 his primary intent as a jurist was to establish for them a definitive legal status, in this case the canonical category known in Latin as miserabiles personae. In order to rationalize the existing body of Indian law according to the principles of the ius commune, Solórzano’s preliminary task was to assign a group identity.48 Rather than rely directly on his own impressions from nearly two decades in the Audiencia of Lima, he cited other authors to describe both the Native Americans’ “humble, servile, and submissive condition”49 and, even when their suffering did not reach Biblical proportions, their position as recent converts was noted for “ignorance, lack of sophistication, poverty, and faintheartedness.”50 Solórzano went on to discuss the Indians’ need for protection against mistreatment, not only for their own benefit but also because they are the “feet” of the republic without which it cannot stand.51 Largely absent from this account is consideration of hispanicized indios ladinos, including those who were able to win small but significant victories within the Spanish system of justice52 or compose a book-length work intended to inform the crown of colonial abuses.53 Instead, Solórzano relied on his elite, educated perspective to gather documentary evidence characterizing Native Americans as a relatively homogenous group in need of Spanish protection. Once Solórzano had established a working description of Indian identity, he was able to assign the group to an existing category of European law. According to the canonists, the Church had a special duty to protect miserabiles personae, a term used to describe widows and 46. JUAN SOLÓRZANO PEREYRA, POLÍTICA INDIANA 2.28 (Francisco Tomás Valiente & Ana María Barrero eds., Biblioteca Castro 1996) (1647) (author’s translation) [hereinafter POLÍTICA INDIANA]. 47. Id. at 2.28.2. 48. See Laurent Mayali, Le droit des autres dan la France médiévale: Système de différenciation et mode d’harmonisation, in IDENTITÉ ET DROIT DE L’AUTRE 183, 183 (Laurent Mayali ed., 1994) (noting that while approaches to the issue differ across legal systems, the initial problem is defined in terms of identity). 49. POLÍTICA INDIANA, supra note 46, at 2.28.1. 50. POLÍTICA INDIANA, supra note 46, at 2.28.3. 51. POLÍTICA INDIANA, supra note 46, at 2.28.20. 52. See, e.g., STEVE J. STERN, PERU’S INDIAN PEOPLES AND THE CHALLENGE OF SPANISH CONQUEST: HUAMANGA TO 1640, at 114-37 (2d ed. 1993) (describing Indians’ successful use of the court system to, inter alia, reduce payment of tributes and pursue land claims). 53. See generally ROLENA ADORNO, GUAMAN POMA: WRITING AND RESISTANCE IN COLONIAL PERU (2d ed. 2000) (analyzing the work of sixteenth and seventeenth century Native American author Felipe Guaman Poma de Ayala). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 201 orphans in particular, as well as those who were old, blind, mutilated, worn-down by long sickness, or poor and oppressed in general.54 The breadth of this category, which Solórzano defined simply as “all those whom we naturally pity because of their status, capacity, and labors,”55 could easily accommodate an additional group characterized by their alleged need for protection. By analogy, then, the indigenous peoples of the Americas became miserabiles personae, and the Spanish government acted as their guardians on behalf of the Catholic Church. Although the purported benefits of this dependent status under canon law were limited, Solórzano compiled a wider range of legal “protections” on the basis of existing colonial laws. Traditionally, miserabiles personae enjoyed only the option of bringing their cases directly before an ecclesiastical court rather than seeking justice in the secular realm.56 Influential commentary on the law, however, suggested that this special original jurisdiction would apply only if the litigant were actually poor and powerless; wealthy widows and others who were technically miserabiles but not in actual need of protection could appeal to the Church only after failing in the first instance to obtain justice from a secular court.57 Ordinary litigants, by contrast, could appeal to ecclesiastical courts only as a last resort after exhausting all avenues of secular justice.58 In his expansion and adaptation of the concept of miserabiles personae, the former oidor did not limit himself to shifting jurisdiction away from the royal courts, in which he had once served, to potentially more sympathetic ecclesiastical courts. Instead, he focused on guidelines for judicial treatment of Native Americans and specific provisions drawn from both Roman and canon law. Among these were the admonition “that trials and court cases involving Indians, especially poor ones, be concluded quickly and with paternal love,”59 limitations on contractual capacity intended to protect against alienation of goods,60 and the presence of “protectors” to provide legal assistance.61 Later, in the third book of Política Indiana, Solórzano employed a similar method to support the continuance of the encomienda system while reasserting the importance of safeguards against abuse. This reinterpretation of the duty owed to miserabiles personae allowed Solórzano to collect many of the ad hoc royal protections and 54. BRIAN TIERNEY, MEDIEVAL POOR LAW: A SKETCH OF CANONICAL THEORY AND ITS APPLICATION IN ENGLAND 15-19 (1959) (citing Decretum Gratian, Dist. 84 ante c. 1; Innocent IV, Commentaria ad X 1.29.38). 55. POLÍTICA INDIANA, supra note 46, at 2.28.1 (author’s translation). 56. TIERNEY, supra note 54. 57. Id. at 18-19 (citing Innocent IV, Commentaria ad X 1.29.3). 58. Id. 59. POLÍTICA INDIANA, supra note 46, at 2.28.27 (author’s translation). 60. POLÍTICA INDIANA, supra note 46, at 2.28.42-45. 61. POLÍTICA INDIANA, supra note 46, at 2.28.46-52. 202 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 reforms of the first century and a half of Spanish colonial law under the umbrella of the ius commune. Using legal analogy and the analytical techniques of the learned law, Solórzano incorporated the original inhabitants of the New World into the jurisprudence of the old, establishing an Indian identity and formal legal status that would endure for another 150 years. V. ON ANALOGICAL REASONING Although analogy is a venerable method of legal reasoning, its validity has been challenged in recent years. Roberto Unger and other Critical Legal theorists have argued that analogical reasoning is incoherent outside its own cultural context, and thus incapable of yielding just results in a heterogeneous society.62 Quite so, since epithets such as “childlike” or “savage” are likely to mean very different things in different cultures, and near-nudity on Caribbean beaches today is unlikely to justify foreign conquest. By this account, Solórzano’s use of analogy to categorize peoples and govern lands largely foreign to him is extremely suspect. As one modern judge has pointed out, however, the use of legal analogy remains in good repute among members of the bar, and thus in little danger of disappearance.63 Cognitive science, moreover, demonstrates that human beings have an innate tendency to analogize and to create categories; in other words, analogical reasoning is part of human hardwiring.64 In light of these twin pillars of tradition and nature supporting the continued use of legal analogy, the contemporary legal community may enjoy more success if it attempts to re-examine this 62. See, e.g., Roberto Mangabeira Unger, The Critical Legal Studies Movement, 96 HARV. L. REV. 561, 570 (1983). 63. Robert E. Keeton, Statutory Analogy, Purpose, and Policy in Legal Reasoning: Live Lobsters and a Tiger Cub in the Park, 52 MD. L. REV. 1192, 1213 (1993). 64. Keith J. Holyoak et al., Introduction: The Place of Analogy in Cognition, in THE ANALOGICAL MIND: PERSPECTIVES FROM COGNITIVE SCIENCE 1, 2 (Dedre Gentner et al. eds., 2001). An approachable introduction to the realm of metaphor and cognitive thought is GEORGE LAKOFF & MARK JOHNSON, METAPHORS WE LIVE BY (1980). Other recent works exploring analogical reasoning from a variety of perspectives include METAPHOR AND THOUGHT (Andrew Ortony ed., 1993) (indicating a cross-disciplinary collection of essays); KEITH J. HOLYOAK & PAUL THAGARD, MENTAL LEAPS: ANALOGY IN CREATIVE THOUGHT (1995) (noting an extended account of the mechanism and applications of analogy); GEORGE LAKOFF & MARK JOHNSON, PHILOSOPHY IN THE FLESH: THE EMBODIED MIND AND ITS CHALLENGE TO WESTERN THOUGHT (1999) (wideranging exploration of the relationship between the embodied mind and philosophical inquiry); and BARBARA MARIA STAFFORD, VISUAL ANALOGY: CONSCIOUSNESS AS THE ART OF CONNECTING (1999) (noting an account of analogy from the perspective of an art historian). In addition, a related legal study on employment discrimination offers an in-depth exploration of the relationship between cognitive processes of categorization and formation of potentially harmful stereotypes. Linda Hamilton Krieger, The Content of Our Categories: A Cognitive Bias Approach to Discrimination and Equal Employment Opportunity, 47 STAN. L. REV. 1161 (1995). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 203 method of reasoning rather than simply overturning it. Essential to this enterprise are two questions: Are there benefits to analogical reasoning, particularly in the construction of socio-legal identity? And, is it possible to circumvent its parochial tendencies? Cass Sunstein has provided a moderate defense of analogical reasoning, albeit while claiming a preference for Rawlsian “reflective equilibrium,”65 and Solórzano’s seventeenth-century attempt to rationalize Native American legal status according to the norms of his era offers a hypothetical object for this new perspective. Sunstein identifies several benefits to the use of legal analogy, all stemming from the “incomplete theorization” of analogical reasoning. Two of these potential benefits are particularly applicable to the issue of indigenous legal status under Spanish colonial rule. The first significant advantage is that those who cannot reach agreement on general principles may be able to agree on the outcome of a particular case through legal analogy.66 This formulation suggests that in the Americas, decades of debate over the essential identity of the Indians might have been circumvented by an earlier appeal to legal analogy. It is plausible to imagine that Dominican friars like Las Casas seeking fair treatment for Native Americans under the law and royal governors seeking to police the abuses of the encomienda system in order to avoid international disapprobation might agree that Indians seeking access to justice would need special protection, not unlike the existing categories of miserabiles personae, even if they could not reach immediate agreement as to the Indians’ nature and character. The second significant advantage is that analogical reasoning allows moral evaluation over time because it is open to new facts and perspectives,67 at least when unencumbered by the fixed categories of a formalist legal system. In Spanish colonial terms, it is possible that the steadily increasing ability of many disempowered groups of people, including Indians, to exercise influence and to assert their limited rights within the legal system might have prompted a revision of Solórzano’s analogy. To speculate further, it is possible that such a revised analogy might have led to a more inclusive formulation of Spanish citizenship, or even the possibility of multiple group affiliations, rather than a series of revolutions against an oppressive colonial power. Legal analogy is a basic tool from the lawyer’s workbench, and one that we need to examine further, rather than unsuccessfully attempt to 65. Cass R. Sunstein, On Analogical Reasoning, 106 HARV. L. REV. 741, 751 (1993). For another analysis and reconsideration of legal analogy, see Scott Brewer, Exemplary Reasoning: Semantics, Pragmatics, and the Rational Force of Legal Argument by Analogy, 109 HARV. L. REV. 925 (1996). 66. Sunstein, supra note 65, at 782. 67. Id. 204 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 discard, in order to avoid cultural incomprehensibility or oppression. In the context of socio-legal identity, an important threshold issue is whether and how a legal system focused on individual rights can also be capable of protecting group identity. If legal analogy appears to be an avenue for such protection, jurists must attempt to ensure that the modern realist legal system is flexible enough to protect groups of people without reifying them. Perhaps most importantly, if legal analogy is used to define sociolegal categories, the law must provide for group boundaries to remain permeable and group identity to retain the opportunity to evolve. VI. CHECKING THE REARVIEW MIRROR In the mid-seventeenth century, an ordinary Spanish civil service lawyer undertook to situate the indigenous peoples of the Americas within the established categories of the formalist European legal system, an organizational task that had thus far eluded a society preoccupied by the complexities and opportunities of a newly “discovered” world. Reasoning from time-honored principles of medieval law, he discovered that legal analogy would allow him to identify Native Americans with the poor, wretched members of European society. Analogy ossified into a set of rules and expectations, and Indians—elite and otherwise—became wards to be educated and protected by guardians under the special protection of the Spanish legal system. This compact legal theorem, though inconsistently applied at the local level, gave the crown claim to the “Indies” and reclassified the native population as eligible for membership in a dependent class of Spanish subjects. As one might predict of the construction of a subordinate group within a formalist legal system, however, one inconsistency still remained: the apparent lack of a mechanism to ensure full participation in society when the characteristics used to justify dependency had dissipated. Eventually, this legal rigidity contributed to the crumbling of the entire colonial system. By attempting to apply the rule of law to a rapidly growing and changing sphere of influence through the use of analogical reasoning, Spain accepted a challenge familiar to both ancient and modern legal systems. Its resulting legal process displayed many evident flaws, in particular the near-complete absence of indigenous participation. The historical evolution of this jurisprudence, alongside an early national debate surrounding the construction of an empire incorporating multiple populations, is nevertheless a significant and overlooked chapter in the evolution of Western law. CLUSTER II CUBANS WITHOUT BORDERS: THE POSSIBLE DREAM Alice G. Abreu* Cubans are nothing if not bordered. Cubans on the island are not free to go out and Cubans off the island are not free to come in. Nevertheless, these borders, once seen as rigid and legally defined, are increasingly being revealed as both porous and malleable. Cubans living in the United States send massive amounts of aid to Cubans on the island, usually prompted by familial concern, but undermining the border imposed by the embargo all the same.1 Travel to Cuba, while nominally prohibited, is possible with Treasury Department permission and that permission is rather routinely granted.2 Travel from Cuba, while also nominally * Professor of Law, Temple University School of Law. I am grateful for the unwavering support of my friend Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, and for the time, energy and wisdom of the scholars who participated in the panel on Cubans Without Borders at LatCrit VI. I also appreciate the thoughtful participation of those in the audience during that session, some of whom have contributed essays to this Symposium growing out of the discussions of the panel. Finally, I am grateful for the excellent research assistance provided by John Necci, Director, Temple Law School Library. Nevertheless, all errors and opinions are mine alone. 1. See, e.g., Roxana Hegeman, Exiles Prop Up Cuban Economy by Sending Money to Families, ASSOC. PRESS, Nov. 28, 1997, available at http://www.athensnewspapers.com/1997/ 112897/ 1128.a3cuba.html. See also Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Out in Left Field: Cuba’s Post-Cold War Strikeout, 18 FORDHAM INT’L L.J. 15, 69-70 n.299-301 (1994) and sources cited therein. The Cuban Liberty and Democratic Solidarity (LIBERTAD) Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104114, 110 Stat. 785 (1996) (often refered to to as the Helms-Burton Act, because it was sponsored by Senator Jesse Helms and Congressman Dan Burton), prohibits many forms of commercial trade and travel to Cuba. See generally id. For a good summary of the the history of the Act and the provisions therein, see Andreas F. Lowenfeld, The Cuban Liberty and Democratic Solidarity (Libertad) Act: Congress and Cuba: The Helms-Burton Act, 90 AM. J. INT’L L. 419, 420 n.8-12 (1996) (noting that restrictions on travel to and commerce with Cuba have been in effect since February 1962, when President Kennedy authorized the issuance of the Cuban Import Regulations, 31 C.F.R. § 515.201, 27 Fed. Reg. 1116 (Feb. 7, 1962), exercising the authority given to him by the Foreign Assistance Act of 1961, (Pub. L. No. 87-195) § 620(a), 22 U.S.C. § 2370(a)(1) (2000)). 2. For a general description of the restrictions and the process for obtaining permission to visit Cuba, see Cuba—Consular Information Sheet (Dep’t State, Aug. 13, 2001), available at http://travel.state.gov/cuba.html (last visited Mar. 14, 2002); Travel to Cuba, at http://state.gov/www/regions/wha/cuba/travel.html (last visited Mar. 14, 2002); Cuba Travel Violations: New Procedures for Fully Hosted Travelers, available at http://www.state.gov/ www/regions/wha/fs_980513_cuba_travel.html (last visited Mar. 14, 2002) (Fact Sheet prepared by the Office of the Coordinator for Cuban Affairs, Bureau of Inter-American Affairs, May 13, 1998) (Dep’t State, May 13, 1998). Despite attempts to lift the embargo, see, e.g., House Passes Bill Lifting Ban on Travel to Cuba, WASH. POST, July 26, 2001, at A2, and some softening of the restrictions, see, e.g., Christopher Marquis, Congressional Leaders Approve a Deal to Allow Food Sales to Cuba, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 28, 2001, at A25, significant restrictions remain. 205 206 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 restricted, occurs frequently, as the island exports its music and dance, and some Cubans are given permission to study and work abroad.3 The plight of a six-year old boy found floating on an inner tube off the coast of Florida on Thanksgiving Day, 1999, forced a concerted examination of the contours of the borders that for over forty years have defined Cubans both on and off the island. The controversy surrounding Elian Gonzales and whether he should be allowed to remain in the United States or be forcibly returned to Cuba riveted the attention of the news media in the United States and polarized the Cuban exile community. Nevertheless, this cluster of essays is not about the plight of Elian. While Elian inspired the introspection that is reflected in this cluster, and the essays collected here are the product of that introspection, we do not, here, re-engage in that debate. Elian catapulted Cubans and the borders that divide us into the national consciousness and in doing so caused many of us to think more seriously about dismantling those borders. Elian’s plight offers a lens through which we can view many experiences of the last forty years. As mature, educated scholars, those of us who have lived with these borders for over forty years are poised to take a leadership role in pointing the way to reunification. We have been the beneficiaries of a liberal, and in some cases also a legal, education; and most of us left Cuba when we were old enough to remember it. Thus we struggle with a dual sense of loss. The loss is dual because not only did we lose the opportunity to grow up in our homeland, but because for a long time we lacked the opportunity to find out for ourselves what our homeland was really like, or at least what it would “really” feel like to us. As the borders between Cuba and the United States have become increasingly porous, the opportunity to remedy the second loss has grown and has been enhanced by the receptivity to new and alternative ideas that is often the product of a liberal, and perhaps especially a legal, education. Although none of us may really be able to go home again, many of us are trying, and in doing so we are beginning to point the way toward reconciliation and reunification. This cluster of essays represents one attempt at that endeavor. 3. The Cubans Without Borders panel at LatCrit VI provided evidence of this. Among us was Jesus Jambrina, a Cuban journalist who had received permission from the Cuban government to study in the United States. Although the Cuban government eased travel restrictions in 1991, and artists and others seem to be able to travel outside of Cuba at will, travel is particularly difficult for certain professionals, particularly physicians. For a description of the Cuban government’s legislation and policies concerning travel abroad by Cubans, see Hernández-Truyol, supra note 1, at 68 n.291-92, and the U.S. State Department’s Country Reports on Human Rights Practices 2001, (Bureau of Democracy, Human Rights, and Labor Mar. 4, 2002), available at http://www.state.gov/g/drl/rls/hrrpt/2001/wha/8333.htm. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 207 Each of the essays in this cluster describes both division and unity. The authors, all born in Cuba, each discuss a division and analyze the ways in which the division can be healed. They bring their personal experiences to bear on the analysis, sometimes overtly, sometimes not. Still, division and reunification are the themes of the essays. We are divided in the way we perceive ourselves, and in the dual ways we are, in turn, perceived: we are and are seen as dual-lingual, dual-cultured, and dual-citizens—neither fish nor fowl.4 On a personal level, reunification occurs as we try to unite the parts on either side of the hyphen that divides the parts of our self. Thus, we write in both English and Spanish, we travel to Cuba, we take the time to know island Cubans as people rather than caricatures, and in doing so we hope to arrive at an understanding that respects the wounds of the past while acknowledging the differences of the present. Of the paths to reunification, traveling to Cuba—transcending the physical border—is the most concrete but, in many ways, the most difficult. The mere prospect of such travel can pit members of a family against one another and cause wounds deeper than many inflicted by Fidel himself, as the controversy over Elian showed. Traveling to Cuba—returning—is loaded with symbolic meaning not only for Elian but for each of us as well. Although for some it symbolizes reunification, for others it symbolizes acceptance of communism and Fidel, and acceptance is a tribute that many see as incompatible with the repudiation that prompted exile in the first place. Although some parents who left everything behind while fleeing Fidel are pleased to hear that their children have not repudiated their birthplace but want to return and learn about their homeland, others see in the act of returning a rejection of the principles that led them to emigrate so many years before. The physical border has become symbolic of the ideological border, and crossing one can be seen as tantamount to crossing the other. Perhaps one of the reasons the Elian episode elicited such strong emotions is that it conflated the crossing of the physical border—returning Elian—with the crossing of the ideological border—accepting Fidel’s regime. Those who opposed the return of Elian almost certainly did not oppose it because they thought boys should be raised by cousins rather than fathers or because they thought that Elian’s father was an unfit parent. They opposed Elian’s return because it was a return to Cuba; returning him from the United States was seen as acknowledging that at least in some cases, it was better to be in Cuba than in the United States. For many in exile who left everything behind to come from Cuba to the United States, 4. As Myra Mendible observes in Paradise Lost, Paradise Found: Oral Histories and the Formation of Cuban Identities, 55 FLA. L. REV. 269 (2003), we are members of the “one-and-ahalf” generation who are, “in Gustavo Perez Firmat’s catchy phrase, ‘born in Cuba, made in the U.S.A.’” Id. 208 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 to suggest that living in Cuba might be preferable to living in the United States was to impugn the sacrifice they made when they left Cuba to come to the United States. The Elian controversy thus represented much more than a custody fight over a little boy. Only that understanding explains the vehemence of the feelings so graphically documented by the United States media. The conflation of the physical border with the ideological one also revealed the bipolar nature of the ideological division. Just as one can be only on one side or another of the physical border, so, ideologically, Castro’s revolution has largely been viewed as either good or bad. In the United States, where the Cuban revolution has been both the darling of liberals and the bane of conservatives, nuanced analysis has been virtually nonexistent. The Cuban community has also suffered from monovision. Among many in the Cuban-exile community, the issues have been too emotionally charged to permit nuanced analysis, and the Elian controversy was no exception. For many in that community, Fidel is the devil incarnate, period. Ironically, one of the things that Cuban exiles have in common with Fidel is the bipolar way in which each views the revolution. For both exiles and Fidel the revolution was either good or bad. Nothing in-between is conceivable. For Fidel, any expression of dissent from a revolutionary goal or deed is regarded as counter-revolutionary, is decidedly bad, and is sometimes dangerous to the health or life of the disagreer.5 For an exile, any expression of agreement with a revolutionary goal or deed proves that the agreer is a communista or Castrista and is, therefore, presumptively bad.6 No in-betweens are brokered by either side. Yet, it is from the inbetween that reconciliation must come. Only after a more nuanced analysis that recognizes the existence of both good and bad on each side can the sides come together. 5. The Cuban government’s repression of dissenting views has been widely documented and often criticized. See, e.g., Cuba’s Repressive Machinery, Human Rights Forty Years After the Revolution (Human Rights Watch, June 1999), available at http://www.hrw.org/reports/1999/cuba; Hernandez-Truyol, supra note 1, at 80-94. As recently as April, 2002, the United Nations Commission for Human Rights encouraged “the Government of Cuba to accede to the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights” and to “allow the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights to send a personal representative with a view to cooperation between her Office and the Government of Cuba in the implementation of the present resolution.” Situation of Human Rights in Cuba, U.N. Comm’n on Human Rts., 48th Sess., U.N. Doc. E/2002/23-E/CN.4/2002/200 (2002), available at http://www.unhchr.ch/huridocda/huridoca.nsf. 6. For a chilling description of the strength of this reaction, see Francisco Valdes, Diaspora and Deadlock, Miami and Havana: Coming to Terms with Dreams and Dogmas, 55 FLA. L. REV. 283 n.30 (2003), describing how a well-known Miami restaurant was bombed after it allowed a Cuban singer (from the island) to perform. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 209 An analysis that examines nuances would acknowledge that Castro’s revolution did things that were both good and bad. It would neither demonize nor cannonize, but would instead acknowledge the pain of those who left while validating the accomplishments of some who stayed. Validation of the experiences of those on both sides of the border is crucial to reunification. Reunifcation cannot occur if we simply tell those who fled under threats of persecution, or those who lost friends and loved ones to human rights abuses, that bygones should be bygones because more than forty years have elapsed. We cannot ask people to forget what they gave up. Acknowledging the exiles’ sacrifice is necessary if we are to move toward dismantling the bipolar border and embark on a path to reunification. But, acknowledging that Castro’s revolution did good things is also important. Accepting that he improved literacy and health care for the general population need not signify acceptance of all of the means he used to effect such improvement, but must occur if we are to pave the way to a more sophisticated, more realistic understanding of circumstances on the island.7 Traveling to Cuba or returning Elian each provide a point of departure for this more nuanced analysis, perhaps because the choices in each situation are starkly bipolar. The Cubans Without Borders panel at LatCrit VI was a microcosm of this polarity and the ways to move beyond it. It revealed the diversity of the Cuban experience and the paths both communities can take toward reconciliation. Of the seven members of the Cubans Without Borders panel at LatCrit VI only one, me, who organized the panel, had neither returned nor attempted to return to Cuba. By contrast, Professor Yvonne Tamayo was the most recent returnee, having made her first trip to Cuba just weeks 7. Improved literacy and healthcare have long been cited as the most significant accomplishments of the revolution. See, e.g., Hernandez Truyol, supra note 1, at 21-29; Jim Lobe, Learn From Cuba, Says World Bank, INTER PRESS SERV., Apr. 30, 2001, at http://www.foodfirst.org/cuba/news/2001/wb-ips.html (describing World Bank President James Wolfenshohn’s comments on the significant progress made by Cuba on health and education). Its reduction in infant mortality rates “places it firmly in the ranks of the western industrialised nations,” and in education performance Cuba “‘is very much in tune with the developed world, and much higher than schools in, say, Argentina, Brazil, or Chile.’” Id. (quoting Jo Ritzen). Cuba’s gains in health and education are probably due to the commitment of fiscal resources to those areas. Thus, [p]ublic spending on education in Cuba amounts to about 6.7 percent of gross national income, twice the proportion in other Latin American and Carribean countries and even Singapore . . . . Cuba devoted 9.1 percent of its gross domestic product (GDP) during the 1990s to health care, roughly equivalent to Canada’s rate. Its ratio of 5.3 doctors per 1,000 people was the highest in the world. Id. 210 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 before LatCrit VI, and Jesus Jambrina was the only island-raised Cuban among us. Both Professor Myra Mendible and Judge Ana Otero had returned, and Professor Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol had attempted to return, only to be foiled by bureaucracy, as she describes in the essay that she wrote for this Symposium. Of the two other contributors to this Symposium, Professor Ofelia Schutte has returned often, while Professor Francisco Valdes has not. Despite the differences in our choices, what emerged from our planning discussions, the panel presentations themselves, and the reflections memorialized in the essays that compose this cluster and other submissions to this Symposium, was the similarity in our longings and our fears. I, having not returned, can understand Yvonne’s desire to return and to see for herself, through the eyes of an adult, the country in which she was born and that shaped much of who she is. Yvonne, who has so recently returned, can understand my deference to the feelings of my parents, who would see my return as a betrayal of the principles that they stood for when they left, and as a repudiation of the decision they made by leaving. We can both understand how difficult it will be for Jesus to decide whether to return to Cuba once his authorized stay in the United States has finished. What we all have in common is that Castro has marked us, and continues to do so, whether we are here or there. The key to reunification is recognizing that although the choices—returning or staying—are bipolar, their implications need not be. Returning need not mean approval of Castro’s regime. More importantly, it need not mean that exile, and the pain suffered by exiles who left everything behind, was in vain. Lasting reconciliation cannot occur unless pain suffered is acknowledged. Many of the experiences described by the essays in this cluster, and in this Symposium more generally, illustrate this point eloquently. In doing so, they show that reunification is possible and demonstrate how it can be achieved. In the first essay in this cluster, Professor Berta Esperanza HernándezTruyol begins where many of us do—with her own experience in thinking about returning to Cuba—and uses it, together with the polarities revealed by the Elian saga, as a springboard for a critical examination of whether any common ground of cubanidad might still exist and serve as a platform for reunification.8 As she explains, she “suspected that while social, political, and economic differences might result in some insurmountable divides, cultural tropes might unite us, even if not always through desirable traditions.”9 In Building Bridges V—Cubans Without Borders: Mujeres Unidas Por Su Historia, Professor Hernández-Truyol traces the 8. Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Building Bridges V—Cubans Without Borders: Mujeres Unidas Por Su Historia, 55 FLA. L. REV. 225 (2003). 9. Id. at 230. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 211 role of women in Cuban society by reviewing Cuba’s laws on women, international norms on gender equality, and United States, laws as they affect Cuban women in the United States.10 Surprisingly, she finds that “cultural assumptions about sex roles have persisted in Cuban societies whether within the island or in the Cuban community within the U.S.”11 She concludes that “further study is likely to reveal additional commonalities with respect to attitudes in matters such as family, race, and sexuality.”12 Her work is thorough and scholarly, and offers a unique view of a too-long neglected subject. She reveals, for example, that the first Cuban feminists emerged during the Cuban fight for independence during the latter part of the nineteenth century, and describes their role not only in that fight but in crafting laws that would allow women to start on the path to equality.13 The picture she paints is of brave women who nevertheless succumb to marianismo and male dominance when the danger is past.14 The story of women in Cuba today, she finds, is not much different from that of Cuban women in exile, but her insight is that the similarity of oppression and subordination can provide the unifying trope for a post-subordination ideology.15 Her conclusion that the common experience of sexism can serve as a unifying force is both novel and inspiring, for, at bottom, it posits that the glass is at least half full. In the next essay, Paradise Lost, Paradise Found: Oral Histories and the Formation of Cuban Identities,16 Professor Myra Mendible advances the cause of mutual understanding by deftly exploring “how conflicts between Cubans on and off the island boil down to [a] critical intersection where personal stories assume historical significance.”17 Professor Mendible offers lessons from post-colonialism and examines the role of history in defining the condition of exile.18 She describes the role that her personal history has had in defining her identity and the way she has come to terms with her condition as “in-between” two cultures.19 She also examines the way in which such personalized histories have shaped visions of Havana, both as paradise lost and paradise found.20 Professor Mendible returned to Havana in search of answers to questions raised by years of hearing seemingly incomplete versions of history; her essay 10. 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. See generally id. Id. at 231. Id. Id. at 231-32. See generally id. See generally id. See generally Mendible, supra note 4. Id. at 271. See generally id. Id. at 277. Id. at 271. 212 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 lucidly explains her discoveries.21 We see that the experience of returning proved transformative, even though it raised more questions than it answered.22 It gave her a framework upon which to build a more nuanced understanding of what had previously been “a clear-cut polarity.”23 It can serve as a model for a more widespread reunification. Professor Yvonne Tamayo’s reflections on her first trip to Cuba since leaving as an exile over forty years ago is an example of the kind of personalized history Professor Mendible urges.24 In Cubans Without Borders: Finding Home, poignantly subtitled “Everybody Gets To Go Home But Cubans,” Professor Tamayo describes her return and her discovery that she and many of the Cubans she met shared some core values, even as their views on other matters differed.25 Professor Tamayo was struck both by what has changed and what has not.26 By integrating what she learned on the island with what she has learned as a United States-trained lawyer, Professor Tamayo offers a view of how the physical, intellectual, and emotional borders might be constructively navigated. Having the occupant of the house that used to belong to her family “slowly but deliberately” close the door in her face graphically illustrated the border that made her an outsider in what had been her home, but seeing the ways in which Cuban families interacted and the reasons many stayed showed her that in some areas of life, the borders did not exist.27 Her detailed account of a conversation with a theretofore forbidding Cuban official shows that many intersections are possible even for those who are physically and ideologically separated.28 Finding the points of commonality she shared with island Cubans allowed Professor Tamayo to see Cubans and their life on the island in a complex, nuanced way.29 Such a view forecloses the kind of absolutist thinking that led to demonstrations and violence in Miami over the return of Elian. It points toward dismantling the borders that now separate us. The final essay in the cluster, written by Professor Frank Valdes, brings together the threads explored in the preceding essays, and therefore is the perfect closing for this cluster. In Diaspora and Deadlock, Miami and Havana: Coming to Terms with Dreams and Dogmas,30 Professor Valdes 21. Id. at 277-81. 22. Id. 23. Id. at 279. 24. Yvonne A. Tamayo, Cubans Without Borders: Finding Home: “Everybody Gets to Go Home But Cubans,” 55 FLA. L. REV. 215 (2003). 25. See generally id. 26. See generally id. 27. Id. at 218. 28. Id. at 218-20. 29. See generally id. 30. Valdes, supra note 6. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 213 poignantly describes his own emigration experience and uses it to gain insights into the polarities that divide Cubans on both sides of the Florida Straits and on ways of neutralizing those polarities.31 Professor Valdes begins by describing the polarity that has marked his life, observing that Because Fidel, and his allies and acolytes, have not-ever-been willing to risk a loss or diminution of their power and status, no matter what, I never have found myself able to accept their extended, indefinite and totalitarian monopoly on all power, information, and wealth in Cuba. At the same time, I have been repeatedly disappointed and repelled by the rigid and unrelenting authoritarianism of Miami’s exile politics—an Orwellian authoritarianism that is perpetrated in the name of political pluralism and freedom of expression. Having been raised amidst the ugliness created between these two poles—my two hometowns—I have been unable to come to terms with either.32 Professor Valdes then traces the “post-Fidel Cuban exodus” and analyzes the contrasts and similarities between the cultures on both sides of the Florida Straits, sparing neither.33 He also analyzes the effect of United States politics on the relationship between Cubans in Miami and Havana, concluding that [T]he Left’s romance with Havana and disdain for Miami have produced the same net effect here as the Right’s romance with Miami and disdain for Havana have produced over there: the Right’s partisan promotion of the Miami elites’ agenda nonetheless has allowed the Havana elites to exacerbate and exploit the fears and concerns of Cubans on the island as a means of maintaining their corrupt control, while the Left’s partisan promotion of the Havana elites’ agenda ironically has allowed the Miami elites to excite and exagerate diasporic fervor and fanaticism . . . . The net effect of these interventions, both over here and over there, is to reinforce rigidity, license impunity and inflame conflict. It is way past time to recognize that both kinds of essentialization, valorization and demonization are false, exploitative and destructive.34 31. 32. 33. 34. See generally id. Id. at 285 (footnotes omitted). See id. at 287-89. Id. at 304-05. 214 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 Professosr Valdes then provides a blueprint for moving to a postsubordination society, both in Miami and in Havana, and concludes with five LatCrit exhortations that can serve as principles to guide the way to reunification.35 His essay is insightful and compelling. It invites precisely the kind of thoughtful and deliberate analysis that is necessary, and it should inspire scholars from many disciplines to continue the dialog that will eventually lead to reunification of what he describes as his two hometowns. It is because I emphatically agree with Professor Valdes’ characterization of Havana and Miami as our two hometowns, that I want to conclude this introduction by describing what I learned from Jesus Jambrina, a Cuban-born and Cuban-educated journalist who was studying in the United States, and who gave a moving oral presentation (in Spanish, aided by voluntary simultaneous translation from a member of the audience), at LatCrit VI. Jesus revealed that within present-day Cuba itself, there exists a society that is as diverse, and as nuanced, as those existing outside the island. In discussing issues such as class-based and racially-based discrimination in Cuba, and talking about the plight of gays, lesbians, and transsexuals in Cuba, Jesus forced us to see that contemporary Cuban society is complex and faces many of the challenges faced by the society located on the other side of the Florida Straits. It is that more complex, nuanced understanding that will allow Cubans on both sides of the Straits to go beyond demonizing one another to reach an individualized understanding that will allow each side to transcend the borders that now divide us. This is neither a quixotic undertaking nor an impossible dream. The fact that nine participants in LatCrit VI have started to work towards it shows that it can be done. What we need now is more. We need to talk and write about the borders that separate us and how we can overcome them, so that we can continue to lead by example. Our pain and the pain of our parents need not condemn our children to growing up without knowing the land of their parents, from which, for good or ill, at least some of their heritage derives. 35. Id. at 313-16. CUBANS WITHOUT BORDERS: FINDING HOME “Everybody gets to go home but Cubans”1 Yvonne A. Tamayo* Recently, I returned to my birthplace of Cuba.2 During spring break of 2001, I, along with twenty-nine of our law school’s faculty, alumni, and friends, attended a seven-day educational program in Havana entitled “Cuba for Law Professionals.”3 Because we were permitted entry to Cuba pursuant to a U.S. Treasury Department license requiring that the program contain a strong educational component,4 we obtained the cooperation of the National Union of Cuban Jurists (Union), Cuba’s loose equivalent of the American Bar Association. The Union is allegedly a non-governmental organization comprised of Cuban law professors, lawyers, judges, researchers, and consultants that conduct conferences and symposia to further the development of the legal profession.5 1. Mireya Navarro, A Return to Cuba, A Search for Himself, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 21, 2001, § 2, at 6 (quoting Eduardo Machado, author of the play Havana Is Waiting). * Associate Professor, Willamette University College of Law; J.D., Loyola University School of Law; B.S., Louisiana State University. I dedicate this Essay to my father, Ignacio J. Tamayo, for his unwavering support in my journey to finding home. I wish to thank Abbey Vanderbeek and Carmencita More for their review of prior drafts of this Essay. Financial support for this research was provided by Willamette University College of Law. 2. See generally Yvonne A. Tamayo, Doing Good While Doing Well in the Twenty-First Century: One Cuban’s Perspective, 70 FORDHAM L. REV. 1913 (2002). 3. Professor Michael Wise and I, along with the Willamette University College of Law Alumni Director, conceptualized and developed this program. 4. License No. CU-65453, issued by the Office of Foreign Assets Control, Department of the Treasury, stated, in pertinent part: SECTION 2—CONDITION: a) It is a condition of this license that activities in Cuba fully conform to the educational exchange activities as set forth in your application. SECTION 3—RECORDKEEPING REQUIREMENT: The licensed organization is required to keep a list of individuals whose travel was authorized under this license. Such records shall be made available for examination upon demand for at least 5 years from the date of each transaction. SECTION 4—WARNING: a) This license only authorizes travel-related transactions in connection with full-time educational exchange activities in Cuba and does not authorize transactions related to commercial or touristic activities . . . . Id. 5. We were given a promotional pamphlet entitled “National Union of Cuban Jurists: NonGovernmental Organization with Consultative Status in the United Nations,” which stated: 215 216 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 At 10:15 p.m. on March 17, 2001, Taca Airlines flight #8529 smoothly touched down at Jose Marti International Airport in Havana. I stepped from the plane onto the metal gangplank and inhaled deeply. The warm, humid air felt familiar, as if I had been away only a short time. Yet, I had not been on Cuban soil since my family’s hurried exit from Havana on April 26, 1960. On that day, my parents, my two brothers, and I left behind our extended family, our home, our patria. The first morning in Havana, our group received a detailed outline of the classes that we would attend. The Union would present, over the course of four days, seven three-hour lectures on the Cuban legal system.6 The presentations were held at the Union headquarters, a nondescript white 1950s stucco building located in Miramar, a residential area of Havana. Probably a former residence, its first floor contained a small interior courtyard where we took a ten minute break halfway through each lecture. The breaks were accompanied by welcomed offerings of thick, black café cubano in thimble-sized paper cups and little golden rectangular cakes topped with a clear, sweet syrup. Each day we heard lectures on the Cuban judicial system, penal law, family law, and Cuba-U.S. relations. I listened with rapt attention as our hosts delivered long and winding discourses desbordandose7 with unrelentingly rigid thinking and stale ideology. Questions from our group often sparked circuitous answers containing preordained rhetoric unresponsive to the inquiry, and almost always ending with a redundant reminder that Castro’s Cubans enjoy a high literacy rate and widely accessible medical care. The National Union of Cuban Jurists (UNJC) is a non-profit and self-financed non-governmental organization of Law professionals with its own juridical personality and a scientific-professional profile . . . . An important role in the UNJC’s professional activity is played by its Scientific Societies, nationwide associations created with the common purpose of contributing to develop the Legal Sciences and practice Law [sic], as well as the professional qualification of their membership, requested by and granted to those jurists who maintain a salient professional performance and meet the admission requirements. NATIONAL UNION OF CUBAN JURISTS, NATIONAL UNION OF CUBAN JURISTS: NON-GOVERNMENTAL ORGANIZATION WITH CONSULTATIVE STATUS IN THE UNITED NATIONS (on file with author). 6. The lectures were entitled: 1) Introduction to Cuban History and Geography; 2) The Cuban Legal System: Constitution, Election System; 3) The Cuban Constitution; 4) The Cuban Legal System: Penal Legislation and Procedure; 5) Cuban Law Studies; 6) Helms-Burton: Background; and 7) Cuba-U.S. Relations. 7. Desbordandose is derived from the Spanish word desbordamiento, which means “1. Inundation. 2. Overflowing.” MARIANO VELÁZQUEZ DE LA CADENA ET AL., NEW REVISED VELAZQUEZ SPANISH AND ENGLISH DICTIONARY 239 (1966). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 217 I noted that not one of the speakers brought any written notes to aid in their presentations. I wondered why, and then concluded that decades of repetition, without change or innovation, adhered their respective discourses to memory, rendering written notes superfluous. I also observed that for emphasis, Union members often shook their right hand index fingers in an up-and-down motion, a gesture for which Fidel Castro is widely known. By the third day, my internal response to the lectures was consistent: I vacillated between incredulousness at the message, contempt for the messengers, and pity for the human beings. In their well-worn clothes and dusty shoes, the Cuban jurists resembled old, tired puppets defending a failed social experiment. It was clear that Castro’s repressive authority has created an insular population that seems stuck, frozen in time, living an enigmatic existence akin to a forty-three year quarantine from the rest of the world. Unlike the presentations’ rehearsed rhetoric, lunchtime afforded me a chance for one-on-one repartee with our Cuban hosts. Each day at noon, our tour bus transported us to a different Cuban restaurant, but the offerings varied only slightly: chicken or pork cooked with a lemony mojo criollo,8 white rice, a salad of sliced tomatoes, shredded cabbage and sometimes, a wedge of lime. Dessert usually consisted of a scoop of vanilla ice cream, followed by Cuban coffee. During my chats with the Union panelists, talk of family subtly but persistently entered our conversations. When I asked about her life on the island, the sole woman in the group quickly responded that “la vida aquí no es fácil, pero por lo menos tengo cerca a mi hijo y nieto.”9 Another Union member explained, in broken English, that although Cuba’s “situation” is not good, he remains to care for his eighty-five-year-old mother: “You don’t uproot old trees,” he whispered intently. Walking through the streets of Havana, displays of familial bonds were abundant. On Sunday morning, a teenage girl and her boyfriend, plus her parents, strolled together towards la catedral, arms all interlocked. A young man drove an ancient Packard onto el malecón boulevard. Next to him snugly sat a young girl and Mami, while the back seat remained empty. On a street corner, a middle-aged man repeatedly kissed his mother on her left cheek before boarding an overcrowded public bus. While in Havana, I attempted to visit my family’s residence, where I lived until age five. A woman answered my knock on the front door. She seemed to be of middle-age and had a pleasant face. Nervously, I greeted her with “hola.” I quickly explained that the house had been my family’s 8. Mojo criollo is a mixture of garlic, bitter orange, lemon, and pepper used to marinade meats in Cuban dishes. 9. “Life here is not easy, but at least my son and grandson are near me.” 218 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 home until 1960 when we left Cuba, and asked if I could view the inside of it. “Por favor,” I continued, “quisiera poder contarle a mi padre en Miami que visité nuestra casa en Cuba.”10 She smiled, hesitatingly, and without a word slowly but deliberately closed the door.11 I was flooded with sadness. Nonetheless, I smiled at the irony of the situation—I had finally returned home, but I was not welcome there, not even as a visitor. On the day of the final lecture, the Union jurists staged a fiestesita12 for us. They served cubes of yellow cheese and green olives on small white styrofoam plates and drinks of rum and cola. An aging boom box played a feisty Cuban salsa, and soon some of our group members began dancing to the music. Looking around, I spotted one of the jurists standing alone, apart from the festivities. During that day’s lecture, he had quietly sat at the panelists’ table, looking bored, perhaps even angry. Inexplicably, I now felt drawn to this seemingly inhospitable man. I approached him and in Spanish, I introduced myself. He looked at me intently, then asked if I was Cuban. I answered yes, and explained that since our departure in 1960, none of my family had returned to the island. The following exchange ensued: ¿Te costó trabajo poder venir a Cuba? Vine bajo permiso de grupo educacionál, pero me costó un poco mas trabajo conseguir mi visa. Porque soy nacida en Cuba, tuve que presentar cinco fotos personales, aunque al resto del grupo le pidieron solamente dos. También tuve que presentar un documento contestando varias preguntas sobre mi familia y las circumstancias de nuestra salida de Cuba. ¿Donde vivía tu familia? En el Vedado. ¿Visitaste tu casa? Traté de visitarla, pero la sen#ora que vive ahí no me dejó entrar. 10. “Please, I would like to tell my father in Miami about my visit to our home in Cuba.” 11. Our tour guide explained that Castro has frightened much of the Cuban population by “warning” them against an alleged plot by the U.S. government and exiled Cubans to reclaim the exiles’ homes and evict the present occupants. 12. “Little party.” 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 219 ¿Que irónico verdad? Durante tantos an#os no pudiste regresar a tu patria- por fin lo logras, y aun no puedes entrar en tu casa. ¿Piensas volvér a Cuba? Sí, me gustaría regresar. Te doy un consejo- no te limites en poder imaginar que un día podrás volver a tu patria, a tu casa, facilmente y sin problemas. Espero que tengas razón.13 My conversation with the angry jurist was surprising and insightful. At first, we had been strangers with seemingly irremediable differences. Yet, despite the ideological polarities between us, our personal exchange had engendered mutual good will. Our week in Havana passed quickly. Too soon it was time to leave. On our last day in Cuba, we traveled to the countryside. The arching palm trees, rolling green hills, and lush foliage welcomed me. Among the 13. Was it difficult for you to gain entry into Cuba? I traveled under an educational permit, but it was a bit more difficult obtaining my visa. Because I was born in Cuba, I had to submit five personal photographs, while the rest of the group members were only asked for two. Also, I had to submit a document providing answers to questions about my family and the circumstances surrounding our exit from Cuba. Where did your family live? In the Vedado neighborhood. Did you visit your home? I attempted to visit, but the woman who lives there did not let me enter. Isn’t that ironic? For many years, you cannot return to your homeland—finally, you are able to travel here, and still you cannot enter your home. Do you plan to return to Cuba? Yes, I’d like to return. I’ll give you some advice—don’t limit yourself in your ability to imagine that one day you will return to your homeland, to your home, easily and without problems. I hope you’re right. 220 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 verdant scene, I noticed aging billboards proclaiming Patria o Muerte14—they repelled me. Then, as a huge orange sun set in a spectacular purple and pink sky, and the bus headed to the airport, our tour guide nodded towards the horizon, and smiled. Softly, she said “Goodbye, Havana.” On the return flight, my thoughts drifted to Elian Gonzalez, the young boy who roused the long-entrenched discordance between exiled and island Cubans. Elian’s story is by now familiar: a risky pre-dawn escape from the island on a flimsy boat; the sudden, violent death of Elian’s mother, Elizabeth Brotons, leaving her son alone; and, finally, Elian’s heroic rescue, bringing him to freedom in the United States. I remembered the Cuban community’s response to the prospect of Elian’s return to Cuba. It was a deeply emotional, extraordinarily vocal, and highly public expression of anger, sadness, and despair. Repeatedly, I had been struck by the sharp tone and brazen, uncompromising words employed by some Miami Cubans. On one occasion, Elian’s uncle Lazaro Gonzalez stood outside his home surrounded by a Cuban crowd shouting “War! War! War!”, and defiantly stated that “(t)hey will have to take this child from me by force[!]”15 The intransigence resonated not only in Gonzalez’ strident vow to keep Elian, but also in Miami-Dade Mayor Alex Penelas’ announcement that local law enforcement officers would not aid a federal attempt at forcefully retrieving Elian from Lazaro’s home.16 Gonzalez and Penelas’ provocative declarations reflected the sentiments of many Cuban exiles, some of whom held around-the-clock vigils outside of Gonzalez’ home.17 The events that followed Elian’s rescue, replete with mass protests and violence leading to the arrest of approximately three hundred and fifty Cubans, exposed some Miami Cubans as unreasonable, unyielding, even hysterical.18 14. “Homeland or Death” is a slogan of Castro’s revolution. 15. Elian’s Relatives Lose in Battle of the Videos, S.F. CHRON., Apr. 14, 2000, at A28. 16. Castro’s Promise: Elian’s Dad, Family Will Come to U.S., NEWSDAY, Mar. 30, 2000, at A03. 17. Miami Cubans’ opinions on Elian’s fate were overwhelmingly uniform. Ninety-one percent of Cubans polled in South Florida thought that Elian should remain in the United States. Oscar Corral, Miami Tangled in Memories, NEWSDAY, Apr. 15, 2000, at A22. Conversely, eightyfour percent of the non-Cuban community opined that Elian should return to Cuba. See id. 18. Sue Anne Pressley, In Little Havana, Mourning Subdued Crowd Shows Up at House Where Elian Lived, WASH. POST, June 2, 2000, at A20. One political group, the “Cuban Force,” publicly urged Cubans to withdraw their money from U.S. banks in protest of adverse court rulings in the Elian case. Id. One newspaper described the Cuban community’s behavior during Elian’s stay in Miami as follows: [T]he policy grip of the fanatical anti-Castro lobby, led by the Cuban American National Foundation which financed and often dictated the strategy, 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 221 I also recalled the morning of Saturday, April 21, 2000, when I first saw video clips of the FBI’s pre-dawn raid on Lazaro Gonzalez’ home. I stood transfixed, as the television screamed with eerie footage of a terrified Elian being whisked from Gonzalez’ little white house into a van filled with hooded men armed with machine guns. The swift, sudden, and violent extraction of Elian from Little Havana marked the culmination of his tumultuous five month stay in the U.S. Elian’s arrival and subsequent departure from the United States unearthed many Cuban exiles’ deep feelings of loss. Regarding the Miami exile community’s longstanding sentiments, one author has written: The exile’s grief for the Cuba that had been lost was an all but inescapable part of the ambient noise of Cuban Miami. For all its glittering appurtenances, its prosperity, and, at times, its self-satisfaction, there was a level on which no pleasure, no level of attainment, nor any material accumulation could make up for what had been taken away from these exiles by the triumph of Fidel Castro.19 Elian exposed the wounds of Castro’s revolution. Specifically, he disinterred memories of the forced disformation of Cuban families. One example of Cubans’ desperate response to Castro’s coercion of Cuban families was the covert “Operation Pedro Pan.” In 1961, a rumor spread throughout the island that Castro was planning to deport school-age children to the Soviet Union for communist indoctrination. As a result, desperate parents who were denied exit visas placed their young children, alone, on commercial flights from Havana to Miami. In total, 14,048 children were separated from their parents in a frantic exodus to escape the movements and statements of Elian’s Miami relatives, as it has done over the years for so many elected officials and policy makers, is now at its weakest. Having . . . turned Elian into the human symbol of its vitriol against Castro’s Cuba . . . the hard-line exile community has utterly exposed itself in front of the United States and international community. In a supreme effort to use Elian to isolate Castro, the Cuban-American hardliners have successfully isolated themselves. .... The strident politics of the Elian case have weakened the Cuban-American grip on U.S. policy . . . . Clinton’s Chance on Cuban Policy, BALT. SUN, Apr. 30, 2000, at 1C. Arguably, the death of Jorge Mas Canosa, the founder of the powerful political group “Cuban American National Foundation” precipitated a division among the Cuban ranks in Miami that was magnified during the Elian controversy, and that damaged the group’s public image. David Adams, Cuban Exile Group Loses Host, ST. PETERSBURG TIMES, July 21, 2001, at 2A. 19. DAVID RIEFF, THE EXILE: CUBA IN THE HEART OF MIAMI 64 (1993). 222 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 threat of Fidel Castro’s regime.20 The Cuban children were dispersed to foster homes, or remained in orphanages while they waited months, or years, for their parents to join them in the United States.21 Unlike the Pedro Pan children, however, the reformation of Elian’s family would occur not in this country, but in Cuba. On my visit to Cuba, I experienced, first-hand, the polarization between Cubans within and Cubans outside the island. In spite of their differences, however, I discovered keen similarities between the two groups. Cubans on both sides of the Florida Straits are strikingly similar in their fierce family loyalties. The uninhibited displays of love and loyalty that I witnessed by Cubans towards their families abundantly resonated with my own experiences among my own, and other, exiled Cuban families. Regarding those who create and influence policy in Cuba and the United States, Professor Frank Valdes has observed the existing parallels: The “Havana elites” encompass primarily the circles of power that control the two overlapping institutions that authoritatively and forcefully supervise all life within Cuba: the government and the party, including those . . . officials with the power to conduct economic and political relations with the world external to the island. The “Miami elites” encompass a loose assemblage of [businessmen] . . . and politicos . . . who have amassed [wealth] or position in this country, and who use their . . . influence strategically and methodically to promote their . . . struggle against the . . . economic and political monopoly of Havana’s elites. Both elites cloak themselves in nationalistic fervor, and invoke it to mobilize their foot soldiers.22 On the island, Cubans live in insularity and isolation from the rest of the world. This is largely a result of Castro’s repressive dictatorship, which deprives Cubans access to news from independent sources, generally bans travel outside Cuba, and closely monitors the speech and actions of every Cuban.23 Recently, Castro allowed Granma, the official state-run Cuban newspaper, to publish President Jimmy Carter’s speech to a Cuban 20. See generaly YVONNE M. CONDE, OPERATION PEDRO PAN: THE UNTOLD EXODUS OF 14,048 CUBAN CHILDREN (1999). 21. Anne Rochell, In the Dawn of Castro’s Cuba, ATLANTA J.-CONST., Feb. 21, 1993, at A1. 22. Francisco Valdes, Diaspora and Deadlock, Miami and Havana: Coming to Terms with Dreams and Dogmas, 55 FLA. L. REV. 283, 288-89 (2003) (footnotes omitted). 23. Cuba’s only newspaper, the government-run Granma, was described by Argentinean editor Jacobo Timerman as “a degradation of the act of reading.” Christopher Hitchens, Havana Can Wait, VANITY FAIR, Mar. 1, 2000, at 101. One Cuban succinctly expressed the dearth of independent news in Cuba by remarking that “if you listen to the radio you don’t need the newspaper.” Id. at 110. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 223 audience during his visit to the island. Despite the public criticism by President Carter of Cuba’s one-party Communist government for denying basic human freedoms to Cubans, Castro nonetheless allowed the unprecedented media coverage.24 This unusual gesture, however, was followed by a sharp reminder of Castro’s ongoing tyranny over Cubans’ lives on the island. In June 2002, Castro called on the National Assembly to amend Cuba’s constitution and pronounce socialism as “untouchable.”25 Not surprisingly, the referendum passed by a unanimous vote.26 During the past four decades, the United States has reinforced the isolationist posture of much of the Cuban exile community by refusing to ease restrictions on commercial, educational, and cultural exchanges between the two countries. In fact, the U.S. embargo has succeeded in effectively depriving Cubans of U.S.-exported basic necessities like soap, medicine, and clothing.27 This harsh measure has fueled an already acrimonious relationship, and has further decreased the likelihood of reconciliation between the two countries. 24. In his speech at the University of Havana, President Jimmy Carter stated that “Cuba has adopted a socialist government where one political party dominates, and people are not permitted to organize any opposition movements. [Your constitution recognizes freedom of speech and association, but] other laws deny these freedoms to those who disagree with the government.” David Gonzalez, In Address to Cuban Nation, Carter Urges Reform, N.Y. TIMES, May 15, 2002, at 1A. 25. Cristobal Herrera, Cuban Lawmakers: Keep Socialism, MIAMI HERALD, June 26, 2002, at 3A. 26. Id. 27. In 1996, Congress passed the Cuban Liberty and Democratic Solidarity Act. Cuban Liberty and Democratic Solidarity (LIBERTAD) Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-114, 110 Stat. 785 (codified as amended in scattered sections of 22 U.S.C.). Commonly referred to as the HelmsBurton Act, the law codified existing federal regulations, and reaffirmed the U.S. embargo against Cuba under the Trading With the Enemy Act of 1917 and the Cuban Democracy Act of 1992. The Helms-Burton Act defines “embargo” as including “all restrictions on trade or transactions with, and travel to or from, Cuba, and all restrictions on transactions in property in which Cuba or nationals of Cuba have an interest.” Id. § 4(7)(A) (emphasis added). In summary, the Act provides as follows: (1) It prohibits loans, credits, or financing by U.S. citizens or residents for transactions involving nationalized property in Cuba; (2) It sets out a program whereby the U.S. will remove the trade embargo and provide economic assistance to Cuba when the President determines that Cuba has a transitional or democratically-elected government; (3) U.S. citizens are allowed to sue in the U.S. federal court system anybody who traffics in U.S. property nationalized by Cuba; Helms-Burton extends this right to persons who were not U.S. citizens at the time of the expropriation; and (4) It blocks entry to the U.S. by foreign citizens involved in trafficking with confiscated property. Id. §§ 103(a), 104(a), 202(a)(1), 302-304. 224 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 My response to the four-decade-old standoff between Castro and the exiles is ya basta.28 Polarization must cede to allow movement towards reconciliation. This, in turn, necessitates desbordamiento, a dis-bordering, or crossing over the ideological and physical restraints on the Cuban communities inside and outside of Cuba. In Miami, the exiles’ public release of deeply-felt, long-held emotions of anger and sorrow in response to Elian’s rescue and subsequent return to Cuba is a harbinger of desbordamiento. Post-Elian, a number of powerful members of the Cuban community have displayed subtle signs of an increasingly conciliatory tone.29 For the island Cubans, desbordamiento is a more difficult process, as Castro’s absolute authority over nearly every aspect of their lives thwarts individual or independent movement towards that end. It is clear, however, that as they struggle for survival amongst barren stores, decrepit buildings, and ubiquitous food lines, island Cubans would benefit in large measure by the dissolution of the borders containing and restraining them. Perhaps, Castro’s demise will provide opportunities for reconciliation. During my trip to Cuba, I experienced ideological contradictions and conflicting emotions. For the first time, I was compelled to examine my entrenched feelings about the island and its people. As a result, I know that I will not find home simply by visiting my family’s former residence. I also know that during the unguarded lunchtime conversations with the jurists, and my subsequent exchange with the angry jurist, we transcended our polarities. In mirroring our similarities and mutual goodwill, those fleeting but unforgettable exchanges brought me closer to finding home. 28. “Enough, already.” 29. The Miami Herald recently reported that “South Florida is witnessing the ascendancy of a new Cuban-American leadership intent on improving the community’s image and nurturing better relations with its non-Cuban neighbors.” Robert L. Steinback, CANF Rift May Open New Doors, MIAMI HERALD, July 29, 2001, at 1B. Joe Garcia, Executive Director of the Cuban American National Foundation, told the newspaper that “[t]he ‘we’re right and everyone else be damned’ attitude was fine during the Cold War, but it [became a problem] when our policy perspectives no longer had the comprehension of the nation.” Id. In fact, CANF’s new thirty-eight-year-old leader, Jorge Mas Santos, wants to elevate the exile community’s profile by adopting a political strategy that is representative of the twenty-first century. Jorge Mas Santos, Two Worlds, Two Cultures, MIAMI HERALD, July 29, 2001, at 1A. BUILDING BRIDGES V—CUBANS WITHOUT BORDERS: MUJERES UNIDAS POR SU HISTORIA1 Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol* I. INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 225 II. A BRIEF HISTORY OF WOMEN IN CUBA . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . A. Mambisas: The First Women’s Movement in Cuban Society . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . B. Early Legal Changes Favoring Women . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1. Property and Family Rights . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2. The Rights to Vote and to Equality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . C. The Castro Revolution and Beyond . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1. Women Join the Fight for Independence . . . . . . . . . . . . 2. Women’s Participation in Education, Labor, and Politics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3. El Periódo Especial . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 231 231 233 233 236 238 239 240 244 III. OTHER RELEVANT EQUALITY LAWS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 245 A. International Laws . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 245 B. United States Laws . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 250 IV. CULTURE INSIDE AND OUT . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 254 A. The Myth of Women’s Equality in Castro’s Cuba . . . . . . . . 258 B. Inequality en el Exilio . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 261 V. CONCLUSION: EQUALITY AND CULTURE . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 267 I. INTRODUCTION Since the Castro revolution, it is impossible not to think of the existence of two Cubas—radically different politically, socially, and economically 1. Author’s translation: “Women united by their history.” * Levin, Mabie & Levin Professor of Law, University of Florida Levin College of Law. Many thanks to Florida Law Review for their help with, and publication of, this Symposium. Mil gracias to Shelbi Day (University of Florida, May 2002), Rebecca DeConcilio (University of Florida, May 2002), and Veronica Díaz (University of Florida, May 2002) for their research assistance on this project. Since the writing of this Essay, I have gone on my first trip to Cuba. I mention this because it effectively changes the representation in this work that I have yet to return to my birth-land. Many of the questions I raise in this Essay, however, remain unanswered. Nonetheless, I can say that during my visit, the purpose of which was to attend the Second Annual Cuba/U.S. Legal Forum, I felt both at home and a stranger. There is, to be sure, a paper to be written about that experience, but that project is in the hopefully not too distant future. 225 226 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 from each other. One is the post-revolutionary society created in the actual physical island, a mere ninety miles from the southernmost tip of the United States. This Cuba—Castro’s Cuba—has existed for the last forty-two years under a socialist, communist regime imposed by the revolution, whose objectives have been to develop a social and an economic rights agenda and reject capitalism, imperialism, and colonialism.2 In this society, much as in other socialist/communist societies, individual freedoms are sacrificed for the good of, and subordinated to, the collective interests. It is the government’s business to provide healthcare, education, welfare, food, and work for its citizens, even if it is at the expense of the personal freedom to choose a field of work or education. The other Cuba is purposely dramatically different. Quintessentially represented by the Miami-Cuban exile community, this Cuba views Castro’s revolution as a travesty that robbed cubanas/os of a beautiful, enchanted island and stalled economic progress to the detriment of the country and its people.3 This Cuba embraces capitalism, democracy, and personal freedoms above all else, and it condemns Castro’s denial of these rights to those on the island. Freedoms of movement, speech, and association, as well as the rights to privacy, to vote, and to travel—all rights denied in Castro’s Cuba—are rights and freedoms to be protected at all costs. Notwithstanding these incontrovertible political, philosophical, and ideological divergences, for years I have interrogated whether the distinctions were, or could be, defining of authentic cubanidad. I often have wondered whether the Cuban people on the island would be really different from those in exile. In other words, I questioned whether the revolution had succeeded in changing the cultura cubana and thus truly created a different Cuban society. After all, save for the Castro period, one is still engaging in a society with shared roots of conquest and dependency, colonialism and independence.4 I suspected that the history and cultural ties, binding cubanas/os across the ninety-mile span of sea, would be stronger than the dividing force of the political regimes under which we live. My initial explorations into the situación cubana focused on the existing political, economic, and governmental system and how it fit into the human rights model.5 As that 2. See generally FIDEL CASTRO & ERNESTO CHE GUEVARA, TO SPEAK THE TRUTH: WHY WASHINGTON’S ‘COLD WAR’ AGAINST CUBA DOESN’T WORK (Mary-Alice Waters ed., 1992). 3. See Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Out in Left Field: Cuba’s Post-Cold War Strikeout, 18 FORDHAM INT’L L.J. 15, 32-35 (1994) (providing an analysis of economic well-being in pre-Castro Cuba; assessing Castro’s impact on “development” through regulation of radio stations, telephones, etc.). 4. If indeed the revolution resulted in different Cuban peoples, the issue of authenticity–of true cubanidad–would then lead to further interrogations as to whether territorial ties could, alone, ascribe authenticity. That is, however, a question for another work. 5. See generally Hernández-Truyol, supra note 3. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 227 intellectual exercise ceded to cultural considerations and a desire to explore similarities between the two Cubas, I started longing to visit the actual physical place that was driving my studies—the place of my birth. My first planned trip to Cuba since my family left in 1960 was in 1999. Because I am a naturalized U.S. citizen, my passport plainly indicates my place of birth as Havana, Cuba. Castro does not recognize naturalizations, making me a Cuban subject in his eyes. Thus, while I had anxiously desired to return to my birth-land for some time, I was not willing to risk falling outside the realm of the protections afforded by my U.S. passport by taking popular, but unauthorized routes through either Canada, Nassau, or Mexico to mi isla. In 1999, the perfect opportunity to visit Cuba arose: I was offered a position as a representative of a nongovernmental organization (NGO), Madre, to attend a human rights conference that was taking place in Havana. Madre’s focus is on helping mothers and children; so the mission of the organization would not be controversial and would not imbue me with any sort of political baggage in the eyes of mi familia en el exilio. I happily submitted my paperwork to Madre for the NGO to procure the requisite U.S. and Cuban visas. Once I completed my part of the paperwork, my emotions started to make their way into my consciousness—emotions that vividly reflected the existence of the two Cubas. How would I feel about visiting my birth country? Would I be considered a real Cuban and warmly welcomed and accepted—an interrogation that in a very personal context raised the issue of the authenticity of one form or another of cubanidad? Or, would I find myself as an “other” in Cuba—a stranger in an unfamiliar, yet at the same time familiar, territory, much the same as (but at the same time different from) the way I am an “other” within the U.S. borderlands because of my cubanidad? Would the accents, music, and food be those to which I was accustomed or would they be foreign and strange? Could I bond with the family I planned to visit even though I barely knew them, or would we live the deep and cavernous divide that separates cubanas/os inside and out of the fronteras that constitute Cuba’s sovereign margins? In order to problematize these complicated geographies, I recruited mami y papi to construct a genealogical tree that would enable me to locate my perch in the family history—a concrete location that might provide a sense of my elusive niche. Mami y papi spent hours pasting together sheet after sheet of paper creating a map of our shared histories. They also spent hours (literally hours as the telecommunications routes with Cuba are less than efficient) calling relatives to arrange for meetings during my stay. They contacted first cousins with whom they were raised and the aunts and uncles who had assisted in raising them to alert la familia about my upcoming visit. All relatives were poised to welcome me with open arms. One of mami’s cousins, Adigio Benitez Gimeno—a well-known artist whose work is 228 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 considered cultural patrimony—was having an art opening on the date of my arrival. He planned to pick me up at the hotel to take me to the event—one that I much anticipated as I would have the unique opportunity to meet the local artists and their friends. One of papi’s cousins—interestingly the part of the family who lives in what used to be our family home in Havana—was equally welcoming, even referring to the place at which they have lived for almost forty years as my house. Feeling more grounded because I had firm plans with la familia, my sense of belonging on both sides of the Cuban borderlands was starting to take hold as a reality. I planned my journey so that I would spend a few days with my parents—in this Cuba—before going to la isla—that Cuba. Visiting home would allow much needed time in this Cuba for me to start getting to know la familia in that Cuba. Mami y papi showed me pictures and shared stories that allowed me to start my travels without leaving familiar territory. Those days were the start of the process of weaving connections that would traverse geographic, economic, and political boundaries; cultural threads that provided unity in distance. Sangre llamando a sangre.6 Only one week before my projected departure date, I received a call alerting me that the paperwork necessary for the issuance of my Cuban visa was incomplete. Specifically, the NGO working on processing my application had failed to state that I was born in Cuba, a reality that triggers different information and reporting requirements than for native-born estado unidenses. Thus, merely days prior to the anticipated starting date for my anxiously awaited journey, I found myself scrambling to secure details concerning a past about which I had no actual knowledge and an unknown future—my history in, and my future plans while visiting that Cuba. Fortunately, mami y papi again jumped in to help. They located documents and compiled required data such as the address of the hospital where I was born, the addresses where I resided when I lived in Cuba, and the names and addresses—including cross-streets—of any relatives or family friends with whom I intended to be in contact during my stay. Sadly, there was not enough time to resolve all the deficiencies in my application. I still visited my folks, learned about la familia, studied the genealogical tree mami y papi had meticulously prepared, and looked at 6. Jeanette Rodriguez, Sangre Llama a Sangre, Cultural Memory as a Source of Theological Insight, in HISPANIC/LATINO THEOLOGY: CHALLENGE AND PROMISE 117-18 (Ada María Isasi-Díaz & Fernando F. Segovia eds., 1996); Guadalupe T. Luna, Gold, Souls, and Wandering Clerics: California Missions, Native Californians, and LatCrit Theory, 33 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 921, 954 (2000) (translating this reference as blood cries out to blood; explaining that the expression “connotes something in the blood that allows one to access the affective, ‘intuitive level’”); see also PAULA GUNN ALLEN, THE SACRED HOOP: RECOVERING THE FEMININE IN AMERICAN INDIAN TRADITIONS 209 (1992) (explaining that to her, this phrase refers to knowing our mothers). To me, this phrase is a combination of Allen’s approach and our LatCritical goals of creating and practicing community and building coalitions. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 229 pictures of those familiares I would have visited. But I never traversed the physical borders to the land of my birth. I failed to savor Adigio’s art; I did not meet any artists. I missed the opportunity to visit the wheelchair-bound, eighty-year-old daughter of an uncle of mom’s who I remember well—he raised chickens and was thus, popular with the kids in the family. He is the very same uncle who was an early victim of the revolution. My desires and careful planning notwithstanding, I would not cross the geographic boundaries of my cubanness; I would not explore the cultural (dis)connections. I was committed to observe the rule of law governing my travel to Cuba and, this time, I was unable to meet its requirements. Being determined to have a visa in hand before I touched Cuban soil, this voyage could not become a reality. Not much more than a year after my failed attempt to go to mi tierra, the social, political, and geographic distance between Castro’s Cuba and the Cuba of Miami’s exiles was boldly underscored. Elian happened. The ninety-mile stretch I never crossed emerged as the light years that separate la isla y el exilio. I have never forgotten the exact date on which my family left Cuba: November 10, 1960. I was Elian’s age. During the Elian controversy, I—sometimes unconsciously, sometimes knowingly—kept placing myself in the little boy’s shoes. What I remembered in 2000 about what I felt in 1960 was that I remembered nothing. Well, nothing other than hugging my doll Alicia, a doll that still sits tall, if a little weathered, at my parents’ home in Miami, sharing space with my high school, college, and law school diplomas; my reprints; my volleyball, basketball, and softball letters; and my picture albums. I also remember going through (what I now realize was) customs with mami, papi, and Ernesto, my three-year-old little brother, and feeling lost. In hindsight, those reluctant memories, albeit limited, are safe because mami y papi were there with us, holding our hands. As a young child, my brother and I did not have to worry about being little kids in a new place with unknown persons—strangers if not strange, speaking an alien tongue, looking different, eating unfamiliar foods. I could not help but invoke those memories as I thought about Elian and his plight. To be sure, cubanas/os on both sides of the ninety-mile divide may hold widely different opinions, as individuals, on the Elian affair.7 Such reality notwithstanding, dramatically divergent group narratives emerged. Those 7. Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, On Becoming the Other: Cubans, Castro, and Elian—A LatCritical Analysis, 78 DENV. U. L. REV. 687 (2002) (discussing the facts of the Elian Gonzalez affair; analyzing the legal principles; engaging in a critical analysis of varying views of several Cuban-American law professors concerning the outcome of the case, specifically noting that the law is used just as effectively by those holding different positions to justify and substantiate their respective positions). 230 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 collective narratives were bounded by geography, and resulted in a new location in which to study the tragedy of the commons.8 The cubanas/os en el exilio adopted a hard-core, anti-Castro master narrative. That storyline insisted that Elian, just like any child, would be better off being raised in a free country that follows the rule of law, a country in which he would pursue his own (American) dreams, free from meddling by the government.9 This script exhorted that civil liberties were more important than economic rights, capitalism superior to communism, and freedom more meaningful than family if that family was in Cuba—arguing that a dead mother’s (and distant uncle’s) apparent wishes were more significant than those of a living, caring, and involved father. The cubanas/os in Cuba, on the other hand, insisted that the rule of law was on their side: a child—particularly a minor child—belongs with his/her parents. They challenged the exiles’ anti-Castro’s fanaticism that would separate father and son, simply based on their political ideology and the U.S.’s imperialistic power. They observed that the boy was healthy and welladjusted, was receiving a good education, and had a good home.10 Plainly, the divergent positions were ideologically, philosophically, and emotionally driven. The debate made me rethink whether there could exist a Cuban society that was culturally cohesive, whether cubanidad was dependent on territorial borders and political ideology, and whether there could be a singular narrative on cubanidad. I suspected that, while social, political, and economic differences might result in some insurmountable divides, cultural tropes might unite us, even if not always through desirable traditions. To test this thesis, as this Essay will set out, I undertook to study the role of cubanas in society. Part I traces the role of women in Cuban society throughout history. It includes a review of the development of Cuban laws concerning women, and women’s role in developing them. This Part also addresses laws pertaining to women that were adopted by the present revolutionary regime. Part II sets out laws, beyond the laws of Cuba, that address the issue of gender/sex equality. It focuses on international norms that protect sex equality pertinent to women in Cuba as well as to Cuban 8. Garrett Hardin, The Tragedy of the Commons, 162 SCIENCE 1243, 1244 (1968) (describing dilemma about use of a common field by individuals each of whom positively benefits from adding one more animal to his stock with the result of an over-grazed field; noting that care for public goods necessitates either public regulation or an understanding of proper levels of use). In the Cuba analogy, Cubanness is at risk because culture, like the field, is being indiscriminately loaded with tropes in an unregulated context in which there is no common ground for cultural conversations. 9. See generally Gonzalez v. Reno, 212 F.3d 1338, 1344-45 (11th Cir. 2000); HernándezTruyol, supra note 7 (presenting the sentiments expressed by those Cuban Americans who felt that Elian should be allowed to stay in the U.S.). 10. Gonzalez, 212 F.3d at 1345. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 231 women outside of Cuba. It also reviews U.S. laws on equality as they affect Cuban women within U.S. borders. Part III turns to look at culture and its function in defining the reality of Cuban women on the island as well as in the U.S. The work concludes that culture trumps law: cultural assumptions about sex roles have persisted in Cuban societies whether within the island or in the Cuban community within the U.S.; further study is likely to reveal additional commonalties with respect to attitudes in matters such as family, race, and sexuality.11 II. A BRIEF HISTORY OF WOMEN IN CUBA This Part will chronicle the role of women in developing Cuban law and society. Significantly, women throughout Cuba’s history have played key roles in the evolution of the island’s society. Although their participation has directly triggered and effected change, they have not always been full beneficiaries—at least in the public manifestations of change. In the early periods as well as today—both inside and outside the island’s fronteras—they seldom hold public office or belong to the elite political, civic, or corporate spheres. A. Mambisas: The First Women’s Movement in Cuban Society Cuban feminism emerged, and throughout history re-emerged, in times of revolution. The first Cuban women to break from the mold established by society, church, and state which dictates that women are to be weak, dependent, and submissive—the first Cuban feminists—were the mambisas, woman warriors.12 The mambisas were in their apogee when Cubans were seeking independence from Spain and challenging the Catholic Church, Spanish laws, patriarchal privilege, slavery, social ordering, and a plantationcentered economy.13 The mambisas, feminist pioneers who were wives and mothers, redefined the borders of womanhood by leaving the safety of their 11. See, e.g., Lillian Manzor-Coats, Performative Identities: Scenes Between Two Cubas, in BRIDGES TO CUBA/PUENTES A CUBA 253, 256 (Ruth Behar ed., 1995) [hereinafter BRIDGES TO CUBA]. See generally Alejandro la Fuente, The Resurgence of Racism in Cuba, NACLA REPORT ON THE AMERICAS, May 1, 2001, at 29; G. Derrick Hodge, Colonization of the Cuban Body: The Growth of Male Sex Work in Havana, NACLA REPORT ON THE AMERICAS, Mar. 1, 2001, at 20. 12. See K. LYNN STONER, FROM THE HOUSE TO THE STREETS: THE CUBAN WOMAN'S MOVEMENT FOR LEGAL REFORM, 1898-1940, at 5-6, 13 (1991). 13. See id. at 5-6. Early Cuban feminists struggled within, rather than against society; rather than being an autonomous movement, Cuban feminism sought to work with men for change. See id. at 13. Pre-revolution feminists tended to be white, upper-middle class women in a society that was based on race and class distinctions. See id. After the revolution, however, feminism became part of the movement, and it was government sponsored and supported. See id. at 6-7. Within the context of the socialist revolution that eradicated both class and race distinctions, feminists became much more representative of Cuban society as a whole. See id. at 5-6. 232 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 hogares to join in the fight for Cuban independence from Spain in two wars.14 First, they took part in the Ten Years War of 1868-1878, and then in the War of 1895, when Martí called the rebel armies to arms and reminded them of their dreams of an independent Cuba.15 Through their participation in war, the mambisas challenged the traditional female spaces of weakness and submissiveness and embraced the male spaces of strength and leadership. Considering their active role in battle as well as their continued domestic duties, the mambisas may well have been the precursors of today’s superwoman: they worked full time both inside and outside the home. Interestingly, even their role in battle was appreciated in the context of their exalted natural role as mothers. Indeed, Mariana Grajales—La Leona, the mother of ten soldiers, including Antonio Maceo, one of Cuba’s best-known, loved, and respected heroes—fought alongside her sons in war and thus, became the archetype and exemplar of motherhood.16 Such an image of the madre patriota became an emblem of Cuban sacrifice and endurance—traits that are demanded of all women by the culture in its marianista outlook.17 Yet, the mambisas were the first women in Cuba to own their own property, once again challenging the whole notion of male authority over family property, and establishing a woman’s right to control her own property without a pre-nuptial agreement.18 The “legal” changes effected by the mambisas constituted a blueprint for the legal changes that would take place in Cuba pursuant to women’s initiatives. Significantly, however, the social changes—or lack thereof—as manifested by the mambisas’ marianismo also foretell the laws’ lack of social impact. B. Early Legal Changes Favoring Women The war of independence ended in 1898 with the defeat of Spain—a Cuban victory that could not have been possible without the revolutionary participation of women.19 Interestingly, these women had to protest the 1901 14. Id. at 13. 15. Id. at 28. 16. ISABEL HOLGADO FERNÁNDEZ, ¡NO ES FÁCIL! MUJERES CUBANAS Y LA CRISIS REVOLUCIONARIA 261 (Icaria Antrazyt 2000). 17. See infra note 209 and accompanying text; see also BONILLA-SANTIAGO, BREAKING GROUND AND BARRIERS: HISPANIC WOMEN DEVELOPING EFFECTIVE LEADERSHIP 11 (1992); P IERRETTE HONDAGNEU-SOTELO, GENDERED TRANSITIONS: MEXICAN EXPERIENCES OF IMMIGRATION 9 (1994) (explaining that “[t]he ideological corollary [to machismo] for women, . . . marianismo (marianism), is modeled on the Catholic Virgin Madonna, and prescribes dependence, subordination, responsibility for all domestic chores, and selfless devotion to family and children”). 18. See STONER, supra note 12, at 22. 19. See id. at 24. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 233 Cuban Constitution because it ignored women’s rights.20 After the war, female independence fighters returned home and fell back into their societally defined roles.21 Although the women warriors were hopeful of social change based on Jose Martí’s pronouncements of social justice, this hope quickly fizzled.22 Martí did not emphasize women’s positions in the new society nor did he prosecute social injustices affecting women; he only recognized their wartime contributions.23 Between 1902 and 1940, women’s organizations—some called feminist and some called feminine, thus underscoring the cultural tensions inherent in women’s rights struggle in Cuba—formed and worked to influence the direction of the legal protections.24 Indeed, as is detailed below, women were central to effecting myriad legal changes for women and their condition. Never, however, did women put aside their focus on morality and the sanctity of motherhood; rather, these were the causes of the movement.25 1. Property and Family Rights The property rights for which the mambisas fought became law in 1917, with the passing of a bill that granted married women the right to administer their dowries and their property.26 Ironically, the passage of this bill depended on the arguments of two male senators who maintained that giving women this small right would prevent a revolution and the dissolution of the family.27 They illustrated the latter point by noting that allowing women the right to control their own property would protect a man’s fortune and prevent it from passing to another family line when a family only had daughters.28 In addition to granting married women control over their dowries and family properties, this 1917 bill also granted women the right to sue and be sued and gave women authority over their children from previous marriages.29 Following this property rights bill, other laws that expanded women’s rights quickly followed. Even before obtaining the right to vote, women received protection from the 1918 divorce law, which separated church and state and lessened the church’s influence over Cuban women.30 This law 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. See id. at 33. See id. See id. at 28-29. See id. at 29. See id. at 25-39. See id. See id. at 45. See id. at 44-45. See id. at 45. See id. Id. at 51-52. 234 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 passed without women’s advocacy or even their expression of the law’s desirability.31 The divorce law was revised in 1930 and again in 1934, resulting in one of the most progressive divorce laws in the world.32 Grounds for divorce were expanded to include separation of spouses for five years or more, corruption of one marriage partner by the other, use of drugs, bigamy, and abandonment of six months.33 In addition, under the law, husbands and wives were charged with equal responsibility for the stability of the family and the support of the children.34 Custody was awarded on the basis of ability to support, rather than gender of the parent.35 Unfortunately, this meant that women who were less financially solvent than men often lost custody of their children.36 The new divorce law also entitled women to either liquidate or assume control of their husband’s estate in the event that the husband could not meet his alimony payments.37 However, alimony was not need-based and, following the marianista notion of women’s purity, it was only awarded to innocent wives.38 In 1928, ten years after the passage of the first divorce law, women were freed from the adultery law—a law that gave men complete authority over their wives and daughters and basically sanctioned violence against women.39 This adultery law, Article 437 of the Spanish penal code, allowed a husband who discovered his wife in the act of adultery, or who encountered his minor daughter with a lover, to kill his wife or daughter and the offending lover, without being tried for homicide; the maximum penalty was exile.40 Indeed, the husband suffered no penalty at all if he only wounded the wife or daughter, or her lover.41 Women’s groups made it a priority to change the adultery law, and turned adultery from a tool of violence against women into grounds for divorce for either party.42 Notwithstanding the legal change effected by the 1928 bill that abolished the adultery law, the societal underpinnings of the law failed to change.43 Interestingly, evidence of the lack of change in mores 31. See id. at 51. 32. See id. at 52 (indicating that issues stemming from earlier laws prompted the involvement of feminists in the 1930 and 1934 processes). 33. See id. at 159. 34. See id. 35. See id. 36. See id. 37. See id. 38. See id. 39. See id. at 148. 40. Id. 41. Id. 42. See id. at 151. 43. See id. at 155. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 235 is found in the circumstances of the enactment of the law, which passed without presidential signature because President Machado did not want to be associated with “the loosening of sexual standards”44 that presumptively would take place if men could not put or keep “their” women in women’s proper place. In 1934, only a few years after the dramatic changes in the adultery law, Cuba’s legislature passed the first national maternity law, which included a grant of twelve weeks leave for maternity (six weeks before and six weeks after giving birth); payment of subsistence pension to mothers while absent from work on maternity leave; and a requirement that all public and private industrial factories that employed more than fifty women maintain a nursery for children under two years of age.45 In 1937, provisions were added to the maternity law, which included giving nursing mothers half an hour in the morning and half an hour in the afternoon to breast-feed the children until they reached one year of age, and made it illegal for employers to fire female employees when they married.46 Although these maternity laws represented a great legal advance for many women, their tragic flaw was that domestic servants, who made up 32% of the population, were excluded from coverage.47 Moreover, while the paper rights existed, in reality, many women failed to receive the services formally guaranteed.48 Significantly, women obtained these broad legal rights without any acknowledgment of, or demand for, women’s equality. Indeed, the Cuban feminists who fought for these rights were far from representative of Cuban society as a whole.49 The Cuban feminists were white, middle to upper class, and educated, about 40% were mothers, 42% were married, 60% had, at some time, been employed, 75% had graduated from a university, 33% had post-graduate degrees, and every single one had at least one servant.50 These women were the product of a Cuban culture that reflected many years of Spanish influence. That traditional culture dictated the proper sphere of women’s participation in society: women were not to work, but were supposed to stay at home and prepare for marriage. Even if a woman did work, it was understood that it was temporary, and once she married, she would give up her job. 44. See id. 45. Id. at 177-78. However, agricultural workers, who made up about 10% of the female labor force, did not have access to the nurseries. Id. at 178. 46. Id. 47. See id. 48. See id. 49. See generally id. ch. 4 (providing a detailed background for, and demographics of, the feminists). 50. Id. at 78. 236 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 However, these cultural aspirations and expectations were different for black, mulata, and poor white women who had no option but to leave home and work.51 So, although only a small number of women were employed during the early years of Cuban independence, approximately three-quarters of the employed women were black and most were engaged as domestics—some of whom were serving the feminists as laundresses—and tobacco plantation workers.52 These women, in contrast to the educated feminists, faced poverty, ill health, sexual exploitation, and disrespect for their race and/or class.53 They were shamed and considered inferior, and they were expected to be at the sexual service of the men with whom they worked.54 2. The Rights to Vote and to Equality Another one of the main goals of the early feminist movement was to secure the right to vote for women. Although President Ramón Grau San Martín granted women the right to vote in the provisional Constitution of 1934, that right, together with the right to be elected to public office, became a confirmed reality in the Constitution of 1940, one of the most progressive constitutions in the world as far as rights for women were concerned.55 Like the right to own property, however, neither the constitutional right to vote nor the express constitutional provisions regarding gender equality translated into any recognition or acknowledgment of women’s equality, nor did they effect gender equality in Cuban society. Grau San Martín’s 1934 Decree-Law 589 was the precursor to some of the 1940 Constitution’s equality provisions.56 This law mandated that salary should correspond to the nature of the work, not the sex of the worker, and assured women equal access to work, except for protective legislation preventing them from working in dangerous environments—which effectively restricted women from some 400 job categories.57 In addition, Article 8 of the Decree-Law 589 sought to protect domestic servants by requiring them to register their employers’ names and their salaries with the Secretary of Labor so that officials could detect underpayment and domestics would have access to national insurance.58 51. See id. at 3. 52. See MARGARET E. LEAHY, DEVELOPMENT STRATEGIES AND THE STATUS OF WOMEN: A COMPARATIVE STUDY OF THE UNITED STATES, MEXICO, THE SOVIET UNION, AND CUBA 93 (1986). 53. See STONER, supra note 12, at 3, 85-86. 54. See id. 55. See id. at 124-25, 181-82. 56. See id. at 124-26, 179-83. 57. See id. at 179-80. 58. Id. at 179. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 237 Notwithstanding the reality of the inequality of women, the 1940 Constitution had several noteworthy provisions regarding technical legal rights to equality. For example, Article 23 provided that “[a]ll Cubans are equal before the law. The state does not recognize special privileges or status. It is illegal and punishable by law to discriminate based on sex, race, color, class, and any other prejudice against human dignity.”59 In addition, Article 62 provided equal pay for equal work, regardless of sex, race, or nationality; Article 68 made it illegal to distinguish between married and single women in the workplace; and Article 66 mandated an eight-hour workday while restricting night work for women.60 Once these extensive gender-based legal rights were realized, the feminist movement in Cuba basically died.61 Unfortunately, although Cuba’s Constitution was one of the most progressive in the world, especially with respect to its treatment of women, these praiseworthy paper rights did not result in real changes in women’s lives. Rather, the legal advances in the Constitution did not alleviate the profound economic and political subordination of women. In 1953, while Cuba ranked third highest in Latin America for its literacy rate, with 78.8% of the female population literate,62 women fared worse than men. In higher education, only 1.6% of women had received some secondary education, as compared to 2.4% of men, and only 0.8% of women received some university education, compared to 1.6% of men.63 Similarly, women did not fare well in employment. Women comprised only 17% of the work force, and those working women were concentrated in the “pink ghetto.”64 While one-third of the labor force was unemployed or partially employed between 1956 and 1958,65 women had less opportunity than men, with an economy allowing few options for support other than marriage, and a culture that, despite broad legal pronouncements on women’s equality, reinforced the view of a woman’s place being in the 59. CONSTITUCIÓN DE LA REPÚBLICA DE CUBA art. 20 (1940), in CONSTITUCIONES CUBANAS: DESDE 1812 HASTA NUESTROS DIAS 246 (1974). 60. See id. at 255, 256, 257; see also STONER, supra note 12, at 181 (citing Cuban Constitutional provisions). 61. See STONER, supra note 12, at 181-83. 62. See Susan Kaufman Purcell, Modernizing Women for a Modern Society: The Cuban Case, in FEMALE AND MALE IN LATIN AMERICA 257, 260 (Ann Pescatello ed., 1973). 63. See id. at 261. 64. WOMEN: CHALLENGES TO THE YEAR 2000, at 45 (United Nations Report 1991). The United Nations has reported that “[w]hereas under socialist systems women are relatively less confined to low level, pink ghetto jobs, they are still predominant in occupations that are poorly paid and do not require educational or technical qualifications.” Id.; see also Purcell, supra note 62, at 261. 65. WORKING WOMEN IN SOCIALIST COUNTRIES: THE FERTILITY CONNECTION 201 (Valentina Bodrova & Richard Anker eds., 1985). 238 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 home.66 Even when women entered the work force, they did so in fields which were deemed “appropriate” and “acceptable” for women.67 Traditionally, these “pink collar” jobs were low-paying and low-status. For example, before the revolution, between one-quarter and one-third of Cuban women worked as domestics, and over 60% of female professionals were school teachers in the lower grades while a majority of the teachers at the secondary level and above were men.68 Finally, women may have had a constitutionally dictated equal right to hold public office, but women rarely ran for such office and few who ran were elected.69 Thus, although women apparently had very strong paper legal rights, these were merely aspirational, as the social, everyday reality did not comport to the technical rules. C. The Castro Revolution and Beyond In 1952, after Batista’s overthrow of the government, the feminists dispersed to various political groups to fight against the dictator.70 Fidel urged women’s groups to consolidate and form a united women’s front—which they did, and in so doing, played a fundamental role in the positioning of the revolution.71 They raised funds, acted as teachers, recruited and created sympathy for the guerilla movement, took care of the wounded, transported arms and documents, and organized revolutionary groups.72 Once the guerilla armies were established on the Sierra de Escambray, the women continued their support; they transported weapons and messages, made uniforms, placed bombs, gathered medicines, visited the guerillas in jail, and took care of the wounded.73 Castro’s revolution was founded on the concept of egalitarianism. In fact, in his first address to the nation, Castro noted the need to end discrimination against women’s participation in the labor force. Shortly thereafter, the Labor Ministry started to enforce labor legislation regarding women more strictly and to pass new regulations addressing the right of pregnant women to their jobs. Similarly, in Castro’s September 26, 1960 address to the United Nations General Assembly, he clearly stated that one of the aims of the revolution was to eradicate inequality and discrimination specifically against 66. See LEAHY, supra note 52, at 93. 67. See Purcell, supra note 62, at 261. 68. See LEAHY, supra note 52, at 92-93. 69. See id. at 92. 70. FERNÁNDEZ, supra note 16, at 265. 71. Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Women in Contemporary Cuba, in WOMEN IN THE THIRD WORLD: AN ENCYCLOPEDIA OF CONTEMPORARY ISSUES 618, 620-23 (Nelly P. Stromquist & Karen Monkman eds., 1998). 72. Id. at 621. 73. See, e.g., FERNÁNDEZ, supra note 16, at 266-67. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 239 blacks, Indians, and women.74 Castro designated this move toward equality for women as “a revolution within [a] Revolution.”75 The 1976 Constitution encoded this right to equality into law, with Chapter Five expressly providing that “all citizens [enjoy] equal rights and are subject to equal duties.”76 1. Women Join the Fight for Independence Just as they had done in the war to free Cuba from Spanish domination, in the revolution of 1959, women fought alongside men.77 Women were involved in every aspect of the revolution, including producing rebel uniforms, participating actively in sabotage units, transporting arms, and hiding in the mountains.78 In fact, by 1958 about one-twentieth of the rebel army’s 3,000 soldiers were women.79 Although some men opposed female platoons, Castro fully supported them, noting that “there are men who ran, M-1 and all, but we don’t have a single example of one of the Mariana Grajales women who ran from combat.”80 In order to institutionalize the women’s place in the revolution, Castro created the Federación de Mujeres Cubanas (Federation of Cuban Women) (FMC) in August 1960.81 Although initial membership was less than 100,000, by 1968, membership had swelled to almost one million women; by 1970, membership numbered 1,343,098, or 54% of the Cuban women over the age of 14.82 As of 1995, close to 3,600,000 or 82.4% of Cuban women were members of the FMC.83 The goals of the FMC have been to “[prepare] women educationally, politically and socially to participate in the Revolution,” as well as to incorporate women into the work force and raise 74. Fidel Castro, The Case of Cuba Is the Case of All Underdeveloped Countries, Address to General Assembly (Sept. 26, 1960), in TO SPEAK THE TRUTH, supra note 2, at 31, 91-92 [hereinafter The Case of Cuba]. 75. See Purcell, supra note 62, at 258. 76. CONSTITUCIÓN DE LA REPÚBLICA DE CUBA (1976), in THE CONSTITUTIONS OF THE COMMUNIST WORLD 99, 111 (William B. Simons ed., 1980). Significantly, Chapter 5 provides for equal access to employment, services, military rank, salary for equal work, education (primarily through university), medical assistance, housing, restaurants, transportation, beaches and other public places. Id. at 111-12. 77. See MARGARET RANDALL, WOMEN IN CUBA: TWENTY YEARS LATER 22 (1981). 78. See id. 79. See Diana M. Riveira, Women’s Legal Advances in Cuba, ch.II, 9 (1989) (unpublished Masters Thesis, University of Miami) (on file with author). 80. See id. (emphasis added) (explaining that the Mariana Grajales troops saw action in about twenty important battles, and once the enemy surrendered, they took on peace-time tasks). 81. See Purcell, supra note 62, at 262. 82. See id. at 263. 83. FERNÁNDEZ, supra note 16, at 270. This membership figure breaks down, by occupation, as follows: 42.5% homemakers, 38.9% salaried employees, and 10.5% students. Id. 240 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 their educational consciousness.84 Significantly, the head of the FMC was Vilma Espín, Castro’s sister-in-law and the only woman to serve in the Politburo, albeit for a very short time.85 2. Women’s Participation in Education, Labor, and Politics86 One of Castro’s first revolutionary campaigns was to abolish illiteracy.87 His campaign succeeded in reducing illiteracy from 23.9% to 3.9% of the population, making approximately three-quarters of a million persons, 56% of whom were women, literate.88 Volunteers, among which many were Cuban youths, carried out the literacy campaign.89 The FMC figured prominently in this campaign, mobilizing women for the volunteer work, which resulted in 55% of the volunteers—brigadistas—being young women.90 Another major undertaking of the revolution in which the FMC played a major role was the re-education or re-training of domestic servants and prostitutes, a goal consistent with the revolutionary aim of ending gender, class, and race-based distinctions in society.91 Under specially designed programs run by the FMC, domestics—most of whom were women—were allowed to leave their employment and study full-time or stay at their posts and take courses at night.92 Women as a whole have fared well in formal education.93 In fact, figures show that females are on par with, if not ahead of, males in formal educational attainments. Not only were women well-represented in enrollment, they were also well-represented in most fields, including some fields traditionally viewed as “male”94—by 1975, women comprised 30% of all engineering students and 35% of all agricultural science students.95 Despite such incontrovertible progress, in 1974, at an FMC Congress, Castro recognized that women’s equality was not yet a reality.96 Ironically, a decade later, the government imposed quotas specifically designed to limit 84. See Purcell, supra note 62, at 263 (alteration in original). 85. See id. at 262. 86. This Part draws largely from one of my previous pieces, Women in Contemporary Cuba, supra note 71. 87. See RANDALL, supra note 77, at 54. 88. See id. at 55; see also Purcell, supra note 62, at 264. 89. See RANDALL, supra note 77, at 55. 90. See Riveira, supra note 79, ch.II, 13, 18; see also Purcell, supra note 62, at 264. 91. See Riveira, supra note 79, ch.II, 22-25; see also Purcell, supra note 62, at 264. 92. See Purcell, supra note 62, at 264. 93. See FERNÁNDEZ, supra note 16, at 83, 86. 94. Id. at 86; see also LEAHY, supra note 52; Hernández-Truyol, supra note 71, at 621. 95. Hernández-Truyol, supra note 71, at 622. 96. Id. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 241 the number of women allowed to attend medical school.97 The government’s twofold explanation for the quota was seemingly based on the critical role played by civilian medical assistance in Cuba’s foreign policy.98 Incidentally, both of the government’s proffered rationales “revealed the status of women as one of inequality.”99 Most interestingly, the rationales were based upon and ceded to traditionalist gender stereotypes—a proposition wholly inapposite to the equality rhetoric of the regime and the legally mandated equality norms. The government’s first explanation was that the substantial responsibilities that women had to their families would make it difficult for necessary extended overseas travel to render medical assistance.100 Secondly, the government rationalized that because many of the countries which needed assistance had not yet recognized (as Cuba purportedly had) the changing role of women in society, male doctors were necessary to render such assistance.101 Certainly, through the medical school quota, the government effectively denied women the right to decide for themselves whether to travel and put up with sexist attitudes. Thus, Castro’s supposed notion of equality—the heart of his revolution—“ceded to the governmental policy to deliver aid.”102 Significantly, the FMC, despite its agenda to promote and ensure gender equality, failed to challenge this discriminatory policy.103 Notwithstanding such contradictions, progress for women is evident in the employment figures—another area in which the FMC has made great efforts to achieve equality for women. In fact, the changes in employment figures regarding women in the labor force is telling. In 1964, only 282,000 women were gainfully employed; by 1970, the number of women in the labor force had reached 600,000.104 By the end of the 1970s, nearly 31% of the work force was female.105 In 1990, women comprised 32% of the labor force, about average for all developing countries but below the 42% figure for industrial states.106 Aside from increasing their numbers, women also have broadened their role in the labor force. While women now hold many jobs that exclusively 97. 98. 99. 100. 101. 102. 103. 104. 105. 106. Id. Id. Id. Id. Id. Id. Id. See Purcell, supra note 62, at 266. See LEAHY, supra note 52, at 104. See Human Development Report 1993, UNITED NATIONS HUMAN DEVELOPMENT PROGRAMME 150-51, 195, 214 (1993) [hereinafter UNHDR 1993]. This figure is not consistently reported. Riveira, in her work, noted that as of 1985, women comprised 48% of the work force. Riveira, supra note 79, ch.II, 42. 242 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 had been held by men—women work as cane cutters, citrus fruit packers, auto mechanics, dentists, doctors, engineers, and traffic police—female participation in the labor force still mostly follows traditional patterns.107 For example, the most common occupational group for women is in the classification of “other intellectual activities,” a classification that includes clerical and secretarial jobs.108 Notwithstanding their concentration in traditionally female jobs, women also make up the majority in some “nontraditional female” fields such as medicine109 and, increasingly, in law.110 One last indicia of the lasting difference between men and women in the labor force is noteworthy: retirement age is fifty-five for women but sixty for men,111 which reflects the cultural expectation that men are presumed to be the “breadwinners” and to provide for their families. Thus, in Cuba today, as in other cultures, women are considered a supply of labor when there are shortages.112 When the state, however, found it necessary to tinker with employment figures because of the economic climate, it did not hesitate to take measures to discourage female employment, including the very unequal step of classifying some jobs as male only.113 In fact, there are still some job categories from which women are excluded, although the list now only includes approximately 25 jobs, whereas in the 1970s it included about 300 jobs.114 These government regulations themselves limit women’s access to certain jobs—a patently discriminatory policy—although the government has facially explained the restrictions as aimed at protecting women’s health.115 Moreover, the over- 107. See Sergio Diaz-Briquets, The Cuban Labor Force in 1981 and Beyond, in THE CUBAN ECONOMY: DEPENDENCY AND DEVELOPMENT 99, 107 (Antonio Jorge & Jaime Suchlicki eds., 1989). 108. Id. 109. See Sarah M. Santana, Whither Cuban Medicine? Challenges for the Next Generation, in TRANSFORMATION AND STRUGGLE: CUBA FACES THE 1990S 251, 253 (Sandor Halesbsky & John M. Kirk eds., 1990) [hereinafter TRANSFORMATION AND STRUGGLE]. 110. See Debra Evenson, The Changing Role of Law in Revolutionary Cuba, in TRANSFORMATION AND STRUGGLE, supra note 109, at 53, 63. 111. FERNÁNDEZ, supra note 16, at 85 n.3. 112. For example, during WWII, advertising executives created the character “Rosie the Riveter” to encourage women to work during the war. See David Rohde, From Film Auteur to Advertising Man, in a Campaign for Indonesian Democracy, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 28, 2000, at E3; see also Diaz-Briquets, supra note 107, at 102 (explaining that a good example of this in Cuba was the “agricultural push of the late 1960s . . . [when] [w]omen were . . . called to replace male urban workers that had gone to labor in the fields, and also to directly contribute their input to the sugar harvest”). 113. Diaz-Briquets, supra note 107, at 102-03. 114. FERNÁNDEZ, supra note 16, at 89-90; see also Hernández-Truyol, supra note 71, at 623. See generally Diaz-Briquets, supra note 107, at 102-03 (explaining that in the late 1970s, “several measures were introduced to discourage female employment”). 115. FERNÁNDEZ, supra note 16, at 91-92. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 243 representation of women in “pink collar” jobs reflects the preservation of traditional gender roles, including one that presumes work outside the home is more important for men. To be sure, the FMC has objected to the work restrictions imposed on women as violative of principles of gender equality.116 In its 1990 Congress, the FMC also noted that one of the obstacles to achieving gender equality is women’s double burden of work and home.117 The FMC also recognized the continued discrimination in job promotions, the lack of women receiving promotions to leadership positions, and the significantly lower earnings of women as compared to men, even when women were better educated.118 Women in Cuba also have made some strides in parliamentary representation. In 1999, the percentage of parliamentary seats occupied by women in Cuba was 27.67%, down from 34% in 1991, which was then behind only Norway, Romania, and the Soviet Union. Now, Cuba is behind many more.119 This figure, however, places the number of seats occupied by women in Parliament in Cuba at more than two times the 12.5% figure for the United States in 1999.120 However, women lag far behind in the “more powerful and prestigious occupational levels in revolutionary Cuba.”121 It was not until 1986 that a woman became a full Politburo member, a position from which she was excluded in 1991 when that body again was all male. Although one out of every three workers is a woman, less than one in five directors of state, political, and economic organizations [are] female. This female under-representation in the pinnacles of political and economic power . . . remains puzzling if one is to accept the official rhetoric calling for equality between the sexes.122 3. El Periódo Especial 116. 117. 118. 119. See id. at 94. Id. See id. at 83, 86. See Human Development Report 1999, UNITED NATIONS HUMAN DEVELOPMENT PROGRAMME 142-45 (1999) [hereinafter UNHDR 1999]; UNHDR 1993, supra note 106, at 150-52, see also THE WORLD’S WOMEN 2000: TRENDS AND STATISTICS 172 (United Nations 2000) [hereinafter WORLD’S WOMEN 2000]. 120. UNHDR 1999, supra note 119, at 142-45; see also WORLD’S WOMEN 2000, supra note 119, at 175; Human Development Report 1995, UNITED NATIONS HUMAN DEVELOPMENT PROGRAMME 60-61 (1995) [hereinafter UNHDR 1995] (reporting that in 1994, women held only 10% of the parliamentary seats in the United States and 23% of the parliamentary seats in Cuba). 121. Diaz-Briquets, supra note 107, at 109. 122. Id. Similarly, women are under-represented in industrial groupings, including agriculture and manufacturing—the leading activities for males—as well as construction and transportation. Id. at 109-10. 244 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 The burdens that formal government policies and cultural traditions place on women were exacerbated in Cuba with el periodo especial, in which the shortages of resources fell mostly on women who, therefore, had to run their homes with less. As in past epochs, with necesidad the mujeres got loud, and the women began to dissent—thus eliciting a gendered revolution within the Castro revolutionary regime. This women’s movement resulted in the birth of the Magin, whose objective was to demonstrate that socialist politics are insufficient to modify the relations between the sexes. The goal of this movement was to realize women’s autonomy and equality in the context of socialism. The magineras are women who used to belong to the partido comunista, but when the promise of equality did not become a reality they organized a new group and protested. Women disproportionately suffered because their unchanging primary roles as mothers, wives, and homemakers became more onerous due to the difficulties in finding everyday needs such as food; they also suffered because, although many had college degrees, they were forced to sell trinkets on the streets because it enhanced the possibility of earning dollars.123 This internal revolutionary struggle for women’s equality follows the pattern established by Cuban women throughout history but with a more purely feminist twist. Here, the aim was to fix the revolution’s failing in the arena of sex equality.124 The women involved have paid dearly for their nontraditional acts. The anti-revolutionary reputation of the organization has caused its members many hardships.125 For example, María Angeles Gonzalez Amaro, a journalist, now receives very little pay from overseas for her articles and lost her job in Cuba because of her association with Magin.126 She has been arrested repeatedly and milicianos regularly search her house.127 Her two daughters were kicked out of the university and lost their jobs.128 Interestingly, she wants to stay in Cuba and make women’s dreams of equality a reality.129 One of her favorite sayings is “no hay mal que dure cien años ni cuerpo que lo resista.”130 III. OTHER RELEVANT EQUALITY LAWS 123. See generally id. (explaining the trend throughout Cuba’s economic history of denying women employment). 124. FERNÁNDEZ, supra note 16, at 13. 125. See id. at 282. 126. Id. at 285. 127. Id. 128. Id. at 286. 129. Id. 130. Id. Author’s translation: “there is no evil that lasts for a 100 years nor body that can resist it.” 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 245 As this is a study on whether mujeres cubanas have ties that bind them beyond the island’s territorial boundaries, it is important to explore whether the mujeres cubanas that left Cuba are bound by the same, or at least similar, rules of law as the women in Castro’s Cuba. There are two sets of rules that will be discussed below. The first is the set of international human rights norms that mandate sex equality. These norms are equally applicable to all Cuban women—both inside and outside the island. The second is the sexequality norms that evolved in the United States as these govern the rights of Cuban women en el exilio. A. International Laws International human rights are those rights vital to individuals’ existence—they are fundamental, inviolable, interdependent, indivisible, and inalienable rights, and predicates to life as human beings.131 Human rights are moral, social, religious, legal, and political rights that concern respect and dignity associated with personhood, with a human being’s identity.132 Human rights’ origins are traced to religion, “natural law, [and] contemporary moral values.”133 The concept of human rights is a relatively recent, modern concept that is universally applicable, at least in principle. World War II marked a turning point in international law with respect to the status of individuals.134 Indeed, international criminal tribunals were established at Nuremberg and Tokyo to punish war participants for criminal atrocities.135 These newly established standards spawned from the overwhelming public desire to avoid the recurrence of such crimes against humanity and the resultant need to protect human rights.136 The individual, however, was “recognized in the global setting prior to the Second World War.”137 It was not until after the signing of the United Nations Charter (U.N. Charter) in 1945138 that international action concentrated on providing 131. See generally Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, To Bear or Not to Bear: Reproductive Freedom as an International Human Right, 17 BROOK. J. INT’L L. 309 (1991); see also REBECCA M.M. WALLACE, INTERNATIONAL LAW: A STUDENT INTRODUCTION 175, 175 (1986) (explaining that “[h]uman rights . . . are regarded as those fundamental and inalienable rights which are essential for life as a human being”). 132. See generally WALLACE, supra note 131; Hernández-Truyol, supra note 131. 133. RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF THE FOREIGN RELATIONS LAW OF THE UNITED STATES § 701 cmt. b (1987). 134. Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Human Rights Through a Gendered Lens: Emergence, Evolution, Revolution, in 1 WOMEN AND INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS LAW 3, 10 (Kelly D. Askin & Dorean M. Koenig eds., 1999). 135. Id. 136. Id. 137. Id. 138. U.N. CHARTER STATUTE OF THE INTERNATIONAL COURT OF JUSTICE, as amended, June 246 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 comprehensive protection for all individuals against various forms of injustice. Such protections now exist regardless of whether the abuse or injustice was committed by a foreign sovereign or the individuals’ own state of nationality and, for the most part, irrespective of the presence of a war.139 The U.N. Charter embraces the natural law notion of these as “rights to which all human beings have been entitled since time immemorial and to which they will continue to be entitled as long as humanity survives.”140 As such, these rights are inalienable—permanent and universal—and are ingrained as one of the purposes of the U.N. Charter to “promot[e] and encourag[e] respect for human rights and for fundamental freedoms for all without distinction as to race, sex, language, or religion.”141 Thus, for the first time in the international realm, the U.N. Charter articulated the formal notion of sex equality as a core human rights tenet by “reaffirm[ing] . . . the equal rights of men and women.”142 Following the U.N. Charter’s lead, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (Universal Declaration),143 the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR),144 and the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights (Economic Covenant),145 all expressly include equality based on “sex.” These documents insist that “[e]veryone is entitled to all the rights and freedoms . . . without distinction of any kind, such as race, colour, sex, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin, property, birth or other status.”146 26, 1945, 59 Stat. 1031, U.N.T.S. 993, available at 1945 WL26967 (entered into force Oct. 24, 1945) [hereinafter U.N. CHARTER]. 139. See MICHAEL AKEHURST, A MODERN INTRODUCTION TO INTERNATIONAL LAW 75-76 (5th ed., 1984). Two other post-World War II events are noteworthy. First, economic development of states has been polarized. Programs of aid that were envisioned without an understanding of the various cultures and problems in various countries failed and led to schisms in theory and practice. More recently, post-Cold War discord and its attendant results of increased nationalism, ethnic strife, civil war, and human rights abuses for which the community of nations was not prepared, have presented a grave challenge to the development of human rights law. 140. Louis B. Sohn, The New International Law: Protection of the Rights of Individuals Rather Than States, 32 AM. U. L. REV. 1, 17 (1982). 141. U.N. CHARTER, supra note 138, art. 1, ¶ 3. 142. Id. Preamble. 143. Universal Declaration of Human Rights, G.A. Res. 217A, U.N. GAOR, 3rd Sess., Supp. No. 127, at art. 2, U.N. Doc. A/810 (1948) [hereinafter Universal Declaration]. 144. International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, G.A. Res. 2200A(XXI), 21 U.N. GAOR, 21st Sess., Supp. No. 16, at 52, U.N. Doc. A/6316 (1966) (entered into force Mar. 23, 1976; ratified by the United States June 8, 1992) [hereinafter ICCPR]. 145. International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights, G.A. Res. 2200A(XXI), 21 U.N. GAOR, 21st Sess., Supp. No. 16, at 49, U.N. Doc. A/6316 (1966) (entered into force Jan. 3, 1976) [hereinafter Economic Covenant]. 146. Universal Declaration, supra note 143, art. 2 (emphasis added). Similarly, the ICCPR provides that 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 247 Moreover, the thematic and regional human rights instruments that have expanded and strengthened human rights foundations also expressly provide for sex and gender equality. The three regional instruments aimed at the protection of human rights, the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (European Convention),147 the American Convention on Human Rights (American Convention),148 and the African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights (African Charter),149 all explicitly incorporate sex equality, as do other international human rights instruments.150 Notwithstanding the international prohibition against sex-based discrimination as confirmed in human rights documents, women are far from attaining equality. As the short history of human rights jurisprudence has shown, the “trickle-down theory of human rights does not serve any population other than [the] relatively privileged males.”151 These distinctions based on status are not surprising if one considers that in the domestic [e]ach State Party to the present Covenant undertakes to respect and to ensure to all individuals within its territory and subject to its jurisdiction the rights recognized in the present Covenant, without distinction of any kind, such as race, colour, sex, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin, property, birth or other status. ICCPR, supra note 144, art. 2, para. 1 (emphasis added). In addition, in art. 26, the ICCPR provides that, with respect to the nondiscrimination provisions, “the law shall prohibit any discrimination and guarantee to all persons equal and effective protection against discrimination on any ground such as . . . sex . . . .” Id. art. 26 (emphasis added). Finally, the Economic Covenant also provides for non-discrimination on the part of the basis of sex. Economic Covenant, supra note 145, art. 2, para. 2. In addition, the Economic Covenant provides that parties will “ensure the equal right of men and women to the enjoyment of all economic, social and cultural rights set forth in the present Covenant.” Id. art. 3. 147. European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, Nov. 4, 1950, 312 U.N.T.S. 221, art. 14 (1950), signed in Rome Nov. 4, 1950 (entered into force Sept. 3, 1953), in INTERNATIONAL LAW: SELECTED DOCUMENTS 2001-2002, at 462 (Barry E. Carter & Phillip R. Trimble eds., 2001) [hereinafter European Convention]. The European Convention was amended by Protocols 3, 5, 8, and 11, which entered into force on Sept. 21, 1970, Dec. 20, 1971, Jan. 1, 1990, and Nov. 1, 1998, respectively. Id. 148. American Convention on Human Rights, Nov. 22, 1969, 1144 U.N.T.S. 123, art. 1 (1970), opened for signature Nov. 22, 1969 (entered into force July 18, 1978), in INTERNATIONAL LAW: SELECTED DOCUMENTS 2001-2002, supra note 147, at 479 [hereinafter American Convention]. 149. African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights, June 27, 1981, 21 I.L.M. 58, art. 2 (1981), adopted by the Organization of African Unity at Nairobi, Kenya, June 27, 1981 (entered into force Oct. 21, 1986), in INTERNATIONAL LAW: SELECTED DOCUMENTS 2001-2002, supra note 147, at 500 [hereinafter African Charter]. 150. See generally supra notes 147-49. 151. Marsha A. Freeman & Arvonne S. Fraser, Women’s Human Rights: Making the Theory a Reality, in HUMAN RIGHTS: AN AGENDA FOR THE NEXT CENTURY 103, 105 (Louis Henkin & John Lawrence Hargrove eds., 1994). 248 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 movements on which the human rights ideal are based all women, regardless of race, were property, and nonwhite men and women could be slaves. Thus, the notion of international human rights that emerged was normative, rather than universal as the U.N. Charter aspired. Sociologist Rhoda Howard made the following observation: The easiest and clearest social distinction to make is between men and women; in many societies, as our own language reflects, the male is the standard of humanness and the female is the deviation. As Simone de Beauvoir put it in her classic feminist meditation, to be female is to be the existential “Other.” . . . The female possessed of knowledge threatens the orderly acquisition and delimitation of society’s cognitive symbols created—in most cultures—by her male status superiors; thus from Eve to medieval wise-women and beyond, Judeo-Christian culture has punished the woman who exercises the human capacity for self-reflection with its attendant threat of making claims upon society.152 Women’s real entry into the human rights discourse occurred in 1975, which was proclaimed International Women’s Year. That year, the first World Conference on Women took place in Mexico City. It was followed by the United Nations Decade for Women (1976-1985),153 and the second World Conference on Women, held in Copenhagen in the middle of the decade (1980). All these events focused on women and their condition with the goal of bettering women’s lives. Progress for women continued with the 1979 U.N. General Assembly’s adoption of the Women’s Convention in 1979, which entered into force in 1981.154 For the first time in the international human rights discourse, an international instrument was devoted exclusively to protecting and enhancing women’s rights. The third World Conference on Women, again seeking to improve women’s condition, took place in Nairobi in 1985.155 152. Rhoda E. Howard, Dignity, Community, and Human Rights, in HUMAN RIGHTS IN CROSSCULTURAL PERSPECTIVES: A QUEST FOR CONSENSUS 81, 88 (Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na’im ed., 1992) (footnotes omitted) (emphasis in original). 153. For a thorough discussion of the impact of the U.N. Decade for Women on women’s international human rights, see HILKKA PIETILA & JEANNE VICKERS, MAKING WOMEN MATTER: THE ROLE OF THE UNITED NATIONS 75-83 (1994) (discussing, in part, the women’s movement of 19721974, which resulted in the Decade for Women). 154. Convention on the Elimination of all Forms of Discrimination Against Women, Dec. 18, 1979, 19 I.L.M. 33 (1980) (entered into force Sept. 3, 1981), in INTERNATIONAL LAW: SELECTED DOCUMENTS 2001-2002, supra note 147, at 432. 155. See generally PIETILA & VICKERS, supra note 153 (providing information on the evolution of the international women’s movement, beginning in the early 1970s). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 249 A series of U.N. conferences held in the 1990s solidified the momentum and force of the international women’s rights movement. Starting with the Rio Conference in 1992 (Earth Summit),156 and continuing with the 1993 World Conference on Human Rights (Vienna Conference),157 the 1994 International Conference on Population and Development (Cairo Conference),158 the 1995 World Summit for Social Development (Social Summit),159 the 1995 United Nations Fourth World Conference on Women (Women’s Conference),160 and the 1996 United Nations Conference on Human Settlements (Habitat II),161 the international community witnessed the firm inclusion and participation of women at the nucleus of the human rights discourse. Together with the Women’s Convention, [t]he consensus documents that comprise this blueprint [for women’s equality and] address issues ranging from the environment to education; from universality of rights to respect for cultural traditions; from population to sustained economic growth and sustainable development; from gender equity and equality to the empowerment of women; from the role of the family to the role of the government; from health to migration; from equity among generations to the placing of people at the center of development; from the recognition that social development is both a national and international concern to the recognition of the need to integrate economic, cultural, and social policies to achieve desired ends; [and] from education to employment to respect for women to the need for affordable housing so that the health, education, and welfare goals of 156. United Nations Conference on Environment and Development, Rio De Janeiro, Brazil, U.N. Doc. E/CN.6/1995/5, Ch. 24 (endorsing Agenda 21, which extensively incorporated activities for strengthening the role of women in sustainable development, including a separate chapter on women). Agenda 21, at chapter 24, is entitled “Global Action For Women Towards Sustainable and Equitable Development.” Id. ¶ 24.11 (providing that all entities in the implementation of Agenda 21, “should ensure that gender considerations are fully integrated into all the policies, programmes and activities”). See also Report of the United Nations Conference on Environment and Development, Agenda 21: Program of Action for Sustainable Development, U.N. GAOR, 46th Sess., Agenda Item 21, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.151/26 (1992) [hereinafter Agenda 21]. 157. Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, June 25, 1993, U.N. Doc. A/CONG.157/23. 158. Report of the International Conference on Population and Development, Oct. 18, 1994, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.171/13. 159. Report of the World Summit for Social Development, Apr. 19, 1995, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.166/9. 160. Beijing Declaration and Platform for Action, Fourth World Conference on Women, Sept. 15, 1995, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.177/20 (1995) & A/CONF.177/20/Add.1. 161. Statement of Principles and Commitments in Global Plan of Action: The Habitat Agenda, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.165/PC.3/4 (1996). 250 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 individuals, of families, of governments, and of the global community can be met.162 Significantly, women have played a critical role in the drafting, acceptance, and implementation of all of these instruments. As was the case with the laws of Cuba, however, women’s international legal rights are dramatically different from women’s lived reality everywhere around the world.163 As the U.N. Report provides, women are still far from attaining equality in any aspect of their lives in any country in the world.164 B. United States Laws The basic right to equality in the United States is found in the Fourteenth Amendment of the U.S. Constitution.165 Significantly, the fact that it is an amendment indicates that the original Constitution did not contemplate a concept of equality. To be sure, this is not surprising, as the framers were representative of the elite and privileged.166 They were married men at a time when women were chattel; they were slaveowners167 as well. As far as sex equality is concerned, the sentiment embodied in the Declaration of Independence was intentionally gendered, with “all men [being] created equal.”168 The Fourteenth Amendment itself, on which sex and gender equality rights are now grounded, was intended to eliminate race, not sex, discrimination. In fact, in the late 1800s, the Supreme Court held that the Fourteenth Amendment did not grant women the right to vote169—a right women did not enjoy until 1920 when the Nineteenth Amendment to the Constitution was passed.170 Obtaining the right to vote did not, however, confer on women all the rights of full citizenship, such as the right to serve in the military, sit on juries, or work at the employment of their choice. 162. 163. 164. 165. 166. Hernández-Truyol, supra note 134, at 5. See id. at 34-35. See id. at 24; UNHDR 1995, supra note 120, at 29. U.S. CONST. amend. XIV. See JOE R. FEAGIN, RACIST AMERICA: ROOTS, CURRENT REALITIES, AND FUTURE REPARATIONS 9 (2000). See generally LAWRENCE M. FRIEDMAN, A HISTORY OF AMERICAN LAW (1985). 167. See FEAGIN, supra note 166, at 9-14, 41 (suggesting that at least half of the signatories to the Declaration of Independence were slave owners and involved in the slave trade); see also Ursula Vogel, Marriage and the Boundaries of Citizenship, in THE CONDITION OF CITIZENSHIP 76, 79 (Bart van Steenbergen ed., 1994). 168. THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para. 2 (U.S. 1776) (emphasis added). 169. Minor v. Happersett, 88 U.S. (21 Wall.) 162, 178 (1874). 170. U.S. CONST. amend. XIX (stating that “[t]he right of citizens of the United States to vote shall not be denied or abridged by the United States or by any State on account of sex”). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 251 Another late 1800s case, while not a constitutional sex equality case, vividly presents the gendered view of women’s proper location in U.S. society.171 In Bradwell v. Illinois,172 the Supreme Court upheld Illinois’s rejection of Myra Bradwell’s application to practice law.173 In her first attempt, she was denied because, “as a married woman [she] would be bound neither by her express contracts nor by those implied contracts which it is the policy of the law to create between attorney and client.”174 When she challenged that conclusion, the state court said that women were ineligible to practice law.175 In her appeal to the federal system, she claimed that her “privileges or immunities” as a United States citizen were being abridged by the prohibition.176 The Court, holding that the right to practice law was not a protected right under the federal system, but rather a right to be regulated by the states,177 concluded that there was no violation of the Fourteenth Amendment.178 Most revealing is the Court’s honest, albeit disturbing, attribution of the proper sphere for women. The Court quoted at length from the state court: That God designed the sexes to occupy different spheres of action, and that it belonged to men to make, apply and execute the laws, was regarded as an . . . axiomatic truth. In view of these facts, we are certainly warranted in saying that when the legislature gave to this court the power of granting licenses to practice law, it was with not the slightest expectation that this privilege would be extended [equally to men and] women.179 The Supreme Court’s opinion itself then embraces the separate spheres ideology: [T]he civil law, as well as nature herself, has always recognized a wide difference in the respective spheres and destinies of man and woman. Man is, or should be, woman’s protector and defender. The natural and proper timidity and delicacy which belongs to the female sex evidently unfits it for many of the occupations of civil life. The constitution of the family organization, which is founded in the divine ordinance, as well as in the nature of things, indicates the domestic sphere as that 171. 172. 173. 174. 175. 176. 177. 178. 179. See generally Bradwell v. Illinois, 83 U.S. (16 Wall.) 130 (1872). 83 U.S. (16 Wall.) 130 (1872). Id. at 138-39. In re Bradwell, 55 Ill. 535, 535-36 (Ill. 1876). Id. at 539. Bradwell, 83 U.S. at 138. Id. at 138-39. Id. at 139. Id. at 132-33 (quotation marks omitted). 252 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 which properly belongs to the domain and functions of womanhood. The harmony, not to say identity, of interest and views which belong, or should belong, to the family institution is repugnant to the idea of a woman adopting a distinct and independent career from that of her husband. So firmly fixed was this sentiment in the founders of the common law that it became a maxim of that system of jurisprudence that a woman had no legal existence separate from her husband, who was regarded as her head and representative in the social state . . . a married woman is incapable, without her husband’s consent, of making contracts which shall be binding on her or him.180 It was not until 1971 that the Fourteenth Amendment was interpreted to prohibit state laws that created different rights for men and women.181 Since then, the Fourteenth Amendment has served to extend sex equality rights. However, these are not necessarily rights of full equality in all cases. For example, the level of scrutiny required for an analysis of sex equality, while not the lowest level of “rational basis,”182 also is not the highest level of strict scrutiny as it is in cases of race discrimination.183 Rather, some middle ground has evolved so that an “intermediate” scrutiny level has been created for these sex-based classifications.184 Actually, in Frontiero v. Richardson,185 four Justices proposed that the strict scrutiny standard would be the proper level of review for sex discrimination cases.186 However, such a suggestion, to date, has not been adopted. Moreover, there are cases where it becomes patent that women are still seen as belonging in a separate sphere. In Rostker v. Goldberg,187 men 180. Id. at 141 (Bradley, J., concurring). 181. Reed v. Reed, 404 U.S. 71, 76 (1971). 182. Bd. of Trs. of the Univ. of Ala. v. Garrett, 531 U.S. 356, 366-67 (2001) (articulating the rational basis review standard as State activity that serves a rational purpose to further a legitimate government interest); see also Richard B. Saphire, Equal Protection, Rational Basis Review, and the Impact of Cleburne Living Center, Inc., 88 KY. L.J. 591, 597 (1999-2000) (stating that “[a]rguably, rational basis (or ‘rationality’) review represents the first and oldest strand of modern equal protection analysis”). See, e.g., id. at 597 n.24. 183. See Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214, 216 (1944) (establishing that “all legal restrictions which curtail the civil rights of a single racial group are immediately suspect. That is not to say that all such restrictions are unconstitutional. It is to say that courts must subject them to the most rigid scrutiny.”). 184. See Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190, 197 (1976) (establishing an intermediate level of scrutiny for sex equality, requiring a sex-based classification to “serve important governmental objectives and . . . be substantially related to achievement of those objectives”). 185. 411 U.S. 677 (1973). 186. Id. at 682 (reasoning that sex-based classifications are inherently suspect and should receive strict scrutiny review). 187. 453 U.S. 57 (1981). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 253 challenged the male-only draft based on equal protection principles.188 The Court found that such a male-only category did not constitute sex discrimination, as men and women were not similarly situated.189 The sexes’ different situations were based on the prohibition of women from positions of combat.190 Hence, the male-only registration was said to make sense, as it was a list from which to call persons who were combat-ready (or more accurately, combat-able).191 Similarly, in Geduldig v. Aiello,192 the Court considered whether exclusion of pregnancy and childbirth benefits from an insurance plan constituted sex discrimination as prohibited by the Constitution.193 The Court, finding no equal protection violation and noting that not all disabilities must be covered, concluded that there was no discrimination as the proper categories for comparison were pregnant persons and nonpregnant persons.194 Because the latter category included both men and women, there was no sex discrimination.195 This brief overview of U.S. law shows both that there is no consistency in the treatment of sex under the Constitution, and that women’s separate sphere is still a reality today. Indeed, a recent study confirms such separateness by reporting that attitudes toward working mothers have not changed—notwithstanding the reality that 56% of women with infants and two-thirds of women with preschool children work outside the home.196 Sixty-eight percent of fathers and 69% of mothers agreed with the following statement: “It is much better for the family if the father works outside the home and the mother takes care of the children.”197 Echoes of Bradwell resonate two centuries later. These are the equality laws governing Cuban women living in the United States. As with the laws in Cuba and the international laws on equality, legal and lived realities are vastly different. IV. CULTURE INSIDE AND OUT 188. See id. at 78. 189. Id. 190. Id. at 79. 191. Id. 192. 417 U.S. 484 (1974). 193. Id. at 492. 194. Id. at 497. 195. See id. 196. See Tamar Lewin, Study Finds Little Change in Working Mothers Debate, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 10, 2001, at A26. 197. Id. (quotation marks omitted). 254 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 The concept of Cuban culture is foundational to understanding the paradoxes that emerge in Cuban law and society, both inside and outside the island’s territorial borders—paradoxes underscored by the disjunction that exists between the reality of gender and sex equality and the law’s equality mandate. Other social structures—the family, work, and politics, to name but three—also reflect gendered inequities. Indeed, the subordinating legal and social consequences of gender are manifested daily in Cuban women’s lives—both in this and that Cuba. Octavio Paz, in El Laberinto de la Soledad, presented the popular image of womanhood that prevails in the Latina/o mind.198 This Nobel prizewinning author wrote as follows: Como casi todos los pueblos, los mexicanos consideran a la mujer como un instrumento, ya de los deseos del hombre, ya de los fines que le asignan la ley, la sociedad o la moral. Fines, hay que decirlo, sobre los que nunca se le ha pedido su consentimiento y en cuya realización participa sólo pasivamente, en tanto que “depositaria” de ciertos valores. Prostituta, diosa, gran señora, amante, la mujer transmite o conserva, pero no crea, los valores y energías que le confían la naturaleza o la sociedad. En un mundo hecho a la imagen de los hombres, la mujer es sólo un reflejo de la voluntad y querer masculinos. Pasiva, se convierte en diosa, amada, ser que encarna los elementos estables y antiguos del universo: la tierra, madre y virgen; activa, es siempre función, medio, canal. La feminidad nunca es un fin en sí mismo, como lo es la hombría.199 Beyond the parameters of any discussion with respect to what should be the proper location of women in society generally, or of women en las 198. See OCTAVIO PAZ, EL LABERINTO DE LA SOLEDAD (1997). 199. Id. at 57. Author’s translation: Like almost all other peoples, Mexicans consider woman as an instrument, object of masculine desires, object of the ends assigned to her by morality, society and the law. It must be admitted that she has never been asked to consent to these ends and that she participates in their realization only passively, as a “repository” of certain values. Whether as prostitute, goddess, grande dame or mistress, woman transmits or preserves—but does not create the values and energies entrusted to her by nature or society. In a world made of man’s image, woman is only a reflection of masculine will and desire. When passive, a woman becomes a goddess, a beloved one, a being who embodies the ancient, stable elements of the universe: the earth, motherhood, virginity; when active, she is always a function, a means to an end, a vehicle. Femininity, unlike manhood, is never an end in itself. Id. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 255 sociedades cubanas more specifically—in the context of family, home, work, or the public sector—Paz’s proffered description is not one that even remotely centers on, or even recognizes, the concept of sex equality.200 Rather, women’s role as presented by Paz is one of expectations and stereotypes—expectations and stereotypes that nevertheless constitute reality for women who are cubanas.201 As the quoted passage reveals, the Latina is defined by the Latino in his dominant position in the family, church, and state.202 The Latina did not participate in, or consent to, the definition that determines her identity. She is fabricated and sculpted in the image, desire, and fantasy of the Latino.203 The Latina is a vessel relegated to be the repository of values that she did not create but that she is responsible to preserve and transmit. The cultural expectations and interpretations of Latinas, simply because of their sex, within the cultura Latina tracks the dominant paradigm’s construction of sex. Like all girls, Latinas are socialized to be feminine, to be mothers and wives. Society mandates that their most important aspiration is to get married, have children, and serve their families. Our playthings—muñequitas, juegitos de cocina y de casa204—are to prepare us for our adult life: home-making and child and husband care-taking. The feminist critique of such male-defined, female-role normativity is extensive. Sociologists, philosophers, and legal scholars alike have identified the male as the standard of humanness and the female as less than the standard.205 The cultura Latina, including its predominantly Catholic religious mandates, intrudes to aggravate Latinas’ gender subordination. The Latina identity is developed in the context of the “ideal woman” fabricated in the mold of the Virgin Mary,206 a construct called marianismo that “glorifie[s] 200. See generally id. 201. See generally id. 202. See id.; see also generally Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Borders (En)Gendered: Normativities, Latinas, and a LatCrit Paradigm, 72 N.Y.U. L. REV. 882 (1997). 203. See RUTH BURGOS SASSCER & FRANCISCA HERNÁNDEZ GILES, LA MUJER MARGINADA POR LA HISTORIA: GUIA DE ESTUDIO 83 (1978) (noting that the role of Latinas is traditionally reproductive, domestic, one of homemaking and child raising, and subordinate to men). 204. Author’s translation: dolls, kitchen sets, and homemaker games. 205. See Howard, supra note 152, at 88. See also generally SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR, THE SECOND SEX (1989); SANDRA LIPSITZ BEM, THE LENSES OF GENDER: TRANSFORMING THE DEBATE ON SEXUAL INEQUALITY (1993). See, e.g., CATHARINE A. MACKINNON, FEMINISM UNMODIFIED: DISCOURSES ON LIFE AND LAW (1987). 206. Significantly, 85% of Latinas consider themselves Catholic, and many hold political and social views that are influenced by religious doctrine. See BONILLA-SANTIAGO, supra note 17, at 15. The imagery of the Virgin Mary as the female ideal is firmly rooted in and praised by culture. As one author stated, “Some Chicanas are praised as they emulate the sanctified example set by [the Virgin] Mary. The woman par excellence is mother and wife. She is to love and support her husband and to nurture and teach her children. Thus, may she gain fulfillment as a woman.” Id. at 256 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 [Latinas] as strong, long-suffering women who ha[ve] endured and kept Latino culture and the family intact.”207 [M]arianismo defines the ideal role of woman. And what an ambitious role it is, taking as its model of perfection the Virgin Mary herself. Marianismo is about sacred duty, self-sacrifice, and chastity. About dispensing care and pleasure, not receiving them. About living in the shadows, literally and figuratively, of your men—father, boyfriend, husband, son—your kids, and your family. Aside from bearing children, the marianista has much in common with una monja de convento, a cloistered nun—but the order she enters is marriage, and her groom is not Christ but an all too human male who instantly becomes the single object of her devotion for a lifetime. .... [M]arianismo insists you live in a world which no longer exists and which perpetuates a value system equating perfection with submission. Veneration may be the reward tendered to la mujer buena, but in actuality you end up feeling more like a servant than a subject for adoration. Indeed, the noble sacrifice of self (the ultimate expression of marianismo) is the force which has for generations prevented Hispanic women from even entertaining the notion of personal validation. Yet such female subjugation is not only practiced today, it is—ironically—enforced by women, handed down as written in stone by our mothers, grandmothers, and aunts! We have reduced the mandates of marianismo to a set of iron-clad rules of behavior, ten commandments if you will.208 Culture teaches us to be pulcra (pure) and passive; we are discouraged from activity and aggressiveness. We also are taught early, and severely, the meaning of respeto (respect): we must be deferential to our elders, and to all the men in our lives—fathers, brothers, husbands, uncles, cousins—and ask permission for everything.209 In sum, the Latina is supposed to be a selfsacrificing, virgin mother, a saint, super-human. She is deemed a failure, 11 (quotation marks omitted). 207. Id. (emphasis added); see also HONDAGNEU-SOTELO, supra note 17, at 9. “The ideological corollary [to machismo] for women, . . . marianismo (marianism), is modeled on the Catholic Virgin Madonna, and prescribes dependence, subordination, responsibility for all domestic chores, and selfless devotion to family and children.” Id. (citation omitted). 208. ROSA MARIA GIL & CARMEN INOA VAZQUEZ, THE MARIA PARODOX: HOW LATINAS CAN MERGE OLD WORLD TRADITIONS WITH NEW WORLD SELF-ESTEEM 7-8 (1996). 209. See BURGOS SASSCER & GILES, supra note 203, at 85 (observing that woman’s most important function is to marry and serve her family). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 257 however, if in her humanness she falls short of this super- and supra-human religious ideal. This marianista—the mythical ideal Latina—sharply contrasts with its better known counterpart: machismo, which molds men as “cold, intellectual, rational, profound, strong, authoritarian, independent, and brave.”210 One recent book describes machismo and characterizes it as having a “dark side:” [M]achismo mandates that men have options, and women have duties. It means that a man’s place en el mundo, in the world, and a woman’s place is en la casa, in the home. It means that your brother is praised for being ambitious, while you are discouraged for that same quality. And it means that first your father, then your brothers, then your husband give the orders and you obey them.211 Lest anyone think that these descriptions of social and familial expectations and roles are not realistic today and are from el tiempo de las nanas (from the dark ages), they appear in a book The Maria Paradox,212 written in 1996 by two Latinas—one Cuban and one Dominican, both of whom hold doctorates and practice in the mental health field in New York City.213 Having engaged in this brief exploration of cultural gender tropes it is proper to ask whether this and that Cuba are geographies that still feel as Octavio Paz so colorfully captured. Significantly, it is important to look at each Cuba separately to explore whether the political and legal norms prevalent in each society make a difference with respect to the role of women as ascribed by the guardians of normativity. To be sure, before el exilio, with Cuba in one place, the cultural norms described by Paz were uniformly accepted. With the post-revolutionary separation into two Cubas, and the location of women inside the island within a socialist society and women in exile in a society with non-Latina/o roots, an interrogation of whether the political and legal conceptions of equality have an impact on cultural norms is appropriate. 210. BONILLA-SANTIAGO, supra note 17, at 11-12 (citation omitted) (explaining that “many Latin males are expected to show their manhood by behaving in a strong fashion, by demonstrating sexual powers, and by asserting their authority over women”). The author notes that both gender role descriptives are a socio-cultural phenomena. Id. at 11. 211. GIL & VAZQUEZ, supra note 208, at 6; see also HONDAGNEU-SOTELO, supra note 17, at 9 (“Machismo calls for men to be sexually assertive, independent, and emotionally restrained, to wield absolute authority over their wives and children, and to serve as family breadwinners.” (footnote omitted)). 212. GIL & VAZQUEZ, supra note 208, at 11. 213. See generally id. 258 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 A. The Myth of Women’s Equality in Castro’s Cuba The revolutionary equality notions, mostly encoded in law, were noble and perhaps partly realized insofar as one considers the improvements in health, education, and welfare discussed above. In reality, gender equality remains aspirational. As the disparities in employment and government policies discussed reveal, the reality is that sex equality is a persistent myth. As detailed, the revolutionary messages regarding equality are often inconsistent. Beyond the double standard evident in its employment policies, and contrary to the “rule of law,” the revolution actively reinforced traditional domestic arrangements by paying for honeymoons.214 The revolutionary government encouraged women to join the labor force because it considered housewives “un-integrated” and thought that they would raise children that also would be un-integrated.215 Also, engaging in paid employment was deemed to be a key to women’s emancipation.216 Yet, when family emergencies arise, it is only women’s, not men’s, time at work that becomes dispensable. In short, the revolutionary government’s policies giving women, but not men, time off work to care for family or to stand in food lines, simply and actively reinstated and reinforced gendered roles.217 Moreover, while domestic tasks are seen as unproductive and unpleasant, the state has failed to provide the means to relieve women of their double burden218—working outside of the home all day, and then working at the home and caring for their children and husbands at night. To be sure, the law requires men’s equal participation in housework and child care.219 The reality, as studies have shown, is vastly different. Working women have an average of only two hours and fifty-nine minutes of free time a day.220 Women spend six hours and twenty-nine minutes at their job, and then four hours and four minutes in domestic chores.221 In contrast, men, on the average, spend seven hours and forty-eight minutes working at their jobs, and then only thirty-two minutes on housework.222 The result of the persistence of traditional roles is that cultural tropes trump legal “paper” rights. “[M]en are viewed as inherently unreliable regarding family responsibilities” and women continue to be seen primarily 214. Lois M. Smith & Alfredo Padula, The Cuban Family in the 1980s, in TRANSFORMATION supra note 109, at 175, 177. 215. See id. 216. Id. 217. Id. at 179. 218. See id. at 177. 219. See id. at 177-78. 220. Riveira, supra note 79, ch.II, 34. 221. Id. 222. Id. AND STRUGGLE, 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 259 as mothers, wives, and homemakers.223 Indeed, formal government policies have actually reinforced traditional gender roles and placed primary family care burdens on women.224 For example, during the 1960s and 1970s, the government promulgated three major legal changes designed to lift the double burden of work and home-making on women.225 While the goal was accomplished to a degree, the traditional views behind the perpetuation of the burden on women remained stubbornly unchanged as the laws and policies behind them were based on the assumption that a cubana’s place is in the home.226 One such legal change was the 1975 Family Code, which purported to create a new equality between men and women in marriage.227 It has been interpreted to require an equal division of housework and child rearing,228 a vision that is even incorporated into the marriage ceremony. But these legal entitlements are virtually impossible to enforce, as they rely on women taking their husbands to court, with the result of the child- and house-care obligations remaining firmly planted on women’s shoulders. The second major legal change that has, nonetheless, not effected real change is the 1974 Maternity Law, which gives women an eighteen-week paid maternity leave—six weeks prior to and twelve weeks subsequent to delivery; paid days off for doctors’ visits; an optional nine-month unpaid leave for new mothers; and a six-month unpaid leave for women with children under age sixteen to attend to family matters.229 To be sure, such provisions are beneficial to, and thus, desirable for women and children. As there exists no paternity leave, however, the law serves to entrench women’s location as being in the home.230 In fact, in Cuba, work is an obligation from which women with small children, but not similarly situated men, are exempt.231 A third major legal reform aimed at enabling women’s workforce participation is the child-care facilities called children’s circles. These cooperatives take in children from forty-five days of age (an age that essentially corresponds to the end of the paid maternity leave) until age six, 223. See Smith & Padula, supra note 214, at 178. 224. Id. at 179. 225. See id. at 178-79. 226. See id. at 178. 227. See FAMILY CODE (Cuba), Law No. 1289, Feb. 14, 1975, art. 24, 26 (providing that marriage partners have equal rights and duties and that they both must care for the family); see also id. art. 27 (stating that both spouses must contribute to the needs of the family by sharing household duties and childcare, regardless of whether only one or both partners work outside the home); id. art. 28 (stating that both partners have the right to practice their profession or skill). 228. See, e.g., Smith & Padula, supra note 214, at 179. 229. See id. 230. See id. 231. See id. 260 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 which is the age at which children begin school. A child can stay for the average workday or until Saturday afternoon. The children get three meals a day, snacks, a bath, naps, and learning and play time. There is a sliding scale fee for the circles. Like the Family Code and Maternity Law, these circles may facilitate women’s labor force participation, but the underlying basis of the accommodations is that it is women’s obligation to provide these services.232 In sum, notwithstanding the post-Castro revolutionary philosophy of gender equality, the reality is persistent inequality. This inequality can be traced to the cultural tropes guiding women’s roles in society—being the homemakers, and child- and family-caretakers. The condition of women only worsened during the “special period”—the economically depressed post-Soviet-support era.233 A recent book, ¡No Es Fácil! Mujeres Cubanas y la Crisis Revolucionaria, written by a Spanish anthropologist, Isabel Holgado Fernández, who has spent long periods of time living in Cuba, chronicles much of the life of women in Cuba today.234 She confirms that women bear the brunt of the economically difficult times by doing the double duty of engaging in productive work outside the home and keeping the home and society together.235 This duty is based upon the inability of the revolution to eradicate discriminatory sex roles notwithstanding the gains attained by women. Rather, the socialist regime has enabled the reproduction of cultural patterns that consider women the only ones responsible for the care of the home and children by its ideological privileging of economic issues and dictating, but not enforcing, sex equality.236 Indeed, the revolution did nothing to change the focus on family or the structures of extended families, all the responsibility of women. Women’s labor force participation was not free of persistent sexism237 notwithstanding their increased presence in “male” jobs.238 In fact, even after the revolution, laws prohibited women from holding certain jobs considered dangerous, and hundreds of jobs were listed as exclusively women’s work.239 Castro himself justified the exclusion of women from some productive work assignments by noting that women had other obligations in society, particularly as the 232. See FERNÁNDEZ, supra note 16, at 92-94. 233. See id. at 46 (describing one woman’s experience having to work outside the home and care for the home while her husband just goes to the beach and returns home expecting food on the table). This book consists of not only text but narratives of the experiences of over sixty Cuban women. See generally id. 234. See generally id. 235. See id. at 12, 94. 236. See id. at 13. 237. See id. at 83. 238. See id. at 86. 239. See id. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 261 ones who raise human beings.240 Specialists justified the sex-based limitations for women in the work force because the feminine organism has limitations and women suffer constant changes during menstruation and during maternity.241 Concerning sex equality, Article 43 of the 1976 Constitution paradoxically provides that women have equal rights in the economic, political, social, and familial realms, and that to guarantee these rights, consideration must be given to grant women jobs that are compatible with their physical makeup.242 As these attitudes make patent, machista prejudices and attitudes prevail in socialist Cuba—both at home and at work.243 Women’s roles and appropriate locations in the social structure remain as mothers and wives, caretakers and homemakers, and givers and sacrificers.244 B. Inequality en el Exilio Initially, it is important to note that there is a dearth of information about the condition of Cuban women in exile. We know that Cuban men and women together have higher earnings and levels of education than other Latina/o groups in the United States.245 We also know that Latinas have lower earnings and education than Latinos.246 It is thus not surprising that cubanas earn less and attain lower levels of education than cubanos, although more recent numbers show that women are surpassing men in some areas of education, such as the conferral of masters degrees.247 These results, of course, are predictable if the cultural sex-role mandates are in place as women must devote their primary attention to home and family at the expense of work and individualism. The available data also allows the conclusion that, based on a majority of society’s gender role expectations, the economic and educational shortcomings of Latinas in the United States is, at least in part, due to their 240. See id. at 91. 241. See id. (stating “e[s] necesario limitar la libertad de acceso a algunos trabajos ‘porque el organismo femenino no tiene sus limitantes y la mujer sufre constantes cambios durante la mestruación y la maternindad” (footnote omitted)). 242. See id. at 93. 243. See id. at 95, 123. 244. See id. at 123, 125, 127, 131, 133, 136, 138, 146, 160, 178, 186, 190, 192, 194, 198, 199, 250, 255, 281. 245. Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Building Bridges—Latinas and Latinos at the Crossroads: Realities, Rhetoric and Replacement, 25 COLUM. HUM. RTS. L. REV. 369, 394-95 (1994); see also Uva de Aragón, La Mujer Cubana: Historia e Infrahistoria (El Exilio), in LA MUJER CUBANA: HISTORIA E INFRAHISTORIA 79, 81-83 (2000). 246. Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Las Olvidadas-Gendered in Justice/Gendered Injustice: Latinas, Fronterás and the Law, 1 J. GENDER RACE & JUST. 353, 358-59 (1998). 247. Aragón, supra note 245, at 83, 85. 262 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 sex, based on a majority of society’s gender role expectations.248 Beyond the sex-based discriminations that Latinas experience because of their sex, Latinas further encounter the barriers erected by their multiple otherness249—their race, ethnicity and possibly language, religion, and sexuality.250 A significant factor that distinguishes between cubanas en Cuba and cubanas en el exilio is the migration experience. Consequently, it is appropriate to explore the impact of migration on sex roles. It is well established that migration has an impact on gender roles and sexuality as “the crossing of borders through migration provides the space and ‘permission’ to cross boundaries and transform their sexuality and sex roles.”251 Thus, cubanas emerging from a society burdened by traditional Spanish sex roles might find different options in a modern society. Such changes are often difficult, however, because “[t]he internalization of cultural and familial norms has deep roots in the psychology and identity of all human beings.”252 It is important to note that with migration and the stresses that migration effects, communities often rely on the enforcement of traditional gender roles for continuity of their life experience. Significantly, sexual and gender-role[s] . . . of women serve a larger social function beyond the personal. They are used by enemies and friends alike as proof of the morality—or decay—of social groups or nations. In most societies, women’s sexual behavior and their conformity to traditional gender roles signify the family’s value system.253 People who feel a need to maintain old values in a new setting become the guardians of morality and tradition. 248. See generally Hernández-Truyol, supra note 202, at 911-20. 249. Id. at 892. It should be noted that cubanas in Cuba will be “others” only if racially different and/or if lesbians, while cubanas in the United States will be others simply because of their cubanidad; their color and sexuality as well as their language and religion are additional deviations from the estado unidense normativity. See id. 250. Id. at 892, 914; see also Hernández-Truyol, supra note 246, at 400. While it is beyond the scope of this Essay, it is noteworthy that inequality based on the combined otherness of sex and race persist both inside and outside of Cuba, with these realities being complicated and exacerbated by minority sexuality. See generally FERNÁNDEZ, supra note 16; Manzor-Coats, supra note 11; OLIVA M. ESPÍN, WOMEN CROSSING BOUNDARIES: A PSYCHOLOGY OF IMMIGRATION AND TRANSFORMATIONS OF SEXUALITY (1999). Those explorations, however, are a separate project. 251. ESPÍN, supra note 250, at 5. 252. Id. 253. Id. at 6. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 263 .... Women’s roles become the “bastion” of tradition, and women’s bodies become the site for struggles concerning disorienting cultural differences. . . . While men are allowed and encouraged to develop new identities in the new country, girls and women are expected to continue living as if they were still in the old country. . . . They are often forced to embody cultural continuity amid cultural dislocation.254 Frequently, as has happened with Cubans, the home culture becomes idealized, with its values, characteristics and customs—including strictly defined and ascribed gender roles—being representative of something better that was left behind.255 This phenomenon is humorously captured in a short story, In Cuba I Was a German Shepherd, written by a contemporary cubana en el exilio author.256 The story is told by an older exilado cubano, Máximo, who regularly tells stories to his cohorts as they play dominoes in Little Havana.257 The story really is about Máximo, the storyteller, and the impact of exile on lives as well as about sex roles.258 But as told by Máximo, the story is ostensibly about Juanito the little dog . . . . .... [Juanito] is just off the boat from Cuba. He is walking down Brickell Avenue. And he is trying to steady himself, see, because he still has his sea legs and all the buildings are so tall they are making him dizzy. He doesn’t know what to expect. He’s maybe a little afraid. And he’s thinking about a pretty little dog he knew once and he’s wondering where she is now and he wishes he were back home. .... He’s not a depressive kind of dog, though. . . . He’s very feisty. And when he sees an elegant white poodle striding toward him, he forgets all his worries and exclaims, ‘O Madre 254. Id. at 6-7 (citation omitted); see also ANA MENÉNDEZ, IN CUBA I WAS A GERMAN SHEPHERD 73, 89, 145-46, 201 (2001). 255. ESPÍN, supra note 250, at 23; MENÉNDEZ, supra note 254, at 102. 256. MENÉNDEZ, supra note 254. 257. See generally id. 258. See generally id. 264 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 de Dios, si cocinas como caminas . . .’ [oh mother of god if you cook like you walk. . . .] .... [B]ut the white poodle interrupts and says, ‘I beg your pardon? This is America—kindly speak English.’ So Juanito pauses for a moment to consider and says in his broken English, ‘Mamita, you are one hot doggie, yes? I would like to take you to movies and fancy dinners.’ .... So Juanito says, ‘I would like to marry you, my love, and have gorgeous puppies with you and live in a castle.’ Well, all this time the white poodle has her snout in the air. She looks at Juanito and says, ‘Do you have any idea who you’re talking to? I am a refined breed of considerable class and you are nothing but a short, insignificant mutt.’ Juanito is stunned for a moment, but he rallies for the final shot. He’s a proud dog, you see, and he’s afraid of his pain. ‘Pardon me, your highness,’ Juanito the mangy dog says. ‘Here in America, I may be a short, insignificant mutt, but in Cuba I was a German shepherd.’259 This story reflects the strong pull against loss of cultural identity effected by migration and the desire to keep traditions in its wake.260 As discussed, these are primarily preserved by women who are seen, as Paz’s quote confirms, as the vessels for the transmission of culture.261 An interesting fact concerning cubanas en el exilio is that their rate of participation in the work force is higher than other Latinas and higher than their Angla and African-American women counterparts.262 In part, this labor force participation is made possible because of the traditional family patterns which signify that older family members—typically grandmothers—are present in the household and take over the child care and home-making obligations such as cooking and cleaning.263 Thus, while cubanas in exile have turned to work outside the home, the traditional lifestyle of multiple 259. Id. at 27-28. 260. See generally id. 261. See supra note 199 and accompanying text; see also ESPÍN, supra note 250, at 146, 149 (“Because women are expected to preserve culture and traditions, immigrant women who are mothers are expected to be the carriers of culture for their children in the new country.”). 262. Aragón, supra note 245, at 82. 263. Id. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 265 generations under one roof has enabled the preservation of cultural gender roles. To be sure, cubanas’ increased participation in the labor force defied the norm, dictating that married women should not work outside the home because it constitutes a show of independence which is an affront to male authority.264 Tradition translates women’s dependence and male authority to respect and family honor; to the proper location of men’s and women’s lives: the man labors outside the home to provide for his family and the woman dedicates herself—engages in her labor—to home and family.265 Notwithstanding these cultural mandates, cubanas en el exilio justified their labor outside the home based on the economic exigencies of exile. Thus, acts that would have been outlawed became befitting of, and respectable for, the female sex because they were contextualized within their proper sphere. Employment outside the home was viewed as mothers’ and wives’ fulfillment of their proper obligation to their families.266 This perspective eradicated the conflict generated by the competing cultural requirements; on the one hand defining women’s primary obligations as caring for their families, and on the other hand viewing employment outside the home as disrespectful and impugning family honor. This ability to render coherent competing cultural gendered norms, however, did not translate into shifting expectations inside the home. Much like their counterparts in Castro’s Cuba, the changed conditions with respect to participation in productive labor did not alter the gendered expectations inside the home. When a woman arrived home after a long day’s work, she still was responsible for the duties in her “proper” sphere: preparing dinner, doing laundry, helping schoolchildren with homework, caring for the older members of the extended-family household, and serving cafecito to her husband and his friends “who in the living room would discuss how to topple Castro.”267 There are some indications that the influence of U.S. society has seeped into younger generations. However, las mujeres cubanas en el exilio, much like their counterparts in Castro’s Cuba, remain bound by the marianista canon. Marianismo still today dictates that women in both Cubas take care of all in the home (parents, in-laws, husband, children, dogs, cats, and plants) and transmit cultural values as well as work in the productive labor market.268 The need to engage in productive labor has not translated to equal access in the public sector. Cubanas en el exilio, just as their estado unidense 264. Id. at 85. 265. Id. 266. Id. at 86. 267. Id. at 86. English in quote is author’s translation of: “que discutía en la sala con los amigos cómo tumbar a Castro.” See id. 268. See id. at 87; ESPÍN, supra note 250, at 5-9; PAZ, supra note 198, at 57. 266 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 sisters, are limited by the glass ceiling; few attain high executive posts. Also, while the cubanas en el exilio do carry out their civic duties by participating in charitable works, few are represented on the executive boards of these civic and political organizations, nor are they represented in the circle of powerful elite exile leaders.269 Thus, here, too, the cultural patterns of gendered locations of power are reproduced. Although not much formal information is available, one can find confirmation of the permanence of cultural dictates in works of fiction. Carolina García-Aguilera is a Cuban-born author of five Lupe Solano mysteries.270 Lupe Solano is a Cuban-American private eye who works in Miami.271 Lupe and her family reveal much about the contemporary exile community. Her mom passed away. She has two sisters, one divorced with two children, and the other a very hip nun. The divorced sister lives, with her children, at her father’s home—a luxurious villa in Coco-plum, with a yacht moored in the backyard. The sister who is a nun nominally lives in a convent, but spends most of her time at papi’s where she still has her childhood bedroom. Lupe herself is a rather thoroughly modern working woman with her own apartment, but mostly stays at her papi’s home, using her own place mostly as cover for romantic encounters. The rest of the household is comprised of an elderly couple who were the parents’ live-in domestic help in Cuba and who came to el exilio with them. Notwithstanding their advanced age, the wife cooks and cleans, and the husband gardens and cares for the cars and the yacht. The daughters take care of the father, particularly in his unrelenting quest to topple Castro—the reason for the well-stocked, well-fueled yacht in the backyard—and make sure to maintain a cohesive familia. Plus ca change. . . . Similarly, Cristina García, acclaimed Cuban-born contemporary author,272 weaves the flavor of cubanidad throughout her writings—as do others. The cultural tropes invoked by writers include the problems women confront when in non-traditional occupations;273 the importance of family and the mother figure;274 Cuban men’s machista view of themselves as 269. Aragón, supra note 245, at 88. 270. CAROLINA GARCÍA-AGUILERA, HAVANA HEAT (2000); CAROLINA GARCÍA-AGUILERA, A MIRACLE IN PARADISE (1999); CAROLINA GARCÍA-AGUILERA, BLOODY SECRETS (1998); CAROLINA GARCÍA-AGUILERA, BLOODY SHAME (1997); CAROLINA GARCÍA-AGUILERA, BLOODY WATERS (1996). 271. See generally supra note 270. Interestingly, the author—Lupe’s creator—was a private investigator before she turned to writing full time. 272. CRISTINA GARCÍA, THE AGÜERO SISTERS (1997) [hereinafter SISTERS]; CRISTINA GARCÍA, DREAMING IN CUBAN (1992) [hereinafter DREAMING]. 273. See, e.g., SISTERS, supra note 272, passim. 274. See, e.g., id. at 15, 27; DREAMING, supra note 272, at 176-77. See also, e.g., Ruth Behar & Lucía Suárez, Two Conversations with Nancy Morejón, in BRIDGES TO CUBA, supra note 11, at 129, 133-34. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 267 alluring and irresistible to women (no matter how unattractive in reality) and their infidelity;275 persistent machismo, sex roles, and separate spheres ideology;276 and the marianista image of the mujer cubana as “passionate, self-sacrificing, and deserving of every luxury,”277 and at the same time virginal.278 V. CONCLUSION: EQUALITY AND CULTURE As the above sections reveal, both Cubas retain and embrace cultural tropes that render the Cuban world a gendered place. In both instances, the consequences are double standards and double duties for women. These results fly in the face of the “rule of law” regardless of where one looks. In Castro’s Cuba, equality as a constitutional mandate is effectively a doubleedged sword—requiring accommodation for women’s “special needs” and hence, enabling unequal and inequitable treatment. In the United States, the equality laws do not yet view sex as an issue to which strict scrutiny applies, thus allowing gendered views to pass as normative. In the international realm, protections for sex equality and prohibitions against discrimination are often tempered by alluding to the protections of culture, which often is the veil behind which discrimination and inequality lurk. To be sure, the rule of law ought not be used by a majority culture to eviscerate minority cultural norms, but neither should culture be used by a minority culture to eviscerate the rule of law’s application to its vulnerable members. In this regard, and specifically with respect to women, the two Cubas are more alike than they are different. Notwithstanding the laws, women still remain bound by cultural tropes not of their making, but for which they must take responsibility and even pride. This is not to suggest that cultural norms should always be eradicated. Rather, it is to note a location of commonalty between persons in the two Cubas which may allow for exploration of conversations. Notwithstanding the political and economic differences, we are still one in our cubanidad. Cuban women have played key roles in every revolutionary movement and global initiative on the island—including the struggles to obtain independence from Spain, fighting Castro’s revolution challenging its 275. See, e.g., SISTERS, supra note 272, at 15; DREAMING, supra note 272, at 26, 113. 276. See, e.g., SISTERS, supra note 272, at 126, 223, 225; DREAMING, supra note 272, at 42, 112, 113, 129-30, 162. See also, e.g., Iraida H. López, “ . . . And There is Only My Imagination Where Our History Should Be”: An Interview with Cristina García, in BRIDGES TO CUBA, supra note 11, at 102, 112; Patricia Boero, Cubans Inside and Outside: Dialogue Among the Deaf, in BRIDGES TO CUBA, supra note 11, at 189, 190; Elena M. Martínez & René Vázquez Díaz, Contradictions, Pluralism, and Dialogue: An Interview with René Vázquez Díaz, in BRIDGES TO CUBA, supra note 11, at 232, 235-36. 277. See, e.g., SISTERS, supra note 272, at 131. 278. See, e.g., DREAMING, supra note 272, at 168-69. 268 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 gender-inequalitarian policies, and being economic caretakers en el exilio. In the historical process, las mujeres Cubanas have been instrumental to changing the governing laws—ranging from property law, to family law, including marriage, divorce, maternity, and childcare, as well as from laws on enfranchisement to labor laws. Notwithstanding their prominent roles and the legal changes in which their participation resulted, the social reality for women remains largely unchanged. Women’s social roles remain defined and circumscribed by the mandates of marianismo, which insists on women deferring to men and being primarily mothers and homemakers. This model has traveled the borders of the island’s myriad governments, including the narrative of Cubans in exile. Most recently in Cuba, the magineras have repeated the rich Cuban history by rebelling against the maleness of the public revolutionary discourse.279 Within the revolution and after the onset of the special period, women are again taking the lead in the battle for a better Cuba. Women, throughout Cuban history, have stepped outside their marianista designated roles and fought for freedom and equality. At the end of every revolution, however, they have retreated to their traditional roles. In exile, these cultural patterns have been replicated. The struggle for real rather than legal equality is ongoing, difficult, and arduous. We should contemplate finding locations where we can both protect our precious cubanidad while recognizing full citizenship and dignity for the cubanas que siguen unidas por su historia.280 279. Lois M. Smith & Alfredo Padula, The Cuban Family in the 1980s, in TRANSFORMATION note 109, at 175, 181. 280. Author’s translation: Women united by their history. AND STRUGGLE, supra PARADISE LOST, PARADISE FOUND: ORAL HISTORIES AND THE FORMATION OF CUBAN IDENTITIES Myra Mendible* Borderlands are physically present wherever two or more cultures edge each other . . . . Living on borders and in margins, keeping intact one’s shifting and multiple identity and integrity, is like trying to swim in a new element, an “alien” element . . . [n]ot comfortable but home. -Gloria Anzaldua1 For those of us accustomed to navigating the fluid borders dividing our “Cuban” and “American” cultural identities, the condition of being both and neither at the same time is indeed not comfortable but home. We are, in Gustavo Perez Firmat’s catchy phrase, “[b]orn in Cuba . . . made in the U.S.A.”2 We are members of that group referred to as the “one-and-a-half” generation, a designation that, like “Generation X” or “Baby Boomer,” reduces complex social phenomena to an accessible and familiar sound bite. Like all such terms, “one-and-a-half” attempts to classify some aspect of human experience, to name (and thus tame) its many intricate and elusive strands. The phrase captures the “in-between” status of cubanos/as who immigrated to the United States as children or adolescents and have lived, as Firmat calls it, “on the hyphen.”3 As LatCrit scholars, our analyses proceed from the assumption that Latinos are multifaceted and multidimensional; that identity is socially constructed and intertextual; and that all of us are continuously shaped and reshaped by variable influences, experiences, and mediations. Our position as bicultural and bilingual individuals only complicates and highlights the fact that identity is not a snugly tailored, creaseless suit. It is a wardrobe teeming with creative possibilities—a colorful silk scarf, a couple of hats, a sequined gown, an austere wool suit—each expressing an aspect but not the whole of us. We understand that how we see ourselves and how others classify us fluctuates according to context and perspective. I am an exile, a refugee, a naturalized citizen, ethnic, an immigrant, and gusana. As * Associate Professor Contemporary Literature & Cultural Studies, Florida Gulf Coast University. 1. GLORIA ANZALDUA, PREFACE TO BORDERLANDS/LA FRONTERA: THE NEW MESTIZA Preface (1987). 2. GUSTAVO PEREZ FIRMAT, NEXT YEAR IN CUBA: A CUBANO’S COMING OF AGE IN AMERICA 1 (1995). 3. See generally GUSTAVO PEREZ FIRMAT, LIFE ON THE HYPHEN (1994). 269 270 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 Alice Abreu’s “Lessons from LatCrit” reminds us, “[t]o full-fledged, natural born Americans,” we are simply Cubans; to Cubans on the island, we are Americanized Cubans.4 Most of us have learned to cohabit two or more identities at once, to recognize, in Abreu’s words, that “[a]spects of identity don’t just intersect, they co-exist. They affect and inform one another.”5 We are insiders and outsiders, both and neither simultaneously.6 We swim in waters as turbulent and treacherous as the Caribbean Sea itself, but they are our waters and our familiar shores bordering the distance. It is one thing to acknowledge and accept this indeterminacy, however, and another to imagine the possibilities suggested by our panel topic, “Cubans Without Borders.” While the former calls for a celebration of our multiplicity and differences, the latter challenges us to seek a common thread across time and place. Given the intensity of debates surrounding such issues as diálogo (initiating dialogue or negotiation between Cuban government representatives and U.S. Cubans), Elián, and Los Van Van (a Cuba-based band invited to perform in Miami, which resulted in vociferous protests and threats), the challenge to locate and pursue that elusive thread is no less urgent than it was four decades ago. As U.S. Cubans, we are often separated from Cubans on the island by a sea of silence, and from each other by misunderstanding, frustration, hostility, or indifference. I have heard fellow Cubans in the U.S. dissociate themselves from the identity essentialized as “Miami Cubans,” and Cubans in Miami denigrate marielitos.7 Private memories dictate public policy, and as Berta Hernández-Truyol discovered in her conversations with Cuban-American law professors after the Elián crisis, “personal experience is outcome determinative.”8 4. Alice G. Abreu, Inter-Group Solidarity: Mapping the Internal/External Dynamics of Oppression: Lessons from LatCrit: Insiders and Outsiders, All at the Same Time, 53 U. MIAMI L. REV. 787, 800 (1999). 5. Id. at 788. 6. Id. at 788-89. 7. “Marielitos” is an often used derogatory reference to Cubans who emigrated from the Mariel port during the 1980 boatlift. See B.E. Aguirre et al., Marielitos Ten Years Later: The Scarface Legacy, 78(2) SOC. SCI. Q. 487, 487 (1997). The exodus brought approximately 125,000 Cubans to U.S. shores. Id. at 488. Fidel used the vast migration to release prisoners and asylum inmates, forcing boat captains to bring them back to Miami along with their families. See id. at 49192. While later analysis found that only about 1% of these Cubans actually had criminal records, stories circulated locally and recounted in national news reported a Miami overrun by rapists and murderers as a result of Mariel. See id. at 493-94. 8. See Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, On Becoming the Other: Cubans, Castro, and Elián, in which the author examines reactions to the Elián situation among fellow Cuban-American law professors and finds that “the migration experience itself had an indelible impact on the way respondents perceived, analyzed, and related to the Elián saga.” Berta Esperanza HernándezTruyol, On Becoming the Other: Cubans, Castro, and Elián-LatCrit Analysis, 78 DENV. U. L. REV. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 271 This Essay will attempt to negotiate this relationship between personal experience and historical perspective, highlighting the importance of collective memory in articulating and mediating exile politics. It is founded on the belief that history and memory share much the same function in shaping community: both employ imagination and experience to look into the past; both are subject to revision; and both intermix personal and public consciousness. Most importantly, both are indispensable for knowing one’s personal and national identity. My broader aim throughout this discussion is to explore how conflicts between Cubans on and off the island boil down to this critical intersection where personal stories assume historical significance. In imagining a future of Cubans without borders, I locate 1959 as the dividing line, a border where history and memories collide. I argue the need for Cubans on all sides of the divide to extend our historical memories beyond the 1959 border and locate a shared vision that can connect us through time and space. Such a project of recovery and recuperation calls for a critical re-examination of Cuba’s history and a remapping of the political terrain bordered by 1959. LatCrit scholars can guide the way in this collective effort; this Essay is a preliminary step towards reclaiming the complexity and breadth of Cuban history, the voices silenced by dominant discourses or forgotten in exile. Specifically, this Essay aims to erode the simplistic dichotomy of pre- and post-Castro scenarios that frame discussions about Cuba’s present predicament, particularly as it defines Cuba’s struggle to achieve social justice and equality merely in terms of Castro’s so-called “New Society” or in terms authorized by so-called representatives of the Miami exile community. In the Cuban exile community, univocal versions of history often serve as borders that buttress ideology and divide members of the “one-and-ahalf” generation from each other. I raise this issue in relation to my opening comments about the “in-between” generation’s ambivalence and diversity because history, and its offspring—cultural memory, are among the most powerful forces shaping our perspective and marking our boundaries. Here let me distinguish between the concept of history as an authorized, objectified, and fact-based reconstruction of the past, from history as a body of communal and personal memories, transmitted through time and subject to reinterpretation and reconstruction. This secularized conception of history is certainly more fluid and tricky, more tangential, anarchic, and subjective. Yet it is no less powerful in its didactic significance or formative function. Maurice Halbwachs argues that collective memories form the basis of both personal and cultural 687, 715 (2002). In all cases, the individuals’ personal experiences determined how they judged events. 272 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 identity and help to define our membership in a particular group.9 These memories are born in the lived experiences of individuals who then bear witness to events through storytelling.10 Recounted and remembered, events are “kept alive” and granted authenticity (if not accuracy); the past is given shape, accorded value, and preserved.11 Given the primacy of oral histories in the formation of national identity, it is not surprising that competing groups tinker with the past to fashion a positive, self-serving collective identity based on history but creatively embellished by memory. During periods of nation building and transition, empowered groups interpret and ritualize historical events in ways that build solidarity in the present and an agenda for the future. As historian Charles Maier points out, memory “mingles private and public spheres . . . [and] conflates vast historical occurrences with the most interior consciousness.”12 This fusion of public and private history articulates aspects of Cuban exile group identity and contains the seeds for both discord and solidarity. For it is a richly textured and polyvalent voice that speaks to us through these collective memories, a chorus of conflicting and incoherent stories that deny us the comfort of tidy, imperious history. Personal memories, like the shards of a collective history, can reconfigure and revitalize the past in ways that help a community reclaim the present. Through this sharing of memories and telling of stories, we redefine our sense of community and foster our connection through blood and history. What I am suggesting is not new; postcolonial theory and criticism has led the way in this approach by recognizing the importance of cultural memories in national identity and reunification. While “postcolonialism” marks a contested theoretical terrain, its critics and authors nevertheless share a preoccupation with history.13 Postcolonial discourses are engaged in an ongoing dialogue with “official” history; as Helen Tiffin explains, postcolonialism seeks to dismantle and demystify European cultural authority with a view to erecting a systematic alternative to define a denied or outlawed self.14 This decolonizing project consistently involves a strategy of dismembering the colonizer’s history of self-definition and self-critique that reclaims, in Simon During’s words, “an identity uncontaminated by universalist or Eurocentric concepts and images.”15 9. See generally MAURICE HALBWACHS, THE COLLECTIVE MEMORY 50-55 (Francis J. Dilter, Jr. & Viola Yazdi Dilter, trans., 1980). 10. See generally id. at 50-87. 11. See generally id. 12. CHARLES S. MAIER, THE UNMASTERABLE PAST: HISTORY, HOLOCAUST, AND GERMAN NATIONAL IDENTITY149 (1988). 13. See, e.g., Helen Tiffin, Teaching Post-Colonial Literary Theory, in BRIDGING THE GAP: LITERARY THEORY IN THE CLASSROOM 41-54 (J.M.Q. Davies ed., 1994). 14. Id. at 42-45. 15. Simon During, Postmodern or Post-Colonialism Today, in TEXTUAL PRACTICE 1.1 32-47 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 273 Similarly, the condition of exile separates people from their homeland and their history. Like colonized subjects, Cuban exiles and their bicultural sons and daughters carry fragments of a shattered history like baggage. Forty years of migration and separation have eroded and confused our communal memories and colonized our history. We are left with conflicting stories, each account filtered through personal experience and historical perspective. At the same time, we hear dominant voices proclaiming their authority to dictate our memories, to view the entirety of a collective past through narrow and myopic lenses focused on the speaker’s own interests. Often, these interests conflict with our own experiences or distort images of self and community. We cling to a thread of connection even as we feel our grasp slipping with each negative depiction of Cubans or each public incident of intolerance among our own people. Like many of my generation of Cubans raised in the United States, I have regarded my ancestry with mixed feelings, torn between a need to reject the identity conjured by these dominant perspectives and a desire to connect to my heritage without shame. As Margaret Ferguson has remarked, exile is “the metaphorical name for the experience of ambivalence.”16 Vincent Llorens, himself an exile from Spain, once wrote that “a life of exile assumes an essentially unstable alteration of human existence which is paradoxically and tenuously balanced between two opposing points: the present and the future.”17 Critic Michael Ugarte argues that “this ‘tenuous balance’ disguises the very existence of the present as it persists in blending with the past and future. Immediate surroundings have meaning only in terms of a lost geography, a place that is absent.”18 Thus, exile defines the present only in relation to the past; it perceives “the world always in terms of relations: nostalgia, the fictional recreation of better times in relation to a negative reading of the present.”19 This predicament sheds some light on an older generation of Cuban exiles who confound the “in-between” generation with their inability to act upon the present. Many are caught in this labyrinth of history where all paths lead to the past and there is no exit to the present. Any vote cast, any position taken, any alliance formed in the United States seems bound to this obsession with the past. Such a preoccupation with the past makes exiled and displaced peoples (1987). 16. Margaret Ferguson, The Exile’s Defense: Dubellay’s La Deffence et Illustration de la langue francoyse, PMLA 93, 277 (1978). 17. Vincent Llorens, Literatura, Historia, Politica, in MADRID: REVISTA DE OCCIDENTE 9 (1967). 18. Michael Ugarte, Luis Cernuda and the Politics of Exile, 101 MLN 325, 327 (Mar. 1986). 19. Id. 274 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 particularly keen on storytelling. They seem to sense its profound influence, its formative and instructive role in shaping identity and recording cultural memory. Perhaps, as Ugarte remarks, “to be displaced is to be obsessed with memory.”20 Communal stories of exile are often preserved and disseminated through autobiographies, testimonials, or historical fictions. They produce a body of literary texts that expresses its own poetic, its own language, conceits, and motivations.21 Ugarte’s analysis suggests that regardless of the specific context, an exile’s voice records the experiences of loss, absence, separation, and fragmentation that seem to characterize the migratory experience.22 Most significantly, exile gives rise to a polemic that “brings into play a series of ideological and historical disputes whose battle ground includes the new home as well as the old.”23 In the context of Cuban politics and discourse, Cuba’s history is often reduced to a dichotomy of simplistic pre- and post-Castro scenarios. On this side of the border, a dominant version of Cuba’s past sounds like an echo of Milton’s “Paradise Lost.”24 On the other side, present day Cuba emerges as “Paradise Found” when compared to selective memories of Batista, neocolonialism, widespread poverty, and racism. Cuban exiles that cling to this singular vision, memorialize the past as the moment of solidarity, and communality; only insiders to this vision may share its glory. Similarly, dominant voices on the island extol the progress represented by Castro’s “New Society,” and proclaim themselves the enlightened ones, the founders of a discourse of equality in Cuba.25 This polemic, which Frank Valdes aptly locates in elitist Miami and elitist Cuba factions, is founded on contrasting versions of the past.26 It rejects the complexity of Cuba’s history in favor of a singular and myopic vision.27 Each side insists on the authenticity of “their” story, refusing the possibility that the story of Cuba’s struggle for social justice and equality extends beyond these narrow boundaries. Each constructs a notion of cubanidad founded on imagined past and present communities. In Alan Singer’s words, “[d]esire dreams the identity of the one with the many, the plenitude of truth, the absence of difference.”28 But as Fredric Jameson 20. Id. 21. Id. at 326. 22. See id. 23. Id. 24. JOHN MILTON, PARADISE LOST (1820). 25. See generally Francisco Valdes, Diaspora and Deadlock, Miami and Havana: Coming to Terms with Dreams and Dogmas, 55 FLA. L. REV. 283 (2003). 26. See generally id. 27. See generally id. 28. Alan Singer, Desire’s Desire: Toward an Historical Formalism, 7 ENCLITIC 57 (1984). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 275 reminds us, “[h]istory is what hurts, it is what refuses desire.”29 An exile community’s historical consciousness is deepened by two kinds of experience: direct participation in the events, or emotional engagement through oral testimonies, memoirs, autobiographies, familial lore, and imagination. Since I left Cuba at the age of five, I possessed few memories borne of my own reality. Instead, I relied on the many stories I remembered and the diverse people I met who shared their private memories of Cuba’s past. These shared memories fostered in me the sense that I belonged to a colorful, sometimes dysfunctional, sometimes extraordinary extended family. As a carryover of our Cuban heritage, cultural memories are fundamental to the ideological formation of CubanAmerican identity. Kept alive in exile through stories, myths, hearsay, and gossip, these memories shape and sustain our collective values, forge a communal and individual sense of self, and transmit a vision of the past that can guide us toward the future. Perhaps my position as the only literature professor among the conference’s many legal scholars leads to this emphasis on the role of storytelling in my identity formation, believing as I do that history is simply another twice-told tale. Yet during LatCrit VI, I was also surprised and delighted by the number of discussants who used personal anecdotes and family history as the springboard for analysis during sessions, and by the ways that all of us on the “Cubans Without Borders” panel crossed borders the day that we exchanged personal narratives and thus claimed our own bit of history. Terry Dehay characterizes this collective remembering as “reclaiming and protecting a past often suppressed by the dominant culture, and in this sense, as re-envisioning, it is essential in the process of gaining control over one’s life.”30 During these intimate exchanges, I felt the extent to which our interpretation and understanding of Cuba’s past—our experience of cubanidad—grew out of the story of exile, its justificatory narratives, accusations, and loss.31 Like others of the “in-between” generation, my knowledge of Cuban history stemmed from secondary, often contradictory sources. It was 29. FREDRIC JAMESON, THE POLITICAL UNCONSCIOUS 102 (1981). 30. Terry Dehay, Narrating Memory, in MEMORY, NARRATIVE, AND IDENTITY 405 (Amriitjit Singh et al. eds. 1994). 31. I am indebted to Jesus Jambrina, the only discussant in the group who had recently migrated to the United States, for expressing his perspective as someone born and raised in Cuba. All of us on the “Cubans Without Borders” panel benefited from Jesus’ reminder that he did not share our sense of divided identity. As he remarked to us in an earlier email, “les confieso incluso que, a veces, me siento saturado de cubania y quisiera, cosa imposible claro esta, liberarme un poco de ella.” [I confess that, at times, I feel saturated by my cubanness and desire, something clearly impossible, to liberate myself from it.] While my emphasis here is on the development of a historical consciousness in exile, I in no way mean to exclude Jesus’ contribution. His insights enriched all of us. 276 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 mediated by my parents and later filtered through an educational system that measured Cuban history only in relation to its own cultural myths and perspectives. On those rare occasions when Cuba was mentioned during my formal schooling, it was as representative of the “Communist Other” to democratic America—as an island nation defined by loss and lack. Cuba’s complex history, filtered through this narrow lens, served to affirm the virtues of capitalism or to admonish young Americans who may be lured by pop culture images of el Che or Fidel. I was keenly reminded of this colonized history by Adrian Wing’s cautionary remark during the LatCrit VI Conference that the U.S. often holds itself up as an example of democracy and justice against its “Other”: Latin America. Understandably, my view of Cuba from that perspective was that it had always been a “banana republic,” its history simply a string of strongmen dictators, racists, and regressive initiatives. In this version, Cuba’s long war for independence from Spain is named the “Spanish-American War,” obscuring the fact that a generation of Cubans, led by a military leadership comprised of forty percent Afro-Cubans, paid for that victory with their own blood.32 This script calls for the United States to play the enlightened democracy to Cuba’s “third world” role. It ignores the U.S. Government’s role in imposing their own segregationist policies on Cuba’s military during its occupation, and neglects to mention the fact that, unlike the United States’ war for independence, Cuba’s war for independence articulated a vision of racial equality and harmony.33 Yet for years I felt destined to carry these remnants of a tattered and dishonored heritage like an albatross around my neck.34 Stuart Hall’s remark that identity is never simple or stable but happens over time and is “subject to the play of history and the play of difference” suggests that identity is an ongoing process of identification and association. In this sense, my cubanidad became as much a political choice as a question of birthplace or native language. But it was a choice implicated by the stories I internalized as my own—personal and cultural narratives founded on family lore, personal experience, and hearsay that complicated my perspective. As is often the case with children of immigrants, these stories usurped the role of recorded history. Because I grew up in Miami, the 32. See BETWEEN RACE AND EMPIRE: AFRICAN-AMERICANS AND CUBANS BEFORE THE CUBAN REVOLUTION 13 (Lisa Brock & Digna Casteñeda Fuertes eds., 1998) 33. See generally Cathy Duke, The Idea of Race: The Cultural Impact of American Intervention in Cuba, 1898-1912, in POLITICS, SOCIETY AND CULTURE IN THE CARIBBEAN: SELECTED P APERS OF THE XIV CONFERENCE OF CARIBBEAN HISTORIANS 87-108 (Blanca G. Silvestrini ed., 1983). 34. In Samuel T. Coleridge’s, Rime of the Ancient Mariner, a sailor is bound to wear a dead albatross around his neck in penitence for sinning against nature. Samuel T. Coleridge, The Rime of the Ancient Mariner, in LYRICAL BALLADS (1978). The sailor, doomed to wander endlessly, repeats his shameful tale to all who will listen. Id. at 38-40. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 277 Mecca of many Cuban exiles, my birthplace remained a living memory. It was alive on the streets of calle ocho in Little Havana, in the language we spoke at home, and in the stories that nurtured my childhood. To me, those tales of home were like a lifeline to my Cuban identity. They provided a personalized history that helped to counter the less forgiving, sometimes hostile images reflected by my public world. To my parents, those stories were the only way they knew to cross the boundaries of time and place, to unite me—their Americanized cubanita—with her heritage and her birthplace. I realize now that my parents’ many stories were meant to safeguard not only our family’s history, but also the history of an entire culture in exile. That storytelling was more than an entertaining pastime—that it was part of an oral tradition linking generations of displaced and fractured communities across time—was a history lesson that I would learn later. My parents fled Cuba in 1959, just two months after Fidel Castro and his Revolutionary Army occupied Havana. Yet year after year of exile had not faded my father’s memory of his homeland, and his stories were rich in detail. Although my father’s gratitude to his adopted land was unquestionable, he never forgot his first love. He yearned for her, idealized and idolized her; she was his Havana. Eyes full of emotion, he referred to her as “the Paris of the Caribbean,” a graceful, exuberant city that never slept. He knew every nook and cranny of her, and she clung to his senses—her vibrant rhythms, pleasant and familiar smells, sultry breezes, and gentle sun. At home and on the street, I heard other stories too—stories fueled by rage and disappointment. In those stories, Havana was “Paradise Lost,” and Cuba a nation violated—her people scattered, oppressed, imprisoned, executed, or lost at sea. She was the Republic whose possibilities had been cut short by comunistas, by traitors, and despots. Later, my university studies offered other versions as well. If conditions in Cuba were so ripe with potential; if the island had sustained a healthy, vibrant economy; if there was little evidence of discontent—then why did the Revolution happen? To my adult mind, my father’s stories seemed unreliable, like memories filtered through the eyes of a lover. I began to question contradictions, inconsistencies, and partial truths. In the summer of 1996, I traveled to Cuba as part of a Delegation of North American Philosophers and Social Scientists. During my seven-day visit, I exchanged ideas with Cuban professors, met my 83-year-old godfather, and sought some answers. I wanted to know if the Havana of my father’s stories still existed. I wondered if it ever had. I hoped that with this visit, I would finally get “the real story.” The Conference was held at the University of Havana, a prestigious university with a long history of revolution. It had been the setting of student protests against the Spanish colonizers at the turn of the century, 278 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 and where Fidel and his followers rallied fellow students to oppose Batista’s government. My days were spent at the University, where students and professors offered stories that differed radically from those I knew. In their version, the Revolution has made remarkable progress in health care and education, and its ideals endure despite constant and powerful opposition from exiled Cubans and the U.S. government. Through their eyes, I envisioned other, less forgiving images of Cuba’s past. Their answers to my questions transformed my father’s Havana into a decadent, impoverished city rife with corruption. Meanwhile, my U.S. colleagues toured Cuba with University guides who escorted them during scheduled visits to “collective farms” and health facilities. Sympathetic to these selected examples of egalitarian incentives, most seemed to accept uncritically the accompanying grand narrative: according to this version of history, the 1959 Revolution marks the onset of a vision towards social justice in Cuba and its discourse holds title to a critique of racism, social inequality, imperialism and patriarchy. Only the memory of Batista seemed to speak to Cuba’s history before 1959. During one of my discussions with a U.S. economics professor, theory and social realities collided when I persisted in my efforts to understand why these gains could not have been achieved without sacrificing human rights. Frustrated by my unwillingness to accept the embargo, U.S. policy, and “Miami Cubans” as definitive justification, he finally responded that Latin American history shows that “we” seem to need a “more heavy-handed” type of leader to achieve our national goals. This remark, coming from someone with whose progressive politics I identified, disappointed and saddened me. On what political framework would I rely to understand Cuba’s history, and in the process, my own? Whose stories would I choose to remember, whose would I reject? In the afternoons and evenings, I encountered other, less official versions of Cuba’s present. I met people who expressed anger and frustration in whispers. I spoke to many Cubans who had lost their jobs and been harassed or imprisoned for their discontent. I heard different answers to my questions. Is it true that the U.S. embargo is to blame for the people’s hardship? That all decisions affecting labor are made only after affected workers approve them? That no other developing nation can boast a higher literacy rate? That Afro-Cubans have achieved social equality and justice? One woman quipped that the only thing keeping Cubans on the island alive is the flow of money and goods from Miami. My cousin, a university-educated “son of the Revolution,” laughed at the notion that workers in Cuba would dare to oppose any policy or objective endorsed by Fidel. So much for consensus. And as for literacy, my learned godfather’s comment tells it own tale: “En Cuba hay mucha instrucción—pero no hay educación.” [“In Cuba, there is much instruction—but no education.”] 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 279 I did not find the answers I sought, and in fact, found more questions. But I did see traces of my father’s beloved city. The once majestic colonial buildings still line the city’s streets, but their walls are crumbling, literally collapsing into piles of rubble. With those crumbling old buildings, a city’s rich history is fading. I saw two-by-four wood planks holding up balconies, layers of peeling paint on walls that revealed years of neglect. The sea was still deep blue, and the night breeze still cooled the city even in the dead of summer. Young couples still strolled through shady plazas, people still gathered at el malecón (the seawall that stretches along central Havana), and the Tropicana nightclub still entertained tourists. But the city had lost its luster, and its nightlife catered to tourists paying in dollars. There were few cars on the road, and weary faces waited in line for a dilapidated, overcrowded bus that may never arrive. After my return, I tried to further complicate my notions of Cuba’s history. I learned that Cuba’s struggle to define both cubanidad and ciudadanía stretches back generations, and the ideals and discourse of the 1959 Revolution were employed throughout the Island’s history (yes, even by Batista and others). I recognized the extent to which Cuba’s complex past had been reduced in my own mind to a clear-cut polarity, its present evaluated and understood only in relation to 1959 as sole historical marker and determinant. I discovered new stories that overturned the notion that Latinos are innately incapable of enlightened self-rule, that the struggle to build a just nation translates into the “American way of life.” Over the years, I had engaged in endless debates with Cuban scholars, friends, family, and colleagues about Cuba in an effort to hear their stories. Invariably, among Cubans on and off the Island, discussions had led back to 1959 as the litmus test for Cuba’s alleged progress or deterioration. It was as if the year of Fidel’s triumph stood as a great wall blocking our view of Cuba’s past and our vision for its future. Following the Elián debacle, I read the stories the national newspapers and television news shows disseminated about Cubans in Miami, where all of us were neatly lumped into one mass of loud-mouthed, narrow-minded fanatics. I heard many of my own closest friends disparage and ridicule “Miami Cubans.” Some participated in the “banana republic” parade held in Coconut Grove by a predominantly “Anglo” population—a parade in which a few Confederate Flags waved proudly beside the U.S. flag. One morning during the Elián protests, I witnessed police officers antagonizing protestors then pushing a male protestor to the ground and handcuffing him. I later saw front-page photos featured across the nation that decontextualized and exaggerated events to such an extent that my best friend’s parents in Kansas City were under the impression that Miami had been overrun by a riotous, violent herd of Cubans. Another friend blandly defended Elián’s armed seizure with the remark, “Well, you know that most Cubans in Miami carry guns.” As anecdotal and media “evidence” 280 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 continued to characterize the Miami Cuban community as heartless zealots intent on destroying their compatriots on the Island, I struggled to reconcile those depictions with my own experiences or with the knowledge that “reliable estimates put Cuban-American remittances [to Cuba] at close to $1 billion per year, far exceeding the sum total of private contributions by charitable organizations to Cuba worldwide.”35 Attending the LatCrit VI Conference marked an important point in my search for perspective. I had never met any of the panel participants until I arrived in Gainesville, though we had exchanged warm and lively emails. Seated among the fellow Cubans who would comprise the “Cubans Without Borders” panel, I discovered the extent to which all my stories converged and formed my self-image. As I sat among the wonderful people who would share their little bit of history and self and thus venture across borders, I felt like both an insider and an outsider to this group. It was not a distance created by discipline (I was a literature professor among a majority of law scholars). The distance I felt stemmed simply from the fact that I was a “Miami Cuban,” a cubanita who had not moved away or dissociated herself from the Miami exile community. It seemed that years of graduate study or personal successes had not erased the negative selfimage projected upon me by that association. I longed to cross the border imposed upon us by those who would control our history, who insist on “representing” our views. I wanted to vindicate my community, to humanize the demonized, to share stories that spoke of individual acts of generosity, courage, or forgiveness. And most of all, I felt an absurd desire to redeem our history, to recall a dream of economic, social, and racial equality that links us across generations. I expressed my discomfort to the group, and we exchanged personal memories, reaching across differences and finding that we shared intellectual, political, and emotional bonds. On that day, we aired our dirty laundry; we looked critically at notions of cubanidad that disappointed, divided, or alienated us. We expressed our rage and our hopes. Our exchange did not produce a coherent narrative of Cuban identity. Nor did it seek to deny the ugly aspects of our collective history or to supplant them with idealized and nostalgic personal musings. I do believe that our familial dialogue served to remind us, again, of the truism, “there are more than two sides to every story.” It may also have achieved some “historical consciousness raising.” Most importantly, it allowed us to see, reflected in our differences, traces of familiarity; it reaffirmed the need to engage relentlessly in a process of self-critique and self-reconstruction, of historical deconstruction and recovery. Such a process will doubtless 35. Alejandro Portés, Morning in Miami: A New Era for Cuban Americans, 9 AM. PROSPECT 28 (1998). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 281 produce more ambivalence, a more tentative and open-ended view of our own Cuban “Others.” But as Cubans struggling to come to terms with our differences and yet longing for connection, we can live with ambiguity. In fact, we can make it home. DIASPORA AND DEADLOCK, MIAMI AND HAVANA: COMING TO TERMS WITH DREAMS AND DOGMAS Francisco Valdes* I. INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 283 A. Division and Corruption: Dueling Elites, the Battle of the Straits . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 287 B. Arrogation and Class Distinctions: The Politics of Tyranny and Money . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 297 C. Global Circus, Domestic Division: Cubans as Sport and Spectacle . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 300 D. Time and Imagination: Toward the Denied . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 305 E. Broken Promises and Bottom Lines: Human Rights, Cuban Rights . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 310 F. Reconciliation and Reconstruction: Five LatCrit Exhortations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 313 II. CONCLUSION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 317 I. INTRODUCTION The low-key arrival of Elian Gonzalez in Miami on Thanksgiving Day 1999,1 and the custody-immigration controversy that then ensued shortly afterward,2 transfixed not only Miami and Havana but also the entire * Professor of Law and Co-Director, Center for Hispanic & Caribbean Legal Studies, University of Miami. I thank the participants in the Faculty Seminar at Quinnipiac School of Law and in the Colloquium at Harvard Law School, where drafts of this Essay were presented. I thank also Carmen Gonzalez, Evelio Rodriguez, Ricardo Camara, Robert Westley, and Lisa Iglesias for feedback that helped to develop the thoughts presented here. Finally, I thank the organizers, participants and attendees of the Sixth Annual LatCrit Conference, and the editors and contributors of this symposium, for providing a fitting venue and community for this rather personal Essay. All errors are mine. 1. The arrival was reported in the local paper as yet another dramatic example of escape from the island, with no inkling of the greater drama to follow. See Lisa Arthur et al., 5-Year-Old Survivor Clung to Inner Tube, Two More Rafters Rescued, But 11 Other Cubans May Have Died at Sea, MIAMI HERALD, Nov. 26, 1999, at 1A; see also Melissa Leavister, Ambiguity Equals Authority: The Immigration and Naturalization Service’s Response in the Elian Gonzalez Case, 31 GOLDEN GATE U.L. REV. 219 (2001). Elian’s case is not an isolated occurrence, although it has been the most chronicled. See, e.g., Marika Lynch & Alfonso Chardy, Mother Indicted for Taking Son to Cuba, MIAMI HERALD, Feb. 24, 2001, at 1B. Elian’s notoriety apparently continues in Cuba, despite Cuba’s criticism of the U.S. media circus surrounding Elian’s story. Elian Featured in Museum of Castro Doctrine, MIAMI HERALD, July 15, 2001, at 5A. 2. This drama concluded with the Supreme Court’s anticlimactic pronouncement, which simply ratified the outcome already determined through public relations campaigns and federal 283 284 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 world,3 thereby bringing into sharp relief the condition of the Cuban nation. As his case mushroomed, that photogenic boy came to personify, and to embody for the entire world, the image of a nation and people—indeed, a family—divided by decades of passionate polarities. That tragic image, unfortunately, does capture a significant portion of Cuban realities, both on the island and throughout the diaspora. Elian’s fate exemplifies one human tragedy of the Twentieth Century on both micro- and macro-levels of human experience and existence. But that image also reifies a grossly simplistic, and increasingly inapt, understanding of Cuba and Cubans—again, both on the island and throughout the diaspora. It is a reification with which I have struggled my entire life—and which Elian’s protracted predicament put squarely in front of me like no other event had ever before. Born in Cuba to middle-class working parents a few years before Fidel and his comrades wrested control of the government from their predecessors, I recall that particular transition of power from the perspective of a child the age of Elian. What I recall most, however, is how my father and mother argued about it: he in support of the Revolution as a means of social justice and she warning against an elegant but deceptive appeal to his and others’ utopian longings. After some scary brushes with the forces of revolution, I found myself on a plane at the age of five with my cousin (aged six), headed first to Miami and eventually to an orphanage in Pueblo, Colorado. I recall still the curiosity and anxiety I felt then about going to a place where, I inferred, everything—people, trees, cars, houses—would be in red. “Pueblo colorado” means, in Spanish, literally, red town. After nearly two years of greenery and snow—only the bricks and the Garden of the Gods were red—my mother, aunt and sister arrived from Cuba. My cousin and I were dispatched to them, in Miami, and then we all lived on a daily basis around the expectation of eventual family reunions and on the clock of erratically periodic telephonic contacts. Over the next several years my uncle and my father arrived, creating a gradual sense of familial reunion and restoration. During all of that time, my mother showered my sister and me with many expressions of maternal care, executive decisions. See generally Gonzalez v. Reno, 530 U.S. 1270 (2000); Manny Garcia, Seized Raid Returns Elian to Father as Angry Protests Dwindle, Strike Called for Tuesday, MIAMI HERALD, Apr. 23, 2000, at 1A. 3. See, e.g., What Next?, ECONOMIST, Apr. 29, 2000, at 27. See also Joe Carroll, Cuban Boy Returns Home as Miami Saga Ends, IRISH TIMES, June 29, 2000; Cuba to Honor Migratory Accords with U.S., XINHUA GEN. NEWS SERVICE, June 29, 2000, available at LEXIS, News Library, AFP file; Brian Knowlton, Reno Rejects Florida Ruling on Cuban, INT’L HERALD TRIB., Jan. 13, 2000; Elian ready to head home Wednesday: supporter, AGENCE FR. PRESSE, June 28, 2000, available at LEXIS, News Library, Xinuah file. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 285 including lectures about the beauty of Cuba and the evil of Fidelismo. As I grew into adolescence, perhaps in knee-jerk fashion, I rebelled at the continuing anti-Fidel tirades and critiqued her sentimentalism for preFidelista Cuba as self-serving defensiveness. Those were heated times for us. But, even as I countered my mom’s lectures, it seemed plain enough that oppressive regimes are contemptible and, in the long run, untenable enterprises—I could sense this basic point personally in the unjust realities of everyday life in Miami (and elsewhere). I sensed, also clearly, that Fidel’s regime was among these forms of enterprise (and, not because of my mother’s rants). Because Fidel, and his allies and acolytes, have not ever been willing to risk a loss or diminution of their power and status, no matter what,4 I never have found myself able to accept their extended, indefinite and totalitarian monopoly on all power, information, and wealth in Cuba. At the same time, I have been repeatedly disappointed and repelled by the rigid and unrelenting authoritarianism of Miami’s exile politics—an Orwellian authoritarianism that is perpetrated in the name of political pluralism and freedom of expression.5 Having been raised amidst the ugliness created between these two poles—my two hometowns—I have been unable to come to terms with either. In many ways, therefore, this Essay is about the difficulty of establishing a grounded identity and social space for children who have come from Cuba to the United States—like Elian—at a very early age and in the context of stalemated polarization. These children have been forced to develop a personal and national identity not only in the midst of a skeptical and alien culture but also in the face of high-pitched ideological conflict between the bipolarized world views of Havana’s and Miami’s elites, the dueling camps that have instigated and fueled so much hostility among and between Cubans for so many years. Perhaps not surprisingly, Elian’s case brought this all to the fore for me.6 One day, a guest arriving at my home picked up the dozen or so newspapers that had piled up by the front door and handed them to me when I opened the door for him. “Do you want to throw these away?” he 4. See generally THEODORE DRAPER, CASTRO’S REVOLUTION: MYTHS AND REALITIES (1962) (discussing the tight hold Fidel Castro and his allies have on Cuba). 5. See generally MARIA DE LOS ANGELOS TORRES, IN THE LAND OF MIRRORS: CUBAN EXILE POLITICS IN THE UNITED STATES 140-48 (2002). 6. The flight of children has been a continuing story, including the now-fabled “Operation Pedro Pan” that facilitated the travel of thousands of children from Cuba to Miami. This operation is the only time in United States history that the federal government has delegated its “plenary power” over immigration to the sole discretion of private individuals, who were empowered to grant visas in the name of the United States government. This operation accounts for my travel and entry to this country. See generally YVONNE M. CONDE, OPERATION P EDRO PAN: THE UNTOLD EXODUS OF 14,048 CUBAN CHILDREN (1999). 286 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 queried. I took them and set them down in a corner, but I soon afterward started to concentrate on why I recently, and suddenly, had begun to avoid reading the newspaper. After a while, I realized that I simply could not deal with my reactions to Elian’s story, as it was in some ways reminiscent of my own trajectory through life. After some time, as Elian’s case dragged on, I decided that I had to read the stacked-up newspapers, even if only to be minimally prepared for the daily conversations from which references to Elian’s situation regularly erupt(ed). One day, alone, I went through them one by one, and then threw them all away. Since then, I have focused myself more than previously on transcending the inflammatory rhetoric of “both” sides, as well as the limitations of my intellectual and personal knowledge, to find ways of identifying as Cuban. Since then, I have intensified an ongoing, life-long struggle with the facts and forces that have recreated the leading city of the state in which we meet this year—as well as the land and people who, in great measure, have catalyzed that recreation: Cuba and Cubans.7 During the past two years, this effort has taken the form mainly of a research project in which I have sought to understand, in comparative and critical terms the worlds offered to us—to me—by the versions of Cuba and Cubans emanating without relent from Havana and Miami. This research project, along with my origins and experience, provide the backdrop for my opinions both of Elian’s story and the larger national tragedy that it represents. This venture is, for me, a personal, political, and jurisprudential project: as a Queer, Latino law professor in Miami committed to social justice, I seek to cohere myself in part by composing a LatCrit and QueerCrit position toward the reconciliation of Cubans and the reconstruction of Cuba as a postsubordination society. I therefore approach this Essay, as well as my larger study of Cuba and Cubans, from a “LatCrit” and a “QueerCrit” perspective.8 It is from this perspective and with this motivation that I invite you to join me, and Cubans on both sides 7. See, e.g., SHEILA L. CROUCHER, IMAGINING MIAMI: ETHNIC POLITICS IN A POSTMODERN WORLD (1997); ALEJANDRO PORTES & ALEX STEPICK, CITY ON THE EDGE: THE TRANSFORMATION OF MIAMI (1993). The Cuban influx and its ramifications have attracted more Latinas/os to Miami in recent years. See, e.g., Amy Driscoll & Tim Henderson, Many Lands Give Florida Its Latin Flavor, MIAMI HERALD, July 25, 2001, at 17A; Andres Viglucci, Census Shows Increase in Hispanics’ Diversity, MIAMI HERALD, May 10, 2001, at 1A. 8. Both LatCrit Theory and Queer Legal Theory are evolving discourses and subject positions that emerged within the legal academy of the United States in the mid-1990s to study the place and prospects of multiple diverse Latinas/os and sexual minorities, respectively, in inter/national law and society. Like other strands of outsider jurisprudence, LatCrit Theory and Queer Legal Theory bring an antisubordinationist stance to the study of legal and social issues. See generally Francisco Valdes, Theorizing “OutCrit” Theories: Coalitional Method and Comparative Jurisprudential Experience—RaceCrits, QueerCrits and LatCrits, 53 U. MIAMI L. REV. 1265 (1999). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 287 of the Florida Straits, in an effort to transcend the invidious bifurcation that Havana’s and Miami’s elites have co-constructed and co-directed since 1959. A. Division and Corruption: Dueling Elites, the Battle of the Straits Since 1959, with the ascension of Fidelismo and the subsequent outflux of refugees, Cuba and Cubans have been understood mostly through the unidimensional lens of political ideology in the context of the Cold War.9 But, at the time of their ascension, Fidel and his comrades most likely possessed, and certainly professed, a vision with integrity of social transformation.10 Looking to the bottom of Cuban society, they rightly saw the condition of Cuba and Cubans as Twentieth Century subalterns, a people and nation held down by the weight of colonial histories and their enduring capitalist legacies—the joint bequest of Spanish and North American imperialism.11 While their immediate predecessors in Havana’s corridors of power had cared mostly about simple wealth and might,12 Fidel and his cohorts focused, at the beginning, on the centrality of national sovereignty, and on social-economic rights, in the design and achievement of a post-subordination Cuban society.13 Though a difference of opinions continues to prevail on this subject,14 it probably is a crude essentialization of Fidel and his original comrades to insist that they were merely power-hungry and ethically corrupt from the beginning. At the same time, the early exiles and their families—those who comprised the “first” wave of post-Fidel Cuban exodus—also were most likely motivated by a vision—and by fears—that they possessed and professed with integrity.15 The early (as well as later) exiles were, from all appearances, motivated by a genuine belief in political as well as economic 9. For a recent and incisive critical account, see MARIFELI PEREZ-STABLE, THE CUBAN REVOLUTION: ORIGINS, COURSE, AND LEGACY (2d ed. 1999). 10. See GEOFF SIMONS, CUBA: FROM CONQUISTADOR TO CASTRO 65-164 (1996). 11. Id. 12. Id. at 303-10. 13. For a selection of Fidel’s writings, see FIDEL CASTRO, REVOLUTIONARY STRUGGLE 19471965, at 2-25 (Rolando E. Bonachee & Nelson P. Valdés eds. 1972). 14. In particular, anti-communist Cuban activists insist that Fidel was corrupt and hypocritical from the beginning of his professedly egalitarian movement. See generally DRAPER, supra note 4, at 115-72. For various news accounts, see Leslie H. Gelb, The Boiling Point, N.Y. TIMES, July 24, 1983, § 4, at 1; Rick Kogan, Sorry story: ‘Last Communist’ a solid portrait of Fidel Castro, CHI. TRIB., Feb. 11, 1992, at 7C; Charles Krauthammer, The Great Dictator, WASH. POST, Dec. 14, 1986, at H7; John T. Skelly, The Men Who Left the 26th of July Movement, MIAMI HERALD, July 26, 2001, at 9B. 15. See RICHARD R. FAGEN ET AL., CUBANS IN EXILE: DISAFFECTION AND THE REVOLUTION 75-98 (1968). 288 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 agency; they foresaw and feared not only economic centralization but also political dictatorship.16 They feared the loss of not only property, but also liberty—and they were right, for the dictates of political and economic centralization have meant that everyday people in Fidel’s Cuba cannot aspire to customize and self-direct their individual lives, either in political or in economic venues.17 Thus, it probably is an equally crude essentialization of Cuba’s exiles to insist that they were merely a petty and trenchant bourgeoisie from the beginning. Instead, from the beginning, Cuba and Cubans on both sides of the Florida Straits have been caught amidst a complex tangle of noble aspirations and well-founded reactions that nevertheless have devolved since then—both in Havana and in Miami—into arrogant systems of social control while giving rise to selfrighteous, materially comfortable and mean-spirited elites. The “Havana elites” encompass primarily the circles of power that control the two overlapping institutions that authoritatively and forcefully supervise all life within Cuba: the government and the party, including perhaps most notably those officials with the power to conduct economic and political relations with the world external to the island.18 The “Miami elites” encompass a loose assemblage of businesspersons—mostly but not exclusively men—and politicos and politicas (again, mostly men) who have amassed money or position in this country, and who use their socioeconomic influence strategically and methodically to promote their political struggle against the social, economic, and political monopoly of 16. See id. See generally CROUCHER, supra note 7, at 121. Interestingly, in this particular respect, these exiles mirrored the concerns of this country’s “founders” in the 1770s and 1780s. See, e.g., THE FEDERALIST No. 10, at 18 (James Madison) (Roy P. Fairfield ed. 2d ed., 1966) (discussing property and democracy in the construction of the federal constitution and government). In both instances, then, these groups were concerned both about personal property and political power. This ideological similarity perhaps accounts at least in part for the powerful connections forged between Miami’s elites and Washington’s elites during these years of diaspora and deadlock. 17. See DRAPER, supra note 4, at 128-33; see also THOMAS M. LEONARD, CASTRO AND THE CUBAN REVOLUTION 1-18, 33-66 (1999); U.S. DEPARTMENT OF STATE (CUBA: Country Reports and Human Rights Practices 2000) (Feb. 2001), available at http://www.state.gov/g/drl/rls/hrrpt/2000/wha/751.htm (last visited Oct. 17, 2002). See generally CUBA’S REPRESSIVE MACHINERY: HUMAN RIGHTS FORTY YEARS AFTER THE REVOLUTION (June 1999), available at http://www.hrw.org/reports/1999/cuba (last visited Oct. 17, 2002). 18. See PEREZ-STABLE, supra note 9, at 180-83; GOVERNMENT AND POLITICS OF CUBA: A COMPREHENSIVE RESOURCE OF CUBA’S GOVERNMENT STRUCTURE, POLITICS, AND ACTORS (July 2001), available at http://www.cubapolidata.com/gpc/gpc_institutional_order.html; LEONARD, supra note 17, at 3-50. See generally Papers and Proceedings of the Ninth Annual Meeting of the Association for Study of the Cuban Economy, 9 CUBA IN TRANSITION 1 (1999), available at http://lanic.utexas.edu/la/cb/cuba/asce/cuba9. See also Domingo Amuchastegui, Cuba’s Armed Forces: Power and Reforms, 9 CUBA IN TRANSITION 109 (1999), available at http://lanic.utexas.edu/la/cb/cuba/asce/cuba9; Armando F. Mastrapa, III, Evolution, Transition and the Cuban Revolutionary Armed Forces, 9 CUBA IN TRANSITION 115 (1999), available at http://lanic.utexas.edu/la/cb/cuba/asce/cuba9 (1999). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 289 Havana’s elites.19 Both elites cloak themselves in nationalistic fervor, and invoke it to mobilize their foot soldiers. But, while both elites speak of “the people of Cuba,” neither is willing to bear the possibility that Cuba and Cubans might prefer life without them. On the contrary, they effectively conspire with each other to disenfranchise Cuba and Cubans.20 As these observations make plain, Havana’s and Miami’s elites are very differently structured and positioned. In Havana, the elites depend on their monopoly over the prerogatives that accompany sovereignty in this world: they control a state recognized globally as an independent country, and therefore the apparati of nationhood. Havana’s elites have at their disposal tools that range from a diplomatic corps to armed and espionage services to the tax and police powers of formal statehood.21 In Miami, the elites depend on their focused influence over the policy of the world’s sole superpower on one particular issue—relations with Cuba;22 though they do 19. See John F. Stack, Jr. & Christopher L. Warren, The Reform Tradition and Ethnic Politics: Metropolitan Miami Confronts the 1990s, MIAMI NOW! 160, 160-85 (Guillermo J. Grenier & Alex Stepick III. eds., 1992); CROUCHER, supra note 7, at 133; Understanding the Cuban Model: Cuban-Americans in Miami Politics, CUBAN-AMERICAN P OLITICAL EMPOWERMENT (Dr. Wilbur Rich ed.), available at http://www.fiu.edu/~morenod/scholar/empower.htm; see also Karen BranchBrioso et al., Power Shift Seen for Dade Experts Predict Hispanic Gains, MIAMI HERALD, Sept. 4, 2000, at 1A. See generally Guillermo J. Grenier & Max J. Castro, Triadic Politics: Ethnicity, Race, and Politics in Miami, 1959-1998, 68 HIST. REV. 273 (1999); Dan Sewell, Cubans Have Transformed Miami Into an Island of Opportunity Immigrants: The Exiles and Their Children Dominate the Economy, Government and Culture. The new order worries some black leaders, L.A. TIMES, Dec. 23, 1990, Pt. A, available at 1990 WL 2290507; Jan Nijman, Globalization to a Latin beat: the Miami growth machine, ANNALS AM. ACAD. POL. & SOC. SCI. 164 (1997). 20. See, e.g., TORRES, supra note 5, at 143. 21. See infra note 25 and sources cited therein on political repression in Cuba. While bringing fiercely to bear the attributes and apparati of sovereignty to club down nonconforming persons who threaten their dictatorial domination, the Havana elites have reveled in and cultivated the romantic image of themselves as a heroic David slaying—or at least defying—the menacing Goliath of the North, especially when the United States has brought to bear the same attributes and apparti of its sovereignty against them; in both instances, ironically, sovereignty serves oppression. The use of statehood extends to espionage operations designed to “infiltrate” and destabilize the Miami elites, which Fidel and his minions label a “mafia” in intentionally pejorative ways. See, e.g., Ellis Berger, INS Official Convicted in Spy Case: Federal Jury Rules Exile Passed Secrets to Cuba, SUNSENTINEL, May 31, 2000, at 1A.; Alfonso Chardy & Elaine De Valle, The New Cuba Crisis: Havana Has Spied on Exiles for Years, MIAMI HERALD, Feb. 28, 1996, at 13A; David Kidwell, Three More Accused Spies Agree to Plead Guilty, MIAMI HERALD, Oct. 9, 1998, at 4B; Associated Press, 5 Cubans Convicted in Plot to Spy on U.S., N.Y. TIMES, June 9, 2001, at A12; Gail Epstein Nieves & Alfonso Chardy, Cuban Spies Convicted: Sweeping Espionage Verdicts Include Murder of Fliers: Exiles Call Castro’s Indictment in Air Deaths, MIAMI HERALD, June 9, 2001, at 1A; Situation of Human Rights in Cuba, Comm’n on Human Rights Res. 16, U.N. ESCOR, 57th Sess., U.N. Doc. E/CN.4/RES/2001/16 (2001). 22. The “embargo” and its recent intensification via the Helms-Burton Act is one apt example of this influence. See, e.g., Maya Bell, Powerful Foundation Focuses Fight to Free Cuba, ORLANDO SENTINEL, Sept. 25, 1994, at A1, available at 1994 WL 4722917. See also Robert E. 290 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 not “own” a country outright, as do the Havana elites, Miami’s elites have shown a singular capacity (at least until the Elian affair) to manipulate American policy toward all things Cuban (and, in turn, to be manipulated by American policymakers23). Thus, in limited but crucial instances Miami’s elites indirectly can activate the attributes and apparati of American sovereignty to destabilize the Havana elites and to assert their own interests.24 Without doubt, then, both sets of elites ground their power in formidable structures and leverage them shrewdly. They are caught in a mutual death grip because both have enough might to survive and struggle endlessly, but neither has enough to triumph definitively. Though positioned very differently in their sources and instruments of power, the two elites have co-constructed a world of tensions suspended indefinitely between their bipolar entrenchment.25 Despite the internal complexities Freer, Jr., Helms-Burton Myths and Reality, 5 CUBA IN TRANSITION 429 (1995), available at http:// lanic.utexas.edu/la/cb/cuba/asce/cuba5; Digna B. French, Economic Sanctions Imposed by the United States Against Cuba: Thirty-Nine Year Old Embargo Culminating with the Cuban Liberty and Democratic Solidarity (Libertad) Act of 1996, 7 U. MIAMI INT’L & COMP. L. REV. 1 (19981999); Andreas F. Lowenfield, Agora: The Cuban Liberty and Democratic Solidarity (Libertad) Act Congress and Cuba: The Helms-Burton Act, 90 AM. J. OF INT’L L. 419 (1996); Robert L. Muse, International Symposium on the Cuban Liberty and Democratic Solidarity (Libertad) Act of 1966: A Public International Law Critique of the Extraterritorial Jurisdiction of the Helms-Burton Act (Cuban Liberty and Democratic Solidarity (Libertad) Act of 1966), 30 GEO. WASH. J. INT’L L. & ECON. 207 (1996-1997); Mercy B. Pina, Comment: Despite the Controversy Surrounding the Helms-Burton Act Its End is Far From Becoming a Reality, 4 ILSA J. INT’L & COMP. L. 1259 (1998); Alejandro Portes, Morning in Miami; A New Era for Cuban-American Politics, AM. PROSPECT, May-June 1998, at 28. This race-sex hierarchy of course reflects—and perpetuates—historic hierarchies established by European colonization. See generally BETWEEN RACE AND EMPIRE: AFRICAN-AMERICANS AND CUBANS BEFORE THE CUBAN REVOLUTION (Lisa Brock & Digna Castaneda Fuertes eds., 1998), avaiable at http://www.netlibrary.com/ ebook_info.asp?product_id=51296. 23. The Bay of Pigs fiasco and missile crisis are ready examples of this mutual manipulation. See HUGH THOMAS, CUBA, OR THE PURSUIT OF FREEDOM 1355-1419 (1998 ed.). 24. The Elian affair is a prime example of a failed effort. See Juan O. Tamayo, Saga of Elian; Raid and Reunion, MIAMI HERALD, Apr. 25, 2000, at 9A. The Helms-Burton Act is a prime example of a successful effort. See also supra note 22. 25. While both elites operate cohesively, as past and present experience—including the Elian affair—amply confirm, they are not necessarily monolithic congregations of groups, persons, and institutions. Havana’s and Miami’s elites do not always operate smoothly, or have all their foot soldiers marching neatly in unison to the beat of the master drummers. In Havana, reports surface periodically of political purges that reflect internal fissures. See, e.g., Rey Moseley, Drug Crackdown Spurs Cuba Purge, CHI. TRIB., June 30, 1989, at 4M; Juan O. Tamayo, Cuba Toughens Crackdown: ‘Biggest Wave of Repression So Far This Year,’ MIAMI HERALD, Nov. 11, 1999, at 1A; Juan O. Tamayo, Havana Tries to Stem Wave of Boat Escapes, MIAMI HERALD, July 22, 1999, at 1A; Cuban Dissidents Complete Human Rights Fast, MIAMI HERALD, July 17, 1999, at 1A. See also infra note 35 regarding political repression in Cuba. In Miami, in the meantime, intergenerational transitions are causing similar splits within the Cuban American National Foundation (CANF), which oftentimes is described as the crucible for Miami’s Cuban elites. See, e.g., Rafael 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 291 and comparative differences, on both sides of the Straits, these dual elites exist and operate as interconnected groups, persons, and institutions actuated by a common formal platform of political ideology. On both sides of the Straits, the adherents of these sometimes unruly factions can be, and are, disciplined forcefully in various ways by their respective commanders and comrades for straying too far from approved dictates. These elites, however, do not represent—they do not even try to—the multiple diverse communities that they profess to care so much about. Indeed, both Havana and Miami house elites that represent the worst of colonialism’s contemporary legacies. Both sustain racist, sexist, and homophobic premises and structures of subordination. In Cuba, for instance, positions of power both in the government and in the party overwhelmingly still are held, controlled, and dispensed by openly straight white men.26 Ditto in Miami’s Cuban enclave27—as Lorente & Tamara Lytle, Trade Demands, Loss of Leader Sap Clout of Anti-Castro Cubans in U.S., CHI. TRIB., June 21, 2000, at 8; Christopher Marquis, Cuban-American Lobby on the Defensive, N.Y. TIMES, June 30, 2000, at A12; Luisa Yanez, CANF Board Ponders Future Amid Public Rift, MIAMI HERALD, July 22, 2001, at 3B. See also Cynthia Corzo et al., Foundation riven by dissent among Miami Cubans, MIAMI HERALD, July 21, 2001, at 1A; Elaine De Valle & Carol Rosenberg, Ex-CANF Member Explains Resignation, MIAMI HERALD, July 24, 2001, at 1B; Elaine De Valle & Carol Rosenberg, CANF Ignites Cuban Media, MIAMI HERALD, July 25, 2001, at 3A; Fabiola Santiago, CANF leader claims his late father’s legacy but says he doesn’t walk in his shadow, MIAMI HERALD, July 29, 2001, at 1A.; Robert L. Steinback, CANF Rift May Open New Doors, MIAMI HERALD, July 29, 2001, at 1B. Nevertheless, and in spite of their various differences, both bipolar elites have shown themselves over time to be cohesive forces and formations, even if only by their increasing interest in self-perpetuation and self-aggrandizement above all—certainly above the protection or advancement of the principles they loudly tout(ed). 26. See generally LOIS M. SMITH & ALFRED PADULA, SEX AND REVOLUTION: WOMEN IN SOCIALIST CUBA 45-187 (1996); Julie Marie Bunck, Women and the Post-Cold War Socialism: The Cases of Cuba and Vietnam, 7 CUBA IN TRANSITION 21, 26-27 (1997), at http://lanic.ulexcs.edu//a/Cuba/ asce/Cuba7/bunck.pdf; Debra Evenson, Women’s Equality in Cuba: What Difference Does a Revolution Make?, 4 LAW & INEQ. 295 (1986). See also STATISTICAL RECORD OF WOMEN WORLDWIDE 605-606 (Linda Schmittroth ed., 1991); Nadine T. Fernandez, The Color of Love: Young Interracial Couples in Cuba, 23 LATIN AM. PERSP. 99 (1996); Alejandro de la Fuente, Race, National Discourse, and Politics in Cuba, 25 LATIN AM. P ERSP. 43 (1998); Alejandro de la Fuente, The Resurgence of Racism in Cuba, 34 NACLA REP. ON AM. 29 (2001); Tanya Kateri Hernandez, Multiracial Matrix: The Role of Ideology in Enforcement of Antidiscrimination Laws, A United States-Latin America Comparison, 87 CORNELL L. REV. 1093, 1133-44 (2002) (analyzing race and White supremacy in Cuba); Sheryl L. Lutjens, Reading Between the Lines: Women, the States, and Rectification in Cuba, 22 LATIN AM. PERSP.100, (1995); National Assembly of the People’s Power, Government and Politics of Cuba: A Comprehensive Resource of Cuba’s Government Structure, Politics, and Actors (July 2001), available at http://www.cubapolidata. com/gpc/gpc_institutional_order.html (last visited Oct. 18, 2002). As with male and White supremacy on the island, today’s Cuba similarly retains its historic hetrosexism. See, e.g., IAN LUMSDEN, MACHOS, MARICONES AND GAYS: CUBA AND HOMOSEXUALITY (1996). 27. See generally U.S. CENSUS BUREAU, CURRENT POPULATION REPORTS, SERIES P23-205, Population Profile of the United States: America at the Close of the 20th Century (U.S. Government 292 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 throughout the United States, more generally.28 And, both camps are elitist and classist—though they differ on their choice of political or ideological pivots for the erection of their elites, classes, and hierarchies. Thus, Havana’s elites favor the straight white men who espouse their pet slogans while Miami’s elites do likewise; and, in both instances, these are the persons who tend to reside in the nicest homes and neighborhoods of their respective domains. In both instances, these post/neo/colonial elites use Law to buttress their control of Society, and embed personal predilection in Law to safeguard their arrogated privileges and reproduce the structural predominance of their kind in Law and throughout Society. While apologists on both sides of the Florida Straits are quick to issue impassioned defenses of the ultimate intentions that justify present shortcomings, the fact remains that in nearly a half century neither Havana’s nor Miami’s elites have shown much interest in social transformation when it might disturb their preferred positions at the apex of their respective heaps. Euroheteropatriarchy still governs hegemonically in the worlds and agendas constructed both by Havana’s and Miami’s elites:29 both sides of Printing Office, 2002); U.S. CENSUS BUREAU; POPULATION PROJECTIONS OF THE UNITED STATES BY AGE, SEX, AND HISPANIC ORIGIN: 1995 TO 2050, available at http://www.census.gov/prod/www/titles.html#popest; THE CUBAN AMERICAN NATIONAL COUNCIL, A DEMOGRAPHIC P ROFILE OF CUBAN AMERICANS (1994) [hereinafter DEMOGRAPHIC PROFILE OF CUBAN AMERICANS]; Anthony DePalma, For Haitians, Voyage to a Land of Inequality, N.Y. TIMES, July 16, 1991, at A1; Lydia Martin, Lifting the Burden of Machismo More Women Speaking Out Against Hispanic Tradition of Patriarchy, MIAMI HERALD, Feb. 13, 1994, at 1J; Government & Elections, HISPANIC AMERICANS: A STATISTICAL SOURCEBOOK, 108-09 (2001); Mireya Navarro, Black and Cuban-American: Bias in 2 Worlds, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 13, 1997, at A3; Mirta Ojito, How Race is Lived in America, N.Y. TIMES, June 5, 2000, at A1; Schmittroth, supra note 26, at 600 & 612. See also Karen Branch-Brioso et al., The Real Power in Dade Despite Hispanic Majority, White Non-Hispanics Hold Sway Control of Key Public, Private Positions Contradicts Image, Herald Survey Finds, MIAMI HERALD, Sept. 3, 2000, at 1A. 28. See generally BUREAU OF CENSUS, 1992 CENSUS OF GOVERNMENTS, 1 GOVERNMENT ORGANIZATION, NUM. 2, POPULARLY ELECTED OFFICIALS 20-21 (1995). 29. Euroheteropatriarchy describes a Eurocentric fusion of androsexist and heterosexist biases and prejudices producing over time the systematic privileging of humans, groups, norms and values that are identified, among other things, as white, masculine and heterosexual. See Francisco Valdes, Symposium, Intersections: Sexuality, Cultural Tradition, and the Law: Unpacking HeteroPatriarchy: Tracing the Conflation on Sex, Gender and Sexual Orientation to Its Origins, 8 YALE J.L. & HUMAN. 161 (1996) (describing some of the sex/gender and sexual orientation norms that underlie and animate androsexism and heterosexism to produce the patriarchal form of homophobia—heteropatriarchy—that still prevails in Euroamerican societies, including the United States, today). As elaborated here, it is prevalent in Cuba and among Cubans, both on the island and throughout the Diaspora. It is rooted in the normativities introduced and imposed by Iberian and other European conquistadors. It is supported by the cultural and political preferences of American imperialism throughout this hemisphere during the past century or two. Today, both sets of elites reproduce Euroheteropatriarchy in the act of re/producing themselves and their hierarchies; 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 293 the Florida Straits remain anchored to a preference for openly straight white men as the leaders and principal beneficiaries of their inter/national projects. White supremacy, male supremacy, and straight supremacy reign still over Cubans, whether in Havana or Miami.30 These dueling elites thus represent little more than sanitized competing political ideals to which they once might have aspired authentically, but to which they no longer bow. Both sides of the Straits now connive to foist on Cuba and Cubans the worn, sugarcoated slogans that serve mainly to maintain their personal positions and mutually self-interested politics. This devolution today shows that Havana’s elites would rather sell the country to opportunistic and ravenous neocolonial capitalists from Canada and Europe—most noticeably, and some would say ironically, the old colonial master, Spain—and to accommodate the growing prostitution and sex tourism on the island generated from the “decadent” societies with which Havana elites choose to conduct “business,” than to accept even a modicum of political or economic decentralization.31 For their part, Miami’s elites would rather destroy the country’s infrastructure and, apparently, starve every single person on the island than take even a first tiny step toward negotiated resolution to the embargo they erected with a regardless of the emphasized differences in political ideology, the same social profile comes out “on top” while the same marginalized identities are pushed to “the bottom”—both in Havana and in Miami. 30. Of course, Fidelismo has enabled the betterment of living conditions for some segments of the population: some women and nonwhites have risen in the ranks of Cuba’s hierarchies while the oppression of sexual minorities waxes and wanes according to the pulse of Havana’s elites. See generally ALEJANDRO DE LA FUENTE, RECREATING RACISM: RACE AND DISCRIMINATION IN CUBA’S “SPECIAL PERIOD” (1998); FAGEN, supra note 15, at 39-47 and 121-42; Phillip Geyelin, Fidel’s Cuba: Castro Hangs Onto His Big Following Despite Rising Economic Woes, WALL ST. J., Aug. 14, 1964, at 1; James C. McKinley, In City of Castro’s Triumph, Most Still Back Him, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 2, 1999, at A3. See also supra note 26 and sources cited therein on race, sex, and sexual orientation in Fidel’s Cuba. The same is true in the United States generally. See U.S. CENSUS BUREAU, CURRENT POPULATION REPORTS, MONEY INCOME IN THE UNITED STATES: 1999 (U.S. Government Printing Office), P60-209 pg. xi, available at http://www.census.gov/hhes/ www/income99.html; U.S. CENSUS BUREAU, HISTORICAL INCOME TABLES: CURRENT POPULATION SURVEY (2002), available at http://www.census.gov/hhes/income/histinc/histinctb.html.; and specifically among the exile enclave in Miami. See, e.g., PORTES & STEPICK, supra note 7, at 12349. See also DEMOGRAPHIC PROFILE OF CUBAN AMERICANS, supra note 27. Both over there and over here, some social and legal conditions indeed have been made “better” in material terms for some Cubans, including some identified with traditionally oppressed outgroups. Yet the privilege and dominance of straight white men remains structurally entrenched. 31. See, e.g., Julia O’Connell Davidson, Sex tourism in Cuba, 38 RACE & CLASS: J. FOR BLACK & THIRD WORLD LIBERATION 39-49 (1996); Paul Cullen, Tourism Corrodes Soul of Cuban Revolution, IRISH TIMES, Jan. 8, 2001, at 14 (World News); Isabel Garcia-Zarza, Restricted Access, available at http://abc.go.com/sections/travel.DailyNews/cubatourism000302.html (last visited Aug. 8, 2001); Ron Howell, In Cuba, Old Racial Attitudes Revived; Critics Say Tourism Has Brought Bias Back, NEWSDAY, May 13, 2001, at A04;. 294 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 complicitous United States.32 Both sets of elites, in short, remain uniformly committed first and foremost to their own reproduction in both ideological and demographic terms. Each camp has failed in ultimate and substantive terms, for neither has cared enough about its proclaimed communities and original principles, and both have cared too much about the pursuit and perpetuation of their supremacy; both have opted for personal gain over principled nationbuilding. On the island, Fidel certainly has not honored his early words and promises of egalitarian reformation with actions and policies designed consistently to fulfill them.33 His regime has, instead, cultivated a cultist centralization of power in his person; while Fidel does not (and humanly cannot) control every act or abuse that takes place in his revolution’s name, he wields virtually absolute influence over any particular decision of policy or practice in his government, and he has shown himself ready, willing, and able to order unilaterally, and at will, acts of violence or intimidation directed against the Cuban people.34 Today, his government increasingly misuses and abuses national sovereignty and its attributes to oppress, rather than to empower or liberate, Cuba and Cubans.35 Fidelismo’s early promise consequently does not match its actual record—even before the embargo and even in matters that cannot, by any stretch of the imagination, be imputed by rote to “the embargo.” In the enclave, Miami’s elites on the whole have shown a stalwart interest in “freedom of expression” and “democracy”—but only when they liked what they saw and heard.36 And when not, exile elites have whipped up 32. See, e.g., Peter G. Bourne, The Impact of the U.S. Embargo on Health and Nutrition in Cuba, 8 CUBA IN TRANSITION 213 (1998), available at http://lanic.utexas.edu/la/cb/cuba/ asce/cuba8; Maria C. Werlau, The Effects of the U.S. Embargo on Health and Nutrition in Cuba: A Critical Analysis, 8 C UBA IN T RANSIT ION 219 (1998), available at http://lanic.utexas.edu/la/cb/cuba/ asce/cuba8; Guy Gugliotta, Hard-Liners Dig in on the Issue of Embargo; Cuban American Foundation Is Determined Not to Founder After Loss of Its Leader, WASH. POST, Jan. 21, 1998, at A16; Juan O. Tamayo, Ex-U.S. Official to Lead Pro-Embargo Drive, MIAMI HERALD, June 30, 2000, at 1A. See generally UNITED STATES INTERNATIONAL TRADE COMMISSION, THE ECONOMIC IMPACT OF U.S. SANCTIONS WITH RESPECT TO CUBA, Investigation No. 332-413 (2001), available at ftp://ftp.usite.gov/reports/studies/pub3398.pdf. But cf. Ken Guggenheim, Embargo’s Impact Slight, Report Says Cuba’s Trade Seen as Limited by Own Politics, MIAMI HERALD, Feb. 16, 2001, at 1A. 33. See generally LEONARD, supra note 17, at 85. 34. See generally id. 35. See, e.g., Castro Abuses Crime Crackdown to Muzzle Political Dissidents, FORT LAUDERDALE SUN-SENTINEL, Feb. 23, 1999, at 22A; Howard W. French, Castro Meets Dissent With an Iron Hand, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 8, 1991, at 3; Colin McMahon, Castro’s Crackdown, CHI. TRIB., Mar. 1, 1996, at 1N. See also supra notes 17, 18 and 25 and sources cited therein on Fidel’s political dictatorship. 36. For example, one of Miami’s most established and prominent restaurants in Little Havana—Centro Vasco—was bombed and driven out of business when it dared to allow a Cuban 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 295 outrageous reactions, including acts of violence and intimidation, from misinformed and excitable constituencies.37 In sum, the dominant elites on both sides of the Straits have resorted to vicious disinformation, social suppression and physical violence for the sake of power, preferring to “win” their petty but destructive battles at any cost—especially when “winning” has become tantamount to personal power and privilege. In their reciprocal craving for status, comfort and triumph, both have deformed or eclipsed their original sense of ethics and have rendered themselves into caricatures of their early, and perhaps once authentic, impulses. Nonetheless, or perhaps consequently, since 1959 Cubans both on the island and throughout the diaspora increasingly have been situated by themselves and others as “for” and “against” the two different and powerful political camps that emerged contemporaneously in Havana and Miami from the ascension of Fidelismo and the outflux of refugees.38 In Havana, time has enabled a bold, if corrupt, experiment that still defies the homogenizing pressures of rapacious capitalism and, most recently, neoliberal embrace of corporatist globalization; despite its fundamental flaws, this soiled experiment provides some hope that a concrete alternative to this newest, transnational hegemony-in-the-making may yet become vital.39 From Miami, time has permitted the formation and singer from the island to perform on its premises. See Armando Correa, Restaurant Cancels Cuban Singer’s Performances Centro Vasco Had Been Firebombed, MIAMI HERALD, July 13, 1996, at 1B; Frances Robles, A Landmark’s End: Centro Vasco Falls Prey to Exile Politics, MIAMI HERALD, Oct. 27, 1996, at 1B. This example is neither unique nor rare. See Heating up Cuba: Anti-Castro Exiles Plot New Raids, Aim to Win Stronger U.S. Support, WALL ST. J., Sept. 18, 1962, at 1; All Things Considered, Analysis: Cuban-American Radio Stations Influence the Cuban Community (Nat’l Pub. Radio Broadcast), Apr. 18, 2000, 2000 WL 21468835; David Adams, Bombs Do Not Destroy Miami’s New Tolerance, ST. PETERSBURG TIMES, Aug. 5, 1996, at 1B; Pamela Constable, New Voices of Exile Although the Cuban-American Political Establishment Remains Conservative, Democrats and Socialistic Iconoclasts Are Gaining Ground. “For The First Time in This Community,” Says One Party Leader, “There Is A Legitimate Debate Going On,” BOSTON GLOBE, July 25, 1993, at 10; Shelley Emling, Miami Politics Bar Cuban Musicians From Festival, ATLANTA J. & CONST., Aug. 31, 1997, at 8A; Lydia Martin, Violence, Dialogue In a Year of Tumult, MIAMI HERALD, Dec. 29, 1996, at 1I. 37. See, e.g., Liz Balzameda, Emilio Milián, Broadcaster Who Denounced Terror, Dies, MIAMI HERALD, Mar. 16, 2001, at 1A; Liz Balsameda, Milián a Symbol of Courage, MIAMI HERALD, Mar. 19, 2001, at 1B; Castro Foe Injured in Miami Car Blast, N.Y. TIMES, May 1, 1976, at 42. See also Cuban Hit Squad: Anti-Castro ‘Omega 7’ Evokes Terror in U.S. With Murders, Bombs, WALL ST. J., Dec. 30, 1981, at 1; ALPHA 66, available at http://www.alpha66.org/; Luisa Yanez, Hundreds Mourn ‘Man of Honor,’ MIAMI HERALD, Mar. 18, 2001, at 4B. 38. See generally TORRES, supra note 5. 39. This possibility attracts support for Fidel despite his political totalitarianism. See, e.g., Richard Boudreaux, Mandela Lauds Castro as Visit to Cuba Ends; Diplomacy: ANC Leader Cites the Communist Revolution and Says “We, too, want to control our own destiny,” L.A. TIMES, July 28, 1991, at A4; Castro’s Anti-U.S. Message Is Welcomed By a Malaysian Leader Critical of 296 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 flourishment of an “exile” community that, despite its regular fits of intolerance and vitriol, still vaunts within Cuban inter/national discourse and politics the importance to human wellbeing of individual agency and freedom of expression in economic and political matters; this rancorous experiment has prevented a quiet consolidation of both tyranny and social justice within the island’s confines.40 During this time, as the Elian case has illustrated, both camps have done a superlative job in propagating and legitimating their world views. Both sets of elites have constructed discourses, regimes, and communities that give political, intellectual, and material spectacle to the hierarchies that they signify and valorize. Both sets of elites, in tandem, have enabled each other’s clamp on their respective levers of power and privilege, as opposing cosmologies that coexist primarily, if not exclusively, as a result of the high-tension stalemate that they have managed to cocreate before a rapt and dazed world. Increasingly, then, it has become clear that Havana and Miami represent, for Cuba and Cubans, a choice between a rock and a hard place. Havana, like a rock, has insisted that its bold experiment can exist only if “the people” agree to forfeit political agency on both individual and national levels—and in effective perpetuity.41 Miami, like a hard place, has insisted that human agency and freedom of expression can exist only if “the people” accept the unjust precepts and vagaries of rampant capitalism, including social inequality and extreme poverty—also in effective perpetuity.42 With increasing absolutism, inspired in part by the demands and dynamics of bipolarization, these two capitals of Cuba and Cubans have preached and practiced ideologies that construct politically “different” yet strikingly similar hierarchies of privilege and power—arrangements that structurally and substantively benefit the neocolonial few at the expense of the multiply diverse many. Despite their tangible successes as measured in narrow and selfish terms, time is not on their side. Globalization, Cuban Salutes His Hosts as Fellow Rebels, ST. LOUIS POST-DISPATCH, May 13, 2001, at A5; At Castro’s Invitation, Aristide Visits Havana, MIAMI HERALD, July 18, 2001, at 14A; Castro Uses Forum of Poor Nations to Attack Capitalism, CHI. TRIB., Apr. 13, 2000, at N23; Roger Simon, Mandela Commends Clinton, Defends Ties to Libya, Cuba, CHI. TRIB., Mar. 28, 1998, at N3; Richard Sine, Castro Looms Over Meeting: Cuba Questions Fill Air As IDB Members Debate, NEW ORLEANS TIMES-PICAYUNE, Mar. 29, 2000, at C01. 40. See generally TORRES, supra note 5 (recounting and analyzing the waves of Cuban immigration since Castro’s victory over Batista’s dictatorship, and the sociopolitical implications of these migrations). 41. See generally DRAPER, supra note 4, at 42-48. 42. See generally TORRES, supra note 5, at 155-200. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 297 B. Arrogation and Class Distinctions: The Politics of Tyranny and Money One of Fidel’s principal methods of imposing “justice” and disempowering his “enemies” upon seizing power in 1959 was ruthlessly to concentrate control over all property in himself and his cronies.43 This sweeping dispossession of the Cuban people was not a nuanced or orderly project. And it extended not just to grand plantations, or even street-corner pharmacies, but to everything of every kind, including personal possessions. Though Fidel’s rules on property ownership and use have shifted with the winds of need and strategy,44 his centralized control over the disposition and reallocation of all forms of property, and of their commercial or personal uses, has been the crucible for the construction of “rich” and “poor”—those who eat well and those who do not, those who travel and those who do not, those who live comfortably and those who do not. Thus, in Cuba, Havana’s elites control the party that controls the state 43. See generally STEVEN E. HENDRIX, TENSIONS IN CUBAN PROPERTY LAW, 29 (1996); Nicolas J. Gutierrez, Jr., Esq., The De-Constitutionalization of Property Rights: Castro’s Systematic Assault on Private Ownership in Cuba, 5 Y.B. OF INT’L L. 51 (1996/1997); Jose A. Ortiz, The Illegal Expropriation of Property in Cuba: A Historical and Legal Analysis of the Takings and a Survey of Restitution Schemes for a Post-Socialist Cuba, 22 LOY. L.A. INT’L & COMP. L. REV. 321 (2000); Eduardo Moises Penalver, Redistributing Property: Natural Law, International Norms, and the Property Reforms of the Cuban Revolution, 52 FLA. L. REV. 107 (2000). See also infra note 44 on Fidel’s property take-overs. 44. See generally LEONARD, supra note 17, at 85. The reports of the news media over the years reflect these policy shifts. See, e.g., Joie Chen & Lucia Newman, Bad Business: Cuba Cracks Down on Private Enterprise, (CNN Television Broadcast, Mar. 9, 2001), available at LEXIS, News library, CNN file; A Crash Course in Economics: The Belated Discovery of Profit and Loss, ECONOMIST, Apr. 6, 1996, at 5; Robert D. Cruz & J. Antonio Villamil, Sustainable small enterprise development in a Cuban transition economy, 34 STUD. COMP. INT’L DEV. 100 (2000); Business Group Wants Private Sector in Cuba, ORLANDO SENTINEL, Dec. 2, 1999, at A18; Cuba’s Economy: Mala Vista Social Club, ECONOMIST, Oct. 23, 1999, at 37; Open for Business? Cuba’s Economy, ECONOMIST, Dec. 4, 1993, at 71; Cuba’s Economic Repression, Mar. 16, 2001, available at http://www.ibb.gov/editorials/09186.htm; Cuba Promotes Oil Business in Exclusive Economic Zone, BBC WORLDWIDE MONITORING, (BBC Television Broadcast, Aug. 11, 1999), available at LEXIS, News library, BBCMIR file; Laurie Goering, The Hazards of Enterprise, ECONOMIST, Apr. 6, 1996, at 7; Laurie Goering, Cuba’s Small Capitalists Face Less Friendly Future: They Helped the Nation Weather an Economic Low, But the Government is Making Things Much Tougher Now, CHI. TRIB., Jun. 20, 2001, at N1, available at CUBANEWS, http://www.cubanet.org/Cnews/y01/ jun01/20e9.htm; Hispanics-Cuba/Spain (1st Lead) Spaniards and Cubans Pledge More Business, EFE NEWS SERVICE, July 7, 2001, available at LEXIS, World library, 6NW file; Lucia Newman, Cuba squeezes private business as economy grows, CNN, Mar. 11, 2001, available at CUBANEWS http://www.cuabmet.org/ Cnews01/mar01/12e6.htm; Marta Beatrice Roque, A Cuban Economist Calls for Less Official Meddling, WALL ST. J., Nov. 24, 2000, at A17; Cuba Slows Free Market Changes, May 1, 1996, available at http://www.sn.apc.org/wmail/issues/ 960501/BUS17.html. 298 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 that controls all property.45 In this way, the governing cliques retain effective control over the attributes of “ownership” of all property and its uses via their strict control of the party and government—due to their prior deployment of “the state” to “nationalize” property, thereby arrogating personal control (and, if desired, personal possession) of any given asset. In this manner, Havana’s elites arrogate and dispense the best of everything to themselves, their courtiers, and their foot soldiers. In key and ironic ways, the Fidelista construction of personal economic security or wellbeing is very similar to Cuba’s colonial structuring, in which personal material comforts, or socioeconomic status, are linked to the personal favors of the king or jefe—or of his designated agents—based, typically, on demonstrated levels of political servitude and utility.46 This construction is similar, in fact, to the days immediately preceding Fidel’s revolution, when another corrupt dictatorship controlled the state and the people—and their personal properties or fortunes—with brute force.47 In today’s Cuba, as in yesterday’s, access to economic advancement remains structurally correlated to manifest political allegiance to the Havana elites’ self-serving agendas. Today as before, the loyalists live well—and it is no coincidence that Cuba’s ruling class continues to consist mostly of White men; the rest, for the most part, do not.48 In this ongoing scheme, both possession and dispossession are 45. See generally supra note 44 and sources cited therein on Cuba’s changing policy on property, trade, and private enterprise. 46. See SIMONS, supra note 10, at 102-13 (discussing colonial arrangements). 47. The followers of Fidel’s predecessor, Fulgencio Batista, continue to live in the United States and abroad. See Michael Bowning, The Cuban Revolution, 40 Years Later: For Batista’s Dwindling Band, Each New Year Dawns Somberly, PALM BEACH POST, Jan. 1, 1999, at 1A. 48. See generally supra note 26 cited therein on the identity politics of Cuban society and government. The material dimensions of these power/status disparities have been exacerbated by the “dollarization” of the Cuban economy—an ironic act for a socialist state, and one that has spawned a “dual economy” on the island, vividly illustrating both how far Havana’s elites have compromised their original principles as well as that they effectively have abandoned their formal revolutionary aspirations. See generally CARMELA MESA-LAGO, ARE ECONOMIC REFORMS PROPELLING CUBA TO THE MARKET? 24-30 (1994). In this dual economy, the Havana elites’ control over jobs—and over coveted access to the dollar—freely use their control over such access to practice politics, and to shore up their elite status and power, as illustrated in the political maneuvering over the “Varela Project.” One woman, for example, expressed the fear of job loss if she did not publicly subscribe to the party line on questions of political reforms, saying “Don’t you realize? I work in a dollar store.” Another was quoted as saying that, “You know what is expected of you . . . so you go and get it over with.” See Anita Snow, Associated Press, Cubans Want to Know Text of Varela Project, ORLANDO SENTINEL, June 24, 2002, at A11. At a recent academic conference on Cuba’s economy, Cuba scholars widely reported the existence of a highly centralized economic order controlled directly by the party elites through the structures and apparati of government—a centralization of control that ensures control over the nation’s (non)productivity, wealth and potential in part by adopting capitalist techniques in highly strategic ways. See Time Johnson, Castro has Chokehold on Private Sector, Scholars Say, MIAMI HERALD, Nov. 21, 2002, 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 299 decided from above—centrally and potentially immediately—in economic, social, and political terms. Also in keeping with colonial times, this political monopoly over the “good things in life”—ranging from private residences to international travel, and from shoes to vegetables—is the scheme through which not only class hierarchies are constructed in today’s Cuba but also through which political allegiance is induced strategically. This monopoly both entrenches the Havana elites’ political power and determines class position for everyone on the island. This unchecked power over material conditions and comforts, now as then, has served mightily to help Havana’s elites entrench political control over the people and economy of the island. Today, under Fidelismo’s tightly centralized systems of control, persons deemed ideologically unreliable simply have no chance of personal security, much less success, either in social or economic terms.49 The Havana elites’ complete control and shrewd manipulation of their unjust monopoly, which gives them the power to determine socioeconomic status for every single individual on the island, is a mighty source of tyranny because it manipulates and exploits human needs and wants. Fidelismo, of course, has not erased the need to acquire food, shelter, and other material necessities and luxuries of corporeal human existence. But, despite its longstanding monopoly on power, Fidelismo has not erased stratification based on distinctions in access to, enjoyment of, and control over socioeconomic goods and opportunities. Class construction thus occurs in Cuba, albeit differently than in Miami or other capitalist contexts. Fidelismo, in other words, has not erased the existence of “class” in Cuba or material inequalities among “classes” of Cubans. Under Fidelismo, where “the state” holds dominion over all property, and where “the state” in fact amounts to a small self-anointed clique of straight white men that rule by the force of the gun, the social and economic fortunes of multiply diverse individuals are decided by those men in reference to their own perceived self interests, and at the expense of all others, including society as a whole. Fidelismo, then, simply has reconfigured the politics of class construction between and among Cubans in Cuba. In Miami, as one might expect, class is constructed in the typical capitalist ways of these times, as practiced generally in the United States at 9A. See also supra note 18 and sources cited therein on power structures, relations, and dynamics on the island. The bottom line generated through these intersections of identity, ideology, class, and status is that the formally supreme political body on the island, the party Politburo, remains a bastion of White men—none of them openly gay. See PABLO ALONSO, LOS ULTIMOS CASTRISTAS (1998) (describing the individual members of this ruling group). 49. See generally Andres Oppenheimer, Free Four Dissidents, Europe Tells Cuba, MIAMI HERALD, Mar. 18, 1999, at 1A; Cuba Law Cracking Down on Dissidents Passed, MIAMI HERALD, Feb. 17, 1999, at 10A. See also supra notes 25 and 35 on Fidel’s political monopoly. 300 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 and, increasingly, globally: human exploitation for short-term profit maximization and personal material enrichment. But the Miami elites also have carved out their well-publicized socioeconomic “enclave” in Miami, an ethnic universe that in many ways parallels the local traditional Anglo establishment and that serves as a springboard both to economic enrichment and inter/national political influence.50 In this enclave’s highly politicized environment, politics, ideology, and class also intersect relentlessly; although the overarching (dis)incentive structure is organized around contemporary capitalism, and although Miami elites do not enjoy the centralized and nearly absolute political power of their Havana counterparts, access to opportunity and comfort in Miami, and especially in the enclave, oftentimes is linked to politics and ideology—more specifically, political allegiance to, and ideological conformance with, the Miami elites and their interests. It is no coincidence that the rich and famous produced by the enclave are time and again elite-identified in both ideological and demographic terms;51 in this circular process, allegiance begets recognition and reward, while opposition attracts the ostracism and oppression—removal from the corridors of opportunity, status, and influence. Thus, both in Miami and in Havana, the elites use ideology to design and engineer class construction. Both here and there, the elites strive to control individuals’ access to personal advancement and enrichment in a manner designed principally to shore up their own political agendas and personal status. Both are unjust because both elevate in structural terms the personal gain of a powerful few at the expense of social equity and progress for the many. C. Global Circus, Domestic Division: Cubans as Sport and Spectacle While Havana’s and Miami’s elites are the principal antagonists in this tragedy, the colossus to the North—the United States, its government and its public—represents an omnipresent set of factors that exert a powerful force on the dynamics of Cubans’ bifurcated state. “Yanquis” are both the audience and actor in myriad and interlacing ways. The government of the United States, like the Havana and Miami elites, is integral to this stalemated status quo; Cuba remains a uniquely sore point for the United 50. See supra note 7 on Miami’s “Latinization.” 51. The Cuban power structure in Miami tends to be white, male, capitalist, and conservative. See generally LEONARD, supra note 17, at 67-78 (describing the “angry exiles” of Miami). Relations between Miami’s Cuban elites and the local Black community generally are distant, or worse. See PORTES & STEPICK, supra note 7, at 177-202 (discussing Miami’s Black communities since the Cuban influx). See also supra note 27 on Cuban demographics in Miami and the United States. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 301 States because it is one of the few “little” countries that ever had the audacity and capacity to stand up, successfully, to the United States and its elites while under their shadow, literally, and because it did so in the midst of a larger bifurcation: the Cold War. The Miami elites and their foot soldiers thus have served a dual role for the government of this country and its ruling elites: while exercising great and sometimes definitive influence over the Cuba policy of the United States government, they also have been used as pawns or surrogates when the United States and its elites have elected to manipulate the exiles’ rigid views of Cuba for their own—and sometimes base—purposes.52 It is no coincidence, after all, that we find Miami Cubans involved in everything from the Watergate burglary in Washington D.C. to the Contra campaign in Nicaragua.53 Thus, the role of the United States—as represented by its formal government agencies and driven by its Left and Right wings—has been less than positive or benign; these North American forces lend legitimacy to their favored camps and thereby create significant impediments to any effort that seeks to transcend the Havana-Miami axis of conflict. The Left in the United States, still in a hangover from the heady days of now-broken revolutionary promises, has romanticized Havana’s elites for years. This romance effectively occludes the horrors the Havana elites perpetrate on the people of Cuba, in particular those who seek to express a dissenting sense of self. As a corollary, the North American Left demonizes not only Miami’s elites in ideological terms, but also in racial and other essentialist and essentializing terms: in the Left’s “progressive” mindset, Cubans in Cuba are imagined and constructed as socially just and principled, and their “mistakes” are unfortunate but due only to the embargo, while Miami’s Cubans are depicted as a crazy bunch of White and spoiled members of Cuba’s pre-Fidelista ruling classes.54 At the same time, the Right in the United States conversely romanticizes Miami’s elites 52. See generally TORRES, supra note 5, at 127. 53. See, e.g., Alfonso Chardy, Cuban Fugitive Tied to Contras’ Supply Delivery, MIAMI HERALD, Aug. 26, 1987, at 18A; Alfonso Chardy, Mas Canosa Helped Cuban Exile Contact Contras, Testimony Says, MIAMI HERALD, May 19, 1988, at 6A; Sandra Dibble, Who’ll Help Our Cause? Cubans Ask Debate Contra Aid, Anti-Castro Battle, MIAMI HERALD, Nov. 2, 1986, at 15A; David Lawrence, Jr., The Man From Watergate, MIAMI HERALD, June 15, 1997, at 3L; Lourdes Merluza, Cuban Contras Recruited in Miami, MIAMI HERALD, June 26, 1986, at 11A; Carol Rosenberg, Plotter of Bay of Pigs, Watergate Conspirator: ‘File and Forget’ Castro, MIAMI HERALD, June 28, 2001, at 4A; Andres Viglucci, Watergate Thief Denies Portrayal in Exile’s Book, MIAMI HERALD, Nov. 20, 1999, at 3B. 54. See generally Susana Barciela, Bashing the Cubans: The Elian Saga Prompted Open Season on Exiles, 13 HISPANIC 128, (2000); Victor M. Diaz, Jr., The Few Liberal Voices Don’t Represent Views of Most Cuban Americans, MIAMI HERALD, May 15, 2000, at 7B; Andres Oppenheimer, Media Bias, Dismissive Labels Anger Cuban Exiles, MIAMI HERALD, Apr. 6, 2000, at 6A; Fabiola Santiago & John Dorschner, Outside Image Bewilders Exiles, MIAMI HERALD, Apr. 23, 2000, at 4B. 302 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 as brave freedom fighters while demonizing Cuba and Havana in similarly essentialist and essentializing ways: Cubans in Cuba are uniformly cast as dictatorial devils with not even a scintilla of principle or vision. In this way, both the Right and the Left prop up the stalemate that divides Cuba and Cubans; for this reason, both the Left and the Right share responsibility with Miami’s and Havana’s elites in the fanatical maintenance of this tense bifurcation. “International public opinion” similarly has helped to construct an unproductive framework for the dueling elites ensconced in Miami and Havana. The resolutions and reports of entities ranging from the United Nations to Amnesty International have shown the same tendencies as the forces within the United States: Leftist groups help to promulgate the propaganda of Havana’s elites and their allies55 while Rightist groups help to promulgate the propaganda of Miami’s elites and their allies.56 Many around the world therefore continue romanticizing Fidel’s regime as the “victim” of the colossus to the North and its Miami puppets, while many others around the world romanticize the exile Cuban community and their North American patrons as valiant upholders of democracy, freedom, and liberty. By valorizing their respective “side” of Cuba’s forced bifurcation, they reinforce the ossified viewpoints and tensions of both Havana and Miami—and thus help to prop them up despite their corrosive and corrupt ways. Thus, both “domestic” political factions and “international public opinion” abet the Miami and Havana elites’ co-construction of this antagonistic discourse, impelling these dueling elites both with substantive and symbolic supports that, in effect, help to drive a destructive wedge between Cubans and other Latinas/os in the United States. Both from the Left and the Right, the Miami elites have been encouraged structurally and pressured politically to digress from progressive agendas on issues ranging from affirmative action, to social welfare, to immigration policy. The confluence of pressures from all sides has been baneful. The Left belittles the Miami elites with ignorant indulgence and reckless acceptance of simplistic race-class stereotypes while slighting legitimate demands for political pluralism and personal liberty on the island, thereby confirming and cementing diasporic fears that only the Right will help in the vindication of these basic human rights—of course, in exchange for the Miami elites’ support of the Right agenda more generally.57 Rather than extend to the Miami elites a principled reason to 55. For one example, see SIMONS, supra note 10, at 33-34 (acknowledging, albeit grudgingly but immediately exculpating the repression of human rights in Cuba by Havana’s elites). 56. For one example, see HOWARD HUNT, GIVE US THIS DAY (1973) (giving a personal account of his involvement in CIA Cuba-related activities by the Watergate burglars). 57. An apt example is the cultivation of Cuban voters by right-wing Republicans since 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 303 align with progressives and people of color in this country’s raging culture wars, the Left has provided many reasons for the Miami elites’ (ultimately misguided) alliance with the Right.58 Moreover, the Left’s internalization of its own dichotomous stereotypes about Cuba and Cubans has caused it to overlook the existence and significance specifically of diasporic Cubans who seek to transcend the internal and international politics of divide-anddestroy pursued relentlessly both from Miami and Havana. The longstanding “progressive” essentialization and demonization of the Miami elites in racial and class terms, coupled with the absurd valorization of the Havana elites in political terms, thereby helps to generate and sustain a general sociolegal climate within the United States that solidifies the Miami elites’ Rightist “domestic” tilt. This, in turn, helps to undermine intra-Latina/o solidarity and truncate coalitional possibilities among people of color, in myriad equality struggles that remain significantly affected by this (mis)alignment of social groups and interests in the inter/national politics of the United States. Contemporaneously, the Right’s essentialization and valorization of the Miami elites as a hard-working “model minority” led by courageous freedom fighters, coupled with the reductionist demonization of the Havana elites as merely typical tyrants, complements this farcical yet serious state of affairs. It is no coincidence, after all, to find Jesse Helms and his ilk squarely in the Miami elites’ ideological corner.59 Thus, from both the Left and the Right, Miami’s (and Havana’s) elites receive external aid and comfort that effectively undercut antisubordination struggles in this country (and beyond it—including on the island itself). While the resulting domestic divisions that alienate Cubans and Cuban Americans from Latinas/os and other people of color in this country may make sense from the selfish and ideological perspective of the Right, it is sheer folly to do so from the principled and progressive perspective of the Left. In both cases, however, it wreaks human havoc and is wrong. Not surprisingly, the ripple effects of the Left’s and Right’s interventions in this tragedy have had the same or similar effects in Cuba. The Right’s romance with Miami and disdain of Havana have helped to engineer the embargo that today provides the Havana elites with a handy pretext to disclaim responsibility for every failure or brutality that they Ronald Reagan decided to target the Cuban vote as the only “minority” camp vulnerable to Republican blandishments. See generally William Schneider, Elian Gonzalez Defeated Al Gore, 33 NAT’L J. 1274 (2001). 58. Whether “cause” or “effect,” the Miami Cuban community generally is described as “conservative,” especially when compared to other Latina/o communities. See, e.g., Mark Falcoff & Elliot Abrams, The Other Cuba, 47 NAT’L REV. 34 (1995). See generally Gerald P. Lopez, Symposium, Learning About Latinos, 19 UCLA CHICANO-LATINO L. REV. 363 (1999). 59. See TORRES, supra note 5, at 144-47 (discussing the effects of the American right). 304 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 perpetrate, and which makes credible to some “observers” the lame excuses offered by Havana elites for their stubborn, decades-long suppression of political diversity on the island.60 Over time and into the present, the Right’s promotion of measures to leverage and tighten the embargo has helped to enable the Havana elites’ concoction of a paranoid siege mentality on the island that has provided the chief excuse for their unending infliction of dictatorship.61 While the Right decidedly bears partial responsibility for the misery and suffering they have licensed on the island, the Left’s romance with Havana also has provided the trappings of credibility for the Havana elites’ blatant tyranny. The Left’s willingness to justify unabashed oppression as an operational necessity of a revolution long ago dead has made it complicit in the Havana elites’ systematic and barbaric mistreatment of Cubans on the island seeking only to claim, secure, and enjoy basic rights and options similar to those that progressives regularly demand for themselves as well as for “subordinated groups” around the globe. Thus, both from the Left and the Right, Havana’s elites have been encouraged politically and pressured structurally to compromise, and effectively to abandon, the progressive agendas they mapped for their revolution four decades ago. In sum, the Left’s romance with Havana and disdain for Miami have produced the same net effect here as the Right’s romance with Miami and disdain for Havana have produced over there: the Right’s partisan promotion of the Miami elites’ agenda nonetheless has allowed the Havana elites to exacerbate and exploit the fears and concerns of Cubans on the island as a means of maintaining their corrupt control, while the Left’s partisan promotion of the Havana elites’ agenda ironically has allowed the Miami elites to excite and exaggerate diasporic fervor and fanaticism. In both cases, the Right and the Left have incited and consolidated the elites’ 60. See id. 61. See Georgie Anne Geyer, Ending the Cuban Embargo Would Perpetuate Castro’s Totalitarian Control, CHI. TRIB., July 7, 2000, at N15; see also Holger Jensen, After Four Decades, Has Embargo Against Cuba Worked?, CAPITOL HILL BLUE, Mar. 13, 2001; AMERICAN ASSOCIATION FOR WORLD HEALTH, “DENIAL OF FOOD AND MEDICINE: THE IMPACT OF THE U.S. E MBARGO ON H EALTH AND NUTRITION IN CUBA,” March 1997, available at http://www.CubaSolidarity.net/ aawh.html; U.S. Department of State: Washington File, Text: Bush Announces Strengthening of Measures Dealing with Cuba (July 13, 2001), available at http://www.usinfo.state.gov/regional/ar/us-cuba/bush13.htm; James Cox, U.S. ponders more aggressive Cuba policy if Helms-Burton law is invoked, lawsuits, troubles with trading partners could increase rapidly, USA TODAY, Apr. 18, 2001, at 3B; U.S. Department of State: Washington File, Powell says Cuban Sanctions Should Remain in Place (Mar. 15, 2001), available at http://www.usinfo.state.gov/regional/ar/us-cuba/powell15.htm; U.S. Department of State: Washington File, U.S. Ambassador Cunningham Remarks on Cuba Embargo at U.N. (Nov. 9, 2000), available at http://www.usinfo.state.gov/ regional/ar/us-cuba/cuba9.htm; Deborah Kalb, 3 Cuban-American lawmakers stand firm against loosening embargo on Cuba, GANNETT NEWS SERVICE, Mar. 13, 1998. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 305 worst fears and regressive political tendencies, simultaneously enhancing both camps’ moral and material resources to wage, year after year, decade after decade, their unjust war against each other and most importantly, at the expense of the Cuban people’s human rights and historical aspirations. The net effect of these interventions, both over here and over there, is to reinforce rigidity, license impunity, and inflame conflict. It is way past time to recognize that both kinds of essentialization, valorization, and demonization are false, exploitative, and destructive. D. Time and Imagination: Toward the Denied Despite the patent falsity of the dichotomy that island and diasporic elites have co-created and propped up since 1959, their ruthless tactics have helped them both to establish and enjoy their social, legal, economic, and political prerogatives over their respective preserves. They have accumulated and marshaled tremendous resources of all kinds, which they now activate and orchestrate to wage their respective parts of this global public relations campaign. Through their respective resources and positioning they have occupied center-stage in public discourse, centering themselves in the public eye as (re)presenting “Cuba” and “Cubans.” Through their resources, and because of their converging interests in stalemate, they opportunistically have co-produced suspenseful displays of life and death, of law and society, and of politics and passion, that from time to time have entertained and riveted the world. The Bay of Pigs in 1961, the Pedro Pan Airlift of the 1960s, the Freedom Flights of the 1970s, the Mariel Exodus of 1980, the Venceremos Brigades, Fidel’s fantastical orations at the Plaza de la Revolucion, the Brothers-to-the-Rescue dogfights and shootdowns, the Elian immigration controversy of 19992000: these inter/national moments of Cuban struggle present but a few of the instances that constitute this long-running, high-ratings coproduction of Havana’s and Miami’s elites.62 Through these opportunities for theatrics, both camps and their political allies in the United States and internationally, slowly but surely have choreographed skewed perceptions that they have hoped, as they still do, eventually will yield favored realities. The high drama and visibility accorded to these bipolar elites and their skirmishes have ingrained their images as the dualistic parameters of national choice in the imagination of Cubans here and there, as well as among the inter/national public more generally. Today, Cuba and Cubans effectively are pushed to choose between these two “communities” and their structures of oppression as all-or-nothing alternatives frozen in time. 62. For a good overview and analysis of this period, see FELIX ROBERTO MASUD-PILOTO, WITH OPEN ARMS: CUBAN MIGRATION TO THE UNITED STATES (1988). 306 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 The push remains powerful, but time stands still for no one and nothing. While today’s elites were consolidating their power and positions, Cuba and Cubans caught in the riptides of their bipolar extremes also have dared to resist and reject both. They—we—have dared to imagine possibilities denied both from here and there. Indeed, Cuba and Cubans never have limited our visions of the possible to the options offered by these two camps: from the inception of today’s bipolar paradigm, Cubans have dared to imagine a future plagued neither by political oppression nor by economic exploitation—I know so because it was precisely this capacity for imagination, and yearning to make it real, that caused my father both to support Fidelismo initially and to flee its tightening grip as a political and economic refugee just a few years later. I have learned since then that his example, while personal to me, was neither unique nor rare in the early days of Fidelismo—nor now.63 Yet, the vision harbored by my father and others like him has been overshadowed during these years, as the elites of Havana and Miami entrenched themselves and eliminated systematically the immediate visibility or viability of any intermediate approach to the project of building a Cuba that, for the first time in Cuban history, would repudiate substantively the traditional stratification of Cuban society and combat proactively the perpetuation of post/neo-colonial subordination under Euroheteropatriarchy.64 In so doing, these elites effectively have collaborated on a project in which both are fundamentally invested: the denial of the possibilities, imagined by persons like my father, that evoke the ideals imagined by the earlier revolutionaries in Cuba—those who fought to tear away Spain’s imperial yoke and to replace it with an egalitarian society, and those who even later sought to conclude Cuba’s historic waves of uprisings with the establishment of the 1940 Constitution.65 In their joint project to deny this possibility, Havana’s elites long have imprisoned anyone who sought seriously to articulate a vision of Cuba in which everyday people enjoyed personal and political freedoms as part of the project of building a postcolonial nation-state, while Miami elites long have harassed anyone who sought seriously to pursue social justice rather than gross economic enrichment as the endgoal of the nation-state.66 Both elites intolerantly have labeled as “enemy” and targeted for vicious attacks anyone who has sought to delineate a vision in which all three generations of human rights 63. See FAGEN ET AL., supra note 15, at 62-97. 64. In some ways, this would vindicate the original revolutions against Spain, which were fought in the name of egalitarian reforms. See generally LEONARD, supra note 17, at 81-83, 153-54; SIMONS, supra note 10, at 157-59. 65. See CARLOS M. PIEDRA Y PIEDRA, LA CONSTITUCION Y EL TRIBUNAL SUPREMO (1943). 66. See, e.g., supra notes 36 and 37 on the use of political violence in Miami. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 307 would be respected not only formally, but also in fact. Both on the island and throughout the diaspora, ideologically opposed elites insist selfrighteously, but increasingly unconvincingly, that either Cuba and Cubans go their way or no way. The selfish interests of both elites have converged, perversely, in the joint construction and maintenance of today’s conflicted and polarized status quo, a scenario that protects little else than the two elites’ own creature comforts and their status systems and symbols. But, in this, their sole collaborative project, the two elites have failed, and it remains only for time to confirm their joint and ultimate failure. The elites on both sides of the Florida Straits have failed because they have not been able to erase the vision of, or still the yearning for, social justice and personal liberty, both on the island and throughout the diaspora. Both on the island and throughout the diaspora, Cubans are working toward principled yet aspirational projects, awaiting and inviting the day in which the joint project of today’s dominant elites will crumble of its own weight. And for this reason, the self-serving fantasies and politics of both sets of elites are doomed. Neither time nor knowledge favors them: though both elites have managed to suppress or occlude the manifestation of these visions and yearnings, dissidents on both sides of the Straits continue to show us that repression from both sides has succeeded in neither. On the island, for instance, a group called “La Patria Es de Todos Cubanos” (The Whole Land Belongs to All Cubans) only recently issued a manifesto that rejects the “deal” imposed by Fidelismo, insisting instead that Cuba and Cubans need not forsake—should not and cannot forsake—political pluralism and individual agency in exchange for social and economic justice.67 They insist, instead, on a national pursuit both of social justice and political freedom. And these dissidents clearly are not alone.68 In refusing submission, these and other dissenters have incurred 67. See The Homeland Belongs to Us All, CUBANET NEWS, Aug. 1, 2001. See also supra notes 17, 18, 25, and 35 on political control and dissidence under Fidel’s government. 68. A prime example of another dissident movement is the Varela Project, which collected a sufficient number of petitions calling for democratic decentralization of power in claimed satisfaction of the Cuban Constitution’s procedure for presenting petitions to the government for legislative consideration. The Varela Project gained attention when Jimmy Carter mentioned it during his visit to the island in 2002; previously, the government had suppressed news of the dissidents’ petition drive. See Cubans Want to Know Text of Varela Project, supra note 48 (describing the Varela Project and Carter’s visit). In a response that effectively serves as a caricature of the Havana elites, the government promptly reported that 99% of the entire population—over eight million people—had turned out to vote on a counter petition proposed by the political machines of Havana’s elites. This turnout was described as “spontaneous” despite the government’s public orchestration of this spectacle. And in a coincidence that might be described as miraculous, all eight million Cubans voted the same way: as their elites had proposed, the island’s masses agreed that the status quo should be declared “untouchable” as a matter of formal law. See Vanessa Bauza, Cuba’s Pro-Socialist Petition Drive Steamrolls Varela Project, ORLANDO SENTINEL, June 24, 2002, at A11. Within a week, in a move reminiscent of corrupt rulers enacting 308 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 personally the wrath of Havana’s elites and their apparati of brute oppression.69 In Miami, in similar fashion, a new generation of Cubans and Cuban Americans has begun to emerge, and to dissent from the orthodoxies of the local elites.70 This generation comprises Cuban children who, like me, arrived in the diaspora while very young, as well as Cuban Americans born in the diaspora after their parent’s flight from the island; like our counterparts on the island, we view the politics and trajectories of “being Cuban” from a broader and more critical perspective, and we decidedly do not see ourselves—or our nation—as necessarily invested in the outcome of the Cold War still being waged from Havana and Miami. As our island counterparts, this new generation does not envision human rights and social policy as a zero-sum game, in which we are forced to elect between some rights and forego other freedoms—or to buy into an Orwellian mindset where rights and violations are transposed by fiat.71 We do not see, and affirmatively reject, the proposition that humans are unable to pursue, simultaneously and as a nation-state, all three generations of human rights in authentic and concrete terms. As in Cuba, this nonconformance to prevailing orthodoxies instigates their repressive retaliations, ranging from social exclusion and public vilification to personal denigration and physical intimidation. On both sides of the Florida Straits, the dominant elites do their best to keep a tight lid on things, using whatever means of power they can grab at the moment. This assessment is neither facile nor partisan. In naming the fate of this perverse strategic collaboration I do not seek to invoke simplistic notions of Fidel’s death or fall followed by a quick and happy return to a false desperate measures in the shadow of their reign’s imminent end, the national Assembly had duly amended the Constitution’s text to formally declare the current elites’ status perpetually “irrevocable.” See Vanessa Bauza, Government Responds to Varela Project with Show of Unity, ORLANDO SENTINEL, July 1, 2002, at A11. This response, however, has not stifled dissent; on the contrary, dissident groups continue to proliferate despite the “unity” and apparent unanimity claimed by the Havana elites. See Vanessa Bauza, New Opposition Document Comes Soon After Varela Project, ORLANDO SENTINEL, Aug. 26, 2002, at A13. 69. See The Right to Dissent Nonexsitent in Cuba, MIAMI HERALD, Mar. 22, 1999, at 20A; Anita Snow, With tough sentences, Cuban attacks dissent, BOSTON GLOBE, Mar. 16, 1999, at A15; Juan O. Tamayo, Cuba Takes Aim at Dissent, Crime Legislation Casts a Wide Net, MIAMI HERALD, Feb. 16, 1999, at 1A; Juan O. Tamayo, Crackdown on Dissent Raises Questions About Castro’s Motives, MIAMI HERALD, Feb. 19, 1999, at 16A. See also supra notes 17, 18, 25, and 35 on tyranny in Cuba. 70. See Anne Moncreiff Arrarte, The quiet rise of the ‘yucas’ in America, 106 U.S. NEWS & WORLD REP. 41 (1989); Constable, supra note 36; LEONARD, supra note 17, at 88. See also supra note 25 on generational shifts within CANF. 71. One relevant indicant of this “new generation” is the participation of Cuban and CubanAmerican scholars in LatCrit Theory. See, e.g., Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, On Becoming the Other: Cubans, Castro and Elian—LatCritical Analysis, 78 DENV. U.L. REV. 687 (2001). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 309 halcyon. The future of Cuba and Cubans is bound to be complex and volatile—and both elites are striving mightily to make sure it is so. On the one hand, Miami’s elites busy themselves with new charters and model codes to effectuate their version of a transition to a conventionally capitalist democracy—having been dispossessed in both political and material terms, they seek a return on both levels and on their terms, as if time had stood still, or could be rolled back.72 On the other hand, Havana’s elites brace themselves for the day when they no longer can depend on the mystique of their supreme leader to buttress the hierarchies that privilege them—having long ago abandoned the principles of their revolution to real-world pressures and self-interested agendas, this mystique and its strategic activation, backed up of course by ever-efficient policing, are key to holding their morally and fiscally bankrupt regime together. In some respects, Havana’s elites must be fearing the inexorable passage of time most of all.73 Both camps, seeking to use time to their advantage, now are working feverishly to retain, and perhaps expand, their positions of status and accumulations of wealth as they prepare for the inevitable death of the man who has engineered so much of this tension and tragedy. However, I also do not seek with this forecast to validate the equally simplistic notion that Fidel’s inevitable date with mortality will leave his cultist orthodoxy and its apparati of social control substantially unaffected. Removing Fidel from the equation can make all the difference in the worlds of the island and the diaspora. Fidel, like other original leaders, commands a unique veneration and obedience within the island because of his unique role in the history of the rise to power of Havana’s dominant elites and their installation in government. Because of this history and positionality, Fidel’s words do carry a unique force on the island—for better or worse.74 But Fidelismo has been internalized by many Cubans throughout the island over the years, and as an ideology it does have a certain substantive coherence: while it cannot justify his cultist dictatorship, Fidel’s critique of neoliberal corporate globalization is cogent, and it can serve as an insightful contribution to antisubordination 72. See generally Ian Ball, US Forces on Standby for Castro’s Death, SUNDAY TEL., July 15, 2001, at 29; Dana Canedy, On Land and Sea, Florida Plans for Turmoil After Castro’s Death, N.Y. TIMES, July 2, 2001, at A1. See also LEONARD, supra note 17, at 87. 73. This point was driven home recently, when Fidel fainted during one of his multi-hour harangues, drawing attention to the unease on the island and among its rulers over the fate of their jefe. See Reuters, Castro Wilts under the Sun, N.Y. TIMES, June 24, 2001, § 1, at 6; Vanessa Bauza, Castro’s Fainting Spell Stirs Speculation About Cuba’s Course, Next Leader, CHI. TRIB., June 25, 2001, at 3; Charles Piggott, What if Castro Died?, 12 WORLD LINK 112 (1999), available at http://www.backissues.worldlink. co.uk.articles/101199171232.htm. 74. See LEONARD, supra note 17, at 88; Envision Cuba Without Castro, CHI. TRIB., July 25, 2001, at 18. 310 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 discourse and inter/national policymaking.75 Thus, Fidel’s unavoidable demise is unlikely to mean the automatic dissolution of Cuba’s governmental infrastructure and disappearance of its reigning ideology, but it does close a singular chapter in the continuing history of Cuba and Cubans—a chapter that, given the mutual intransigence of Havana’s and Miami’s elites, apparently cannot be concluded until then. After that point, I hope, believe, and trust that the following chapters of this continuing story will be written, in part, by Cubans on the island and Cubans in the diaspora, both equally and mutually devoted to Cuban reconciliation on egalitarian, antisubordination, and anti-essentialist principles. E. Broken Promises and Bottom Lines: Human Rights, Cuban Rights Cuba and Cubans face a Hobson’s choice, and both “alternatives” look alike—literally, and demographically. Moreover, both demand abject subordination in social, economic, and political terms to self-anointed elites. Ultimately, both “choices” are fundamentally flawed in common yet different ways: both promise to Cuba and Cubans the vindication of important human rights for the forfeiture of others. Neither promises a post-subordination society. In some key respects, this Hobson’s choice conceptually reflects the structure of human rights as they generally have been conceived and organized internationally during the second half of the Twentieth Century—roughly the same period of time during which Havana and Miami have erected themselves as the mirror images through which Cuba and Cubans are gazed. During this time, international covenants have recognized “three generations” of human rights: (1) “civil and political” rights that, like due process, freedom of conscience, and freedom of association, generally require governments to refrain from interfering with an individual’s right to participate in civil society or the political process; (2) “economic, social, and cultural” rights that seek to secure the elemental components of basic individual well-being and development, such as access to food, housing, education, health care, employment, and participation in the cultural life of the community; and (3) “solidarity and self-determination” rights, which focus on the collective needs of individuals as groups and that include principally the right of a people to choose their own government and, additionally, rights to development, peace, and a healthy environment.76 Their precise contents of course 75. See supra note 13 on Fidel’s political critique of global power arrangements. 76. See Natsu Taylor Saito, Beyond Civil Rights: Considering “Third Generation” International Human Rights Law in the United States, 28 U. MIAMI INTER-AM. L. REV. 387 (1997). See also Elizabeth M. Iglesias, Foreword—International Law, Human Rights and LatCrit Theory, 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 311 remain indeterminate and contested, and to a large extent these rights are honored globally mostly in the breach.77 Nevertheless, these rights are conceived as “indivisible” and “interdependent”—they not only are not susceptible to a cherry-picking approach but they positively depend mutually on each other for their social efficacy.78 This general framework thus provides a ready point of departure for a critical and comparative assessment of the Cuba promised to Cubans both by Havana’s and Miami’s Cuban elites.79 When we step back from the rhetoric of self-justification that envelopes the thinking of both camps’ adherents, we can begin to see how island elites effectively demand that Cuba and Cubans forsake “first generation” human rights in exchange for “second generation” human rights while diasporic elites demand the exact opposite. Neither is overtly cognizant of, nor overly friendly to, third generation group rights—especially those relating to the right of self-determination. Indeed, the totalitarian and authoritarian Cuban regimes in Havana and Miami violate in spirit and in fact the right of the Cuban people to self-determination as a nation, for neither set of elites has shown any serious disposition to let Cuba or Cubans get them out of power and off our backs. In this scheme, Havana’s elites continue pointing to their health and education initiatives, as if bringing better health and expanded awareness to people—a laudable accomplishment—could substitute for, be reconciled with, or justify the simultaneous denial of a people’s right or ability to employ that health and awareness for personally chosen rather than bureaucratically dictated endeavors or projects. Havana’s elites, in effect, boast of their selectively displayed commitment to a more educated and healthy population as if such a population then could not be trusted to 28 U. MIAMI INTER-AM. L. REV. 177 (1997); Berta Esperanza Hernández–Truyol, Building Bridges: Bringing International Human Rights Home, 9 LA RAZA L.J. 69 (1996). See generally INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS IN CONTEXT: LAW, POLITICS, MORALS (Henry J. Steiner & Philip Alston eds., 1996). 77. See generally Bureau of Democracy, Human Rights, and Labor, U.S. Department of State, 1999 Country Reports on Human Rights Practices 6-7 (2000), available at http://www.state.gov.www/global/human-rights/1999.hrp.report/99hrp.toc.html. 78. See supra note 76 on international law and human rights. 79. Of course, the human rights framework is not the only—perhaps not even the best—template to use in deconstructing—and escaping—the dead-end view each camp has of the other, and that both foist on Cuba and Cubans. This formal, imperfect template cannot capture every nuance relating to Cuba and Cubans—nor do I seek to do so in this Essay. Rather, the human rights framework serves here, simply, as one useful lens through which we might access in relatively concrete terms the possibility of another, or alternative, way toward the reconciliation of Cubans and the reconstruction of Cuba on positively egalitarian, antisubordination principles. In this Essay, I use the human rights template only as an example that partially illustrates how and why the two doctrinaire visions of Cuba pushed by the two sets of dominant elites are substantively wanting—and fatally so. 312 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 manage its own affairs in a politically plural and economically decentralized social order. Miami’s elites, meanwhile, rely on neoliberal capitalist platitudes about “hard work” and “opportunity” to justify structural neglect of poverty and related social ills, including lack of proper education and health care based on economic class, as if political or expressive “freedom” could cure or comfort the sick and starving. Miami’s elites, in effect, have been content to go along with the quintessentially elitist blame-game that pities the poor but finds the cause for their lot in their own individual failures—after all, “they” like “us” are “free” to “work hard” and “get ahead” in this “land of opportunity.” Cuba and Cubans thus are under coercive pressure from both elites to relinquish, indeed to renounce and forget about, basic rights that international agreements recognize and promise to all humans. While this nutshell description necessarily oversimplifies, it also captures a fundamental aspect of the current stalemate between Havana’s and Miami’s vision of Cuba: both visions explicitly compromise the indivisibility of human rights and, as applied, both visions also methodically subvert their interdependence. The Hobson’s choice offered by both elites is distilled to social justice versus personal freedom, but never both. Nonetheless, both camps indeed do proffer compelling goals and values. Both camps exude not only fear and insecurity, but also idealistic aspirations. And no intellectually honest reason exists for denying it. No good reason exists to deny or denigrate either the incisiveness of Fidel’s anti-capitalist analysis in the pursuit of international social justice or the importance of the exiles’ insistence on political freedom as a fundamental condition of post-subordination society.80 But neither Fidel’s social justice insights nor the exiles’ focus on personal and political freedom can justify their subordinationist transgressions “at home”: on Fidel’s part, this objection includes the brutal oppression of dissenting voices and systemic acquiescence to Euroheteropatriarchy, and on the exiles’ part, it includes their ready acceptance of “free enterprise” gospels to justify similarly Euroheteropatriarchal structures, precepts, or legacies. In this stalemated scheme, each set of elites offers to Cuba and Cubans something compelling, but both attach unconscionable—and unacceptable—strings: both camps adamantly insist that the vindication of preferred rights must mean the formal and actual surrender—even wholesale violation—of other human rights; or, in the alternative, they demand from us an Orwellian pretension that violations are rights, and that lies are truths. This stalemated scheme neither concedes, tolerates, nor wishes Cuba and Cubans to imagine the possibility of a social and legal order in which 80. For an excellent example, see Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Out in Left Field: Cuba’s Post-Cold War Strikeout, 18 FORDHAM INT’L L.J. 15 (1994). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 313 Cuba and Cubans forsake no human rights but secure and protect them equally for all. Showing themselves decidedly more interested in selfpreservation than in national reconciliation, both camps righteously continue to sow the seeds of enduring suspicion and discord on both sides of the Florida Straits among Cubans already conditioned (poisoned?) by both sides’ extended bombardment of hypocritical misinformation and hyperbolic invective. In the tradition of the “Big Lie,” both have collaborated in the perpetration of a massive and fanatical campaign to make us and the world believe that their self-interested versions of Cuba and Cubans really comprise the only, or best, options toward a postcolonial, post-subordination reconstruction of Cuban society. While both pontificate about the benefits they offer, their aim is to consolidate power and privilege by selling to the Cuban nation an incomplete bill of human rights as Cuban rights. F. Reconciliation and Reconstruction: Five LatCrit Exhortations Many moons may pass before reconciliation and reconstruction come to pass, but pass they shall. Human mortality, and the enduring limits of medical magic, ensure it. The challenge for those of us who seek to pursue a post-subordination order in Cuba is to avoid until then a firm identification with, or internalization of, the inflammatory propaganda generated from either camp or its followers. The challenge is to sift through the records, ideals, and limits of each to learn from both, and to be duped by the seductions of neither. The challenge is to distinguish the “good” from the “bad” in both instances—and toward a combination of both—and more that could provide a principled sociolegal transformation toward Cuba’s progressive emancipation from all forms of oppression. The challenge is to lay a solid foundation for the work that will make it possible for Cuba and Cubans to chart a consensual path toward social justice and political pluralism once the circumstances permit it, a path cut by antisubordination principles rather than by the selfish imperatives of one established elite or another. In this spirit, I conclude with five basic points offered here as LatCrit exhortations: 1. Stay Independent of the Prevalent Bipolarities and Their Politics of Oppression. This first point, obviously, restates the above admonition and provides a basic threshold toward reconciliation and reconstruction. This admonition bears exhortation because it is crucial as a method: without a conscious and conscientious commitment to this independence, we simply cannot sustain our capacity to imagine and pursue the possibilities—to imagine and pursue a post-subordination vision that transcends the limitations imposed by the bents of Havana’s and Miami’s elites. 314 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW Without independence of viewpoint, we progressively compromise our ability to attain and sustain a critical (and self-critical) stance toward the postures and emissions of both bipolar elites—a stance that is necessary to deconstructing the status quo as a first step toward imagining a reconstructed social order. 2. Insist on Critical (and Self-Critical) Approaches to Cuban Reconciliation and Reconstruction. The second point flows from the first, and it also relates to method. Rather than envelop ourselves in sentimental romanticisms about either of the bipolar narratives of Cuban histories and hopes, we must insist instead on critical (and self-critical) analysis of power relations, and of the antisubordination ramifications of actions and policies undertaken both in Havana and in Miami (as well as elsewhere). Sentimentalism—fawning over either set of elites or indulging our idiosyncratic (pre)dispositions toward them—most likely will impair deconstructive, as well as reconstructive, analysis and praxis, and thus inhibit our capacity for envisioning, as capaciously as possible, the design of a post-subordination, postcolonial era in Cuba. Without a genuine commitment to criticality and independence, we cannot hope to pierce through the powerful and entrenched cosmologies that have been concocted and enacted on both sides of the Florida Straits so assiduously since 1959. 3. Frame Reconciliation and Reconstruction Around Egalitarian Vindication of the “Three Generations” of Human Rights. This point relies on the broad assortment of international convenants, and their ultimate human rights aspirations, as a general—even partial—but nonetheless substantive source for the development of a postcolonial, post-subordination social and legal order in Cuba. While patently limited and breached routinely worldwide, this formal international human rights model repudiates as a substantive matter key demands of both elites: that the Cuban people effectively and formally abandon the hope and pursuit of a national community dedicated in principle, as well as in fact, to all three of the rights “generations” conceived thus far by humanity. This third LatCrit exhortation instead affirms the global notion that all human rights are “interdependent” and “indivisible” and asserts that a principled and actual vindication of all human rights for all humans is the only path toward a post-subordination, postcolonial Cuba. And because it provides an approach to reconstruction that is independent of either elites’ ideological delimitations, this international rights framework also helps to provide a substantive anchor [Vol. 55 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE for the first point—this third exhortation, in other words, shifts from method to substance, and does not preclude in any way the use of other substantive sources for the design of Cuban reconciliation and reconstruction along antisubordinationist lines. Substantively, then, this third exhortation points to a forthright rejection of both elites and their agendas; an egalitarian vindication of human rights visá-vis Cuba and Cubans calls for the elimination both of the embargo and of Fidel’s monopoly on social, economic, and political life in the island. This point beckons Cuba and Cubans to take a substantively independent approach toward national reconciliation and reconstruction based on international sources and developments that transcend the Miami-Havana scripts for our common future. 4. Commit to the Project of Reconciliation and Reconstruction and to the Proactive Social and Legal Dismantling of Euroheteropatriarchy. The fourth exhortation takes the substantive commitment of egalitarian reconciliation and reconstruction further, calling for a specific commitment to the dismantlement of a particular sociolegal ideology, which has been and continues to be hegemonic in Cuban society and culture. While the national reconciliation project beneficially may be framed, at least partially, around the three generations of human rights as a general and independent grounding, the project must be focused specifically on the dismantlement of Euroheteropatriarchy because the structures, imperatives, and agents of this particular ideology are, in Cuba and among Cubans, key and pervasive sources of subordination that systematically deny rights to nonconforming persons and projects while systematically promoting conforming persons and projects. Because this pernicious ideology still accounts for so much of Havana’s and Miami’s sociolegal architecture, the antisubordination reconstruction of Cuba as a post-subordination society requires us to focus consciously and explicitly on the material dismantlement and social disablement of Euroheteropatriarchy. 5. Demand Disgorgement of Unjust Riches and Reallocation of Social Goods as Integral to Cuba’s Reconstruction as a Post-subordination Society. This fifth and final exhortation presents perhaps the most difficult hurdle, but it flows directly from the prior four. This point recognizes a bottom line learned from prior antisubordination experience: that social justice, if it is to be more than a cynical platitude, hinges on social transformation—even if orderly and incremental. Transformation, in turn, denotes and requires an 315 316 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 actual reallocation of social goods; transformation without disgorgement and reallocation is but another “Big Lie.” The disgorgement of unjust past gains, and the reallocation of existing and future social goods, no doubt will entail a long and arduous process of national dialogue as part of the reconciliation project. These redistributive efforts also will require creative negotiation of myriad interests and conflicts. But without confronting the past and present maldistribution of social goods and economic assets on the island as a structural source of widespread misery, the resilient legacies of Euroheteropatriarchal colonialism will continue to bedevil Cuba and Cubans. The objective—and challenge—is to ground our approach to and resolution of these issues in egalitarian antisubordination principles and communitybuilding values. Though exceedingly difficult to accomplish due to the perpetual problem of entrenched and reactionary interests, this final LatCrit exhortation nonetheless is indispensable to reconstructing Cuba as a post-subordination society that repudiates in fact, rather than merely in words, the enduring material and cultural manifestations of its post/neo/colonial histories and legacies. These five points obviously are not, and are not proffered here as, a panacea. On the contrary, these exhortations serve only as a point of departure for a reciprocal and open dialogue toward reconciliation and reconstruction. As a set, they identify some difficult issues that, for some time, may even be intractable—especially if the dominant elites continue to have their way most of the time. These five LatCrit exhortations recognize the daunting nature of the enterprise and work, therefore, to root it in substantive social justice commitments that usefully may help to inform the conception and negotiation of reconciliation and reconstruction. Rather than posit a nebulous ideal or ultimate fantasy, these points and exhortations can serve as one antisubordinationist and anti-essentialist basis with which Cubans collaboratively may begin to delineate an agenda for a “reunion” of the island and the diaspora without structurally or ideologically preadvantaging any subset of “Cubans”—or the unilateral customs that may have been instilled amongst us during this nearly half century of division and divisiveness. Though susceptible to manipulation, these points and exhortations can provide some common ground for a discourse of reconciliation, and the project of reconstruction, among and between Cubans there, here, and elsewhere around the globe. If pursued earnestly and cooperatively, these points may yet provide a sturdy platform and flexible framework for the development of a postcolonial society built on substantive and principled antisubordination commitments rather than on broken promises or selfish interests. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 317 II. CONCLUSION My father is now ninety-one years old and declining steadily. Bemused at having witnessed the dawn of a new millennium, my father knows that he never will see his vision of a “free” Cuba materialize in his homeland. But he and others like him, whether on the island, here, or elsewhere on the globe, have planted seeds of principle and vision that continue to flower and blossom. The future is not his, nor is it Fidel’s or his adversaries’—it is, instead, ours: Cubans at the margins of this century’s dichotomies, who are captive neither to Miami nor to Havana, and who seek instead a principled alternative to both. If ever you visit either of my two hometowns during this era of diaspora and deadlock—and as you enjoy their local delights, including their respective versions of Cuban cuisine and culture—look around you for subtle signs of the histories and hopes sketched above, and you will see them. In this way, you may begin to navigate for yourself the slivers of unoccupied space that exist stubbornly between the bipolar narratives urged upon you from Miami and Havana. In this way, and over time, you may become able to help us—Cubans there and here—to navigate successfully the treacherous shoals of contention and manipulation that have co-enabled the elites here and there jointly to keep Cubans apart while we remain a nation. CLUSTER III INTRODUCTION Angela P. Harris I. INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 319 II. RACE AND CRIMINAL PROCEDURE . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 324 III. CONCLUSION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 337 I. INTRODUCTION In this cluster, Alfredo Mirandé, Christopher Slobogin, and Kevin Johnson provide a LatCrit view of the jurisprudence of criminal procedure. Mirandé, examining recent Supreme Court decisions, argues that there is convincing evidence that the Fourth Amendment proscription on unreasonable searches and seizures has a “Mexican exception,”1 and wonders “whether non-resident aliens have sufficient connection to the United States to be considered one of ‘the people.’”2 Slobogin, examining the same set of cases as Mirandé, suggests that the decisions better support the existence of an “illegal alien”3 exception rather than an exception specific to Mexicans.4 Slobogin then speculates that another—perhaps the most likely—impetus for the Court’s criminal procedure jurisprudence is a tone-deafness to the hardships of poverty.5 Finally, Kevin Johnson points out the similarities between racial profiling in domestic law enforcement and in immigration enforcement, and identifies the common interest that Latinas/os and African Americans have in challenging these practices despite the obstacles that stand in the way of a political alliance.6 Criminal procedure in the United States is a field so inextricably intertwined with race that Charles Ogletree has described it as a branch of American race law.7 Yet it differs markedly from antidiscrimination law, 1. Alfredo Mirandé, Is There a “Mexican Exception” to the Fourth Amendment, 55 FLA. L. REV. 365 (2003). 2. Id. 3. Christopher Slobogin, The Poverty Exception to the Fourth Amendment, 55 FLA. L. REV. 391 (2003). 4. Id. 5. Id. at 392. 6. Kevin R. Johnson, The Case for African American and Latina/o Cooperation in Challenging Racial Profiling in Law Enforcement, 55 FLA. L. REV. 341 (2003). 7. Gary Peller, Criminal Law, Race, and the Ideology of Bias: Transcending the Critical Tools of the Sixties, 67 TUL. L. REV. 2231, 2245 (1993) (citing Charles Ogletree, Lecture at the 319 320 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 that body of law that most explicitly addresses issues of race and racism. Students of the law of antidiscrimination in employment, voting, and education are familiar with the Supreme Court’s increasingly emphatic pronouncements of the dangers of racial classification. We are told that state racial classifications are inherently politically divisive and socially damaging; that they create psychological trauma and lasting stigma; that state racial classifications constitute racial discrimination in and of themselves; and that explicitly race-based state action must always receive the strictest judicial scrutiny.8 Racialization of the law, in short, is an extremely dangerous thing. The authors in this cluster all agree that the American criminal justice system is dramatically racialized.9 The statistics are shocking and yet utterly familiar. As Johnson notes, African Americans constitute more than fifty percent of the population of prisons and jails in the United States, despite the fact that they constitute only twelve percent of the population; Latinas/os make up one-third of the prison populations in California and New York, despite the fact that they constitute only twenty-seven and thirteen percent of the population, respectively.10 Yet, in stark contrast to American Association of Law Schools Annual Meeting (Jan. 1990)). 8. See, e.g., Shaw v. Reno, 509 U.S. 630, 643 (1993): Classifications of citizens solely on the basis of race “are by their very nature odious to a free people whose institutions are founded upon the doctrine of equality,” . . . . They threaten to stigmatize individuals by reason of their membership in a racial group and to incite racial hostility . . . . “[E]ven in the pursuit of remedial objectives, an explicit policy of assignment by race may serve to stimulate our society’s latent race consciousness, suggesting the utility and propriety of basing decisions on a factor that ideally bears no relationship to an individual’s worth or needs.” Id. (citations omitted); see also Rice v. Cayetano, 528 U.S. 495, 515 (2000) (defining “‘racial discrimination’ [as] that which singles out ‘identifiable classes of persons . . . solely because of their ancestry or ethnic characteristics’”); Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña, 515 U.S. 200, 224 (1995) (concluding the Court’s precedents establish that “any person, of whatever race, has the right to demand that any governmental actor subject to the Constitution justify any racial classification subjecting that person to unequal treatment under the strictest judicial scrutiny”). 9. See generally Mirandé, supra note 1; Slobogin, supra note 3; Johnson, supra note 6. 10. See Johnson, supra note 6, at 347 n.31 (citing statistics cited by Kenneth Nunn and Margaret Montoya). As I write this Essay, a study by the Institute for Children, Youth and Families at Michigan State University has found that Latino youths receive longer terms of incarceration (and other harsher penalties) than White youths charged with the same offenses. See Latino Juvenile Offenders Get Harsher Treatment, Study Finds, 32 CRIM. JUST. NEWSL. 13, 2 (2000): For example, among youths with no prior admissions to state correctional facilities, Latinos charged with violent offenses were more than five times as likely as whites to be incarcerated, (as opposed to other . . . sanctions). Latinos charged 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 321 the Court’s fears about race-consciousness in education, employment, and voting, the Court has been reluctant to take seriously the possibility that state action might be necessary to combat the extreme racialization of American criminal justice. Representative in this regard is the Court’s opinion in McCleskey v. Kemp.11 In that case, the Court considered Eighth Amendment and Fourteenth Amendment equal protection challenges to Georgia’s death penalty statute.12 Warren McCleskey, a Black man sentenced to death for the murder of a White police officer during the course of a robbery, sought habeas corpus relief with the help of a sophisticated statistical study conducted by Professor David Baldus and his colleagues.13 The study revealed, among other things, that persons who murdered Whites were statistically much more likely to be sentenced to death than were persons who murdered Blacks, and that Black murderers were more likely to be sentenced to death than White murderers.14 In its opinion, the Court affirmed in no uncertain terms its commitment to eradicating racial prejudice from the criminal justice system.15 Nevertheless, citing the familiar antidiscrimination principle that racial discrimination must be with property offenses were nearly [twice] as likely as whites to be incarcerated . . . . [F]or drug offenses, the admission rate for Latinos was 13 times the rate for white youths, [and] . . . the average term . . . was more than double that of whites . . . . Id. at 2-3. Overall, incarcerated Latino youths served an average of 305 days, compared to 193 days for White youths, and Latino youths were found to be “incarcerated in adult jails and prisons at far higher rates than white youths . . . rates two to three times higher in nine states, three to six times higher in eight states, and seven to 17 times higher in four states.” Id. at 3. 11. 481 U.S. 279 (1987). 12. See id. 13. Id. at 283, 286-87. 14. See id. at 286. For example, Baldus and his colleagues found that, even after taking into account thirty-nine nonracial variables, defendants charged with killing White victims were 4.3 times more likely to receive a death sentence than were other defendants. Id. at 287. The study also found that prosecutors sought the death penalty in 70% of the cases involving Black defendants and White victims; 15% of the cases involving Black defendants and Black victims; and 19% of the cases involving White defendants and Black victims. Id. at 286-87. 15. See id. at 309-10: Because of the risk that the factor of race may enter the criminal justice process, we have engaged in “unceasing efforts” to eradicate racial prejudice from our criminal justice system. Our efforts have been guided by our recognition that “the inestimable privilege of trial by jury . . . is a vital principle, underlying the whole administration of criminal justice.” Thus, it is the jury that is a criminal defendant’s fundamental “protection of life and liberty against race or color prejudice.” Id. (citations omitted) (footnotes omitted). 322 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 conscious and deliberate to violate the Equal Protection Clause, the Court rejected McCleskey’s claim because he could not prove that the prosecutors, the jury, or the Georgia Legislature had acted, in his particular case, with a discriminatory purpose.16 Although the Court accepted Baldus’ statistical findings as accurate for purposes of deciding the claim, the Court made equally clear that these findings, although shocking, did not constitute proof of discriminatory purpose:17 “Because discretion is essential to the criminal justice process, we would demand exceptionally clear proof before we would infer that the discretion has been abused.”18 The Court expanded on this position in its Eighth Amendment discussion: McCleskey’s argument that the Constitution condemns the discretion allowed decisionmakers in the Georgia capital sentencing system is antithetical to the fundamental role of discretion in our criminal justice system. . . . Where the discretion that is fundamental to our criminal process is involved, we decline to assume that what is unexplained is invidious.19 In their now-classic book, Racial Formation in the United States,20 Michael Omi and Howard Winant treat political activity as “the continuous process of formation and superseding of unstable equilibria.”21 In this view, “the state” is best understood not as a unity, but as an unruly field of institutions and individual and collective entrepreneurs, pursuing various 16. 17. 18. 19. at stake: Id. at 298-99. Id. at 297. Id. Id. at 311-13. In the last section of its opinion, the Court expressed its view on what was McCleskey’s claim, taken to its logical conclusion, throws into serious question the principles that underlie our entire criminal justice system. The Eighth Amendment is not limited in application to capital punishment, but applies to all penalties. Thus, if we accepted McCleskey’s claim that racial bias has impermissibly tainted the capital sentencing decision, we could soon be faced with similar claims as to other types of penalty. Moreover, the claim that his sentence rests on the irrelevant factor of race easily could be extended to apply to claims based on unexplained discrepancies that correlate to membership in other minority groups, and even to gender. Id. at 316-37 (citations omitted) (footnotes omitted). Justice Brennan, in his dissent, described this concern, ironically, as a “fear of too much justice.” Id. at 339 (Brennan, J., dissenting). 20. MICHAEL OMI & HOWARD WINANT, RACIAL FORMATION IN THE UNITED STATES: FROM THE 1960S TO THE 1990S (2d ed. 1994). 21. Id. at 84 (citing ANTONIO GRAMSCI, SELECTIONS FROM THE PRISON NOTEBOOKS 182 (Quentin Hoare & Geoffrey Nowell Smith eds., 1971)). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 323 material and ideological projects.22 Some of these projects conflict, and some are consistent with one another; some projects gain strength over time, while others diminish in their political support.23 At the same time, Omi and Winant claim that in the United States, “the state is inherently racial,”24 by which they mean that “[f]ar from intervening in racial conflicts, the state is itself increasingly the preeminent site of racial conflict.”25 Putting these insights together, they argue: Every state institution is a racial institution, but not every institution operates in the same way. In fact, the various state institutions do not serve one coordinated racial objective; they may work at cross-purposes. Therefore, race must be understood as occupying varying degrees of centrality in different state institutions and at different historical moments.26 The law, I will argue, plays two important roles in the Constitution and maintenance of state-centered racial projects. First, since legal rules are central to the organization of all state action generally, and since race itself is such a creature of the law in the United States, legal rules are central to the Constitution and maintenance of racial projects with which state institutions are involved. Second, legal doctrine and ideology serve a jurisdictional function, making it possible for state racial projects that are very different, perhaps even opposed to one another, to coexist. Recent criminal procedure jurisprudence—the subject of this Cluster—provides an example of these two functions of the law. While one type of racialized state project—the social welfare state—has been under recent attack, another racialized state project—the penal state—is on the ascendancy. Both the social welfare state and the penal state interact with various institutions of the capitalist state, which itself is complexly racialized. Legal rules shape the meaning of race; the meaning of race, in turn, affects the fortunes of various state projects. Meanwhile, legal doctrine and legal ideology make it possible for various state projects to coexist. Opinions like that of the majority in McCleskey v. Kemp reconcile the egalitarian ideals of the social welfare project with the racialist practices of the penal state. The jurisprudence of the Fourth Amendment similarly allows both Mirandé’s “Mexican Exception” and Slobogin’s race-neutrality to find a place in the law. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. Id. at 84-85. Id. at 83. Id. at 82. Id. Id. at 83. 324 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 II. RACE AND CRIMINAL PROCEDURE According to Alfredo Mirandé, “[t]he answer to the question of whether there is a Mexican Exception to the Fourth Amendment is at once both complex and at the same time remarkably simple.”27 The complex answer has to do with the reasoning the Court has offered to explain its holdings. As Mirandé notes: While the [Supreme Court and other] courts have consistently held that in principle Hispanic, or Mexican, appearance is not sufficient to justify a stop, they have also held that Hispanic appearance is one of several factors that may, in conjunction with other articulable facts which, as in Terry, “taken together with rational inferences from those facts, reasonably warrant that intrusion.”28 Under current Fourth Amendment jurisprudence, the apparent race of a suspect alone is not enough to support a stop, but race is a permissible factor to be considered if it is one among many other factors. For Mirandé, however, this principle must be understood in terms of how it is actually applied by law enforcement: The reality of course is that there is a Mexican Exception. Mexican appearing persons are routinely stopped with articulable facts that are consistent with law-abiding behavior such as driving on a highway within 100 air miles of the border, driving a late model sedan, wearing a cap, and driving a car that appears to be weighed down, or has a number of passengers in it.29 In addition, “either looking at the officers, or not looking at the officers, may be interpreted as suspicious conduct.”30 If these “other factors” only justify suspicion when combined with apparent Mexican ancestry, then the suspect’s race is the controlling factor after all. Christopher Slobogin challenges Mirandé’s assertion that there is a Mexican Exception. Carefully examining Supreme Court opinions, he argues that, with one exception,31 the cases better support an “illegal alien” 27. Mirandé, supra note 1, at 385. 28. Id. 29. Id. at 385-86. 30. Id. at 386. 31. Slobogin concedes that United States v. Martinez-Fuerte, 428 U.S. 543 (1976), seems to support the existence of such an exception, but condemns the decision. Slobogin, supra note 3, at 399. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 325 exception.32 As Slobogin points out, the Court has never limited its analysis or holdings in such a way as to restrict its relaxed judicial review to cases involving Mexicans.33 The mere fact that many of the case names are Mexican does not suggest that other undocumented immigrants are immune to prosecution, nor have any of the Justices suggested that Mexican origin makes any difference to the analysis. Whether Slobogin is really in disagreement with Mirandé, however, is not clear. Mirandé’s argument may not be that the Supreme Court has created a doctrinal, “law on the books” Mexican Exception, but rather that the Supreme Court has created the rhetorical and practical space for law enforcement officials to create their own “law in action” Mexican Exception. If this is so, Slobogin’s analysis does not really contradict Mirandé’s. Slobogin is concerned not with what the police and the INS actually do, but with what the Supreme Court says can be done. On this level, he is persuasive that the Court’s Fourth Amendment jurisprudence supports a much broader underlying principle than a Mexican Exception. Yet, as Slobogin concedes, at the Mexican border, phenotypical race is relevant, perhaps central, to the project of identifying suspected undocumented immigrants.34 Since it is the United States border with Mexico, and not with Canada that is most politically charged and, therefore, most intensively policed, the “illegal alien” exception and the Mexican Exception are largely contiguous. One way, then, to think about the seeming conflict between Mirandé and Slobogin is to think of it as the difference between “law on the books” and “law on the ground.” Another way is to see their conversation as reflecting the juxtaposition of two different racialized projects of state power. It would be surprising, indeed shocking, if there were a Mexican Exception at the level of constitutional doctrine. Since Plessy v. Ferguson,35 the Supreme Court has interpreted the Fourteenth Amendment to require that the state act in a race-neutral manner. Moreover, Plessy’s interpretation of the equality principle served as a legal foundation for the American social welfare state, a loose set of institutions including not only the components of the “social safety net” (unemployment insurance, Social Security, AFDC), but also, in the wake of Brown v. Board of Education,36 a federal administrative apparatus that manages employment, education, public family law, collects data, and issues statistics according to strict rules set forth by the judiciary. These rules prohibit malignant raceconscious “state action” in an ever-widening number of arenas, while at the 32. 33. 34. 35. 36. See id. at 392-99. See id. See id. at 398. 163 U.S. 537 (1896). 347 U.S. 483 (1954). 326 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 same time keeping track of people by racial classification for the purpose of administering antidiscrimination law. Even while the Court’s understanding of race-consciousness gradually broadened and its understanding of invidious state action narrowed, the Court was able, as in Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña,37 to insist that its Fourteenth Amendment jurisprudence was unified by the suspect nature of state racial classifications.38 Defenders of this racialized social welfare state have pointed out that the ideal of equal citizenship has permitted an ever widening group of those formerly excluded from national citizenship to claim legal, political, and social rights.39 Leftist critics of this project have condemned the project’s focus on the individual and its failure to recognize the ways in which the values and privileges of elites are taken as the standard for those later to be “included.”40 Nevertheless, the liberal project remains home base for most lawyers concerned with racial justice. Indeed, in some ways liberal legalism is synonymous both with “the state” (as contrasted to “the market”) and with “the rule of law” itself. Liberal legalism is also inextricably interwined with a mode of governance that gives legal professionals, social science professionals, and other “experts,” great authority and influence in the making of government policy. Austin Sarat and Jonathan Simon argue that this mode of governance has been focused on managing the “social” sphere: For more than a century of “reform,” which culminated in the “welfare state” of the 1950s, 1960s, and 1970s, the liberal rationality of government associated with laissez faire capitalism41 and methodological individualism was generally 37. 515 U.S. 200 (1995). 38. Id. at 223-24 (identifying “skepticism,” “consistency,” and “congruence” as the unifying principles of equal protection jurisprudence). 39. See, e.g., KENNETH L. KARST, BELONGING TO AMERICA: EQUAL CITIZENSHIP AND THE CONSTITUTION (1989). Karst defines the “principle of equal citizenship” thusly: “Each individual is presumptively entitled to be treated by the organized society as a respected, responsible, and participating member. Stated negatively, the principle forbids the organized society to treat an individual as a member of an inferior or dependent caste or as a nonparticipant.” Id. at 3. 40. See Angela P. Harris, Beyond Equality: Power and the Possibility of Freedom in the Republic of Choice, 85 CORNELL L. REV. 1181, 1185 (2000). 41. I disagree with Sarat and Simon’s characterization of the economy in this period as “laissez faire capitalism.” Rather, I would argue that the dominance of “the social” as the paradigm of governance is strongly associated with the so-called economic “Golden Age,” during which growth was high and economists confident of their ability to smooth out the highs and lows of the business cycle and to control inflation with fiscal and monetary policy. In economics during this period, as in the other social sciences, the prestige and confidence of experts in their ability to manage large-scale institutions and forces was at a maximum. See MICHAEL PERELMAN, THE PATHOLOGY OF THE U.S. ECONOMY REVISITED: THE INTRACTABLE CONTRADICTIONS OF ECONOMIC 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 327 reordered around the social as a terrain for positive knowledge and effective governmental intervention . . . . In the twentieth century, . . . [t]he space of legal constructs was colonized and occupied by “facts” generated by social scientists. Law and government came to rely heavily on the methodologies and constructs of the social sciences in order to shape the exercise of governmental power in areas as diverse as prisons, schools, and labor . . . . Thus, whether we look to government policy, legal doctrine, or social science, the residue of the era of social liberalism remains a powerful fusion of law, social science, and government.42 More recently, however, as Sarat and Simon recognize, governance by reliance on experts on “society” has come under attack. In the late 1960s and early 1970s, a long economic boom period gave way to a steady decline in prosperity. By the late 1970s and early 1980s, right-wing political activists and politicians, reinventing themselves as “neoconservatives,” were using the economic crisis as an opportunity to attack government policies and programs associated with the “left,” such as affirmative action and programs like Aid to Families with Dependent Children; to reject Keynesian economics in favor of new laissez-faire corporatist, “supply side” economic policies; and more broadly to attack “Big Government,” or the ideal of governance through management of “the social,” itself.43 Legally, the project of dismantling the social welfare state has been associated with the capture of the federal judiciary by neoconservatives and libertarian sympathizers, and with the concomitant moves to restrict civil rights and liberties, to cut taxes, and to expand corporate and property rights as they have been traditionally understood.44 Even in the heyday of the social welfare state, however, the government’s commitment to racial egalitarianism was always sharply limited by its relatively narrow scope. As I have discussed elsewhere, Plessy45 inaugurated an era in which White supremacy, though banished from official state policy, was allowed to thrive in the realm of “custom” and “the social”—a realm that included employment, education, industrial POLICY 15-17 (2002). 42. Austin Sarat & Jonathan Simon, Beyond Legal Realism?: Cultural Analysis, Cultural Studies, and the Situation of Legal Scholarship, 13 YALE J.L. & HUMAN. 3, 5-6 (2001). 43. Emblematic here is Margaret Thatcher’s famous statement, “There is no society. There are only individuals and families.” Jon Margolis, Market Versus Family Values; GOP Debate Cut to Core About Conservatism’s Vision, CHI. TRIB., Mar. 24, 1996, at C7, available at 1996 WL 2655294. 44. See generally Frank Valdes, Culture, ‘Kulturkampf,’ and Beyond: The Antidiscrimination Principle Under the Jurisprudence of Backlash (unpublished manuscript on file with author). 45. 163 U.S. 537 (1896). 328 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 production and exchange, and residential housing patterns.46 The revolution marked by Brown v. Board of Education47 and the antidiscrimination statutes passed during the “Second Reconstruction” brought housing, employment, and education into the realm of “the public,” but cases such as Milliken v. Bradley48 and Washington v. Davis49 thereafter indicated that nonconscious action and “market forces” would remain shielded from the mandate of racial equality. Moreover, the egalitarianism required by the Fourteenth Amendment was always limited by that amendment’s limitation to citizens. Noncitizen residents of the United States, including most Asian American immigrants before 1952 and many Mexican immigrants, remained subject to color-conscious state policy.50 Despite their egalitarian aspirations, the institutions of the welfare state were deeply “raced” and “gendered” from the beginning, as policymakers took race into account in their efforts to distinguish between the deserving and the undeserving poor.51 As welfare was increasingly marked as African American, welfare policies grew more punitive until “welfare as we know it” was finally abolished altogether.52 The familial administrative state, as Dorothy Roberts has documented, has also been racialized:53 nonwhite women and children are disproportionately subject to stunning levels of neglect and brutality in the adoption and foster care system.54 Gabriel Chin has examined the ways in which administrative governance served to enforce the federal policy of Asian exclusion in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.55 Finally, governance in the name of “the social” generally, and the social welfare state in particular, never completely displaced older forms of governance. Kevin Johnson’s essay in this cluster explores the parallels between the contemporary state projects of immigration enforcement and 46. See generally Angela P. Harris, Equality Trouble: Sameness and Difference in TwentiethCentury Race Law, 88 CAL. L. REV. 1923 (2000). 47. 347 U.S. 483, 495 (1954) (concluding that racial segregation in public elementary schools is inconsistent with the Equal Protection Clause). 48. 418 U.S. 717, 745 (1974) (noting that federal courts lack the power to impose interdistrict remedies for school segregation absent an interdistrict violation or interdistrict effects). 49. 426 U.S. 229, 238-43 (1976) (noting that violations of the Equal Protection Clause require proof of discriminatory intent, not merely of discriminatory effect). 50. See Harris, supra note 46. 51. DOROTHY ROBERTS, KILLING THE BLACK BODY: RACE, REPRODUCTION, AND THE MEANING OF LIBERTY 204 (1997). 52. Id. at 208-09. 53. See id. See generally DOROTHY E. ROBERTS, SHATTERED BONDS: THE COLOR OF CHILD WELFARE (2002). 54. See ROBERTS, supra note 51, at 273. 55. Gabriel J. Chin, Regulating Race: Asian Exclusion and the Administrative State, 37 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 1, 37 (2002). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 329 domestic criminal law enforcement from the perspective of racial exclusion.56 These state activities can be linked to a more generalized state project: the penal state. Governments are responsible not only for “law” but for “order” as well; if liberal legalism represents the “law” in this equation, then the penal state—also sometimes referred to as the sovereign state—represents “order.” The areas controlled by the state in its role as sovereign include domestic policing, immigration and naturalization matters, foreign policy, including treaty making, and war making.57 Violence is a prominent feature of the sovereign state: domestic law enforcement and immigration, for example, are areas in which state officials are explicitly authorized to use violence against lawbreakers.58 Additionally, in the sense in which “law” 56. See generally Johnson, supra note 6. 57. Family law can be understood as a project related to the project of the sovereign state. Like penal law, family law traditionally has provided generously for the exercise of White supremacy. More recently, the racial norms of the liberal project have slowly begun to infiltrate family law, in the wake of Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967) (holding that antimiscegenation statutes are unconstitutional under the Equal Protection Clause). Yet, explicit racial management has been slow to disappear. For example, in the context of the Multiethnic Placement Act, a federal statute intended to foster transracial adoptions, Rachel Moran explains: Although the law is designed to establish a norm of colorblindness, enforcement officials continue to acknowledge the social and cultural relevance of race to family formation. Race is considered in evaluating parental competency at two levels. In the first place, the placement process can accommodate a prospective parent’s preference for a child of the same race . . . . After personal preferences are ascertained, race enters the process again when adoption agencies make objective evaluations of parental fitness. Because culture is presumptively relevant even though race is not, federal law leaves considerable room for same-race placements to persist out of concern that adoptive parents are not competent to raise children from a different background. By failing to define culture yet forbidding its use as a proxy for race, official interpretations hardly clarify which parenting strategies are desirable and which are disqualifying. Federal officials do not say whether colorblind parenting is culturally insensitive or racially neutral. Nor do they tell adoption agencies whether color-conscious parenting is culturally competent or racist. Far from making a norm of colorblindness clear, current federal law leaves the mystery of what constitutes healthy racial socialization unsolved. RACHEL F. MORAN, INTERRACIAL INTIMACY: THE REGULATION OF RACE AND ROMANCE 143 (2001). 58. The practices of military, police, and immigration officials often overlap. Domestic police forces were developed on the model of the military, and the arm of the Immigration and Naturalization Service (INS) concerned with enforcement is organized similarly. In fact, critics have regularly complained about the “militarization” of both police and immigration practices, particularly in light of the various civil “wars” that presidential administrations have declared, first on drugs and more recently on terrorism. For one critique of the militarization of border control, see Timothy J. Dunn, Border Militarization Via Drug and Immigration Enforcement: Human 330 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 is commonly opposed to “politics,” political strategy is at the forefront of the workings of the sovereign state. The liberal legal state of rights where the rule of law holds sway is a place of reason and argument; the sovereign legal state is a place where might makes right, and power, rather than reason, settles disputes. Where the liberal state treats its citizens as lacking in bodies, the penal state manages power through the marking and management of bodies. For Machiavelli, sovereign power is the “register in which sexuality and political purpose are thoroughly entwined.”59 As feminist scholars have demonstrated in detail, the exercise of sovereign power, whether by the military, the police, or border officials, is thoroughly masculinist: hostile to both women and sexual minorities as a matter of principle as well as practice.60 Race also has long been central to the exercise of sovereign power in the United States. American history suggests that the social projects of creating the nation, and of creating the idea of “whiteness,” have long been intertwined.61 This is perhaps the most profound sense in which Omi and Winant are correct that the United States is a “racial state.” As Ian Haney López points out, the very first federal naturalization statute specified that prospective citizens of the United States be “White.”62 The post-Civil War amendment of this statute to permit naturalization by persons of African descent left in place the power of the national government to exclude other nonwhite groups, a power that has been treated as “plenary.”63 From this perspective, the “Mexican Exception” of which Mirandé speaks is only one of the most recent manifestations of the continuing political project that historian Rogers Smith describes as “ascriptive Americanism.”64 Rights Implications, 28 SOC. JUST. 7 (2001). 59. Wendy Brown, Finding the Man in the State, in STATES OF INJURY: POWER AND FREEDOM IN LATE MODERNITY 186 (1995). 60. See, e.g., CYNTHIA H. ENLOE, MANEUVERS: THE INTERNATIONAL POLITICS OF MILITARIZING WOMEN’S LIVES 37 (2000); CYNTHIA ENLOE, BANANAS, BEACHES AND BASES 65-92 (1989); Sylvanna Falcon, Rape as a Weapon of War: Advancing Human Rights for Women at the U.S.-Mexico Border, 28 SOC. JUST. 31 (2001); Madeline Morris, By Force of Arms: Rape, War, and Military Culture, 45 DUKE L.J. 651, 690-91 (1996). 61. See, e.g., MATTHEW FRYE JACOBSON, WHITENESS OF A DIFFERENT COLOR: EUROPEAN IMMIGRANTS AND THE ALCHEMY OF RACE (1998); ROGERS M. SMITH, CIVIC IDEALS: CONFLICTING VISIONS OF CITIZENSHIP IN U.S. HISTORY (1997). 62. IAN F. HANEY LÓPEZ, WHITE BY LAW: THE LEGAL CONSTRUCTION OF RACE 1 (1996) (citing Act of March 26, 1790, ch. 3, 1 Stat. 103). 63. See Gabriel J. Chin, Segregation’s Last Stronghold: Race Discrimination and the Constitutional Law of Immigration, 46 UCLA L. REV. 1, 6 (1998) (“The cases that created the plenary power doctrine . . . not only continue to be cited but, in the words of one distinguished authority, ‘said nearly everything the modern lawyer needs to know about the source and extent of Congress’s power to regulate immigration.’”). 64. See SMITH, supra note 61, at 36 (proposing that “ideologies of ascriptive Americanism 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 331 In contrast to the activities regulated by the welfare state, where race is thought to be a difference that makes no difference, the penal state both actively manages racial difference (in the form of people’s racialized bodies) and actively constructs it (in the form of symbolic resources). Sovereign power is “about race” in the most obvious ways: law enforcement officials look for racial differences among people and direct violence against them based on what they find. As scholars have noted in exhaustive detail, United States prisons and jails are disproportionately full of African American and Latina/o bodies. As Mirandé emphasizes, immigration enforcement activities target Mexican-looking people, people who appear to be of Indio-Hispanic racial ancestry.65 Kevin Johnson’s essay describes the practices of racial profiling both at the border and on the streets.66 In addition, the sovereign state actively draws on racialized meanings and images to justify its actions. Sovereign power is a register in which the protection of abstract national and social bodies is understood as allimportant, and to make these imaginary bodies seem real, elites appeal to the rhetoric of physical bodies. Immigration law protects the integrity of the national body; criminal law protects the integrity of the domestic body. Both areas of law are subject politically to “moral panics” in which the language of contagion, corruption, and impurity—rhetoric that uses bodily metaphors of health and disease to describe the nation—become prominent.67 In both areas of the law, the task of protecting the fantasized purity of legal-social bodies from contagion is identified more or less explicitly with the task of controlling (actual) racialized bodies. From the nineteenth-century panic about the “Yellow Peril” to present-day fears about Arab Americans, dark bodies are associated with threats to national and social integrity.68 As Gabriel Chin has made clear, since the Chinese Exclusion Cases, the Supreme Court has granted nearly plenary power to immigration officials to protect the national body, a protection that is have always done some of the work that civic myths do more effectively than liberalism or democratic republicanism, despite the mythical components that those traditions also possess”). 65. See generally Mirandé, supra note 1. 66. See generally Johnson, supra note 6. 67. On the rhetoric of health, disease, and pollution in criminal justice policy, see, e.g, Martha Grace Duncan, In Slime and Darkness: The Metaphor of Filth in Criminal Justice, 68 TUL. L. REV. 725, 751 (1994); Mona Lynch, Pedophiles and Cyber-Predators as Contaminating Forces: The Language of Disgust, Pollution, and Boundary Invasions in Federal Debates on Sex Offender Legislation, 27 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 529, 530 (2002). On the dehumanizing of immigrants in public discourse, even by immigrant rights activists, see John S.W. Park, Race Discourse and Proposition 187, 2 MICH. J. RACE & L. 175, 176 (1996). 68. For a historical examination of both racialized and gendered moral panics in the history of United States drug policy, see NANCY D. CAMPBELL, USING WOMEN: GENDER, DRUG POLICY, AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 11, 32 (2000). 332 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 permissibly race-conscious.69 It is not surprising, therefore, that both police and immigration officials engage in racial profiling as a means of protecting the nation from disorder.70 As Mirandé points out, protection of the nation from the “other” often means defending the Mexican border.71 Johnson adds that police engage in an everyday, domestic version of this ethnic cleansing when they profile African American suspects.72 The contrast between these explicitly racialized state projects and the rhetoric of equality, in which state racial classifications are forbidden, could not be more stark. Yet, in practice, there is much less conflict between sovereign and liberal power than one might expect. Judges, who administer the liberal “rule of law,” typically grant extreme deference and a high degree of discretion to state actors when those actors cite reasons of national security and public order. McCleskey v. Kemp73 is only one example; another might be the infamous Supreme Court decision in Korematsu v. United States.74 Deference and discretion to the state actors charged with the business of exercising sovereign power provides a cover for racial and ethnic cleansing activities that would otherwise be considered anathema in an egalitarian society. The jurisprudence of criminal procedure is a paradigmatic example of this co-dependent relationship between liberal rights and sovereign power. As many legal scholars have complained, although criminal procedure is highly constitutionalized, the Court has, especially in recent years, gone out of its way to show deference to the customary practices of police and other law enforcement officials. In the “salad days” of the Warren Court, the Supreme Court showed a willingness to disrupt business as usual in the name of protecting individuals accused of crime from police abuse, and the Court acknowledged the strong possibility that such abuse might not be arbitrary but rather discriminatory in character.75 Since that time, as 69. See Chin, supra note 63. 70. Indeed, at least one commentator argues that domestic law enforcement officers subjectively experience their jobs as a kind of racialized colonial adventure. See generally James M. Doyle, “It’s the Third World Down There!”: The Colonialist Vocation and American Criminal Justice, 27 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 71 (1992). 71. Mirandé, supra note 1, at 388-89. Other times, it means defending the United States against Asian “spies.” See Miriam Kim, Discrimination in the Wen Ho Lee Case: Reinterpreting the Intent Requirement in Constitutional and Statutory Race Discrimination Cases, 9 ASIAN L.J. 117, 152 (2002). Recently, it came to mean protecting the United States against Arab “terrorists.” See Leti Volpp, The Citizen and the Terrorist, 49 UCLA L. REV. 1575, 1576-81 (2002). 72. Johnson, supra note 6, at 349-51. 73. 481 U.S. 279 (1987). 74. 323 U.S. 214, 216 (1944) (upholding the wartime internment of Japanese Americans, despite acknowledgment that “all legal restrictions which curtail the civil rights of a single racial group are immediately suspect”). 75. See DAVID COLE, NO EQUAL JUSTICE: RACE AND CLASS IN THE AMERICAN CRIMINAL JUSTICE SYSTEM (1999). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 333 Mirandé and Slobogin note, constitutional protections for individual persons under suspicion of criminal activity and individuals in the custody of the criminal justice system have been steadily eroded by the emergence of a series of ad-hoc “exceptions” to general protections.76 These exceptions provide, once again, an excellent cover for the targeting of persons according to their perceived race. In this way, McCleskey stands for more than the intent requirement of the Fourteenth Amendment and how it applies to the criminal justice system; it stands for the complicity of liberal and sovereign power. At the end of his essay, Slobogin develops the intriguing idea that a “poverty exception” underlies Fourth Amendment jurisprudence.77 As he points out, “[s]everal Court decisions define expectations of privacy in a way that makes people who are less well-off more likely to experience warrantless, suspicionless government intrusions.”78 Moreover, Slobogin continues, “[e]ven in those situations where the interior of the home is not viewable from a public space, the homes of poor people are more likely to receive little or no Fourth Amendment protection.”79 The Court grants less Fourth Amendment protection to apartments, cars, and containers located outside a dwelling than to single-family homes;80 has held that public arrests do not require a warrant, as opposed to arrests taking place in a private space;81 has ruled that “brief police-citizen encounters on the street and on public transportation are ‘consensual,’”82 and most recently, has permitted custodial arrests even for very minor crimes.83 Constitutional protection, in criminal procedure, is tied to the concept of a reasonable expectation of “privacy;” but privacy is tied to the ability to control access to private property. Whereas the social welfare state and the penal state are centrally concerned with race—making sure that it does not matter or making sure that it does—the capitalist state is structurally indifferent to race. Indeed, the capitalist mode of power is, at least in principle, opposed to all status hierarchies because it obeys the single principle of economic efficiency or wealth maximization, under which all areas of social life should be subject to markets and within which all participants in markets are presumed equal, even fungible, with one another. This does not mean, however, as some have argued, that racial discrimination has been or will soon be 76. 77. 78. 79. 80. 81. 82. 83. Mirandé, supra note 1, at 367-68; Slobogin, supra note 3, at 391, 393. Slobogin, supra note 3, at 408-12. Id. at 400. Id. at 402. Id. Id. at 403-04. Id. at 405. Id. at 405-06. 334 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 driven out by market forces.84 Because capitalism both generates and thrives on inequality, and because markets are imperfect and not separate from politics, racial inequalities are perpetuated and often magnified by the market practices of production, exchange, and consumption, and by the processes of market creation.85 The criminal procedure cases Slobogin discusses are in accord with decisions in other areas of constitutional law concerning wealth and poverty.86 It is uncontested that government “wealth classifications” in general do not receive heightened scrutiny.87 Rather, as the Court reasoned in Dandridge v. Williams,88 [f]or this Court to approve the invalidation of state economic or social regulation as “overreaching” would be far too reminiscent of an era when the Court thought the Fourteenth Amendment gave it power to strike down state laws “because they may be unwise, improvident, or out of harmony with a particular school of thought.” That era long ago passed into history.89 Although the Court has mandated that government spend resources on poor people when access to legal counsel is at stake, that mandate is extremely narrow.90 The general rule that the Constitution does not create “positive” but only “negative” rights remains. In practice, this means that access to 84. See, e.g., Richard A. Epstein, Standing Firm, on Forbidden Grounds, 31 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 1, 1 (1994) (“[T]he best set of overall social outcomes would come from a legal order that tolerated any form of private discrimination or favoritism, whether practiced by the most vicious and ardent white supremacist or the most dedicated proponent of diversity or affirmative action.”); James E. Macdonald & Caryn L. Beck-Dudley, A Natural Law Defense to the Employment Law Question: A Response to Richard Epstein, 38 AM. BUS. L.J. 363, 399-400 (2001) (describing Epstein’s position on Title VII that rational racial discrimination should be permitted and that irrational racial discrimination will be driven out by market forces). 85. The discussion that follows focuses on initial allocations of property rights and systematic transfers of wealth according to political rules that link race strongly to class. However, it has also been suggested that another mechanism for the maintenance of racial discrimination in markets is that individuals have a preference or “taste” for discrimination because discrimination is a means by which social groups produce status for their members. See generally Richard H. McAdams, Cooperation and Conflict: The Economics of Group Status Production and Race Discrimination, 108 HARV. L. REV. 1003 (1995). If this is true, then even successful “reparations” programs that attempted to undo unjust transfers and creation of wealth would soon be stymied by continuing racial discrimination. 86. See generally Slobogin, supra note 3. 87. See, e.g., San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1, 102 n.61 (1973). 88. 397 U.S. 471 (1970). 89. Id. at 484-85 (citations omitted). 90. See COLE, supra note 75, at 92 (describing the Court’s moves to alleviate inequality as “more ceremonial bows than actual reforms”). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 335 constitutional rights may be conditioned on the ability to pay for their exercise. The inability of the homeless and the poor to control access to property not only prevents them from exercising basic constitutional rights; but it also means that, to the extent they cannot enjoy all the rights and privileges of liberal citizenship, they are subject to the regulation and control of the administrative arm of the social welfare state, an apparatus that, as Jill Elaine Hasday explains, functions “to manage the dependency of poor people in a wage labor economy.”91 Thus, the law of government benefits, family law, and housing is bifurcated, with one set of rights for those who have access to property through income or wealth, and another set of rights (often couched in the legal terms of “privilege” rather than “right”) for those who do not.92 In the new era of privatization and erosion of the welfare state, responsibility for these “dependents” has increasingly been transferred to the penal state.93 Race, gender, and class are historically interrelated in the United States. At the founding of the nation, certain groups of people were excluded by law from full participation in capitalist activity: African Americans, as slaves, constituted property and thus could not hold property or make contracts themselves; married women, subject to the law of coverture, could not hold property or make contracts in their own names but were persons only indirectly, through their fathers and husbands; indigenous Americans were considered incapable of holding full title to land under the doctrine of discovery.94 The Plessy95 era, as we have seen, gave 91. Jill Elaine Hasday, Parenthood Divided: A Legal History of the Bifurcated Law of Parental Relations, 90 GEO. L.J. 299, 301 (2002); see also NANCY FRASER, JUSTICE INTERRUPTUS: CRITICAL REFLECTIONS OF THE “POSTSOCIALIST” CONDITION 121-44 (1997) (discussing “dependency” as a keyword of the welfare state that labels individuals as targets for bureaucratic social control). For a philosophical exploration of the lack of freedom of the homeless in a society based on private property, see Jeremy Waldron, Homelessness and the Issue of Freedom, 39 UCLA L. REV. 295 (1991). 92. See generally Hasday, supra note 91; see, e.g., Dept. of Housing v. Rucker, 535 U.S. 125 (2002) (upholding against a due process challenge a federal statute giving local public housing authorities the discretion to terminate the lease of a tenant when a member of the household or a guest engages in drug-related activity, regardless of whether the tenant knew, or should have known, of the drug-related activity); William E. Forbath, Constitutional Welfare Rights: A History, Critique and Reconstruction, 69 FORDHAM L. REV. 1821 (2001) (describing the ultimately failed effort by constitutional scholars to have the Court recognize welfare rights as property). 93. In the process, Malcolm Feeley and Jonathan Simon argue, the penal state itself takes on some of the characteristics of the bureaucratic state, although now based on principles of risk management rather than on social services. Feeley & Simon call this “the new penology.” See Malcolm M. Feeley & Jonathan Simon, The New Penology: Notes on the Emerging Strategy of Corrections and Its Implications, 30 CRIMINOLOGY 449, 449 (1992). 94. See Johnson v. M’Intosh, 21 U.S. (8 Wheat.) 543 (1823) (describing the doctrine of discovery). 95. 163 U.S. 537 (1896). 336 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 constitutional sanction to the economic exploitation and to the exclusion of African Americans, Asian Americans, and other nonwhites through employment discrimination, housing discrimination, and the post-World War II “suburban-industrial complex,” which was developed with the intensification of racial segregation and hierarchy in mind.96 These and other state projects succeeded in obstructing the efforts of racialized groups to build capital, and systematically transferred wealth from people of color to Whites. In contemporary times, people of color continue to routinely experience differential access to credit as well as discrimination in employment and housing, compounding the effects of past discrimination and exclusion. The legal and social institutions of capitalism have absorbed, and now reproduce, and even intensify, the economic inequalities generated by decades of White supremacy. Here, again, the jurisdictional function of liberal legalism provides room for possibly conflicting state projects to co-exist. The social welfare state has attempted to implement norms of equality and, to a modest extent, substantive social and economic rights. At the same time, capitalism operates not to produce equality but inequality, and is indifferent to questions of distribution. The primary way in which the antiegalitarian tendencies of capitalism are shielded from scrutiny through the egalitarian lens of the welfare state is through the “public/private distinction”—first criticized by the Legal Realists, later by Critical Legal Studies, and finally by mainstream constitutional theorists.97 Despite nearconstant critique, the courts continue to treat common law institutions and distributions of power, particularly those central to capitalism, as prepolitical and thus as “not state action.” As Lisa Iglesias has put it, the 96. On suburbanization and the role of federal policy in the making of the Black ghetto, see MELVIN L. OLIVER & THOMAS M. SHAPIRO, BLACK WEALTH/WHITE WEALTH: A NEW PERSPECTIVE ON RACIAL INEQUALITY 16-18 (1999). For a general discussion of racialized state policies that blocked Blacks from creating wealth, see id. at 37-45. For a discussion of historical state and private actions resulting in widespread racial discrimination in housing markets, see DOUGLAS S. MASSEY & NANCY A. DENTON, AMERICAN APARTHEID: SEGREGATION AND THE MAKING OF THE UNDERCLASS 26-59 (1993). On the importance of home ownership, subsidized for Whites but not for Blacks, see Phyllis Craig-Taylor, To Be Free: Liberty, Citizenship, Property and Race, 14 HARV. BLACKLETTER L.J. 45 (1998). The post-slavery exploitation of Black labor included the sharecropping system, id. at 57-59; race discrimination on the part of unions and successful employer efforts to use African Americans as lower-wage “scabs,” id. at 65; and the convict labor system. The alien land laws and the Japanese internment also intentionally prevented the development of Asian American wealth. See Gabriel J. Chin, Citizenship and Exclusion: Wyoming’s Anti-Japanese Alien Land Law in Context, 1 WYO. L. REV. 497, 505 (2001). 97. See, e.g., CASS R. SUNSTEIN, THE PARTIAL CONSTITUTION 51-54 (describing the Legal Realist critique of laissez-faire through the recognition that “private” law was necessarily the product of government action); MARK KELMAN, A GUIDE TO CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES 102-09 (1987) (setting out the Critical Legal Studies critique of the public/private distinction); SUNSTEIN, supra, at 3-4 (adopting a critique of “status quo neutrality” in constitutional law). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 337 United States subscribes to the idea of an “anti-political economy.”98 Keeping the economy away from politics, of course, makes it possible to preserve the anti-egalitarian tendencies of capitalism and shield them from critique. From this perspective, Slobogin’s suggestion that insensitivity to class, rather than hostility based on race, drives Fourth Amendment jurisprudence is again not so much in conflict with Mirandé’s and Johnson’s focus on race as it might first appear. On the one hand, Slobogin is surely right to suggest that “class” and “race” are not the same thing;99 the state project of protecting and fostering corporate capitalism involves different institutions and different forms of power than the state project of preserving and protecting the imaginary national community, or the project of managing social welfare. The simple insistence that “it’s all about race” thus fails to consider the complexities of how White supremacy functions in different arenas. On the other hand, it has been my argument, following Omi and Winant, that each of these quite distinct state projects is nevertheless racialized.100 Race and political economy are so deeply intertwined in the United States that class and race can never be fully separated. To this extent, Mirandé and Johnson are right to focus on White supremacy as a, if not the, master narrative. III. CONCLUSION Johnson’s essay takes us to the point where the rubber meets the road. The complexities of racial formation in the contemporary United States mean, as Johnson explains, that Latinas/os and African Americans may experience short-term benefits from supporting the penal state’s racialization of criminal law and immigration enforcement.101 Yet, the long-term interest of both groups is in challenging, rather than strengthening, White supremacy. As Johnson puts it, “[o]nce race is let out of the proverbial genie’s bottle . . . it is difficult to limit where and when it will be considered by law enforcement authorities.”102 The result, as he acknowledges, is a classic “prisoner’s dilemma”: each player will be far better off if it cooperates with the other, but neither can trust the other not to defect and thus seek a smaller but more certain benefit.103 98. See Lisa Iglesias, Structural Violence: Law and the Anti-Political Economy (unpublished manuscript, on file with author). 99. Slobogin, supra note 3, at 400. 100. See OMI & WINANT, supra notes 20-26 and accompanying text. 101. Johnson, supra note 6, at 360-62. 102. Id. at 361. 103. Id. 338 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 Complicating the prisoner’s dilemma is the fact that there is not one form of racism, but many. As Robert Chang and Keith Aoki have pointed out, “nativist” racism operates differently from color racism, and racialized groups can and do play these differences against each other.104 Indeed, as Omi and Winant recognize, race itself is not a stable thing but a social construction always in process.105 We have seen different relationships between various state projects and racial formation. The social welfare state has sought to enforce norms of race neutrality in the “legal” sphere and to permit “social” management on the basis of race. The agencies of the penal state have entrusted state officials with the power and discretion to punish actual colored bodies in the name of an imaginary pure White national body. The institutions of the capitalist state have permitted racial differentials of political power to be leveraged in the creation and amassing of wealth. Racialized groups involved in politics in and around Omi and Winant’s “racial state” face not one, but a multitude, of prisoner’s dilemmas. Moreover, we are now also facing potential changes in the organization of White supremacy, as the social welfare state gives way to both a newly revitalized penal state concerned openly with racial and cultural policing, and a newly revitalized “free market” capitalist state being exported around the world. Traditional civil rights and civil liberties arguments are uncertain tools in this new environment. McCleskey106 symbolizes the deference liberal law pays to state forces that promise order and security, even when the terms of that security seem blatantly in conflict with egalitarian values. The survival of the public/private distinction represents the similar deference that protects the anti-political economy. Although the essays in this cluster were written before the events of September 11, 2001, they are timely in their focus on the difficulties of confronting the penal state with liberal values. Slobogin demonstrates the difficulty in finding racism in the text of the applicable law.107 Mirandé reminds us of the layers of law not penetrable by courtroom arguments.108 Johnson sets out both the necessity and difficulty (if not impossibility) of building coalitions among those groups that bear the burden of American 104. Robert S. Chang & Keith Aoki, Centering the Immigrant in the Inter/National Imagination, 10 LA RAZA L.J. 1395, 1414 (1997) (noting that “[b]ecause of the construction of the national community as White and Black, Asian Americans and Latina/os are discursively produced as foreign”). 105. Omi and Winant famously propose that “racial formation”—“the sociohistorical process by which racial categories are created, inhabited, transformed, and destroyed”—consists of “a process of historically situated projects in which human bodies and social structures are represented and organized.” OMI & WINANT, supra note 20, at 55-56. 106. 481 U.S. 279 (1987). 107. See generally Slobogin, supra note 3. 108. See generally Mirandé, supra note 1. 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 339 elites’ attempt to secure security for themselves.109 If these essays do not offer us easy optimism, they at least make clear the difficulty of the path that lies ahead. 109. See generally Johnson, supra note 6. THE CASE FOR AFRICAN AMERICAN AND LATINA/O COOPERATION IN CHALLENGING RACIAL PROFILING IN LAW ENFORCEMENT Kevin R. Johnson* I. RACIAL PROFILING IN LAW ENFORCEMENT . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 343 A. Criminal Law Enforcement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 343 B. Immigration Enforcement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 347 II. SIMILAR HARMS, COMMON CONCERNS, AND THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN DIFFERENT FORMS OF RACE-BASED LAW ENFORCEMENT . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 353 III. THE EFFICACY OF MULTIRACIAL COALITIONS IN CHALLENGING RACIAL PROFILING IN LAW ENFORCEMENT . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 357 IV. CONCLUSION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 363 The formal and informal targeting of African Americans, Latinas/os, and other racial minorities for police stops on account of race, known popularly as racial profiling, has grabbed national attention.1 Race-based enforcement of the United States’ immigration laws, which grew in importance as the U.S. government escalated efforts to deport undocumented immigrants in the 1990s, has just begun to gain public * Associate Dean for Academic Affairs at the University of California-Davis School of Law and Chicana/o Studies; Director, Chicana/o Studies Program (2000-2001), University of California, Davis. B.A., University of California at Berkeley; J.D., Harvard University. This Essay was presented in draft form at the University of Florida as part of the Sixth Annual Critical Latina/o Theory Conference, LatCrit VI, in April 2001. I thank the conference planning committee, especially Berta Hernández, for organizing a successful conference; Devon Carbado, who asked me to participate on the panel; and those who attended the presentation and offered comments. This Essay benefitted from discussions with Richard Delgado and Ken Nunn as well as the comments of George A. Martínez, Mary Romero, and Sylvia Lazos on a draft. 1. See, e.g., THE PRESIDENT’S INITIATIVE ON RACE, THE ADVISORY BOARD’S REPORT TO THE PRESIDENT—ONE AMERICA IN THE 21ST CENTURY: FORGING A NEW FUTURE 78 (1998) [hereinafter THE PRESIDENT’S INITIATIVE ON RACE] (discussing racial profiling in law enforcement as a criminal justice problem); 60 Minutes: Blacks and Latinos Deal with Harassment from Police (CBS television broadcast, Feb. 11, 2001). 341 342 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 awareness.2 The two law enforcement practices share a common thread—both use race as a signal of potential unlawful conduct or status. This Essay contends that African Americans and Latinas/os share mutual concerns with governmental reliance on race in the enforcement of the criminal and immigration laws. Both suffer civil rights deprivations resulting from the reliance on statistical probabilities by law enforcement officers. Overlapping interests create the potential for intellectual linkages and political alliances designed to remove the taint of race from law enforcement.3 More generally, the criminal justice system in the United States, which skews enforcement, prosecution, and imprisonment toward young African American and Latino males,4 represents a legitimate target for concerted action. The common need and goal of reforming law enforcement creates the potential for far-reaching alliances.5 Eliminating racial bias from law enforcement through multiracial coalitions—like all diverse alliances—will no doubt prove to be an arduous project, marked by setbacks as well as breakthroughs. Formidable barriers exist to the building of political coalitions between and among African Americans and Latinas/os, as well as other minority communities.6 Importantly, the various groups may perceive themselves as having competing interests. Nonetheless, political realities dictate that alliances are essential to the quest for racial justice in the United States.7 Critical Latina/o Theory has much to add to the analysis of coalitionbuilding. LatCrit theorists contend that, to fully understand racial subordination in the United States, scholars must study its impact on African Americans, Latinas/os, and other groups, and how the subordination of various groups fits into broader patterns of racial and other discrimination.8 Coalitions designed to combat racial inequality are 2. See, e.g., Susan Sachs, Files Suggest Profiling of Latinos Led to Immigration Raids, N.Y. TIMES, May 1, 2001, at B1; Jim Yardley, Some Texans Say Border Patrol Singles Out Too Many Blameless Hispanics, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 26, 2000, at A17. Similarly, the growing number of deaths of Mexican citizens resulting from increased border enforcement operations has begun to attract national attention. See, e.g., James Sterngold, Devastating Picture of Immigrants Dead in Arizona Desert, N.Y. TIMES, May 25, 2001, at A1; James Sterngold, Rights Groups Urge Change in Border Policy, N.Y. TIMES, May 26, 2001, at A10. See generally Bill Ong Hing, The Dark Side of Operation Gatekeeper, 7 U.C. DAVIS J. INT’L L. & POL’Y 121 (2001) (analyzing human toll of U.S. border enforcement). 3. See, e.g., George A. Martínez, African-Americans, Latinos, and the Construction of Race: Toward an Epistemic Coalition, 19 CHICANO-LATINO L. REV. 213 (1998). 4. See infra text accompanying notes 10-62. 5. See infra text accompanying notes 63-121. 6. See infra text accompanying notes 90-121. 7. See infra text accompanying notes 110-21. 8. See Elizabeth M. Iglesias, Foreword: Identity, Democracy, Communicative Power, Inter/National Labor Rights and the Evolution of LatCrit Theory and Community, 53 U. MIAMI L. REV. 575, 595, 622-29 (1999); Athena D. Mutua, Shifting Bottoms and Rotating Centers: 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 343 central to LatCrit Theory.9 Both aspects of LatCrit Theory are implicated by the potential African American and Latina/o challenge to race-based law enforcement. Part I of this Essay sketches the legal problems with race profiling in criminal and border enforcement, showing how both forms adversely impact Latinas/os and African Americans. Part II studies the common interests of Latinas/os and African Americans in eliminating race-based law enforcement. Part III analyzes the efficacy of coalitions to remedy the racism at the core of law enforcement in the United States. This Essay concludes that, difficult as it may be, collective action is essential to bring about much needed racial reform in law enforcement. I. RACIAL PROFILING IN LAW ENFORCEMENT Racial profiling in both criminal and immigration law enforcement adversely affects African Americans, Latinas/os, and other racial groups. Unfortunately, misconceptions and stereotypes result in law enforcement’s excessive reliance on physical appearance as a proxy for legal wrongdoing. Intellectually and practically, racial profiling in criminal law differs little in kind and substance from that employed in immigration enforcement. The reliance on race has proven difficult to eliminate from law enforcement. This Essay contends that race cannot be removed selectively from one form of law enforcement but not the other. As history suggests, once race-based enforcement taints one aspect of law enforcement, it almost inevitably infects other areas.10 Consequently, the most durable solution is to seek to remove the impermissible use of race, root and branch, from all forms of law enforcement. A. Criminal Law Enforcement Few dispute that African American men are routinely stopped by police for “driving while Black.”11 This practice is the tip of the proverbial Reflections on LatCrit III and the Black/White Paradigm, 53 U. MIAMI L. REV. 1177, 1202-15 (1999); Francisco Valdes, Piercing Webs of Power: Identity, Resistance, and Hope in LatCrit Theory and Praxis, 33 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 897, 897-98 (2000); see also Mari J. Matsuda, Beside My Sister, Facing the Enemy: Legal Theory Out of Coalition, 43 STAN. L. REV. 1183 (1991) (analyzing the importance of multiracial coalitions because of the interrelationships between all subordinations). 9. See Francisco Valdes, Foreword: Under Construction—LatCrit Consciousness, Community, and Theory, 85 CAL. L. REV. 1087, 1094 (1997). 10. See infra text accompanying notes 74-89. 11. See, e.g., Angela J. Davis, Race, Cops, and Traffic Stops, 51 U. MIAMI L. REV. 425, 43132 (1997); David A. Harris, The Stories, the Statistics, and the Law: Why “Driving While Black” Matters, 84 MINN. L. REV. 265, 275-88 (1999); Tracey Maclin, Race and the Fourth Amendment, 51 VAND. L. REV. 333, 342-62 (1998); David Rudovsky, Law Enforcement by Stereotypes and 344 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 iceberg of discrimination against the African American community in this nation’s criminal justice system.12 Similarly, police officers stop Latinas/os for “driving while Brown.”13 Police departments in urban metropolises like Chicago, Los Angeles, and New York City, for many years have focused the criminal justice machinery on Latinas/os, just as African Americans have been targets of law enforcement. 14 Studies show that police “are stopping . . . blacks, Latinos and Asians approximately eight to ten times as often as they are stopping whites.”15 Few deny the concrete harms of racial profiling. When criminal investigation focuses on African Americans and Latinas/os, more members of these groups will be arrested and convicted of crimes, thereby Serendipity: Racial Profiling and Stops and Searches Without Cause, 3 U. PA. J. CONST. L. 296 (2001); Katheryn K. Russell, “Driving While Black”: Corollary Phenomena and Collateral Consequences, 40 B.C. L. REV. 717, 718-19 (1999); David A. Sklansky, Traffic Stops, Minority Motorists, and the Future of the Fourth Amendment, 1997 SUP. CT. REV. 271; Anthony C. Thompson, Stopping the Usual Suspects: Race and the Fourth Amendment, 74 N.Y.U. L. REV. 956, 957 (1999). 12. See, e.g., DAVID COLE, NO EQUAL JUSTICE: RACE AND CLASS IN THE AMERICAN JUSTICE SYSTEM (1999); DAVID A. HARRIS, PROFILES IN INJUSTICE: WHY RACIAL PROFILING CANNOT WORK (2002); RANDALL KENNEDY, RACE, CRIME AND THE LAW (1997); KATHERYN K. RUSSELL, THE COLOR OF CRIME: RACIAL HOAXES, WHITE FEAR, BLACK PROTECTISM, POLICE HARASSMENT, AND OTHER MACROAGGRESSIONS (1998). 13. See, e.g., Chavez v. Illinois State Police, 251 F.3d 612 (7th Cir. 2001) (analyzing claims of police racial profiling of Latinas/os and African Americans); Martinez v. Village of Mount Prospect, 92 F. Supp. 2d 780, 781 (N.D. Ill. 2000) (discussing Latina/o racial profiling); Rodriguez v. Cal. Highway Patrol, 89 F. Supp. 2d 1131, 1134 (N.D. Cal. 2000) (Latina/o and African American profiling); Nat’l Cong. for Puerto Rican Rights v. City of New York, 191 F.R.D. 52 (S.D.N.Y. 1999) (Latina/o and Black plaintiffs); Chavez v. Ill. State Police, 27 F. Supp. 2d 1053 (N.D. Ill. 1998) (Latinas/os and African Americans); see also Devon W. Carbado, [E]Racing the Fourth Amendment, 100 MICH. L. REV. 946 (2002) (analyzing Fourth Amendment decisions’, negative impact on African Americans and Latinas/os); Frank Rudy Cooper, The Un-Balanced Fourth Amendment: A Cultural Study of the Drug War, Racial Profiling and Arvizu, 47 VILL. L. REV. 851 (2002) (same). 14. See, e.g., Cruz Reynoso, Hispanics and the Criminal Justice System, in HISPANICS IN THE UNITED STATES: AN AGENDA FOR THE TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY 277 (Pastora San Juan Cafferty & David W. Engstrom eds., 2000); see also Robert Garcia, Latinos and Criminal Justice, 14 CHICANO-LATINO L. REV. 6, 7 n.4 (1994) (observing the lack of academic attention to Latinas/os in criminal justice system); Laura E. Gómez, Race, Colonialism, and Criminal Law: Mexicans and the American Criminal Justice System in Territorial New Mexico, 34 LAW & SOC’Y REV. 1129 (2000) (investigating impact of race on persons of Mexican ancestry in criminal justice system of territorial New Mexico); Mary Romero, State Violence and the Social and Legal Construction of Latino Criminality: From El Bandido to Gang Members, 78 DENV. U.L. REV. 1081 (2001) (analyzing negative impacts of police classification of Latina/o youth as gang members and criminals); Reynaldo Anaya Valencia, Latinos and the Criminal Justice System: An Overview of the Invisible/Visible Minority, 1 HARV. LATINO L. REV. 27 (1994) (analyzing available data on Latinas/os in criminal justice system). 15. Symposium: Panel V: Promoting Racial Equality, 9 J.L. & POL’Y 347, 365 (2001) (discussing comments of Professor Deborah A. Ramirez). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 345 contributing to disparate incarceration rates.16 Racial profiles punish, embarrass, and humiliate innocent people, whose skin color is used as a proxy for criminal conduct.17 Moreover, as U.S. society becomes increasingly multiracial, “the possibility for error [when using race in law enforcement] likewise increases, simply because the diversity of groups and of individuals within each group makes extrapolations from group characteristics to individual conduct more tenuous.”18 Unfortunately, profiling, as part of a long history of discriminatory law enforcement, fosters a deep cynicism among racial minorities about the criminal justice system.19 Fearing the police, they may not cooperate in the reporting and investigation of criminal activity.20 Ultimately, the targeting of African Americans and Latinas/os for police stops increases the likelihood that they will suffer police brutality.21 Besides African Americans and Latinas/os, Asian Americans are, at times, affected by racial profiling. The Wen Ho Lee case, in which an Asian American scientist was jailed on trumped up espionage charges, is a well-known example.22 Police in some localities also employ gang profiles to target Asian American youth.23 16. See infra note 31 and accompanying text. 17. Because of the intersection of race and class in U.S. society, poor and working class African Americans and Latinas/os suffer the brunt of race-based policing. See generally David A. Harris, Factors for Reasonable Suspicion: When Black and Poor Means Stopped and Frisked, 69 IND. L.J. 659 (1994). 18. Viet D. Dinh, Races, Crime, and the Law, 111 HARV. L. REV. 1289, 1303 (1998) (book review). 19. See Harris, supra note 11, at 298-300; see also William J. Stuntz, Race, Class, and Drugs, 98 COLUM. L. REV. 1795, 1797 n.6 (1998) (reviewing survey data reflecting that African Americans have deeply negative views of the criminal justice system). 20. See Erik Luna, Transparent Policing, 85 IOWA L. REV. 1107, 1118-19 (2000). 21. See DERRICK BELL, RACE, RACISM AND AMERICAN LAW § 9.6, at 478 (4th ed. 2000); see, e.g., JOHN L. BURRIS & CATHERINE WHITNEY, BLUE VS. BLACK 15-25 (1999) (discussing various incidents of police brutality); Alan Feuer, Three Are Guilty of Cover-Up Plot in Louima Attack, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 7, 2000, at A1 (describing brutal attack by New York police on Abner Louima, a Black Haitian immigrant); Jane Fritsch, 4 Officers in Diallo Shooting Are Acquitted of All Charges, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 26, 2000, at A1 (reporting on acquittal of police officers in the killing of Black immigrant, Amadou Diallo). 22. See generally Neil Gotanda, Comparative Racialization: Racial Profiling and the Case of Wen Ho Lee, 47 UCLA L. REV. 1689 (2000). In large part, the U.S. government’s investigation of Wen Ho Lee was founded on stereotypes of Asians as “foreigners,” see infra text accompanying notes 61-62, and enemies of the United States. See ERIC K. YAMAMOTO ET AL., RACE, RIGHTS AND REPARATIONS: LAW AND THE JAPANESE AMERICAN INTERNMENT 464-74 (2001). 23. See Cynthia Kwie Yung Lee, Race and Self-Defense: Toward a Normative Conception of Reasonableness, 81 MINN. L. REV. 367, 439 n.283 (1996); see also Suzin Kim, Note, Gangs and Law Enforcement: The Necessity of Limiting the Use of Gang Profiles, 5 B.U. PUB. INT. L.J. 265, 277-78 (1996). 346 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 To comply with the Constitution, police officers ordinarily must have individualized reasonable suspicion of criminal conduct before conducting an investigatory police stop.24 Reliance on racial profiles, based on alleged group propensities, generally violate the law.25 Unfortunately, the courts have not been particularly effective in removing race and racism from criminal law enforcement.26 The Supreme Court has repeatedly failed to recognize the racial context of criminal law enforcement or the raciallydisparate implications of its decisions. Police departments across the country also have proven to be resistant to reform.27 Consequently, investigations and reports of racial profiling continue.28 Racial profiling is just one of many discriminatory aspects of the criminal justice system adversely affecting African Americans and Latinas/os. Both groups are demonized as criminals, drug dealers, and gang 24. See, e.g., United States v. Sokolow, 490 U.S. 1, 7 (1989); Terry v. Ohio, 392 U.S. 1, 27 (1968). 25. See United States v. Laymon, 730 F. Supp. 332, 339-40 (D. Colo. 1990) (granting motion to suppress evidence in case in which drug task force focused enforcement efforts on African Americans and Latinas/os). But see United States v. Weaver, 966 F.2d 391, 396 (8th Cir. 1992) (allowing law enforcement to rely on drug courier profile, including race, in questioning person); United States v. Malone, 886 F.2d 1162, 1164-65 (9th Cir. 1989) (affirming conviction in case in which Drug Enforcement Administration agents claimed that person fit “L.A. gang member” profile, including that he was Black). Unlawful race profiling differs factually and legally from investigatory stops of African Americans after a victim has identified a Black person as the perpetrator of a crime. For example, in Brown v. City of Oneonta, 221 F.3d 329 (2d Cir. 1999), cert. denied, 534 U.S. 816 (2001), the court of appeals dismissed a civil rights action against police for stopping African American men because a crime victim had identified the assailant as Black. Brown, 221 F.3d at 341. For criticism of police reliance on race in this manner, see Richard Banks, Race-Based Suspect Selection and Colorblind Equal Protection Doctrine and Discourse, 48 UCLA L. REV. 1075 (2001); Andrew E. Taslitz, Stories of Fourth Amendment Disrespect: From Elian to the Internment, 70 FORDHAM L. REV. 2257, 2316-27 (2002). 26. See, e.g., Illinois v. Wardlow, 528 U.S. 119, 125-26 (2000) (refusing to disturb conviction in which police stopped defendant because individual fled upon seeing police patrol area known for heavy narcotics trafficking, despite fact that innocent minorities might flee police out of fear for personal safety); Whren v. United States, 517 U.S. 806, 813 (1996) (holding that, even if traffic stop was pretextual and based on race, Fourth Amendment requirements satisfied so long as probable cause existed that the driver had committed traffic infraction); McClesky v. Kemp, 481 U.S. 279, 320-21 (1987) (upholding imposition of death penalty on African American man in face of strong statistical evidence that State of Georgia administered death penalty in racially discriminatory manner). 27. See, e.g, infra text accompanying notes 74-79 (describing corruption in Los Angeles Police Department). 28. See Debra Livingston, Police Reform and the Department of Justice: An Essay on Accountability, 2 BUFF. CRIM. L. REV. 815, 815-17, 816 n.4 (1999) (stating that U.S. Department of Justice was reportedly investigating several local police agencies for racial profiling and other civil rights violations). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 347 members,29 are the most likely victims of police brutality,30 and are disproportionately represented in the prison population.31 B. Immigration Enforcement Judicially-sanctioned race profiling is central to the U.S. government’s enforcement of the immigration laws.32 In United States v. BrignoniPonce,33 the Supreme Court stated that “[t]he likelihood that any given person of Mexican ancestry is an alien is high enough to make Mexican appearance a relevant factor” to the Border Patrol in making an immigration stop.34 Given this encouragement, Border Patrol officers 29. See, e.g., United States v. Weaver, 966 F.2d 391 (8th Cir. 1992) (allowing law enforcement to rely on drug profile including race in questioning person); United States v. Malone, 886 F.2d 1162 (9th Cir. 1989) (allowing law enforcement to rely on drug profile including race in questioning person); see also Shelan Y. Joseph, Six Flags Magic Mountain: A Family Entertainment Park, But Only If You Wear the Right Clothes, 16 LOY. L.A. ENT. L. REV. 359 (1995) (analyzing amusement park’s gang screening policy directed at African American and Latina/o youth employed by amusement park); Kim, supra note 23 (discussing use of gang profiles by law enforcement and detrimental impacts on African Americans, Latinas/os, and Asian Americans); Margaret M. Russell, Entering Great America: Reflections on Race and the Convergence of Progressive Legal Theory and Practice, 43 HASTINGS L.J. 749 (1992) (analyzing critical theory to offer insights on how progressive lawyers might challenge amusement park’s gang profiles that targeted Latina/o and African American youth). 30. See supra note 21 (citing authorities). 31. See Kenneth B. Nunn, “Darden Dilemma”: Should African Americans Prosecute Crimes?, 68 FORDHAM L. REV. 1473, 1480 (2000) (“African Americans are roughly twelve percent of the national population. Yet, African Americans constitute more than fifty percent of the inmates held in prisons and jails in the United States.”); Margaret E. Montoya, Of “Subtle Prejudices,” White Supremacy, and Affirmative Action: A Reply to Paul Butler, 68 U. COLO. L. REV. 891, 924 (1997) (“[T]he states with the four largest prison populations, California, Texas, New York, and Florida, all have substantial Latino/a populations. Approximately one-third of the prison populations of California and New York are Latino/a, although the percentages of Latinos/as in the general population are twenty-seven percent and thirteen percent, respectively.”); Reynoso, supra note 14, at 293-94 (offering statistical data on Latina/o rates of incarceration); see also Paul Butler, Racially Based Jury Nullification: Black Power in the Criminal Justice System, 105 YALE L.J. 677, 695-96 (1995) (offering capsule summary of racism against African Americans in criminal justice system in United States). 32. Arguments for ending the practice are elaborated on in detail in Kevin R. Johnson, The Case Against Race Profiling in Immigration Enforcement, 78 WASH. U. L.Q. 675 (2000). 33. 422 U.S. 873 (1975). 34. Id. at 886-87. But see United States v. Montero-Camargo, 208 F.3d 1122 (9th Cir. 2000) (en banc) (disregarding this language in Brignoni-Ponce and holding that Border Patrol cannot lawfully consider “Hispanic appearance” in deciding to make an immigration stop). Race-based immigration enforcement stands out as a striking anomaly from the color-blindness in governmental programs required by the current Supreme Court. See, e.g., Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña, 515 U.S. 200, 235 (1995) (holding that all racial classifications, including those in federal program to increase government contracting with minority businesses, are subject to strict scrutiny); City of Richmond v. J.A. Croson Co., 488 U.S. 469, 494 (1989) (holding to the same effect as Peña, 515 348 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 routinely admit that a person’s “Hispanic appearance” contributed to their decision to question a person.35 Over the years, plaintiffs in lawsuits have regularly alleged that the Border Patrol relies almost exclusively on race in immigration enforcement.36 One experienced court of appeals judge observed that “of all of the cases involving people who were stopped or searched because of their ‘foreign-looking’ appearance or ‘foreignsounding’ names, we are not aware of any in which the targeted individuals were Caucasian.”37 Like racial profiling in criminal law enforcement,38 race-based immigration enforcement fails at a number of levels. Dignitary harms to Latinas/os lawfully in the United States, including embarrassment, humiliation, and other attacks on their membership in U.S. society, result from the unjustified interrogation of their citizenship status.39 The vast majority (roughly ninety percent) of the Latinas/os in the United States are lawful immigrants or citizens;40 therefore Latina/o ancestry is not a particularly good indicia of undocumented status. “That the Border Patrol targets persons of ‘Hispanic appearance’ almost invariably contributes to the fact that close to ninety percent of [all] removals [are of] Mexican and [Latin] American citizens, even though they only constitute slightly more than one-half of the total undocumented population in the United States.”41 U.S. at 235). 35. See, e.g., United States v. Cruz-Hernandez, 62 F.3d 1353, 1356 (11th Cir. 1995); United States v. Rodriguez, 976 F.2d 592, 595 (9th Cir. 1992), amended, 997 F.2d 1306 (9th Cir. 1993). 36. See, e.g., Hodgers-Durgin v. de la Vina, 199 F.3d 1037, 1040 (9th Cir. 1999); Nicacio v. INS, 797 F.2d 700, 701 (9th Cir. 1985); LaDuke v. Nelson, 762 F.2d 1318, 1321 (9th Cir. 1985), modified, 796 F.2d 309 (9th Cir. 1986); Ramirez v. Webb, 599 F. Supp. 1278, 1280 (W.D. Mich. 1984), aff’d, 787 F.2d 592 (6th Cir. 1986) (per curiam); Illinois Migrant Council v. Pilliod, 540 F.2d 1062, 1065 (7th Cir. 1976), modified, 548 F.2d 715 (7th Cir. 1977) (en banc); Murillo v. Musegades, 809 F. Supp. 487, 490-91 (W.D. Tex. 1992); see also United States v. Portillo-Aguirre, 2002 U.S. App. LEXIS 22712 (5th Cir. Nov. 1, 2002) (reversing drug conviction in case in which Border Patrol stopped bus, questioned passengers about citizenship, and searched for drugs); Norma Ortiz, Comment, The Dangers of Unguarded Discretion: The Unconstitutional Stops of Buses by Roving Patrols, 2 SCHOLAR 289, 292 (2000) (criticizing Border Patrol practice of stopping buses in small towns on the U.S./Mexico Border to search for undocumented persons). The Border Patrol’s undocumented immigrant profile contains class as well as racial elements. See, e.g., Nicacio v. INS, 797 F.2d 700, 704 (9th Cir. 1985) (discussing INS official’s testimony that an officer might properly rely, along with Hispanic appearance, on a “hungry look” and the fact that a person was “dirty, unkempt,” or “wears work clothing”). 37. Orhorhaghe v. INS, 38 F.3d 488, 498 n.16 (9th Cir. 1994). 38. See supra text accompanying notes 16-31. 39. See Johnson, supra note 32, at 711-16; see also MIKE DAVIS, MAGICAL URBANISM: LATINOS REINVENT THE U.S. CITY 59-65 (2000) (discussing how border enforcement adversely affects Latinas/os lawfully in United States far from the border). 40. See Johnson, supra note 32, at 708-09 (reviewing statistical data to make this estimate). 41. See id. at 712 (emphasis added). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 349 Finally, race-based immigration enforcement may well contribute to welldocumented Border Patrol abuses of persons of Mexican ancestry.42 Importantly, race-based border enforcement adversely impacts racial minorities other than Latinas/os. A U.S. General Accounting Office study of searches by U.S. Customs Service officers showed that Black women entering the country were more likely to be subject to intrusive searches than any other group: Black women who were U.S. citizens . . . were 9 times more likely than White women who were U.S. citizens to be xrayed after being frisked or patted down . . . . But on the basis of x-ray results, Black women who were U.S. citizens were less than half as likely to be found carrying contraband as White women who were U.S. citizens.43 In one lawsuit, customs inspectors subjected an African American woman, a U.S. citizen returning from Nigeria who complained about the treatment of a Nigerian citizen by inspectors, to a full pat down and strip search, and many other intrusive procedures, including examination of her rectal and vaginal cavities, in an unsuccessful hunt for drugs.44 Incidents of discrimination in customs searches at ports of entry are regularly reported.45 In addition, persons of African ancestry who arrive at airports often are presumed to be entering the country unlawfully. The Immigration and Naturalization Service (INS) accused a Black college student, returning from a visit to Jamaica, with lawful immigration status, of being in the United States on false documents and strip searched, shackled, and 42. See AMNESTY INT’L, UNITED STATES OF AMERICA: HUMAN RIGHTS CONCERNS IN THE BORDER REGION WITH MEXICO (1998); AMERICAN FRIENDS SERVICE COMMITTEE, HUMAN AND CIVIL RIGHTS VIOLATIONS ON THE U.S. MEXICO BORDER 1995-97, SAN DIEGO, CA. (1998), available at www.afsc.org/border.htm. See, e.g., Murillo v. Musegades, 809 F. Supp. 487 (W.D. Tex. 1992). 43. See U.S. GEN. ACCOUNTING OFFICE, U.S. CUSTOMS SERVICE: BETTER TARGETING OF AIRLINE PASSENGERS FOR PERSONAL SEARCHES COULD PRODUCE BETTER RESULTS 2 (2000). 44. Brent v. United States, 66 F. Supp. 2d 1287, 1289 (S.D. Fla. 1999), aff’d sub nom., Brent v. Ashley, 247 F.3d 1294, 1306 (11th Cir. 2001). 45. See, e.g., David Stout, Customs Service Will Review Drug-Search Process for Bias, N.Y. TIMES, Apr. 9, 1999, at A18 (reporting claims of racial discrimination by U.S. Customs officers in searches); Daria MonDesire, Stripped of More Than My Clothes, USA TODAY, Apr. 7, 1999, at 15A (offering personal account of strip search by U.S. Customs of the only African American woman on flight). In response to concerns about racial profiling, the Customs Service adopted reforms, including limiting discretion of officers to conduct searches, that reduced unwarranted searches of minorities while increasing drug seizures. See Kevin R. Johnson, U.S. Border Enforcement: Drugs, Migrants, and the Rule of Law, 47 VILL. L. REV. 897, 912-15 (2002). 350 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 detained him.46 At San Francisco International Airport, immigration officials shackled an African American U.S. citizen returning from Africa, accusing her of unlawfully entering the United States.47 Similarly, in Orhorhaghe v. INS,48 the court of appeals found that the INS was wrong to investigate a person’s immigration status based on his possession of a “Nigerian-sounding name,” which the court reasoned might serve as a proxy for race.49 Such abuses fit into a larger pattern of exclusion of immigrants of African ancestry from the United States.50 The pattern of racial policing at the border reflects reliance on stereotypes about persons of African ancestry as lawbreakers, the same preconceptions that contribute to racial profiling in domestic criminal law enforcement.51 At the border, the law permits racial profiling, just as it does in immigration enforcement in the interior of the country.52 Indeed, the Supreme Court has held that the U.S. government has free reign to conduct warrantless searches without probable cause at ports of entry.53 As the Court explained, “[s]ince the founding of our Republic, Congress has granted the Executive plenary authority to conduct routine searches and seizures at the border, without probable cause or a warrant, in order to regulate the collection of duties and to prevent the introduction of contraband into this country.”54 As one court emphasized in rejecting the challenge of a lawful U.S. immigrant from Nigeria to a search, the “contention that a border search is not routine [and thus subject to the 46. See Toni Locy, Lawsuit Spotlights Alleged INS Abuses at Airports, USA TODAY, Oct. 18, 2000, at 11A. 47. See Reynolds Holding, Power of INS Agents Outweigh Proof, S.F. CHRON., June 4, 2000, at 3. 48. 38 F.3d 488 (9th Cir. 1994). 49. Id. at 497-98. 50. See Bill Ong Hing, Immigration Policies: Messages of Exclusion to African Americans, 37 HOW. L.J. 237 (1994) (documenting exclusion of African immigrants to United States through immigration law and its enforcement); Lolita K. Buckner Inniss, Tricky Magic: Blacks as Immigrants and the Paradox of Foreignness, 49 DEPAUL L. REV. 85 (1999) (analyzing treatment of Black immigrants and African Americans in United States); Hope Lewis, Global Intersections: Critical Race Feminist Human Rights and Inter/National Black Women, 50 ME. L. REV. 309 (1998) (discussing international human rights issues of Jamaican immigrant women to United States). 51. See supra text accompanying notes 11-31. 52. See supra text accompanying notes 33-35. 53. See Theodore P. Metzler, Thirtieth Annual Review of Criminal Procedure: Introduction and Guide for Users: I. Investigation and Police Practices: Warrantless Searches and Seizures, 89 GEO. L.J. 1084, 1141-46 (2001) (analyzing case law of border searches); see also United States v. Zapata-Ibarra, 223 F.3d 281, 281 (5th Cir. 2000) (Wiener, J., dissenting) (contending that U.S. “government’s so-called War on Drugs and its efforts to interdict illegal immigration” have eviscerated Fourth Amendment protections in entire border region). 54. United States v. Montoya de Hernandez, 473 U.S. 531, 537 (1985) (citation omitted) (emphasis added). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 351 requirement that a border officer have reasonable suspicion of wrongdoing] if motivated by ethnicity of a person searched is groundless.”55 Racial profiles in immigration enforcement affect other groups as well. The U.S. government has harshly treated Arab and Muslim persons, who had been classified as suspected terrorists, in the name of fighting terrorism.56 Based on stereotypes of Arabs and Muslims as terrorists, Congress enacted harsh immigration laws, which the Attorney General has 55. United States v. Ojebode, 957 F.2d 1218, 1223 (5th Cir. 1992) (emphasis added), cert. denied, 507 U.S. 923 (1993). Similarly, the Supreme Court created the plenary power doctrine to immunize the substantive Congressional immigration requirement, which at times has shielded racial and national origin exclusions in the immigration laws. See, e.g., The Chinese Exclusion Case (Chae Chan Ping v. United States), 130 U.S. 581 (1889). Although much-criticized, see, e.g., GERALD L. NEUMAN, STRANGERS TO THE CONSTITUTION: IMMIGRANTS, BORDERS AND FUNDAMENTAL LAW (1996), the doctrine remains good law. See, e.g., Reno v. Flores, 507 U.S. 292, 305-06 (1993); Fiallo v. Bell, 430 U.S. 787, 792 (1977). 56. See generally Susan M. Akram, Scheherezade Meets Kafka: Two Dozen Sordid Tales of Ideological Exclusion, 14 GEO. IMMIGR. L.J. 51 (1999) (analyzing critically U.S. government’s use of secret evidence in seeking to remove two dozen Arab and Muslim noncitizens from United States); Natsu Taylor Saito, Symbolism Under Seige: Japanese American Redress and the “Racing” of Arab Americans as “Terrorists,” 8 ASIAN L.J. 1, 11-26 (2001) (analyzing treatment of Arabs as a distinctive “race” and stereotyping them as terrorists with negative immigration consequences); Michael J. Whidden, Note, Unequal Justice: Arabs in America and United States Antiterrorism Legislation, 69 FORDHAM L. REV. 2825 (2001) (analyzing how 1996 immigration reform legislation has resulted in discrimination against persons of Arab ancestry); see, e.g., Al Najjar v. Reno, 97 F. Supp. 2d 1329 (S.D. Fla. 2000) (reviewing habeas corpus petition of Palestinian man detained by the U.S. government while facing removal based on secret evidence); Kiareldeen v. Reno, 71 F. Supp. 2d 402 (D. N.J. 1999) (granting habeas corpus to Palestinian man detained for over a year based on secret evidence of alleged terrorist activity). After the tragic loss of life on September 11, 2001, racial profiling of Arab- and Muslim-appearing people reached new heights as part of the “war on terror.” See Susan M. Akram & Kevin R. Johnson, Race, Civil Rights, and Immigration Law After September 11, 2001: The Targeting of Arabs and Muslims, 58 NYU ANNUAL SURVEY AM. L. 101 (forthcoming 2002). For analysis of the civil rights impact of the federal government’s responses to the events of September 11, see David Cole, Enemy Aliens, 54 STAN. L. REV. 953 (2002); Bill Ong Hing, Vigilante Racism: The De-Americanization and Subordination of Immigrant America, 7 MICH. J. RACE & L. 441 (2002); Thomas W. Joo, Presumed Disloyal: Wen Ho Lee, War on Terrorism and Construction of Race, 34 COLUM. HUM. RTS. L. REV. (forthcoming 2002); Victor C. Romero, Proxies for Loyalty in Constitutional Immigration Law: Citizenship and Race After September 11, 52 DEPAUL L. REV. (forthcoming 2002); Leti Volpp, The Citizen and the Terrorist, 49 UCLA L. REV. 1575 (2002); see also Samuel R. Gross & Debra Livingston, Racial Profiling Under Attack, 102 COLUM. L. REV. 1413 (2002) (analyzing debate over racial profiling after September 11). 352 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 enforced with vigor.57 Arab and Muslim immigrants, and at times citizens, have suffered the full legal consequences. Similarly, persons of Asian ancestry have suffered from race-based immigration enforcement. In one case, a court ruled that the “appearance of being oriental” combined with other factors justified continued observation by an INS officer.58 Similarly, the Board of Immigration Appeals stated that “Oriental appearance, combined with the past history of illegal alien employment at [a] particular restaurant, and [an] anonymous tip” justified INS questioning of restaurant workers about their immigration status.59 Not that long ago, Portland earned the nickname “Deportland” because of the rigorous scrutiny by the INS of the immigration status of Asian tourists, causing a major airline carrier to end direct flights from Japan to the city.60 Exemplified by the infamous Japanese internment during World War II,61 Asian Americans, whatever 57. See STEPHEN H. LEGOMSKY, IMMIGRATION AND REFUGEE LAW AND POLICY 735-37 (2d ed. 1997) (summarizing 1996 changes to immigration law creating special “alien” terrorist removal proceedings, in which noncitizens could be ordered removed from country based on secret evidence); see, e.g., Reno v. Am.-Arab Anti-Discrimination Comm., 525 U.S. 471 (1999) (declining review of various constitutional, including First Amendment, challenges to deportation by various noncitizens who allegedly had provided financial support to Palestinian organizations); see also Berta Esperanza Hernández-Truyol, Nativism, Terrorism, and Human Rights–The Global Wrongs of Reno v. American-Arab Anti-Discrimination Committee, 31 COLUM. HUM. RTS. L. REV. 521 (2000) (criticizing the decision in American-Arab Anti-Discrimination Committee on the grounds that it violated international human rights prohibitions on discrimination on the basis of race, nationality, and ethnicity); Adrien Katherine Wing, Reno v. American-Arab Anti-Discrimination Committee: A Critical Race Perspective, 31 COLUM. HUM. RTS. L. REV. 561 (2000) (analyzing American-Arab Anti-Discrimination Committee decision from Critical Race Theory perspective). In response to the events of September 11, 2001, Congress passed the Uniting and Strengthening America by Providing Appropriate Tools Required to Intercept and Obstruct Terrorism (USA PATRIOT Act) Act of 2001, Pub. L. No. 107-56, 115 Stat. 272 (2001), which expanded the definition of “terrorist activity” under the immigration laws and likely will have an adverse impact on Arab and Muslim noncitizens. See Akram & Johnson, supra note 56. 58. Cheung Tin Wong v. INS, 468 F.2d 1123, 1127-28 (D.C. Cir. 1972). 59. In re King & Yang, 16 I. & N. Dec. 502, 504-05 (BIA 1978). 60. See Florangela Davila, Hard-Line INS Under Fire in ‘Deportland’, SEATTLE TIMES, Sept. 11, 2000, at B5; Sam Howe Verhovek, Besmirched ‘Deportland’ Wrestles with the I.N.S., N.Y. TIMES, Aug. 31, 2000, at A14. 61. See Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214 (1944). See generally Symposium, The Long Shadow of Korematsu, 40 B.C. L. REV. 1 (1998) (analyzing implications of Korematsu decision). 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 353 their immigration status, long have been classified as foreigners,62 which makes them of presumptively suspect immigration status. II. SIMILAR HARMS, COMMON CONCERNS, AND THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN DIFFERENT FORMS OF RACE-BASED LAW ENFORCEMENT Similar harms to African Americans and Latinas/os flow from the influence of race in the enforcement of criminal and immigration laws.63 Importantly, race-based law enforcement is part of a larger series of institutions and cultural practices that relegate racial minorities to a castelike, second-class citizenship.64 Both African Americans and Latinas/os have suffered serious limitations to their citizenship rights, often finding those rights manipulated through law.65 The only way that both groups can move toward full membership in U.S. society is by “de-racing” law enforcement. Common concerns suggest the need for political coalitions generally challenging the use of race in law enforcement.66 The operation of the criminal justice system deeply shapes the lives of African Americans and Latinas/os in the United States. These groups, both overrepresented in our jails and prisons, must work together politically to eradicate the endemic 62. See generally ROBERT S. CHANG, DISORIENTED: ASIAN AMERICANS, LAW, AND THE NATION-STATE (1999); Keith Aoki, “Foreign-Ness” and Asian American Identities: Yellowface, World War II Propaganda, and Bifurcated Racial Stereotypes, 4 UCLA ASIAN PAC. AM. L.J. 1 (1996); Natsu Taylor Saito, Alien and Non-Alien Alike: Citizenship, “Foreignness,” and Racial Hierarchy in American Law, 76 OR. L. REV. 261 (1997). Because of common concerns with immigration enforcement, political coalitions between Asian Americans and Latinas/os to challenge arbitrary INS conduct hold promise. See Kevin R. Johnson, Racial Hierarchy, Asian Americans and Latinos as “Foreigners,” and Social Change: Is Law the Way to Go?, 76 OR. L. REV. 347, 365-67 (1997). But see Rachel F. Moran, What If Latinos Really Mattered in the Public Policy Debate?, 85 CAL. L. REV. 1315, 1321-31 (1997) (questioning whether Asian American and Latina/o experiences are analogous). 63. See supra text accompanying notes 16-31, 38-42. 64. See generally KENNETH L. KARST, BELONGING TO AMERICA: EQUAL CITIZENSHIP AND THE CONSTITUTION (1989) (discussing efforts of various subordinated groups to secure full citizenship status in U.S. social life). 65. See Guadalupe T. Luna, The Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo and Dred Scott v. Sandford: “Aren’t They All Illegal Anyway?,” in RACE IN 21ST CENTURY AMERICA 297 (Curtis Stokes et al. eds., 2001) (examining how citizenship rights of Chicanas/os and African Americans have been manipulated through legal and illegal means). 66. See John Garcia, Coalition Formation: The Mexican-Origin Community and Latinos and African Americans, in IMMIGRATION AND RACE: NEW CHALLENGES FOR AMERICAN DEMOCRACY 255, 265-74 (Gerald D. Jaynes ed., 2000) (analyzing potential for African American and Latina/o political coalitions); see also Charles R. Lawrence III, Race, Multiculturalism, and the Jurisprudence of Transformation, 47 STAN. L. REV. 819, 839-47 (1995) (discussing importance of multiracial coalitions in seeking to build movement for social change). 354 FLORIDA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55 racism in the criminal justice system. Past successful multiracial coalitions suggest the possibility of future ones.67 African Americans and Latinas/os disproportionately suffer harms from racial profiling in criminal law enforcement.68 Discrimination against Blacks and Browns in the criminal justice system are deeply interrelated. Not coincidentally, many lawsuits challenging racial profiling by police departments claim that African Americans and Latinas/os suffer discrimination due to the practice.69 Similarly, race-based border enforcement not only adversely affects Latinas/os, but also injures persons of African and Asian ancestry.70 Given the similar injuries caused by the influence of race on law enforcement, racial minorities have common interests in removing race from the enforcement calculus. Because of the disparate racial impacts of the operation of law, criminal and immigration law scholarship have taken similar intellectual trajectories. As in the criminal law,71 attention is now being paid to the racial consequences of immigration law and its enforcement.72 Indeed, Professor Randall Kennedy treats the use of race in both criminal law and immigration enforcement as interchangeable.73 This makes sense given that they are difficult to distinguish intellectually. The Los Angeles Police Department (LAPD), which has a long history of violating the civil rights of Latinas/os and African Americans, offers a case study of the relationship between race-based criminal and immigration enforcement. During the Depression, the LAPD helped facilitate the forced repatriation—in the name of reducing the welfare rolls—of Mexican citizens and immigrants to Mexico.74 Later, during the infamous “Zoot Suit” riots in which white mobs attacked Mexican “gang” members during World War II, the LAPD declined to protect the minority crime victims.75 67. See Kevin R. Johnson, Lawyering for Social Change: What’s a Lawyer to Do?, 5 MICH. J. RACE & L. 201, 226-27 (1999) (providing examples of multiracial coalitions in civil rights litigation); William R. Tamayo, When the “Coloreds” Are Neither Black Nor Citizens: The United States Civil Rights Movement and Global Migration, 2 ASIAN L.J. 1, 30-31 (1995) (offering some examples of multiracial political coalitions). 68. See supra text accompanying notes 10-62. 69. See cases cited supra note 13. 70. See supra text accompanying notes 43-62. 71. See supra text accompanying notes 11-15. 72. See THE PRESIDENT’S INITIATIVE ON RACE, supra note 1, at 90-92; NINETY-EIGHTH AMERICAN ASSEMBLY, RACIAL EQUALITY: PUBLIC POLICIES FOR THE TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY 1214 (2001); George A. Martinez, Race and Immigration Law: A Paradigm Shift?, 2000 U. ILL. L. REV. 517. 73. See KENNEDY, supra note 12, at 150-59. 74. See EDWIN J. ESCOBAR, RACE, POLICE, AND THE MAKING OF A POLITICAL IDENTITY: MEXICAN AMERICANS AND THE LOS ANGELES POLICE DEPARTMENT, 1900-1945, at 84-90 (1999). 75. See Robert S. Chang, Policing the Criminal Justice System: Los Angeles as a SingleCelled Organism, 34 LOY. L.A. L. REV. 843, 845-49 (2001) (analyzing relationship between Los 2003] THE SIXTH ANNUAL LATCRIT CONFERENCE 355 In 1992, violence sparked by the legal vindication of police officers who brutalized Rodney King76 was followed by police abuse of African Americans and Latinas/os, many of whom were rounded up by the LAPD and turned over to the INS for removal as part of the massive effort to quell the violence.77 Over the last few years, media attention has focused on the infamous LAPD Ramparts Division for its systematic violations of the civil rights of African American and Latina/o youth.78 Part of this unit’s unlawful strategy involved police cooperation with the INS, including street sweeps, arrests of Latinas/os, and turning over noncitizens to the INS who could not be subject to criminal prosecution due to the lack of evidence, all o