EMPIRICISM Quine`s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”
Transcription
EMPIRICISM Quine`s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”
Quine EMPIRICISM PHIL3072, ANU, 2015 Jason Grossman http://empiricism.xeny.net Willard van Orman Quine, 1908–2000 anecdote PhD supervised by Whitehead. Very important mathematician. Taught (e.g.) Donald Davidson, Gilbert Harman, David Lewis, Daniel Dennett and Hao Wang. lecture 15: 20 October Quine's “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” Ayer to Quine Quine is sometimes seen as the great “post-positivist” defeater of the logical positivists but he was essentially a logical positivist himself. e.g., “Our channel of continuing information about the world is the impact of molecules and light rays on our sensory receptors; just this and some kinaesthetic incidentals.” — W. v. O. Quine, “In praise of observation sentences”, The Journal of Philosophy, 1993; XC: 107–116,p. 108 “So far as evidence goes . . . our ontology is neutral. Nor let us imagine beyond it some inaccessible reality. The very terms `thing' and `exist' and `real', after all, make no sense apart from human conceptualization. Asking after the thing in itself, apart from human conceptualization, is like asking how long the Nile really is, apart from our parochial miles or kilometers.” — W. v. O. Quine, “In praise of observation sentences”, The Journal of Philosophy, 1993; XC: 107–116,p. 113 “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” 1951; revised 1961 “Modern empiricism has been conditioned in large part by two dogmas. One is a belief in some fundamental cleavage between truths which are analytic, or grounded in meanings independently of matters of fact and truths which are synthetic, or grounded in fact.” — W. v. O. Quine, Two Dogmas of Empiricism, 1961, http://www.ditext.com/quine/quine.html, viewed 12/2/2008 And this is not just a dogma of empiricism. Quine is not completely opposed to the analytic/synthetic distinction. In fact he seems to believe in exactly the same distinction as Hume used in his Fork. Unlike Hume, he thinks this is bad news for empiricism. “The other dogma is reductionism: the belief that each meaningful statement is equivalent to some logical construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience.” From analyticity to meaning “Kant's intent . . . can be restated thus: a statement is analytic when it is true by virtue of meanings and independently of fact.” — W. v. O. Quine, Two Dogmas of Empiricism, 1961, http://www.ditext.com/quine/quine.html, viewed 12/2/2008 But Quine is dubious that that's the case except in the case of logical analyticity . . . Two types of analyticity (at least not four any more) “(1) No unmarried man is unmarried. . . . is not merely true as it stands, but remains true under any and all reinterpretations of `man' and `married'. If we suppose a prior inventory of logical particles, comprising `no', `un-', `not', `if', `then', `and', etc., then in general a logical truth is a statement which is true and remains true under all reinterpretations of its components other than the logical particles.” — W. v. O. Quine, Two Dogmas of Empiricism, 1961, http://www.ditext.com/quine/quine.html, viewed 12/2/2008 Quine has nothing bad to say about this type of analyticity. But this is the whole of the “relations of ideas” side of Hume's fork (I think — Hume is not very clear about this) and It's all that Russell and Carnap need for their reductionist programs! And Quine explicitly agrees with this! A complicating factor is that this rst type of analyticity depends on logic, and logic may be a moving target. Quine agrees with Russell “With regard to the word “synthetic”, the precise de nition is dif cult, but for our purposes we may de ne it negatively as any proposition which is not part of mathematics or deductive logic, and is not deducible from any proposition of mathematics or deductive logic. Thus it excludes not only `2 and 2 are 4' but also `two apples and two apples are four apples'.” Two types of analyticity (at least not four any more) “(1) No unmarried man is unmarried.” “(2) No bachelor is married. . . . can be turned into a logical truth [only] by putting synonyms for synonyms . . . by putting `unmarried man' for its synonym `bachelor'.” This is Quine's target. — Betrand Russell, “Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits”, Allen and Unwin, 1948, p. 516 So his question is whether we can judge sameness of meaning. He thinks not. Meaning The argument against meaning “For the theory of meaning the most conspicuous question is as to the nature of its objects: what sort of things are meanings? “Meanings . . . purport to be entities of a special sort: the meaning of an expression is the idea expressed. A felt need for meant entities [!] may derive from an earlier failure to appreciate that meaning and reference are distinct.” Now there is considerable agreement among modern linguists that the idea of an idea . . . is worse than worthless for linguistic science. I think the behaviorists are right in holding that talk of ideas is bad business even for psychology.” This is criticism of Frege and Russell. “Once the theory of meaning is sharply separated from the theory of reference, it is a short step to recognizing as the business of the theory of meaning simply the synonymy of linguistic forms and the analyticity of statements; meanings themselves, as obscure intermediary entities, may well be abandoned.” Linguists do not say that, and didn't in 1951 either. Some psychologists did (in 1951). — W. v. O. Quine, “The Problem of Meaning in Linguistics”, in From a Logical Point of View, Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1961, pp. 47–48 Note the almost complete lack of argument for this . . . A restricted type of synonymy “we are not concerned here with synonymy in the sense of complete identity in psychological associations or poetic quality; indeed no two expressions are synonymous in such a sense.” So perhaps it's not surprising that non-logical synonymy turns out to be suspect. — W. v. O. Quine, Two Dogmas of Empiricism, 1961, http://www.ditext.com/quine/quine.html, viewed 12/2/2008 — and all the rest of the quotes are also from this Can synonymy be de ned? “There are those who nd it soothing to say that the analytic statements of the second class reduce to those of the rst class, the logical truths, by de nition; `bachelor,' for example, is de ned as `unmarried man.' But how do we nd that `bachelor' is de ned as 'unmarried man'? Who de ned it thus, and when? Are we to appeal to the nearest dictionary, and accept the lexicographer's formulation as law? Clearly this would be to put the cart before the horse. The lexicographer is an empirical scientist, whose business is the recording of antecedent facts” I think this is dead right . . . although again not argued for! Quine didn't have to argue for all his views, but you do! Why de nition doesn't give us synonymy Interchangeability If the empirical lexicographer “glosses `bachelor' as `unmarried man' it is because of his belief that there is a relation of synonymy between these forms, implicit in general or preferred usage prior to his own work.” “A natural suggestion . . . is that the synonymy of two linguistic forms consists simply in their interchangeability in all contexts without change of truth value . . . So? Note that synonyms so conceived need not even be free from vagueness, as long as the vaguenesses match. Why can't he (or she) discover real synonymies from people's behaviour? But it is not quite true that the synonyms `bachelor' and 'unmarried man' are everywhere interchangeable salva veritate. Especially if behaviourism is right? Truths which become false under substitution of `unmarried man' for `bachelor' are easily constructed with help of `bachelor of arts' or `bachelor's buttons.' ” And even more easily now: `con rmed bachelor'. Extensionality “Suppose now we consider a language containing just the following materials. There is an inde nitely large stock of one-place predicates (for example, `F' where `Fx' means that x is a man) and many-placed predicates (for example, `G' where `Gxy' means that x loves y) . . .” “Such a language can be adequate to classical mathematics and indeed to scienti c discourse generally, except in so far as the latter involves debatable devices such as contrary-to-fact conditionals or modal adverbs like `necessarily'. [!!] . . . Now [in] a language of this type . . . any two predicates which agree extensionally (i.e., are true of the same objects) are interchangeable salva veritate. . . . therefore, interchangeability salva veritate is no assurance of cognitive synonymy of the desired type.” “Empiricism without the dogmas” — the web of belief “The totality of our so-called knowledge or beliefs, from the most casual matters of geography and history to the profoundest laws of atomic physics or even of pure mathematics and logic, [!] is a man-made fabric which impinges on experience only along the edges. . . . A con ict with experience at the periphery occasions readjustments in the interior of the eld. Truth values have to be [and can be] redistributed over some of our statements. . . . But the total eld is so underdetermined by its boundary conditions, experience, that there is much latitude of choice as to what statements to re-evaluate . . . No particular experiences are linked with any particular statements in the interior . . . except indirectly through considerations of equilibrium affecting the eld as a whole. [So] it is misleading to speak of the empirical content of an individual statement — especially [or only?!] if it be a statement at all remote from the experiential periphery” “Empiricism without the dogmas” — conclusions “As an empiricist I continue to think of the conceptual scheme of science as a tool, ultimately, for predicting future experience in the light of past experience. Physical objects are conceptually imported into the situation as convenient intermediaries — not by de nition in terms of experience, but simply as irreducible posits . . . Ontological questions, under this view, are on a par with questions of natural science. . . . Some issues do, I grant, seem more a question of convenient conceptual scheme and others more a question of brute fact. The issue over there being [mathematical sets] seems more a question of convenient conceptual scheme; the issue over there being centaurs, or brick houses on Elm Street, seems more a question of fact. But I have been urging that this difference is only one of degree.”