The artist as researcher
Transcription
The artist as researcher
Reader Can art be demonstrated? The artist as researcher A two-day international conference on artistic research and the PhD in visual art and design. Royal Academy of Arts (KA BK) The Hague, 5-6 February 2010 For more information www.lectoraatkabk.nl and www.phdarts.eu Contact: [email protected] The conference is organised by PhDarts in collaboration with the Institute for Practice-based Research in the Arts (IvOK) of the K.U. Leuven Association. PhDarts - Leiden University Academy of Creative and Performing Arts - Royal Academy of Arts Prinsessegracht 4 NL 2514 AN The Hague Contents: James Elkins. The Three Configurations of Studio-ArtPhDs. James Elkins (ed.). Artists with PhDs – On the new Doctoral Degree in Studio Art. New Academia Publishing, Washington DC 2009, pp. 145-164. Kristin Baxter, Hugo Or tega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan. The Necessity of Studio Art as a Site and Source for Dissertation Research. JADE 27/1 (2008), pp. 418. Stev en Scrivener. Reflection in and on action and practice in creative-production doctoral projects in art and design. Working Papers in Art and Design 1 (2000) Mick Wilson. Four Theses Attempting to Revise the Terms of a Debate. James Elkins (ed.). Artists with PhDs – On the new Doctoral Degree in Studio Art. New Academia Publishing, Washington DC 2009, pp. 57-70. Die ter Lesage. Whoʼs Afraid of Artistic Research? On measuring artistic research output. Art&Research – A Journal of Ideas, Contexts and Methods 2/2 (Spring 2009) Henk Borgdorff. Artistic Research and Academia: an Uneas y Relationship. Autonomi och egenart - konstnärlig forskning söker identitet (Autonomy and Inividuality - Artistic Research Seeks an Identity), Yearbook for Artistic Research 2008. Swedish Research Council, pp. 8297. Kathrin Bush. Artistic Research and the Poetics of Knowledge. Art&Research – A Journal of Ideas, Contexts and Methods 2/2 (Spring 2009) Mika Hannula, Juha Suoranta, Tere Vadén. Chapter 5: The Meaning of Artistic Research. In: Artistic Research – theories, methods and practice. Academy of Fine Arts, Helsinki 2005, pp 151-162. Tom Holert. Art in the Knowledge-based Polis. E-Flux. Journal #3 (February 2009). Die ter Lesage. A Portrait of the Artist as a Researcher. Vector. arta si cultura în context/art and culture in context 04/07, pp.168 – 171. The Necessity of Studio Art as a Site and Source for Dissertation Research Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan Abstract The issue raised by the authors in this article question why studio art continues to be ignored as a site and source for research in art education. The necessity of the field to be able to participate within the research community in addressing cultural, social, educational and political concerns is acknowledged. It is argued, however, that the exclusive use of methods of inquiry that align with the conventions of social science research has been done at the expense of fully appreciating the capacity of artistic research undertaken in studio contexts. This tendency is especially prevalent in doctoral research in higher education. Three accounts of dissertation research are given that incorporate studio activity as a central agency of inquiry in conceptualising and theorising issues. Each highlights the capacity of art practice to reveal insights that are a consequence of what the researcher did in the studio setting as issues, ideas and interpretive stances emerged, and problems were re-conceptualised. What is different in these accounts from more mainstream approaches to research is the readiness to accept that constructing new knowledge is a creative and critical process. JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd Introduction A common call heard across email listserves, in conference corridors, within seminar sessions and among an increasing number of graduate students, is to question how it is that studio art has become so estranged from art education research. Yet there is a perception that approaches to inquiry favoured in art education has moved far from the core experience that has long informed the field, namely, studio art. For a discipline to be able to participate effectively in educational, cultural and political discourse, the necessity of knowledge of prevailing theories and practices is well understood. The history of art education as a discipline mirrors most fields in its transition from a domain that was mainly practical, professional and often provincial, to one that by the latter part of the last century, was grounded in a range of theoretical orientations. Yet, art has always been theoretically robust; it is just that the philosophical and historical traditions did not quite measure up to the powerful theories of the human sciences, which dominated educational research. To become part of the community of disciplines fledgling fields such as art education had to show that research practices could be just as rigorous and clinical as the best social science. This was not too difficult to do because operationalising concepts and exploring effects and relationships under controlled conditions could be done with a similar level of abstraction (some would say precision) as most artificial interventions. What was missing in this early effort to formalise the research basis of art education was a valid connection to reality because experience could not always be defined in incremental measures. Consequently a more expansive attitude to the purposes and practices of research surrounding qualitative inquiry offered more interpretive flexibility in studying the lifeworld of individuals and communities. Seeing the classroom or community as a contextually rich ensemble of complex phenomena and a diverse world of human understanding meant that it had to be understood on its own terms. And this the arts did well. A difficulty arose, however, when the logical outcomes of increasing the range of ways of representing reality as forms that could be identified, explored, analyzed and interpreted as plausible accounts of experience remained wedded to empirical strategies located in the social sciences. The research content certainly expanded, and the narratives became grounded in real life experience, but the procedures stayed well within the analytical traditions that characterised inquiry that was inherently iterative, instrumentalist, bounded by convention, and conceptually rigid in dealing with uncertainty, intuition and imagination. Those in the arts knew that any inquiry undertaken within a framework of constraints could be undertaken quite successfully for limits provide a necessary set of contrasts against which difference can be highlighted. Consequently many practitioners have infused the arts into research, or used the arts as a basis from which research can originate. This is based on the premise that art practice forms a central core of research practice (Sullivan 2006) and has given rise to an expanding repertoire of approaches that serves several purposes. For instance, arts-based research has a clear educational focus (Barone and Eisner 1997), arts-infused research responds to broader social and educational interests (Cole et al. 2004) and practice-based, or practice-led, research is expanding the domain of research practice at the doctoral level in higher education (Macleod & Holdridge 2006). Common to these initiatives is a reconsideration of the role of the artist within the research process. Graduate students in particular are questioning the frameworks that inform the research methods they are being introduced to and are looking to more expansive means to achieve their quest to create and construct new knowledge. This article highlights three such cases. All feature a rethinking of the artist-as-researcher where the domain of inquiry that is missing from the traditional research methods class is found within the art studio. Driven by a desire to identify the most appropriate ways to open up questions and problems, the critical and creative inquiry these examples illustrate are no less rigorous or conceptually taut than more conventional approaches. But they do reconfigure ways to invigorate inquiry with fresh perspectives that have long been associated with studio exploration. These accounts have JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan purposefully been presented in the first person to ensure the vision and voice of the researchers is maintained. Hugo Ortega López: The ‘&’ Dilemma in Art & Art Education Negotiating commonalities among individual practices in art and art education, and the institutional activities these generate, creates a polarity of sorts between those of us labelled ‘artists’ and ‘art teachers’. This is particularly apparent within academic settings. Based on the perceived nature of the art activities, the relation among identity claims, and the cohabitation within an institutional landscape, implies and denies a tacit integration of the realms of practice of both the artist and the art teacher. Materials, tools, techniques and objects are similar, but one claims art as its nature, based on an evolving search through practice, while the other uses art as a means with specific procedures towards pre-established outcomes. It is clear that both are constituted upon the same small units (materials, tools, techniques), but their procedures and processes may differ greatly (acts, events, practices). While the integration of both identities of practice seems to be mutually beneficial, in actuality, their academic cohabitation and professional recognition and branding generates a dichotomy of difference and otherness. Therefore there is a need to understand and locate intrinsic educational knowledge that emanates from art practices within existing institutional procedures in art education. As Fernand Braudel notes in On History (1980, 25) ‘the wish to affirm one’s existence in the face of others is necessarily the basis for new knowledge: to deny someone is already to know him’. Reflecting in those terms, what is behind the studio artist’s instinct to not label its activities as art education and follow different paths of inquiry in research? JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd In considering the dichotomies facing art practitioners who undertake doctoral research several tensions are encountered – some of these are identified in Figure 1. Reading the diagram from the top in the manner of a flow chart, the initial dilemma faced is the need to reconcile individual expectations and institutional demands. This sharpens the focus because personal conceptions and self-interests, which are the primary motivation for inquiry, sometimes compete for attention with academic settings. Yet the unending desire for personal investment in the process of creating new knowledge that is believed to reside within one’s art practice often has a hard time finding a place within academic agendas and actions. Yet conceptual confusion can be a creative spur in its own right as the space between art and art education is opened up. ‘And’, ‘or’, ‘versus’ or any other preposition that could replace the ampersand, clearly establishes a commonality of sorts around art. There is a clear proximity between both activities, whether of form, content, structure, product, technique, history or institutional scaffolding. But, their interaction within an act, event or practice varies greatly. Therefore the initial inquiry into the art and art education divide, within an art education academic paradigm, sets up polarities of a professional practice that involves studio art on one side and art education on the other. Both parts have distinct languages – but build upon the same ‘alphabet’ – yet produce diverse perspectives surrounding the investigation within, about, or on art; what needs to be known; how it may be understood; and the structures used to implement findings as educational implications and strategies. Dilemmas and dialectics An initial stance of this reflection is to assert that the clarification of the proximal relationship between art and art education is more complex than that which can be captured by a mere preposition or an ampersand. The interactive relation of the parameters, within a gradient of practice, should be described, explained and represented through an assemblage of ideas. In my work this can be likened to a set of gears that implements a cycle of practice whereby my individual eye serves to re-vision things in an institutional setting, and this draws on opportunity and improvisation as much as insight and understanding. Cycle, Gear, Eye, Vision, a conceptual dynamic generated from the 1996 New York solo exhibition of assemblages How Many Times … Briefly (Figure 2), has become a conceptual model that guides my philosophy of professional practice and has been extended to strategies used in my doctoral research. Within the academic environment the assemblage practices transfer the materiality of found objects on to fragments of written texts. The rapid assimilation of these concepts, as key components of my methodological perspective, was due to their appropriate ‘fit’ into the rules and regulations of my studio practice. The first theoretical objects were ‘cross-contextualisation’ (Schank 1999) and ‘proximity’ (Bruns 1999). These two concepts expanded the explanation of implemented strategies through immediacy (proximity) and assimilation/appropriation of random material (cross-contextualisation). I never went ‘too far’ to look for materials, the found objects were always around me, and once chosen their modification was always kept to a minimum: only acknowledging their current state as an element of a new work with a new history. Roger Schank, in Dynamic Memory Revisited (1999), explains cross-contextualisation as a simple content transformation with the purpose of borrowing similar dynamics that aid reflection and understanding, through reminders that in the broadest sense become alternative explanations of the original concern. As a found object, ‘proximity’ starts to define the interaction of an assemblage of ideas that may be symbolised by the JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan Opposite page: Figures 1 Locating Art Practice in Graduate Research: Inclusion or Differentiation? This page: Figure 2 Cycle, Gear, Eye, Vision: A Sequence of Art and Research Practice Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan ampersand (&). Gerald Bruns, in Tragic Thoughts at the End of Philosophy (1999), looks at the intersection of literature and philosophy where the attention shifts from universals, spectators, structures and the morality of rules, to particulars, inhabitants, events and the ethics of responsibility. This privileges practice over theory within the limits of language and its mediated form (Bruns 1999). This is what I foresee to be the divide between art and art education – the individual versus the institutionalised intersection between art and art education. The redefinition of this interaction is intended to generate new lines of inquiry, changes in theoretical sources and strategies of how, or what art practices – beyond the art objects – ‘feed’ into art education. For Bruns, proximity is the third component of his philosophical perspective –the first two being theory and practice. The concept of proximity acknowledges the interaction of two factors, the location of the professional and its impact on the surrounding environment. First, he addresses the engagement of the philosopher within the local context. As a result, the philosopher is relocated, not as an outsider, but as a serious and profound inhabitant at ground level of their domain (Bruns 1999, 14). This can be likened to the artistresearcher’s activities within the academia of art education. The second factor that underlies Brun’s notion of proximity comes from the French philosopher Emmanuel Levinas, who acknowledges the impact of the philosopher – due to its new location at ground level – through an exposure that overturns the sovereignty of the philosopher’s former position of ‘privilege’ while retaining the responsibility. Here, proximity, as an ethical concept, is both an event as well as a relation. It is an intervention in the existing order that follows no rules and in a sense it is lawless. It is not a relation that is fostered, or predetermined, it just happens. It ‘is anarchically a relationship with a singularity without mediation of any principle or ideality’ (Bruns 1999, 16). Is this the relation of art and art education in the current paradigms of practice and research? Does art education in the proximity of art happen within the dynamic processes of studio practice? The interaction of these two ‘engines’ with studio practice ‘gears’ allows random findings in other disciplines to provide a visual metaphor to work with and adapt to new forms of explanation for doctoral research within studio art and education. In other words the meaning found in texts, when used as theoretical objects through artistic strategies, can readily be ignored as they stand for a structure of relationships in a new context that invests meaning through proximity and crosscontextualisation. The ‘&’ dilemma and the specific dialects of both parts serve as a reminder of the intrinsic conflict of knowledge structure and communication strategies of an individual and an institution. The challenge is how the intrinsic knowledge structure and language of an art practitioner, as it happens, is accepted as evidence and valid testimony of a research event for academic standards. Could it be that the voice and vision of the artist and his or her studio practice has been altered, even ‘mutated’ by the standardised practices of the academy and the prevalence of verbal/written languages dealing with art related activities? If this is the case, then the way artist-researchers create opportunities, strategies, and make use of forms of inquiry that explore alterity and differentiation (Taussig 1993) needs to be acknowledged. Kristin Baxter: Family Photographs as Organisers of Experience Considering art practice as research can be looked at in two, seemingly opposing, ways. On the one hand, the identification of an inquiry or a problem is the fuel generating one’s art practice. On the other hand, one’s art practice generates an area of inquiry or a problem within the field. In short, one can look at art-practice-as-research as an area of inquiry or problem solving that generates ideas for making things, or as a process of making things that identifies an area of inquiry. In my experience, however, there is often a bit of both. During the writing of my dissertation, my studio practice allowed me to probe areas of inquiry until I could clearly identify research questions. As I returned to the studio, it provided further insight into additional questions, research methods and limitations, as well as possibilities JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan for analysis. The reflexive process characteristic of my art practice yielded research questions and the making of a specific art installation allowed me to work through research design problems, and provided insights into my methodology. Re-searching problems Through my art practice, I re-collect found objects from the home, such as old letters, souvenirs, diary entries and photographs, and create installations and assemblages. The reflexive creation of meaning in works of art and research practice first became evident to me as I viewed hundreds of family slides from the 1960s. The content and composition of many snapshots and slides beg for deeper understanding, such as family snapshots from the 1920s (Figure 3), 1960s (Figure 4), and 1970s (Figure 5). Similarly, the slides I viewed with my parents triggered stories about the objects contained in them: the dinner plates, cars, bedspreads, jewellery, shoes and so on. The meaning of the images appeared limitless, yet they were ordinary pictures of ordinary people doing ordinary things, surrounded by ordinary objects. Furthermore, a review of the literature on family snapshots and family albums pointed to gaps in knowledge about privately held meanings that photographs hold for family members. The question that emerged as my dissertation focus was, ‘What evidence is there that family photographs and their associated narratives organise experience?’ Contextualising research issues through art practice Clearly, as I spoke with my parents about their slides in the early months of 2001, I witnessed the stories and meanings of my parents’ slide collection, created forty years earlier, and how these stories gave shape to lives that were lived. This appeared a rich area of exploration for my art practice. Therefore, the search for understanding multiple layers of meaning of family-created images was the purpose of the installation entitled Imagine a posterity that would know your face. This installation was part of my doctoral exhibition entitled Recollections presented in Macy Gallery, Teachers College Columbia University. The issues that emerged from building the research design for this dissertation were similar JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd This page: Figure 3 Evan Blomkvist Sr. 1926, unknown location Figure 4 Kay Baxter. 1964. Bermuda Figure 5 Glenn Baxter and his cat. September, 1974. Queens, New York 10 Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan issues addressed in this installation. The first concerned how to select and exhibit family slides as sites of research and artistic inquiry. The second concerned the use of the stories associated with family photography given the range of personal meanings associated with images. A final issue related to the impact of intersubjectivity and reflexivity in forming meanings from images. The installation included a white box, measuring approximately 0.9 metre square and 1.2 metres high in the centre of a room in Macy Gallery. The box contained three slide projectors that displayed images on three walls of the gallery. The projectors were programmed to run on a continuous loop so that when a viewer entered the room, he or she met three simultaneously running slide shows depicting images from my parents’ collection of weddings, babies, tourist locations, scenery, homes, pets and the like, taken during the 1960s through to the early 1970s. Each slide carousel contained 140 slides that were, in their original context, part of my parents’ collection of more than 900 slides. In selecting the slides for this installation, I avoided creating a linear, chronological narrative about certain experiences depicted in the slides. Instead, I was interested in including a representa- tive sample of images, from posed wedding shots, for instance, to ‘mistake’ images, where the slide was entirely black, out of focus, or the content was almost indecipherable, such as the image of my father looking down the end of a cannon (Figure 6). Moreover, groups of slides that shared content were not necessarily placed next to one another in the carousels. This reflected the experience I had discussing the images with my parents: the slides were sometimes out of order in the boxes in which they were stored; the narratives associated with the slides often did not proceed in a linear way, but instead branched off into related (or seemingly unrelated) narratives triggered by the slides. I wanted the installation to reflect the range of content found in the slides and the experience of sharing narratives about them. In creating the installation, I was the artist, the researcher, as well as a family member engaging with other family members who also helped me create the work of art. During the installation the slide projectors advanced images at different intervals, so the experience involved the viewer continually shifting his or her attention among the slides projected on the three walls of the room. Moreover, each slide appeared on each wall for only several seconds. The cumulative effect of the JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd 11 Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan installation involved the sound of the projectors clicking as they advanced, their fans humming, the movement of the images, and the intervals of light and darkness this created in the room. The physical arrangement of this installation engaged layers of senses. This interactive relationship between researcher and participants is framed by intersubjectivity and also explores the reflexive ways in which an image shapes a viewer’s meaning and, at the same time, how a viewer’s meaning also changes the image. One intention of the installation was to engage the individual’s senses while at the same time invoke personal meanings. One viewer remarked that she was moved by the experience of this installation because although she did not know any of the people pictured in the slides, she felt, ‘They still could have been my photographs. It’s like I have the same photographs at home of my parents’ wedding and all.’ Even if a viewer did not make a personal connection to the images, it opened up a line of questioning, consciously or unconsciously, such as ‘How do other families live?’ ‘How do they represent themselves doing the things they do in photographs?’ ‘How do these “ways of living” relate to my own experiences?’ The slides asked viewers to imagine the identity of the people in the images, what they were doing and where they were. Simultaneously, the images nested into the viewer’s prior experiences as he or she related the people, events, locations and experiences that were photographed. Thus, in this reflexive interaction, the image shapes the viewer’s meanings which emerge from various contexts, and the viewer’s meanings changed how the image is viewed from that point on. Hinging narratives that re-contextualise experience The reflexive relationship between the slides and the viewers creates meaning in a continual interplay of images and ideas. As a result of interview data and visual data from family photographs, I concluded that there are unique types of narratives I call, ‘hinging narratives’ (Baxter 2005, 156), which have reflexivity as a key component, and through which one remembers and conceptually organises life experiences. Although the slides indeed depicted particular moments and recorded specific places at specific times, the slides, like all photographs, were not static. Photographs remind us of a past (Figure 7) but they also imply a future. For instance, when viewing a recent family photograph a viewer may imagine what future generations might think of the image. Or, when viewing an old photograph in a family’s collection a viewer might imagine what life was like generations ago, imagine details about the people and their homes and imagine what the children were like and who they grew up to be (Figure 8). The title of my installation Imagine a posterity that would know your face comes from Hirsch’s (1981) insight that family photography has democratised the ability for individuals to create, preserve, and collect images of them. Until the introduction of popular photography in the mid nineteenth century, only the rich enjoyed this opportunity through painted portraits, miniatures or sculptures. As a result of the innovation of print photography, Hirsch (1981, 44) observes that a broad range of people could capture images of their families ‘to see before them their own gene- JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd Opposite page: Figure 6 Cannon’s view. September 1964. Bermuda This page: Figure 7 Evan and Jean Blomkvist, Glenn, Tom, and Kay Baxter at the funeral of Ruth Isakson. September, 1996. Long Island, New York Figure 8 Evan, Sr. and Agot Blomkvist and friends. c.1930. New York 12 Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan alogy, and to be able to imagine a posterity that would know their faces’. On the one hand, family photographs allow viewers to see their ‘own genealogy’, their own ancestral links. On the other hand, family photographs allow viewers to imagine how they will be portrayed to their descendents. This conceptual movement in time and space is a key feature of photography and was one of the central themes explored of the installation. Using art practice as research allowed me to identify valuable areas of inquiry, to interrogate methodological issues, and ultimately to understand how images and narratives are continually re-collected and used to organise life experience. Dan Serig: A Conceptual Structure of Visual Metaphor As with the research of Kristin Baxter and Hugo Ortega López, my art practice weaves through several processes, from developing research questions to forming findings. This case study focuses on how my studio practice influenced and impacted my data analysis and the transition from results to findings. In doing so, I illuminate how artistic practices can transform a critical point in conducting research. My dissertation explores how artists create visual metaphor (Serig 2005; 2006) [1]. The voice of the artist seemed absent from the literature on this topic despite the multi-disciplinary interest in metaphor. There are cognitive ideas about visual metaphor appearing in the arts (Efland 2002), philosophical ideas (Aldrich 1968; 1971; Hausman 1989) and psychological ideas (Dent 1987; Dent & Rosenberg 1990), but the voice of the artist was missing. Since I am interested in cognition and patterns of artistic behaviour and artistic thinking, this seemed like an appropriate area for my inquiry. I organised a group of artists for an exhibition at the Pearl Street Gallery in Brooklyn, New York [Resonance 10/04], and conducted a series of interviews exploring this central research question: Is there a conceptual structure to the creation of visual metaphors by artists that closely aligns with the cognitive view of metaphoric thinking? A consortium of four artists was identified through an opportunity sample to plan and undertake an exhibition at the gallery. These primary artist-participants were engaged in developing the gallery into an artist-run space for exhibitions, and I knew them through previous collaborations. The artists met to collaborate and explore connections to the research question. Part of the process was the recruitment of other artists for the exhibition and study. The resulting group of artists worked in various media, processes and content. My assumption was that the relationships between the artists would enable the differing works of art to be integrated in a group exhibition. Data analysis and conceptual structures The analysis of data during this study involved continual reflection in which many components occurred simultaneously. These critical moments were facilitated by a phenomenographic approach whereby information in all of its forms was analysed. This analysis included two major divisions outlined by Ference Marton (1986): first, data was selected through emerging criteria of relevance; second, data was analysed to create conceptual categories used to frame the phenomenon. These two steps were repeated in that the categories and data resulting from the first analysis underwent a second round of iteration in creating more finely tuned conceptual categories. The repetition clarified data and categories, as well as allowed for a checking of the first-round decisions. These processes were organised and the information treated using NVivo data analysis software. These steps in the treatment of the information also provided means for checking the accuracy of the findings and, thus, increasing the validity of the study. Arrival at the resulting conceptual structure emerged from a coalescence of qualitative data analysis methods with methods from my art practice. The results led to a conceptual structure of how the artists create visual metaphors that took the form of one of the sculptures from the exhibition (Figure 9). Metaphoric thinking was thus seen to involve the reorganisation or blending of concepts. This is the essential ingredient for thinking metaphorically, which is grounded in sensory experience and leads to conceptual blending, JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd These knowledge claims set the stage for a phenomenographic approach to the research. Tesch (1990, 49) summarised phenomenography as ‘describing conceptually perceived qualities of a phenomenon through contextual analysis’. Marton (1986, 34) felt that the goal of phenomenography was to ‘discover the structural framework within which various categories of understanding exist [which] should prove useful in understanding other people’s understandings’. This approach flowed directly from the research question that regarded the study of visual metaphor from the perspectives of others and myself as the researcher in relationship with others within a specific context. Several aspects of my research questions led me to phenomenography: representing mind–body interconnectedness (Serig 2005; 2006). The sculpture also represents a conceptual structure of visual metaphor. Phenomenography as method The qualitative approach to this inquiry included phenomenography using opportunity sampling based on theoretical criteria derived from the review of literature. My intent was to understand the conceptual structure of visual metaphor through the perspectives of others and my interpretations. As a participant-observer, the study served as an example of art practices as socially constructed. This involved socially constructed knowledge claims as summarised by Creswell (2003, 9): Humans engage with their world and make sense of it based on their historical and social perspective – we are all born into a world of meaning bestowed upon us by our culture. Thus, qualitative researchers seek to understand the context or setting of the participants through visiting this context and gathering information personally. They also make an interpretation of what they find, an interpretation shaped by the researchers’ own experiences and backgrounds. 13 Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan • The study focused on the perspectives of artists as the main source of information. • Studying visual metaphor in this setting required multiple, interactive and humanistic data collection strategies. • Meaning emerged during the study: Transcribed interviews were coded. Initial coding was based on variables established from the literature reviews and reflections. Transcripts underwent multiple coding rounds. Variables changed and were generated as my interpretations evolved. Meaning also emerged from my continued artistic practice. Another source of emergent meaning was the ongoing dialogue between the primary participants. • My interpretations of the data were central to the findings of the study, and my reflective practices were an essential process of doing the research. Since I am an artist as well as researcher, phenomenography allowed me to be reflexive, using my insights as relevant to the findings. The aspects of my inquiry that led me to use phenomenographic methods occurred principally because they resonated with processes from my art practice. People’s perceptions of phenomena become the focus of study allowing for the construction of a conceptual structure. In my study the phenomena were visual metaphors and their uses within the practices of artists. The context JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd This page: Figure 9 Boris Curatolo, Sweet Spot, 2004. Courtesy of the artist 14 Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan for analysis involved structuring the exhibition process as a common framework within which individual interpretations would be observed. Yet there can be difficulties in drawing clear distinctions between what was a phenomenographic method in my research and what was my art practice as method. After all, doing art is a humanistic process of data collection, analysis and interpretation where perspectives of others can influence how phenomena are understood and the expressive forms they take through text and visuals. In the next section I explore the methods that may be more closely associated with my art practice as research. Art practice as method I spent extended periods of reflective time in the gallery with the artwork to enable description of the works for interpretations. I also used the time to reflect on the study as it progressed to continually refine the research questions. As an artist, I continued to make art and reflect on my own artistic practice as it related to the study (Figure 10). These procedures allowed for the exhibition at the Pearl Street Gallery to emerge from the interactions of the participants while also allowing for the study of visual metaphor creation. Use of the sculpture as a model for the conceptual structure occurred over the course of this study. During one of my extended visits at the exhibition, I began sketching the sculpture from various angles paying particular attention to how the negative spaces changed depending on the angle. The spaces remained in concert with each other because of the delimiting line, but also created spaces that opened to the surrounding gallery. On another gallery visit I photographed the exhibition for documentation. That process led me to take a series of photographs with the sculpture in the foreground and the other artworks in the background, appearing through the negative spaces (Figure 11). Only after struggling with more conventional diagrams and layered modelling using NVivo software did I return to my sketchbooks and photographs to develop this conceptual structure. Arrival at the resulting conceptual structure as sculptural form emerged from a coalescence of qualitative data analysis methods with methods from my art practice. The results led to a conceptual structure of how the artists create visual metaphors that took the form of one of the sculptures from the exhibition (Figure 9). Reflexivity as ongoing dialogue Reflecting on my research process, the central question that I developed led to new understandings and those understandings led to more questions. While this may be a typical trajectory in doctoral research, this cycle evolved in this instance from methods associated with my art practice and phenomenography. A pattern of reflexivity emerged that became the process through which the research study emerged. The reflexive cycle involved making, reflecting and acting on the reflections – and often a messy combination of these. This reflexive pattern so prevalent in my art practice served my research as I contended with multiple processes and layers such as data collection, analysis and interpretation that interacted simultaneously as an ongoing exchange. The reflexive cycle seemed to be a central component, not only in my own practice, but in the artists that I was studying as well. Reflexivity also seemed to be the cycle of action and reaction that enabled my art practice as research method to work in concert with other research methods. Discussion The three accounts presented above highlight different domains of inquiry of the artistresearcher. What is common, however, is that they all involve encircling art making as a research practice so as to explore issues and problems in creative and critical ways, as well as reaching out to adapt analytical and interpretive strategies from the research methods literature as needed. As a form of research, art practice can subsequently be seen in these examples to extend the conventions of inquiry, but in a way that privileges the creative and critical processes that artists use as agencies, actions and structures in their explorations. When designed within institutional contexts such as dissertation research, these inquiries offer a distinctly different way to JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd 15 Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan This page: Figure 10 Left: Dan Serig, October 13, 2004 and right: Boris Curatolo, Gist, 2004. Courtesy of the artists Figure 11 Three views of Sweet Spot, a conceptual structure of visual metaphor. Courtesy of the artist JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd 16 Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan address important research issues in the field (Figure 12). In the first case study, The ‘&’ Dilemma in Art & Art Education, Hugo Ortega López contemplates the intrusive ampersand – & – that is often placed between ‘art’ and ‘education’. Even when compressed as ‘art education’ there is an implied fusion that historically has seen education taking the dominant role. This is understandable to the extent that becoming legitimised within educational settings means that art has had to be integrated into existing theories and practices. Further, as a primary educational end is to excite others about the value of art, the message and the means needs to be expressed in ways that others understand and appreciate. What is at odds, as Ortega López points out, is the lack of opportunity for artist-researchers to make use of forms of inquiry that emphasise difference rather than conformity in conceptualising research practices and outcomes. In this case, the domain of inquiry that Ortega López opens up is dialectical in nature as personal agency and creative action is seen to contrast with the more conventional practices of the academy. His goal is to reinvigorate both the research community as well as the practices of artists so as to achieve a more open interpretive community that is responsive to the demands of ongoing change. In her case study of Family Photographs as Organisers of Experience, Kristin Baxter mines the depths of meaning found in the ubiquitous but multi-layered narratives bound up in individual and family snapshots of the past, which she sees as visual hinges that locate changing perceptions and contexts for understanding. Crucial to her inquiry was the re-working of ideas and issues through her art practice as she negotiated the accounts of generations of photographs with family members and friends; a circle within which she was quite clearly embedded. Yet Baxter explored these relationships through her artistic explorations and her ethnographic inquiries as she pursued the role as artist-researcher. In this case, the domain of inquiry that Baxter opens up is a quest for meaning whereby personal agency JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd and structural elements found in collections of photographs are explored in discursive and nondiscursive ways through art making and empirical inquiry. Rather than archaeological fragments that represent meanings and purposes lost in time, family photographs for Baxter are seen as indices of ever-changing content and meaning. In his search for a Conceptual Structure of Visual Metaphor, Dan Serig was prompted in part by the missing vision and voice of the artist in research accounts of metaphor. In supporting the cognitive argument that sees metaphor as a powerful form of human understanding and knowing, the lack of conceptual scope beyond figurative language was seen by Serig as a severe limitation in considering the significance of metaphor. When used as a structuring element within artistic actions, Serig saw that practitioners such as artists made use of metaphoric thinking in a range of ways that helped visualise the dynamics of metaphoric processes. In this case, the domain of inquiry that Serig opens up is a search for an explanatory system whereby the actions, decisions and structures evident in the work of artists uncover a conceptual structure of visual metaphor. This is a deconstructive process that uses the creative and critical processes of the artist as sites that can be interrogated in search for plausible interpretations of how visual metaphors are developed. Conclusion The premise framing the arguments presented in this article centres on the dissatisfaction felt among the authors about the way that studio art practice continues to be ignored as a necessary site and source for research in general, and dissertation research in particular. These views echo the sentiments expressed by Keys and Guyas (2006, 124), who complained that the rejection of artistic production as a viable form of inquiry ‘absurdly suggests to us a denial of visual art creation as a vivid and valid learning modality for arts educators and likewise our students’. The argument presented in this article draws on three brief accounts of dissertation study that used the art studio as a central element in the research process. Each highlights the capacity of art practice to reveal insights that are a consequence of what the researcher did in the studio setting as issues, ideas and interpretive stances emerged, and problems were re-conceptualised. What is different in these accounts from more mainstream approaches is the readiness to accept that constructing new knowledge is a creative and critical process that often resists easy labelling, simple resolution or elegant summary. As a process, research outcomes often have to accommodate messy and mobile ideas and concepts, yet like artworks, these can be forged into defensible representations and approximations. As a flexible but robust form of inquiry, art practice is a vital and viable area of research that generates new lines of inquiry, offers different theoretical orientations, and encourages ways to continually question the adequacy and accuracy of the knowledge we create and construct. 17 Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan Note 1. The creation of visual metaphor is argued in Serig’s dissertation (2006) to be a cognitive process of conceptual blending that can derive from artistic practice and may be applied to the resulting art objects. References Aldrich, V. C. (1968) Visual metaphor, The Journal of Aesthetic Education, Vol. 2, No. 1, pp. 73–86 Aldrich, V. C. (1971) Form in Visual Arts, The British Journal of Aesthetics, Vol. 11, No. 3, pp. 215–26 Barone, T. & Eisner, E. W. (1997) Arts-based educational research, in R. M. Jaeger [Ed.] Complementary Methods for Research in Education, 2nd edn. Washington, DC: American Educational Research Association, pp. 73–116 Baxter, K. (2005) Recollections of family photographs from five generations: the role of narrative and reflexivity in organizing experience. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Teachers College, Columbia University, New York Braudel, F. (1980) On History, trans. S. Matthews. Chicago: University of Chicago Press JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd Opposite page: Figure 12 Domains of Inquiry in Dissertation Research 18 Kristin Baxter, Hugo Ortega López, Dan Serig and Graeme Sullivan Bruns, G. L. (1999) Tragic Thoughts at the End of Philosophy: Language, Literature, and Ethical Theory. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press Cole, A. L., Neilson, L., Knowles, J. G. & Luciani, T. (2004) Provoked by Art: Theorizing Artsinformed Research. Halifax, Nova Scotia: Backalong Books Creswell, J. W. (2003) Research Design: Qualitative, Quantitative, and Mixed Methods Approaches, 2nd edn. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Dent, C. H. (1987) Developmental studies of perception and metaphor: The twain shall meet, Metaphor and Symbolic Activity, Vol. 2, No. 1, pp. 53–71 Dent, C. H. & Rosenberg, R. (1990) Visual and verbal metaphors: Developmental interactions, Child Development, Vol. 61, No. 4, pp. 983–94 Schank, R. (1999) Dynamic Memory Revisited. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press Serig, D. (2005) A conceptual structure of visual metaphor in the practices and exhibition of a consortium of artists. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Teachers College, Columbia University, New York Serig, D. (2006) A conceptual structure of visual metaphor, Studies in Art Education, Vol. 47, No. 3, pp. 229–48 Sullivan, G. (2006) Research Acts in Art Practice. Studies in Art Education, Vol. 48, No. 1, pp. 19–35 Taussig, M. (1993) Mimesis and Alterity: A Particular History of the Senses. New York: Routledge Tesch, R. (1990) Qualitative Research: Analysis Types and Software Tools. New York: Falmer Press Efland, A. D. (2002) Art and Cognition: Integrating the Visual Arts in the Curriculum. New York: Teachers College Press Hausman, C. R. (1989) Metaphor and Art. New York: Cambridge University Press Hirsch, J. (1981) Family Photographs: Content, Meaning and Effect. New York: Oxford University Press Keys, K. & Guyas, A. S. (2006) Commentary: What we can’t say: ain’t we artists? Studies in Art Education, Vol. 48, No. 1, pp. 123–8 Macleod, K. & Holdridge, L. [Eds] (2006) Thinking through Art: Reflections on Art as Research. New York: Routledge Marton, F. (1986) Phenomenology: A research approach to investigating different understandings of reality, Journal of Thought, Vol. 21, No. 3, pp. 28–48 Resonance exhibition (2007) (online). Available from URL: www.pearlstreetgallery.net/index. html [As of January 1 2008 to be found at www.boriscuratolo.com] JADE 27.1 (2008) © 2008 The Authors. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd Reflection in and on action and practice in creative-production doctoral projects in art and design Steven Scrivener Having now supervised to completion nearly twenty PhD students and examined a similar number, I have experience of a relatively wide range of projects. Most of these can be best described as technological research projects. Technology and design share a common concern for generating artefacts that are intended to transform the world from what it is to something better: both are concerned with intervention, innovation and change. Design research that is intended to effect change (which is the kind of design research that I am concerned with here) is closer, in my opinion, to technological research than it is to scientific or humanities research. From my experience, technology research projects share a number of common features (see Table 1). First, the product of the research is usually an artefact 1 of some kind. For example, it might be the design of a robot arm that can pick up an egg without breaking it. Second, the resultant artefact is one that either didn’t exist before or is an enhanced variant of an existent product. Third, the need for the new or variant product is justified (e.g., there is a need for robots that can pick up eggs): that is to say that a solution to a problem is needed. Fourth, it can be demonstrated that the solution resolves the problem, thereby satisfying need. Fifth, the solution to the identified problem is of general interest to the domain (e.g., robot designers, manufacturers and users). Sixth that the outcome of the research is useful. Seventh, that the knowledge embodied in the artefact (e.g., how to pick up an egg without crushing it) can be described separate from it (thus offering the potential for reuse). Eighth, that knowledge embodied in the artefact is applicable to other contexts (e.g., picking up a glass) and, ninth, transferable to the construction of other artefacts (e.g., a different kind of robot). Tenth, that the beyond-the-single-case applicable and transferable knowledge embodied in the artefact is more important than the artefact, which is merely a demonstration of its existence. artefact is produced artefact is new or improved artefact is the solution to a known problem artefact demonstrates a solution to problem the problem recognised as such by to others artefact (solution) is useful knowledge reified in artefact can be described this knowledge is widely applicable and widely transferable knowledge reified in the artefact is more important than the artefact Table 1 Norms of Technology Research Projects In my experience, most students’ and supervisors’ interests can be accommodated in design research projects, which like technological projects, exhibit the features identified in Table 1. What characterises this type of project, whether technological or design, is that it is focussed on problem solving. Nevertheless, I have encountered, supervised and examined students whose projects, while being concerned with the production of artefacts, exhibit few of the other features identified in Table 1. What characterises this latter kind of project is that its is focussed on creative production. In the remainder of this paper, I will explore these differences and how they are reflected in problems of process, form and presentation. Finally, I shall explore ways of doing and documenting that I believe offer a way forward - at least for me. Creative-production Projects and Problem-solving Projects Norms Having supervised many students in what I have characterised as problem-solving projects, when working with a new student my natural tendency is to try and frame the student’s project in such a way that it offers the potential to exhibit the features listed in Table 1. As noted above, in some cases I have found that the proposed work could not be straitjacketed into this mould. Here, I shall call these creative-production projects. Typically, the candidate researchers, whether artists or designers, are experienced practitioners who want to engage in research that will contribute directly to their ongoing practice. Furthermore, they wish to conduct the research through art- or designmaking, or, put another way, they do not wish to suspend their creative work or allow it to become separate from, or sub-ordinate to, the research activity. This in itself is not a problem, as moulding a through-practice research project that meets the criteria listed in Table 1 is straightforward. Problems seem to arise when the candidates’ primary interest is in producing artefacts, i.e., in creative production, and when their practice is closely associated with their self-identification as creators. For these candidates, the artefacts arising from the research cannot simply be conceived as byproducts or exemplification of "know-how". Instead, they are objects of value in their own right. Typically, the candidates involved are artists or studio/craft designers, focused on producing work that will stand up in the public domain (e.g., be worthy of exhibition). For them, doctoral study is mainly seen as an opportunity to develop as creators and to produce more satisfactory work. In problem-solving research projects, judgement as to whether an artefact is novel or an improvement on an existent product depends on the identification of weaknesses in existing products or needs that are not yet fulfilled by any product: in other words, on the identification of a problem. With some PhD candidates it proves virtually impossible to identify a problem as such. For example, one of my research students, a photographer, was interested in producing work that dealt with the subject of breast cancer. Among other reasons for undertaking the work, it was his hope that photography could contribute to awareness and understanding of how breast cancer affects the sufferer, the family, etc. However, the primary purpose of the project was not to test photography’s contribution to understanding but to produce photographs dealing with the subject of breast cancer, or rather to discover, or learn, how to produce them. Hence, while the programme could have been framed as a hypothesis testing project this would have been of little practical interest to the candidate. Nor was the work concerned with generating a new or improved artefact whose novelty or enhancement could be recognised in the fact that it provided a solution to a known problem. A number of photographers had already dealt with breast cancer in their work, so new work could only add to this body of work. However, had this project been the first to deal with the topic, this, of itself, would not have provided a justification for undertaking the work. There would have been no value in undertaking the work if the only reason for doing it was the fact that it had not been done before. Nor would the fact that it had been done before have been a reason for not doing it. The justification for undertaking the work was that the photographer was motivated to undertake it. Similarly, the student would have had little interest in taking identified "weaknesses" in the work of other photographers as his starting point, as the resolution of those "weaknesses" would not necessarily have related at all to his underlying interest in undertaking the work. It was what the photographer learnt, realised, or found that mattered. The work would be original in the sense of not being derivative or imitative, but not necessarily in the sense of new-to-the-world or an improvement on existing works, or of satisfying an identified need. In such a situation, what one is dealing with is a topic of interest (e.g., breast cancer) and creative objectives (e.g., work dealing with breast cancer) that resist, throughout the programme of work, reduction to single problem and its solution. Furthermore, the selection of topic and goal are made on the basis of personal rather than collective judgement. 2 This is not to suggest that the selection is self-indulgent. Of course, it can be, but, while individually unique, every person has much in common with others, sharing with them a social space. As such, what interests one person is likely to be of interest to others. Nevertheless, although artefacts are produced, their novelty, shared interest and usefulness may not be easily demonstrated or assessed. Another problem with this kind of work (which we will explore in more detail later) is that the project’s topic of interest and goal may change as the work progresses. This occurs for a number of reasons: first, the student is usually exploring manifold interests and goals and the priorities given to them may change as the work progresses; second, new issues and goals may emerge in response to the work in progress. In my experience, something similar occurs in problem-solving projects and comprises what might be called the problem finding phase of a project. Normally, however, there comes a point in such a project when a problem is found, defined and followed through to the realisation of a solution. In contrast, in projects where the work is progressed through the creation of and interaction with artefacts, issues, goals, and priorities may change throughout the project resulting in a stream of outcomes, thereby never settling on a specific problem or yielding a "final" solution. Perhaps the main reason for this is that the artefact matters as an object of experience. If it is not "working" in this sense then something has to be done about it. While in a typical problem-solving project the "know-how" exemplified in the artefacts is of central interest because it can be reused, in creative-production projects there is no general interest or utility in this "know-how". For example, even if one knew how to, why should one want to reproduce the photographs produced by a particular artist or the ceramics of a particular ceramist. For the same reason, there is no obvious merit to this knowledge being widely applicable and transferable (however, later I shall argue that it does provide examples, images, understandings that others may adopt for, or adapt to, their own purposes). Furthermore, as noted above, the artefacts are not exemplars of the project outcomes, they are the project outcomes. Table 2 illustrates how creative production projects relate to the norms of problem-solving projects. artefact is produced artefact may not be a new or improved version of an earlier artefact artefact is not a solution to a known problem artefact doesn’t demonstrate a solution to a problem the topic of interest and creative objectives may not be of obvious relevance to others artefact may have no obvious use there may be no value abstracting knowledge for reuse "knowledge" reified in the artefact is unlikely to widely applicable or transferable the artefact is more important than any "knowledge" reified in it Table 2 Relating Creative-production to the Norms of Problem-solving Research Although I stress what seem to me to be fundamental differences between creativeproduction and problem-solving projects, its important to recognise that this is not a black-and-white distinction. A creative-production project may comprise some problem solving and, indeed, it may involve cultural theory, cultural history and scientific research, inter alia. Where this is the case, it is important that the outcomes of this activity are reported. Nevertheless, it is inappropriate to view the contribution to knowledge made through these activities as the primary goal of the activity, or for the fact of this knowledge or these activities to be used to obfuscate, i.e., to claim that one is the same as the other. In a creative-production project this knowledge is a byproduct of the process rather than its primary objective. One reason for seeking to distinguish this form of project from the problem-solving form is to establish a framework of ideas and concepts that will prevent the former from becoming subsumed under the latter, which has a longer doctoral tradition and well-established norms. Assessing Problem-solving Research Projects The outcomes of a problem-solving research programme can be tested against the norms identified in Table 1. For example, we can ask, has the research student: • • • • • • • Demonstrated that there is a problem to be solved? Shown that the solution to the problem will result in a new or improved artefact? Shown that the problem is one that the World would like to see solved? Demonstrated the usefulness of the solution? Demonstrated that the knowledge exemplified in the solution can be abstracted (i.e, described and/or formalised)? Considered the general applicability and transferability of this knowledge? Proved this knowledge (i.e., demonstrated that the problem has been eradicated or ameliorated by the solution)? However, it is important to note that a student would not be awarded a PhD for merely producing a new or improved artefact, even if all of the above questions had been answered positively. The PhD candidate would have to show that they arrived at the problem and its solution in a self-conscious and reasoned way. In other words, if the decision-making involved in framing a problem and arriving at its solution were not evident, then the work would not be satisfactory. This is why a problem-solving project is presented as an "argument", which is usually, in fact, a post hoc justification for the decisions that were made. So, we can add one further and crucial test to those listed above: Has the research student demonstrated that he or she is a self-conscious and systematic problem-setter and -solver? In my experience, there is no generally agreed methodology for this demonstration. The primary research methodology is problem-solving itself, which often, in practice, cannot be fully explicated. There are, of course, methods, techniques and tools that can assist the researcher, but in many cases, the problem finding and solving processes retain an element of the black arts. Consequently, the student is not required to describe in detail the problem-setting and problem-solving processes. Rather, the student is expected to provide a persuasive case for the worthiness of research problem, the rationality of the steps taken to solve it and their execution. In short, although there is no overarching methodology there is an overarching ethic of selfconscious, informed and systematic problem selection and solution. Earlier, it may have occurred to you that the problem-solving research norms are characteristic of technological and design problem-solving in general. This being the case, what makes one everyday design or engineering, say, and the other research? One part of the answer to this is that not all of the norms need to be satisfied in everyday practice, e.g., a problem may not be worth solving; neither is it is necessary for the problem-solver to pass all the tests identified above. The additional requirements imposed on the student in the context of a doctoral programme take the activity beyond everyday problem solving. The Norms of Creative-production Projects While a creative-production project may not exhibit the norms of a problem-solving project, this does not mean that norms cannot be indentified, quite the contrary. First, whilst one may not wish to describe creative outcomes as new, in the sense of having no precedent or being an improvement on a precedent, one can describe work as being original, i.e., not derivative or imitative of others’ work. Second, while the "problem" and "solution" may be inappropriate descriptors, the work can be described as a response to a set of on-going issues, concerns and interests expressed through one or more artefacts. Third, while these issues, etc., may not be understood as framing a problem and although they may originate in a highly personalised way, they are usually rooted in the cultural context, i.e., they reflect culture. Furthermore, these issues, concerns and interests should be manifested through the creative-productions, i.e., the artefacts produced. Fourth, whether useful or not, the important attribute of the artefact is that it should contribute to human experience. The main difficulty comes in talking about knowledge; which I am coming to believe is inappropriate in this context. Instead, as implied above, the criterion to be met is that the work makes a contribution to human experience. This being the case, the creative production, as an object of experience, is more important than any knowledge embodied in it. artefacts are produced artefacts are original in a cultural context artefacts are a response to issues, concerns and interests artefacts manifests these issues, concerns and interests the issues, concerns and interests reflect cultural preoccupations artefacts contribute to human experience artefacts are more important than any knowledge embodied in them. Table 3 Norms of Creative-production Research Projects Using these norms, Table 3, a creative-production research programme can be tested by asking, for example, has the student: • • • • • • • Described the issues, concerns and interests stimulating the work, i.e., something that will contribute to human experience? Shown that the response to these stimulants is likely to be original? Shown that the issues, concerns and interests reflect cultural preoccupations? Shown the relationship between the artefact and those issues, concerns, and interests? Presented original, high-quality and engaging artefacts that contribute to human experience? Communicated knowledge, learning or insight resulting from the programme of work? Shown themselves to be a self-conscious, systematic and reflective creative artist or designer? The Underlying PhD Process in a Problem-solving Project Hence, specific norms projects (against which outcomes can be assessed) can be established for creative-production which differ in a number of respects to the norms and tests of problem-solving projects. The question is how do these differences impact on the PhD process and the nature of "argument" in a creative-production project? In the search for an answer to this question, I will first consider the nature of the underlying the problem-solving PhD process. If one were to take a typical problem-solving PhD thesis as representative of the problem-solving process then it would appear highly rational, deliberate and clinical. However, this is rarely how the researcher experiences the project, especially when the work is highly original. Typically, the experience for much of the programme of study is one of false starts, readjustment, redefinition and uncertainty, inter alia. Indeed, in my experience, the problem-solving PhD process is much closer to that characterised in Schön’s theory of reflective practice (1983). In everyday action, Schön (ibid.) argues, our knowledge is ordinarily tacit, implicit in our patterns of action and in our feel for the stuff with which we are dealing - our knowing is in action. Similarly, the professional depends on tacit knowing-in-action. On the other hand, we often think about what we are doing. Usually reflection on knowing-in-action goes together with reflection on the stuff at hand. As the professional tries to make sense of it, he also reflects on the understandings which have been implicit in his action, understanding which he surfaces, criticises, restructures, and embodies in further action. According to Schön it is this entire process of reflection-in-action which is central to the "art" by which practitioners deal with situations of uncertainty, instability, uniqueness, and value conflict. In my view, the process by which the problem-solving researcher arrives at research outcomes is very similar. Reflection-in-action has a characteristic structure. Typically, the practitioner finds that problem cannot be solved as it has been initially set, so the framing of the problem must be surfaced and criticised, and the problem reframed: a way of shaping the situation to a new frame must be found. The reframed problem becomes the basis for experimentation to discover what consequences and implications follow from it, and the situation is made to fit the frame through moves that adapt the situation to the frame. But moves generate unintended changes that give new meaning to the situation: the situation talks back and the problem is reframed. New discoveries call for new reflection-in-action. The process spirals through stages of appreciation, action, and reappreciation, whereby the unique and uncertain situation comes to be understood through the attempt to change it, and changed through the attempt to understand it. Schön (1983) asks further questions of this process. If the practitioner conducts a reframing experiment how is it evaluated? Accepting the uniqueness of a situation, how is the accumulated experience of practice made use of? If reflection-in-action is a kind of experiment, in what sense is such on-the-spot experimentation rigorous. Given that the characteristic research stance is that of objectivity, control, and distance, how might the stance of the practitioner be described? The answer to the first question is that evaluation is grounded in a frame experiment’s ability to keep things moving and the practitioner’s appreciate systems, i.e., that knowledge which the practitioner draws on to establish whether changes and unintended changes are liked or disliked. Schön views the practitioner’s experience as a repertoire of "examples, images, understandings, and actions". According to Schön, when a practitioner makes sense of a situation that is perceived to be unique, she sees it as something already present in her repertoire. "Seeing this situation as that one, one may also do in this situation as in that one", continues Schön (1983:139). It is this capacity that allows practitioner to bring past experience to bear on new cases. Schön (ibid.) defines several types of experiment in practice. Exploratory experiment is when an action is undertaken only to see what follows, without accompanying predictions or expectations. A move-testing experiment is when an action is undertaken in order to produce an intended change. Such a move can be affirmed or negated. A hypothesis-testing experiment succeeds when it effects an intended discrimination among competing hypothesis. He argues that experiment in practice is different from research in a number of ways. First, the practitioner is interested in transforming the situation from what it is to something better. Second, when a practitioner reflects-in-action, experimentation is at once exploratory, move-testing, and hypothesis testing. The three functions are fulfilled by the very same actions. Third, in hypothesis-testing the practitioner is in imperative mode, "Let it be the case that X....", and shapes the situation so that X becomes true. Phenomena is changed to make the hypothesis fit. Fourth, the practitioner violates the canon of controlled experiment, which calls for objectivity and distance. The practitioner’s relation to the situation is transactional. The situation is shaped, but in conversation with it, so that his own models and appreciations are also shaped by the situation. Fifth, the practitioner/experimenter need discriminate among contending hypothesis only to the point where moves are affirmed or yield new appreciations of the situation. In the practice context the experimental logic is one of affirmation not confirmation. The sequence initiated by the negation of a move terminates when a new theory leads to a new move that is affirmed. Sixth, hypotheses must lend themselves to embodiment in a move. Only hypotheses that can immediately translate into action are of interest. However, although this process might resemble the experience of undertaking a problem-solving PhD the student would not be encouraged to write it up; indeed, the student would be actively discouraged from doing so. I doubt that there is a problemsolving PhD project supervisor who, when encountered by a student with writing-up problems, has not responded by saying, "You need to distinguish doing the PhD from writing it up". And what does this mean? Well, in the first place, the problem finding phase of the project is rarely written up (i.e., the cycle of problem framing, action, consequence, and reframing). The experienced supervisor knows that, with guidance, there will come a point when the student will frame a problem that will become the primary research focus. In the thesis, the student is expected to justify the existence of the problem rather than to explain how it was found. Hence, the problem is usually presented as if it were the natural consequence of rational analysis of past work in the field. The experienced supervisor also knows that the research problem, once set, will change as the work progresses and may only be properly defined in the writing up of the thesis. Here again, the student would be discouraged from describing this process. Similarly, the student will be discouraged from reporting much of the problemsolving process, the often-faltering steps from problem identification to solution. Instead, the student will be encouraged to focus on describing the "know how" reified in the solution (i.e., the destination rather than the journey) and on demonstrating, rationally and empirically, that this knowledge solves the research problem. In so far as the problem-solving process is described, this will tend to take the form of a means-end analysis: that is to say, a technical procedure, a "calculus of decision" (Schön, 1983:47), to be measured by its effectiveness in achieving pre-established goals. One reason for leaving out this material is that its inclusion makes the thesis both very difficult to write and to read. However, the most important reason is that it doesn’t usually matter how the problem was arrived at or how the solution was found. What matters is the existence of a valid problem, the demonstration of its solution and the abstraction of the reusable "know how" embodied in it. All the same, because the writing up of a problem-solving doctorate may comprise a significant element of post hoc rationalisation, students often find writing up a difficult process, even feeling that they are being dishonest. Nevertheless, notwithstanding the potential for actual dishonesty, what matters from the supervisor and the examiner’s point of view is that the thesis is in a form which can be challenged using tests such as those presented in Section 4. While challenging the thesis may sometimes reveal dishonesty, considerable trust is placed in the basic honesty and professionalism of all of those involved in the PhD programme. Reflective Practice and Creative Production Clearly, although Schön (1983) presents a theory of practice that is very different to Simon (1969), practice is nevertheless conceived in terms of problems and solutions. Furthermore, Schön’s scientific language of theory of action, logic, experimentation, hypothesis and experimental rigour is at odds with my sense of creative-production. While I do not have adequate alternatives to put in their place, I would emphasise that I do not see creative production in these terms. Nevertheless, in my experience, the things onto which these words are attached, the process and its characteristics, seem to capture much of that which I have also observed in the actions of my creativeproduction project students. For example, Schön’s (1983) theory stresses the role of tacit knowledge in competent practice, i.e., knowing-in-action and -in-practice. Second, he puts store on problem setting as something that recurs throughout the process in response to difficulty or uncertainty encountered during a task. Dialectic occurs between the situation and the practitioner’s conception of the task in hand which stimulates a parallel dialectic between problem setting and problem solving. Third, reflection is the primary conceptual tool for handling the unexpected. Fourth, creative action is a way of keeping things moving. Then there is the notion that past experience provides examples, images, understandings and actions, rather than generalised theories, methods, techniques or tools. Sixth, there is the recognition that the creator’s interest is in transforming the situation (i.e., psychological, emotional and created) to something better (e.g., equilibrium between intention and realisation). Seventh, there is idea that action seeks to shape the situation to intentions, rather than to test understanding. Eighth, there is the recognition that the process is subjective. Ninth, there is the insight that the creator seeks affirmation, not confirmation, of the appropriateness of a course of action. Then there is the idea that only those things that lend themselves to embodiment in creative action are worth exploring. Finally, Schön shows that the practitioner’s response to the situation demands a certain kind of rigour; there are appropriate and inappropriate ways of responding (see Section 8 for further discussion of this point). However, because a creative-production project is not concerned with and does not reduce to a problem and its solution it is not possible to separate formative processes from outcomes and to specify a "calculus of decisions" (i.e., that relates means to ends). The relationship between issues, concerns and interests and outcomes in a creative-production project is one that changes throughout the entire process. Thus, unlike a problem-solving project, where we can largely ignore the actual problem setting and solution processes, I am of the view that description of the creativeproduction process should be the principle means by which students demonstrate that they are self-conscious, systematic and reflective creators. In the following sections, I will argue that Schön’s (1983) theory of design as reflective practice provides us with concepts which help to characterise creative production, e.g., to identify what should be attended to in the process, its form and documentation. The Importance of Reflection in Creative Production Schön (1983) describes how practice is an exploration in which the practitioner seeks to come to terms with a given creative task. This exploration involves the formulation and testing of ways of proceeding. Generally, all thinking in this activity is directed toward action. Occasionally, when ways of proceeding don’t work or when they produce unintended consequences, the practitioner is forced to reflect on implicit knowledge and strategies. At such points, the practitioner steps out of action momentarily and past action and outcomes become objects of conscious attention. When a practitioner reflects on knowing-in-practice they reflect on knowledge and ways of working automated over an extended period (cf., Figure 1, reflection-inaction and -practice, RIAP). Practice is made up of projects lasting days, weeks or months. Whenever work is suspended, at the end of the day, at weekends, during project suspensions and upon project completion, the opportunity exists to reflect on the current project, the approach taken to it, and on its relation to past projects. (cf., Figure 1, reflection on action and practice, ROAP). In contrast to reflection-in-action and -practice, reflection on action and practice is not driven by the unexpected per se but by the desire to learn from experience: it is a discipline rather than a necessity for further action. Figure 1 Reflection in and on design episodes and projects According to Schön (1983) reflection is central both to the practitioner’s ability to successfully complete projects and to their professional development. However, such reflection is unremarkable to and unmarked by the practitioner. Hence, the importance of such events or how they have changed the practitioner may not be consciously registered. As noted earlier, Schön sees reflection as the primary cognitive mechanism for dealing with the unexpected and, through the resolution of the unexpected, for learning. There is, then, an argument for suggesting that the practitioner could benefit if reflection was recorded and then reported more systematically. Table 4 shows the full range of outcomes arising from on-the-spot experimentation, i.e., those meeting the practitioner's expectations or not, together with the desirability of intended and unintended consequences. Consequences in relation to intention Desirability of all perceived consequences intended or unintended 1 Surprise Undesirable 2 Surprise Desirable or neutral 3 No surprise Desirable or neutral 4 No surprise Undesirable Table 4 The outcomes of on-the-spot-experimentation (from Schön, 1983: 153) In the first case, the move is disaffirmed and the practitioner’s theory of action is refuted; here the practitioner is obliged to reconsider its relevance and appropriateness. In the second case, although the theory of action is refuted, since the result is desirable there is no obligation, in the logic of reflective practice, for the practitioner to surface and reflect on the underlying theory of action. In the third case, the move is simply affirmed and design can continue without any need for reflection. Finally, in the fourth case, although the theory of action has produced the expected result the outcome is undesirable. This will necessitate reflection, not some much about the truth of the theory but its scope of relevance, thus promoting a search aimed at extending the theory of action to cover the observed case. Consequently, only outcomes 1 and 4 demand reflection-in-action and -practice, but demand it they do and to ignore such demand is a failure of rigour in on-the-spot experimentation. I am suggesting that if we are to give greater attention to the process of creative production, then this should focus on the recording and reporting of these moments of reflection, including intended and unintended consequences and responses to them. The systematic recording of making and reflection-in-action and -practice would play a crucial role in supporting the practitioner’s reflections on action and practice and in making the whole creative-production project more accessible, both to the researcher and those to whom the project is communicated. While systematic, relevant and practical methods of recording need to be developed for creative production, useful schemes can be appropriated from other research realms. In the appropriation and application of such techniques to describe and interpret activity, a balance will have to be struck between rigour and action. I am proposing to introduce an additional layer of activity into creative-production. This layer is in the service of action, i.e., it is intended to inform and enhance action. Consequently, it must not become so burdensome that action is impeded or stopped. Rigour in reflection-in-action and -practice must be the maidservant of effective action, yielding to action’s inherent structural integrity. Reflection on Action and Practice The record of creative-production is the starting point for its documentation. At the very least, this should record reflection (i.e., reflection-in-action and -practice). This will provide the material for reflection on action and practice. As noted above, this latter process is more a matter of discipline than necessity. Given a record of creative production, reflection on action and practice amounts to reflection on a description of creative-production. Given that it is likely to be rich, elaborate and extensive, how should reflection on the description of creative-production be approached? The answer, I propose, is that the focus should be on moments of reflection-in-action and practice. Each surprise during working, together with its associated frame, refuted theory of action, surfaced tacit knowledge, revised theory of action, revised frame and subsequent action, should be reflected on both with regard to its contribution to the project and its implications for future action and practice. Like reflection-in-action and -practice, the designer’s reflection on action and practice will need to be evidenced. The Shape of a Creative-production Project A creative-production project will be grounded in a practitioner’s current practice and realised in future projects. Consequently, it should begin with reflection on past practice and appreciative system. This will generate issues for further investigation, goals for future practice and a reappraisal of appreciate system (e.g., a designer might choose to put a higher value on sustainability or user involvement in the design process, while a painter might choose to explore narrative in static imagery). This reappraisal is likely to stimulate a search for information and knowledge relevant to the identified issues, goals and appreciation. Only superficially does this resemble the preparation stage of more typical forms of research. First, the goal isn’t to draw a boundary separating what is inside and outside the focus of study as a starting point for identifying an unanswered question that lends itself to expression in a single problem or hypothesis that through solution or confirmation will make an original contribution to knowledge. Instead, in creativeproduction, multiple issues and goals may be appropriate and it should be acknowledged that these may change, grow, and be given different emphasis as the work proceeds. While the literature review in traditional research puts emphasis on the logic of problem or hypothesis selection, preparation for creative-production sets out to provide a valid rationale that affirms the direction of making, at the moment that making commences. Second, while information and knowledge should be systematic and rigorous, because issues and goals are manifold this process will be necessarily broad in scope and lacking in depth. Furthermore, knowledge acquisition and information gathering activity will be stimulated when progress becomes difficult. Thus, breadth and depth of relevant knowledge and information is likely to widen, deepen and accrue with work. Following the initial preparation stage, further opportunities to reflect in and on action and practice will arise at the completion of work episodes. Here the artist or designer should reflect back on the issues, goals and appreciation surfaced in the preparation stage, and subsequent stages. At the end of the project there should be a final reflective stage. Here, the researcher should reflect both on the project as a whole in relation to the issues explored, the work produced, development in appreciative system, and the reflection on action and practice itself. Pre-, within- and post- project reflections will provide the primary material for communicating and sharing experience with peers, together with descriptive records of the work and decisions made. Reporting a Creative-production Project Research can be normally described as a process that narrows down to the consideration or testing of one or a few primary research propositions. Hence, its makes sense to begin the thesis by setting out all the knowledge relevant (and irrelevant) to the project to bound the research question. Having established the question or problem, one can proceed to describe the method of testing or solution, the application of this method, the results, and, finally, the discussion of the results which may involve some examination of theory and knowledge additional to that set out in the review. As noted earlier, this thesis format will not work for creative production project: multiple and changing issues are explored, theory and knowledge is accrued, and different strategies employed to further the work. Given the underlying structure of the creative-production PhD described above, I am suggesting that a creative-production project report 3 would more properly take a form something like that show in Figure 2. Main body • Pre-project reflection on practice (including identification of issues, concerns and interests to be worked with in the project) • Review of theory, knowledge and information (relevant to identified issues, concerns and interests) • Reframing of issues, concerns and interests (in response to material found in the review) Cycles of: • • • • summary of a work episode (i.e., to place subsequent description into context, e.g., when it occurred, what the objectives were, who was involved, how long it lasted, what the outcomes were, etc.) reflection on the work episode (i.e., focussing on moments of reflection-inaction and practice, supported by records of working) Post-project reflection on action and practice (i.e., on the project as a whole) Reflection on reflection on action and practice (i.e., critical reflection on one’s work-focussed reflection) Appendices • Accumulated theory and knowledge • Description (records) of designing • Analysis of reflection-in-action and -practice Figure 2 Suggested Basic Structure of a Creative-production Project Report From Figure 2, it is clear that greater emphasis is placed on the process and in particular, how the process changes as the work progresses. This cyclic process of reflection draws upon theory, knowledge, records of designing and analysis of reflection-in-action and -practice as appropriate, and hence this material will be described in the context of this process, rather than separate from it. At the end of productive project work, all the work should be reflected on. Here, the focus should be on reporting the learning acquired through the project, together a description of one’s current position as an artist or designer. The final reflective cycle is concerned with an analysis of how one approached the project (see Section 12 for further discussion). In Figure 2, the elements described above are presented as comprising the main body of the report, meaning that this material is essential to a third party wishing to make sense of the project. In contrast, the appendices contain material which, while underpinning that reported in the main body, need not be read. Here, I’m suggesting that there might be a need for an appendix which presents knowledge and theory accumulated throughout the project. A creative-production project is commenced in the context of relevant theory and knowledge. There is, for example, the practitioner’s personal knowledge base: the repertoire of personal ideas, beliefs, and appreciation, etc., derived from actual experience and shared theory and knowledge acquired during education and from books, journals and the like. It is this personal knowledge base that contributes to the practitioner’s framing of the issues, concerns and interests at the outset of the project. If, as is likely to be the case, personal knowledge is insufficient for immediate creative production, then a search will be initiated for relevant theory and knowledge which will be written up in the primary review (second element, Figure 2) When reflection-in-action and -practice force the practitioner to reconsider the theory and knowledge informing the work in progress, it is likely, first, that the designer will search his personal knowledge base and, second, external sources of knowledge and theory when his personal resources prove inadequate. These secondary searches should be written up as part of the action-reflection cycle. While reflection may be the primary mechanism for drawing on known-to-thepractitioner theory and knowledge and for initiating the search for new (to-thepractitioner) theory and knowledge the latter may be brought into the process by a quite different route. In general, practitioners are not simply focused on practice: they look at and read about the work of others, they read professional and (sometimes) academic journals and monitor social, cultural and scientific development. In other words, they try to keep up with the times, to have a grasp on the state-of-the-art in a range of human affairs. This activity, which runs parallel to practice, may uncover new theory and knowledge that is recognised as relevant to the task in hand and which functions in ways comparable to that "earmarked" through reflection. That is to say, when the practitioner’s progress is blocked it may contribute to a reframing of the situation that clears the way ahead. It may also act to transform the practitioner’s theory of action, which may promote new frames and moves during a task. Where this background information gathering can be seen to have contributed directly to making, it too should feature when reporting action-reflection cycles. Given that it is only necessary, and possibly meaningful, to report that information contributing to the affirmation of a move, it is highly likely that accumulating wisdom will be drawn upon in an ad hoc and partial manner. It may therefore be necessary to document separately the true breadth and depth of theory and knowledge acquired during the project. However, since the role of this theory and knowledge is only meaningful in context of the actions to which it contributed, then emphasis should be on reporting it in order of use, not acquisition. For this reason, I’m suggesting that it may be helpful to report the acquisition of theory and knowledge during the project in a separate appendix. Rigour and Reflexivity We have described above the consequences of on-the-spot experimentation and their implications for the practitioner’s subsequent actions, e.g., when a move is unsuccessful and yields undesired consequences requiring reflection back on how the task has been framed and the associated theory of action. Rigour in on-the-spot experimentation demands that these events are acknowledged and handled. Another aspect of rigour relates to the stance of the inquirer. According to Schön (1983) the inquirer must impose an order of his own rather than falling into his transaction with the situation. At the same time as trying to shape the situation, the inquirer must be open to the situation’s talk-back. Also, he must depend on relative constant elements that he may bring to a situation otherwise in flux: an overarching theory, an appreciative system, and a stance of reflection-in-practice. A third aspect of rigour relates to the researcher’s engagement and contribution to the activity of study. Reflexivity is the name employed in qualitative research for the cyclic process whereby the way we describe a phenomenon changes the way it operates for us, which in turn changes our perception, which changes our description of it, and so on. The term is used both to describe the process and the researcher’s attempts to acknowledge its effects and impact on her research. Tindall (1994) argues that in this latter sense, reflexivity is possible the most distinctive feature of qualitative research. She goes on to say that, "It is an attempt to make explicit the process by which the material and analysis are produced" (1994: 149). In essence it is an on-going and disciplined self-reflection in which the research topic and process, together with the experience of doing the research, are critically evaluated. Like qualitative researcher, the artist and designer is central to the sense that is made and is engaged in a process in which reflexivity dominates. Hence, reflexivity must be seen as a central feature of research-in-design. The Value of Research-in-design and Doctoral Degrees Why bother to undertake a doctoral education in creative-production? This can be answered in a number of untested ways. First, the process should yield more reflective practitioners: the assumption being that reflective practitioners will produce better results than their unreflective peers will. Second, these benefits will be reflected in innovative artefacts and the explication of overarching theory, appreciative system and the norms used to evaluate the unintended and unexpected. While it is not assumed that this will lead to generalisations, the communicable outcomes of the activity will provide, "examples, images, understandings" (Schön, 1983:138) and strategies for action that other practitioners may employ to extend their own repertoires. It should be remembered that the PhD is a relatively modern phenomenon. In 1870 the PhD was exclusively a German phenomenon developed within the German scientific positivist school of thought, as a preparation for the scholastic life. After 1870, the PhD changed dramatically when adopted in the USA, where it took the form of a distinct cycle of formal education, differing only in terms of its level from those preceding it. In the USA the PhD quickly became a passport into teaching (as it is today in many disciplines in the UK) prompting some commentators to note that in practice it is now a qualification for teaching rather than research. Similarly, a doctorate in creative-production might be seen as appropriate training to teach others to become reflective artists and designers. Conclusions This paper is essentially a personal manifesto which sets out the ideas I hope to explore in working with future PhD students undertaking what I have called, for want of a better term, creative-production projects. I have written the paper from a personal perspective - my experience as a supervisor and examiner of PhD students. Much of this has been acquired through involvement in problem-solving projects. However, I have recognised that some students’ interests, intentions, and ways of working, although concerned the creation of artefacts, cannot be moulded into a problemsolving project and that to do so would somehow be a failure of imagination. I have called this form of project creative-production, because it is inventive and imaginative, and realised through and in artefacts. Given the personal nature of this dilemma, what is problematic for me may not be so for others with a different research background. Even so, the on-going debate about the nature of research in art and design suggests that others are experiencing similar problems, and this has encouraged me to review my own uncertainties. My approach has been to consider why the norms and tests of problem-solving research are not appropriate to creative-production, before framing what seem to me to be appropriate ones. However, I have concluded that this in itself isn’t sufficient: the relationship between the issues, concerns and interests explored and the artefacts produced is so tied up with act of making that this can only be revealed through description and reflection on the underlying creative-production process. I am persuaded that Schön’s (1983) theory of reflective practice provides us with ways of thinking about the nature of the creative-production process, the way past experience (both personal and collective) is brought to bear on it, the assessment of action, rigour in creative-production, and the stance of the practitioner. I have proposed that reflection should be central to the discipline of creativeproduction. This will involve recording creative production in a way that captures moments of reflection-in-action and -practice (i.e., material for reflection on action and practice). This emphasis on the underlying experience of creative production has implications both for the shape of the research programme and the form of its reporting, and I have sketched out patterns for each that I hope to work from in future projects. Earlier, I considered what distinguished the problem-solving research project from everyday problem solving. Of course, the same question can be asked of creativeproduction, how is it different to everyday art and design making? Here, the former answer suffices: the additional requirements imposed on the student in the context of a doctoral programme take the activity beyond ordinary art and design making. But, is it right to call it research? Implicit in this question is the assumption that research is a well-defined concept that has a clear and unequivocal meaning to all disciplines that employ the term. However, what technologists do in research is different to what psychologists do, and what psychologists do is different to what anthropologists do, and so on. While recognising that the activities are different, we might wish to argue that each shares a set of underlying criteria which determine the shared meaning of the term research. However, attempts to frame these criteria (cf., Cross, 2000) usually end up producing general principles which seem equally applicable to a range of activities that would not be regarded as research. Alternatively, we could argue that the term research is not an absolute: that it is socially constructed and its meaning shifts depending on the community using the term. From this standpoint, both activity and meaning differ from one discipline to another. I tend towards the latter persuasion and think, for example, that technology has become comfortable with using the term research to describe an activity which satisfies specific norms and tests and which, in being designed to meet these criteria, contributes systematically to the development of the discipline. The use of the term by one discipline is accepted by a second when the latter recognises that research is to the former as research is to it. This being the case, the answer to the question must start with the discipline using the term research. If it is becomes accepted that creative-production is different to art and design making, that it contributes to their development, and that it is to them as research is to other disciplines, then we will stop asking the question and simply use the term without discomfort. Therefore, at this point in term I cannot answer the question. However, I am convinced that creative-production is different to art and design making, is distinguishable from bachelor and master education, and has a value, both to the student and to society. It is this conviction that sustains my interest in supervising and examining creativeproduction students. Endnotes 1 Here I am taking a very broad view of what is meant by an artefact. For example, it could be a tool or technique for doing something, e.g., picking up fragile objects, or a tool, technique or method for designing such tools and techniques. 2 In a problem-solving project, one would normally be concerned that a topic of interest that was recognised by one’s peers as being worth investigation. Usually, such topics can be found in the suggestions for future work reported in writings of one’s peers. 3 Report or dissertation may be more appropriate than the term thesis, given the definition of the latter as "a proposition to be maintained or proved", which is often that ascribed to the PhD thesis rather than the more general definition of a thesis as "a dissertation, especially by a candidate for a degree" (cf., The Concise Oxford Dictionary, Oxford University Press, 1992). References Cross, N. (2000) Design as a discipline. In: Durling D, Friedman K (eds.) Doctoral education in design: foundations for the future. Staffordshire University Press, Staffordshire, pp 93-100 Schön, D.A. (1983) The reflective practitioner: how professionals think in action. Basic books, New York Simon, H.A. (1969) The sciences of the artificial. MIT Press, Cambridge Massachusetts Tindall, C. (1994) Issues of evaluation. In: Banister P, Burman E, Parker I, Taylor M (eds.) Qualitative methods in psychology: a research guide. Open University Press, Buckingham, pp 142-159.