- Federal Law Review
Transcription
- Federal Law Review
FEDERAL LAW REVIEW FACULTY OF LAW THE AUSTRALIAN NATIONAL UNIVERSITY This issue may be cited as (2001) 29 F L Rev The Dewey Decimal number of this volume is 347.05 FL Rev ISSN 0067–205X FEDERAL LAW REVIEW EDITOR ADRIENNE STONE ___________________________________________________________________________ ADVISORY BOARD Professor Philip Alston, European University Institute, Florence Professor Tom Campbell, Professorial Fellow, Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics, Charles Sturt University Professor James Crawford, University of Cambridge The Hon Justice Finn, Federal Court of Australia The Hon Justice WMC Gummow AC, High Court of Australia The Hon Justice Kenny, Court of Appeal (Victoria) Professor G J Lindell, Faculty of Law, Melbourne University Professor D N MacCormick, Faculty of Law, University of Edinburgh Professor Kathleen Mahoney, University of Calgary The Hon Sir Anthony Mason AC KBE, formerly Chief Justice, High Court of Australia The Hon Justice JA Miles AO, Chief Justice of the Supreme Court of the ACT Professor Dennis Pearce, Faculty of Law, The Australian National University Ms Hilary Penfold, First Parliamentary Counsel, Canberra Professor Joseph Weiler, Harvard Law School, Cambridge, Massachusetts Professor Leslie Zines AO, Research School of Social Sciences, The Australian National University EDITORIAL COMMITTEE Judith Jones John McMillan Daniel Stewart EDITORIAL ASSISTANTS Andrew Battison Robyn Briese Bethwyn Morris Alexandra Owens BUSINESS MANAGERS Martin Guthrie Jo Woodbury ____________________________________________________________________________ The Faculty of Law wishes to thank the following patron of the Review for their kind support — ALLENS ARTHUR ROBINSON Any person or organisation wishing to become a patron of the Review is welcome to contact the Editor for relevant information. The Review specialises in matters of federal law. These include the analysis of legal and policy questions relating to the nature of federalism, both in Australia and elsewhere. With regard to Australia, our definition of federal law includes: • Commonwealth constitutional and administrative law; • Matters within Commonwealth legislative competence (whether or not these matters fall within public or private law); • Decisions of courts exercising federal jurisdiction; • International law in so far as it affects the Commonwealth; • Matters of law which have given rise, or might give rise, to national or uniform legislation. The Review is a refereed journal. Contributions are welcomed. Manuscripts should conform to the Australian Guide to Legal Citation. Communications should be addressed to: The Editor Federal Law Review Law School Australian National University Canberra ACT 0200 or by email: [email protected] Enquiries concerning and orders for subscriptions should be addressed: ____________________________________________________________________________ From North America to: Gaunt Inc. 3011 Gulf Drive Holmes Beach Florida USA 34217-2199 From the rest of the world to: The Business Manager Federal Law Review Law School Australian National University Canberra ACT 0200 VOLUME 29 NUMBER 2 ________________________________________________________________ ARTICLES Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution SIMON EVANS 121 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication CATHERINE PENHALLURICK 151 Political Donations by Australian Companies IAN RAMSAY, GEOF STAPLEDON, JOEL VERNON 177 In the Wake of Teoh: Finding an Appropriate Government Response WENDY LACEY 219 A Turtle by Any Other Name: The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution ANTHONY DILLON 241 The Military Call-out Legislation — some Legal and Constitutional Questions MICHAEL HEAD 273 COMMENT AND BOOK REVIEW The High Court – Legitimacy and Change: Review Essay: Haig Patapan, Judging Democracy – The New Politics of the High Court of Australia ANDREW LYNCH 295 COMMENT Brownlee v The Queen: Method in the Madness JAMES STELLIOS 319 PROPERTY AND THE DRAFTING OF THE AUSTRALIAN CONSTITUTION Simon Evans* In this article, I present the results of a study into the extent to which property figured as a constitutional and political concept in the drafting of the Constitution at the Australasian Federal Conventions of the 1890s. Property is a fundamental concept of western legal orders and a powerful political and rhetorical tool. Accordingly, it is important to understand both how it affected the drafting of the Constitution and how it is reflected in it. In Section I, I outline the process by which the Constitution was drafted by the Australasian Federal Conventions in the 1890s. In Section II, I identify the constitutional provisions in which 'property' and some related terms appear and assess the extent to which the Conventions shed light on the meaning of those provisions. In Section III, I discuss the striking ways in which property, as a political concept, influenced debate at the Conventions on constitutional provisions that do not themselves deal with property. In the final section, Section IV, I attempt an overall assessment of the significance of the concept of property at the Conventions. I. THE AUSTRALASIAN FEDERAL CONVENTIONS The Australian Constitution was drafted at a series of meetings during the 1890s (I refer to these variously titled meetings as 'the Conventions' and the delegates to the Conventions as 'the Framers'). • Thirteen delegates appointed by the colonial parliaments (including New Zealand) met as the Australasian Federation Conference in Melbourne from 6 February 1890 to 14 February 1890. • The next convention, the National Australasian Convention, held in Sydney from 2 March 1891 to 9 April 1891, again consisted of delegates (on this occasion 45 in number) appointed by the colonial parliaments. It produced a draft Constitution Bill which formed the basis of discussions at the next national Convention in 1897– 98. • That Convention, the Australasian Federal Convention, held three sessions in 1897 and 1898. The first session was held in Adelaide from 22 March 1897 to 23 April 1897, the second session in Sydney from 2 September 1897 to 24 September 1897 _____________________________________________________________________________________ * Lecturer, Faculty of Law, University of Melbourne. I am most grateful for the excellent research assistance provided by Josephine Tan and for the ARC Small Grant that funded it. I am also grateful for the comments of participants at the 2001 Real Property Teachers Conference where a draft of this paper was first presented. 122 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ and the third session in Melbourne from 22 January 1898 to 17 March 1898. The 50 delegates were elected, except the delegates from Western Australia who were once again appointed by the colonial parliament. There were no delegates from Queensland or New Zealand. There is no space here to record all the details of the Convention process.1 It is sufficient to note that, ultimately, the draft Constitution Bill produced by the 1897–98 Convention (amended somewhat by the colonial premiers) was adopted at referenda in each of the States and was enacted by the Imperial Parliament (again after some mostly minor amendments). It came into effect on 1 January 1901. The records of the debates at the Conventions ('the Debates') and the draft Constitution Bills produced by the Conventions were published in six volumes during the 1890s.2 They form an important record of the federation movement (at least in its public and official manifestations) and of the Constitution it produced. The Debates and the draft Constitution Bills also have a legal significance. The High Court has confirmed that they may be used in a limited way,3 along with other historical materials, in interpreting the Constitution: Reference to the history of [constitutional provisions] may be made, not for the purpose of substituting for the meaning of the words used the scope and effect – if such could be established – which the founding fathers subjectively intended the [provisions] to have, but for the purpose of identifying the contemporary meaning of language used, the subject to which that language was directed and the nature and objectives of the movement towards federation from which the compact of the Constitution finally emerged.4 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 1 There are many excellent accounts of the Federation movement and the Conventions, including Helen Irving, To Constitute A Nation (paperback edition, 1999) and John Hirst, The Sentimental Nation: The Making of the Australian Commonwealth (2000). 2 Official Record of the Proceedings and Debates of the Australasian Federation Conference, 1890 (1890) ('CD Melbourne 1890'); Official Report of the National Australasian Convention Debates. Sydney, 2 March to 9 April, 1891 (1891) ('CD Sydney 1891'); Official Report of the National Australasian Convention Debates. Adelaide, March 22 to May 5, 1897 (1897) ('CD Adelaide 1897'); Official Record of the Debates of the Australasian Federal Convention. Second Session. Sydney, 2nd to 24th September, 1897 (1897) ('CD Sydney 1897'); Official Record of the Debates of the Australasian Federal Convention. Third Session. Melbourne, 20th January to 17th March 1898 (two volumes, 1898) ('CD Melbourne 1898'). The Draft Bills are reproduced as follows: CD Sydney 1891, 943-964 ('1891 Draft Bill'); CD 1897 Adelaide, 1221–43 ('1897 Draft Bill'); CD Melbourne 1898, 2523–44 ('1898 Draft Bill'). The 1891–98 Debates were reprinted in a 1986 facsimile edition as Official Record of the Debates of the Australasian Federal Convention with a sixth volume of indices and commentary. The Debates have also been scanned and made available in searchable text form on the internet by the Senate <http://www.aph.gov.au/senate/pubs/records.htm> and the SETIS project <http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/fed/>. These electronic versions of the Debates were indispensable in carrying out the research on which this article is based. 3 Despite earlier taking the opposite view, see James A Thomson, 'Constitutional Interpretation: History and the High Court: A Bibliographical Survey' (1982) 5 University of New South Wales Law Journal 309. 4 Cole v Whitfield (1988) 165 CLR 360, 385. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 123 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Accordingly, there is a rich and growing legal scholarship that focuses on the Debates and assesses the extent to which they can assist in resolving current constitutional problems.5 It is important to recognise, however, that the Conventions and the Debates are not coterminous with the federation movement and that they offer no more than one slice of federation history. However, for constitutional scholars, it is an important slice. In practice if not in strict theory, the Debates and the draft Constitution Bills have had greater interpretive significance than most other aspects of federation history. It is debatable whether they identify any more clearly than other sources 'the nature and objectives of the movement towards federation from which the compact of the Constitution finally emerged'.6 But they are more like the lawyers' familiar tool of a text that is complete, canonical and authoritative. That is, the Debates are complete in that they encompass all of the matters dealt with in the Constitution and substantially all of its text; they are canonical in that their form and content was fixed in the 1890s by the shorthand notetakers and the publishers; and they derive authority from the statutory foundations of the Conventions, their (mostly) democratic and charismatic make-up and their substantial authorship of the text ultimately adopted by the people and enacted by the Imperial Parliament. Although lawyers must deal with the internal contradictions and inconsistencies of the Debates, those difficulties may appear less significant than the open-endedness and multiplicity of the wider historical record. Moreover, as an historical resource, the Debates are a useful record of the intellectual milieu that produced the text of the Constitution, if not of the whole federation movement. For these reasons they are a worthwhile object of study. Accordingly, it is against this background that I turn to consider the historical and legal significance of property as it was discussed at the Conventions. II. PROPERTY IN THE CONSTITUTION A. 'Property', 'land' and 'territory' In this Part, I identify the constitutional provisions in which 'property' and some related terms appear, in preparation for Parts IIC, IID and IIE, which assess the extent to which the Conventions shed light on the meaning of those provisions. Five sections of the Constitution refer expressly to 'property'. The two sections of greatest significance today are ss 51(xxxi) and 114. • Section 51(xxxi) gives the Parliament the power to make laws with respect to: The acquisition of property on just terms from any State or person for any purpose in respect of which the Parliament has power to make laws. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 5 Noted by John Waugh, 'New Federation History' (2000) 24 Melbourne University Law Review 1028, 1041, referring to Kim Rubenstein, 'Citizenship and the Constitutional Convention Debates: A Mere Legal Inference' (1997) 25 Federal Law Review 295; Haig Patapan, 'The Dead Hand of the Founders? Original Intent and the Constitutional Protection of Rights and Freedoms in Australia' (1997) 25 Federal Law Review 211; Rowan McMonnies, 'Ngo Ngo Ha and the High Court v New South Wales: Historical Purpose in History and Law' (1999) 27 Federal Law Review 471, 474–81; Fiona Wheeler, 'Original Intent and the Doctrine of the Separation of Powers in Australia' (1996) 7 Public Law Review 96. 6 See reference from Cole v Whitfield, above n 4, 385. 124 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ • Section 114 provides (in relevant part) that each State and the Commonwealth may not tax the property of the other without consent: A State shall not, without the consent of the Parliament of the Commonwealth … impose any tax on property of any kind belonging to the Commonwealth, nor shall the Commonwealth impose any tax on property of any kind belonging to a State. Three other provisions are of limited significance today: • Section 85 operated when State government departments were transferred to the Commonwealth on its establishment. In particular, s 85 provided for the Commonwealth to pay compensation to the State for any property that passed to the Commonwealth under such a transfer. The transfer provision, s 69, operated on the establishment of the Commonwealth (and subsequently on dates proclaimed by the Governor-General) to enable the Commonwealth to take over the administration of some areas of government that came within the legislative competence of the Commonwealth Parliament. It has no continuing operation. However, the compensation provisions of s 85 remain interesting for their contrast with s 51(xxxi). • Section 104 provides: Nothing in this Constitution shall render unlawful any rate for the carriage of goods upon a railway, the property of a State, if the rate is deemed by the Inter-State Commission to be necessary for the development of the territory of the State, and if the rate applies equally to goods within the State and to goods passing into the State from other States. The Inter-State Commission does not exist (it was abolished for the second time in 1989) and therefore s 104 also has no continuing operation.7 • Section 98 confirms that the Commonwealth's legislative power with respect to trade and commerce extends to 'railways the property of any state'. Although the provision continues to operate, its interpretation and application has not proved contentious recently. And as is the case with s 104, there is nothing in the Debates that sheds light on the property concept used in this provision. I do not discuss either provision further. As well as the direct references to 'property', the Constitution also contains four linked provisions that together deal with the related concepts of 'land' or 'territory'. • Section 111 provides that the States may surrender 'any part of the State' to the Commonwealth and that following surrender (and acceptance by the Commonwealth) 'such part of the State' becomes subject to the exclusive jurisdiction of the Commonwealth. The sidenote to s 111 reads 'States may surrender territory'. • Section 125 provides for the seat of Government of the Commonwealth: The seat of Government of the Commonwealth shall be determined by the Parliament, and shall be within territory which shall have been granted to or acquired by the Commonwealth, and shall be vested in and belong to the Commonwealth, and shall be in the State of New South Wales, and be distant not less than one hundred miles from Sydney. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 7 Michael Coper, 'The Second Coming of the Fourth Arm' (1989) 63 Australian Law Journal 731. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 125 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Such territory shall contain an area of not less than one hundred square miles, and such portion thereof as shall consist of Crown lands shall be granted to the Commonwealth without any payment therefor. The Parliament shall sit at Melbourne until it meet at the seat of Government. • Section 122 provides that the Parliament may make laws for the government of the Territories: The Parliament may make laws for the government of any territory surrendered by any State to and accepted by the Commonwealth, or of any territory placed by the Queen under the authority of and accepted by the Commonwealth, or otherwise acquired by the Commonwealth, and may allow the representation of such territory in either House of the Parliament to the extent and on the terms which it thinks fit. • And s 52(i) gives the Commonwealth Parliament the exclusive power to make laws with respect to: The seat of government of the Commonwealth, and all places acquired by the Commonwealth for public purposes. In short, of the provisions which remain in operation or are of current interest: • three provisions (ss 51(xxxi), 85 and 125) deal with the compulsory acquisition of property by the Commonwealth;8 • one provision (s 114) deals with taxation of Commonwealth and State property; and • four provisions (ss 52, 111, 122 and 125) deal with the Commonwealth's territorial sovereignty and legislative power over land it acquires or which is surrendered to it. I discuss the provisions in this order in the following Parts, after first considering one place in the Constitution where property is not mentioned. B. Property Remains a State Responsibility Section 51 enumerates the powers of the Commonwealth Parliament. It contains no general provision with respect to property, civil rights, land law or public lands. As a result, regulation of these subjects remains largely a state responsibility.9 It was not inevitable that the States retain responsibility for property or land law after federation. For one thing, one of the models on which the Australian framers drew, the Canadian Constitution of 1867, gave the central legislature the power to make uniform laws with respect to property and civil rights for three provinces.10 For _____________________________________________________________________________________ 8 Note also s 51(xxxiii) which deals with consensual acquisition of a particular kind of property. 9 The Commonwealth is able to regulate property to some extent under other heads of legislative power, such as Australian Constitution s 51(xxvi) which since 1967 has allowed recognition and regulation of indigenous property rights and Australian Constitution s 51(xxix) which (given Australia's international treaty obligations) has allowed for regulation of environmentally significant areas. 10 British North America Act 1867 (Imp) s 94. No such law had effect in any province until it was adopted by the legislature of that province. Apart from this provision, property and civil rights were within the exclusive legislative power of the provinces (s 92(13)), as was 'The Management and Sale of the Public Lands belonging to the Province and of the Timber and Wood thereon' (s 92(5)). 126 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ another, in 1857, a Victorian Parliamentary Select Committee had concluded that there was 'but one opinion' on 'the ultimate necessity of a federal union' and specifically drew attention to the need for uniform 'land systems'.11 Nonetheless, the Conventions rejected, without debate, the option of enabling the Commonwealth Parliament to make uniform property laws. Sir Samuel Griffith, perhaps the dominant figure of the 1891 Convention,12 baldly stated that under Federation the States would retain their legislative autonomy in relation to a list of subjects including 'all the laws relating to property and civil rights, the whole subject of public lands and mines [and] registration of titles'.13 Giving the Commonwealth Parliament power with respect to property and civil rights simply was not considered seriously; neither was giving the Commonwealth power with respect to the colonies' public lands.14 Moreover, when it was suggested that other Commonwealth powers might have had an incidental effect on public lands, property and civil rights, Griffith and Barton, among others, argued and assured the Conventions that these powers should not, and sometimes could not, have this effect.15 And as founding members of the High Court they were able to ensure that this remained the constitutional orthodoxy until the Engineers Case in 1920.16 At one level it is clear why the Conventions took this view and the Framers did not include property as a federal legislative subject-matter in the Constitution. Most of the Framers desired a relatively small Federal government that had power only with respect to matters 'properly federal'.17 They sought a 'federal union of sovereign states' rather than a 'national government'.18 Throughout the Debates and the contemporary material, there is an assumption that the colonies would remain significant political entities as States of the Commonwealth. In particular, they would retain their sovereignty19 and not be reduced to mere municipal governments.20 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 11 Report of the Select Committee of the Victorian Legislative Assembly on the Federal Union of the Australian Colonies (8 September 1857) reprinted in Papers Relating to A Federal Union (1862) 9 and quoted by Sir Henry Parkes, CD Melbourne 1890 (10 February 1890), above n 2, 34–5. 12 Concise biographical information on the various delegates can be found in Helen Irving (ed), The Centenary Companion to Australian Federation (1999). 13 CD Sydney 1891 (31 March 1891), above n 2, 525. See also Thynne, CD Sydney 1891 (3 April 1891), above n 2, 685. 14 See generally Abbott, CD Sydney 1891 (12 March 1891), above n 2, 302. 15 For example, Barton, CD Sydney 1891 (8 April 1891), above n 2, 690 (rivers); Griffith, CD Sydney 1891 (6 April 1891), above n 2, 781–4 (conciliation and arbitration). See also Wise, CD Sydney 1897 (16 September 1897), above n 2, 644; Thynne, CD Sydney 1891 (3 April 1891), above n 2, 685 (objecting to Commonwealth power in relation to banking, bills of exchange, promissory notes, bankruptcy and insolvency on the grounds that these invaded the States' authority over property and civil rights). 16 Amalgamated Society of Engineers v Adelaide Steamship Co Ltd (1920) 28 CLR 129. 17 Deakin, CD Melbourne 1898 (2 February 1898), above n 2, 455; Barton, CD Melbourne 1898 (7 March 1898), above n 2, 1992. 18 Symon, CD Sydney 1897 (10 September 1897), above n 2, 296 quoting from the American, Samuel Adams. 19 Reid, CD Melbourne 1898 (11 March 1898), above n 2, 2268, 2270, 2272–3; Reid, CD Melbourne 1898 (23 February 1898), above n 2, 1384–5; Trenwith, CD Sydney 1897 (15 September 1897), above n 2, 603–4; Robert Garran, The Coming Commonwealth (1897) 15–16. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 127 ____________________________________________________________________________________ The link with property arises because power to regulate land and land use appears to have been an important part of the then contemporary vision of States as significant political entities. Without this power, they would be 'mere municipal governments' (I develop this point in Part IIE below.) Accordingly, it was virtually beyond question that the states would retain responsibility for property, civil rights, land law and public lands if they were to remain the significant political entities the Framers anticipated. Moreover, by the 1890s, the concerns of the Victorian Parliamentary Select Committee in 1857 about the need for uniform land systems21 were quite remote. From 1858, the Torrens system spread rapidly throughout Australia, producing broadly uniform land titles legislation.22 Moreover, in 1857, Victoria and Tasmania had only recently been separated from New South Wales and, with South Australia, had just received self-governing status; Queensland would remain part of New South Wales for another two years before it too became self-governing.23 With self-government came the power to determine land policy, including policy about the grant or sale of Crown lands.24 The novelty of the power may have contributed to the concerns of 1857. Whatever the source of the concerns, over the next forty years, the colonial parliaments separately addressed the problems of providing secure tenures for squatters on Crown land and opening the land up for selection by others. Their policies were not always successful and they changed regularly. But by the 1890s the differences between the colonies do not appear to have been regarded as cause for concern and certainly not as requiring a national solution.25 Given these developments and the general pre-commitment to the states as significant political entities, it is hardly surprising property remained a state responsibility.26 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 20 Playford, CD Melbourne 1890 (10 February 1890), above n 2, 71; Thynne, CD Sydney 1891 (16 March 1891), above n 2, 402–3. 21 Report of the Select Committee of the Victorian Legislative Assembly on the Federal Union of the Australian Colonies, above n 11. 22 Douglas J Whalan, The Torrens System in Australia (1982) 3–12. 23 Western Australia did not receive responsible self-government until 1890 under the Constitution Act 1889 (WA). 24 Bruce Davidson, 'An Historical Perspective of Agricultural Land Ownership in Australia' in James Lees (ed), A Legacy Under Threat?: Family Farming in Australia (1997) 15, 30–1; Stephen H Roberts, History of Australian Land Settlement 1788–1820 (1968) 218–58. 25 To the extent that there were differences, they appear to have been fiscal. New South Wales derived a disproportionately large amount of its revenues from land sales: Donaldson, CD Sydney 1897 (6 September 1897), above n 2, 38–9; see also CD Sydney 1891 (12 March 1891), above n 2, 311. Barton certainly did not endorse New South Wales' policy: CD Sydney 1897 (8 September 1897), above n 2, 209 ('We are in an advantageous financial position in this respect as compared with the rest of the colonies, because we may be said to be cutting down the ancestral trees'). 26 An unsuccessful attempt was made to provide for how the Commonwealth should deal with its own public lands, apparently following the enthusiasm for perpetual leasehold sparked by Henry George in 1883: Glynn, CD Melbourne 1898 (8 February 1898), above n 2, 698–9. The view of the Convention appears to have been that this was the kind of contentious matter which ought to be left to the Federal Parliament: Brown, CD Melbourne 1898 (8 February 1898), above n 2, 699 (on Henry George and perpetual leaseholding, see Davidson, above n 24, 44; Roberts, above n 24, 408–9). 128 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ C. Acquisition of Property by the Commonwealth I now turn from the omission of property as a subject of Commonwealth legislative power to consider the provisions of the Constitution that do deal with property. The first group of these provisions, ss 51(xxxi), 85 and 125, provide for the Commonwealth to acquire property from the States; s 51(xxxi) also provides for acquisitions from private persons. The debate on what was to become s 51(xxxi) was brief and came close to the end of the Conventions. Barton moved the adoption of text equivalent to s 51(xxxi) on 25 January 1898, in response to concerns that the other provisions of the draft Constitution would not be sufficient to enable the Commonwealth to acquire the land it needed for public purposes. Barton commented that, although s 85 would allow for the transfer of parts of the State public service and s 111 would allow for the (consensual) surrender of territory by States, there was no general power of acquisition. Barton invited comments from other Framers on whether the express incidental power (now s 51(xxxix)) would fill this gap.27 In an oblique response, Quick pointed out that the United States, Canadian and Swiss constitutions all explicitly authorised the central legislature to enact compulsory acquisition legislation, at least for the acquisition of land required for military purposes.28 More to the point, Isaacs asserted that the express incidental power would authorise such legislation.29 Quick (anticipating the view later expressed in his and Garran's Annotated Constitution of the Commonwealth of Australia30) and Glynn then insisted that it would not; accordingly they pressed for an express power authorising acquisition legislation.31 Typically, the debate did not resolve the point of legal principle. Rather, it focussed on three objections to Barton's proposal: • First, Turner feared that any extension of the Commonwealth's power to acquire property (and therefore of its liability to pay for that property) would reduce the funds that the Commonwealth would otherwise have returned to the States.32 • Secondly, Turner objected to the use of the words 'just terms' 'on the grounds that they are not proper words to put into the Constitution': 'We assume that the Federal Parliament will act strictly on the lines of justice'.33 This is the familiar objection to protecting rights in the Constitution: the legislature should not be _____________________________________________________________________________________ 27 CD Melbourne 1898 (25 January 1898) , above n 2, 151. 28 Ibid 151–2. In Germany a similar power was vested in the Emperor. 29 Ibid 152. Isaacs expanded on this point later, referring to American authorities: CD Melbourne 1898 (28 January 1898) , above n 2, 260–1 (here he also distinguishes between the Commonwealth as proprietor and the Commonwealth as sovereign). See also Isaacs, CD Melbourne 1898 (16 February 1898), above n 2, 1007. 30 John Quick and Robert Garran, The Annotated Constitution of the Australian Commonwealth (first published 1901, reprinted 1976) 640–1. 31 CD Melbourne 1898 (25 January 1898), above n 2, 152. See also the exchange between O'Connor and Cockburn, CD Melbourne 1898 (28 January 1898), above n 2, 258. 32 CD Melbourne 1898 (25 January 1898), above n 2, 152. He need not have worried about a surplus: see New South Wales v Commonwealth (the Surplus Revenue Case) (1908) 7 CLR 179; Denis James, 'Federal–State Financial Relations: The Deakin Prophecy', The Vision in Hindsight: Parliament and the Constitution: Paper No 2, Research Paper No 17 1999–2000, Department of the Parliamentary Library (2000) 4-5. 33 CD Melbourne 1898 (25 January 1898), above n 2, 153. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 129 ____________________________________________________________________________________ presumed to act in a manner that adversely affects individual rights and if it does the sanction lies at the ballot box rather than in the courts.34 • Thirdly, Isaacs observed that the clause would enable the Commonwealth to acquire land within a state without the consent of that state, contrary to the requirements of what was to become s 111 and to the then current draft of what became s 52(i).35 Barton answered Turner's first objection clearly enough. Without a power such as that conferred by s 51(xxxi), any acquisition would be carried out by contract and would be more expensive than a compulsory acquisition carried out under s 51(xxxi) where the compensation would be determined by arbitration or court proceedings.36 However, Barton did not respond to Turner's second objection or to Isaacs' objection; rather, at their suggestion, he withdrew the proposed section for further discussion outside the chamber.37 The Debates do not reveal whether any such discussions took place and, if so, what was said. The matter returned to the chamber several days later when O'Connor moved the adoption of what eventually became s 51(xxxi).38 O'Connor simply said: Some question has been raised as to whether the Commonwealth has the power inherently of acquiring property under just terms of compensation; that is to say, whether it is not driven to bargain and sale only. It is quite clear that there must be a power of compulsorily taking property for the purposes of the Commonwealth. … And this clause is framed to provide for that.39 In answer to a question about the terms on which acquisitions would be carried out, O'Connor said that it was not appropriate to provide in detail in the Constitution for the actual method of acquisition: that was a matter for legislation.40 The clause was then adopted without further debate. What can be drawn from this perfunctory discussion? Clearly enough, it provides little assistance in interpreting s 51(xxxi). The section was adopted without amendment _____________________________________________________________________________________ 34 Owen Dixon, 'Two Constitutions Compared' in J Woinarski (ed), Jesting Pilate and other Papers and Addresses (1965) 100, 102; Robert Menzies, Central Power in the Australian Commonwealth (1967) 54; Amalgamated Society of Engineers v Adelaide Steamship Co Ltd (Engineers Case) (1920) 28 CLR 129, 151–2. 35 CD Melbourne 1898 (25 January 1898), above n 2, 153. Section 53(II) then provided for exclusive Commonwealth power with respect to: II. The government of any territory which by the surrender of any State or States, and the acceptance of the Commonwealth, becomes the seat of Government of the Commonwealth, and the exercise of like authority over all places acquired by the Commonwealth, with the consent of the State in which such places are situated, for the construction of forts, magazines, arsenals, dockyards, quarantine stations, or for any other purposes of general concern. This aspect of s 53(II) was discussed further at CD Melbourne 1898 (28 January 1898), above n 2, 256–61. Note also s 51(xxxiii) which authorises Commonwealth laws with respect to 'the acquisition, with the consent of a State, of any railways of the State on terms arranged between the Commonwealth and the State' (emphasis added). 36 CD Melbourne 1898 (25 January 1898), above n 2, 152. 37 CD Melbourne 1898 (25 January 1898), above n 2, 154. 38 CD Melbourne 1898 (4 March 1898), above n 2, 1874. 39 Ibid. 40 Ibid. 130 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ at the last Convention, so it is not possible to trace successive drafts through the draft Constitution Bills, seeking to identify significant alterations and omissions. There is nothing in the Debates that identifies the contemporary meaning of 'property' or 'acquisition' or 'just terms'. There is little that takes the reader beyond the words of the section itself in identifying 'the subject to which [the] language' of the section 'was directed'.41 The examples given by the speakers of the purposes for which property could be acquired under the section (military facilities,42 a federal court-house or a federal custom-house43 or a leper station44) cannot limit the generality of the purposes comprehended by the language of the provision: 'any purpose in respect of which the Parliament has power to make laws'. Nor can the speakers' apparent assumption that the property to be acquired would be land limit the generality of 'property' as the subject-matter of the section.45 And even if their examples and assumptions could in principle have been used to limit the scope of the section in this way, the High Court has long taken the view that 'property is the most comprehensive term that can be used'46 and that it includes for the purposes of s 51(xxxi) every species of valuable right and interest including real and personal property, incorporeal hereditaments such as rents and services, rights of way, rights of profit or use in land of another, and choses in action.47 It appears to be too late to retreat to the narrower conception of the section that was apparently intended by the Framers. One thing is clear, however. The Debates do not support the assertion that the section was modelled on the American Takings Clause. That assertion was made by Dixon J in Andrews v Howell: The source of sec. 51 (xxxi.) is to be found in the fifth amendment of the Constitution of the United States, which qualifies the power of the United States to expropriate property by requiring that it should be done on payment of fair compensation.48 Whatever support for this view there might be elsewhere, there is no evidence of it in the Debates.49 Not only is the language of the sections very different,50 so too are their respective historical contexts. The Australian colonies had not undergone the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 41 See reference from Cole v Whitfield, above n 4, 385. 42 Quick, CD Melbourne 1898 (25 January 1898), above n 2, 151. See also the purposes referred to in draft cl 53(II), above n 35. 43 Quick, CD Melbourne 1898 (25 January 1898), above n 2, 152. 44 Cockburn, CD Melbourne 1898 (28 January 1898), above n 2, 258. 45 Unless an argument can be built on the more specific acquisition powers in ss 51(xxxiii) and 85(ii). That seems unlikely. 46 Commonwealth v New South Wales (1923) 33 CLR 1, 20–1. 47 Minister of State for the Army v Dalziel (1944) 68 CLR 261, 290. 48 (1941) 65 CLR 255, 282. See also The Australian Apple and Pear Marketing Board v Tonking (1942) 66 CLR 77, 82–3. 49 Quick and Glynn had referred to Art 1, s 8, paras 17 and 18 of the United States Constitution: CD Melbourne 1898 (28 January 1898), above n 2, 151–2, but had not referred to the Takings Clause. 50 One is framed as a legislative power subject to a limitation, the other as a guarantee of individual rights; one refers to 'acquisition', the other to 'tak[ing]'; one refers to 'just terms', the other to 'just compensation'; and one limits the purposes of acquisition to 'any purpose in respect of which the Parliament has power to make laws', the other to takings 'for public use'. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 131 ____________________________________________________________________________________ American experience of revolution and its aftermath. Following the revolution, newly powerful majorities confiscated the property of the British and their allies, introduced debtor-relief laws and required that depreciated paper money be accepted in payment of debts.51 Moreover, James Madison's fears for the property rights of the minority if political power were entrusted to the propertyless majority never assumed major significance in the Australian Debates;52 and to the extent that such issues were discussed it was in the context of the powers and composition of the Senate rather than in creating judicially enforceable barriers to the redistribution of property.53 Accordingly, there is no comparison with the background to the American Constitution and Bill of Rights. The modern tendency to regard s 51(xxxi) as a broad guarantee of individual rights has no basis in the Debates.54 This point is reinforced when the late introduction of s 51(xxxi) is contrasted with the significantly longer history of s 85. At least from the 1891 Convention, acquisition of property under s 85 and its antecedents was linked with an obligation to pay compensation. The 1891 Draft Bill provided that if a State and the Commonwealth could not agree on the amount of compensation payable for property acquired by the Commonwealth when a State government department was transferred to the Commonwealth, 'the value thereof shall … be ascertained in the manner in which land taken by the Government of the State for public purposes is ascertained under the laws of the State'.55 This compensation formula appeared in substantially the same form in the 189756 and 189857 Draft Bills. However, from 1898, a distinction was drawn between (a) property exclusively used in connection with the State government department and (b) property used, but not exclusively used, in connection with the State government department. In the Constitution as enacted, as in the 1898 draft, s 85(ii) provides that the 1891 compensation formula (based on the compensation payable under State compulsory acquisition laws) only applies to property of the latter kind. Section 85(iii) provides separately for compensation for property of the former kind: 'if no agreement can be made as to the mode of compensation, it shall be determined under laws to be made by the Parliament'.58 In short, compensation was required by the Draft Bills prepared by the Conventions whenever the Commonwealth compulsorily acquired property from private individuals or the states.59 Three standards of compensation were employed: the 'just _____________________________________________________________________________________ 51 James W Ely Jr, The Guardian of Every Other Right (1992) 34–58. 52 On Madison's fears, see Jennifer Nedelsky, Private Property and the Limits of American Constitutionalism (1990) 16–66. 53 See below Part III(B). 54 See Smith v ANL Limited (2000) 176 ALR 449, 451-452, 468, 476, 487, 494, 496-497 and the earlier cases cited in Simon Evans, 'When Is an Acquisition of Property Not an Acquisition of Property?' (2000) 11 Public Law Review 183, 199 n 67. 55 1891 Draft Bill, above n 2, Chapter IV, cl 6, para 2. 56 1897 Draft Bill, above n 2, cl 86, para 2. 57 1898 Draft Bill, above n 2, cl 85(II). 58 Australian Constitution s 85(iii). That is supplemented by a requirement that the Commonwealth take over the current obligations of the states in respect of the departments transferred: Australian Constitution s 85(iv). 59 Section 125 provides in part that so much of the seat of government as was Crown land should be acquired from the state in which it was situated 'without any payment therefor'. 132 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ terms' required by s 51(xxxi) of the Constitution; the standards fixed by state compulsory acquisition legislation required by s 85(ii); and the standards to be fixed by federal legislation required by s 85(iii).60 In light of this pattern of providing compensation when property is acquired compulsorily, and the longstanding British and colonial tradition which it reflects,61 it is difficult to fix on an American constitutional provenance for one of these provisions (s 51(xxxi)) and attribute to the Framers an intention that it reflect an American constitutional guarantee, particularly one cast in significantly different language. Ultimately, then, the Debates provide little assistance in resolving the current problems of s 51(xxxi) jurisprudence.62 Not only is the debate on this section brief and largely unrevealing, the High Court has long since moved beyond what does emerge as the apparently intended operation of s 51(xxxi). Nonetheless, this fragment of debate on s 51(xxxi) does provide a useful illustration of some more general features of the Debates. In particular, the Framers' assumptions about property and constitutionalism are unstated and unexplored. There is no discussion of what property is; why compensation is appropriate when the Commonwealth acquires property; or whether this requirement should be entrenched (apart from Turner's objection to doing so63). These issues lie firmly in the background. The debate occurs at a level of generality appropriate to reaching political agreement on a constitution rather than one appropriate to reaching philosophical agreement about the issues to which the constitution is addressed. This example reinforces the need to be cautious in attempting to rely on the Debates to resolve interpretive problems that reflect disagreements about the scope and purpose of particular provisions. D. Property and Taxation The next provision of the Constitution that refers to property is s 114. This section prevents the Commonwealth and the States from imposing taxation on the property of the other. The initial draft (so far as is relevant here) only prohibited the States from imposing taxation on 'on any land or other property belonging to the Commonwealth'.64 The provision was made reciprocal (prohibiting the Commonwealth from imposing tax on any land or other property belonging to a State) in 1891 on a motion by Griffith and with brief discussion of only one question.65 In 1897, the clause was introduced in a slightly amended form: the subject-matter of the proscribed taxation became 'property of any kind' rather than 'any land or other _____________________________________________________________________________________ This text was introduced by the premiers after the 1897–98 Convention had ended and the first referendum in New South Wales had failed: John Quick, Historical Introduction to Annotated Constitution (1901) 219–20. It does not represent the outcome of the Convention's deliberative processes. 60 The last is supplemented by a requirement that the Commonwealth take over the current obligations of the states in respect of the departments transferred: Australian Constitution s 85(iv). 61 Dating at least from the time of Blackstone: William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England (first published 1765) vol 1, 139. Compare Durham Holdings Pty Ltd v The State of New South Wales (2001) 177 ALR 436, 443–444 (Kirby J). 62 On those problems, see Evans, above n 54. 63 See text above n 33. 64 CD Sydney 1891 (8 April 1891), above n 2, 883. 65 Ibid. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 133 ____________________________________________________________________________________ property' as in 1891.66 However, the debate focused chiefly on other parts of the clause.67 This aspect of the clause was discussed only in response to South Australian concerns. Glynn pointed out that much land in South Australia was leased with the right of purchase and that the clause might defeat any taxation of that property.68 O'Connor and Barton pointed out that the State's property in such a case was the reversion, which could not be taxed by the Commonwealth, but that the 'interest of the lessee in the property would be taxable'.69 In answer to another question, Barton asserted that the clause would not prevent the Commonwealth levying customs duties on goods (such as rails, machinery and engines) imported by the States,70 an assertion later vindicated by the decision of the High Court in Attorney-General (NSW) v Collector of Customs (NSW) (the Steel Rails Case).71 Once again the debate was perfunctory and is of limited assistance in interpreting the section. The language and history of the section are as one in identifying the breadth of the subject-matter of the proscribed taxes. The debate, particularly Barton's contribution, supports the High Court's approach to distinguishing between taxes on owning and holding property (proscribed by s 114) and taxes on transactions involving property (not proscribed by s 114).72 But beyond this there is little of interest. In particular, there is no discussion of why it was thought necessary to prohibit the States from taxing the Commonwealth's property (and vice versa) but not necessary to prohibit them imposing other burdens (including non-property taxes) on each other.73 As in the (non-)debate on whether the States or the Commonwealth should have legislative power with respect to property matters, a complex set of assumptions about the relationship between property and governments appears to lie behind the discussion. But once again it is not articulated by any of the Framers. In the next Part, I consider the extent to which those assumptions can be discerned in other parts of the Debates. E. Property – Ownership and Sovereignty The final set of provisions (ss 52, 111, 122 and 125) deal with the acquisition of property by the Commonwealth as a polity (rather than as a proprietor) and with the Commonwealth's legislative power over property it acquires. Although the High Court has found useful material in the Debates and draft Constitution Bills for interpreting _____________________________________________________________________________________ 66 CD Adelaide 1897 (20 April 1897), above n 2, 1001. 67 The prohibition on states imposing harbour rates and tonnage dues. Ultimately, the provision in relation to tonnage dues was omitted: CD Adelaide 1897 (20 April 1897), above n 2, 1004. 68 CD Adelaide 1897 (20 April 1897), above n 2, 1001. Glynn returned to this theme in 1898, misconstruing the intended effect of the text: CD Melbourne 1898 (7 February 1898), above n 2, 653. Barton pointed out that the provision would not prevent taxation of private property and the clause was agreed to without division: ibid. 69 CD Adelaide 1897 (20 April 1897), above n 2, 1001–2. 70 CD Adelaide 1897 (20 April 1897), above n 2, 1002. 71 (1908) 5 CLR 818. 72 Deputy Commissioner of Taxation v State Bank of New South Wales (1992) 174 CLR 219. 73 Nor to prohibit the States from imposing taxes on one another and one another's property: State Authorities Superannuation Board v Commissioner of State Taxation (WA) (1996) 189 CLR 253. 134 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ some aspects of these provisions74 there is little that bears on the specific concepts of 'property' or 'territory' used here. However, the debate on these provisions does raise the question of the relationship between property as an object of ownership and property as an area over which a polity exercises sovereignty or political dominion. Section 122 (which provides for Commonwealth legislative power over the Territories) certainly contemplates the Commonwealth acquiring sovereignty over the land to which it applies, including land acquired under ss 111 and 125. But s 52(i) (in so far as it provides for exclusive Commonwealth legislative power over 'all places acquired by the Commonwealth for public purposes') does not necessarily contemplate the Commonwealth acquiring sovereignty over the land to which it applies (consider for example land acquired under s 51(xxxi) for the purpose of building and operating a post office). 1. Sovereignty and Commonwealth property Nearly a century after federation, the High Court's decisions in Mabo v State of Queensland [No 2]75 and Wik Peoples v State of Queensland76 made clear that sovereignty over land does not entail beneficial ownership of that land. That position was not the received view at the time of the Conventions77 and accordingly the concepts were more tightly linked in the Debates than would be expected today. Isaacs appears to have been the only delegate to distinguish explicitly between proprietorship of and sovereignty over land acquired by the Commonwealth. He argued: [W]hen the Government does take land, compulsorily or by purchase, in a state as its possession, it takes that land certainly by virtue of its sovereign power of eminent domain, that is, the highest dominion. But it does not hold that land as sovereign, it holds the land as proprietor. 78 Isaacs then distinguished between the case where the land was acquired with the consent of the state and where it was acquired without consent: Now, where it holds the land merely as proprietor, without the consent of the state being given to it, it is quite plain that the jurisdiction of the state should run, except, of course, so as not to interfere with the performance of the governmental functions of the Federal Government. But, as far as punishing crime is concerned, as far as any other ordinary state supervision relates, not inconsistent with the performance of the supreme functions of the Commonwealth, the ordinary state law will run. But … where the state consents to the Federal Government acquiring any land, either by purchase or compulsorily, it thereby consents, and that consent is equivalent to the admission of the right of the Federal Government to exercise exclusive jurisdiction in respect to that particular portion of territory.79 Hence, s 52 was initially drafted to require the consent of the state before the Commonwealth acquired exclusive jurisdiction over the property it acquired.80 Ultimately, Isaacs' view did not prevail and s 52 now draws no distinction between _____________________________________________________________________________________ 74 For example, Svikart v Stewart (1994) 181 CLR 548 on whether s 52(i) applied to property acquired by the Commonwealth within a territory. 75 (1992) 175 CLR 1. 76 (1996) 187 CLR 1. 77 Mabo v State of Queensland [No 2] (1992) 175 CLR 1, 43–5. 78 CD Melbourne 1898 (28 September 1898), above n 2, 261. 79 Ibid. 80 1891 Draft Bill, above n 2, cl 53(2). 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 135 ____________________________________________________________________________________ property acquired with and without the consent of the state; in both cases the Commonwealth has exclusive jurisdiction. But Isaacs' recognition of the distinction between proprietorship and sovereignty remains relevant. As Mason CJ, Deane, Dawson and McHugh JJ pointed out in Svikart v Stewart: It is … plain that s 52(i) was intended to provide for exclusive Commonwealth legislative power with respect to places acquired by the Commonwealth in a State. To achieve this in an Australian context there was no need, as there was in the United States, to think in terms of territorial sovereignty. It was sufficient that acquisition of property should carry with it legislative authority without political dominion.81 Accordingly, as Isaacs foreshadowed, s 52 deals with legislative authority over land held by the Commonwealth as proprietor, not with political dominion over land held as sovereign. 2. Property, sovereignty and development I have already introduced one other way in which the concepts of sovereignty and proprietorship were linked in the Debates. The colonies (or at least their representatives at the Conventions) saw their sovereignty, their political existence and significance, as tightly linked with control over land and its development.82 Much more recently, Western Australia maintained this view in Western Australia v Commonwealth (the Native Title Act Case) when it challenged the Native Title Act 1993 (Cth) on the grounds that it interfered with its continued existence as a State.83 Western Australia had pleaded: 62. The capacity and power to grant, regulate and otherwise deal with land and other resources in Western Australia, including the capacity and power to appropriate land for public purposes and to alienate and develop Crown lands, particularly for agricultural, pastoral and mining purposes in accordance with the laws in force in Western Australia is a fundamental sovereign function of the Government of Western Australia as a State. 63. The capacity and power to administer and regulate land and other resources in Western Australia and the revenue derived from it are essential to the continued existence of the State and its capacity to function as a government.84 These arguments carried no weight in the High Court in 1995.85 But similar arguments did play a part at the Conventions. For example, Barton saw the railways, the land and the sovereignty of the states as integrally connected: If the land is the possession of the province let us consider what railways were created for. Were they not created for the development of the land, and are they not as much an instrument for the development of the land as the roads and bridges … ? … [T]hey exist for the same purpose as the roads and bridges, namely, for the development of the land which we, the people of the individual colonies, mean to retain. There is something which inherently makes them a provincial and not a federal property.86 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 81 (1994) 181 CLR 548, 560–1. 82 See text above n 18, and following. 83 (1995) 183 CLR 373. 84 (1995) 183 CLR 373, 478–9. 85 Ibid 480–2. 86 CD Adelaide 1897 (31 March 1897), above n 2, 370. 136 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Accordingly, the Commonwealth should not be able to acquire the railways without the consent of the states. The railways were 'so inherently connected with the development of the States, it should be for the local Parliaments to say whether they would hand them over or not'.87 And so s 51(xxxiii) now provides. Similarly, Holder used the nexus he perceived between land development and the sovereignty of the states to argue (ultimately unsuccessfully) that the power to grant bounties should remain with the states: [W]hat has more to do with the development of the Crown lands and the foundation of the settlement of these lands, as well as enlarging the industries dependent upon those lands, than bounties for the export of produce from that land?88 That the argument carries less weight today draws attention to the shift, culturally and economically, that has occurred in the last century away from perceiving the land as an important part of national and state identity. Equally important for some was control over the rivers. South Australia depended (then as it does now) on the River Murray for irrigation and drinking water and (then but to a greatly reduced extent now) for commercial navigation. The Murray is fed by a number of rivers that rise in New South Wales and which New South Wales farmers also depend on for irrigation. Of course, water taken by New South Wales farmers means less water for South Australia. South Australia's delegates, therefore, sought federal control over rivers and navigation. New South Wales resisted and framed its defence of state control of the rivers on the basis that the river and its waters were New South Wales property. Wise said: The water is as much the property of New South Wales as any inch of its territory. The bed of the river is ours, and we have the power to gather a pretty considerable revenue from wharfage and tonnage dues, the whole length of the boundary between New South Wales and Victoria.89 Barton observed that '[m]atters relating to irrigation and so on [were] intimately connected with property and civil rights', matters of state and not federal concern, and he therefore argued that they be left in State hands.90 On the other side of the debate, Deakin quoted from a paper by Inglis Clark defending the South Australian position in property terms: 'The riparian rights of the owners of land abutting on the River Murray, in the colony of South Australia, are rights of property in South Australia'.91 New South Wales legislation could not authorise infringement of those property rights and any infringer would be liable to suit in the federal courts.92 Even those who sought a measure of joint control over the rivers conceived of the problem in property terms. Turner suggested that 'water ought to be considered as common property'.93 Higgins used similar language: 'The water does not belong to _____________________________________________________________________________________ 87 CD Adelaide 1897 (31 March 1897), above n 2, 373. See also Barton, CD Sydney 1897 (8 September 1897), above n 2, 207. 88 CD Adelaide 1897 (19 April 1897), above n 2, 844. 89 CD Adelaide 1897 (17 April 1897), above n 2, 825. 90 CD Sydney 1891 (3 April 1891), above n 2, 690. 91 CD Melbourne 1898 (3 February 1898), above n 2, 516–17. 92 Ibid 517. 93 CD Melbourne 1898 (25 January 1898), above n 2, 125. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 137 ____________________________________________________________________________________ New South Wales, Victoria, or any other colony; it is the public property of Australia'.94 And Gordon argued: Rivers which take their rise in New South Wales, but which run for huge distances through other colonies, cannot be described by the residents of New South Wales as "our rivers," using the term in the sense of exclusive and sole possession. They are no more the rivers of New South Wales in that sense than the sun which warms them belongs to New South Wales, or the air which sweetens them is the air of New South Wales.95 The use of the rivers should be 'controlled in the interest of all riparian coproprietors'.96 And (then) modern legislation recognised that even the riparian owner's property rights in the stream were subject to 'a higher, a paramount, right' of others who depended on the stream.97 The pervasive use of 'property-talk' on all sides of the debate obscured the real issues. Higgins demonstrated how inapt it was to refer to the rivers as the property of any state: At what point, then, does it become New South Wales property? I say that you cannot sever a river from its tributaries, any more than you can sever an engine from its wheels, or a man from his arms. Do these waters become exclusively New South Wales property when they are in the clouds in the form of rain, or in the Queensland hills in the form of creeks? Is the Darling the property of New South Wales when it forms a part of that colony, or when it empties its waters into the Murray and passes through South Australia?98 Ultimately the compromise reached was to balance the Commonwealth's power over navigation and shipping as part of interstate trade and commerce (s 98) with a prohibition (s 100) on it abridging the right of any State or its residents to 'the reasonable use of the waters of rivers for conservation or irrigation', deferring the issue for resolution by the Parliament, the Inter-State Commission and ultimately the High Court. The debate on the rivers shows the other side of the property-sovereignty equation from the arguments raised in the Native Title Act Case. That is, in this debate, the proprietor is conceived of as sovereign over its property: the rivers are identified with property, the states as their owners, and it is said to follow that the state should have sovereignty over them. The argument fails at each stage. Higgins showed how problematic it was to talk of the rivers as property. Even if they can be so regarded that fact does not identify their 'owner'. And the elision of property and sovereignty is plainly problematic in any coordinate federal system. But that is not the only point. The rhetoric of property and ownership parallels the rhetoric of territory and sovereignty. Each appeals to notions of exclusive control over a resource – expressed in Blackstone's influential conceptions of property on the one hand as a person's 'free use, enjoyment and disposal of all his possessions' and his or her 'sole and despotic _____________________________________________________________________________________ 94 CD Melbourne 1898 (1 February 1898), above n 2, 406. 95 CD Melbourne 1898 (21 January 1898), above n 2, 32–3. 96 Ibid 34. 97 Ibid 37. 98 CD Melbourne 1898 (21 January 1898), above n 2, 60–1. O'Connor was not persuaded: 'Now that is a very pretty rhetorical figure, but by the same process of reasoning I have heard gentlemen satisfy themselves that there is no such things as property at all, that "all property is robbery," and that we ought to "begin again".' (CD Melbourne 1898 (24 January 1898), above n 2, 64.) 138 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ dominion' over the external things of the world,99 and of sovereignty on the other hand as the 'supreme, irresistible, absolute, uncontrolled authority' necessarily possessed by some agency over a territory.100 The appeal of these conceptions is strong. It was deployed strategically on all sides of the debates as a political argument in the search for a political solution to the problems of federation. This is a useful reminder of the nature of the Conventions and the mistake of attempting to read them as a coherent statement of one vision for federated Australia. III. PROPERTY AND THE POLITICAL CONTEXT OF FEDERATION In the previous Section, I focused principally on property as it appears in the Constitution. In this Section, my focus is broader. I discuss the striking ways in which property, as a political concept, influenced debate at the Conventions on constitutional provisions that do not themselves deal with property. In Parts IIIA and IIIB, I discuss how property influenced debate on two key issues that are not explicitly linked with property, first, the availability of appeals from Australian courts to the Privy Council and, secondly, the franchise and membership of the Commonwealth Parliament. In Part IIIC, I discuss the limits of property and how it becomes invisible in discussion of women's and indigenous people's interests. A. Property, the Privy Council and the Objects of Government The property lawyer's traditional concern with clarity and certainty of property rights and the impartial determination of property disputes permeated the Debates. Some of the Framers were, of course, sceptical of the claims for certainty: I do not think that we can, in human affairs, prevent the possibility of some doubt. We have only to get as near absolute certainty as we can. We know that things are always changing in the management of property and of public and private affairs. It is impossible to reduce to a specific and certain rule anything that involves the rights of mankind. That never has been done yet, and we cannot do it in this Constitution.101 But the predominant view was in favour of clarity and certainty.102 The great concern was ensuring that public and private investment in Australia, particularly inward investment, was not threatened by federation.103 This concern was put most robustly in relation to the question whether it should be possible to bring an appeal from the decisions of Australian courts to the Privy Council. Concern with property rights was not the only issue here. The Framers were split between those who wanted a strong national supreme court and those who wanted to retain the Imperial link to the Privy Council. Both were important symbols with strong resonances. Costs were also an issue104 as were the Privy Councillors' _____________________________________________________________________________________ 99 Blackstone, above n 61, vol 1, 138, and vol 2, 2. 100 Ibid vol 1, 49. 101 Symon, CD Melbourne 1898 (2 February 1898), above n 2, 438. 102 Including in relation to the rivers: Carruthers, CD Melbourne 1898 (1 February 1898), above n 2, 389; Reid, CD Melbourne 1898 (4 February 1898), above n 2, 579; Carruthers, CD Melbourne 1898 (7 March 1898), above n 2, 1955. 103 Ibid. See also Wise, CD Melbourne 1898 (24 January 1898), above n 2, 105; Carruthers, CD Melbourne 1898 (1 February 1898), above n 2, 393. 104 Abbott, CD Melbourne 1898 (11 March 1898), above n 2, 2292. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 139 ____________________________________________________________________________________ knowledge of local property conditions105 and the relative qualities of local judges and the members of the Privy Council.106 But of the practical (as opposed to symbolic) issues, the interests of 'property' and 'capital' featured most strongly. In 1891, one speaker identified the fear of many: terminating appeals to the Privy Council would have the effect of 'stopping capital from flowing into this country'.107 Another said: [A] vast amount of English capital is invested in these colonies, … and I apprehend that the owners of capital and the projectors of business in the old country will view with anything but satisfaction a determination on the part of these colonies to prohibit them in the case of a conflict involving large interests on their part from having the opinion of the best judges in the land upon the question involved.108 A third adopted an argument made by Richmond J of the Supreme Court of New Zealand in an 1891 letter to Parkes: The confidence with which investments of all sorts are now made in Australasia by people at home must be largely due to the knowledge that rights of property will be dealt with here by the Law Courts on British principles of justice, and subject to final review by one of the highest English courts.109 But Higgins and Isaacs were doubtful of the effect of the availability of an appeal to the Privy Council on British capitalists' investment decisions: Another point raised is that British capital will be terrified from investment in Australia if we keep this High Court only. Does anyone say that British capital has been kept away from the United States because the States have not got an appeal to Great Britain? We know that British capital flows more readily there than to Australia … As British capital flows to the States so it will flow to Australia, so long as Australia keeps its settled condition and shows its wholesome dread of any violent changes.110 The British capitalist, when he considers whether he will invest his money here, will ask, not what is likely to be the decision of a court of law in a contest, but what is our legislation. He will ask what are the laws which govern the subject-matter on which he is asked to invest his money. … He is never looking to the courts of law for an ultimate decision. He is not apprehending the question of litigation. He relies on the honour and integrity of those with whom he is dealing, and all he asks and likes to see is what is the legislation on the subject.111 Typically, the solution adopted in the Draft Bill adopted by the 1898 Convention was a compromise. Clause 74 provided that no appeal lay to the Privy Council in any matter involving the Commonwealth or State constitutions 'unless the public interests of some part of Her Majesty's Dominions, other than the Commonwealth or a State, are involved'.112 Appeals were possible in other matters by special leave granted by the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 105 Ibid 2287; contrast Carruthers, CD Melbourne 1898 (11 March 1898), above n 2, 2313. 106 Higgins, CD Adelaide 1897 (20 April 1897), above n 2, 987. 107 Fitzgerald, CD Sydney 1891 (9 March 1891), above n 2, 173. 108 Wrixon, CD Sydney 1891 (1 April 1891), above n 2, 541. 109 Abbott, CD Adelaide 1897 (20 April 1897), above n 2, 971 (and see more generally, ibid 970– 2). Richmond’s letter was received by the 1891 Convention and ordered to be printed, together with Clark’s notes on the letter: CD Sydney 1891 (24 March 1891), above n 2, 510511. 110 Higgins, CD Adelaide 1897 (20 April 1897), above n 2, 988. 111 Isaacs, CD Melbourne 1898 (11 March 1898), above n 2, 2316. 112 1898 Draft Bill, above n 2, cl 74. 140 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Queen, however, the Parliament could limit the matters in which leave might be sought. The 1898 Draft Bill was not the end of the story. Even after the text of the Constitution was approved by the Australian people at referenda, it still had to be enacted by the Imperial Parliament. Contrary to the view taken in Australia, the British government preferred that the right to seek leave to appeal not be restricted. After intense lobbying in London by Australian delegates and debate in the Imperial Parliament, a compromise was reached and the question was eventually resolved in the terms of the current s 74: the High Court could itself grant leave in certain constitutional cases and the Australian Parliament could limit the other matters in which leave might be sought.113 The concern with protecting property rights that in large part drove the debate on Privy Council appeals is representative of a larger concern with property and the objects of government. Parkes was more explicitly libertarian (at least in his rhetoric) than most others: Government, I apprehend, on any just, honest, not to say any philosophical basis, is a contrivance which is found necessary in a community of men to protect their rights, and property, and their liberty, to enforce their laws, and to repress crime; and whatever form this government assumes, the true principle is to call upon the people for whom this government is necessary, in the form of taxation, for just such sacrifices as may be necessary to support it. I am one of those who hold it to be a fundamental wrong to impose burdens upon a free people for any purpose whatever than the purpose of sustaining necessary institutions under a settled government; and in that case the taxes should be raised in the manner most consistent with liberty, the manner which will least interfere with the free actions of the citizens, and the manner which will be least oppressive as a pecuniary burden.114 The Debates contain many statements to the effect that the role of government is the protection of 'life and property' or 'life, liberty and property'.115 Downer regarded property and life as 'the most sacred of all subjects'.116 Symon said: He speaks of our financial interests, and we hear of the great bogie of the rights of property. I have as great a desire to maintain the rights of property as he has. I do not believe in the sacred rights of contract being wantonly interfered with. I do not believe in sacred rights of property being assailed unnecessarily.117 Of course, a commitment to the protection of life, property and liberty is not necessarily an evenhanded commitment to the protection of every person's life, _____________________________________________________________________________________ 113 The story is told in more detail in, for example, Hon Sir Gerard Brennan AC KBE, 'Centenary of the Enactment of the Commonwealth of Australia Constitution Act' (2001) 75 Australian Law Journal 31, 32–3. 114 CD Sydney 1891 (13 March 1891), above n 2, 315. Compare his Burkean vision of the ideal senate: ibid 319. 115 See, for example, Hall, CD Melbourne 1890 (12 February 1890), above n 2, 184; Wise, CD Sydney 1897 (10 September 1897), above n 2, 326 (quoting Story J); Isaacs, CD Melbourne 1898 (9 February 1898), above n 2, 722; Deakin, CD Melbourne 1898 (8 March 1898), above n 2, 2042. 116 CD Adelaide 1897 (20 April 1897), above n 2, 975 (in debate on a provision limiting appeals from Australian courts to the Privy Council); referred to by Higgins, CD Melbourne 1898 (31 January 1898), above n 2, 338–9. 117 CD Adelaide 1897 (20 April 1897), above n 2, 983. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 141 ____________________________________________________________________________________ property and liberty. The Tasmanian proposal that the Constitution should include a provision corresponding to the American 14th Amendment (which would have prevented states from depriving any person of their property without due process of law) was defeated, not out of any lack of solicitude for property rights but largely out of concerns that it would prohibit racially discriminatory state legislation.118 Inglis Clark was atypical among the Framers in perceiving how rhetoric about the protection of property and liberty could be used to justify legislation that protected sectional interests: [W]e know that the law is often used as a means of effecting indirectly some ulterior purpose, also for the purposes of class or special interests. The game laws of England occupied in former years, and occupy now to a certain extent, a foremost place in the provisions of British criminal legislation. We know what detestable and abominable laws they were, and we know that they were introduced not for the protection of life and property and individual liberty in the ordinary sense – not for the same purpose as that for which you make murder or forgery a crime – but for the conservation of certain class interests and class privileges.119 On the other hand, many Framers found it difficult to see in debate how their position reflected and protected their class position. This was particularly the case in the debate on the franchise for elections to and eligibility for membership of the Commonwealth Parliament, which I consider next. B. Property and the Franchise Two important tasks facing the Framers were to determine how the members of the Commonwealth Parliament were to be chosen and, if they were to be elected, to define the franchise that was to apply. Unsurprisingly, property concerns powerfully influenced the debate on these questions. 1. The 1891 Convention The 1891 Convention, following the Draft Bill that Inglis Clark had prepared and the then prevailing American position, resolved that the Senate would be chosen by the members of the State Parliaments.120 At the time of federation, several of the colonies restricted the franchise to adult male property owners.121 For example, in Victoria although adult male suffrage applied for elections to the Legislative Assembly following s 128 of the Constitution Act Amendment Act 1890 (Vic),122 the Legislative _____________________________________________________________________________________ 118 CD Melbourne 1898 (8 February 1898), above n 2, 667–90; CD Melbourne 1898 (3 March 1898), above n 2, 1791–1802. The Tasmanian proposal was in the following terms: The citizens of each state, and all other persons owing allegiance to the Queen and residing in any territory of the Commonwealth, shall be citizens of the Commonwealth, and shall be entitled to all the privileges and immunities of citizens of the Commonwealth in the several states, and a state shall not make or enforce any law abridging any privilege or immunity of citizens of the Commonwealth, nor shall a state deprive any person of life, liberty, or property without due process of law, or deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of its laws. 119 CD Sydney 1891 (11 March 1891), above n 2, 252. Compare EP Thompson, Whigs and Hunters: The Origin of the Black Act (1975). 120 1891 Draft Bill, above n 2, ch 1, cll 9 and 10. 121 See McGinty v Western Australia (1996) 186 CLR 140, 242–3. 122 See Quick and Garran, above n 30, 57. 142 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Council franchise was more restricted and required that the elector hold land for life with an annual value of at least £10 (or hold land that, for a term of at least five years, had an annual value of at least £25).123 On the other hand, in New South Wales, adult male suffrage prevailed in the Legislative Assembly but the Legislative Council was appointed rather than elected.124 Queensland and Western Australia permitted plural voting by voters who owned property in more than one electorate although Western Australia extended the franchise to adult females as well as males.125 Understandably, the differences in the colonial franchises provided a point of division in the definition of the national franchise. Opponents of property qualifications objected to the Senate being chosen by the State Parliaments for so long as those Parliaments were appointed from among the propertied class or elected on a property franchise. Grey perceived a risk that 'power may fall almost entirely into the hands of capital', which dominated the colonial upper houses.126 He was quite direct in identifying why he thought the Convention largely supported such a proposal: [Y]ou propose then to establish a machinery made up of the existing machineries which will enable you to hold every one of the advantageous powers that you have now in your possession.127 Deakin observed that the proposal would endow members of nominee houses with power equivalent to that of members of elective houses, and [would] endow members elected by a limited franchise with equal power so far as their numbers go to that exercised by the popular branch of the legislature.128 His counter-proposal was that the State governments should nominate the senators and be responsible for their nomination. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 123 Constitution Act Amendment Act 1890 (Vic) ss 43-45, 50-51. Certain professional and military men were exempted from the property requirements. See Quick and Garran, above n 30, 57. 124 See Quick and Garran, above n 30, 48. 125 Ibid 71, 74. 126 CD Sydney 1891 (2 April 1891), above n 2, 598. See also CD Sydney 1891 (9 April 1891), above n 2, 926. 127 CD Sydney 1891 (2 April 1891), above n 2, 634. See also his comments on property qualifications for membership of the Parliament (CD Sydney 1891 (18 March 1891), above n 2, 487) and on the unfairness of plural voting based on property ownership (CD Sydney 1891 (6 April 1891), above n 2, 750–1; CD Sydney 1891 (8 April 1891), above n 2, 889–90; CD Sydney 1891 (9 April 1891), above n 2, 926–7). Contrast CD Sydney 1891 (6 April 1891), above n 2, 751: The state legislatures are not allowed to represent the people, but are forced by the present laws to represent capital, and, that being so, hon. members say that the state legislatures shall elect the senate – that is, a constituency unfairly and unjustly created is to return the senate – and then hon. members debate as if it were a matter of the greatest consequence to the liberties of the people of this country whether the senate or the house of representatives shall have the greater power. What care we for their power? It is the power of capital alone, and squabbles between two parties of capitalists little interest the people at large. with CD Sydney 1891 (6 April 1891), above n 2, 753, where he extols the democratic composition of the Senate (whose members need not satisfy any property qualification) and urges that its powers not be limited. 128 CD Sydney 1891 (2 April 1891), above n 2, 591–2. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 143 ____________________________________________________________________________________ On the other hand, some (whether optimistically or somewhat blindly) saw no reason to believe that the Senate would represent property-owners despite the manner in which its members were chosen.129 Rutledge was much influenced by Bryce's assessment of the American Senate whose members at this time were appointed by the state legislatures: Both [the Senate and the House of Representatives] equally represent the people, the whole people, and nothing but the people. The individual members come from the same classes of the community; and though there are more rich men (in proportion to numbers) in the Senate than in the House, the influence of capital is not markedly greater.130 Accordingly, as he thought that the Senate would not be significantly different in character from the House, he saw no objection to giving the two Houses equal powers.131 But Gillies appeared to be entirely oblivious to the different treatment of those with and without property. He responded indignantly to claims that the Victorian Legislative Council represented a property class: A property class! Every man in these colonies, I am glad to say, is a propertied man. I believe that you cannot go to any part of the world where there is such a large proportion of the population who have got something. You cannot go down the street without seeing every one pretty well dressed. Of course there are occasions in every great city when a certain number of persons are unable to obtain work; but I venture to say that every hardworking, determined, sober-minded, honest man can throughout the greater portion of the year get work. … [I]n all the colonies there are large sums of money in the savings banks, and in the various institutions where the people can lodge their money and get a considerable amount of interest. … There are a few people who, through hard work, thrift, and good opportunities, have acquired great wealth, a fact to which I have no objection, and am sure that everybody would like to see everybody else in a comfortable position; but as to talking about the working-classes as contra-distinguished from any other classes in the state, I venture to say that we are all members of the working-classes … and to create such distinctions is quite unnecessary. I pointed out that in Victoria the suffrage is so low that the great body of the working-men – I mean men who work every day with their hands, tradesmen and others – have votes for the Legislative Council, and the members of the council see that they are under a great responsibility in representing such a large constituency.132 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 129 For example McIlwraith, CD Sydney 1891 (5 March 1891), above n 2, 63. There were other reasons for having the State Parliaments chose Senators other than preference for propertyinterests. Griffith saw it as a way of ensuring uniformity: if selection was instead in accordance with legislation enacted in each State, 'in one state they might represent the property-holders of the state, and in another state universal suffrage, and one man one vote' (CD Sydney 1891 (2 April 1891), above n 2, 591). 130 CD Sydney 1891 (9 March 1891), above n 2, 148. Bryce was an English commentator on the American political and constitutional system. His The American Commonwealth (first published 1888, 3rd ed, 1893–1895) was much quoted at the Conventions. The United States moved to popular election of senators in 1913 on the ratification of the 17th Amendment to the United States Constitution. 131 CD Sydney 1891 (9 March 1891), above n 2, 143–50, especially 146–8. 132 CD Sydney 1891 (11 March 1891), above n 2, 235. Cuthbert said, 'I believe the Council now represents 130,000 of what may be called the very pick and flower of the population of Victoria. We have represented there both rich and poor. … We have every careful and prudent man represented there'. (CD Sydney 1891 (12 March 1891), above n 2, 292.) It is 144 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ South Australian delegates were in the vanguard of attempts to remove the property qualification. Cockburn regarded the absence of a property qualification as a matter of 'vital principle' in relation to which 'certain definite lines … should be laid down as part of the constitution'.133 Accordingly, he proposed an amendment that would have prevented the Parliament from imposing any property qualification.134 Munro developed a point also made by Cockburn in arguing that a property qualification gave the lie to the ideal that the Houses be 'chosen by the people'.135 If the Senate was to be appointed, its democratic legitimacy was lessened and Kingston therefore objected to it having equal powers with the House of Representatives: Instead of the senate representing the same body of electors as those who will return members to the house of representatives, it will represent a much more limited class. … What does that, amount to? It amounts to this: That an equal voice will be accorded in all cases which are most favourable to the exercise of popular rights to a limited class, representative not of the general body of the people, but of persons possessing a property qualification.136 In Kingston's view, the likely class basis of the Senate also required that its powers be limited to the protection of state interests137 and that it not have the power to amend or originate taxing and spending bills.138 The issue of democratic principle, typically, fell away. Barton, following Downer's pleas that the issue not be pressed as it could stand in the way of federation,139 instead proposed that the Commonwealth Parliament have the power to define its own franchise.140 This lead to a heated, but confused debate, as speakers objected to Cockburn's and Barton's very different proposals on the same ground, that they interfered too greatly with the states' rights to settle their own franchise and the basis on which they were represented in the Federal Parliament. Ultimately both amendments were defeated141 and the 1891 Convention produced a Draft Bill under which the Senate would be appointed by the State Parliaments. That was to change in 1897. 2. The 1897-1898 Convention In 1897, the Convention resolved to have the Senate directly elected by the people of the States. But that position was not reached without debate, and it still left for decision _____________________________________________________________________________________ worth comparing the Framers' ideas about poverty and pauperism in the debate seven years later on the proposal that the Commonwealth have power with respect to invalid and old-age pensions: CD Melbourne 1898 (21 January 1898), above n 2, 6-29; CD Melbourne 1898 (7 March 1898), above n 2, 1991–6. That debate largely concerned the federal issue (that is, whether the Commonwealth or the States should be responsible for pensions) rather than the merits of government-provided pensions and is accordingly not treated in detail here. 133 CD Sydney 1891 (2 April 1891), above n 2, 613. 134 CD Sydney 1891 (2 April 1891), above n 2, 613–14. 135 Ibid 615. 136 Kingston, CD Sydney 1891 (6 April 1891), above n 2, 736. 137 Ibid 736–7. 138 Ibid 735 (indicating his intention to vote against Baker's amendment: ibid 722). 139 CD Sydney 1891 (2 April 1891), above n 2, 618–19. 140 Ibid 619–20. 141 Ibid 636–7. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 145 ____________________________________________________________________________________ the question whether the franchise for the two Houses of the Federal Parliament would be the same. There was widespread support for the proposition that there should be no property qualification for the members or electors of either house. Turner sought to have this 'definitely and distinctly laid down' in the Constitution as Cockburn had six years previously.142 Kingston argued: We resist a limited franchise on a property qualification. Why? Not because of any attempt to dictate to us, but because we did not believe in it. Similarly we advocate female franchise, because we believe in it.143 Nonetheless, he favoured State rights to determine franchise lest the Federal Parliament introduce its own property qualification or permit plural voting.144 Cockburn once again proposed (unsuccessfully) an amendment stating that no property or income qualification should be required of any elector.145 However, some still feared that an elective Senate on a uniform franchise would not eliminate the influence of property. In this vein, Howe argued that, if each State consisted of only the one electorate for Senate elections, it was likely that the Senate would effectively represent 'property' because of the costs of being a candidate for such a large electorate.146 Accordingly, he proposed that each State should consist of several Senate electorates. Arrayed against these 'advanced democrats'147 were many who supported (more or less clearly) the proposition that property as a class or as a concept ought to be represented in the Parliament. The conservative position was summarised (but not entirely endorsed) by Baker: There are many people in these colonies who look upon this Constitution from a conservative point of view. … They point out that this is a Constitution in which one set of people – those who have little or no property – because they are the majority, will have the power of dictating how the taxes shall be raised, and how the taxes shall be spent; and that another set of people – those who have property, and are the minority – will pay the taxes; that representation and taxation will not go hand in hand, because taxation will be imposed by one class and paid by another.148 Accordingly, they sought the protection of a Senate that represented their interests. Among the mildest of these conservatives, McMillan, unwilling to admit to wanting a conservative Senate or one elected by a propertied class, still wanted the Senate to have a distinctive character: You must have no cry, "Here is the popular house representing the people (with a big 'P'); the other house represents capital, conservatism, and other elements." We do not want that; what we want is that, while not giving any undue influence to the senate, we shall keep up its character as a senate.149 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 142 CD Adelaide 1897 (24 March 1897), above n 2, 38. 143 CD Adelaide 1897 (15 April 1897), above n 2, 724. 144 Ibid 726. 145 Ibid 732. 146 CD Sydney 1897 (13 September 1897), above n 2, 381. 147 Dobson, CD Adelaide 1897 (26 March 1897), above n 2, 196–7. 148 Baker, CD Melbourne 1898 (17 March 1898), above n 2, 2482. 149 CD Sydney 1897 (20 September 1897), above n 2, 815 (emphasis added). 146 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ And in his view, if the Senate did not have a distinctive character (whatever that might be), deadlocks between the Houses could not be resolved by sending both Houses to the electorate.150 Others saw the distinct representation of property as required by principle. In 1891, Douglas, objecting to residency requirements, had argued that property ownership should be sufficient to establish a right to vote: '[I]f a man leaves the colony for two or three years, still having property in it, when he returns he will have to serve a sentence of five years' residence before he is eligible'.151 In 1897, Forrest saw property-based (and plural) voting as justified by the interests of investors: 'We think that where we have invested our capital and other people's capital in far-away districts, we should have something to say as to the persons those districts should return'.152 Zeal put the justification slightly differently; people who pay taxes on their property are entitled to consideration in the political process: Men who have to pay ways and means for the carrying on of the Government should get some consideration, for it is not the men who are here to-day and gone to-morrow who are held responsible.153 Dobson was the staunchest advocate of the representation of property. In his view, the phrase 'one man one vote' was overtaken by the phrase 'one vote for manhood and another for thrift': There is a common opinion all the world over that the people are divided into two classes, those who have and those who have not; and those who have, although some of us have been born with a golden or silver spoon in our mouths, have generally acquired their property by thrift, hard work, industry, and by the sweat of the brow or brain; and the people who have, require, in my idea, far more consideration than those who have not.154 Here is to be a Constitution in which we are absolutely giving property no representation of any description. We are actually giving to men who have nothing, the absolute right to tax all those who have and you are not giving to those who have any single direct voice except what they get by election on manhood suffrage. … [T]here are two classes of people, men who have something to pay their debts, and something in the way of security to offer to the English lender; and on the other hand there are those – to some extent the bone and sinew of the Commonwealth – who have nothing, men who can take up their swag and go away, men who have no property of any description.155 But Dobson, like Gillies in 1891, did not think that he was favouring property for property's sake: 'I do not want to be told that money-bags and property rule the world; it is brains, intelligence and character which rule it'.156 Clearly property played an extraordinarily important part in the debate on the franchise. But property qualifications – like women's suffrage – generated divisions that ran too deep for an answer to be agreed and entrenched in the Constitution. So just as there was no express guarantee of women's suffrage, there was no prohibition of a property qualification. The 'advanced democrats' did succeed in ensuring that the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 150 Ibid. Compare Dobson, CD Melbourne 1898 (9 March 1898), above n 2, 2130. 151 CD Sydney 1891 (2 April 1891), above n 2, 606–7. 152 CD Adelaide 1897 (29 March 1897), above n 2, 251. 153 CD Adelaide 1897 (31 March 1897), above n 2, 363. 154 CD Adelaide 1897 (26 March 1897), above n 2, 192. 155 CD Adelaide 1897 (15 April 1897), above n 2, 671. See also Dobson, CD Melbourne 1898 (8 March 1898), above n 2, 2026. 156 CD Adelaide 1897 (15 April 1897), above n 2, 671. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 147 ____________________________________________________________________________________ franchise for the House of Representatives and the Senate would be the same157 and there would be no plural voting.158 But the larger questions were left for resolution by the political process. The Commonwealth Parliament was authorised (but not required) to define the franchise for all Australia;159 the franchise so defined could be uniform (but was not required to be); the franchise could be expansive (adult and with no property qualification) or narrow (male and property-based) provided only that it did not deprive any person of any right to vote they had for a State Legislative Assembly as at 1901.160 The valuable lesson of the debate on the franchise, and property qualifications in particular, is to remind present-day readers of the Constitution just how divided and divisive opinion on the franchise was. The Framers were deeply committed to radically opposed visions of the democratic polity. As Downer argued: All are agreed that the members of the other House should be returned by the most popular vote that can be obtained. The difference arises from the definition of what is the most popular vote, South Australia considering that the most popular vote is adult suffrage, others considering that it is manhood suffrage, and others again considering that some property qualification ought to be imposed.161 As the majority of the High Court concluded in McGinty v Western Australia,162 this makes it virtually impossible for any interpreter with originalist commitments to draw any implications about the franchise or equality of voting power from the Debates. C. The Rights of Women and Indigenous Peoples Race and gender were major issues at the Conventions. On race, the Framers considered whether the Commonwealth or the States should be responsible for immigration, which in context meant restricting immigration and controlling 'alien races' within Australia.163 A proposal that a version of the American 14th Amendment be adopted was defeated largely because of fears that it would prevent states from discriminating against people of certain races in their factory and mining legislation.164 The Framers excluded indigenous Australians when counting the number of the people of the Commonwealth in order to apportion the seats in the House of Representatives between the States.165 They excluded them also from the power to make special laws for the people of any race.166 South Australian delegates and some others fought a long and only partially successful campaign to include a guarantee of _____________________________________________________________________________________ 157 Australian Constitution s 8. 158 Australian Constitution ss 30, 8. 159 Australian Constitution ss 30, 8 and 51(xxxvi). 160 Australian Constitution s 41. 161 CD Adelaide 1897 (29 March 1897), above n 2, 207. 162 (1996) 136 CLR 140. 163 See generally John Williams, 'Race, Citizenship and the Formation of the Australian Constitution: Andrew Inglis Clark and the "14th Amendment"' (1996) 42 Australian Journal of Politics and History 10. 164 Ibid. See text above n 118. 165 Australian Constitution s 127. The section was repealed by the Constitution Alteration (Aboriginals) 1967. 166 Australian Constitution s 51(xxvi). The exclusion of 'the aboriginal race' from s 51(xxvi) was repealed by the Constitution Alteration (Aboriginals) 1967. 148 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ women's suffrage.167 And the Framers ensured effectively that women's votes would not be counted in referenda in States where adult suffrage prevailed until adult suffrage was uniformly adopted.168 However, in all this discussion, the Debates include virtually no mention of the property rights of indigenous peoples and women. The property rights of indigenous peoples appear to have been mentioned only by the Western Australian Sir George Grey at the close of the 1891 Convention and by Captain Russell, a New Zealand delegate to the 1890 and 1891 Conventions. Grey was concerned about corruption and self-dealing by propertied interests in colonial upper-houses169 and incidentally touched on the consequences for Australia's indigenous population: I could prove that acts of the greatest cruelty have arisen from the causes of which I speak; that great tracts of land – hon. members may laugh – have been under their influence given away in a manner in which they ought not to have been; and that in consequence of regulations to which I object, people of the native races have been expelled from their territory without the least compensation of any kind whatever, purposely that the land might be given to certain persons.170 Russell was concerned to draw attention to the differences between his colony and the Australian colonies.171 After outlining the physical differences, he said: Not only have the settlers [of New Zealand] had to struggle against the forces of nature but against a proud, indomitable, and courageous race of aborigines. That native race has been treated in a manner so considerate that the condition of no other native and savage race on the face of the globe can be compared to it. Their right to their lands was recognised from the first. … [W]e recognised their right to their own land, and instead of confiscating it we admitted their claim to its full possession, administration, and disposal.172 Russell was ambivalent about whether the explanation for this was fear of the indigenous population or the influence of the 'missionary zeal' of the white settlers. But he felt it had a material relevance to federation. 'Native administration' was an important issue for New Zealand and could not be confidently handed over to a Parliament, dominated by Australians who knew nothing about it and who had 'dealt with native races in a much more summary manner than we have ventured to deal with ours in New Zealand': It is extremely improbable that hostilities would again break out between the natives and the white settlers, but the advance of civilization would be enormously delayed if the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 167 Australian Constitution s 41. 168 Australian Constitution s 128. 169 See text above n 126 and n 127. 170 CD Sydney 1891 (9 April 1891), above n 2, 927. Contrast Reid's attitude, expressed some years later: Fortunately, there were no complications in regard to title; the aboriginals were as incapable of bargaining successfully as they were of fighting successfully. The Maoris of New Zealand were quite the opposite. They were just as keen in making a bargain as they were valiant in warfare. Hence this noble native race still possesses some of the most valuable estates in New Zealand. (Sir George Houston Reid, My Reminiscences (1917) 17–18). 171 CD Melbourne 1890 (11 February 1890), above n 2, 125–6. 172 Ibid. 2001 Property and the Drafting of the Australian Constitution 149 ____________________________________________________________________________________ regulation of this question affecting New Zealand was handed over to a body of gentlemen who knew nothing whatever of the traditions of the past.173 In 1891, he returned to the theme in arguing for a loose federation rather than a close, centralised, one. Questions of native title were matters 'of very grave moment' and any interruption in Maori relations 'might be of the most serious importance'.174 Accordingly safeguards would be required before these matters were subjected to federal authority. As for Australia itself: [I]n the colonies of northern Australia, you yourselves may yet find that you have difficulties unforeseen to cope with. It is true that the native races of the more settled portions of Australia have given you but little trouble, and you have dealt with them summarily, but possibly when you go to northern Australia you will find there a race more resolute and more difficult to deal with. 175 There is no recorded response to these parts of Russell's remarks from the other Framers. In the context of federation, the property rights of Australia's indigenous peoples simply did not feature as an issue. Equally, the property rights of women were not perceived as raising issues for debate. Property and civil rights had been defined as a state matter in the 1891 Convention so to some extent this is not surprising.176 But the effect of marriage and divorce on women's property rights were not mentioned when the Framers debated the Commonwealth's proposed legislative powers with respect to those topics.177 They were far more interested in the lack of uniformity between the colonies in the grounds on which a divorce might be granted. Again, it was only Captain Russell who raised the issue and then only in the context of a somewhat tortured analogy. New South Wales, Victoria and Queensland had once formed part of the one colony, he said. There is no reason why they should not be reunited, and if they are reunited it will be a marriage of affection. It will be a case of neighbours whose sons and daughters have married together in order to bring divided lands into one solid property. It will be a marriage of affection if these colonies come together. But with New Zealand it would be simply a mariage de convenance, and her representatives must see that the marriage settlements are not drawn out in a hurry, that before the masculine power and strength of Australia was united to the beauty of New Zealand the settlements are so arranged that the Married Women's Property Act shall have full force in case of any little dispute occurring hereafter. 178 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 173 Ibid 126. 174 CD Sydney 1891 (5 March 1891), above n 2, 66. 175 Ibid. 176 See above Section II(B). 177 CD Sydney 1897 (22 September 1897), above n 2, 1077–85 (including debate on the proposed power with respect to parental rights and the custody and guardianship of infants). 178 CD Melbourne 1890 (11 February 1890), above n 2, 128–9. In 1891, Deakin referred to these remarks: He was careful to tell us that we must not at the present time expect anything from New Zealand; but he laid down with great fulness and freedom the duties which we immediately owed to that most beautiful, important, and wealthy colony, whose position, he led us to understand, was that of the coy maiden, not unwilling, and indeed expecting, to be courted, and whose consent would be granted by-and-by as a favour. (CD Sydney 1891 (5 March 1891), above n 2, 68–9). 150 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ The marriage analogy was pursued by a number of Framers.179 In the previous Sections, I have demonstrated the power of property as a tool of political argument at the Conventions. Here property is silent. The Married Women's Property Act may have recognised married women's separate property interests. But within the Conventions at least those interests were invisible. And despite the New Zealand example, indigenous Australian's property interests were to remain invisible to the legal system for some time to come. IV. ASSESSMENT: GOVERNMENT PROPERTY AND THE BUSINESS OF What, then, are the lessons of this study of property at the Conventions? First, it demonstrates just how little assistance the Debates provide in interpreting the references to property in the Constitution. Section 51(xxxi) and s 114, the two provisions with greatest contemporary interest, were considered briefly and superficially. Their intended meaning is not significantly clarified by the Debates. Property as a concept is taken as a starting point on which the provisions operate and not as something requiring elucidation. Secondly, it reminds us of what the Conventions were. Looking outwards from the Conventions, we are reminded that the they were only part of the process of federation. Federation was a social movement and a study of the Conventions can only present one snapshot of a much wider and extremely complex process. Looking inwards at the Conventions, we are reminded that they were gatherings of colonial politicians engaged on the business of federation. The Framers were political practitioners, not political scientists. So, although there are passing references to Blackstone, Marx and Proudhon, the debate was not oriented towards the latest speculations on the nature of property. Moreover, property considerations were just some among many in the search for a constitution; in particular, a constitution that would commend itself to a majority of voters in each of the colonies, not the ideal constitution envisaged by any particular political theory. Property, then, was used for its rhetorical appeal in a fundamentally political debate. It took its place in the competition between those who favoured a strong and financially well-equipped national government and those who favoured strong states and a small national government; between those who favoured a national supreme court at the apex of the judicial system and those who favoured retaining Imperial links; between those who favoured a democratic system drawn on broad lines and those who favoured a more conservative approach. It was a potent rallying cry for supporters and opponents of these positions, but it provided an answer to none. The concept of property employed by the Framers was ultimately a hollow one. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 179 Hackett, CD Sydney 1891 (12 March 1891), above n 2, 275; Deakin, CD Melbourne 1890 (13 February 1890), above n 2, 106; Cockburn, CD Sydney 1891 (10 March 1891), above n 2, 196; Abbot, CD Sydney 1891 (12 March 1891), above n 2, 298–9; Deakin, CD Melbourne 1898 (17 March 1898), above n 2, 2500; Barton, CD Adelaide 1897 (21 April 1897), above n 2, 1108. COMMONWEALTH IMMUNITY AS A CONSTITUTIONAL IMPLICATION Catherine Penhallurick* INTRODUCTION The existence and potential scope of a Commonwealth constitutional immunity from State law has been a vexed issue ever since the High Court decided its first case on this question in 19041 There have been major shifts in the approach of the Court over the last century, and the doctrines expounded by the Court have been subjected to an unusually large volume of academic criticism.2 The operation of Section 64 of the Judiciary Act 1903 (Cth),3 together with the presumption of crown immunity,4 have in _____________________________________________________________________________________ * BA, LLB (Hons) (ANU). This article is a revised version of an honours thesis completed at the Australian National University Faculty of Law. I would like to thank Adrienne Stone, Matthew Darke, Geraldine Chin and Amelia Simpson for their assistance with this article. 1 D'Emden v Pedder (1904) 1 CLR 91. See, eg, Geoffrey Sawer, Australian Federalism in the Courts (1967) 126. 2 Nicolee Dixon, 'Limiting the Doctrine of Intergovernmental Immunity' (1993) 9 Queensland University of Technology Law Journal 1; John Doyle, '1947 Revisited: The Immunity of the Commonwealth from State Law' in Geoffrey Lindell (ed), Future Directions in Australian Constitutional Law, (1994); Gareth Evans, 'Rethinking Commonwealth Immunity' (1972) 8 Melbourne University Law Review 521; Colin Howard, 'Some Problems of Commonwealth Immunity and Exclusive Legislative Powers' (1972) 5 Federal Law Review 31; HP Lee, 'Commonwealth Liability to State Law — The Enigmatic Case of Pirrie v McFarlane' (1987) 17 Federal Law Review 132; RP Meagher and WMC Gummow, 'Sir Owen Dixon's Heresy' (1980) 54 Australian Law Journal 25; Igor Mescher, 'Wither Commonwealth Immunity' (1998) 17 Australian Bar Review 23; Ronald Sackville, 'The Doctrine of the Immunity of Instrumentalities in the United States and Australia: A Comparative Analysis' (1969) 7 Melbourne University Law Review 15; Geoffrey Sawer, 'State Statutes and the Commonwealth' (1961) 1 University of Tasmania Law Review 580; Leslie Zines, 'Sir Owen Dixon's Theory of Federalism' (1965) 1 Federal Law Review 221. 3 This provision has the effect of submitting the Commonwealth to State law once a 'suit' has commenced. See, eg, Susan Kneebone, 'Claims Against the Commonwealth and States and their Instrumentalities in Federal Jurisdiction: Section 64 of the Judiciary Act' (1996) 24 Federal Law Review 93; see also below n 6. 4 There is a now rather weak presumption that the Crown is not bound by the general words of statutory provisions. See especially Bropho v Western Australia (1990) 171 CLR 1, 23. See also Commonwealth v Western Australia (1999) 196 CLR 392, 410 (Gleeson CJ and Gaudron J). 152 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ many cases prevented the question of constitutional immunity from arising.5 There are, however, a range of situations in which the constitutional issue will still arise.6 More importantly, the Commonwealth immunity from State law remains a highly relevant topic because of the significance of the constitutional issues that it raises. The debate over the existence and scope of the immunity reflects a broader uncertainty as to the form of federalism created by the Australian Constitution.7 In this article, I will argue that the Commonwealth immunity from State law must be recognised as a constitutional implication. Although there has been some acknowledgment that the immunity is an implication, there has been little consideration of the consequences that might follow from this.8 My contention is that the recognition that the Commonwealth immunity is a constitutional implication has major consequences. The Commonwealth immunity has developed in isolation from broader principles of constitutional law, but it must now be reconciled with these principles. Specifically, the implication of Commonwealth immunity must be drawn in a way that is consistent with the approach to implications which has been articulated by the Court; that is, any immunity must be limited to what is necessary to preserve the text and structure of the Constitution. The structure of my argument will be as follows. Part I will outline the development of the Commonwealth immunity doctrine, and show why the doctrine must be recognised as an implication. Part II will outline the approach developed by the Court to the drawing of constitutional implications. Part III will analyse the current doctrine of Commonwealth immunity according to these principles. Part IV I will argue that, given the Commonwealth's ability to protect itself using Section 109, no form of Commonwealth immunity from State law should be implied from the Constitution. PART I: THE DOCTRINE OF COMMONWEALTH IMMUNITY AND ITS CONSTITUTIONAL BASIS In 1904 the Commonwealth Deputy Postmaster-General for Tasmania argued before the newly established High Court that he should not have to pay the two pence of stamp duty on his salary as required by the State of Tasmania.9 In 1997, the Defence Housing Authority sought to convince the Court that it should not be required to submit to New South Wales residential tenancy laws which conferred on their landlord a right to inspect the premises rented by the DHA.10 In these two cases, amongst others, the High Court has been asked to determine whether the Commonwealth _____________________________________________________________________________________ 5 While both of these topics are, in practice, closely connected to the issue of Commonwealth constitutional immunity, they are beyond the scope of this article. 6 For instance, where Section 64 does not apply because there is no 'suit'. See Kneebone, above n 3. 7 Mark Gladman, 'Re the Residential Tenancies Tribunal of NSW and Henderson; Ex Parte Defence Housing Authority (1997) 190 CLR 410: States' Power to Bind the Commonwealth' (1998) 27 Federal Law Review 151, 151; Doyle, above n 2, 49, 68–72; Sackville, above n 2, 15. 8 Doyle, above n 2; Jeremy Kirk, 'Constitutional Implications from Representative Democracy' (1995) 23 Federal Law Review 37, 67. 9 D'Emden v Pedder (1904) 1 CLR 91. 10 Re Residential Tenancies Tribunal (NSW); Ex Parte Defence Housing Authority (1997) 190 CLR 410 ('Residential Tenancies'). 2001 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication 153 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Crown (or Executive), and its agents, possess any immunity from the application of State laws. The text of the Constitution gives the Court no immediately clear answer to this question. Section 109 states that where there is a conflict between Commonwealth and State legislation, the Commonwealth legislation will prevail, but this provision gives no express guidance as to a conflict between the executive power of the Commonwealth and the legislative power of the States. Section 114, which states that neither government may tax the property of another, provides only a limited form of reciprocal immunity. Nor can the Court receive guidance from the intention of the Constitutional founders,11 since the Constitutional Conventions contain few references to the question of intergovernmental immunities and it is unclear whether the founders intended that the Commonwealth would be bound by State law.12 In this Part, I will show that the Court has developed a doctrine of Commonwealth immunity based on the idea that the States lack the power to make laws that affect the Commonwealth in certain ways. I will then argue that this approach is incorrect because the States do have such power, and that the only basis for Commonwealth immunity is as an implication from the Constitution. Although there may appear to be some circularity in this discussion of whether the immunity derives from a lack of power on the part of the States or from an implication protecting the Commonwealth, as will be seen in Part II, given the Court's cautious approach to the drawing of constitutional implications, this is a crucial issue. The approach of the Court to Commonwealth immunity The most recent comprehensive consideration of the issue of Commonwealth immunity from State law by the Court was in the case of Re Residential Tenancies Tribunal (NSW) and Henderson; Ex Parte Defence Housing Authority,13 but in order to understand this decision, it is necessary to examine the earlier cases. The approach prior to the Residential Tenancies decision In the early years of federation, the High Court applied the American doctrine of the implied immunity of instrumentalities to the Australian Constitution,14 holding that any attempt on the part of a State to interfere with the exercise of the Commonwealth's executive or legislative authority, however minor, would be found invalid.15 In Amalgamated Society of Engineers v Adelaide Steamship Company Ltd ('Engineers'),16 a majority of the Court rejected this doctrine as based on a 'vague, individual conception of the spirit of the compact.'17 Analysing the Constitution according to the traditional _____________________________________________________________________________________ 11 Cole v Whitfield (1988) 165 CLR 360, 385. 12 Leslie Zines, 'The Federal Balance' in Gregory Craven (ed), The Convention Debates 1891– 1898: Commentaries, Indices and Guide (1986) 81–84. 13 (1997) 190 CLR 410. See also Commonwealth v Western Australia (1999) 196 CLR 392, 409 (Gleeson CJ and Gaudron J), 421 (McHugh J), 472 (Hayne J). 14 McCulloch v Maryland 17 US (4 Wheat) 316 (1819). See Sackville, above n 2, 19–24. 15 D'Emden v Pedder (1904) 1 CLR 91, 110–111 (Griffith CJ). The doctrine received a reciprocal application in Federated Amalgamated Government Railway and Tramway Service Association v New South Wales Railway Traffic Employees Association (1906) 4 CLR 488. 16 (1920) 28 CLR 129 ('Engineers'). 17 Ibid 144 (Knox CJ, Isaacs, Rich and Starke JJ). 154 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ principles of statutory interpretation left little room for the limitation of power according to notions such as federalism. Although the facts of the case raised the issue of State immunity from the Commonwealth, the majority stated that 'the principle we apply to the Commonwealth we apply also to the States, leaving their respective acts of legislation full operation within their respective areas and subject matters.'18 In Pirrie v McFarlane,19 a majority of the Court applied the Engineers decision in order to find that a Commonwealth soldier was required to hold a state driving licence.20 As Starke J explained, 'the argument denying the power of the States to affect Commonwealth officers based upon some prohibition expressed or implied in the Constitution can no longer be sustained.'21 It was not long, though, before a new doctrine of intergovernmental immunities began to emerge from the judgments of Sir Owen Dixon. Following obiter dicta comments in West v Commissioner of Taxation (NSW)22 and Federal Commissioner of Taxation v Official Liquidator of EO Farley Ltd,23 Dixon J and a majority of the Court held in Melbourne Corporation v Commonwealth24 that the States had a form of immunity from certain Commonwealth laws.25 The pre-Engineers immunity had been reciprocal, but Dixon J indicated in Melbourne Corporation that the Commonwealth's immunity from the States would differ in both its origins and in its scope from the immunity possessed by the States.26 In the same year as Melbourne Corporation was decided, the issue of Commonwealth immunity arose before the Court in In Re Foreman & Sons Pty Ltd; Uther v Federal Commissioner of Taxation,27 in relation to a New South Wales companies law which removed any priority for debts possessed by the Crown in right of the Commonwealth. The Crown's priority in the collection of debts is a prerogative right, and so this case raised the question of whether, as Engineers had hinted, the general principle that the States and Commonwealth could legislate for one another was subject to an exception in relation to prerogative rights.28 A majority of the Court found that the New South Wales Act could validly abolish or restrict the prerogative right of the Crown in right of the Commonwealth to the payment of debt.29 In the majority in Uther, Latham CJ held that, as the Commonwealth had in Section 109, a means of protecting itself against legislation which impaired or interfered with the performance of Commonwealth legislation, unlike the States, it had no need of judicial protection.30 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 18 Ibid 155. 19 (1925) 36 CLR 170. 20 The majority consisted of Knox CJ, Higgins and Starke JJ. Isaacs and Rich JJ dissented for reasons unconnected with any principle of immunity. 21 Pirrie v McFarlane (1925) 36 CLR 170, 226–227. 22 (1937) 56 CLR 657, 681–683 (Dixon J) ('West'). 23 (1940) 63 CLR 278, 299 (Dixon J). 24 (1947) 74 CLR 31 ('Melbourne Corporation'). 25 Ibid 66 (Rich J), 70 (Starke J), 83 (Dixon J). 26 Ibid 82. 27 (1947) 74 CLR 508 ('Uther'). 28 Engineers (1920) 28 CLR 129, 143–144. See also Leslie Zines, above n 2, 225–227. 29 Uther (1947) 74 CLR 508, 513 (Latham CJ), 522 (Rich J), 524 (Starke J), 536 (Williams J). 30 Ibid 520–521. See below Pt IV. 2001 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication 155 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Dixon J dissented in Uther, arguing that the State law was invalid in its application to the Commonwealth.31 In contrast to Latham CJ, his Honour argued that the Commonwealth was entitled to a greater degree of protection than the States. Dixon J's reasoning proceeded in the following steps: The Australian Constitution created a federal system, and 'a federal system is necessarily a dual system'.32 There is an initial presumption that 'in a dual political system you do not expect to find either government legislating for the other.'33 The Constitution confers express grants of specific powers and legislative supremacy on the Commonwealth, which displaces this presumption – therefore, the Commonwealth has power to legislate in relation to the States.34 However, Dixon J argued that the legislative power of the States has no such distinguishing characteristics – it consists only of the residue left after full effect is given to the powers granted to the Commonwealth, and a State law will be subordinate to a Commonwealth law in the case of inconsistency. Therefore the initial presumption, that one government does not legislate for the other, applies to limit State legislative power.35 It is particularly significant that Dixon J's reasoning in Uther made no reference to implications in favour of the Commonwealth. This was despite the fact that, in Melbourne Corporation, his Honour referred to 'the implication protecting the Commonwealth from the operation of State laws',36 and that the statement that a federal system is 'necessarily' a dual system looks very much like an implication. Rather Dixon J's suggestion appeared to be that the States simply lack power to legislate in relation to the rights or activities of the Commonwealth.37 His Honour put forward a number of reasons for this lack of power on the part of the States, which will be discussed below. Sir Owen Dixon's views were confirmed in Commonwealth v Cigamatic Pty Ltd (In Liquidation),38 a case arising on very similar facts to those in Uther, where the now Chief Justice succeeded in overruling the earlier decision.39 'It is not a question,' stated Dixon CJ in Cigamatic, 'of making some implication in favour of the Commonwealth restraining some acknowledged legislative power of the state.'40 Indeed, his Honour indicated that to hold that the States did possess such power would be to 'import' and 'imply' a new proposition into the Constitution.41 There was a great deal of uncertainty about the scope of the immunity established in Cigamatic. In particular, it was unclear whether that decision had to be seen as overruling Pirrie v McFarlane. On a strict reading, the only proposition Cigamatic stood for was that the States were prevented from interfering with Commonwealth prerogative rights. Dixon CJ's comments, though, in particular his suggestion that the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 31 Ibid 528. 32 Ibid 529. 33 Ibid. 34 Ibid. 35 Ibid 529–530. 36 Melbourne Corporation (1947) 74 CLR 31, 83. 37 Uther (1947) 74 CLR 508, 529–531. 38 (1962) 108 CLR 372 ('Cigamatic'). 39 Dixon CJ's view received the support of Kitto, Menzies, Windeyer and Owen JJ. McTiernan and Taylor JJ would have upheld Uther. 40 Cigamatic (1962) 108 CLR 372, 377. 41 Ibid 377–378. 156 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ States had no power to 'control legal rights and duties as between the Commonwealth and its people', seemed to suggest a broader immunity.42 Obiter dicta in Commonwealth v Bogle43 (decided after Uther but before Cigamatic) seemed to provide additional support for the broader interpretation of Cigamatic, by suggesting that the immunity would apply in a situation where no Commonwealth prerogative was involved.44 A majority of the Court in Bogle accepted that 'the State Parliament has no power over the Commonwealth.'45 The only concession was that the Commonwealth might be 'affected' by State law, though exactly what this meant was not explained in Bogle or Cigamatic and remained very unclear.46 The decision in Residential Tenancies47 Largely because of the effect of Section 64 of the Judiciary Act 1903, it was some time before the High Court was called upon to resolve the uncertainties left in the wake of Uther, Cigamatic and Bogle.48 When the issue finally arose in 1997, the question before the Court was whether the Residential Tenancies Act 1987 (NSW) was valid and binding on the Commonwealth Defence Housing Authority.49 Six of the seven judges agreed that the New South Wales Act was binding on the Commonwealth agency.50 However, there was a division of views on the scope of the Commonwealth's constitutional immunity. A majority of the court – comprising Brennan CJ, and, in a joint judgment, Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ – drew a distinction between the 'capacities' of the Commonwealth and the exercise of those capacities, and found that the States could regulate the latter only.51 This meant that 'the Commonwealth might be regulated by State laws of general application in those activities which it carries on in common with other citizens.'52 McHugh and Gummow JJ rejected this distinction in favour of a broader immunity principle, but limited its application by finding that the immunity would generally operate only to the benefit of persons or bodies who derived their _____________________________________________________________________________________ 42 Ibid 377. 43 (1953) 89 CLR 229 ('Bogle'). 44 The case was concerned with whether an increase in accommodation charges at a Commonwealth migrant hostel violated the Victorian Prices Regulation Act 1948. 45 Bogle (1953) 89 CLR 229, 259 (Fullagar J), with whom Dixon CJ and Kitto J agreed. Webb J 'substantially agreed' 255. 46 Ibid 260 (Fullagar J). On the 'affected by' doctrine, see Grant Donaldson, 'Commonwealth Liability to State Law' (1985–86) 16 Western Australia Law Review 135; Evans, above n 2, 532– 547. 47 See generally, Gladman, above n 7; Mescher, above n 2; Leslie Zines, 'The Nature of the Commonwealth' (1998) 20 Adelaide Law Review 83. 48 Section 64 of the Judiciary Act 1903 was applied in Maguire v Simpson (1977) 139 CLR 362 and Commonwealth v Evans Deakin Industries Ltd (1986) 161 CLR 254, removing the need to consider the constitutional immunity. See also Kneebone, above n 3. 49 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410. 50 Brennan CJ and Dawson, Toohey, Gaudron, McHugh and Gummow JJ found the New South Wales law valid. Kirby J dissented on the basis that the State law was inconsistent with the Commonwealth law. 51 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 424–5 (Brennan CJ), 438–439 (Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ). See also below Part III. Gladman, above n 7, discusses the differences between the joint judgment and that of Brennan CJ. 52 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 439 (Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ). 2001 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication 157 ____________________________________________________________________________________ authority from the executive, as opposed to legislative, power of the Commonwealth.53 Kirby J rejected the Cigamatic principle altogether and argued for a reciprocal immunity based on the Melbourne Corporation principle.54 The majority made it clear that they saw the doctrine of the immunity of Commonwealth capacities from State law as emerging from the judgments of Sir Owen Dixon in Uther and Cigamatic. In their joint judgment, Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ repeated the process of reasoning used by Dixon J in Uther. The starting point was a presumption of immunity enjoyed by all governments in a federation – although, where Sir Owen Dixon never made the precise scope of this immunity clear, their Honours were careful to emphasise that the initial presumption was not one of general immunity, but an immunity in respect of executive capacities.55 By adopting this narrower view of the scope of the immunity, the majority ensured that the decisions in Cigamatic and Pirrie v McFarlane could be reconciled. Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ then echoed Sir Owen Dixon's reasoning as to how this basic principle had a different application in respect of the States and the Commonwealth.56 In particular, Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ clearly accepted Sir Owen Dixon's view that the Commonwealth immunity derived from a lack of power on the part of the States rather than from an implication. Their Honours stated that: No implication limiting an otherwise given power is needed; the character of the Commonwealth as a body politic … by its very nature places those capacities outside the legislative power of … a State, without specific powers in that respect.57 Their Honours considered that: [T]he fundamental point made in Cigamatic is that … the priority of the Crown in right of the Commonwealth in the payment of debts is not something over which the States have legislative power.58 Why the Commonwealth Immunity is based on an implication rather than a lack of power The discussion above has demonstrated that the predominant interpretation of a Commonwealth immunity from State law is one based on a lack of power on the part of the States to regulate the Commonwealth in certain ways. This was the basis of Sir Owen Dixon's reasoning in Uther and Cigamatic, it was the view of a majority of the Court in Bogle, and it was accepted by Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ in Residential Tenancies to form the ratio decidendi of that decision. Dixon J's first argument, expressed in Uther, was that there was no possible source of State power to regulate the Commonwealth. The States could not have possessed such a power before federation since the Commonwealth sprang into existence in 1901. Nor did the Constitution confer such a power. Therefore, Dixon J suggested, such a power did not exist.59 Meagher and Gummow have already demonstrated the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 53 Ibid 458–460 (McHugh J), 463–472 (Gummow J). 54 Ibid 499–509 (Kirby J). 55 Ibid 440. 56 Ibid. See above at n 34 and n 35. 57 Ibid 440. 58 Ibid 441. 59 Uther (1947) 74 CLR 508, 530. 158 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ weakness of this argument.60 The source of State power to regulate the Commonwealth is the plenary power, deriving initially from Imperial legislation and confirmed by Section 107 of the Constitution, to legislate in respect of any subject matter from time to time within that power.61 State legislative power is clearly not confined to subjects in existence when the colonies attained responsible government. If it were, the absurd result would follow that the States would be unable to regulate corporations or persons that came into existence after the nineteenth century.62 Dixon J's second claim was that a law adjusting the rights of the Commonwealth could not be for the 'peace, welfare and good government' of a State.63 Meagher and Gummow have observed that this approach was inconsistent with the dual characterisation principle accepted by the Court in relation to Commonwealth powers.64 If a Commonwealth law can admit of more than one characterisation, it is difficult to see why the same principle should not apply to a State law. It is true that a State law regulating the Commonwealth might be outside the scope of the State's plenary power over its territory. For instance, as Latham CJ suggested, a New South Wales law which purported to regulate the functions of the Governor General in summoning and dissolving the Commonwealth Parliament would not be a law for the 'peace, welfare and good government' of New South Wales.65 However, in Uther and Cigamatic, Sir Owen Dixon was concerned with a New South Wales law regulating the winding up of companies in New South Wales. If such a law affects the Commonwealth, it may be said to be a law about Commonwealth prerogative rights, but it remains a law about New South Wales companies. Thus while the terms of State legislative power might render some State legislation affecting the Commonwealth invalid, it is difficult to accept this argument in relation to the type of law before the court in Uther and Cigamatic.66 It should also be noted that the Court has clearly rejected a characterisation approach as the basis for the State immunity from Commonwealth law, as based on artificial reasoning, and that essentially the same criticism applies in the case of Commonwealth immunity.67 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 60 Meagher and Gummow, above n 2, 28; see also Doyle, above n 2, 62–63. 61 See Constitution Act 1855 (NSW). See generally Powell v Appollo Candle Co (1885) 10 App. Cas 282; Union Steamship v King (1988) 166 CLR 1. 62 Although it could be argued that such corporations and persons come within the power of the States because they are of the same general category as previous subjects of State law. As Leslie Zines has noted, if the claim is that the Commonwealth is in a special category, 'we are driven back to the nature of the federal system' — The High Court and the Constitution (4th ed, 1997) 361. This is more appropriately the subject of an implication. 63 Uther (1947) 74 CLR 508, 530–531. 64 Meagher and Gummow, above n 2, 28–29. See A-G (Vic) v Commonwealth (1962) 107 CLR 529; Murphyores Incorporated Pty Ltd v Commonwealth (1976) 136 CLR 1, 19–23 (Mason J), 11 (Stephen J); Fairfax v Federal Commissioner of Taxation (1965) 114 CLR 1; Actors and Announcers Equity Association v Fontana Films Pty. Ltd. (1982) 150 CLR 169. 65 Uther (1947) 74 CLR 508, 521. 66 Uther (1947) 74 CLR 508, 521 (Latham CJ). 67 A characterisation approach to State immunity was advocated by Latham CJ in Melbourne Corporation (1947) 74 CLR 31, 61–62 and by Barwick CJ in Victoria v Commonwealth (The Payroll Tax Case) (1971) 122 CLR 353, 372–373 ('Payroll Tax Case'), but was rejected in Commonwealth v Tasmania (1983) 158 CLR 1, 150–152 (Mason J), 215 (Brennan J); Queensland Electricity Commission v Commonwealth (1985) 159 CLR 192, 215 (Mason J). 2001 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication 159 ____________________________________________________________________________________ An additional argument, raised initially by Fullagar J in Bogle, was that the States had no power to regulate the Commonwealth because the Commonwealth had not assented to a State law.68 Doyle and Evans have both pointed to major flaws in this analysis.69 Most obviously, to suggest that the Crown in right of the Commonwealth cannot be bound by legislation passed by a State legislature, is to ignore the doctrine of the indivisibility of the Crown, which was central to the reasoning of the Engineers decision.70 It would follow from this doctrine that if the Crown in right of a State has assented to a statute, then the Crown in right of the Commonwealth is also bound.71 Moreover, as Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ observed in Residential Tenancies, the significance given to the notion of Crown assent is inconsistent with the reality of parliamentary sovereignty embodied in the Australian Constitution. The Crown is bound by a statute not because it has assented to it, but because Parliament is supreme.72 This principle is reinforced by the fact that the Parliament of a State has the power to bind the Crown in right of another State and the Crown in right of the United Kingdom.73 It is my contention, therefore, that none of the arguments used in support of the view that the States lack power to bind the Crown in right of the Commonwealth stand up to critical analysis. To the contrary, under Section 107 of the Constitution, the States have retained their plenary power to make laws for their own peace, order and good governance, and, prima facie, are capable of binding the Commonwealth. This was recognised in Uther, in Pirrie v McFarlane and, implicitly, in Engineers. Any immunity possessed by the Commonwealth, therefore, must be founded upon an implication from the Constitution. An analysis of the reasoning of Dixon J in Uther shows that the Commonwealth immunity is better understood as an implication, albeit an unacknowledged one. The starting point for his Honour was the idea that a federal system is a dual system, and that in such a system you do not expect to find either government legislating for the other. From this follows a principle of mutual immunity, modified in the case of the Commonwealth by the grant of specific powers, but applicable to the States. Of course, the Constitution does not say that the system it creates is one of 'dual federalism', or that there shall be a mutual immunity beyond Section 114. What Dixon J has done is to form a view as to what the structure of the Constitution requires, and then to imply such restrictions on power as are necessary to maintain that structure. The only difference between Sir Owen Dixon's approach and the process undertaken by the early High Court in creating the doctrine of intergovernmental immunities is that Dixon relies on a form of deduction from the Constitution rather than on American _____________________________________________________________________________________ 68 Bogle (1953) 89 CLR 229, 259. See also Payroll Tax Case (1971) 122 CLR 353, 373 379–80 (Barwick CJ). 69 Doyle, above n 2, 56–65; Evans, above n 2, 527–529. 70 (1920) 28 CLR 129, 152-153 (Knox CJ, Isaacs, Rich and Starke JJ). 71 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 505–506 (Kirby J). Although the doctrine of the indivisibility of the Crown has been subject to criticism – see, eg, Minister for Works v Gulson (1944) 69 CLR 338, 350 (Latham CJ). It was not even discussed in Uther or Cigamatic let alone rejected. 72 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 446. 73 Doyle, above n 2, 60. The author refers to the cases of Public Curator of Queensland v Morris (1951) 51 SR (NSW) 402; Commissioner for Railways v Peters (1991) 102 ALR 579, 589; A-G (Eng) v Sorati [1969] VR 89, 99. 160 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ precedents in moving from the fact that the Constitution creates a federal system to the contention that governments are not entitled to regulate one another.74 Although Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ accepted Sir Owen Dixon's claim that the immunity was based on a lack of power, several of the other judges in Residential Tenancies acknowledged that the Commonwealth immunity was based on a negative implication.75 Kirby J clearly perceived the immunity as being based on an implication, albeit one without legitimate foundations.76 Although McHugh J accepted most of the reasoning in Cigamatic, he realised that the Court was in fact dealing with an implication. McHugh J stated that 'within their respective domains, the polities that make up a federation are regarded as sovereign. Because that is so, it is a necessary implication of the document that creates the federation that no polity in the federation legislate for another.'77 McHugh J, then, recognised that the Cigamatic doctrine is more appropriately viewed as an implication – that the link between a particular view of the federal system and the proposition that governments cannot legislate for one another can only be one of necessary implication.78 PART II – IMPLICATIONS IN CONSTITUTIONAL INTEPRETATION It is a matter of great significance that the current doctrine of Commonwealth immunity is more correctly interpreted as an implied limitation on the power of the States than as the consequence of a lack of State power, for the Court has adopted an entirely different approach to such implied limitations than to questions of a lack of power. Sir Owen Dixon himself had accepted, in Melbourne Corporation, that an implied limitation on power must be 'compelling'.79 In more recent years, the Court has devoted a great deal of attention to the subject of constitutional implications, and has authoritatively determined that such implications are only to be drawn where 'necessary'. The Court has never analysed the Commonwealth immunity according to these principles. But if, as I have argued, Commonwealth immunity is an implication, then it is necessary to evaluate whether the current doctrine of immunity, or in fact any doctrine of immunity, can be reconciled with the Court's approach to implications. This Part will, first, outline the Court's approach to constitutional implications, and second, consider what is involved in this approach, in order to apply these principles to the question of Commonwealth immunity in Parts III and IV. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 74 Geoffrey Sawer, 'Implication and the Constitution, Part I' (1948–1950) 4 Res Judicatae 15, 20. 75 Brennan CJ's judgment in Residential Tenancies is quite ambiguous on this point. 76 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 503–504. 77 Ibid 451. 78 For an interesting parallel with the recent decision of the Court in Re Wakim; Ex Parte McNally (1999) 163 ALR 270, see Graeme Hill, 'The Demise of Cross-Vesting' (1999) 27 Federal Law Review 547, 573–575. Hill argued that the majority, in finding that the States have no power to confer jurisdiction on federal courts, were, without specifically acknowledging this, drawing a negative implication. Hill goes on to contend that this implication is inconsistent with the approach to implications adopted in Lange v Australian Broadcasting Commission (1997) 189 CLR 520 ('Lange'); see also Dennis Rose, 'The Bizarre Destruction of Cross Vesting' in Adrienne Stone and George Williams (eds), The High Court at the Crossroads, (2000), 191–194. 79 Melbourne Corporation (1947) 74 CLR 31, 82. 2001 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication 161 ____________________________________________________________________________________ The first point to note is that the implication of Commonwealth immunity, identified in Part I, would share the same basic features as the implications the Court has devoted its attention to in the past – it is an implied limitation derived from a structural feature of the Constitution.80 The immunity has generally been seen as deriving from the federal structure of the Constitution, although there have been suggestions that its origins may lie in the national character of the Commonwealth.81 Although the Court has generally focused its attention on implications that limit the power of the Commonwealth rather than that of the States, it is clear that the same interpretative principles apply.82 The Court's approach to implications The Court has authoritatively laid down the principles by which implications limiting power are to be drawn. In Australian Capital Television Pty Ltd v Commonwealth,83 Mason CJ stated that 'where the implication is structural…it is no doubt correct to say that the term sought to be implied must be logically or practically necessary for the preservation of the integrity of that structure.'84 In this case, the Court established that the provision for representative government in the Constitution required an implication of a freedom of political communication. The historical precedent that the Court relied on in the Political Broadcasts case was the implication of State immunity in the cases of Melbourne Corporation and Queensland Electricity Commission v Commonwealth.85 In Lange v Australian Broadcasting Commission,86 a unanimous judgment of the Court confirmed that the approach articulated by Mason CJ was the correct one.87 The Court in Lange also took the opportunity to clarify the precise method by which constitutional implications were to be derived: [T]he Constitution gives effect to the institution of "representative government" only to the extent that the text and structure of the Constitution establish it. … under the Constitution the relevant question is not, "What is required by representative and responsible government?" It is, "What do the terms and structure of the Constitution prohibit, authorise or require?"88 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 80 There have also been suggestions of a 'nationhood power' as an implication which operates to expand the scope of Commonwealth power – see Australian Communist Party v Commonwealth (1951) 83 CLR 1, 187–188 (Dixon J); Victoria v Commonwealth and Hayden (1975) 134 CLR 338, 397 (Mason J); Davis v Commonwealth (1988) 196 CLR 79, 110–111 (Brennan J). 81 See Australian Postal Commission v Dao [1985] 3 NSWLR 565, 597–598 (McHugh J); Leslie Zines 'The Commonwealth' in Gregory Craven (ed), Australian Federation Towards the Second Century, (1992), 92–94; Zines, above n 62, 362. 82 Stephens v West Australian Newspapers (1994) 182 CLR 211, 232–234 (Mason CJ, Toohey and Gaudron JJ), 236 (Brennan J). The case for consistency of approach is even clearer where, as here, the implication limiting the States would derive from the Commonwealth Constitution. 83 (1992) 177 CLR 106 ('Political Broadcasts'). 84 Ibid 135. 85 (1985) 159 CLR 192 ('Queensland Electricity Commission'). See especially Political Broadcasts (1992) 177 CLR 106, 134–135. 86 (1997) 189 CLR 520. 87 Ibid 566–567. 88 Ibid. 162 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ This clarification was a response to a perceived divergence of approach in the Court since the initial decisions in Political Broadcasts and its companion case, Nationwide News Pty Ltd v Wills.89 It is clear from the cases discussed above that the same method is to be applied to all implications, whether derived from the system of federalism created by the Constitution, or from the system of representative government.90 Moreover, as the discussion below will show, for as long as the Court continues to accept the interpretive principles laid out in the Engineers decision, the approach endorsed in Lange is the only acceptable approach to constitutional implications. A Consideration of the Court's approach As Stephen Donaghue has observed, 'while the necessity test is frequently invoked, it is rarely explained'. 91 Yet, in order to apply the Court's approach to implications to a new area, it is important to give some consideration to what is involved in this approach. Engineers and Judicial Restraint Despite occasional suggestions by Sir Owen Dixon that the Court should not be 'fearful' of drawing implications,92 as Jeremy Kirk has observed, the weight of Court practice suggests a high degree of caution.93 The necessity test represents a position of judicial restraint which is demanded both by the 'literalist' method of constitutional interpretation and by the Court's concern for its own legitimacy.94 As Mason J acknowledged in Queensland Electricity Commission, the requirement that implications be necessary is directly linked to the more general principles of constitutional interpretation articulated in the Engineers decision.95 The emphasis on a 'literal' and 'legalistic' construction of the text in Engineers had, as Sir Owen Dixon observed, led some to the belief that no implications could be drawn from the Constitution.96 Such an approach, his Honour considered, would 'defeat the intention of any written instrument, but of all written instruments a Constitution seems the last _____________________________________________________________________________________ 89 Nationwide News (1992) 177 CLR 1, 42–45 (Brennan J); 69–73 (Deane and Toohey JJ); Political Broadcasts (1992) 177 CLR 106, 181 186 (Dawson J), 230–232 (McHugh J), 208–215 (Gaudron J). See also Kirk, above n 8, 66–68; Zines, above n 62, 378–379. 90 In Commonwealth v Western Australia (1999) 196 CLR 392, 418, Gleeson CJ and Gaudron J, while not expressly invoking the Lange test, found that particular powers possessed by the Commonwealth left 'no room' for an implied immunity of the Commonwealth from State laws which operated with respect to land set aside for defence purposes. 91 Stephen Donaghue, 'The Clamour of Silent Constitutional Principles' (1996) 24 Federal Law Review 133, 159. 92 Australian National Airways Pty Ltd v Commonwealth (1945) 71 CLR 29, 85 (Dixon J); Lamshed v Lake (1958) 99 CLR 132, 144–145 (Dixon J). 93 Kirk, above n 8, 65–66. 94 On 'literalism' and 'legalism', see generally, Michael Coper and George Williams (eds), How Many Cheers for Engineers? (1997); Zines, above n 62, 424–433; Tony Blackshield and George Williams, Australian Constitutional Law and Theory: Commentary and Materials (2nd ed, 1998), 236–243, 245–251; Gregory Craven, 'The Crisis of Constitutional Literalism in Australia' in HP Lee and George Winterton (eds) Australian Constitutional Perspectives, (1992). 95 (1985) 159 CLR 192 at 212. See also per Brennan J at 230. 96 West (1937) 56 CLR 657, 681. 2001 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication 163 ____________________________________________________________________________________ to which it could be applied.'97 The requirement that implications be necessarily derived from the text and structure of the Constitution represents a reconciliation of the literalism of Engineers with the need to draw implications. Ultimately, the Court's approach to implications can be traced back to the constraints imposed by its own role as the interpreter of the Constitution. If an implication lacks a foundation in the text or structure of the Constitution, then the Court will not be seen to be interpreting the Constitution, but rather to be substituting its own policy preferences for that of the democratically elected Parliament.98 As McHugh J has acknowledged, 'if this Court is to retain the confidence of the nation as the final arbiter of what the Constitution means, no interpretation of the Constitution by the Court can depart from…what is implied by the text and structure of the Constitution.'99 The Issue of Subjectivity Windeyer J suggested that the term 'making implications' was an inappropriate one because 'the avowed task [of the Court] is simply the revealing or uncovering of implications which are already there.'100 This statement reveals the way in which the 'necessity' test can be used as a means of disguising the element of discretion inherent in drawing a constitutional implication. It is now well established that in the interpretation of the text of the Constitution, there is generally an element of subjectivity.101 In determining what necessary implications can be extracted from that text, then, there must also be some element of discretion. The question is, how much discretion? Jeffrey Goldsworthy and Nicholas Aroney, writing in response to the 'free speech' decisions, have suggested that the 'necessity' test involves such a high degree of subjectivity that we might be led to wonder whether the test is much more than a smokescreen for judicial policymaking.102 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 97 Ibid. This statement has been quoted with approval in Pay-Roll Tax Case (1971) 122 CLR 353, 401–402 (Windeyer J), 418 (Gibbs J); Political Broadcasts (1992) 177 CLR 106, 133–134 (Mason CJ); Nationwide News (1992) 177 CLR 1, 42 (Brennan J), 69 (Deane and Toohey JJ). See also Essendon Corporation v Criterion Theatres Ltd (1947) 74 CLR 1, 22 (Dixon J). 98 Michael Coper, 'The High Court and Free Speech: Visions of Democracy or Delusions of Grandeur' (1994) 16 Sydney Law Review 185, 191–192; Adrienne Stone, 'The Limits of Constitutional Text and Structure: Standards of Review and the Freedom of Political Communication' (1999) 23 Melbourne University Law Review 668, 706; Kirk, above n 8, 69–73. 99 Theophanous v Herald & Weekly Times Ltd (1994) 182 CLR 104 at 197; 143 (Brennan J) ('Theophanous'). See also Sir Owen Dixon's speech on his appointment as Chief Justice in (1952) 85 CLR xiv. 100 The Payroll Tax Case (1971) 122 CLR 353, 402. 101 See the extra judicial comments of Sir Anthony Mason in 'The Role of a Constitutional Court' (1986) 16 Federal Law Review 1, 5; and in 'Trends in Constitutional Law' (1995) 18 University of New South Wales Law Journal 237, 237–238; Kirk, above n 8, 67; Bryan Horrigan, 'Paradigm Shifts in Interpretation: Reframing Legal and Constitutional Reasoning' in Charles Sampford and Kim Preston (eds) Interpreting Constitutions (1996); Craven, above n 94. 102 Nicholas Aroney, 'A Seductive Plausibility: Freedom of Speech in the Constitution' (1995) 18 University of Queensland Law Journal 249, 264–267; Jeffrey Goldsworthy, 'Implications in Language, Law and the Constitution' in Geoffrey Lindell (ed), Future Directions in Australian Constitutional Law (1994); Jeffrey Goldsworthy, 'Constitutional Implications and 164 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Even if the criticisms of the implication of political communication are valid,103 they do not establish that the concept of necessity is devoid of meaning, and operates only as a means of disguising policy choices. The basic problem that the critics of the implied freedom have pointed to is that, in order to give some content to the implication of representative government, the Court must look beyond the terms of the Constitution.104 Adrienne Stone has illustrated the limits of the textual approach to implications by reference to the question of the appropriate standard of review to be applied when determining whether a law infringes the implied freedom of political communication.105 Stone observes that the text of the Constitution simply does not provide any guidance on this question – any consistent and principled answer must depend on a view as to the values underlying the implied freedom, and ultimately, the nature of representative government. The source of such ideas must lie outside the Constitution.106 What these arguments show is that, where the Court is required to formulate a complete doctrine based on an implication, as it was in Political Broadcasts and the subsequent cases, the concept of 'necessity' is a very difficult one.107 There is obviously a range of choice in determining the scope of the doctrine, and the limitations which are to be placed on it, and it may be difficult to justify any given choice as more 'necessary' than the others. But it is important to note that, in the context of the political communication decisions, there was little doubt that particular provisions of the Constitution give effect to representative government, and that some limitations must necessarily follow from these provisions.108 Even Dawson and McHugh JJ, who disapproved of the majority reasoning,109 accepted this proposition.110 The focus of this article is on the question of whether any principle of Commonwealth immunity can be said to be necessarily derived from the Constitution, rather than the appropriate form of such immunity. This inquiry, therefore, avoids the greatest difficulties associated with the concept of necessary implications. The widespread agreement that some form of freedom of political communication does flow from the provision for representative democracy suggests that an answer to the question of whether any implied limit can be found in the Constitution is more likely to be provided by an interpretation of the text of the Constitution, than is an answer to _____________________________________________________________________________________ Freedom of Political Speech: A Reply to Stephen Donaghue' (1997) 23 Monash University Law Review 362. 103 Contra Donaghue, above n 91. 104 See above n 102; Stone, above n 98; Leslie Zines, 'The Present State of Constitutional Interpretation' in Stone and Williams (eds), above n 78 227–228; Kirk, above n 8. 105 Stone, above n 98; see also, by the same author, 'Incomplete Theorizing in the High Court' (1998) 26 Federal Law Review 195; 'The Freedom of Political Communication Since Lange' in Stone and Williams, (eds) above n 78. 106 Ibid 696–699. 107 As witnessed by the disagreement of members of the court as well as by the academic criticism – see above n 102; Theophanous (1994) 182 CLR 104, 163 (Deane J), 188 (Dawson J), 194 (McHugh J). 108 AR Blackshield, 'Implied Freedom of Communication' in Geoffrey Lindell (ed), Future Directions in Australian Constitutional Law (1994), 239; Zines, above n 62, 391–392; Kirk, above n 8, 75–76. 109 Political Broadcasts (1992) 177 CLR 106, 186–187 (Dawson J), 229–233 (McHugh J); Theophanous (1994) 182 CLR 104, 194 (McHugh J). 110 Political Broadcasts (1992) 177 CLR 106, 186–187 (Dawson J), 229–233 (McHugh J). 2001 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication 165 ____________________________________________________________________________________ the question of the appropriate content of such a limitation. Thus, on Dawson J's reasoning in Political Broadcasts, some form of limitation must be implied, since Sections 7 and 24 of the Constitution refer to representatives being chosen, and that choice must be a true one.111In Part IV of this article, I will suggest that the answer to the question of whether any implication of Commonwealth immunity can be drawn also lies in the effect of a particular provision of the Constitution, namely Section 109. There is room for legitimate disagreement as to the effect of that section, but nonetheless the section does provide that answer. PART III: AN ANALYSIS OF THE CURRENT DOCTRINE AS AN IMPLICATION In Part I, I argued that the general view of the Court – that the doctrine of Commonwealth immunity was based on a lack of State power – was incorrect, and that the immunity must be seen to be based on an implication. The first question that arises, then, is whether the form of Commonwealth immunity recognised in Residential Tenancies, as the established precedent, could simply be reformulated as an implication consistent with the test endorsed in Lange. I will argue that the majority position emerging from Residential Tenancies – that the capacities of the Commonwealth are immune from State law – is based more on the form of the impugned State law than on its substance. Therefore, this principle cannot be seen as a necessary implication from the federal structure of the Constitution; nor does it have any foundation in the text of the Constitution. A distinction based on form? The distinction between the capacities of the Commonwealth and their exercise has been widely criticised as both unclear and unprincipled.112 It is the latter criticism that I will focus on, because this is directly relevant to the question of whether the doctrine emerging from Residential Tenancies could be said to be a necessary implication from the Constitution. In his judgment in Residential Tenancies, McHugh J was highly critical of the distinction drawn by the majority: The executive capacity of the Commonwealth can only mean its legal right or power to do or refrain from doing something. I cannot see any constitutional rationale for a doctrine that would hold, for example, that the States cannot prevent the Commonwealth from entering into a specific class of contract but can alter the legal rights and obligations of the Commonwealth … once they have entered into a contract of that class.113 McHugh J's example illustrates the way in which the immunity recognised in Residential Tenancies is concerned not with the substantive effect of a State law on the Commonwealth, but with what is essentially a question of the form of the State law. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 111 Ibid 187. 112 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 454 (McHugh J), 472 (Gummow J), 504–505 (Kirby J); Gladman, above n 7, 158–159; Zines, above n 47, 91–92; Bradley Selway, 'The Nature of the Commonwealth: A Comment' (1998) 20 Adelaide Law Review 95, 99; Dennis Rose, 'The Nature of the Commonwealth: A Comment' (1998) 20 Adelaide Law Review 101, 105; Mescher, above n 2, 40. 113 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 454–455. 166 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ In recent years, the Court has placed great emphasis on the examination of the substance rather than the form of a constitutionally impugned law.114 As Gaudron J stated in Street v Queensland Bar Association, 'it is now accepted that in the interpretation … of the Constitution, particularly its guarantees of freedom and the prohibitions by which those freedoms are secured, regard should be had to substance rather than form.'115 In its interpretation of Sections 117, 90 and 92, the Court has rejected tests which focus on the legal criterion of the operation of an impugned law rather than the practical effect of the law.116 Yet by focusing on the technical question of whether a law falls on a Commonwealth capacity, or on its exercise, the majority in Residential Tenancies have proposed a test whose focus is essentially on the legal criterion of the State law. This question of substance and form has, largely, been addressed by the Court in the context of interpreting express limitations on power contained in the Constitution, rather than implied limits. I would argue, though, that an immunity based more on form than on substance cannot be accepted under the Court's approach to drawing constitutional implications. Since an implied limitation is derived only where it is necessary to protect a structural feature of the Constitution, the implication must operate to render void a law which, in substance, operates in such a way as to threaten that structural feature. If the question was one of form, this would, in all likelihood lead to some laws which did not actually threaten that structural feature being declared invalid, and vice versa. The way in which an implied limit on power based largely on form fails as a necessary implication can be seen through a closer examination of the reasoning of Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ in Residential Tenancies. In their joint judgment, their Honours state that the fundamental principle lying behind the capacities distinction, is that which was recognised in Melbourne Corporation, namely the principle that 'the Constitution is predicated upon the continued separate existence of the Commonwealth and the States, not only in name, but as bodies politic to which the Constitution proceeds to distribute powers of government.'117 Since this same principle also forms the basis of the state immunity recognised in Melbourne Corporation,118 we might ask how it is that this federal principle requires that the Commonwealth possess a wider immunity than the States. Although there is a similarity between the two doctrines – for instance, both would operate to render invalid a law discriminating against the other federal entity119 – the Commonwealth immunity is broader. A clear example of a law which would fail under the Residential Tenancies test, and be valid under the Queensland Electricity Commission test, is a law affecting the prerogatives of the Crown.120 How can these two different formulations _____________________________________________________________________________________ 114 Mason, above n 101, 244–245; Zines, above n 62, 444–449. 115 Ibid 569. See also Cole v Whitfield (1988) 165 CLR 360, 383, 401. 116 Street v Queensland Bar Association (1989) 168 CLR 461, 569; Ngo Ngo Ha v New South Wales (1997) 189 CLR 465, 498 (Brennan CJ, McHugh, Gummow and Kirby JJ), 514 (Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ); Cole v Whitfield (1988) 165 CLR 360, 383, 401. 117 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 440. 118 (1947) 74 CLR 31, 82 (Dixon J). 119 Queensland Electricity Commission (1985) 159 CLR 192, 217; Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 443. 120 Compare Cigamatic (1962) 108 CLR 372 with Victoria v Australian Building Construction Employees' and Builders Labourers' Federation (1982) 152 CLR 25, 93 where Mason J stated 2001 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication 167 ____________________________________________________________________________________ both be said to be necessary for the maintenance of the same feature? Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron JJ justified the derivation of these two principles from the same source on the basis of Sir Owen Dixon's argument about the effect of enumerated powers as against residual powers.121 This argument does not, though, apply in the context of determining whether an implication is necessary. The fact that the Commonwealth has enumerated powers does not increase its need for a different and broader protection than that of the States. Of these two forms of immunity, that recognised by the Court in Melbourne Corporation and Queensland Electricity Commission seems to be more appropriately designed to maintain the continued existence of a body politic, or in other words, to be necessary for the preservation of the federal structure provided for by the Constitution, since it is a distinction of substance rather than of form.122 The second branch of the Melbourne Corporation principle, in particular, clearly focuses on the substantive effect of the law, and thus operates to ensure that only laws which actually threaten the continued existence of the polity are struck down by the Court.123 In contrast, by focusing on the question of whether the State law impairs a capacity of the Crown in right of the Commonwealth, it is likely that the Commonwealth immunity will be broader than what is necessarily required by the Melbourne Corporation principle.124 For example, it is difficult to see how the law struck down in Cigamatic could be said to have threatened the continued existence of the Commonwealth as an independent entity. A textual basis for the immunity? Brennan CJ was the only judge in support of the majority distinction in Residential Tenancies to suggest a possible textual basis for the Commonwealth immunity from State law. His Honour considered that the 'capacities and functions' of the Crown in right of the Commonwealth are the 'rights, powers, privileges and immunities' which are described as the 'executive power of the Commonwealth' in Section 61 of the Constitution. Brennan CJ noted that there are two possible sources of this Commonwealth executive power – a Commonwealth statute, and the power known as the royal prerogative. While the executive power of the Commonwealth may be _____________________________________________________________________________________ 'there is no secure foundation for an implication that the Parliament's legislative powers cannot affect the prerogative in right of the States, and the weight of judicial opinion… is against it.' 121 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 440–441. 122 Although it has been argued that the recent application of this test in Re Australian Education Union; Ex Parte Victoria (1995) 184 CLR 188 goes beyond what is necessarily required by the structure of federalism. See Donaghue, above n 91, 162; see also Amelia Simpson, 'The Australian Education Union Case: A Quiet Revolution?' (1998) 7 Griffith Law Review 30. 123 As Michael Coper has observed, the discrimination limb of the principle is less clearly connected to the principle expressed in Melbourne Corporation. Michael Coper, Encounters With the Australian Constitution (1st ed, 1987) 191. In some cases, though, the concept of 'discrimination' has been applied in such a way that the substantive question of the effect of the law on the Commonwealth has been addressed – see Zines, above n 62, 326–328. 124 It may also be possible that the principle is too narrow – in the sense that it failed to cover a State law that did threaten the independence of the Commonwealth, although it is difficult to imagine such a law which was not also discriminatory. 168 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ modified by Commonwealth laws, 'it is beyond the legislative reach of the States.'125 His Honour went on to suggest that a State law which purports on its face to impose a burden on the Crown in right of the Commonwealth fails for one of two reasons. If the burden fell on the enjoyment of a Commonwealth prerogative power, the State law 'would be offensive to Section 61 of the Constitution'; if on the enjoyment of a statutory power, it would be inconsistent with the Commonwealth law conferring that power and hence invalid under Section 109.126 Brennan CJ did not elaborate on why it was that a State law burdening the enjoyment of the Commonwealth prerogative would be offensive to Section 61. In its terms, Section 61 does nothing more than confer the executive power of the Commonwealth on designated persons. The provision does not define the scope of that executive power, nor does it say anything about whether this executive power is to be subject to control by the States – as George Winterton has observed, Section 61 is in general 'remarkably ambiguous'.127 Of course, the States could not exercise the executive power of the Commonwealth, because Section 61 expressly confers that power on the Governor-General. But this does not explain why the States cannot legislate to regulate and even to modify the Executive power of the Commonwealth, provided that such a law is for the 'peace, order and good government' of the State. What Brennan CJ might have been suggesting is that an ability of the States to regulate the capacities of the Commonwealth Executive would amount to an ability to detract from what Section 61 of the Constitution confers. However, this analysis simply assumes, without any kind of justification, that the Constitution confers a power which cannot be detracted from by State laws. The reasoning is circular – Section 61 cannot simply be read to endorse a particular view of intergovernmental relations. Although it might be argued that such an inability to detract from the grant of Executive power is a necessary implication from the Constitution, this is not what Brennan CJ seems to be suggesting, and such an argument would in any case encounter the criticisms directed at this distinction above. It is much easier to see how Section 109 would operate to render a State law burdening the Commonwealth Executive invalid. However, Brennan CJ's suggestion that such a State law would necessarily be inconsistent with the Commonwealth law conferring the executive power is difficult to accept. The Commonwealth and State laws in question would need to be analysed in order to determine whether there was some inconsistency between them. It is possible that a Commonwealth law might actually provide that it was not intended to limit the operation of a State law.128 So, although Section 109 may often invalidate a State law burdening the capacities of the Commonwealth Executive, it does not provide a textual basis for an immunity in all cases involving such a State law. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 125 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 424. 126 Ibid 426. 127 George Winterton, Parliament, The Executive and the Governor General (1983) 27. 128 R v Credit Tribunal; Ex Parte General Motors Acceptance Corp Australia (1977) 137 CLR 545. The limits of the Commonwealth's ability to prevent a State law being inconsistent with a Commonwealth law were outlined in University of Wollongong v Metwally (1984) 158 CLR 447. 2001 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication 169 ____________________________________________________________________________________ PART IV: A RECONSIDERATION OF COMMONWEALTH IMMUNITY Having suggested that the Cigamatic principle, as interpreted in Residential Tenancies, should no longer be accepted by the Court as the basis for Commonwealth immunity, in this section I will consider what principle the Court should adopt. A number of approaches have been suggested over the years, most of them involving a particular interpretation of the Cigamatic principle.129 By contrast, Kirby J in Residential Tenancies argued for a reciprocal application of the Melbourne Corporation principle to the Commonwealth.130 I do not propose to consider these forms of immunity individually, but rather, in the remainder of this article, to focus on an issue that is fundamental to the question of whether there should be any form of implied Commonwealth immunity at all, that is the effect of Section 109 of the Constitution. I will argue that the operation of Section 109 renders an implication of Commonwealth immunity unnecessary. As Kirby J suggested in Residential Tenancies, 'the provision in the Constitution of a power to make laws which will override any provision of an inconsistent State law removes the necessity to imply an immunity where none is expressed.'131 A number of academic commentators have taken a similar view.132 Before the decision in Cigamatic, there was a considerable amount of support for the idea that Section 109 removed the need for a doctrine of Commonwealth immunity. In rejecting a reciprocal application of the Melbourne Corporation principle to the Commonwealth in Uther, Latham CJ argued that as Section 109 places a means of protection in the hands of the Commonwealth, there is no need to invoke any principle of non interference with governmental functions.133 The Commonwealth, which is surely capable of judging its own best interests, can legislate so as to override any State law which might involve such interference.134 It is clear that in the period between the decision in Engineers and that in Cigamatic, the Court interpreted Engineers as requiring that the Commonwealth was bound by a State law unless there was an inconsistency between that law and a valid Commonwealth law. Thus, in Pirrie v McFarlane, the majority held that the fact that the State law in question operated on the Commonwealth defence forces was irrelevant unless there was an inconsistent Federal law, and a similar decision was reached by the majority in West when considering a State income tax law.135 The following sections will address a number of issues – first, whether either constitutional or practical constraints limit the ability of the Commonwealth to protect _____________________________________________________________________________________ 129 See, eg, Evans, above n 2, 547–557; Dixon, above n 2, 18–30; Howard, above n 2, 58. 130 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 507–508. See also Doyle, above n 2, 69–70; Colin McNairn, Governmental and Intergovernmental Immunity in Australia and Canada (2nd ed, 1978) 38; Mescher, above n 2, 41. 131 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 504. 132 Zines, above n 47, 95; Zines, above n 62, 364; Gladman, above n 7, 160, 163; Sawer, above n 1, 203–204; Geoffrey Sawer, 'Implication and the Constitution: Pt II' (1948–1950) 4 Res Judicatae 85, 90; Sackville, above n 2, 45, 64; Coper, above n 123, 192–193. 133 Uther (1947) 74 CLR 508, 520–521. 134 Ibid. 135 Pirrie v McFarlane (1925) 36 CLR 170, 180–184 (Knox CJ), 212–214 (Higgins J), 225–229 (Starke J); West (1937) 56 CLR 657, 664–669 (Latham CJ), 676–677 (Starke J), 711–714 (McTiernan J). Cf West (1937) 56 CLR 657, 681 (Dixon J), 684 (Evatt J). 170 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ itself with the help of Section 109; and second, whether a constraint such as Section 109 is relevant in determining whether an implied immunity is 'necessary'. In determining this second issue, and in reaching a view as to whether Section 109 does operate to render an implied immunity unnecessary, I will draw on a related debate in the United States. I will argue that Section 109 does operate to render an implied limitation unnecessary. The Scope of Section 109 Constitutional Limitations There are few constitutional limits on the Commonwealth's ability to use Section 109 to confer immunity on the Executive. Since Section 109 will only apply to a valid Commonwealth law, the main question is whether the Commonwealth possesses sufficient legislative power to enable it to confer immunity on the Crown in right of the Commonwealth. If the Commonwealth legislature is seeking to protect the Commonwealth Executive or an agent of that executive from interference by State law it is difficult to see how the law could not be 'with respect to' a head of power. As Gibbs J noted in Victoria v Commonwealth and Hayden, 'the Executive cannot act in respect of a matter which falls entirely outside the legislative competence of the Commonwealth.'136 For this reason, it is clear that the Commonwealth possesses the power to legislate so as to control the Executive, or to alter its capacities.137 This same power would enable the Commonwealth legislature to confer immunity on the Executive. The way in which the Commonwealth possesses the legislative power to protect itself was illustrated by Latham CJ in Uther. His Honour noted that the Commonwealth would have had power under Section 51(ii) of the Constitution, the taxation power, to provide that Commonwealth taxes were to take priority over State taxes. The provision of the New South Wales legislation conferring priority for the State in the payment of debts would then be invalid to the extent of the inconsistency.138 We might also note that the Commonwealth would have had power under Section 51(xxxix), the incidental power, to enact a law stating that the Commonwealth's prerogative right to priority in debt was to prevail over all other rights, and this would also have had the same effect as the response suggested by Latham CJ. The significance of Section 109 as a means for the Commonwealth to protect itself against State law is enhanced by the broad interpretation given to the section. In particular, it is now clearly established that, consistently with the principle of dual _____________________________________________________________________________________ 136 Victoria v Commonwealth and Hayden (1975) 134 CLR 338, 379; see also 396 (Mason J), 406 (Jacobs J); Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410, 441; Brown v West (1990) 169 CLR 195, 202. 137 Under the incidental power in Section 51(xxxix) if not one of the other heads of power. See Zines, above n 62, 262–273; JE Richardson, 'The Executive Power of the Commonwealth', in Leslie Zines (ed), Commentaries on the Australian Constitution (1977) 55–56, 64–68. 138 Uther (1947) 74 CLR 508, 516. 2001 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication 171 ____________________________________________________________________________________ characterisation,139 a Commonwealth law can directly and expressly exclude the operation of a State law and remain within power.140 Practical Limitations It has been suggested that the Commonwealth's ability to pass overriding laws to confer immunity on the executive may in some cases be limited by practical circumstances.141 McHugh J has argued that the difficulties faced by the Commonwealth Parliament if the Cigamatic doctrine was overturned would be 'enormous.'142 Parliament may not be able to anticipate which of its activities will need protection, and will have to choose between continual monitoring of State legislation or a possibly harmful blanket exclusion of State laws.143 If Parliament does wish to confer immunity on the executive from a State law, it may not be able to respond sufficiently promptly, so that damage may be done before the overriding legislation is passed. In particular, there is the possibility that the Senate may block the legislation.144 I would argue that these claims of practical difficulty are exaggerated. These claims have greater force in the context in which they were initially developed – in the United States, where the practical problem posed to Congress in dealing with fifty states, many with highly diversified law, is more obvious than that posed in Australia.145 Section 64 of the Judiciary Act 1903 (Cth) has operated for nearly a century to remove the large part of the immunity conferred on the Executive by the Court without such dire consequences. This provision could continue to operate if the implied immunity was removed, so that the general position would remain that the Commonwealth was bound by State law. While it might be difficult, it would certainly not be impossible for the Commonwealth Parliament then to consider which of its activities it did want to be immune from the operation of State law. In future, the issue might become a relatively simple matter of parliamentary drafting. It has been suggested that one of the negative consequences of the Cigamatic doctrine was that it removed the incentive for the Commonwealth to state clearly its position of liability to State law;146 if such an incentive were restored it might reasonably be expected that the Commonwealth would respond according to its best interests. It may be true that the Senate could pose a real obstacle to the passage of legislation intended to override a State law or to provide the Commonwealth Executive with immunity. The suggestion that this gives rise to a need for an implied immunity, though, is based on an incorrect view of what 'the Commonwealth' is for the purposes _____________________________________________________________________________________ 139 Sawer, above n 1, 142; see also above n 64. 140 Wenn v Attorney-General (Vic) (1948) 77 CLR 84, 109–111 (Latham CJ), 120 (Dixon J); Botany Municipal Council v Federal Airports Corporation (1992) 175 CLR 453, 463–464; Western Australia v Commonwealth (1995) 183 CLR 373, 464–467 (Mason CJ, Brennan, Deane, Toohey, Gaudron and McHugh JJ). Contra West (1937) 56 CLR 657, 684 (Evatt J); Airlines of New South Wales Pty. Ltd. v NSW (No 2) ('Second Airlines Case') (1965) 113 CLR 54, 119 (Kitto J). This reasoning has not been more broadly adopted. 141 See generally Dixon, above n 2, 14. 142 Australian Postal Commission v Dao [1985] 3 NSWLR 565, 598. 143 Ibid. 144 Residential Tenancies (1997) 190 CLR 410 (Gummow J during argument). 145 Sawer, above n 2, 588–589. 146 Sackville, above n 2, 63; Cigamatic (1962) 108 CLR 372, 388 (Taylor J, dissenting). 172 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ of such an immunity. An implication would be derived from the system of federalism,147 and accordingly would be concerned with the protection of the polity of the Commonwealth, rather than with the Commonwealth Executive in particular. As Mason J observed in Queensland Electricity Commission, in relation to the implication of State immunity from Commonwealth law, the immunity protects legislatures as well as executive governments.148 The Commonwealth, in the appropriate sense, as a polity in the federal scheme, can protect itself by using Section 109, and the internal workings of the Commonwealth – such as a refusal by the Senate to pass an overriding law – is not a relevant consideration. Are Constraints Like Section 109 Relevant? Ultimately, the question of whether Section 109 provides the Commonwealth with sufficient protection to remove the need for an implied immunity cannot be answered without reference to a more fundamental question: is a factor such as the Commonwealth's ability to protect itself relevant in determining whether an implication of immunity is necessary? The reason that such a consideration might be seen to be irrelevant is that it is at least partly a political rather than a constitutional constraint. Whereas a provision like Section 114, by its presence in the Constitution, confers a particular form of immunity on the Commonwealth, without the Parliament needing to act at all, Section 109 can only be enforced by the Court where there is an overriding Commonwealth law. It might be thought that this form of protection, which I shall term a 'partly political' one, does not remove the need for an implied judicial limitation, it merely operates as a possible additional source of protection. The question of whether such partly political constraints are relevant in determining if there is a need for an implied limitation has not been directly considered by the Court. Mason CJ did indicate in Political Broadcasts that an implication 'must be logically or practically necessary for the preservation of the integrity of that structure'.149 His Honour's reference to practical necessity might suggest that a partly political constraint would be relevant, since at a practical level the protection provided by such a constraint may be just as effective as that provided by a provision such as Section 114. However, it is difficult to tell whether Mason CJ intended to suggest that an implication must be practically necessary; or that it can be either practically or logically necessary. No equivalent question was addressed by the Court in its consideration of the freedom of political communication.150 The question of the relevance of partly political constraints has, however, been closely examined in the United States, by the Supreme Court and by a range of academic commentators. An examination of the debate over this issue in the United States is helpful in considering both whether partly political constraints are relevant, _____________________________________________________________________________________ 147 See above at n 81. If the immunity was said to be derived from the national status of the Commonwealth, the same principle would apply. 148 Queensland Electricity Commission (1985) 159 CLR 192, 217. See also Koowarta v Bjelke Peterson (1982) 153 CLR 168, 216 (Stephen J). 149 Political Broadcasts (1992) 177 CLR 106, 135. 150 Perhaps because the only argument of this nature could have been that the system of representative government operated as a check on Parliament limiting freedom of political communication, and the whole point of the Court's reasoning was that representative government could not function properly without such a freedom. 2001 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication 173 ____________________________________________________________________________________ and in deciding whether the effect of such protection is to remove the need for an implied immunity. The Decision in Garcia v San Antonio Metropolitan Transit Authority151 In this 1985 decision, the Supreme Court greatly narrowed the scope of the previously established implied immunity of the States from the exercise of the Federal power over interstate commerce.152 A majority of the Court rejected the line of authority which had protected 'traditional government functions' from federal interference as 'unsound in principle and unworkable in practice'.153 The majority then proceeded with the more radical argument that any form of substantive immunity was unnecessary because state interests 'are more properly protected by procedural safeguards inherent in the structure of the federal system than by judicially created limitations on federal power.'154 These procedural safeguards, the Court explained, are provided by 'state participation in federal government action' – namely, the representation of States in the Senate – and more generally, by the fact that the President and the members of the House of Representatives are themselves residents of a particular State.155 The Relevance of Partly Political Constraints The Supreme Court in Garcia clearly accepted that what I have described as a partly political constraint was relevant in determining the need for an implied immunity. The ability of the States to protect themselves against federal laws that threatened their vital interests was based on a constitutional feature: the representation of the States in the Senate.156 But this protection depended on political factors as well if it was to be effective – for instance, the ability of the States to unite against a federal incursion on vital State functions. The decision in Garcia was, though, a controversial one and some of the criticisms amounted to a rejection of the Supreme Court's claim that these kinds of constraints were relevant in determining whether there was a need for judicial review. One critic argued that the decision in Garcia amounted to: the piecemeal repeal of judicial review. It also involves a double counting of what are in fact merely pre-judicial and post-judicial "safeguards" of the American constitutional plan, safeguards…merely additional to, and not in substitution of, substantive judicial review.157 A similar claim could be made in the Australian context if the Court was to find that Section 109 removes the need for an implication of Commonwealth immunity. It might be argued that the text and structure of the Constitution require that the Commonwealth possess at least some form of immunity, and the judiciary cannot _____________________________________________________________________________________ 151 469 US 528 (1985) ('Garcia'). 152 See generally Martha Field, 'Comment: Garcia v San Antonio Metropolitan Transit Authority: The Demise of a Misguided Doctrine' (1985) 99 Harvard Law Review 84. 153 Garcia 469 US 528, 546 (1985). This case overruled National League of Cities v Usery 426 US 833 (1976). 154 Ibid 552. 155 Ibid 556. 156 See Constitution of the United States, Article I, s 2, and s 3. 157 William Van Alstyne, 'Comment: The Second Death of Federalism' (1985) 83 Michigan Law Review 1709, 1724. 174 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ abdicate its role of interpreting the Constitution because the Commonwealth can possibly protect itself.158 Such a claim would, however, be based on a mistaken understanding of the role of judicial review under the Australian Constitution. As Stephen Gageler has argued, there is actually a stronger case for the High Court to take non-judicial constraints into account in interpreting the Constitution than there is for the United States Supreme Court.159 As the Court in Engineers recognised, the Australian Constitution in many respects relies on constraints arising from the operation of the system of representative and responsible government rather than on judicial protection.160 For instance, the Court argued that one of the consequences of the presence of representative and responsible government in the Constitution is that the powers granted to the Commonwealth are not to be read down or limited for fear of possible abuse.161 It is, therefore, consistent with the approach of the Court in Engineers to take a consideration like Section 109 into account when determining whether an implied protection is necessary. It may be thought that, in Melbourne Corporation, and the subsequent cases concerning the immunity of the States from Commonwealth laws, the Court rejected the specific suggestion in Engineers that Commonwealth power should not be subject to implied limitations.162 However, the decision should not be read as rejecting the broader emphasis on the importance of non judicial constraints in the Engineers decision. There was certainly no such suggestion in Melbourne Corporation, and in the more recent cases concerning implications, the Court has gone to great pains to emphasise its continued adherence to the general approach to constitutional interpretation laid down in Engineers.163 A recognition of partly political constraints as relevant to the question of 'necessity' would also be consistent with the underlying rationale of the Court's approach to constitutional implications. In Part II of this article, I suggested that the necessity test reflects a cautious and restrained approach to deriving implications from the Constitution that is demanded both by the accepted 'literalism' of the Court, and, more broadly, by the need to maintain the Court's legitimacy as the interpreter of the Constitution. These factors suggest that the concept of a necessary implication should be a narrow one, and should include all factors that can reasonably be considered to be relevant. This is not to suggest that an entirely political constraint should be considered to preclude the need for an implication of immunity. Consider, for instance, if the Commonwealth was said to derive protection from its ability to lobby State _____________________________________________________________________________________ 158 See generally David Meale, 'The History of the Federal Idea in Australian Constitutional Jurisprudence: A Reappraisal' (1992) 8 Australian Journal of Law and Society 25. 159 Stephen Gageler, 'Foundations of Australian Federalism and the Role of Judicial Review' (1987) 17 Federal Law Review 162. See also Sackville, above n 2. 160 Engineers (1920) 28 CLR 129, 146–147. As to the importance of representative and responsible government in the Constitution, see Lange (1997) 189 CLR 520, 557–559; Commonwealth v Kreglinger & Fernau Ltd (1926) 37 CLR 393, 411, 413 (Isaacs J); Commonwealth v Colonial Combing and Weaving Co Ltd ('The Wooltops Case') (1922) 31 CLR 421; Gageler, above n 160, 181–190; Sawer, above n 2, 585. 161 Engineers (1920) 28 CLR 129, 151–152; see also South Australia v Commonwealth ('First Uniform Tax Case') (1942) 65 CLR 373, 429 (Latham CJ). 162 Sawer, above n 74, 21–22. 163 See text above at n 95. 2001 Commonwealth Immunity as a Constitutional Implication 175 ____________________________________________________________________________________ parliaments not to pass laws which interfered with the Commonwealth in an undesirable way. This would be a purely political constraint, with no foundation in the Constitution, and one which the Court might find it difficult to accept as relevant to the question of constitutional interpretation.164 The protection provided by Section 109, though, is firmly grounded in the text of the Constitution, and is clearly apparent on a consideration of the possible effects of the section. Indeed, Geoffrey Sawer has suggested that the basic assumption of the framers of the Constitution was that 'the Senate [would] protect the States, and the Commonwealth [would] protect itself.'165 Why an implication of Commonwealth immunity is unnecessary I would argue that the presence of Section 109 in the Constitution removes any need for an implication of Commonwealth immunity. Although the protection provided to the Commonwealth by Section 109 is contingent on the Commonwealth passing a law to override any objectionable State law, and is therefore different to a protection such as that provided by Section 114, it should be understood as relevant to the question of whether an implied immunity is necessary. For the Court to acknowledge such a form of protection would be consistent with the emphasis in the Engineers decision on the importance of non judicial constraints within the Constitution, and with the element of caution inherent in the requirement that implications be 'necessary'. There are few constitutional limitations on the use of Section 109 by the Commonwealth to provide the Executive with immunity from the operation of State law, and I have argued that the practical difficulties that have been suggested are not significant. In particular, the suggestion that there would be difficulty in passing Commonwealth legislation seeking to confer immunity through the Senate is based on an incorrect view of what 'the Commonwealth' is for the purposes of an implied immunity. Certainly, the means of protection possessed by the Commonwealth are a great deal stronger than those possessed by the States under the United States Constitution and recognised in Garcia. The Commonwealth has the means of protection entirely in its own hands, whereas the protection of the States depends on their exercising their influence on the Federal Government.166 Given the ample capacity of the Commonwealth to protect itself from any State laws that might be thought to threaten the vital interests or continued functioning of the Commonwealth Executive, it cannot be said that an implied immunity is necessary. CONCLUSION In this article, I have argued that a principle of Commonwealth immunity must be based on an implication rather than a lack of State power. The Court has authoritatively determined that implications can only be drawn as necessary with _____________________________________________________________________________________ 164 It would be difficult for the Court even to evaluate the factual evidence as to such a form of protection. See generally Andrew Bell, 'Section 92, Factual Discrimination and the High Court' (1991) 20 Federal Law Review 240. It is notable that in the Garcia decision, there was extensive discussion of evidence concerning the ability of the States to protect themselves. 165 Sawer, above n 132, 90. 166 Much of the criticism of the Garcia decision has been based on the argument that the methods of protection for the State relied on by the majority in Garcia are in fact inadequate. See, eg, John Yoo, 'The Judicial Safeguards of Federalism' (1997) 70 Southern California Law Review 1311. 176 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ regard to the text and structure of the Constitution. I have argued that the current doctrine of Commonwealth immunity, as established in Residential Tenancies, cannot be supported on this basis. Furthermore, since the effect of Section 109 is that the Commonwealth can protect itself against objectionable State laws, it cannot be said that any principle of Commonwealth immunity is necessarily implied by the Constitution. A number of benefits would follow from the absence of a judicially implied Commonwealth immunity. A position where Commonwealth immunity depended on express provision by the Parliament would have a distinct advantage in terms of certainty and clarity, as compared to an implied immunity. The history of previous attempts to define the scope of such an immunity would suggest that such an immunity is likely to be of uncertain application.167 In addition, the Court would not be required to undertake the sort of difficult task which it faces in regard to the implied freedom of political communication – forming a view as to the sort of federalism established by the Constitution in order to give content to the implication. This argument has largely focused on the approach that the Court should adopt to the issue of Commonwealth immunity, consistent with its own interpretative principles. In concluding, though, I make some observations on the more speculative question of whether the Court would in fact accept this approach. The most obvious obstacle is that of precedent.168 Adrienne Stone has suggested that while, in the wake of Lange, the Court may generally require that constitutional implications be firmly grounded in the Constitution, there may be an exception for well established precedents.169 The precedential power of the Cigamatic doctrine is, doubtless, increased by the fact that its main author was Sir Owen Dixon, a widely revered judge.170 The approach of the majority in Residential Tenancies suggests that the Court would prefer to attempt to follow established precedents than to reconsider the question of Commonwealth immunity from principle. This is slightly ironic, given that the Cigamatic doctrine is itself founded on a rejection of an earlier precedent. The decisions that preceded Cigamatic in fact support the position advocated in this article, that there should be no implied protection for the Commonwealth from State law.171 Sir Owen Dixon justified the reversal of the decision in Uther on the grounds that it was based on a 'fundamental error in a constitutional principle'.172 I would suggest that it is the Court's current approach to Commonwealth immunity from State law that is based on a fundamental error, and for this reason it should be overturned. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 167 See above n 112. 168 Cole v Whitfield (1990) 165 CLR 360 is the only case in which the Court has engaged in a comparable overhaul of an entire doctrine, although the elimination of the exceptions to the general interpretation of Section 90 in Ngo Ngo Ha v New South Wales (1997) 189 CLR 465 should also be noted. 169 Adrienne Stone, 'Lange, Levy and the Direction of the Freedom of Political Communication' (1998) 21 University of New South Wales Law Journal 117, 133. 170 See Australian Postal Commission v Dao [1985] 3 NSWLR 565, 598 (McHugh J). 171 See text at nn 133 to 135 above. 172 Cigamatic (1962) 108 CLR 372, 377. POLITICAL DONATIONS BY AUSTRALIAN COMPANIES IAN RAMSAY,* GEOF STAPLEDON,** JOEL VERNON*** I. INTRODUCTION The subject of corporate political donations is highly topical in several countries. The Australian Democrats have called for greater disclosure of donations made by companies to political parties, and for the introduction of a shareholder-approval rule where the donor is a public company. According to Democrat Senator Andrew Murray, 'ever since the first political donation changed hands, money has been used to influence electoral outcomes and the process of government'.1 The problems potentially associated with political donations are probably as old as democracy itself. Where the institution of democracy is coupled with and gives its imprimatur to relatively free market economics, the market for votes takes on characteristics not unlike those of the markets for goods and services.2 Free commerce and free elections give rise to the possibility of political exploitation and manipulation. Where political power depends on commercial attractiveness, commercial interests can be advanced by contributing funds to those political interests which promise the best commercial returns. Consequently, allegations of wealthy citizens – corporate or otherwise – buying political influence are not uncommon where their capacity to donate to political parties (and the parties' correspondent capacity to accept) is relatively unhindered. _____________________________________________________________________________________ * Harold Ford Professor of Commercial Law; Director, Centre for Corporate Law and Securities Regulation, The University of Melbourne. ** Associate Professor and Reader, Law School, The University of Melbourne; Deputy Director, Centre for Corporate Law and Securities Regulation; Principal, Institutional Analysis. *** Research Associate, Centre for Corporate Law and Securities Regulation, The University of Melbourne; Associate to the Honourable Justice Mandie, Supreme Court of Victoria. 1 Australian Democrats, Open the Books – Call for Political Donations Transparency, Press Release, No 00/19 (20 January 2000). See also 'The Invisible World of Political Donations', Australian Financial Review (Sydney), 20 April 2001, 1. 2 Geoff Gallop, 'From Government in Business to Business in Government' (1997) 83 Canberra Bulletin of Public Affairs 81, 85: [T]he development of a market for government functions creates a market for government favours. Influence has the potential to become a commodity in ways unknown to a more traditional balance between public and private sectors. The reason for this is simple – government contracts have become a major part of the balance sheets of many private [sector] corporations. 180 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ This article examines donations to political parties made by companies.3 While donations by individuals are also worthy of analysis, the tendency for commercial power to vest increasingly in corporations highlights the importance of an analysis from a corporate perspective. In a competitive environment, companies can be expected jealously to guard their spending. Consequently, it is not unreasonable to suspect that, when companies make donations (political or otherwise), they do so for reasons other than mere generosity.4 As Fisch has asked: 'if corporations exist to maximise profits, and donations reduce profits, why do corporations donate money to charity?'5 Green has similarly asked: [W]hy do these non-human entities – business corporations – give to charity and how can such philanthropy be reconciled with the most basic aspect of a business corporation, ie: the object of making money for its investors?6 While both political donations and charitable donations are worthy of analysis, political donations present interesting issues of corporate governance, which justify distinguishing them. Whereas charitable donations might, at best, only indirectly benefit the donor, the political donation is likely to confer a more direct benefit because, in Australia, political parties form governments which can then, colloquially speaking, return the favour. The Fitzgerald Inquiry into corruption in Queensland in the 1980s noted that: Practices which were adopted with respect to donations included a propensity to accept large sums in cash, not infrequently from those who had benefited, or hoped to benefit from dealings with the Government… [T]here were other occasions when persons or organizations engaged in business with the Government or seeking business from it, made substantial donations to its political party.7 A link between corporate donations and political leverage has also been suggested by Gallop,8 who surmises that the underlying political economy determines the size and nature of corporate political donations. Citing the example of the Labor Government in Western Australia in the 1980s, and commencing with the proposition that that Government saw its role as one of support for business, Gallop inferred that _____________________________________________________________________________________ 3 Of principal interest are public companies – especially those with a widely held shareholder base. Most of these companies are listed on the stock exchange. The reason why widely held public companies are the focus of attention is that agency costs are much more likely to accompany the making of political donations by these companies compared to closely held companies (see Section III for discussion of agency costs). Nevertheless, for comparative purposes, this article examines data for both public and proprietary companies. 4 Jill E Fisch, 'Questioning Philanthropy from a Corporate Governance Perspective' (1997) 41 New York Law School Law Review 1091, 1101-2. 5 Ibid 1094, citing Nancy J Knauer, 'The Paradox of Corporate Giving: Tax Expenditures, the Nature of the Corporation, and the Social Construction of Charity' (1994) 44 DePaul Law Review 1, 4. 6 Shelby D Green, 'Corporate Philanthropy and the Business Benefit: The Need for Clarity' (1990) 20 Golden Gate University Law Review 239, 240. 7 Commission of Inquiry into Possible Illegal Activities and Associated Police Misconduct: Report (1989) 86. 8 Gallop, above n 2. 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 181 ____________________________________________________________________________________ the Government had overplayed its hand in developing structures to promote business. What became known as 'WA Inc' took the Government into the world of business and commerce and led to the emergence of important relationships between particular entrepreneurs and the Government. …[A] type of system emerged in which support and money passed from the Government to business and, at the same time, healthy donations found their way into the coffers of the ALP. …What proved to be controversial and debatable about this system was the interpenetration of private and public interests. As the two sectors became linked, it was inevitable that questions would be asked about conflicts of interest and the potential for corruption, of process if not of persons.9 In the 1990s, according to Gallop, the political landscape changed in response to the risks posed by the 1980s style of government. It seems that during the 1990s there was a change in perspective as government sought to distance itself as much as possible from business by privatising government business enterprises and contracting-out services. But similar problems emerged: [N]ew and powerful partnerships develop between government and business. Failure of government to renew contracts can become fatal and support from government, including ministers, becomes crucial. Although the theory has government in charge, the practice may very well see governments adjusting and responding to the needs of its private contractors, some of whom may be party benefactors.10 When companies make political donations they may expect to receive a sympathetic hearing on issues affecting them from the leaders of the political party and would hope for favourable treatment.11 Public choice theory may provide insights into not only such arguments but also the issue of corporate political donations more generally. Public choice theory views government and law-making as part of a market: On the demand side, legal rules are the outcome of political struggle among special interest groups to redistribute wealth in their favour, while on the supply side, they reflect the effort of politicians to maximise the political support they receive from interest groups' constituencies. That is, laws are supplied to those interest groups (or coalitions) that out-bid rivals for favourable legislation…On the supply side, the fee may take the form of campaign contributions.12 However, there are limits on the extent to which political influence can be purchased. Legislative decision-making is majoritarian and, in addition, 'there is as yet no consensus on the appropriate model of how money maps into votes'.13 This article begins by examining some of the more recent and topical responses to the phenomenon of corporate political donations. It then examines the motivations which apparently underpin corporate giving. While this is largely informed by American literature on charitable donations, some peculiarly Australian differences are _____________________________________________________________________________________ 9 Ibid 81-2, referring to Royal Commission into Commercial Activities of Government and Other Matters: Report (1992). 10 Ibid 83. 11 Justin Fisher, 'Why Do Companies Make Donations to Political Parties?' (1994) 42 Political Studies 690. 12 Neil Gunningham, 'Public Choice: The Economic Analysis of Public Law' (1992) 21 Federal Law Review 117, 124. 13 David Austen-Smith, 'Interest Groups: Money, Information, and Influence' in Dennis Mueller (ed), Perspectives on Public Choice (1997), 320. 182 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ highlighted. Indeed, Australian law still requires that anything done with company funds be done for the benefit of the company;14 with respect to philanthropy, this requirement has been removed in many US states.15 The article then analyses the legal framework within which corporations may pursue philanthropy, which comprises corporate and electoral regulation, both under statute and at common law. This is followed by a presentation and analysis of the results of an empirical study of corporate donations to Australian political parties during the three years 1995/96 to 1997/98. The article concludes by outlining some options for law reform. II. TOPICALITY A. United Kingdom In 1985, a UK working party established by the Constitutional Reform Centre and the Hansard Society for Parliamentary Government recommended that 'companies should consider their political donation policy seriously and seek the consent of shareholders to political giving'.16 The working party believed that a decision to give to a political party is a decision 'distinct in kind from other decisions of management and requires special validation'.17 Noting that 'it would be illiberal and ineffective to prevent company donations',18 the working party recommended a voluntary code of conduct for companies with respect to political donations. Under the code, companies would be required to disclose to their shareholders why a donation was in the company's best interests and to obtain shareholder approval for political donations at the company's annual general meeting at least once during the life of a Parliament.19 The editorial in Business Law Review noted that the working party's recommendations were 'eminently sensible. But they really do little more than scratch the surface of a very deep malaise. … the time has come for more radical solutions'.20 Those more radical solutions have been over a decade in the making. In late 1997, the UK Prime Minister extended the terms of reference of the Committee on Standards in Public Life (Neill Committee) to encompass a study of political party funding in the UK. The Neill Committee's report to the Prime Minister21 reflected an 'increasing concern by both the public and shareholders that many corporate political donations appear to reflect the directors' personal political affiliations rather [than] the interests _____________________________________________________________________________________ 14 Hutton v West Cork Railway Co (1883) 23 Ch D 654 ('Hutton'). The case is discussed in Section III below. 15 Faith Kahn, 'Pandora's Box: Managerial Discretion and the Problem of Corporate Philanthropy' (1997) 44 University of California of Los Angeles Law Review 579, 583-4, 602-3 and notes thereto, 604-5. See the discussion in Section III below. 16 'Report Urges Democratic Control of Company Political Donations' (1985) 6 Company Lawyer 196. 17 Edmund Dell, Company Donations to Political Parties: A Suggested Code of Practice, cited in (1985) 6 Company Lawyer 196. 18 Ibid; 'Political Donations' (editorial) (1985) 6(10) Business Law Review 269. 19 Dell, above n 17. 20 'Political Donations' above n 18. 21 Committee on Standards in Public Life (Lord Neill of Bladen, chair) (Neill Committee), The Funding of Political Parties in the United Kingdom, (1998) Cm 4057-I (Neill Report). 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 183 ____________________________________________________________________________________ of the company'.22 In March 1999, the UK Department of Trade and Industry (DTI) issued a consultative document titled Political Donations by Companies.23 In the same vein as the Neill Report, the DTI paper observed: In recent years there has been growing concern about directors' accountability to shareholders in relation to political donations by companies. This concern is due in part to the scope for conflict between a director's personal wishes or interests and his [or her] duty to the company. Moreover, the Companies Act, by requiring all donations in excess of £200 to be declared in the directors' report and the recipients identified, already recognises that even small political donations may cause justifiable concern to shareholders and cannot be treated as routine business expenditure. The very low threshold for disclosure suggests that the key issue is not whether the sums are material to the company's finances but whether the donation is in the company's interest.24 In the DTI paper, the UK government accepted the recommendations in the Neill Report that companies should be required to obtain prior shareholder approval to make any type of donation or provide any form of financial benefit to a political party or organisation.25 The government also indicated its intention to amend the Companies Act 1985 (UK) to require companies to disclose annually in the directors' report all forms of financial benefit – direct or indirect – to political parties. 26 These proposals have been enacted as ss 139 and 140 of the Political Parties, Elections and Referendums Act 2000 (UK). In addition, the UK government sought comments on the possibility of requiring a director to disclose in the directors' report any connection with a political party that might give rise either to a conflict of interest or to the perception of a conflict of interest.27 The motivation for a shareholder approval requirement seems to stem from a recognition that shareholders can often do little to rectify conflicts of interest, especially after they have become apparent.28 The suggestion seems to be that, due to the limited avenues of redress, the least that can be done (and at relatively low cost) is to require companies to make prior disclosure so that shareholders at least have the opportunity to make an informed decision when exercising their voting rights,29 and even in evaluating their investment decision before they agree to become shareholders. These and other reforms are evaluated more fully later in this article. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 22 Department of Trade and Industry, Political Donations by Companies: A Consultative Document (1999) (URN 99/757; http://www.dti.gov.uk/cld/condocs.htm), 3 (Foreword by Stephen Byers, Secretary of State for Trade and Industry). 23 Ibid. 24 Ibid para 1.2. 25 Ibid paras 2.6, 3.7, 4.18; Neill Report, above n 21, Recommendation 34. 26 Department of Trade and Industry, Political Donations by Companies: A Consultative Document (1999) (URN 99/757; "http://www.dti.gov.uk/cld/condocs.htm "), paras 2.6, 5.9. 27 Ibid para 5.10. 28 Neill Report, above n 21, para 6.29. 29 Ibid para 6.35. 184 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ B. Australia In Australia, there is no single legislative provision governing corporate political donations.30 The Corporations Act 2001 (Cth) (Corporations Act) contains no provision dealing expressly with donations, although s 19(a) of the old 'uniform' Companies Acts gave companies power 'to make donations for patriotic or for charitable purposes'.31 The legal regime currently applying to corporate political donations in Australia is discussed in detail in Section IV below. The remainder of this section outlines reform proposals that have been made in Australia recently. 1. Current Bill There is currently before the Commonwealth Parliament the Taxation Laws Amendment (Political Donations) Bill 1999. This Bill was reintroduced after lapsing at the last prorogation of the Parliament on the calling of the 1998 election. The purpose of the Bill is to amend the Income Tax Assessment Act 1997 (Cth): • to increase the current deductibility limit for donations from $100 per annum to $1,500 per annum; and • to extend deductibility to corporations.32 The Explanatory Memorandum to the Bill infers that it is desirable that companies now have access to a deductibility regime for political donations.33 The Bill was introduced in response to a report by the Joint Standing Committee on Electoral Matters (JSCEM) on the 1996 federal election.34 The Digest to the Bill explains that the Liberal Party proposed a deductibility limit of $10,000, while the ALP submitted that the limit should be $1,500. Both parties, it seems, were prepared to endorse the following view of the JSCEM: _____________________________________________________________________________________ 30 For discussion of the history of the regulation of political campaign financing in Australia, see Deborah Cass and Sonia Burrows, 'Commonwealth Regulation of Campaign Finance – Public Funding, Disclosure and Expenditure Limits' (2000) 22 Sydney Law Review 477. 31 See, eg, Companies Act 1961 (Vic), s 19(a). 32 The Bill will insert a new subdivision 30-DA in the Income Tax Assessment Act 1997 (Cth); the new s 30-243 will provide for the $1,500 deductibility limit. The current provisions dealing with deductibility of political donations are: Income Tax Assessment Act 1997 (Cth), s 30-15; Income Tax Assessment Act 1936 (Cth), ss 78(9) and (10). 33 Taxation Laws Amendment (Political Donations) Bill 1999 – Explanatory Memorandum, paras 1.36, 1.38, 1.44. Interestingly, in the US deductions for political donations are no longer allowed. See Kahn, above n 15, 640-4, referring to the Revenue Reconciliation Act of 1993, which amended s 162(e) of the Internal Revenue Code to deny deductions: With the exception of expenses attributable to lobbying local government, the Revenue Reconciliation Act of 1993 eliminated the deduction for expenses incurred in direct attempts to influence legislation, expenses attributable to communicating with high federal executive office personnel (whether or not in connection with specific legislation), trade association dues attributable to state and federal lobbying, and grass roots lobbying expenses. Ibid, 644. 34 JSCEM, The 1996 Federal Election: Report of the Inquiry into all Aspects of the Conduct of the 1996 Federal Election and Matters Related Thereto (1997). 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 185 ____________________________________________________________________________________ An increase in the maximum deduction would encourage small to medium donations, thereby increasing the number of Australians involved in the democratic process and decreasing the parties' reliance on a smaller number of large donations.35 However, the findings presented later in this article do not reveal any need to increase the number of small and medium donations – at least as far as corporate donations are concerned. Our empirical study shows that there are already significant numbers of these smaller donations (particularly from corporations). Therefore, the absence of a significant deductibility regime appears not to have been an impediment to corporate political philanthropy. Indeed, the Digest to the Bill notes that deductibility probably makes no difference to the decision to donate. Perhaps the raising of the deductibility limit and its extension to corporations is intended to encourage current donors to maintain (or even increase) their levels of giving. 2. Wider concerns The Australian Financial Review reported in a February 1999 editorial that 'the release of the latest political donations by the Australian Electoral Commission has once again highlighted the major deficiencies that exist in our funding disclosure law'.36 Specifically, the concern was with political parties which relied on 'associated entities' to make donations en masse on behalf of benefactors who wished to remain anonymous. The issue raised in the editorial is one of transparency, both in terms of representative government in a democracy and in terms of shareholder dominion in widely held companies. The underlying concern is that corporate donors wishing to remain anonymous do so either because they wish to avoid the perception that they are buying government influence, or because they wish to avoid alerting their shareholders that they are giving away company property, particularly where the gift is of doubtful benefit to the company's shareholders. 3. The Australian Democrats' proposals In 2000 the Australian Democrats' Accountability spokesperson, Senator Andrew Murray, outlined reform proposals: • to require shareholder approval of 'donation policies' of public companies; and • to require 'full donations disclosure' in a public company's annual report.37 The proposals are in line with the recent UK changes discussed above. The second proposal is unsurprising given that a major Australian bank – a publicly listed company – forgave a large loan (overdraft balance) to an Australian political party after the 1996 federal election, without disclosure. The nature of the financial benefit (forgiving a loan) meant that no disclosure was considered necessary under the rules in the Commonwealth Electoral Act 1918 (Cth).38 However, for a financial benefit of this magnitude to be given to a political party without any form of disclosure certainly _____________________________________________________________________________________ 35 Ibid 103. 36 'Donations Law Needs Overhaul', Australian Financial Review, (Sydney), 6-7 February 1999, 20. See also Editorial, 'Tightening Up Donations', Australian Financial Review, (Sydney), 27 April 2001, 82. 37 Australian Democrats, above n 1. 38 Disclosure was made at a later stage, after an Electoral Commission audit: see below n 120. 186 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ appears contrary to the spirit of the Commonwealth Electoral Act. An appropriately drafted disclosure rule would catch this kind of financial benefit. 4. Senator Brown's proposal Australian Greens Senator for Tasmania, Bob Brown, has recently referred to corporate political donations as 'a growing wave of corporate largesse that is eating at the fabric of [Australia's] democracy [and] a cancer that must be cut out'.39 Senator Brown has recommended that: • corporate donations to political parties should be banned; and • donations should instead be diverted into a 'Democracy Trust Fund' to be distributed to political parties according to their relative electoral success.40 We return to options for law reform in Section VI below. The article now examines what motivates companies to donate corporate funds to political parties. III. MOTIVATIONS FOR GIVING The use of corporate funds for philanthropic purposes is, in some circumstances, an agency cost of running a company. The concept of agency costs in the corporate context goes back at least as far as Adam Smith.41 Agency costs arise where a party (the shareholders of a company) appoints another party (the directors) to be its delegate or agent in a particular transaction or series of transactions (overseeing the management of the company's business). As Berle and Means observed in relation to the typical widely held US company 70 years ago: In the corporate system, the 'owner' of industrial wealth is left with a mere symbol of ownership while the power, the responsibility and the substance which have been an integral part of ownership in the past are being transferred to a separate group in whose hands lies control.42 Agency costs arise where the interests of the principal and the agent (or shareholders and directors) diverge: As residual claimants on the firm's income stream, shareholders want their agents – the firm's managers – to maximize wealth. Because managers cannot capture all of the gains if they are successful, and will not suffer all of the losses should the venture flop, they have less incentive to maximize wealth than if they themselves were the principals. Rather, managers have an incentive to consume excess leisure, perquisites and in general be less dedicated to the goal of wealth maximization than they would if they were not simply agents.43 When managers use company funds other than in the direct course of the company's business, there may be a divergence of interests between ownership and management: _____________________________________________________________________________________ 39 Bob Brown MP, Corporate Donations are a Cancer on Australian Politics, Press Release, 14 April 2000. 40 Ibid. 41 Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations (1937) (first published, 1776) 699-700. 42 Adolf E Berle Jr and Gardiner C Means, The Modern Corporation and Private Property (1932[0]) 68. 43 Daniel R Fischel, 'The Corporate Governance Movement' (1982) 35 Vanderbilt Law Review 1259, 1262-3. 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 187 ____________________________________________________________________________________ [I]t is plain that where corporate managers approve [donations] as a means of furthering their personal objectives, such contributions represent a species of agency costs, and are inconsistent with the essential fiduciary fabric of corporate law.44 A key aim of corporate governance mechanisms is to minimise the divergences between owners' and managers' interests, and hence minimise agency costs.45 On the other hand, as discussed below, a corporate donation may be approved by directors/managers with a view to increasing shareholder wealth.46 In this situation there is no agency cost problem in the traditional sense, although – depending on the circumstances – there may be other legal issues to contend with. Therefore, whether a donation gives rise to agency costs depends largely on its motive, a question we now turn to examine. A. Altruism US companies are more or less prohibited from making overt political contributions.47 It is thought that 'unrestrained corporate campaign spending would pose a substantial threat to the democratic political process, and create at least the appearance of unseemly political quid pro quos'.48 However, this has not prevented US corporations from 'pursuing political objectives through technically philanthropic contributions, [so as to] lawfully avoid the limitations and disincentives pertaining to traditional corporate political advocacy'.49 The ability of US companies to support political parties in this indirect manner is bolstered by the absence of a 'benefit-to-the-company' test for corporate philanthropy (at least in many states). The position in many US states 'accords substantial deference to management's judgment. The fact that a perceived benefit is intangible, non-economic, or uncertain will not invalidate a corporate expenditure'.50 The 'benefit-to-the-business' test (under which a use of corporate funds is valid only if it benefits the company, at least indirectly) seems to have been abrogated by statute in several states. An example is the Californian Corporation Code, s 207(e), which provides authority for charitable donations 'regardless of specific corporate benefit'. Other states limit corporate philanthropy by still adhering to the benefit-to-the-business test, while a large number of states allow corporate contributions for wider purposes either without imposing any express _____________________________________________________________________________________ 44 Kahn, above n 15, 610 (emphasis added). 45 An interesting question, at least for American corporate governance scholars, is the extent to which agency costs arising in this area can be minimised in a jurisdiction whose statutory regime unreservedly confers on company controllers the power to make donations: '[i]n affording them full decisional authority in regard to corporate contributions, these laws have conferred extraordinary power and discretion on corporate managers': Kahn, ibid, 603-4 (notes omitted). 46 See Section IIIE below. 47 Federal Election Campaign Act of 1971, 2 USC 431-455 (1994). See Kahn, above n 15, notes 24663 and accompanying text. 48 Kahn, ibid, 642. 49 Ibid 640-1. 50 Fisch, above n 4, 1096, referring to Levine v Smith 591 A 2d 194, 207 (Del. 1991), and the US common law business judgment rule, which creates a presumption of validity for business decisions made by directors where they act without self-interest, on an informed basis, in good faith and in the honest belief that the action taken was in the best interests of the company. 188 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ limitations or without expressly waiving the benefit-to-the-business requirement.51 Accordingly, in regard to corporate charitable donations, US managers have considerable discretion to choose their beneficiaries, and are permitted to be altruistically motivated, so long as their largesse is not politically inclined. Nevertheless, as Abzug and Webb have observed, rarely are gifts made by US companies seen to be completely altruistic or completely in the interest of society; rather, they are often thought to be beneficial to others, but still in the interests of the corporation: Although possible, it is unlikely that corporate executives are completely altruistic. In addition to the benefit that society receives from a donation, the corporation nearly always benefits from the added goodwill it creates, even if the donation is not highly publicized.52 Australian corporate directors and managers are not permitted to be as altruistic as their US counterparts. In effect, what the Americans call the benefit-to-the-business test applies in Australia. As Bowen LJ stated in Hutton's case (an English decision): They can only spend money which is…the company's, if they are spending it for the purposes which are reasonably incidental to the carrying on of the business of the company. … The law does not say that there are to be no cakes and ale, but there are to be no cakes and ale except such as are required for the benefit of the company. … It is not charity sitting at the board of directors, because as it seems to me charity has no business to sit at boards of directors qua charity. There is, however, a kind of charitable dealing which is for the interest of those who practise it, and to that extent and in that garb (I admit not a very philanthropic garb) charity may sit at the board, but for no other purpose.53 Hutton was decided on corporate capacity grounds; the payment in question was alleged, and found, to have been made ultra vires (beyond the company's powers). In Parke v Daily News Ltd54 – a later English decision which applied Hutton – Plowman J based his judgment not only on the doctrine of ultra vires, but also on directors' duties grounds.55 Given the abolition of the ultra vires doctrine in Australia,56 the relevant legal doctrine is officers' duties – in particular, the general law duty of directors and senior executives to act in good faith in the interests of the company, and the duty of directors and other officers under s 181 of the Corporations Act to exercise their powers and discharge their duties in good faith in the best interests of the corporation. In summary, sheer altruism (however laudable) would not provide a sufficient legal basis for corporate giving in Australia. The likelihood of a corporate donation being motivated purely by altruism is, however, unlikely. Any political donation that is intended to benefit the company, even indirectly, cannot be charitable in the strict _____________________________________________________________________________________ 51 For an overview of the legal regulation of corporate charitable donations in the US, see R Franklin Balotti and James J Franks, 'Giving at the Office: A Reappraisal of Charitable Contributions by Corporations' (1999) 54 Business Lawyer 965. 52 Rikki Abzug and Natalie Webb, 'Rational and Extra-Rational Motivations for Corporate Giving: Complementing Economic Theory with Organization Science' (1997) 41 New York Law School Law Review 1035, 1038-9. 53 Hutton (1883) 23 Ch D 654, 671, 673. 54 [1962] Ch 927. 55 See K W Wedderburn, 'Ultra Vires or Directors' Bona Fides?' (1967) 30 Modern Law Review 566. 56 See Corporations Act 2001 (Cth), ss 124, 125. 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 189 ____________________________________________________________________________________ sense. It appears likely that altruism would often only be a co-motivation to other, more-tangible motivations. Before turning to profit-maximisation (shareholder benefit) as a motivation for corporate giving, we address several other possible motives. B. Management self-promotion or self-dealing As noted above, corporate donations (to charities or political parties) may involve agency costs. In some cases, corporate charitable donations may be 'a form of selfaggrandising or self-promoting behaviour by management'.57 Abzug and Webb speculate that '[m]anagers may give [company funds to charity] because they…enjoy the prestige associated with being a big giver. … "[B]usiness contributions…are attempts to acquire status, prestige, and goodwill for management and the firm"'.58 On the other hand, shareholders might take the view that a little philanthropic dealing by managers is indirectly good for the company. That is, if managers are pleased with the prestige that philanthropy attracts, there may in turn be a positive effect on the managers' productivity, and higher gains for shareholders.59 Turning from charitable donations to political donations, it is possible that political donations may be explained by managerial self-dealing.60 If a manager were to contribute company funds to a political party solely for personal satisfaction, this would be open to question even in the more liberal donations regime existing in many US states: [C]orporate managers may authorize donations to politically active charities as a means of furthering their own political and ideological preferences, irrespective of the firm's best interests. When corporate managers approve donations on this self-serving basis, they satisfy the letter of the [US] law, but fail to fulfill their fiduciary obligation to protect corporate shareholders' property interests.61 Under Australian corporate law, directors and senior executives must not profit improperly from their position as officers of the company.62 A political donation could lead to a breach of this rule if, as a result of a donation, a director was endorsed as a party candidate. As the DTI paper notes, where a director 'was a member of the political party to which a donation was to be given, there could be a conflict between the director's personal interests and [her or] his duty to the company'.63 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 57 Mike Adams and Philip Hardwick, 'An Analysis of Corporate Donations: United Kingdom Evidence' (1998) 35 Journal of Management Studies 641, 641-2, citing O Hart, 'An Economist's View of Fiduciary Duty'(Discussion Paper No 157, LSE Financial Markets Group, 1993) 16. 58 Abzug and Webb, above n 52, 1041, citing Armen A Alchian and Reuben A Kessel, 'Competition, Monopoly and the Pursuit of Pecuniary Gain' in National Bureau of Economic Research, Aspects of Labor Economics (Conference Proceedings, 1962), 156. 59 Ibid 1041-2, citing Charles T Clotfelter, Federal Tax Policy and Charitable Giving (1985), 184. 60 The data examined in the study described later in this article do not enable any definite conclusions to be drawn. A more detailed study examining the most mobile directors amongst the most politically philanthropic companies would shed more light on this point. Directors who were constantly changing companies would be examined to see whether they took their 'giving-pattern' with them. 61 Kahn, above n 15, 611 (notes omitted). 62 Keech v Sandford (1726) Sel Cas Ch 61; Furs Ltd v Tomkies (1936) 54 CLR 583; Corporations Act, ss 182, 183. 63 Department of Trade and Industry, above n 22, para 2.4. 190 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Managerial self-dealing may explain a company's political donations even where no director or senior executive of the company is actively involved in the political party concerned. The donations may result simply from a personal desire among some or all of the directors to assist a particular party. If they were to use their own money this would be completely uncontentious. But where this desire to provide financial support to a political party results in company funds being donated to the political party or a club or foundation supporting the party – or in some other form of financial assistance being given by the company to the political party – matters of corporate law and policy become relevant. C. Corporate social responsibility There is no universally accepted definition of corporate social responsibility (CSR),64 but Engel has said: The term…is most useful if taken to denote the obligations and inclinations, if any, of corporations organized for profit, voluntarily to pursue social ends that conflict with the presumptive shareholder desire to maximize profit.65 CSR is probably interchangeable with terms like 'enlightened self-interest'66 and the corporate governance perspective known generally as 'stakeholder theory'.67 The fundamental theme of CSR is that corporate managers should recognise that their prime duty of profit-maximisation for shareholders is to be tempered by an acknowledgement that corporate power is held on trust for the wider community.68 This approach seems to have been accepted by some US courts.69 In terms of philanthropy, some corporate executives say that supporting philanthropic agencies is a way for the company to 'give something back' to the community.70 Unlike a purely altruistic perspective, however, CSR-prompted charity recognises that the corporation does not exist in a social, ethical or moral vacuum.71 In fact, the term 'enlightened self-interest' best captures the notion that the CSR-aware company is far from altruistic, and indeed recognises that by being good, it can do well. It could be argued that CSR is simply profit-maximisation with a halo: _____________________________________________________________________________________ 64 Kahn, above n 15, 629 (note 191). 65 David L Engel, 'An Approach to Corporate Social Responsibility' (1979) 32 Stanford Law Review 1, 5-6. 66 Kahn, above n 15, 627 (note 184); Company Law Review Steering Group, Modern Company Law for a Competitive Economy: The Strategic Framework (Consultation Document, 1999), ch 5.1. 67 See, eg, E Merrick Dodd Jr, 'For Whom Are Corporate Managers Trustees?' (1932) 45 Harvard Law Review 1145; Lord Wedderburn of Charlton, 'The Social Responsibility of Companies' (1985) 15 Melbourne University Law Review 4. 68 Adolf A Berle Jr, The Twentieth Century Capitalist Revolution (1954) 169. 69 AP Smith Mfg Co v Barlow 98 A2d 581, 586 (1953); Theodora Holding Corp v Henderson 257 A2d 398, 404 (Del. Ch. 1969); Paramount Communications, Inc v Time Inc 571 A2d 1140 (Del. 1990). 70 Abzug and Webb, above n 52, 1039. 71 Kahn, above n 15, 629-30 (notes omitted). It has been argued that corporate charitable donations may reflect CSR on the part of companies yet this does not equate to viewing companies as citizens: Sally Wheeler, 'Inclusive Communities and Dialogical Stakeholders: A Methodology for an Authentic Corporate Citizenship' (1998) 9 Australian Journal of Corporate Law 1. 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 191 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Although researchers in economics, sociology, and other fields suggest that social responsibility or duty motivates corporate executives to donate, economists tend to believe that nearly all donations benefit the corporation in some way. …The benefit to the firm is increased sales or other benefits accruing because the corporation appears to be 'socially minded'.72 Some of those other benefits include public relations, financial performance and employee productivity.73 Abzug and Webb note that, in the US, no studies have conclusively proven causation between higher levels of giving and better financial performance.74 From the US perspective, this would be of little consequence.75 But the Australian position, based on Hutton76, seems to be that if CSR-prompted charity is of no benefit to the company, then the courts can impeach such contributions. This is precisely the situation that arose in Parke v Daily News Ltd.77 A minority shareholder challenged proposed ex gratia payments to employees who were facing imminent redundancy as the company had contracted to sell its main business assets. The board considered that it owed 'a very practical obligation to employees', but the court disagreed: 'the defendants were prompted by motives which, however laudable, and however enlightened from the point of view of industrial relations, were such as the law does not recognise as a sufficient justification'.78 Whatever the relative merits and demerits of CSR, it is doubtful whether it can justify the making of political donations. Political parties are hardly the kind of social actors whose interests are furthered by CSR and, moreover, often represent only narrow sectional political interests. Although CSR masquerading as 'enlightened selfinterest' could serve to validate a political donation under the strict 'benefit' test, the more appropriate rationalisation would appear to be profit-maximisation. D. Political free-speech Another possible motivation for a corporate political donation is a desire by a company's board or management to voice the company's view in a political debate – albeit indirectly. There would, of course, often be other (more direct) means of making _____________________________________________________________________________________ 72 Abzug and Webb, above n 52, 1039-40 (emphasis added) . 73 Dwight F Burlingame, 'Empirical Research on Corporate Social Responsibility: What Does it Tell Us?' (1994) 4 Nonprofit Management & Leadership 473, 474, cited in Abzug and Webb, ibid, 1039 (note 19). 74 Abzug and Webb, ibid, 1040. 75 US managers who operate in a legal environment that has not abrogated the 'benefit-to-thebusiness' test will still enjoy the protection of the business judgment rule where, in making a donation, they acted on an informed basis, honestly, and in good faith, and the donation was a business decision in the best interests of the company. 76 (1883) 23 Ch D 654, 671. 77 [1962] Ch 927 (affirming Hutton). 78 Ibid 963 (Plowman J). Later cases in some overseas jurisdictions have made some inroads into the general principles of Hutton and Parke. For example, in the Canadian case Teck Corporation Ltd v Millar (1973) 33 DLR (3d) 288, 314 Berger J said: If today the directors of a company were to consider the interests of its employees no one would argue that in doing so they were not acting bona fide in the interests of the company itself. Similarly, if the directors were to consider the consequences to the community of any policy that the company intended to pursue, and were deflected in their commitment to that policy as a result, it could not be said that they had not considered bona fide the interests of the shareholders. 192 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ the company's view known; for example, by making a formal submission to a parliamentary committee or law reform body. To the extent that a corporate political donation represents an attempt by the company's board or management to exercise the company's right to 'political free-speech', Kahn is strongly opposed: [B]ecause politicized corporate charitable contributions are a form of corporate political speech, they may impinge on shareholders' speech and associational interests. In light of the fact that shareholders are typically not provided with information regarding the firm's charitable contributions, the investment decision cannot represent a legitimate proxy for shareholder consent to politicized charitable contributions. …[A] deep conflict exists between the firm's right to promote its political interests and the shareholders' interest in not being compelled to subsidize speech with which they are in disagreement.79 E. Profit-maximisation By definition, pure charity cannot be expected to result in gains for a company because, where 'charity' is used in the true sense of the word, the donor cannot anticipate a net gain from his or her contribution.80 There is therefore a widely held view that corporate donations to charitable organisations are motivated primarily by profit-maximisation.81 As Adams and Hardwick argue, 'more and more corporations view their contributions as a form of investment rather than classic philanthropy (ie: pure gifts)'.82 Corporate donations to political parties may also be motivated by profitmaximisation. The link between the political contribution and the benefit to the business may well be direct and obvious; it may be designed to reduce costs or increase revenues in a fairly direct manner. As far as reducing costs is concerned, contributions could be designed to insulate the company from unfavourable tax or regulatory policies, thereby reducing the company's tax and compliance costs.83 As for increasing revenues, contributions may be designed to improve the company's chances of winning government business contracts when the political party, which is the beneficiary, next forms a government. Alternatively, the link between the contribution and the benefit to the business may be more indirect. An example of a contribution designed to maximise profits indirectly is a contribution aimed at minimising or negating adverse publicity: Managers also use contributions to stem governmental criticisms of corporate actions, and to ward off attacks by social activists. …[T]hreats of regulation prompt contributions to civic and political affairs from the utilities.84 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 79 Kahn, above n 15, 637 (notes omitted). 80 Ibid, 663-4 (notes omitted). 81 Abzug and Webb, above n 52, 1045. 82 Adams and Hardwick, above n 57, 641, citing J J Siegfried, K M McElroy and D BiernotFawkes, 'The Management of Corporate Contributions' (1983) 5 Research in Corporate Performance and Policy 87, 87. 83 Usha C V Haley, 'Corporate Contributions as Managerial Masques: Reframing Corporate Contributions as Strategies to Influence Society' (1991) 28 Journal of Management Studies 485, 487, 489. 84 Ibid 501, citing J Cohn, The Conscience of the Corporations: Business and Urban Affairs. 19671970 (1971); F Fry and R J Hock 'Who Claims Corporate Responsibility? The Biggest and the Worst' (1976) 18 Business and Society Review 62; F K Levy and G M Shatto, 'Social 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 193 ____________________________________________________________________________________ From the shareholders' perspective, political donations motivated primarily by profit-maximisation are not a source of agency costs. If the company is offered contracts or tenders when its beneficiary obtains government, or is approached more sympathetically by regulators, then many shareholders would have little cause for complaint. On the other hand, political donations of this nature may involve some significant legal and policy issues in areas other than corporate law. F. The (lack of) evidence on motivation Much of the preceding argument is speculative in the sense that it is almost impossible accurately to discern why companies make donations. Suspicions can be loosely tested by reference to the contours of the corporate landscape and tax laws, but in the absence of a study directly on point no solid conclusions can be reached. A 1980 study considered some motivations, but it did not differentiate between political and non-political donations.85 Of the 101 companies responding to the survey, 96 made donations. The most important factor cited by respondents was a belief in the active support of social programs. The fact that donations provided favourable publicity was mostly claimed to be unimportant. Of the five companies which did not make donations, four refrained because their basic responsibility was to shareholders, while the fact that benefits to the company might not be readily identifiable was claimed to be largely unimportant. Unfortunately, the findings of this study are, for present purposes, largely indeterminate because it did not differentiate between political and non-political donations. Also, the results of surveys in this area must be treated with caution given the possibility of self-serving responses. The possibility that corporate giving is motivated more by management selfinterest (or other factors) rather than profit-maximisation is supported by studies that fail to find a conclusive link between corporate giving and profitability.86 However, the failure to find that conclusive link is not necessarily fatal to the proposition. There is some old UK evidence suggesting that corporate political donations make no difference to election outcomes.87 If this remains the case – that is, if contributions make no difference to a party's chances – then a donor company's directors are possibly in breach of the rule in Hutton.88 If contributions do make a difference, then the rule in Hutton is observed, but at the risk of an accusation of buying political influence.89 _____________________________________________________________________________________ Responsibility in Large Electric Utility Firms: The Case for Philanthropy' in L E Preston (ed), Research in Corporate Social Performance and Policy (1980). 85 A Harris, 'Corporate Donations to Institutions – A Survey of Practice and Disclosure' (1980) 32 (April-June) Professional Administrator 97. 86 Fisch, above n 4, 1097, citing James R Boatsman and Sanjay Gupta, 'Taxes and Corporate Charity: Empirical Evidence from Micro-Level Panel Data' (1996) 49 National Tax Journal 193. 87 David Butler, The British General Election 1951 (1952), 34, cited in K D Ewing, 'Company Political Donations and the Ultra Vires Rule' (1984) 47 Law Quarterly Review 57, 70. 88 If the party is already in government, the donation would not run as great a risk of leading to a breach of the rule in Hutton. This is because the donation may be designed to influence the government's approach to laws and issues affecting the company, and therefore could be 'profit-maximising'. However, a donation of this nature raises issues over and above corporate law. 89 Ewing, above n 87, 71. 194 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ In relation to the US, causal empiricism suggests that political spending is positively related to election outcomes. The restriction on overt political contributions by US companies90 inferentially recognises this and the concomitant point that votes can be bought. The importance of the effect of a contribution – and the motive for making it – cannot be underestimated. Depending on the effect or motive (and it does not seem to matter which), directors and senior executives expose themselves (and their companies) to varying types and degrees of liability. We now consider these legal issues. IV. LEGAL REGULATION IN AUSTRALIA A. Corporate law Disclosure The Corporations Act does not contain any disclosure rules specifically aimed at political donations. But a proposed corporate political donation may fall within a general disclosure rule. If a director has a material personal interest in a proposed political donation by the company, the director must disclose to the other directors as soon as practicable the nature and extent of the interest and the relation of the interest to the affairs of the company.91 If it is a public company, the interested director is not allowed to be present while the donation is being considered by the board, and is not allowed to vote on the matter at the board meeting.92 Also, if the company is a public company or is controlled by a public company, the related party provisions apply. Under Chapter 2E of the Corporations Act, a public company (or an entity that the public company controls) may give a financial benefit to a 'related party' of the public company only if: • the public company's shareholders approve in advance – after full disclosure; or • the giving of the benefit falls within an exception set out in Chapter 2E. The expression 'related party' is defined to include not only the directors of the public company, and their spouses, parents and children, but also (among others) an entity which acts in concert with a related party (X) on the understanding that X will receive a financial benefit if the public company gives the entity a financial benefit.93 If a public-company director is also an office-bearer of a political party, or has some involvement with an organisation that supports a political party, any financial benefit _____________________________________________________________________________________ 90 See Section IIIA above. 91 Corporations Act, s 191. 92 Corporations Act, s 195(1). The director may be present and vote if directors who do not have a material personal interest in the matter have passed a resolution that: • identifies the director, the nature and extent of the director's interest in the matter and its relation to the affairs of the company; and • states that those directors are satisfied that the interest should not disqualify the director from voting or being present: s 195(2). 93 Corporations Act, s 228. 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 195 ____________________________________________________________________________________ given by the company to the party or the supporting organisation would fall within Chapter 2E if the 'acting in concert' test was satisfied. Giving a financial benefit is defined very broadly and would catch not only straightforward donations but also, for example, supplying services, forgiving a loan or leasing property to the political party or supporting organisation.94 If an exception applies, there is no obligation to obtain prior shareholder approval of the financial benefit. But in the political donations scenario the only exception that might be applicable is the 'arm's length terms' exception. This exception applies where a financial benefit is given on terms that would be reasonable in the circumstances if the public company (or controlled entity) and the related party were dealing at arm's length (or on terms that are less favourable to the related party than arm's length terms).95 If one accepts that regulations governing corporate political donations should be based on the two principles of transparency and accountability, the related party provisions provide a sub-optimal disclosure and approval regime. There is no doubt that the Chapter 2E provisions are very broadly drafted. Indeed, the provisions may well have applied to some cases of corporate political giving over recent years, although neither the directors nor the political party concerned (nor the Australian Securities and Investments Commission) were aware of their applicability. Nevertheless, in some instances a public company could provide a financial benefit to a political party, or an organisation supporting a political party, and Chapter 2E would not apply due to the absence of a 'related party'. And, of course, Chapter 2E applies only to financial benefits given by public companies and entities controlled by public companies. It does not apply to financial benefits given by a proprietary company that is not controlled by a public company. In short, Chapter 2E is not a comprehensive disclosure regime as far as corporate political donations are concerned. Corporate capacity and officers' authority96 In the UK, the question of a company's capacity to make a political donation arose in Simmonds v Heffer.97 Mervyn-Davies J considered that the legal capacity of a company to make a donation depended on construing its memorandum and articles of association, and determining whether or not the donation was ultra vires the company. But because the doctrine of ultra vires has been abolished in Australia,98 the validity of a corporate political donation cannot be challenged on grounds of lack of corporate capacity.99 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 94 Corporations Act, s 229. 95 Corporations Act, s 210. 96 For additional analysis, see Simon Fisher, 'Corporations as Donors: A Legal Survey' in M McGregor-Lowndes, K Fletcher and S Sievers (eds), Legal Issues for Non-Profit Associations (1996), Ch 8. 97 [1983] BCLC 298 98 Corporations Act, ss 124, 125. 99 As s 125(2) of the Corporations Act states, 'An act of [a] company is not invalid merely because it is contrary to or beyond the objects in the company's constitution'. Although the expression ultra vires is sometimes used in respect of acts of both individuals or corporations who act beyond their powers, in the context of corporate law, the expression should be used in the narrow sense of being confined to acts by a company with limited capacity beyond its corporate power. With the abolition of the doctrine of ultra vires in 196 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ One possible ground for challenging a political donation made by an Australian company is lack of authority in the officer(s) who approved and/or performed the acts constituting the donation. This is a matter for the general law of agency as it has been applied to companies100 and the statutory assumptions101 which a donee is entitled to make in relation to the contribution. As a practical matter, however, it would be unlikely that a political party would try to challenge the ability of its benefactor to make donations to it. It is therefore more useful to analyse a political donation in terms of officers' duties,102 and any actions which may be brought to enforce those duties. Directors' and officers' duties As discussed earlier in the article, a director or senior executive risks breaching the duty to act in good faith in the interests of the company if he or she authorises a political donation in circumstances where there is no obvious benefit – direct or indirect – for the company's shareholders.103 In addition, if a director or senior executive authorises a political donation in circumstances where he or she stands to gain personally – either directly or indirectly – then there is a risk of breaching the fiduciary duty to avoid a conflict between personal interests and duties to the company, and also the statutory duty not to make improper use of position.104 These duties may be enforced by the Australian Securities and Investments Commission (ASIC),105 by the company itself106 or, in limited circumstances, by a shareholder under the statutory derivative action provisions.107 _____________________________________________________________________________________ Australia, an act of a director in disregard of the interests of the company only affects the validity of the director's acts and does not affect the validity of the corporate action. Directors are under an obligation to ensure that company powers and funds are used only for company purposes: ANZ Executors and Trustee Co Ltd v Qintex Australia Ltd [1991] 2 Qd R 360. 100 See eg, Freeman and Lockyer v Buckhurst Park Properties (Mangal) Ltd [1964] 2 QB 480; HelyHutchinson v Brayhead Ltd [1968] 1 QB 549; Crabtree-Vickers Pty Ltd v Australian Direct Mail Advertising and Addressing Co Pty Ltd (1975) 133 CLR 72. 101 Corporations Act, ss 128, 129. 102 The commentary on Simmonds v Heffer agrees that donations are more-appropriately challenged under heads of directors' duties, and not the doctrine of ultra vires: Ewing, above n 87, 69; Leon Cane, 'Ultra Vires and Political Donations' (1984) New Law Journal 749, 750. 103 See Hutton (1883) 23 Ch D 654 and Corporations Act, s 181. 104 Corporations Act, s 182. For a discussion of the legal duties owed by directors and other officers of companies see H A J Ford, R P Austin and I M Ramsay, Ford's Principles of Corporations Law (10th ed 2001), Chs 8 and 9. 105 Australian Securities and Investments Commission Act 2001 (Cth), s 50; Corporations Act, ss 1317J(1), 1324. 106 The company's right to bring legal proceedings in respect of a breach of fiduciary duty by a director or senior executive is an inherent general law power. In relation to a breach of one of the officers' duties in the Corporations Act (eg, s 181 or s 182), the company has power to apply for compensation under s 1317J(2), and would normally be entitled (as 'a person whose interests have been … affected' by the breach) to apply for an injunction under s 1324. 107 Corporations Act, Part 2F.1A. A shareholder may also be able to apply for an injunction under s 1324 if a board decision to make a political donation amounts to a breach of one or 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 197 ____________________________________________________________________________________ An action by ASIC is probably unlikely except in extreme circumstances, given ASIC's limited resources and wide range of competing demands on its enforcement arm. It is also unlikely that the company would bring legal proceedings – unless there has been a change of control. This is particularly the case where the decision to make a political donation is a 'collective' decision made by the board of directors because the power to commence litigation in the company's name is ordinarily a power of the board of directors.108 A derivative action by a shareholder in respect of a political donation authorised by the board is also considered unlikely except in extreme circumstances. The incentives for this type of shareholder litigation are particularly weak.109 Also, a derivative action could commence only if, among other things, the court considered the alleged breach of duty arising from the political donation as sufficiently serious that it was in the best interests of the company that a derivative action be allowed to proceed.110 Oppression Political donations may form the basis of an oppression application under Part 2F.1 of the Corporations Act. Under Part 2F.1, any member of a company111 has power to apply to the court for an order under s 233 in respect of an act, omission or course of conduct that is contrary to the interests of the company's members as a whole, or oppressive or unfairly prejudicial to, or unfairly discriminatory against, a member or members whether in that capacity or in any other capacity. While there has been no reported oppression case in Australia in which the applicant has cited political donations among the allegedly oppressive acts or conduct, the nature of the oppression remedy is such that the possibility of this occurring in the future cannot be ruled out. For example, a member of a small or medium-sized company may build an oppression application around the fact that the company's directors have decided not to pay dividends but instead to donate heavily to a political party. This example reveals a significant limitation of the oppression remedy for present purposes: the oppression provisions have greater scope for application to proprietary companies than to large public companies.112 _____________________________________________________________________________________ more of the statutory officers' duties. The approach of Young J in Mesenberg v Cord Industrial Recruiters Pty Ltd (1996) 19 ACSR 483 would preclude a shareholder applying for an injunction under s 1324 in respect of an alleged breach of a statutory officers' duty, but this approach was rejected by Einfeld J in Airpeak Pty Ltd v Jetstream Aircraft Ltd (1997) 27 ACSR 715. 108 See, eg, Corporations Act, s 198A (a replaceable rule), and equivalent provisions in company constitutions; John Shaw & Sons (Salford) Ltd v Shaw [1935] 2 KB 113. 109 Ian M Ramsay, 'Corporate Governance, Shareholder Litigation and the Prospects for a Statutory Derivative Action' (1992) 15 University of New South Wales Law Journal 149, 162-4. 110 Corporations Act, s 237(2)(c). 111 Together with a former member in limited circumstances, and also a person nominated by ASIC in certain circumstances: Corporations Act, s 234. 112 G P Stapledon, 'Use of the Oppression Provision in Listed Companies in Australia and the United Kingdom' (1993) 67 Australian Law Journal 575. See also Ian M Ramsay, 'An Empirical Study of the Use of the Oppression Remedy' (1999) 27 Australian Business Law Review 23, for evidence that the oppression remedy is mostly used in relation to proprietary companies. 198 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Court-ordered winding up Under s 461(1)(k) of the Corporations Act, the court has power to order the winding up of a company if the court is of the opinion that it is just and equitable that the company be wound up. A shareholder has standing to apply for a winding up order on this ground.113 Sections 461(1)(f) and 461(1)(g) provide further grounds on which the court may make a winding up order following a shareholder application – namely, that the affairs of the company are being conducted in an oppressive, unfairly prejudicial or unfairly discriminatory manner, or that an act or omission by or on behalf of the company is oppressive, unfairly prejudicial or unfairly discriminatory. An additional ground for a court-ordered winding up is set out in s 461(1)(e) – namely, where a company's directors have acted in the affairs of the company in their own interests rather than in the interests of the members as a whole, or in some other way that appears to be unfair or unjust to members. In practical terms, a member aggrieved by a company's political donations would be better advised to apply for an order under the oppression provisions (Part 2F.1) rather than a winding up order under s 461. This is because compulsory winding up is a drastic remedy, and under s 467(4) the court is required to refrain from making a winding up order on the grounds set out in s 461(1)(e) or (k) if the court believes that some other remedy is available to the applicant and the applicant is acting unreasonably in seeking to have the company wound up instead of pursuing that other remedy. Presumably, the court may well consider that a remedy under the oppression provisions is an acceptable alternative. These remedies include an order for the purchase of the applicant's shares by the company or by another shareholder, or an order prohibiting the payment of further donations. B. The Electoral Act The Commonwealth Electoral Act 1918 (Cth) ('Electoral Act') regulates the practice of donations only by requiring disclosure. The Electoral Act does no more than establish a scheme of annual reporting and disclosure to the Australian Electoral Commission by: • registered political parties of funds they have received (including donations); and • individuals, companies, trusts and foundations of donations they have made to registered political parties. The details of disclosure in each case are not the same. Political parties are required to disclose all amounts they receive during a financial year (including donations, loans and bequests) from a person or organisation where the sum of all amounts received from that person or organisation during the financial year is $1,500 or more. In calculating the sum, an amount of less than $1,500 need not be counted.114 Disclosure must also be made by candidates in an election or by-election of donations they have received relating to the election.115 A person or organisation which donates $1,500 or more to a registered political party during a financial year must provide a return to the Electoral Commission disclosing all donations within 20 weeks after the end of the financial year. Donations _____________________________________________________________________________________ 113 Corporations Act, s 462(2)(c) and s 9 (definition of 'contributory'). 114 Commonwealth Electoral Act 1918, s 314AC. 115 Commonwealth Electoral Act 1918, s 304. 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 199 ____________________________________________________________________________________ made by individuals, companies, trusts and foundations must be disclosed. There have been concerns that the Electoral Act did not require disclosures made indirectly through a trust or foundation. For example, a public company could donate funds to a trust or foundation and if that trust or foundation then used those funds to make a donation to a political party, the source of the original donation (the public company) would not have to be disclosed. This concern has now been addressed. As a result of amendments made by the Electoral and Referendum Amendment Act (No 1) 1999 (Cth), the return lodged by a person or organisation which specifies the donations made to a political party must also include details of all donations received by that person or organisation, being donations used to make the donation to the political party.116 These amendments also require loans made to political parties to be disclosed. The set of donation records maintained by the Australian Electoral Commission are somewhat unworkable. The records do not neatly differentiate 'Donations to XYZ Party made by corporations'. This is because the Electoral Act does not differentiate between corporate and non-corporate donors. Also, it does not require the Australian Electoral Commission to consolidate into one report all the State Branch returns from a particular party. Weaknesses in the disclosure scheme are addressed later in this article. By comparison, the Companies Act 1985 (UK), as amended by the Political Parties, Elections and Referendums Act 2000 (UK), imposes very specific disclosure requirements upon companies. The current UK disclosure regime makes it more difficult for UK companies to conceal political donations than is the case for Australian companies. The Australian Corporations Act contains no specific disclosure rules. V. THE STUDY A. Collecting, categorising and consolidating the data The data collected for the study was derived from party annual returns for 1995/96, 1996/97 and 1997/98. Research was confined to the major parties in Australian politics – the Australian Labor Party, the Liberal Party, the National Party, the Democrats, the Greens117 and One Nation. Because the returns are not restricted to donations, it seems to make more sense to collect data directly from the donor returns, but these are far more numerous and presented significant logistical and analytical problems which could not be as easily overcome as those presented by the party annual returns. Accordingly, data was collected from the party annual returns for ease of later analysis. The use of annual returns as the data source necessitated some qualitative refinements to the extracted information to confine the data to corporate donations. In _____________________________________________________________________________________ 116 Commonwealth Electoral Act 1918, s 305B(3A). The precise requirement is as follows: The return must also set out the relevant details of all gifts received by the person at any time, being gifts used to make gifts the whole or part of which were used to make gifts totalling $1,500 or more in a financial year to the same registered political party or the same State branch of a registered political party and the amount or value of each of which is equal to or exceeds $1,000. 117 There are many registered parties going by the name 'Green' or some derivative of that word. We consolidated these parties under the 'Green' banner for convenience. 200 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ the main, the parties split their annual receipts into gifts and other receipts. In these cases, refinement consisted simply of culling the non-corporate donors from the data. Once the set of corporate donors was obtained, these were separated into public and proprietary companies. Non-corporate enterprises were culled, but we preserved the data on professional firms118 and lobby groups for comparative purposes.119 The next step in the analysis involved consolidating and verifying the data. Where a public company was seen to have made several donations to a party (say, by way of a donation to each state branch of the party), the donations were consolidated under the banner name of that company. Also, donations were – to a limited extent – consolidated according to corporate groups. Where a donation was made by a similarly named subsidiary of a public company, it was consolidated under the parent company's name. However, no attempt was made to consolidate donations made by group companies, which were operating under markedly different names. To have attempted to consolidate in this comprehensive manner would have necessitated an enormous amount of time cross-checking company names against either a database of corporate group constituents or disclosures of subsidiaries in public companies' annual reports. Very little consolidation according to corporate groups was carried out for proprietary companies. The reason is that the sheer number of proprietary companies in existence means that similarities in name may be coincidental rather than evidence of a group relationship. Again, verification would have involved a very substantial exercise. Where the party return was ambiguous or unclear, a number of databases were used to resolve difficulties over entity type or consolidation. In some cases, the donor's address (taken from the return) matched the address which was returned by ASIC's website search facility, the White Pages or the Yellow Pages. However, addresses are not conclusive because several unrelated companies may share the same registered office (eg, that of their mutual accountant). So, in the case of uncertainty, reference was made to the Australian Financial Review's Shareholder guidebook and Dun & Bradstreet's Who Owns Whom, to settle questions of consolidation. Public companies were separated into ASX-listed companies and unlisted companies. The listed companies were then classified according to ASX industry groups. This allowed a comparison of the patterns of corporate giving by industry group over the three years of the study. Given the inconsistencies and flaws in the raw data, the conclusions that may be drawn from this research must necessarily be qualified to some extent. This raises a separate issue. The problems with the database produced under the current disclosure regime highlight the desirability of reforming the existing disclosure rules so that comprehensible and meaningful information is disclosed in the future. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 118 'Professional firms' were those donors that were found to be law firms, barristers' clerking offices and accounting firms. 119 A broad definition of 'lobby group' was adopted because it was considered inappropriate to include some corporate donors in the corporate listings, if in substance the company was a lobby group. In general, lobby groups were those donors that were companies limited by guarantee, or bore the title 'Association', 'Club', 'Federation' or 'Group', but not trade unions. 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 201 ____________________________________________________________________________________ B. Patterns of corporate political philanthropy in Australia – 1995/96 to 1997/98 Aggregate figures over the 3 year period Summary data is presented in Table A. Over the three year period 1995/96-1997/98, total corporate donations were $29 million. Of this amount, 64% ($18.5 million) was donated to the Liberal Party while 23% (or almost $7 million) was donated to the ALP. The National Party received just under $3.5 million. Of the total amount of $29 million, over $17 million was donated by public companies (with 63% of this going to the Liberal Party and 29% going to the ALP) and more than $11.6 million was donated by private companies (with 65% of this being donated to the Liberal Party and 15.5% being donated to the ALP). Professional firms gave almost $250,000 to the Liberal Party, just over $73,000 to the ALP, and a mere $9,000 to the National Party. Lobby groups gave over $11 million to the Liberal Party, almost $9 million to the ALP, and $2.7 million to the National Party. In summary, over the three years of the study, the ALP received most of its corporate money from public companies, while the Liberal Party received significant sums from both the public and proprietary company sectors. The National Party's figures varied too widely to generalise, but tended to the proprietary company sector. The Liberal Party received substantially more than the other parties from professional firms. Finally, the Liberal Party and the ALP both received significant amounts from lobby groups. Aggregate figures, year by year Remaining with Table A, but turning to a year by year analysis, the highest corporate political donations were made in 1995/96 – when total corporate donations amounted to almost $15 million. More than half of this amount ($8.4 million) comprised donations from public companies, while donations from proprietary companies accounted for $6.3 million. Professional firms contributed a little more than $150,000, while lobby groups accounted for almost $9.4 million. The Liberal Party was clearly the most successful at attracting money from all sources, accounting for between 60% and 65% of all categories of corporate donation and lobby group donations, and nearly 90% of donations by professional firms. Overall donations fell in 1996/97, with companies giving less than half of their previous year's level ($6.2 million). Gifts from public companies amounted to just over $4 million, while proprietary companies contributed the remaining $2.2 million. The Liberal Party was able to increase its share of corporate contributions – it received between 67% and 70% of all categories of corporate donation. Professional firms gave $68,000 in 1996/97, with almost 80% of it going to the Liberal Party. Lobby groups gave only slightly less than in the prior year, down just over $1 million to $8.2 million. The Liberal Party received almost 41% of this, the ALP close to 36% and the National Party 23.5%. Corporate giving increased to almost $8 million in 1997/98. Public company donations were up slightly on the previous year, to just under $5 million. Proprietary company donations were also up, to a little over $3 million. Proportionately, the level of giving to the Liberal Party was down at the expense of increased corporate support for the ALP, but the Liberal Party nevertheless continued to hold its position as the most popular destination for corporate gifts. Professional firms gave just over $100,000, 202 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ with the Liberal Party attracting 52% of this (a significantly smaller proportion than in the previous two years); the ALP took almost 42%, and the National Party the remaining 6.5%. Lobby groups contributed much less than in the previous two years ($5.1 million), with 51% of it going to the ALP, 43% to the Liberal Party and the remaining 5.7% to the National Party. Number of contributors and average size of contributions, year by year The number of contributors varied significantly every year. In 1995/96, the Liberal Party accepted gifts from 537 companies, with the average donation being $17,656. The ALP received gifts from 159 corporate contributors (average: $20,918), while the National Party had 80 corporate benefactors (average: $23,073). The Liberal Party received an average of $32,135 from its 171 company donors, while the ALP collected an average of $31,829 from its 77 public company donors. The National Party's 28 public company donors gave an average of $15,367, while the Democrats received an average of $6,250 from its 8 public company donors. Contributor numbers were down in 1996/97. The Liberal Party received gifts from 167 companies, at a higher average of $25,496 per company. The ALP received an average $17,180 from its 74 corporate donors, while the National Party received a similar average amount ($17,337) from its 37 corporate donors. The Democrats received the highest average of $31,917 from just 2 corporate donors. The Liberal Party received gifts from 72 public companies, at an average of $37,599. The ALP received $25,065 on average from 34 public companies, while the National Party received an average $19,622 from 22 public companies. Contributor numbers were up in 1997/98, but average donations were lower. The Liberal Party received an average $18,758 from 256 corporate donors, while the ALP collected $19,473 from 112 corporate donors. The National Party had 107 corporate donors (average: $9,282). The Liberal Party had more public company benefactors than the previous year (106), but with total donations from public companies lower (its average gift being $26,499). The ALP took an average $25,925 from 64 public company donors, while the National Party collected an average $11,816 from its 39 public company donors. ASX-listed companies The pattern of giving by ASX-listed companies is presented in Table B. The data has been totalled over the three years of the study, and is confined to the three major parties that received significant levels of donations. The industry groups shown in Table B are those industry groups represented in the data – not all industry groups were represented. Each party's data can be read and interpreted independently of the data of another party. The overall pattern of giving may be discerned from the three columns following the 'Industry sector' column. The 'Total donated' column represents the total amount in dollars donated to the three parties by the corresponding industry sector. The 'Number of companies' column, however, does not reflect the total number of donations made by the corresponding industry sector. Rather, this column indicates how many companies in a given sector made donations to any combination of parties. For example, in the Gold sector, 24 companies made donations – 22 to the Liberal Party and 3 each to the ALP and the National Party. Adding up each party's number of benefactors would give 28, which would be incorrect because several companies made 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 203 ____________________________________________________________________________________ donations to more than one party. Accordingly, the figure in the 'Number of companies' column avoids double-counting of donors. Finally, the 'Average aggregate overall donation' column is simply the result obtained by dividing 'Total donated' by 'Number of companies'. This aggregate figure represents the average amount which companies in a given industry sector set aside for donations to any destination; where this figure is higher than the averages received by a particular party, it can be concluded that companies in a given sector have donated to more than one party. Tables C and D are derived from Table B, and are more amenable to descriptive analysis. Table C ranks the industry sectors in descending order of total donations per sector. It can be seen that the industry sector with the most donations was the banking and finance sector with almost $3 million in total donations over the 3 year period. This was followed by the tourism and leisure sector with $1.7 million in total donations, the developers and contractors sector with $1.44 million in total donations and the diversified industrial sector with $1.05 million in total donations. The average amount donated by all companies within an industry sector was $686,040 which fell between ranks 8 and 9. Table D ranks the industry sectors in descending order of average aggregate overall donation. The average was $118,172, which fell between ranks 9 and 10. This is the average total amount donated by an ASX-listed company over the three years studied. Table E is identical in form to Tables C and D, except that it is confined to each party in turn. The pattern of ranking for donors to the Liberal Party, in terms of both total industry sector donation and average contributions per sector, closely follows the figures for all parties combined. The ALP's total industry sector donations and average contributions per sector do not follow the overall figures as closely as the Liberal Party. Both sets of figures for the National Party are at great variance to the overall figures. These figures show clearly that the Liberal Party was the most strongly supported party by ASX-listed companies. Table F shows the Top 10 ASX-listed company donors. The companies have been ranked in terms of total disclosable political donations made over the three-year period studied. Donations made to all political parties have been combined. Only Westpac and Village Roadshow donated more than $1 million during the three years.120 Among the Top 10 donors, two made donations to all four major parties (Liberal, ALP, National and Australian Democrats); five made donations to three parties (Liberal, _____________________________________________________________________________________ 120 But note that the total for National Australia Bank would also have been over a million dollars if a disputed amount of $1 million had been counted in our study. The Liberal Party's return for 1996/97 did not show an amount for the transaction described below. However, in a letter to the Australian Electoral Commission, dated 30 July 1998, and on the Commission's public database, the Liberal Party requested that its 1996/97 return be amended to include a $1 million receipt from National Australia Bank. The letter explained: 'During the year ended 30 June 1997, as part of the Party's bank overdraft facilities with the National Australia Bank, a commercial bill of $1 million was credited to our bank account. This amount was not shown as a receipt in the Party's 1996/1997 Annual Return on the basis that it was a component of the overdraft. Overdrafts are not discloseable as receipts, but rather as debts if owed at year-end, and in our view, the same approach should apply to the commercial bill, particularly when it is part of an overall bank overdraft arrangement. This approach was verbally agreed with an officer of the Commission on 20 October 1997, prior to lodgement of the return, but subsequently reversed by another officer during the conduct of the audit.' 204 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ ALP and National); two made donations to two parties (Liberal and ALP); and one made a donation to only one party (Liberal). C. Analysis The Liberal Party consistently outperformed the other parties in terms of attracting corporate donations. So consistent, in fact, and so successful that in each year of the study, over the three-year period in aggregate, and in each corporate category, the Liberal Party's donations amounted to more than those of the other parties combined. With respect to ASX-listed companies, the Liberal Party was able to achieve similarly dominant results for all industry sectors except Engineering, from which it received a few thousand dollars less than the ALP over the three years of the study. The Liberal Party was also able to attract donations from every industry sector except Chemicals, from which there were no disclosed donations at all. In total, the level of donations could be said to be financially immaterial from the perspective of the corporate sector. About $29 million in total was donated by corporations to political parties over the three years of the study, which is not a large amount of money compared to the value of the corporate sector. Confining the analysis for the moment to public companies, the three-year figure of $17 million seems even less significant when contrasted with the multi-billion-dollar market capitalisation of ASX-listed companies.121 Although the figures have not been tested for company size, the data intuitively confirms the findings of US studies that, other things being equal, large companies tend to make larger donations than small companies.122 One thing, though, is certain: the data do not allow us to gauge the effect of the donations. Whether the donations have assisted the commercial aspirations of the donors is entirely speculative. A possible conclusion is that the level of donations is hardly cause for concern. But before this conclusion may be made it is important to consider three factors. First, although the figure of $29 million over three years seems relatively small in contrast to the value of the corporate sector, it would be considered a much more significant sum when compared to the budget of the political parties. From the public policy perspective, a key issue is how much leverage a company (or companies) obtains as a result of political donations. This is more a factor of the importance of the donation to the political party than the relative size of the donation compared to the company's own value. Second, from the corporate perspective, it is important that decisions to donate public company funds to political parties are subject to some checks and balances. Typically, these decisions will be made by the board of directors or a senior executive, but the money being donated is not theirs. As a matter of company law it is the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 121 As at 31 December 1998, the market capitalisation of companies listed on the ASX was $536.2 billion: Australian Stock Exchange, Fact Book 1999 (1999) 26. 122 Adams and Hardwick, above n 57, 645, citing studies by R L Watts and J L Zimmerman, 'Towards a Positive Theory of the Determination of Accounting Standards' (1978) 53 Accounting Review 112-34; A Belkaoui and P G Karpik, 'Determinants of the Corporate Decision to Disclose Social Information' (1988) 2(1) Accounting, Auditing and Accountability Journal 36-44; and S A Lenway and K Rehbein, 'Leaders, Followers and Free Riders: An Empirical Test of Variation in Corporate Political Involvement' (1991) 34 Academy of Management Journal 893-905. 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 205 ____________________________________________________________________________________ company's money – and as a matter of substance it is the shareholders' money; it is not the directors' money. Third, for the period of the study (1995/96-1997/98), there were readily available means to circumvent the existing disclosure provisions. The real level of corporate political 'support' would be revealed to be considerably higher if (i) donations made indirectly via clubs, trusts and foundations, and (ii) gifts-in-kind were to be added to the disclosed gifts in money. Indeed, the real level of corporate political support could be several times higher than the figures reported above. It is simply not possible to say because of the inadequate disclosure requirements that operated during the period of the study. The 1999 amendments to the Electoral Act, outlined in Section IVB above, should operate to improve disclosure. However, further reform is needed, as recommended in the next section. VI. OPTIONS FOR REFORM A. Background Shareholders' current powers in relation to political donations are very limited.123 In its recent consultative paper concerning regulation of corporate political donations in the UK, the DTI summarised the current options for a company's shareholders seeking to prevent the directors from making political donations: (a) challenge the donations in court on the grounds that the making of political donations fell outside the objects clause in the company's [constitution] … (b) challenge the donations in court on the grounds that the directors have acted in breach of their fiduciary duties … (c) require the directors to obtain prior shareholder approval by amending the company's [constitution to that effect].124 The first option is, as already discussed,125 of limited applicability in Australia because the doctrine of ultra vires with respect to companies has been abolished. The second option, concerning directors' and officers' duties, has been considered earlier in this article. The DTI paper considered a shareholder lawsuit over a political donation an unlikely event given the courts' traditional reluctance to review the merits of business decisions made by the board,126 and the limited circumstances in which a shareholder may bring an action for breach of directors' duties.127 A similar view was expressed earlier in this article, in relation to Australia. The third option is unlike the first two options, which are reactive in nature. The DTI's main concern with the third option was the unlikelihood that there would be widespread adoption of such a clause in companies' constitutions. History shows that changes to company constitutions are normally board/management-initiated. In widely-held listed companies, it would be very rare for a shareholder-sponsored _____________________________________________________________________________________ 123 Department of Trade and Industry, above n 26, para 4.1. 124 Ibid. 125 See Section IVA above. 126 See, eg, Harlowe's Nominees Pty Ltd v Woodside (Lakes Entrance) Oil NL (1967) 121 CLR 483, 493. 127 Department of Trade and Industry, above n 26, para 4.1. 206 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ proposal for a change to the constitution – which did not enjoy board and management support – to be successful.128 In summary, the options currently available for shareholders of large companies to place checks and balances on their companies' political donations are very limited. But several interested parties – including a UK parliamentary committee,129 the UK government,130 an Australian political party131 and shareholder advisory firms132 – have concluded that leaving the matter of political donations mainly to the directors' discretion gives rise to an accountability problem. Specifically, it is not clear whether a particular donation has been made to serve primarily the interests of the company, or one or more of the company's directors. Reforms have been sought that would provide shareholders and the public generally with greater confidence that, when a company makes a donation to a political party, it is doing so because the donation is demonstrably in the company's interest.133 B. A statutory requirement for prior shareholder approval The Australian Democrats proposals and UK government legislative changes As mentioned earlier, the Australian Democrats have proposed that public companies be required to obtain shareholder approval for their 'donation policies'.134 A similar – but more detailed – proposal was made by the UK Neill Committee. The Committee recommended a change to the Companies Act 1985 (UK) to require prior shareholder authority as a pre-condition to a company making political donations. The specific nature of the reform suggested by the Committee involves: • shareholders voting by ordinary resolution to give the directors a broad enabling authority to exercise discretion in making donations; • the authority would be subject to renewal at every fourth annual general meeting; • the authority would state a limit on the total amount available for political donations over the four years; • 'political donation' would be defined very broadly; and • donations made by a subsidiary would be permissible only if both the subsidiary's shareholder(s) and the shareholders of its holding company had given prior approval.135 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 128 See Geof Stapledon, Sandy Easterbrook, Pru Bennett and Ian Ramsay, Proxy Voting in Australia's Largest Companies (Research Report, Centre for Corporate Law and Securities Regulation and Corporate Governance International, 2000). 129 Neill Committee, above n 21. 130 Department of Trade and Industry, above n 26. 131 Australian Democrats, above n 1. 132 See, eg, Pensions and Investments Research Consultants (PIRC), Trends in Political Donations and Shareholder Authorisation (PIRC, London, 1998). 133 Department of Trade and Industry, above n 26, Foreword. 134 Australian Democrats, above n 1. 135 Neill Committee, above n 21, paras 4.44, 4.45, 6.34-6.37; Recommendation 34; Department of Trade and Industry, above n 26, ch 3, 4. 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 207 ____________________________________________________________________________________ These recommendations have been enacted as ss 139 and 140 (and Schedule 19) of the Political Parties, Elections and Referendums Act 2000 (UK). Recommendation A shareholder-approval provision of the kind recently enacted in the UK should be introduced into the Australian Corporations Act. There are three factors which, taken in combination, support this recommendation. First, when a company's board (or a senior executive) authorises a political donation out of company funds, the money donated – or other benefit provided – does not come from the directors' own funds. The benefit is provided by the company. In an economic sense the benefit is provided by the company's shareholders. Second, a decision to make a political donation will in many cases be materially different from other 'business' decisions made by a large company's board and senior management. The benefit to the company from the donation will in many cases be at best extremely indirect and of uncertain magnitude.136 However well-intentioned, any benefit to the company from this form of 'investment' is often going to be far more speculative than is the case with other investment decisions made by the board and senior management. Third, it is reasonable to assume that a component of management self-interest accompanies many corporate political donations. But the options currently available for shareholders of large companies to place checks and balances on their companies' political donations are very limited. Therefore, it is likely that many political donations made by public companies entail agency costs. Accordingly, imposing an appropriately designed shareholder-approval requirement can be viewed as a justifiable form of regulatory intervention. The likely benefits of an appropriately designed rule would probably outweigh the likely costs. A key benefit would flow from reducing the agency costs that accompany those donations that are motivated largely by management self-interest. The major cost would probably be the management time spent justifying the proposed shareholder resolution.137 Appropriate design of the rule entails, among other things, recognising that: • The benefit from reducing agency costs would be tangible only in mediumsized and large companies – particularly widely-held public companies. This is because, in many proprietary companies, there is significant overlap between the people who manage the company's business and the people who own the company's shares. • Obtaining shareholder approval can be an expensive process for large listed companies. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 136 We are not referring here to donations that are intended to influence a government tender, or in some other way confer a direct financial benefit on the company. Rather, we are referring to the presumably (hopefully) more common variety: where the board is supporting a particular political party due to a commonality of view over major long-term policy issues. 137 Shareholders must be given adequate disclosure about matters on which they are asked to vote: Corporations Act, s 249L(b); Bulfin v Bebarfalds Ltd (1938) 38 SR NSW 423, 440; Chequepoint Securities Ltd v Claremont Petroleum NL (1986) 11 ACLR 94, 96-7; Fraser v NRMA Holdings Ltd (1995) 15 ACSR 590. 208 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ The first point indicates that the rule should be confined to public companies. But to stop circumvention, the rule should be drafted sufficiently widely to catch benefits provided by subsidiaries or other controlled entities of a public company. The second point explains why, under the recent UK changes, approval and subsequent 'renewals' would be spaced four years apart. Of more importance, though, the political donations matter could be added to the agenda for the annual general meeting – a shareholder meeting which all public companies must hold in any event.138 This suggests that the expense attributable to a new shareholder-approval rule is unlikely to be great. As indicated, it would consist largely of management time spent justifying the proposed resolution granting donation-making power to the board. C. Improved disclosure rules The recent UK legislation referred to above provides for a broad definition of a political donation to a registered political party. It means: • any gift to the party of money or other property; • any sponsorship provided in relation to the party; • any subscription or other fee paid for affiliation to, or membership of, the party; • any money spent (otherwise than by or on behalf of the party) in paying any expenses incurred directly or indirectly by the party; • any money lent to the party otherwise than on commercial terms; and • the provision otherwise than on commercial terms of any property, services or facilities for the use or benefit of the party (including the services of any person).139 The Australian Democrats have proposed that public companies be required to make 'full donations disclosure' in their annual report of donations to political parties.140 The proposal appears to mirror the UK position. That is, it seems to be intended to catch all forms of benefit or 'support' provided by public companies to political parties. Presumably, the Democrats intend the rule to catch: • support provided not only by the public company but also by any subsidiary or controlled entity of the public company; and • support provided not only directly to political parties but also indirectly to organisations (clubs, trusts, foundations, etc) that support political parties. The Australian Democrats' proposals provide support for the shareholder-approval rule proposed above. The information produced under a comprehensive disclosure rule would enable shareholders, when considering whether to empower the board to make political donations for the next four years, to make their decision with detailed knowledge of the way in which company funds had been donated in the previous four-year period. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 138 Corporations Act, s 250N. 139 Political Parties, Elections and Referendums Act 2000 (UK), s 50. 140 Australian Democrats, above n 1. 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 209 ____________________________________________________________________________________ VII. CONCLUSION Corporate political donations are of interest for several reasons including: • a concern that commercial interests can be advanced by donating funds to political parties; and • in the case of public companies, that the funds being donated are not those of the directors of the company who make the decision to donate the funds but are the funds of the company's shareholders. In order to ascertain the extent of corporate political donations, the authors conducted a study, the data for which was derived from the annual returns of the major political parties lodged with the Australian Electoral Commission for 1995/96, 1996/97 and 1997/98. Over this three year period, total corporate donations were $29 million. Of this amount: • 64% was donated to the Liberal Party while 23% was donated to the ALP; • over $17 million was donated by public companies (with 63% of this going to the Liberal Party and 29% to the ALP); and • more than $11.5 million was donated by private companies (with 65% of this going to the Liberal Party and 15.5% to the ALP). In Australia, concerns have been expressed about inadequate disclosure requirements for political donations. The Electoral Act requires disclosure of political donations. However, disclosure under this Act is inadequate because it does not require disclosure of 'financial benefits' other than donations and loans made to political parties. For example, it may not catch a bank forgiving a loan made to a political party. In 2000 the Australian Democrats outlined reform proposals: • to require shareholder approval of 'donation policies' of public companies (this mirrors the recent amendments to the Companies Act 1985 (UK) to require that any company wishing to make a donation to a political party in the UK must obtain the prior approval of its shareholders); and • to require 'full donations disclosure' in a public company's annual report. These reforms should be supported. 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 211 ____________________________________________________________________________________ TABLE A: corporate donations 1995—1998 $ ALP Liberal National Democrat Greens One Nation ALP Liberal National Democrat Greens One Nation n= Mean Median 1995-1996 Total Corporate Donations 3,325,949 159 20918 10000 9,481,495 537 17,656 5,000 1,845,850 80 23,073 5,000 113,210 14 8,086 5,000 3,600 2 1,800 1,800 ----14,770,104 % 22.5 64.2 12.5 0.8 0.0 100.0 1995-1996 Total Public Company Donations 2,450,832 77 31,829 20,000 29.1 5,495,130 171 32,135 10,000 65.2 430,272 28 15,367 6,000 5.1 50,000 8 6,250 5,000 0.6 0 0.0 0.0 8,426,234 100.0 1995-1996 Total Private Company Donations ALP Liberal National Democrat Greens One Nation 875,117 82 3,986,365 366 1,415,578 52 63,210 6 3,600 2 6,343,870 10,672 10,892 27,223 10,535 1,800 5,000 5,000 5,000 7,500 1,800 13.8 62.8 22.3 1.0 0.1 0.0 100.0 $ n= Mean Median 1996-1997 Total Corporate Donations 1,271,287 74 17,180 5,750 4,257,876 167 25,496 5,000 641,465 37 17,337 10,000 63,834 2 31,917 31,917 0 0 6,234,462 % 20.4 68.3 10.3 1.0 0.0 100.0 $ n= Mean Median 1997-1998 Total Corporate Donations 2,180,970 112 19,473 10,000 4,801,927 256 18,758 5,000 993,160 107 9,282 5,000 18,759 3 6,253 5,000 0 0 7,994,816 % 27.3 60.1 12.4 0.2 0.0 100.0 1996-1997 1997-1998 Total Public Company Donations Total Public Company Donations 869,887 34 25,065 15,000 21.7 1,659,196 64 25,925 15,000 33.6 2,707,147 72 37,599 15,000 67.5 2,808,886 106 26,499 10,000 56.9 431,680 22 19,622 10,250 10.8 460,834 39 11,816 10,000 9.3 2,292 1 2,292 2,292 0.1 5,000 1 5,000 5,000 0.1 0 0.0 0 0.0 0 0.0 0 0.0 4,011,006 100.0 4,933,916 100.0 1996-1997 Total Private Company Donations 401,400 1,550,729 209,785 61,542 0 0 2,223,456 40 95 15 1 10,035 16,323 13,986 61,542 4,500 5,000 5,000 61,542 1997-1998 Total Private Company Donations 18.1 521,774 69.7 1,993,041 9.4 532,326 2.8 13,759 0.0 0 0.0 0 100.0 3,060,900 48 150 68 2 10,870 13,287 7,828 6,879 5,000 5,000 5,000 6,879 17.0 65.1 17.4 0.4 0.0 $ % Total Corporate Donations — 3 Year Total 6,778,206 23.4 18,541,298 63.9 3,480,475 12.0 195,803 0.7 3,600 0.0 0 28,999,382 100.0 Total Public Donations — 3 year total 4,979,915 28.7 11,011,163 63.4 1,322,786 7.6 57,292 0.3 0 0.0 0 0.0 17,371,156 100.0 Total Private Company Donations— 3 year total 1,798,291 15.5 7,530,135 64.8 2,157,689 18.6 138,511 1.2 3,600 0.0 100.0 11,628,226 100.0 212 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ $ ALP Liberal National Democrat Greens One Nation ALP Liberal National Democrat Greens One Nation n= Mean Median % $ n= Mean Median % 1995-1996 Total Professional Firm Donations 16,932 8 2,117 2,000 11.1 135,448 19 7,129 2,854 88.9 0 0.0 0 0.0 0 0.0 0.0 152,380 100.0 1996-1997 Total Professional Firm Donations 12,00 3 4,000 5,000 17.6 54,304 3 18,101 25,000 79.5 2,000 1 2,000 2,000 2.9 0 0.0 0 0.0 0 0.0 68,304 100.0 1995-1996 Total Lobby Group Donations 3,246,840 18 180,380 26,600 34.6 5,647,687 38 148,623 6,750 60.1 462,633 13 35,587 15,000 4.9 25,000 3 8,333 10,000 0.3 9,975 1 9,975 9,975 0.1 0.0 9,392,135 100.0 1996-1997 Total Lobby Group Donations 2,936,049 9 326,228 50,000 35.8 3,334,432 40 83,361 3,500 40.7 1,928,929 7 275,561 67,000 23.5 0 0.0 0 0.0 0 0.0 8,199,410 100.0 $ n= Mean Median % $ % Total Professional 1997-1998 Firm Donations — Total Professional Firm Donations 3 year total 44,565 3 14,855 3,000 41.6 73,497 22.4 55,615 11 5,056 5,000 51.9 245,367 74.8 7,000 2 3,500 3,500 6.5 9,000 2.7 0 0.0 0 0.0 0 0.0 0 0.0 0 0.0 0 0.0 107,180 100.0 327,864 100.0 Total Lobby Group 1997-1998 Donation s — 3 Total Lobby Group Donations year total 2,615,010 14 186,786 6,000 51.2 8,797,899 38.8 2,204,408 32 68,888 5,000 43.1 11,186,527 49.3 289,952 8 36,244 5,500 5.7 2,681,514 11.8 0 0.0 25,000 0.1 0 0.0 9,975 0.0 0 0.0 0 0.0 5,109,370 100.0 22,700,915 100.0 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 213 ____________________________________________________________________________________ 43,625 6,500 15,000 146,500 103,062 103,062 53,000 70,000 2,000 87,429 62,000 25,500 50,000 0 325,000 52,833 52,833 120,000 0 120,000 63,767 139,800 1,500 0 0 50,000 23,333 25,000 20,000 81,880 65,750 39,500 198,900 122,119 122,119 64,600 72,250 34,000 64,125 82,750 14,333 84,000 20,500 329,500 60,908 60,908 68,950 4,400 133,500 101,893 335,625 11,167 5,000 0 3,500 22,167 56,500 0 60,000 0 0 60,000 233,972 233,972 67,000 65,000 2,000 57,400 32,000 4,400 16,000 0 5,000 180,596 180,596 0 0 0 36,500 25,000 1,500 0 10,000 0 35,000 35,000 0 1 0 0 1 6 6 2 1 1 9 4 2 2 0 1 3 3 0 0 0 3 1 1 0 1 0 1 1 0 Avg to Nat 5 2 2 1 14 14 5 4 1 12 2 6 2 1 1 9 9 2 1 1 7 2 3 1 0 1 3 1 0 No to Nat 409,400 131,500 79,000 198,900 1,709,661 1,709,661 323,000 289,000 34,000 769,500 165,500 86,000 168,000 20,500 329,500 548,176 548,176 137,900 4,400 133,500 713,250 671,250 33,500 5,000 0 3,500 66,500 56,500 0 Total to Nat 4 2 1 1 10 10 4 3 1 7 3 2 1 0 1 6 6 1 0 1 3 1 1 0 0 1 3 2 1 Avg to Lib 174,500 13,000 15,000 146,500 1,030,619 1,030,619 212,000 210,000 2,000 612,000 186,000 51,000 50,000 0 325,000 317,000 317,000 120,000 0 120,000 191,300 139,800 1,500 0 0 50,000 70,000 50,000 20,000 No to Lib 128,780 72,250 47,000 405,400 212,447 212,447 120,400 141,000 38,000 84,641 63,917 23,567 78,000 20,500 659,500 116,197 116,197 128,950 4,400 253,500 117,631 418,025 12,167 5,000 10,000 53,500 34,300 70,750 20,000 Total to Lib No to ALP 5 2 2 1 14 14 5 4 1 17 6 6 3 1 1 9 9 2 1 1 8 2 3 1 1 1 5 2 1 Avg to ALP Total to ALP 643,900 144,500 94,000 405,400 2,974,252 2,974,252 602,000 564,000 38,000 1,438,900 383,500 141,400 234,000 20,500 659,500 1,045,772 1,045,772 257,900 4,400 253,500 941,050 836,050 36,500 5,000 10,000 53,500 171,500 141,500 20,000 Avg. aggregate overall donation Alcohol and Tobacco Brewer (081) Tobacco (083) Tobacco & Food (084) Banking and Finance Banking (161) Building Materials Building Materials (071) Cement (072) Developers and Contractors Building, Contractor (061) Property, Development Manager (062) Residential Developer (063) Developer, Retailer (064) Developer, Finance (065) Diversified Industrial Diversified Industrial (231) Diversified Resources Oil, Steel, Mining (032) Mining, Smelting (033) Energy Oil/gas producer (041) Oil/gas explorer (042) Oil/gas investor (043) Coal (045) Uranium (046) Engineering Heavy Engineering (111) Steel merchants & Agents (112) Number of companies Industry sector Total donated TABLE B: Donations by listed companies by industry group — 3 year total 60,000 0 0 60,000 38,995 38,995 33,500 65,000 2,000 6,378 8,000 2,200 8,000 0 5,000 60,199 60,199 0 0 0 12,167 25,000 1,500 0 10,000 0 35,000 35,000 0 5,000 5,000 414,200 143,200 10,000 5,000 250,000 6,000 253,037 125,520 85,017 6,500 31,000 5,000 170,000 134,000 7,500 28,500 286,000 286,000 1,028,050 1,028,050 662,350 4,800 556,000 10,000 41,000 50,550 341,146 28,490 212,656 100,000 0 0 157,000 40,000 0 0 115,000 2,000 24,000 10,000 4,000 0 10,000 0 39,000 34,000 0 5,000 75,000 75,000 224,500 224,500 255,000 0 245,000 0 0 10,000 100,000 0 100,000 0 0 0 4 2 0 0 1 1 3 1 1 0 1 0 2 1 0 1 2 2 5 5 4 0 3 0 0 1 1 0 1 0 0 0 39,250 20,000 0 0 115,000 2,000 8,000 10,000 4,000 0 10,000 0 19,500 34,000 0 5,000 37,500 37,500 44,900 44,900 63,750 0 81,667 0 0 10,000 100,000 0 100,000 0 5,000 5,000 215,200 68,200 10,000 5,000 130,000 2,000 211,537 108,020 71,017 6,500 21,000 5,000 131,000 100,000 7,500 23,500 166,000 166,000 791,550 791,550 407,350 4,800 311,000 10,000 41,000 40,550 231,146 28,490 102,656 100,000 1 1 8 4 1 1 1 1 22 9 9 1 2 1 5 1 1 3 2 2 6 6 8 1 3 1 2 1 6 3 2 1 5,000 5,000 26,900 17,050 10,000 5,000 130,000 2,000 9,615 12,002 7,891 6,500 10,500 5,000 26,200 100,000 7,500 7,833 83,000 83,000 131,925 131,925 50,919 4,800 103,667 10,000 20,500 40,550 38,524 9,497 51,328 100,000 0 0 42,000 35,000 0 0 5,000 2,000 17,500 7,500 10,000 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 45,000 45,000 12,000 12,000 0 0 0 0 0 0 10,000 0 10,000 0 0 0 3 1 0 0 1 1 3 2 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 2 2 2 2 0 0 0 0 0 0 1 0 1 0 Avg to Nat No to Nat Total to Nat Avg to Lib No to Lib Total to Lib Avg to ALP 5,000 5,000 51,775 35,800 10,000 5,000 250,000 6,000 10,543 13,947 7,729 6,500 15,500 5,000 34,000 134,000 7,500 9,500 143,000 143,000 146,864 146,864 82,794 4,800 185,333 10,000 20,500 50,550 56,858 9,497 106,328 100,000 No to ALP 1 1 8 4 1 1 1 1 24 9 11 1 2 1 5 1 1 3 2 2 7 7 8 1 3 1 2 1 6 3 2 1 Total to ALP Avg. aggregate overall donation Engineering contractors (114) Light engineering (115) Food and Household Food (091) Flour miller, baker (092) Miller, Baker, Food (093) Soft drink, Confectionery (094) Household goods, Chemicals (096) Gold Gold Producer (011) Gold Explorer (012) Gold, oil (014) Gold, copper (015) Gold, Investment (016) Health Care and Biotechnology Pharmaceutical (211) Biotechnology (212) Hospital Management (213) Infrastructure and Utilities Electricity, Gas (052) Insurance Insurance Company (171) Investment and Financial Services Investment Trust/Company (191) Equity Investor (192) Property investor (193) Trustee company (194) Miscellaneous financial services (195) Media Diversified Media (151) Television (153) Radio (154) Number of companies Industry sector Total donated 214 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ 0 0 14,000 35,000 0 0 5,000 2,000 5,833 3,750 10,000 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 22,500 22,500 6,000 6,000 0 0 0 0 0 0 10,000 0 10,000 0 5 0 0 2 1 1 1 4 2 0 1 0 1 1 1 0 0 2 1 1 0 0 0 0 5 2 0 3 3 1 1 1 11,693 42,375 1,817 7,750 9,537 2,000 4,000 99,286 170,250 10,000 2,000 2,000 0 495,000 495,000 14,500 14,500 115,750 215,375 133,000 7,500 5,321 6,750 2,462 182,107 53,917 10,000 367,667 52,000 59,000 45,000 0 9,500 0 0 7,500 0 2,000 0 85,000 85,000 0 0 0 0 20,000 20,000 0 0 121,000 96,000 25,000 0 0 0 0 10,000 10,000 0 0 15,000 5,000 0 10,000 3 0 0 2 0 1 0 2 2 0 0 0 0 1 1 0 0 2 1 1 0 0 0 0 1 1 0 0 2 1 0 1 Avg to Nat No to Nat 12 2 3 2 3 1 1 7 4 1 1 1 0 1 1 1 1 5 2 1 2 3 2 1 7 3 1 3 2 1 1 0 Total to Nat 140,310 84,750 5,450 15,500 28,610 2,000 4,000 695,000 681,000 10,000 2,000 2,000 0 495,000 495,000 14,500 14,500 578,750 430,750 133,000 15,000 15,962 13,500 2,462 1,274,750 161,750 10,000 1,103,000 104,000 59,000 45,000 0 Avg to Lib Avg to ALP 3,600 0 0 3,750 6,500 2,000 2,000 20,000 37,500 0 2,500 0 2,500 125,000 125,000 0 0 132,990 165,980 100,000 0 0 0 0 82,860 25,000 0 121,433 22,267 20,000 1,800 45,000 No to Lib 18,000 0 0 7,500 6,500 2,000 2,000 80,000 75,000 0 2,500 0 2,500 125,000 125,000 0 0 265,980 165,980 100,000 0 0 0 0 414,300 50,000 0 364,300 66,800 20,000 1,800 45,000 No to ALP 13,984 42,375 1,817 15,250 11,703 6,000 6,000 107,500 210,250 10,000 4,500 2,000 2,500 640,000 640,000 14,500 14,500 193,146 346,365 258,000 7,500 5,321 6,750 2,462 212,381 55,438 10,000 489,100 61,933 84,000 46,800 55,000 Total to ALP 12 2 3 2 3 1 1 8 4 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 5 2 1 2 3 2 1 8 4 1 3 3 1 1 1 Total to Lib 167,810 84,750 5,450 30,500 35,110 6,000 6,000 860,000 841,000 10,000 4,500 2,000 2,500 640,000 640,000 14,500 14,500 965,730 692,730 258,000 15,000 15,962 13,500 2,462 1,699,050 221,750 10,000 1,467,300 185,800 84,000 46,800 55,000 Avg. aggregate overall donation Miscellaneous Industrials Miscellaneous Industrials (221) Miscellaneous services (222) Agriculture and Related Services (224) Automotive and Related Services (225) Entrepreneurial Investors (227) High technology (228) Other Metals Diversified Mining (021) Base metals (022) Mining (producers) (026) Mining (explorer) (027) Mining investment (028) Paper and Packaging Forest products, Trade (122) Property Trusts Property Trust (201) Retail Retail (131) Wholesaler, retail (132) Retail, investments (134) Telecommunications Network operator (181) Equipment, services (183) Tourism and Leisure Casinos/gaming (241) Hotel Operations (242) Leisure Activities (243) Transport Transport (141) International Transport (142) Transport other services (143) Number of companies Industry sector Total donated 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 215 ____________________________________________________________________________________ 3,167 0 0 3,750 0 2,000 0 42,500 42,500 0 0 0 0 20,000 20,000 0 0 60,500 96,000 25,000 0 0 0 0 10,000 10,000 0 0 7,500 5,000 0 10,000 216 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Total to ALP Avg. aggregate overall donation Total donated 10 5 7 103,062 82,860 87,429 1,709,661 1,274,750 769,500 14 7 12 122,119 182,107 64,125 233,972 10,000 57,400 6 1 9 38,995 10,000 6,378 1,045,772 1,028,050 965,730 941,050 860,000 662,350 9 7 5 8 8 8 116,197 146,864 193,146 117,631 107,500 82,794 317,000 224,500 265,980 191,300 80,000 255,000 6 5 2 3 4 4 52,833 44,900 132,990 63,767 20,000 63,750 548,176 791,550 578,750 713,250 695,000 407,350 9 6 5 7 7 8 60,908 131,925 115,750 101,893 99,286 50,919 180,596 12,000 121,000 36,500 85,000 0 3 2 2 3 2 0 60,199 6,000 60,500 12,167 42,500 0 643,900 640,000 602,000 414,200 341,146 286,000 257,900 253,037 185,800 171,500 170,000 5 1 5 8 6 2 2 24 3 5 5 128,780 640,000 120,400 51,775 56,858 143,000 128,950 10,543 61,933 34,300 34,000 174,500 125,000 212,000 157,000 100,000 75,000 120,000 24,000 66,800 70,000 39,000 4 1 4 4 1 2 1 3 3 3 2 43,625 125,000 53,000 39,250 100,000 37,500 120,000 8,000 22,267 23,333 19,500 409,400 495,000 323,000 215,200 231,146 166,000 137,900 211,537 104,000 66,500 131,000 5 1 5 8 6 2 2 22 2 3 5 81,880 495,000 64,600 26,900 38,524 83,000 68,950 9,615 52,000 22,167 26,200 60,000 20,000 67,000 42,000 10,000 45,000 0 17,500 15,000 35,000 0 1 1 2 3 1 2 0 3 2 1 0 60,000 20,000 33,500 14,000 10,000 22,500 0 5,833 7,500 35,000 0 167,810 15,962 14,500 12 3 1 13,984 5,321 14,500 18,000 0 0 5 0 0 3,600 0 0 140,310 15,962 14,500 12 3 1 11,693 5,321 14,500 9,500 0 0 3 0 0 3,167 0 0 No to Lib 1,030,619 414,300 612,000 Total to Lib 212,447 212,381 84,641 Avg to ALP 14 8 17 No to ALP 2,974,252 1,699,050 1,438,900 Number of companies Avg to Nat 21 22 23 No to Nat 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 Total to Nat 4 5 6 7 8 9 Banking and Finance Tourism and Leisure Developers and Contractors Diversified Industrial Insurance Retail Energy Other Metals Investment and Financial Services Alcohol and Tobacco Paper and Packaging Building Materials Food and Household Media Infrastructure and Utilities Diversified Resources Gold Transport Engineering Health Care and Biotechnology Miscellaneous Industrials Telecommunications Property Trusts Avg to Lib 1 2 3 Industry sector Rank TABLE C: Total donations by industry 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 217 ____________________________________________________________________________________ 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 495,000 122,119 182,107 115,750 131,925 83,000 68,950 81,880 64,600 101,893 60,908 99,286 64,125 20,000 233,972 10,000 121,000 12,000 45,000 0 60,000 67,000 36,500 180,596 85,000 57,400 1 6 1 2 2 2 0 1 2 3 3 2 9 20,000 38,995 10,000 60,500 6,000 22,500 0 60,000 33,500 12,167 60,199 42,500 6,378 662,350 8 82,794 255,000 4 63,750 407,350 8 50,919 0 0 0 185,800 341,146 414,200 171,500 170,000 3 6 8 5 5 61,933 56,858 51,775 34,300 34,000 66,800 100,000 157,000 70,000 39,000 3 1 4 3 2 22,267 100,000 39,250 23,333 19,500 104,000 231,146 215,200 66,500 131,000 2 6 8 3 5 52,000 38,524 26,900 22,167 26,200 15,000 10,000 42,000 35,000 0 2 1 3 1 0 7,500 10,000 14,000 35,000 0 14,500 167,810 253,037 15,962 1 12 24 3 14,500 13,984 10,543 5,321 0 18,000 24,000 0 0 5 3 0 0 3,600 8,000 0 14,500 140,310 211,537 15,962 1 12 22 3 14,500 11,693 9,615 5,321 0 9,500 17,500 0 0 3 3 0 0 3,167 5,833 0 No to Nat Avg to Nat 1 14 7 5 6 2 2 5 5 7 9 7 12 Total to Nat 495,000 1,709,661 1,274,750 578,750 791,550 166,000 137,900 409,400 323,000 713,250 548,176 695,000 769,500 Avg to Lib 125,000 103,062 82,860 132,990 44,900 37,500 120,000 43,625 53,000 63,767 52,833 20,000 87,429 No to Lib 1 10 5 2 5 2 1 4 4 3 6 4 7 Total to Lib 125,000 1,030,619 414,300 265,980 224,500 75,000 120,000 174,500 212,000 191,300 317,000 80,000 612,000 Avg to ALP 640,000 212,447 212,381 193,146 146,864 143,000 128,950 128,780 120,400 117,631 116,197 107,500 84,641 No to ALP 1 14 8 5 7 2 2 5 5 8 9 8 17 Total to ALP 640,000 2,974,252 1,699,050 965,730 1,028,050 286,000 257,900 643,900 602,000 941,050 1,045,772 860,000 1,438,900 Total donated Avg.aggregate overall donation 14 Paper and Packaging Banking and Finance Tourism and Leisure Retail Insurance Infrastructure and Utilities Diversified Resources Alcohol and Tobacco Building Materials Energy Diversified Industrial Other Metals Developers and Contractors Investment and Financial Services Transport Media Food and Household Engineering Health Care and Biotechnology Property Trusts Miscellaneous Industrials Gold Telecommunications Number of companies 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 Industry sector Rank Table D: Average corporate donation by industry 218 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Table E: Industry corporate donations — by party 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 Banking and Finance Developers and Contractors Tourism and Leisure Diversified Industrial Avg to ALP No to ALP Total to ALP Industry sector Rank Avg to ALP No to ALP Ranked by average Total to ALP Industry sector Rank Ranked by total 1,030,619 612,000 10 7 103,062 87,429 1 2 Retail Paper and Packaging 265,980 125,000 2 1 132,990 125,000 414,300 317,000 5 6 82,860 52,833 3 4 Diversified Resources Banking and Finance 1 10 120,000 103,062 Retail Investment and Financial Services Insurance Building Materials Energy 265,980 255,000 2 4 132,990 63,750 5 6 Media Developers and Contractors 120,000 1,030,61 9 100,000 612,000 1 7 100,000 87,429 224,500 212,000 191,300 5 4 3 44,900 53,000 63,767 7 8 9 414,300 191,300 255,000 5 3 4 82,860 63,767 63,750 Alcohol and Tobacco Food and Household Paper and Packaging Diversified Resources Media Other Metals Infrastructure and Utilities Engineering Transport Health Care and Biotechnology Gold Miscellaneous Industrials Property Trusts Telecommunications 174,500 157,000 125,000 120,000 100,000 80,000 75,000 70,000 66,800 39,000 4 4 1 1 1 4 2 3 3 2 43,625 39,250 125,000 120,000 100,000 20,000 37,500 23,333 22,267 19,500 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 212,000 317,000 224,500 174,500 157,000 75,000 70,000 66,800 80,000 39,000 4 6 5 4 4 2 3 3 4 2 53,000 52,833 44,900 43,625 39,250 37,500 23,333 22,267 20,000 19,500 24,000 18,000 0 0 3 5 0 0 8,000 3,600 0 0 20 21 22 23 Tourism and Leisure Energy Investment and Financial Services Building Materials Diversified Industrial Insurance Alcohol and Tobacco Food and Household Infrastructure and Utilities Engineering Transport Other Metals Health Care and Biotechnology Gold Miscellaneous Industrials Property Trusts Telecommunications 24,000 18,000 0 0 3 5 0 0 8,000 3,600 0 0 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 219 ____________________________________________________________________________________ 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 14 7 6 12 122,119 182,107 131,925 64,125 1 2 3 4 Paper and Packaging Tourism and Leisure Insurance Banking and Finance 713,250 695,000 578,750 548,176 495,000 409,400 407,350 7 7 5 9 1 5 8 101,893 99,286 115,750 60,908 495,000 81,880 50,919 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 323,000 231,146 215,200 211,537 5 6 8 22 64,600 38,524 26,900 9,615 12 13 14 15 Infrastructure and Utilities Miscellaneous Industrials Diversified Resources 166,000 2 83,000 16 140,310 137,900 12 2 11,693 68,950 17 18 Health Care and Biotechnology Transport Engineering Telecommunications Property Trusts 131,000 5 26,200 104,000 66,500 15,962 14,500 2 3 3 1 52,000 22,167 5,321 14,500 Avg to Lib 1,709,661 1,274,750 791,550 769,500 No to Lib Banking and Finance Tourism and Leisure Insurance Developers and Contractors Energy Other Metals Retail Diversified Industrial Paper and Packaging Alcohol and Tobacco Investment and Financial Services Building Materials Media Food and Household Gold Total to Lib Avg to Lib No to Lib Total to Lib Industry sector 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 Ranked by average Rank 1 2 3 4 Industry sector Rank Ranked by total 495,000 1,274,750 791,550 1,709,661 1 7 6 14 495,000 182,107 131,925 122,119 Retail Energy Other Metals Infrastructure and Utilities Alcohol and Tobacco Diversified Resources Building Materials 578,750 713,250 695,000 166,000 409,400 137,900 323,000 5 7 7 2 5 2 5 115,750 101,893 99,286 83,000 81,880 68,950 64,600 Developers and Contractors Diversified Industrial Transport Investment and Financial Services Media 769,500 548,176 104,000 407,350 12 9 2 8 64,125 60,908 52,000 50,919 231,146 6 38,524 215,200 131,000 8 5 26,900 26,200 19 Food and Household Health Care and Biotechnology Engineering 66,500 3 22,167 20 21 22 23 Property Trusts Miscellaneous Industrials Gold Telecommunications 14,500 140,310 211,537 15,962 1 12 22 3 14,500 11,693 9,615 5,321 220 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 6 3 2 2 2 1 9 38,995 60,199 60,500 42,500 33,500 60,000 6,378 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 45,000 2 22,500 8 42,000 36,500 35,000 20,000 17,500 15,000 12,000 10,000 10,000 9,500 0 0 3 3 1 1 3 2 2 1 1 3 0 0 14,000 12,167 35,000 20,000 5,833 7,500 6,000 10,000 10,000 3,167 0 0 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 0 0 0 21 0 0 0 0 0 0 22 23 121,000 180,596 60,000 85,000 233,972 35,000 67,000 2 3 1 2 6 1 2 60,500 60,199 60,000 42,500 38,995 35,000 33,500 Infrastructure and Utilities 45,000 2 22,500 Paper and Packaging Food and Household Energy Tourism and Leisure Media Transport Developers and Contractors Insurance Gold Miscellaneous Industrials Diversified Resources Investment and Financial Services Health Care and Biotechnology Property Trusts Telecommunications 20,000 42,000 36,500 10,000 10,000 15,000 57,400 12,000 17,500 9,500 0 0 1 3 3 1 1 2 9 2 3 3 0 0 20,000 14,000 12,167 10,000 10,000 7,500 6,378 6,000 5,833 3,167 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 Avg to Nat Retail Diversified Industrial Alcohol and Tobacco Other Metals Banking and Finance Engineering Building Materials No to Nat Rank Avg to Nat No to Nat 233,972 180,596 121,000 85,000 67,000 60,000 57,400 Total to Nat 8 Banking and Finance Diversified Industrial Retail Other Metals Building Materials Alcohol and Tobacco Developers and Contractors Infrastructure and Utilities Food and Household Energy Engineering Paper and Packaging Gold Transport Insurance Tourism and Leisure Media Miscellaneous Industrials Diversified Resources Investment and Financial Services Health Care and Biotechnology Property Trusts Telecommunications Industry sector 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 Ranked by average Total to Nat Rank Industry sector Ranked by total 2001 Political Donations by Australian Companies 221 ____________________________________________________________________________________ TABLE F: Top 10 ASX-listed company donors Company $A Westpac Banking Corporation 1,272,346 Village Roadshow Limited 1,124,800 Santos Limited 833,800 WMC Limited 778,500 Coles Myer Limited 687,730 Lend Lease Corporation Limited 669,500 Amcor Limited 640,000 HIH Winterthur 462,000 National Australia Bank 445,330 Boral Limited 420,000 IN THE WAKE OF TEOH: FINDING AN APPROPRIATE GOVERNMENT RESPONSE Wendy Lacey* INTRODUCTION Few cases of recent times, beyond the decisions of Mabo1 and Wik,2 could rival Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v Teoh,3 for the dramatic response it provoked in political, legal and academic circles. In the aftermath of the High Court's decision in Teoh came three Commonwealth Bills,4 one state Act,5 several 'executive statements' at both the Federal and state level,6 and numerous academic commentaries.7 Yet, despite the many attempts to override the decision by successive federal governments, the Teoh principle continues to apply to the administrative decisions made at the federal _____________________________________________________________________________________ * BA (Hons) LLB (Hons) (Tas), PhD Candidate, University of Tasmania. The author would like to acknowledge the kind assistance of Professor Ryszard Piotrowicz, Mr Rick Snell and Mr Michael Stokes in offering comments on an earlier draft of this article. 1 Mabo v Queensland [No.2] (1992) 175 CLR 1. 2 Wik Peoples v Queensland (1996) 187 CLR 1. 3 Minister for Immigration & Ethnic Affairs v Teoh (1995) 183 CLR 273 ('Teoh'). 4 Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Bill 1995, Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Bill 1997, Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Bill 1999. 5 Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Act 1995 (SA). 6 Gareth Evans and Michael Lavarch, 'International Treaties and the High Court Decision in Teoh', Joint Statement by the Minister for Foreign Affairs and the Attorney General, May 10 1995, A Downer, 'Executive Statement on the Effect of Treaties in Administrative DecisionMaking' (1997) 8 Public Law Review 120. See also the 'Executive Statements' issued by the South Australian and Western Australian Governments, (1996) 17 Australian Yearbook of International Law 554. 7 Leslie Katz, 'A Teoh FAQ' (1998) 16 AIAL Forum 1; Anne Twomey, 'Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v Teoh' (1995) 23 Federal Law Review 348; Margaret Allars, 'One Small Step for Legal Doctrine, One Giant Leap Towards Integrity in Government: Teoh's Case and the Internationalisation of Administrative Law' (1995) 17 Sydney Law Review 202; S Sheridan, 'Legitimate Expectations: Where Does the Law Now Lie?' (1998) 87 Canberra Bulletin of Public Administration 125-133; Kristen Walker, 'Who's The Boss? The Judiciary, the Executive, the Parliament and the Protection of Human Rights' (1995) 25 Western Australian Law Review 238; Ryszard Piotrowicz, 'Unincorporated Treaties in Australian Law: The Official Response to the Teoh Decision' (1997) 71 Australian Law Journal 503; Ryszard Piotrowicz, 'Unincorporated Treaties in Australian law' (1996) Public Law 190; PW Perry, 'At the Intersection: Australian Law and International Law' (1997) 71 Australian Law Journal 841. 220 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ level.8 The third of the Commonwealth Bills aimed at over-riding the Teoh principle of legitimate expectation progressed only as far as its predecessors, with its debate in the Senate having been adjourned on 5 April, 2001. It is unlikely that enactment of the proposed Bill would have laid the Teoh principle finally to rest, and developments since the last Senate Inquiry conducted in 1997 raise further issues pertaining to the original High Court decision. In particular, subsequent case law has provided clear judicial statements regarding the effectiveness (or ineffectiveness) of earlier executive statements issued by successive federal governments, as well as outlining what constitutes a legally enforceable 'executive indication to the contrary'.9 In addition to recent developments on the domestic front, the proposed Bill had also been criticised by one international body for being inconsistent with Australia's international legal obligations, with the recommendation that it be withdrawn.10 Given the very minor differences between the third Bill and its two predecessors, this charge could also have been laid in respect of each of the earlier Bills.11 These recent developments place commentators and politicians in a better position to evaluate the impact of Teoh and the appropriateness of legislative and executive responses to it. In doing so, consideration must be given to broader issues, both domestic and international, associated with Australia's treaty involvement. While successive governments have struggled to pass anti-Teoh legislation prior to the prorogation of Parliament, further consideration of the Teoh decision by the Federal Court has identified a more appropriate and effective response to the decision by using detailed and specific executive measures. The use of these measures, as an alternative to generic legislation, should be preferred as they would alleviate the problems contained in the proposed legislation, would be more consistent with the reforms improving executive accountability in treaty-making, and would be far less likely to damage Australia's international standing than the proposed Act. With the new term _____________________________________________________________________________________ 8 It is doubtful whether the decision extends to administrative decisions made at the state level, at least in the context of legitimate expectations arising out of the act of ratification (an exclusive act of the federal executive). However, the relevance of international instruments may arise on the basis of procedural fairness or other common law principles applicable to administrative decisions made at the state level. South Australian legislation is premised on the fact that Teoh may apply within the States, and precludes any means by which international instruments may affect a decision, with the exception of instances where a decision-maker has regard to the instrument as a matter relevant: Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Act 1995 (SA) s 3. On the question of whether Teoh even applies to administrative decisions made at state level see also, Kristen Walker, 'Treaties and The Internationalisation of Australian Law', in Cheryl Saunders (ed), Courts of Final Jurisdiction: The Mason Court in Australia (1996) 224. 9 Teoh (1995) 183 CLR 273, 291 (Mason CJ and Deane J). 10 Concluding Observations of the Human Rights Committee: Australia. 28/07/2000. CCPR/CO/69/AUS. 11 The 1997 and 1999 Bills are exactly the same. The 1995 Bill (introduced during Labor's term in office) was more detailed in its references to the exclusion of accepted uses of international instruments in domestic law (clause 6), and of the availability of remedies or redress for alleged breaches of Australia's international obligations (clause 7). The 1995 Bill did not, however, include provision for excluding the operation of its operative clause where state enactments applied to decisions at the state level (as was provided under clause 6 of the 1997 and 1999 Bills). 2001 In the Wake of Teoh 221 ____________________________________________________________________________________ of Parliament comes an opportunity for government to re-evaluate the response to Teoh, and to formulate an appropriate policy that takes into consideration these recent developments. Notwithstanding the failure of the third anti-Teoh Bill to be passed prior to the calling of an election (though its ultimate passage was doubtful in any event), the perceived problem of Teoh itself remains. The decision continues to bind administrative decision-makers, and executive statements to the contrary have had no legal effect. While both major parties continue to support anti-Teoh legislation, despite disagreeing on its proposed form, further attempts at overriding the High Court decision through legislation remain a strong possibility. For as long as decision-makers continue to be bound by Teoh, federal governments will be forced to deal with its consequences. How well governments deal with the issue, and with avoiding the potential effects of their own measures taken in response to Teoh (both domestically and internationally), ultimately depends on the nature of their policy approach. In this article I advocate a particular approach to the decision in Teoh that differs from policies adopted during the last three consecutive terms of Federal Parliament. I advocate an approach based on an understanding of the issues that incorporates developments since the decision was first handed down, rather than on the concerns that informed the initial executive and legislative responses to the decision. Accordingly, I propose that executive measures be adopted in specific domestic contexts and with detailed guidelines tailored to that context, rather than the adoption of a policy which rests on generic anti-Teoh legislation as its cornerstone. These conclusions are drawn through an analysis of several complex aspects associated with the decision in Teoh, and of the role that government plays in controlling the domestic effect of international legal standards. Consequently, this article is divided into a number of sections, beginning with a consideration of the decision in Teoh, and of the responses of successive federal governments. Those sections are followed by an analysis of recent decisions of the Federal Court that have provided clarification on issues relating to the effectiveness of government action that seeks to negate the effects of Teoh. In light of these legal developments, and of the reforms implemented in respect of the treaty-making process in 1996, the approach of successive governments is evaluated in the broader context of issues pertaining to executive accountability and the treaty process. In addition to highlighting the underlying inconsistency of the present approach adopted by government, consequences associated with the enactment of anti-Teoh legislation are considered. These include the potential failure of the proposed legislation to fully achieve its intended effect in domestic law and the almost certain adverse consequences for Australia on the international legal plane. MINISTER FOR IMMIGRATION AND ETHNIC AFFAIRS V TEOH The High Court handed down its decision in Teoh at the same time that a Senate Committee Inquiry was receiving submissions in respect of the treaty process.12 Part _____________________________________________________________________________________ 12 A reference was made to the Senate Legal and Constitutional References Committee on December 8, 1994, to inquire into the Commonwealth's treaty-making and external affairs powers. For the Final Report see, Trick or Treaty? Commonwealth Power to make and Implement 222 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ of the backdrop against which the initial reference was made to the Committee was the Toonen13 decision, in which the United Nations Human Rights Committee found that Australia (through sections of Tasmania's Criminal Code) was in breach of its obligations under the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR).14 Consequently, the climate in which the decision was handed down was one where much controversy centred on the level of executive accountability surrounding Australia's treaty participation. This issue emerged in the 1990s to replace the controversy surrounding the Commonwealth's external affairs power and the implementation of treaties – an issue which had dominated political and legal commentary during the 1980s.15 Both the facts and proceedings of Teoh have been outlined extensively by commentators elsewhere,16 and need not be reproduced here. What is necessary, however, is to reconsider the legal developments made in that case. The High Court in Teoh re-articulated the law in respect of unincorporated treaties in domestic law, yet employed the concept of 'legitimate expectation' used in administrative law contexts to extend the law. The Court restated the rule that the provisions of a ratified treaty do not form part of Australian law unless validly incorporated by domestic legislation.17 The Court also affirmed the accepted rule that ratification will have significance for Australian law through the interpretation of legislation where provisions are ambiguous,18 and through its legitimate influence on the development of the common law.19 On this latter use, however, Mason CJ and Deane J advocated a cautious approach, stating that, '[j]udicial development of the common law must not be seen as a backdoor means of importing an unincorporated convention into Australian law'.20 Their Honours listed a number of relevant factors which should be considered before such use of an unincorporated treaty is made, including, 'the nature of the relevant provision, the extent to which it has been accepted by the international community, the _____________________________________________________________________________________ Treaties, Report by the Senate Legal and Constitutional References Committee, November 1995. 13 Nicholas Toonen v Australia, Communication No. 488/1992: Australia. 04/04/94. CCPR/C/50/D/488/1992 ('Toonen'). 14 For a detailed analysis of the issues raised in Toonen, see Sarah Joseph, 'Gay Rights Under the ICCPR: Commentary on Toonen v Australia' (1994) 13 University of Tasmania Law Review 392-411; Wayne Morgan, 'Identifying Evil for What It Is: Tasmania, Sexual Perversity and the United Nations' (1994) 19 Melbourne University Law Review 740. 15 See for example, Cheryl Saunders, 'The External Affairs Power in the Australian Constitution' (1994) 24 International Law News 36-40; DR Rothwell, 'The High Court and the External Affairs Power: A Consideration of its Outer and Inner Limits' (1993) 15 Adelaide Law Review 209-240; RD Lumb, 'The External Affairs Power and Constitutional Reform' (1988) 62 Australian Law Journal 679-689. 16 See for example, Katz, above n 7, 1-14; Twomey, above n 7, 348-361; Allars, above n 7, 202241; Sheridan, above n 7, 125-133; Walker, above n 7, 238-254; Piotrowicz (1997), above n 7, 503-506; Piotrowicz (1996), above n 7, 190-195; Perry, above n 7, 841-859. 17 Teoh (1995) 183 CLR 273, 286-287 (Mason CJ and Deane J). 18 Ibid, 287 (relying on the decisions in Chu Kheng Lim v Minister for Immigration (1992) 176 CLR 1, 38, and Polites v Commonwealth (1945) 70 CLR 60, 68-69, 77, 80-81. 19 Teoh (1995) 183 CLR 273, 288 (Mason CJ and Deane J) (relying on the decisions in Mabo v Queensland [No.2] (1992) 175 CLR 1, 42, and Dietrich v The Queen (1992) 177 CLR 292, 321, 360). 20 Ibid, 288. 2001 In the Wake of Teoh 223 ____________________________________________________________________________________ purpose which it is intended to serve and its relationship to the existing principles of our domestic law'.21 The use of unincorporated treaties in these contexts, however, were not the controversial aspects of the High Court's decision. The controversial feature of the Court's decision was the use of the doctrine of 'legitimate expectation' by the majority judges, Mason CJ and Deane and Toohey JJ. The invocation of the doctrine, which had been developed in a number of administrative law cases,22 was effected by relying on the principle stated in Minister for Foreign Affairs and Trade v Magno,23 and Tavita v Minister for Immigration,24 that ratification of a treaty should not be dismissed as a 'merely platitudinous or ineffectual act'.25 Using this principle, Mason CJ and Deane J employed the legitimate expectation doctrine as follows: [r]atification of a convention is a positive statement by the executive government of this country to the world and to the Australian people that the executive government and its agencies will act in accordance with the Convention. That positive statement is an adequate foundation for a legitimate expectation, absent statutory or executive indications to the contrary, that administrative decision-makers will act in conformity with the Convention…It is not necessary that the person seeking to set up such a legitimate expectation should be aware of the Convention or should personally entertain the expectation; it is enough that the expectation is reasonable in the sense that there are adequate materials to support it.26 The effect of the legitimate expectation was not to give the provisions of a treaty the domestic legal status of a rule of law, thereby compelling a decision-maker to act in accordance with the treaty. Rather, its effect was that, 'if a decision-maker proposes to make a decision inconsistent with a legitimate expectation, procedural fairness requires that the persons affected should be given notice and an adequate opportunity of presenting a case against the taking of such a course'.27 In legal terms, as others have noted,28 the decision of the High Court in Teoh did not involve a major doctrinal leap, but merely an extension of the legitimate expectation rule to a new factual context – the ratification of treaties. Though it has been argued otherwise,29 the decision did not infringe the accepted rule that treaties do not form part of the domestic law until validly incorporated by legislation, as a legitimate expectation only creates a _____________________________________________________________________________________ 21 Ibid. 22 Schmidt v Secretary of State for Home Affairs [1969] 2 Ch 149, (Lord Denning); Heatley v Tasmanian Racing and Gaming Commission (1977) 137 CLR 487; FAI Insurances Ltd v Winnecke (1982) 151 CLR 342; Attorney-General of Hong Kong v Ng Yuen Shiu [1983] 2 AC 629; Council of Civil Service Unions v Minister for the Civil Service (GCHQ) [1985] AC 374; Haoucher v Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs (1990) 169 CLR 648. 23 (1992) 37 FCR 298. 24 [1994] 2 NZLR 257. 25 Minister for Foreign Affairs and Trade v Magno (1992) 37 FCR 298, 343; Tavita v Minister for Immigration [1994] 2 NZLR 257, 266. 26 Teoh (1995) 183 CLR 273, 291 (Mason CJ and Deane J). 27 Ibid, 291-292. 28 Allars, above n 7, 224-225. 29 Senate Legal and Constitutional References Committee, Submissions to the Inquiry into the Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Bill 1997 (1997) (hereinafter referred to as Submissions), Volume 2, Submissions No.41, 216. See also, Darryl Williams, 'International Law and Responsible Engagement', ANSZIL-ASIL Conference, Keynote Address, Australian National University, 29 June 2000 (copy on file with author). 224 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ procedural right and does not confer substantive protection.30 However, the response of successive governments has been that even procedural rights arising out of the ratification of a treaty should be effected by the Parliament and not through executive action.31 THE GOVERNMENT RESPONSE TO TEOH In their response to the Teoh decision, the then Labor Federal Government purported to make 'an executive indication to the contrary' pursuant to the judgment of Mason CJ and Deane J.32 This statement attempted to prevent the creation of legitimate expectations arising out of the ratification of a treaty and was expressed in general terms. In addition, the Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Bill 1995 was introduced into Parliament. The Bill was referred to the Senate Legal and Constitutional References Committee which, by majority, recommended its enactment without amendment.33 However, the calling of a federal election meant that the Bill lapsed. Following a change of government in 1997, the newly-elected Coalition Government issued their own executive statement, intended to replace the one issued in 1995.34 They also introduced a 'statutory indication to the contrary' with a second anti-Teoh Bill in 1997, which once again failed to be passed during the Government's first term. The second Bill was also the subject of a Senate Committee Inquiry,35 yet one which saw a shift in support by the Labor Party towards the form of the second Bill. While still supporting the necessity for such legislation, the Labor Party advocated amendments which would effectively include a statement outlining the recognised uses of unincorporated treaties in domestic law – those uncontentious aspects of the Teoh decision.36 The rationale for this stance rested on the adverse response the legislation would be likely to invoke from the international community. This position of the Labor Party has effectively been retained in respect of the third Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Bill, introduced in late 1999. The third of the proposed anti-Teoh Bills passed through the House of Representatives in May of 2000, though its debate in the Senate was adjourned in April 2001.37 With several months still remaining before the next federal election, the Bill still retained some chance of being passed, at that time. Obviously the fate of the Bill _____________________________________________________________________________________ 30 Allars, above n 7, 231. 31 Submissions, Vol.2, No.41 216. See also Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Bill 1997, Explanatory Memorandum. 32 Gareth Evans and Michael Lavarch, 'International Treaties and the High Court Decision in Teoh' Joint Statement by the Minister for Foreign Affairs and the Attorney-General, 10 May 1995. 33 Report of the Senate Legal and Constitutional Legislation Committee, Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) 1995, tabled on 28 September 1995. 34 Downer, above n 6. 35 Report of the Senate Legal and Constitutional Legislation Committee, Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Bill 1997, tabled on 20 October 1997. 36 See Robert McClelland MHR, 'Labor calls for greater certainty in implementation of international conventions', Press Release, 9 December 1999. 37 Senate Daily Bills Update, as at COB 9 August 2001, available at <http://www.aph.gov.au/legis.htm> (21 August 2001). 2001 In the Wake of Teoh 225 ____________________________________________________________________________________ depended heavily on the priority given to it in the Senate list for 2001, during a time when it had been readily acknowledged that, 'there [we]re a lot of things … before the Senate'.38 However, even if time had permitted, given the Australian Democrats' opposition to the Bill, the Coalition may have been forced to accept the proposed amendments of the Labor Party to ensure its successful passage. Beyond the problem of time, Labor's approach, therefore represented the only practical difficulty in respect of the legislation's passage. Yet, both the legislation and the official positions of each of the political parties were founded on earlier assessments. These assessments included, not only the anticipated impact of Teoh, but also a growing perception that executive statements to the contrary were potentially legally ineffective if issued well beyond the time of ratification and in regard to many treaties (but particularly human rights treaties). Since that time, members of the Federal Court have further elaborated on the Teoh principle, confirming the Government's concerns over the two Executive Statements, but also identifying clear guidelines for the making of valid executive directions or policies in specific contexts.39 RECENT DEVELOPMENTS IN THE FEDERAL COURT Justifications for each of the proposed anti-Teoh Acts have centred on questions associated with the effectiveness of the two executive statements issued in 1995 and 1997 respectively, which are purported to apply pending the enactment of anti-Teoh legislation. Concern on this issue was largely generated by academic commentaries40 and by the judgment, in 1996, of Hill J in Department of Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v Ram.41 In that case a decision of the Administrative Appeals Tribunal (AAT), in which the 1995 executive statement was held to be ineffective,42 was appealed to the Federal Court. Hill J made the following statements on that issue: When, in Teoh, Mason CJ and Deane J refer to 'executive indications to the contrary', it may well be that their Honours intended to refer to statements made at the time the treaty was entered into, rather than to statements made years after the treaty came into force. When initially referring to executive comments, their Honours do so in the context of the act of ratification, an act that speaks both to the other parties to the Convention and to the people of Australia as well as to the world. I doubt their Honours contemplated a case where at the time of ratification, Australia had expressed to the world and to its people its intention to be bound by a treaty protecting the rights of children, but subsequently, one or more Ministers made statements suggesting that they at least had decided otherwise. 43 The correctness of Hill J's approach to the executive statement is certainly questionable. Essentially, it involves a construction of the words of Mason CJ and Deane J in Teoh that effectively leaves denunciation of a treaty as the only method of _____________________________________________________________________________________ 38 Williams, above n 23. 39 Tien v Minister for Immigration and Multicultural Affairs (1998) 53 ALD 32; Baldini v Minister for Immigration and Multicultural Affairs [2000] FCA 173 (25 February 2000). 40 Allars, above n 7, 239-241; Katz, above n 7, 6-9; Piotrowicz (1997), above n 7, 503-506; Walker, above n 7 242; Sheridan, above n 7, 130-131. 41 (1996) 69 FCR 431. 42 Re Yad Ram and Department of Immigration and Ethnic Affairs (1995) 22 AAR 372. 43 (1996) 69 FCR 431, 437-438. 226 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ negating the legitimate expectation generated by ratification. The joint judgment in Teoh made no reference to the timing of an executive statement to the contrary, though an obvious implication is that the contrary statement be sufficiently clear to remove the legitimate expectation. As Professor Allars observed in 1995, negating the effects of Teoh would require a 'published, considered statement of policy … contrary to the ratified convention'.44 While an 'implied inconsistency' would be unlikely to remove the effects of Teoh, an 'express policy statement indicating departure from the relevant convention in a particular area of public administration' would.45 Thus, in contrast to the approach of Hill J, which concentrated on the timing of the executive statement, the approach of Allars focused more on the level of generality of the statement in questioning its effectiveness. The issue again arose two years later in the case of Tien v Minister for Immigration and Multicultural Affairs,46 though in this case, it was the second executive statement, made on 25 February 1997, that was in issue. Justice Goldberg, in Tien's case, considered that there was 'considerable force in the observations of Hill J'47 that the references to 'executive indications to the contrary' in the judgment of Mason CJ and Deane J in Teoh were 'intended to refer to statements made at the time the treaty was entered into, rather than to statements made years after the treaty came into force'.48 However, with specific reference to the second 'executive indication to the contrary' issued in 1997, Goldberg J in Tien made the following comments: I do not consider that the Ministerial Statement made on 25 February 1997 is such an 'executive indication to the contrary' as to displace the application of the Teoh principle to the circumstances before the Court. The executive indication to the contrary contemplated by the judgment of Mason CJ and Deane J is one that a decision-maker or decision-makers in particular circumstances will not act in accordance with a Convention. The Ministerial Statement says nothing about the manner in which decisionmakers will go about their task in reaching a decision. Rather the Ministerial statement appears to be an attempt (in my view unsuccessful) to reverse or overrule the principle for which Teoh is authority. I do not consider that it is a "clear expression by the Executive of a contrary indication". Put shortly, the Statement appears to be saying that Teoh is not the law. However, Teoh is a principle to be observed by decision-makers unless and until the Parliament or the Executive tells decision-makers not to act in accordance with treaties; or until the Parliament legislatively overrules Teoh. In order for a Ministerial Statement to constitute an executive indication to the contrary (as referred to by Mason CJ and Deane J in Teoh) it would be necessary for the statement to say something to the effect that decision-makers will not act, or are directed not to act, in accordance with particular provisions or particular Conventions or treaties.49 What is interesting about this decision is that, although support is expressed in relation to the earlier judgment of Hill J in Department of Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v Ram, the decision more accurately reflects the approach to effectiveness adopted by Allars. This point is evidenced by Goldberg J's reference to a need for specific mention of particular treaty provisions in the executive statement. However, the degree of detail required was not entirely outlined by Goldberg J. Nor was any reference made _____________________________________________________________________________________ 44 Allars, above n 7, 233. 45 Ibid. 46 (1998) 53 ALD 32. 47 (1998) 53 ALD 32, 54. 48 (1996) 69 FCR 431, 437-438. 49 (1998) 53 ALD 32, 56. 2001 In the Wake of Teoh 227 ____________________________________________________________________________________ to a requirement that the administrative context in which the legitimate expectation was to be modified or removed, be stated. The actual requirements necessary for an executive statement to effectively negate the decision in Teoh were still, therefore, unclear. The most significant recent case pertaining to the principle enunciated in Teoh, however, is the case of Baldini v Minister for Immigration and Multicultural Affairs.50 The applicant, Eduardo Baldini, sought to have the decision to affirm his deportation (ordered by a decision of the AAT) overturned by the Federal Court. Baldini had been convicted of armed robbery (upon which the decision to deport him was based) as well as numerous other offences. The principal ground of appeal was that the Tribunal had erred in holding that only one of Baldini's three children need be considered for the purposes of the decision. Directly relevant to this issue was a Ministerial Direction issued on 21 December 1998, under s 499 of the Migration Act 1958 (Cth) (General Direction No 9, otherwise referred to as 'Australia's Criminal Deportation Policy'). The direction specified in a detailed manner how a decision-maker (in this case, the AAT) should handle a decision in which a child would be affected by a decision to deport. Unlike the Convention on the Rights of the Child (CROC), which requires that, in all matters affecting children, the best interests of the child must be a primary consideration, the Ministerial Direction was worded in more specific terms. Only cases 'involving a parental relationship between a child or children' of the deportee required 'the best interests of the child or children' to be considered.51 Drummond J considered the term 'parental relationship' was wide enough to encompass adoptive parents and persons in loco parentis to children, but the relationship could not be established by tenuous links between the child and the potential deportee.52 According to Drummond J, 'if the connection between a child and the potential deportee is so tenuous that it cannot be described as a parental (or similar) relationship, then the Direction casts no obligation on the Tribunal to consider the impact on the child of deportation of the adult'.53 It was on the basis of the specific and detailed guidelines contained in the Direction, that the Court held it constituted a successful attempt by the Legislature and the Executive to overcome the difficulties associated with Ministerial statements aimed at overriding Teoh – the same difficulties identified in the case of Tien v Minister for Immigration and Multicultural Affairs.54 In the opinion of Drummond J, the Direction contained such an elaborate regime with which the AAT must comply in cases involving consideration of the interests of a potential deportee's child, that the Teoh legitimate expectation could not apply.55 Justice Drummond provided the following reasoning: In my opinion, paras 5 and 6 and 16 to 20 of the Direction contain such an elaborate regime with which the Tribunal must, by force of s 499 of the Act, comply in a case in which it is required to consider the interests of a potential deportee's child that there is no room for finding in Australia's ratification of the Convention a basis for any legitimate _____________________________________________________________________________________ 50 [2000] FCA 173 (25 February 2000). 51 Ibid [13]. 52 Ibid. 53 Ibid. 54 (1998) 53 ALD 32, 56. 55 [2000] FCA 173 (25 February 2000) [30]. 228 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ expectation on the part of a potential deportee that the interests of his child will be, in terms of the Convention, 'a primary consideration'.56 In other words, the Direction had effectively displaced the legitimate expectation through the use of a detailed and specific 'executive indication to the contrary',57 and the point of reference for the AAT was the Ministerial Direction rather than the CROC. The Federal Court considered that the Direction had been complied with, and the appeal was accordingly dismissed. While the decision in Tien was obviously concerned with the generality of the second Ministerial Statement and its ineffectiveness in displacing the Teoh principle, a clear judicial pronouncement of what would constitute an effective 'indication to the contrary' was not provided until the decision in Baldini. From that case it is now clear that unambiguous, detailed and specific ministerial guidelines may displace the Teoh principle, and General Direction No 9 provides a clear example for future reference to government departments and agencies. THE NEED TO RE-CONSIDER ANTI-TEOH LEGISLATION In light of the legal developments stemming from the decisions of the Federal Court, the traditional opposition of federal governments to the Teoh principle should be reconsidered, and there are political as well as legal reasons for adopting an alternative solution to the perceived problems associated with Teoh. The justifications for and perceived necessity of the current anti-Teoh Bill are predicated on an evaluation of Teoh's impact conducted prior to cases such as Tien and Baldini. In many respects, the purported need for legislation to override Teoh rested on the legal uncertainty surrounding the executive statements, and doubts over the capacity of governments effectively to construct a statement that would displace the legal obligations associated with treaty ratification. These doubts were clearly heightened by the fact that legitimate expectations were more likely to arise in respect of human rights conventions – conventions that, in some cases, Australia had ratified up to decades prior to the decision in Teoh and, thus, any 'executive statement' issued following that case. Notwithstanding the obvious problems associated with a Bill drafted prior to the recent legal developments, proposed anti-Teoh legislation has always contained a number of significant problems in itself. Inadequacies pertaining to its drafting, coupled with the anomalies associated with an inconsistent approach by governments to the treaty process itself, have always meant that anti-Teoh legislation is as likely to create as many problems as it would purportedly solve. At the heart of this problem rests the inconsistent approach of federal governments to executive accountability and the treaty process. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 56 Ibid. 57 To employ the words of Mason CJ and Deane J in Teoh. See also, Hui v Minister for Immigration and Multicultural Affairs [1999] FCA 985, (21 July 1999) [9], (Carr J). 2001 In the Wake of Teoh 229 ____________________________________________________________________________________ EXECUTIVE ACCOUNTABILITY AND THE POWER TO MAKE AND IMPLEMENT TREATIES Throughout the past two decades, the power to make and implement treaties has been surrounded by political and legal controversy. Yet, while the principal issue throughout the 1980s was the impact of the power upon the 'federal balance' and socalled 'states' rights', in the 1990s the focus shifted markedly toward issues of executive accountability.58 This shift reflected the High Court's consistently broad construction of the external affairs power,59 the prevailing belief that constitutional amendment was unlikely,60 the formalisation of a consultative framework between the Commonwealth and the States in the treaty-making process,61 and a growing realisation of the relevance and impact of international law upon domestic law and practice as evidenced in Toonen62 in 1994 and Teoh the year after. In the wake of these decisions, a legal and political debate emerged in relation to the domestic accountability of the executive in respect of treaties. In response, the Federal Government took statutory measures in the form of its Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Bills of 1997 and 1999, and implemented non-statutory reforms to the treaty-making process.63 On these initiatives, two comments can be made. Firstly, they reflect a continued commitment of successive governments to avoiding the implementation of measures directed at making the Executive legally accountable to the Parliament and the people. Secondly, the particular initiatives of 1996, coupled with anti-Teoh measures, are logically inconsistent, and would only serve to create further controversy surrounding the treaty process. The particular problems associated with executive accountability in regard to the treaty process, stem, fundamentally, from the separation of the power to enter into _____________________________________________________________________________________ 58 Cheryl Saunders, 'Articles of Faith or Lucky Breaks? The Constitutional Law of International Agreements in Australia' (1995) 17 Sydney Law Review 150, 152. 59 Koowarta v Bjelke-Petersen (1982) 153 CLR 168; Commonwealth v Tasmania (1983) 158 CLR 1; Richardson v Forestry Commission of Tasmania (1988) 164 CLR 261; Queensland v Commonwealth (1989) 167 CLR 232; Polyukhovich v Commonwealth (1991) 172 CLR 501; Horta v Commonwealth (1994) 181 CLR 183. 60 Australian Constitutional Convention, Proceedings, Adelaide (1983) and Brisbane (1985); Constitutional Commission (1984) Final Report Vol II (1985); Trick or Treaty? Commonwealth Power to Make and Implement Treaties, Report by the Senate Legal and Constitutional References Committee, November 1985, 85. 61 This framework was established under the principles and procedures for CommonwealthState Consultation on Treaties, January 1, 1992. This framework was amended as part of the Federal Government's reforms to the treaty process in 1996, which included the establishment of a Treaties Council as an adjunct to the Council of Australian Governments (COAG): see Commonwealth, Parliamentary Debates, House of Representatives, 2 May 1996, 233. The former Principles and Procedures have been replaced by a revised framework under the Principles and Procedures for Commonwealth-State Consultation on Treaties (1997) 8 Public Law Review 116-120. 62 Nicholas Toonen v Australia, Communication No. 488/1992: Australia. 04/04/94. CCPR/C/50/D/488/1992. 63 Announced in a Ministerial Statement by the Minister for Foreign Affairs, the Hon. Alexander Downer MHR, Commonwealth, Parliamentary Debates, House of Representatives, , May 2 1996, 231-235. 230 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ treaties from the power to implement treaties under the Australian Constitution.64 The constitutional arrangement allows the Executive to enter into treaties (through the acts of signature and ratification, or accession), however, the domestic application of treaties is dependent on the Commonwealth Parliament implementing the provisions of a treaty through the enactment of legislation. This position corresponds with the accepted position in law that treaties are not directly incorporated into Australian law by the act of ratification or accession, but only by the enactment of incorporating legislation by the Parliament.65 This arrangement contains two inherent problems specifically associated with issues of executive accountability, one of which, however, has been largely addressed by the 1996 reforms to the treaty process. Their existence is a consequence of the fact that the constitutional framework for the making and implementation of treaties is governed by provisions drafted for a nation which lacked control over its own external affairs, and which 'took their present form through evolution and circumstance, rather than design'.66 Firstly, the Executive, in exercising its prerogative power to enter a treaty, thereby committing Australia to obligations under international law, was completely unaccountable (prior to 1996) to either the Parliament or the public. Secondly, in the absence of incorporating legislation, the constitutional arrangement provides no mechanisms for ensuring the domestic accountability of the Executive in respect of the obligations it accepts, thereby committing Australia to observe, under international law.67 The Toonen case in 1994 was pivotal in the debate that emerged in the mid-1990s concerning the treaty process. The case itself was the most widely discussed issue among several which formed the backdrop against which a reference was made to the Senate Legal and Constitutional References Committee on 8 December, 1994.68 Charged with inquiring into the Commonwealth's powers with respect to treaties, the Committee's report was tabled in Parliament on 29 November 1995.69 Among its recommendations, the Committee proposed that legislation be enacted to replace the Commonwealth-State Standing Committee on Treaties with a Treaties Council (Recommendation 7), that treaties be tabled at least 15 sitting days prior to Australia entering a treaty (Recommendation 8), that a Joint Parliamentary Committee on Treaties with broad powers of inquiry be established (Recommendation 9), and that treaty impact statements be prepared on each treaty (Recommendation 10). While many of the Committee's recommendations were implemented under the reforms _____________________________________________________________________________________ 64 The power to enter into treaties is a prerogative power of the Executive Council pursuant to section 61 of the Constitution: Barton v Commonwealth (1974-5) 131 CLR 477. The power to implement treaties is exercisable by the Commonwealth Parliament, falling within the more widely defined power of the Parliament to legislate with respect to 'external affairs' under section 51(xxxix) of the Constitution. 65 Teoh (1995) 183 CLR 273; Dietrich v The Queen (1992) 177 CLR 292, 305; Koowarta v BjelkePetersen (1982) 153 CLR 168, 192-193, 211-212, 225, 253; New South Wales v Commonwealth (1975) 135 CLR 337. 66 Saunders, above n 58, 174. 67 Ibid, 174-175. 68 See Anne Twomey, 'Treaty Making and Implementation in Australia' (1996) 7 Public Law Review 4. 69 Trick or Treaty? Commonwealth Power to Make and Implement Treaties, Report by the Senate Legal and Constitutional References Committee, November 1995. 2001 In the Wake of Teoh 231 ____________________________________________________________________________________ announced on May 1996, the procedural changes effected were not carried out under a legislative framework as suggested in the Report. Thus, while the 1996 reforms represent a very positive step in improving accountability in treaty-making, they evidence a continued commitment by successive governments to reject any regulatory framework established by legislation, under which the Executive would be legally accountable to the Parliament. THE INCONSISTENT APPROACH OF GOVERNMENT TO THE TREATY PROCESS At the same time that the Federal Government has rationalised reforms to the treatymaking process on the basis of the increasing importance and influence of treaties upon domestic law, through anti-Teoh measures it has also resisted legal developments that would provide a small degree of domestic accountability to the assumption of obligations under international law. It is submitted that the reforms to the treaty process, in providing a framework for parliamentary review of treaties prior to ratification, is logically consistent with the notion that ratification gives rise to a legitimate expectation that the Executive will act in accordance with the treaty. Further, it provides a stronger basis upon which it may be assumed that Parliament prima facie intends to give domestic effect to the treaty.70 Reliance upon the argument that treaties have no domestic legal effect unless incorporated through the enactment of domestic legislation by Parliament, cannot logically provide a comprehensive justification for denying the creation of a legitimate expectation in respect of a treaty ratified by the Executive upon the recommendation and approval of the Joint Standing Committee on Treaties (JSCOT). Though, under the new framework for parliamentary scrutiny of treaties, the Executive is not obliged to seek the consent of Parliament, and the Parliament does not vote on whether Australia should ratify a particular treaty, JSCOT makes recommendations on whether the Executive should proceed with ratification, and members of both Houses have the opportunity to initiate debate on a particular treaty (given the new procedure of tabling treaties at least 15 sitting days prior to the Executive taking binding action on the part of Australia). This new system for the regulation and scrutiny of the Executive's power to enter into treaties provides a framework in which the Executive is politically accountable to the Parliament, and where there exists greater transparency and openness in treaty-making. In seeking to regulate the prerogative power of the Executive to enter into treaties by allowing the Parliament to scrutinise treaties prior to ratification, the Government's reforms involve practical changes to the strict separation of powers of the Executive and the Parliament in respect of treaties. They represent what Professor Shearer has described as the 'intermediate position', in which parliamentary scrutiny of treaties prior to ratification involves 'the superintendence of executive action in respect of treaties', which is to be contrasted with the position in the United States where executive action is subject to the 'requirement of advice and consent by the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 70 Teoh (1995) 183 CLR 273, 287 (Mason CJ and Deane J). 232 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ legislature'.71 It is submitted that a corollary of the treaty reforms must inevitably be a greater level of legitimacy attached to the act of ratification itself, and subsequently, added support for the principle established in Teoh that legitimate expectations will arise as a consequence of ratification. This argument rests on the assumption that the act of ratification and the practical and legal consequences which flow from it are logically connected.72 While the Teoh decision is significant to the extent that it gives treaties a legal effect in domestic law not previously assumed, it does not confer upon the provisions of a treaty the status of legally enforceable rights and obligations in domestic law. Such an effect would be contrary to accepted legal principles arising from the separation of powers within Australia. The extension of the legitimate expectation doctrine to the ratification of treaties by the High Court in Teoh does not involve incorporating the provisions of a treaty indirectly, thereby conferring substantive protection of various human rights in domestic law.73 It simply confers a procedural right which cannot compel a decision-maker to reach a particular substantive outcome.74 Notwithstanding this fact, considering the extent to which the Teoh decision gave unincorporated treaties a domestic legal effect previously not acknowledged, or even contemplated,75 the decision is controversial. However, the controversial nature of the decision is obviated to the extent that Teoh is entirely compatible with an intermediate position on parliamentary involvement in the treaty process, encompassed within the 1996 reforms.76 It is submitted that a logical consequence of an intermediate position on parliamentary involvement, is a greater level of legitimacy attached to the Executive's act of ratification, upon which it is easier to argue that legitimate expectations will arise. While the reforms to the treaty process announced in May 1996 have acknowledged both the need and a desire of the Australian community for the Executive to be more accountable to the Parliament and the people in exercising its powers to enter into treaties, the attempted introduction of anti-Teoh legislation signals a commitment to avoiding the domestic accountability of the Executive in giving effect to the treaty obligations it assumes under international law.77 As Ivan Shearer has noted, the Government's position is such that, 'when the Australian Government ratifies a treaty _____________________________________________________________________________________ 71 Ivan Shearer, 'The Growing Impact of International Law on Australian Domestic Law: Implications for the Procedures of Ratification and Parliamentary Scrutiny' (1995) 69 Australian Law Journal 404-407, 406-407. 72 Saunders, writing in 1995 (and, thus, prior to the 1996 reforms), stated, '[m]ost notably, none of the proposals for a greater degree of parliamentary involvement in treaty-making refer to the direct incorporation of the treaties thus approved, which is a logical although not inevitable concomitant': Saunders, above n 58, 175. 73 Teoh (1995) 183 CLR 273, 290-291 (Mason CJ and Deane J); Attorney-General (NSW) v Quin (1990) 176 CLR 1; see also Allars, above n 7, 231. 74 Allars, ibid. 75 See Sir Anthony Mason, 'The Influence of International and Transnational Law on Australian Municipal Law' (1996) 7 Public Law Review 20, 21-22. 76 See the statements of Senator Helen Coonan, Joint Standing Committee on Treaties Report (JSCOT), Commonwealth, Parliamentary Debates, Senate, 30 August 1999, 7932-7933. 77 As Twomey has observed, '[t]he question, ultimately, is whether the Executive commits itself when ratifying a treaty, or whether it commits Australia but excludes itself from any obligation to comply with the treaty?', in Twomey, above n 7, 353-354. 2001 In the Wake of Teoh 233 ____________________________________________________________________________________ and undertakes important and binding obligations…it is speaking only to the world outside Australia and not to its own people also'.78 At the same time that the Government has implemented reforms which are both compatible with, and give support to, the principles underlying the decision of the majority in Teoh,79 attempts have been made to expressly overturn that judgment. That there exists an inconsistency in the official government position is likely to result in the need for further consideration of the question of domestic accountability of the Executive specifically arising out of the act of ratification. CONSEQUENCES ASSOCIATED WITH THE ENACTMENT OF ANTITEOH LEGISLATION It remains to be seen how long the Executive can avoid domestic legal consequences arising out of its ratification of treaties, relying upon the artificial concept that ratification is only a statement to the international community to observe the treaty measures in question.80 The argument made by successive governments, that ratification only entails the making of a statement to the international community, is particularly artificial when considered in relation to the ratification of human rights treaties. Those treaties provide the best illustration of the fact that if ratification is not a statement to the people of Australia that the Government intends to observe the obligations contained therein, the act of ratification is substantially meaningless. To borrow from Mason CJ and Deane J, it becomes a 'platitudinous and ineffectual act'.81 It was noted in 1995 that, as well as highlighting the significance of international law within the domestic legal context, recent decisions of the High Court had also exposed 'both the fragility and inadequacy of the existing policy and legislative framework for dealing with international standards'.82 The same observation could certainly be extended to the Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Bill 1999. Whilst the Bill, if enacted, would have certainly constituted a valid Act of the Commonwealth, its adequacy and necessity were not beyond doubt when one considered the likelihood of the Bill achieving its intended effect, as the discussion below illustrates. In addition, by leaving Australia open to criticism at the international level — already a reality with the concluding observations of the United Nations Human Rights Committee that the proposed Act would constitute a breach of Australia's international obligations — the proposed legislation will only have served to create further political and legal controversy. It is likely that the proposed Act would also have been exposed at the domestic level for relying on an artificial concept _____________________________________________________________________________________ 78 Ivan Shearer, 'The Relationship Between International Law and Domestic Law', in Brian Opeskin and Don Rothwell (eds), International Law and Australian Federalism (1997) 34, 59. 79 This compatibility was in fact acknowledged by the current Attorney-General, Daryl Williams in 'Australia's Treaty-Making Processes: The Coalition's Reform Proposals', in Phillip Alston and M Chiam (eds), Treaty-Making and Australia: Globalisation Versus Sovereignty? (1995) 194. 80 Gareth Evans, 'The Impact of Internationalisation on Australian Law: A Commentary', The Mason Court and Beyond, Seminar, University of Melbourne, September 10, 1995 (copy on file with the author). 81 Teoh (1995) 183 CLR 273, 291. 82 Phillip Alston, 'Reform of Treaty-Making Processes: Form Over Substance', in Alston and Chiam (eds), n 66, 1. 234 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ of executive accountability in relation to treaties which can no longer be maintained.83 Notwithstanding this fact, the Commonwealth Parliament clearly has the constitutional power to negate the procedural right developed by the majority in Teoh based on the legitimate expectation doctrine.84 Failure to Negate Possible Common Law Remedies The third of the anti-Teoh Bills would not have excluded several significant common law mechanisms which could have been used to achieve Teoh-like effects. Clause 7 of that Bill provided that, '[t]o avoid doubt, section 5 does not affect any other operation or effect, or use that may be made, of an international instrument in Australian law'. That the Bill did not exclude these mechanisms was acknowledged in submissions to the Senate Legal and Constitutional Legislation Committee in 1997.85 Mr Bill Campbell, submitting on behalf of the Commonwealth Attorney-General's Department to the Committee, stated that the Bill's purpose was, 'not to anticipate all future development of the common law by the courts in relation to the relevance of treaties in administrative decision making. The Bill is squarely directed towards setting aside the legitimate expectation in administrative law arising out of treaties referred to by the High Court in Teoh's case'.86 However, the significance of these legal mechanisms not excluded, should not be underestimated. As Margaret Allars stated, '…although it may not happen immediately there is every potential for the effect of Teoh's case to be achieved by the courts without reliance on the legitimate expectation which the Bill seeks to destroy'.87 One particular use of treaties which is likely to assume a more prominent role in the future, is where individuals raise the provisions of an instrument as a relevant issue in administrative decision-making. Professor McMillan has argued that in such a case a decision-maker is obliged to give realistic and genuine consideration of the matter which goes to the merits of a person's case.88 The significance of the unincorporated _____________________________________________________________________________________ 83 On this point see the preceding discussion, regarding an 'intermediate position', following the 1996 reforms, at 20-22. 84 Parliament has the power to prescribe the rules of Commonwealth administrative law: section 51 (xxxix) and implied incidental powers; George Winterton 'Limits to the Use of the “Treaty Power”' in Alston and Chiam (eds), above n 79, 35. It may also be that Parliament has the power to negate the effect of Teoh based on the corollary of the power to implement treaties (ie the power to provide that a treaty will have no domestic legal effect): ibid. 85 See Submissions to the Senate legal and Constitutional Legislation Committee: Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Bill 1997 ('Submissions'), in particular Margaret Allars, Submission No.40, Vol.2, and John McMillan, Submission No.36, Vol.2. 86 Submissions, Bill Campbell, Submission No.41, Vol.2, 216. 87 Submissions, Margaret Allars, Submission No.40, Vol.2, 206. 88 Submissions, John McMillan, Submission No.36, Vol.2, 177. That realistic and genuine consideration must be given to the merits of a case is supported by a long list of authority: Kahn v Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs (1987) 14 ALD 291, 292 (Gummow J); Hindi v Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs (1988) 91 ALR 586, 597; Broussard v Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs (1989) 21 FCR 472, 483 (Gummow J); Surinakova v Minister for Immigration, Local Government and Ethnic Affairs (1991) 33 FCR 87, 96 (Hill J); Mocan v Refugee Review Tribunal (1996) 42 ALD 24, 245 (Merkel J); Anthonypillai v Minister for Immigration and Multicultural Affairs [2000] FCA 1368, (27 September 2000) [17] (Merkel J); 2001 In the Wake of Teoh 235 ____________________________________________________________________________________ convention in this case is significant, as it pertains more to the substance of a decision, as distinct from the legitimate expectation which concentrates on the form of decisionmaking.89 There are certainly strong grounds for asserting that, where a person refers to an international instrument, there arises an independent obligation to take the instrument into account on the part of the decision-maker.90 The human rights embodied in international instruments may also become relevant to the exercise of an administrative discretion, on the basis of Gaudron J's approach in Teoh.91 For Gaudron J, such instruments were relevant to the extent that they may reflect or mirror rights already protected in Australian common law.92 However, while a decision-maker may be bound to consider submissions made by a party who could be adversely affected by a decision, the weight to be attached to the issues raised would fall to be determined by the decision-maker.93 Additionally, the inclusion of Clause 7 in the Bill did not inhibit a court in any way from developing common law rights through the legitimate use of unincorporated conventions, or from construing statutes consistently with a convention where ambiguity arises. Nor did it prevent the indirect use of unincorporated conventions through reliance on two alternative doctrines of administrative law. Clause 5 of the proposed Act only prevented the creation of legitimate expectations arising out of the fact of ratification. It, therefore, did not prevent a legitimate expectation from arising out of a published, considered statement of government policy. Based on the decision in Haoucher v Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs,94 such policies generate legitimate expectations, thereby granting an individual a common law entitlement to a hearing on departure from the policy. As Margaret Allars stated in submissions to the Senate Committee in 1997:Thus, a policy of the government (even in the form of a media release regarding its compliance with international human rights norms), may generate a legitimate expectation. This legitimate expectation will not be destroyed by clause 5, which is concerned only with legitimate expectations generated by the fact of being bound by an international instrument or reproduction of the instrument in a statute.95 As the above discussion highlights, the effectiveness of the proposed Act in removing alternative common law remedies was certainly not beyond question. Application to Treaties Ratified Since 1996 That the proposed Act may not have applied to treaties ratified after the implementation of the 1996 reforms was not an issue addressed to any significant extent in submissions to the Senate Committee in 1997. However, it is a very real probability given the specific wording of Clause 5 of the Bill (the operative clause of the proposed legislation). If that clause had been narrowly interpreted to prevent _____________________________________________________________________________________ Tedella v Minister for Immigration and Multicultural Affairs [2000] FCA 1643 (11 October 2000); Ly v Minister for Immigration and Multicultural Affairs [2000] FCA 15 (12 January 2000). 89 Submissions, John McMillan, Submission No.36, Vol.2, 177. 90 Ibid. 91 Teoh (1995) 183 CLR 273, 304-305. 92 Ibid. 93 Minister for Aboriginal Affairs v Peko-Wallsend (1986) 162 CLR 24, 41 (Mason J). 94 (1990) 169 CLR 648. 95 Submissions, Allars, Submission No.40, Vol.2, 207. 236 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ legitimate expectations from arising out of the act of ratification alone, treaties adopted under the new parliamentary procedures could potentially have been excluded from its ambit. This claim rests on the fact that the level of scrutiny and consideration now carried out prior to ratification offers a stronger basis for the generation of a legitimate expectation. Clause 5 provided as follows:The fact that: (a) Australia is bound by, or a party to, a particular international instrument; or (b) An enactment reproduces or refers to a particular international instrument; does not give rise to a legitimate expectation of a kind that might provide a basis at law for invalidating or in any way changing the effect of an administrative decision. Concern was expressed in submissions to the Senate Committee about the use of the words 'the fact that…Australia is bound by, or a party to, a particular international instrument'.96 As Allars pointed out, it is the conduct of the Executive in ratifying a treaty which generates a legitimate expectation, not the fact of the existence of binding international obligations.97 Although it was suggested that the word 'mere' be placed before the word 'fact',98 this was rejected by the Attorney-General's Department. The reasoning behind this rejection was based on the assumption that, '…it would be an invitation to courts and tribunals to find other factors, in combination with the entry into a treaty, which would give rise to legitimate expectations'.99 However, it is submitted that the wording of Clause 5 would still have permitted such an interpretation by a court or tribunal. Clause 5, in seeking to prevent the arising of a procedural right recognised by the common law, was subject to the rule as stated by the High Court in Wentworth v NSW Bar Association100 and Bropho v Western Australia.101 Justices Deane, Dawson, Toohey and Gaudron stated the rule in Wentworth v NSW Bar Association as follows: There are certain matters in relation to which legislative provisions will be construed as effecting no more than is strictly required by clear words or as a matter of necessary implication. They include important common law rights, procedural and other safeguards of individual rights and freedoms and the jurisdiction of superior courts.102 It certainly remained open to a court to interpret the phrase, '[t]he fact that…Australia is bound by, or a party to, an international instrument', contained in Clause 5, as meaning that fact alone. On such an interpretation other factors (including conduct of the Executive or Parliament) combined with the final act of ratification, may have provided instances where ratification of the treaty would still have given rise to a legitimate expectation in the Teoh sense. Such instances could certainly have included the ratification of treaties under the new parliamentary procedures. Thus, treaties which have been ratified by the Executive following the detailed scrutiny involved under the new parliamentary procedures (and which includes consideration and analysis of domestic implementation issues), could have been _____________________________________________________________________________________ 96 Ibid, 205. 97 Ibid. 98 See Submissions, New South Wales Bar Association, Submission No.24, Vol.1, 103. 99 Submissions, Bill Campbell, Submission No.41, Vol.2, 214. 100 (1992) 176 CLR 239, 252; see also Katz, above n 7, 10. 101 (1990) 171 CLR 1 at 17-18; see also Katz, above n 7, 10. 102 (1992) 176 CLR 239, 252. 2001 In the Wake of Teoh 237 ____________________________________________________________________________________ excluded from the operation of Clause 5. The decision to ratify following that process, as well as the conduct of the Executive throughout that process, must surely contribute something towards strengthening the basis upon which an expectation of a future right may arise. In the event that the clause had been interpreted in such a manner, following the decision in Baldini, the executive statements would also have not applied. Therefore, unless an executive indication to the contrary was issued consistent with the decision in Baldini, any treaty entered into by Australia since the implementation of the 1996 reforms may still have created legitimate expectations pursuant to the decision in Teoh. Application to Treaties Scheduled to the HREOC ACT An additional problem relating to the proposed Act's effectiveness concerned its applicability to international conventions scheduled to, or made the subject of, a Declaration under the Human Rights and Equal Opportunity Act 1986 (Cth) (HREOC Act). Indeed one of the key political and legal motivations for the 1997 Bill's introduction related to the effect of those instruments in domestic law based on the legitimate expectation doctrine articulated in Teoh.103 The High Court considered, in Dietrich v The Queen,104 that the conventions scheduled to the HREOC Act could not be construed as having been incorporated into domestic law. Though, pursuant to s 11 of the HREOC Act, the Commission may investigate alleged breaches of any human right contained in instruments scheduled to the Act. A number of cases decided since the decision in Dietrich have, however, raised questions regarding the High Court's approach to the legal status of instruments scheduled to the HREOC Act. In the case of Minister for Foreign Affairs v Magno, Einfield J made the following comments: [T]he statutory approval or scheduling of treaties is not to be ignored as merely platitudinous or ineffectual, but must be given a meaning in terms of the parliamentary will. Thus when the Australian Parliament endorses and acknowledges a treaty by legislation, there being no contrary statutory or clearly applicable common law provision in relation to the matters contained in the treaty, it approves or validates the treaty as part of the law which ought as far as possible to be applicable to and enforceable on or by Australians and others in the country to which it is available.105 In Marriage of Murray and Tam,106 Nicholson CJ and Fogarty J considered that the status of the conventions and declarations scheduled to, or declared under, the HREOC Act, was still an open issue. In Teoh, Toohey J noted the comments by Nicholson CJ, but stated the matter did not arise in that case.107 While Mason CJ and Deane and Gaudron JJ did not refer to the matter, McHugh J expressly rejected the view of Nicholson CJ.108 Therefore, until the issue is authoritatively decided by the High Court, the issue remains somewhat unclear, despite the clear position taken in Dietrich on the matter. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 103 See for example, the Attorney-General's comments made during the Bill's second reading speech: House of Representatives, Parliamentary Debates, June 25 1997, 6308. 104 (1992) 177 CLR 292, 305-306. 105 (1992) 37 FCR 298, 343. 106 (1993) 16 Fam LR 982, 998. 107 (1995) 183 CLR 273, 301. 108 Ibid, 317 (McHugh J). 238 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Nevertheless, two comments can be made on the issue. Firstly, it is highly unlikely that the High Court will reject its earlier position in Dietrich and decide that instruments scheduled to or reproduced in the HREOC Act are now to be considered as having been incorporated into domestic law. However, it is certainly not as clear whether the Court would not consider those conventions to have been accorded a higher status in domestic law over other unincorporated conventions. The likelihood of this has already been foreshadowed in the Family Court in the case of B v B.109 There, Nicholson CJ and Fogarty and Lindenmayer JJ considered the scheduling of a convention to the HREOC Act 'may give it a special significance in Australian law'.110 The proposed legislation, in particular through Clause 5(b), actually acknowledged this likelihood. It prevented the creation of a legitimate expectation arising from an unincorporated convention even where 'an enactment reproduces or refers to an international instrument'. Indeed, this clause went beyond merely negating the effect of the decision in Teoh, and was directed specifically at what must have been perceived as the potential for a court to distinguish the conventions scheduled to or declared under the HREOC Act, had they not been expressly included within the ambit of the Bill. While Clause 5(b) would certainly have prevented those conventions from generating a legitimate expectation, there still remained the potential for a court to achieve Teoh-like effects in relation to those conventions. If it were accepted that these instruments had been accorded a higher status in domestic law than other unincorporated conventions, a court may be more inclined to invoke the use of procedural fairness, without having to employ the terminology of legitimate expectation, in respect of administrative decisions. The proposed legislation would have been completely ineffectual in such a case, though the Parliament would have undoubtedly been free to negate such a decision. Compliance with Australia's International Legal Obligations The remaining problem associated with proposed anti-Teoh legislation is its inconsistency with Australia's international legal obligations. Apart from its reporting obligations under several human rights instruments, Australia is also a party to three human rights conventions (and the International Labour Organisation conventions), which permit individuals to take complaints of alleged breaches to international committees. The procedural provisions providing international avenues for individuals include the First Optional Protocol of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), Article 14 of the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination, and Article 22 of the Convention Against Torture. The principal instrument in respect of the proposed legislation is the First Optional Protocol to the ICCPR which, apart from its scheduling to the HREOC Act, has not been incorporated into domestic law. Article 2(2) of the ICCPR provides as follows:[E]ach State party to the present Covenant undertakes to take the necessary steps, in accordance with its constitutional processes…to adopt such legislative or other measures as may be necessary to give effect to the rights recognised in the present Covenant. The United Nations Human Rights Committee has expressly recognised that the implementation of the legal obligations under the Covenant does not depend solely on _____________________________________________________________________________________ 109 (1997) FLC 92 – 755, [10.20]. 110 Ibid. This view finds additional support in the judgment of Millhouse J in Collins v South Australia [1999] SASC 257 (25 June 1999) [31-36]. 2001 In the Wake of Teoh 239 ____________________________________________________________________________________ constitutional or legislative amendments.111 However, it is important that individuals know what their rights are under the Covenant and 'that all administrative and judicial authorities should be aware of the obligations which the state party has assumed under the Covenant'.112 Given that Australia's compliance with its international legal obligations requires the application of relevant treaties to administrative matters and administrative decision-making, it is not surprising that the 1999 Bill has already been considered to constitute a likely breach of these obligations, if enacted.113 On this matter, the Human Rights Committee made the following statement: The Committee is concerned by the government bill in which it would be stated, contrary to a judicial decision, that ratification of human rights treaties does not create legitimate expectations that government officials will use their discretion in a manner that is consistent with those treaties. The Committee considers that enactment of such a bill would be incompatible with the State party's obligations under article 2 of the Covenant and urges the government to withdraw the bill.114 It is also probable that any anti-Teoh Bill's enactment would be followed with individual complaints to the United Nations Human Rights Committee or other international tribunals, and the general criticism of the international community.115 Such international effects are certain adversely to affect Australia's international reputation in human rights matters. However, given the continued reluctance on Australia's part to implement the provisions of human rights conventions effectively and fully through domestic legislation, it had been observed that, if enacted, the Bill would have damaged our international reputation, 'to the extent that it [would have become] finally more consistent with our national performance'.116 CONCLUSION The Administrative Decisions (Effect of International Instruments) Bill 1999 represents the latest attempt formally to override the High Court decision in Teoh. However, both its basis and provisions reflect earlier drafts constructed in the aftermath of the 1995 decision. In addition to containing several inherent flaws which were likely to impact on the proposed Act's effectiveness, the Bill failed to take into account recent developments at both the domestic and international levels which needed to be _____________________________________________________________________________________ 111 General Comment 3, United Nations Human Rights Committee: 'Implementation at the National Level (Art.2)':31/07/81.CCPR General Comment 3 (Thirteenth Session 1981). See also, Submissions, Robert McCorquodale, Hilary Charlesworth and Peter Bailey, Submission No.26, Vol.1, 109. 112 Ibid. 113 Concluding Observations of the Human Rights Committee: Australia. 28/07/2000. CCPR/CO/69/AUS. See also, Submissions, Robert McCorquodale, Hilary Charlesworth and Peter Bailey, Submission No.26, Vol.1, 109. 114 Ibid. 115 Submissions, Robert McCorquodale, Hilary Charlesworth and Peter Bailey, Submission No.26, Vol.1, 109. 116 Hilary Charlesworth, 'Australia's Split Personality: Implementation of Human Rights Obligations in Australia', in Alston and Chiam (eds), above n 79, 140. 240 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ addressed. In essence, the proposed anti-Teoh legislation had become outdated and unnecessary before its debate in Parliament was even completed. In the new term of the Federal Parliament, the official government position in respect of Teoh must be reconsidered, particularly given that government has been provided with an alternative and more appropriate policy basis in recent decisions of the Federal Court. By developing specific and detailed guidelines in respect of particular treaties which relate to the work of various departments, the government would be adopting an approach to Teoh which is preferable to its previous hasty attempts at executive and legislative repudiation. The benefits of such an approach would include the fact that Australia's international standing would be less likely to be affected, and domestically, the benefit of a consistent approach to the treaty process. The challenge, however, lies in convincing federal governments of any persuasion that there are both legal and political advantages in taking a responsible approach to the domestic implications of ratification, rather than simply avoiding them at all cost. However, time may well prove that, should the government persist with its current approach, the Executive can no longer avoid the fact that the practical consequences of ratification are far wider than merely providing access to a broadly defined external affairs power that can be invoked at their discretion, and whenever there exists a strong political motivation for doing so. A TURTLE* BY ANY OTHER NAME: THE LEGAL BASIS OF THE AUSTRALIAN CONSTITUTION Anthony Dillon ** 'Lawyers are not disposed to look behind the immediate constitutional framework to the ultimate sources of legal authority': Lord Lloyd, The Idea of Law (1987) 173. INTRODUCTION In spite of Lord Lloyd's observation, the centenary of federation has given many Australian lawyers the impetus to do just that, to consider the 'ultimate source' of authority for the Australian Constitution. The general aim of this article is to assess the legal basis of the Australian Constitution and, more specifically, how 'autochthony'1 for the Constitution might be achieved. Part I notes that as a result of the Australia Acts, some members of the High Court have instigated a move away from the traditional basis of the Constitution, the United Kingdom Parliament, to a new basis in popular sovereignty. However, as it could be said that the Australia Acts only dealt unequivocally with 'autonomy', and not 'autochthony', this move is dubious. Whether _____________________________________________________________________________________ * This analogy is drawn from Professor Frank Scott's work where he relates an eastern myth to describe the Canadian Constitution as an elephant standing upon the turtle of the sovereignty of the United Kingdom Parliament. It is said that all former Dominions and colonies must eventually remove the Imperial turtle and replace it with a local one, but without destabilising the whole superstructure. See generally, Frank Scott, Essays on the Constitution: Aspects of Canadian Law and Politics (1977) 246-250. However, even after patriation of the Canadian Constitution, 'it is not entirely clear whether in the sense intended by Professor Scott, Canada now has its own turtle', Geoffrey Marshall, Constitutional Conventions (1984) 206. This article will assess attempts at installing a local Australian turtle as similarly equivocal. ** BA LLB (Hons) (JCU). Postgraduate student, James Cook University. I would like to thank Graham Nicholson and Peter Oliver for the benefit of comments made on an earlier draft of this article. A shorter version of this article was delivered to the 19th Annual Conference of the Australia and New Zealand Law and History Society, Australian National University, Canberra, 6 July 2000. 1 Autochthony is concerned with how 'at some stage, a state must cease to be the offspring and derivative of an Imperial predecessor and exist as a complete and self-contained entity, as a law-constitutive fact itself', Phillip Joseph, Constitutional and Administrative Law in New Zealand (1993) 398. In contemporary Australia, this notion has taken on some importance in both academic and judicial circles because 'the position with respect to autonomy is satisfactory, [but] the position with respect to autochthony is by no means as strong', Mark Moshinsky, 'Re-enacting the Constitution in an Australian Act' (1989) 18 Federal Law Review 134, 135. 242 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Australia's evolutionary achievement of autonomy means that both the political and legal sources of Australian constitutional authority now lie in some concept of popular sovereignty, is a next step. Part I further argues against the necessity for the judiciary alone to take this next step. This Part concludes by suggesting that, if the traditional legal basis is to be judicially discarded, and a local legal source found, the federal compact is the most historically correct interpretation of federation. Parts II and III canvas a number of interrelated factors which hinder an autochthonous2 explanation of Australia's removal from the orbit of the United Kingdom legal system. Part II distinguishes between different approaches to the cessation of the authority of the United Kingdom Parliament and concludes that any such action to date by that parliament is equivocal, and as a result, the search for autochthony is in the hands of Australians. Part III notes that although there are different approaches to the acquisition of autochthony, an approach relying on democratic and peaceful means is to be preferred. As such, two such possible approaches are canvassed: the repeal of the Constitution Act or a declaration of popular sovereignty. Either of these approaches might have consequences for the rule of law, and therefore these must also be considered. I THE AUSTRALIA ACTS: THE AUSTRALIAN PARLIAMENTS AS HEIRS? PEOPLE OR The debate as to the basis of the Australian Constitution depends on two fundamental concepts: 'autonomy' and 'autochthony'. This Part begins with a discussion of those concepts before turning to consider whether the Australia Acts might be taken to have established 'autochthony'. Autonomy Paradoxically, it has been possible to sever Australia's residual constitutional 'links' with the United Kingdom without severing the legal 'chain'. As such, the chain of legal continuity is still available to trace the links back to the United Kingdom. This allows Australians to uphold the validity of the present fundamental legal order, including the Constitution Act, while at the same time accepting that Australia is a completely independent sovereign nation. Thus, Australians can refer to their links with the United Kingdom as they evolved, to show legal continuity and constitutional validity. However, since the passage of the Australia Acts, Australia is free to chart its own legal and constitutional future in accordance with its basic constitutive documents. Consequently, Australia is fully autonomous. Further, the Constitution in that sense might no longer be considered solely an Imperial statute3 but the primary constitutional document of Australia, because the Westminster Parliament has ceased to have any domestic constitutional _____________________________________________________________________________________ 2 Although the concept of autochthony has been described as 'neither very clear nor very useful', Peter W Hogg, Constitutional Law of Canada (3rd ed 1992) 54 n 41, it will be pursued in this article because of an apparent confusion in some circles in Australia between it and the concept of autonomy. As such, the term autochthony is employed in this article in the sense used by Sir Kenneth Wheare, Constitutional Structure of the Commonwealth (1960) ch. 4, 89. See below n 10 and accompanying text. 3 The Australian Constitution is contained in clause 9 of the Commonwealth of Australia Constitution Act 1900 (Imp) (the Constitution Act). 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 243 ____________________________________________________________________________________ role in Australia.4 Even the Queen acts as Queen of Australia (not the United Kingdom) when acting as Australian head of state.5 Tony Blackshield has said, '[a]s a fully autonomous independent nation, we must explain our constitutional arrangements wholly in homegrown terms'.6 Why? Autonomy is not autochthony. It is still logical for a former Dominion, now an autonomous nation, to explain such arrangements by the 'gradual and, to a degree, imperceptible'7 withdrawal of British hegemony, but still within the British legal framework. Even so, it would be mandatory for any successful claim to autochthony that Australia's constitutional arrangements be explained wholly in such terms. Autochthony As noted by Phillip Joseph, 'uninterrupted legal devolution [can] prove a mixed blessing'8 Stability and continuity are preserved through 'orderly development'9 but autochthony can be confounded. An autochthonous or homegrown constitution is said to be one that has 'sprung from the land itself ... and is rooted in the local soil'.10 As such, autochthony requires that a constitution be indigenous. In other words, the only claim to authority of the Australian Constitution must spring from within Australia itself. By dint of legal history, Australia does not have a truly autochthonous Constitution.11 Australia does not have a constitution solely adopted by the spontaneous will (or by an assumed act) of the Australian people, nor a constitution enacted by means of a break in legal continuity. Further, there appear to be competing claims as to the authority of the Constitution; a persuasive one being that of an Imperial statute. To be sure, all the constituent documents of the Australian constitutional order have an external rather than a local root. As a result, Australia, which seems more interested in the 'substance than in the trappings and formal guarantees of independence'12 - apparently unlike New Zealand and to a lesser degree _____________________________________________________________________________________ 4 By virtue of s 1 of the Australia Acts 1986 (UK) and (Cth). As such, Australia's autonomy is complete and irreversible. 5 Royal Style and Titles Act 1973 (Cth). 6 A R Blackshield, 'The Implied Freedom of Communication' in Geoffrey Lindell (ed) Future Directions in Australian Constitutional Law (1994) 232, 242 (emphases added). 7 China Ocean Shipping Co v South Australia (1979) 145 CLR 172, 183 (Barwick CJ). 8 Phillip Joseph, 'Foundations of the Constitution' (1989) 4 Canterbury Law Review 58, 69. 9 Sue v Hill (1999) 163 ALR 648, 675 (Gleeson CJ, Gummow and Hayne JJ), quoting Southern Centre of Theosophy Inc v South Australia (1979) 145 CLR 246, 261 (Gibbs J). 10 Wheare, above n 2, 89. 11 For a similar claim in relation to Canada's patriated Constitution, see Geoffrey Marshall, Constitutional Conventions (1984) 206: '[I]f patriation is equated with the idea of "autochthony" ... Canada's new Constitution is not (in the term popularised by Sir Kenneth Wheare) "autochthonous''. In contrast, Marshall's earlier writing seemed to reflect a broader and less strict view of "autochthony"'. This earlier view will be discussed at length with respect to Australia in this article, see text accompanying n 140 below. 12 R T E Latham, 'The Law and the Commonwealth' in W K Hancock (ed) Survey of British Commonwealth Affairs (1937) Vol. 1, 526. Wheare has also noted that many members of the Commonwealth 'are not interested in the technicalities of law when they have the substance of power', above n 2, 106. 244 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Canada13 - might seem fated to be content with autonomy and not autochthony. However, this perceived inactivity, or even apathy, is not, and should not be, either the cue or the justification for the High Court to step in and tidy up, in constitutional terms, what Australians are unwilling to do for themselves. At this point some might ask '[w]hy does autochthony matter?' and is it not, only 'the concern of sensitive Dominions and fussy persons?'14 Prima facie autochthony does not matter constitutionally or legally, because autonomy is, arguably, the more important constitutional value. That said, autochthony may matter emotionally or symbolically; witness the current republican debate. Michael Detmold has also said that 'autonomy does not need autochthony ... but autochthony is oddly attractive'. 15 Further, in a very practical sense, much of the present debate promoting popular sovereignty as a 'theoretical' and autochthonous explanation of the Constitution, might bring forth unintended and unforseen legal consequences, quite possibly in constitutional interpretation. As Leslie Zines has noted, '[i]t might be suggested that popular sovereignty places a constitutional restriction on legislative power by requiring the parliament to act only for the benefit of the people, its constitutional ruler'.16 Whilst in 1902, Harrison Moore was able to dismiss any 'doubt or speculation as to the theoretical origin or legal foundation of the Commonwealth and the Constitution',17 Andrew Fraser has rightly noted that there now appears a 'persistent doctrinal confusion over the sources of legitimate constitutional authority in Australia'.18 As a result of the 'implied rights cases', it is argued that the High Court has created a constitutional and theoretical 'riddle' concerning which legal principle should be seen as sustaining the Constitution. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 13 Peter Oliver suggests that this is '[p]robably, due in part to the fact that Australia had benefited early on from the highest degree of constitutional independence of any of the three'. Peter Oliver, 'The Constitution of Independence', Paper delivered to the Australia and New Zealand Law and History Society, Melbourne, 4 July 1998 (copy on file with author). 14 R Dawson, quoted in Queensland Constitutional Review Commission, Issues Paper (1999) 212. 15 Michael Detmold, The Australian Commonwealth (1985) 95, 105. 16 Leslie Zines, The High Court and the Constitution (4th ed, 1997) 417. See also recent comments of Kirby J in Durham Holdings Pty Ltd v New South Wales (2001) 75 ALJR 501, 516: ‘The significance of the contemporary realisation that the foundation of Australia’s Constitution lies in the will of the Australian people has not yet been fully explored’; Moshinsky, above n 1, 135: 'The source of authority of the Constitution has significant consequences for the way in which the powers of government are exercised and interpreted'; James A Thomson, 'The Australian Constitution: statute, fundamental document or compact?' (1985) Law Institute Journal 1199; and Geoffrey Lindell, 'Expansion or Contraction? Some Reflections About the Recent Judicial Developments on Representative Democracy' (1998) 20 Adelaide Law Review 111, 144, where Lindell warns of 'inherent dangers' in using the notion of popular sovereignty 'as a factor in constitutional interpretation'. But cf George Winterton, 'Popular Sovereignty and Constitutional Continuity' (1998) 26 (1) Federal Law Review 1, 5. 17 W Harrison Moore, The Constitution of the Commonwealth of Australia (2nd ed, 1910) 66-67. 18 Andrew Fraser, 'False Hopes: Implied Rights and Popular Sovereignty in the Australian Constitution' (1994) 16 Sydney Law Review 213, 215-216 citing Mason CJ in Australian Capital Television v Commonwealth (1992) 177 CLR 106, 138 (‘ACTV’). 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 245 ____________________________________________________________________________________ The legal source of the Constitution is the United Kingdom Parliament, because Australia's constitutional arrangements are still legally derived from, but not subordinate to,19 the United Kingdom Parliament which enacted the Constitution as (part of, not merely a schedule to) one of its statutes. This statute, even after the Australia Acts, has not ceased to hold its paramount status. It is clear that existing Imperial Acts applicable to Australia in 1986, continue in force after 1986 until amended or repealed by valid Australian legislation.20 This applies particularly to the Constitution Act, and the Constitution it incorporates. As John Daley has noted: 'One can only identify the provisions of [the Constitution] exhaustively by reference to the enactments of the Imperial Parliament… [Therefore] a body may remain the authority for legislation made in the past, even if that body lacks the authority to legislate in the present'.21 Moreover, 'there is no difficulty ... as long as authority is distinguished from continuing power ... Thus the common law may recognise the Westminster Parliament as the authority for the Australian Constitution and also recognise that any continuing power in the Westminster Parliament has ceased'.22 Therefore, any attempt by the Westminster Parliament to repeal or amend any of Australia's basic constitutive documents would be met with Australian rejection and disdain. In all probability, the High Court would regard the unwanted law as having no status at all: the law would be a nullity in Australia.23 As Geoffrey Marshall has noted: '[P]reservation of the British historical and legal root is compatible with its being the case that the Westminster Parliament is no longer able to legislate for [Australia]…'24 The political source of the Constitution might be the people of Australia (or possibly the electorate) 25 because in political terms, 'the Constitution ultimately depends for its _____________________________________________________________________________________ 19 In this respect I question Joseph's interpretation, above n 1, 397, of the effects of one legal system being derived from another. This article rejects the view that a legally derived (but now fully autonomous) system must necessarily in any way (historically or otherwise) remain subordinate. As Professor Winterton has noted, '[i]t is surely to confuse continuity with subordination'. Winterton above n 16, 7, quoting Geoffrey Marshall, Constitutional Theory (1971) 63. See also, John Daley, The Bases for the Authority of the Australian Constitution (1999) unpublished D Phil thesis, Oxford, ch 5.3 (copy on file with author): '[A] legislature whose authority is derived from a source need not remain subordinate to that source' and further '[T]he rhetorical desire to assert that Australia's constitutional law is independent of any other country is [often] based on the mistaken belief that derivation from a source implies subordination' ibid ch 5.6.3. Further, although a break in legal continuity would deny legal derivation, there would never be any point in denying Australia's historical derivation. 20 China Ocean Shipping Co v South Australia (1979) 145 CLR 172, 195 (Gibbs J). See also, the recent 'Treaty of Versailles' cases of Joose v Australian Securities and Investment Commission (1998) 159 ALR 260 and Helljay Investments Pty Ltd v Deputy Commission of Taxation (1999) 166 ALR 302. 21 Daley, above n 19, ch 5.3. 22 Detmold, above n 15, 95. See also, Moshinsky, above n 1, 144. 23 Also noted by Hogg, above n 2, 56 in relation to Canada. See, the comments of Gleeson CJ, Gummow and Hayne JJ in Sue v Hill (1999) 163 ALR 648, 666 where the same is implicit. 24 Marshall, above n 11, 207 (emphasis added). Moshinsky similarly notes, 'acceptance of the traditional view that we do not have an autochthonous constitution, does not necessarily mean that the British Parliament can repeal or amend the Constitution Act', above n 1, 136. 25 A V Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (1st ed, 1885; 10th ed, 1959) 73-76 distinguished between 'legal' and 'political' sovereignty, attributing the former to the King-in-Parliament and the latter to electors. The current political or moral basis of the 246 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ continuing validity upon the acceptance of the people, but the same may be said of any form of government which is not arbitrary'.26 As such 'the Constitution is only "homegrown" in a practical, not legal, sense'.27 Further, it is in this practical sense only, that the people of Australia should be regarded as ultimately sovereign. Several Justices of the High Court have attributed the phrase 'ultimate sovereignty' to the people of Australia. However, it is often not clear in what sense it is being used. Does it mean 'legal' or 'political' or both, or something else again? Both Mason CJ in Australian Capital Television v Commonwealth28 (‘ACTV’) and, elsewhere, Dawson J29 have resorted to use of the phrase. It seems unlikely, however, that both Justices used it to mean the same thing. It would appear Mason CJ used it to signify political and legal sovereignty, much like McHugh J was to signify in Ridgeway v The Queen30 and McGinty v Western Australia.31 However, four years later Mason reiterated his views from ACTV about the passage of the Australia Acts, but stated that it was now possible to say 'that political sovereignty resides in the people'.32 In this respect the word 'political' is substituted for the word 'ultimate' as used in ACTV. On the other hand, Dawson J appears to have consistently used 'ultimate' to signify 'political' sovereignty, in the sense that the people's will is ultimately obeyed. The Australia Acts and Autochthony Nicholas Aroney has suggested that some members of the High Court have 'recently expressed interest in finding an autochthonous source for the Australian constitutional system'.33 Often, this trend has been based upon consideration of the Australia Acts. However, it is not clear that the scheme of the Australia Acts amounted to such an invitation. In confirming that Australia is autonomous, some Justices34 have made a _____________________________________________________________________________________ Constitution is however, a matter of some controversy. For a detailed investigation of the moral legitimacy of obeying the Constitution, see Daley, above n 19, ch 5.6.2: '[T]he moral authority of the Constitution never rested simply on the fact that it was legally derived from the Imperial Parliament'. See also, Jeremy Kirk, 'Constitutional Interpretation and Evolutionary Originalism' (1999) 27 Federal Law Review 323, 339. 26 ACTV (1992) 177 CLR 106, 181 (Dawson J). 27 Moshinsky, above n 1, 136. 28 ACTV (1992) 177 CLR 106, 138. 29 Commonwealth v Mewett (1997) 191 CLR 471, transcript of oral argument 6/8/96 from web, 12/9/99, http://www.austlii.edu.au/do/disp...ipts/1995/M42/8.html; 9. 30 (1995) 184 CLR 19, 91 (citing Mason CJ in ACTV). 31 (1996) 186 CLR 140, 230 (citing Mason CJ in ACTV). See also, Michael Wait, ‘The Slumbering Sovereign: Sir Owen Dixon’s Common Law Constitution Revisited’ (2001) 29 Federal Law Review 57, 70: ‘Upon gaining independence, legal sovereignty, relinquished by the Imperial Parliament, was therefore vested in the Australian people, uniting in them both legal and political sovereignty, or "ultimate sovereignty", citing Mason CJ in ACTV and McHugh J in McGinty. 32 Sir Anthony Mason, 'The Interpretation of a Constitution in a Modern Liberal Democracy' in Charles Samford and Kim Preston (eds) Interpreting Constitutions: Theories, Principles and Institutions (1996) 13-30, 30 (emphasis added). 33 Nicholas Aroney, 'A Public Choice? Federalism and the Prospects of a Republican Preamble' (1999) 20 University of Queensland Law Journal 262, 284. 34 See particularly, ACTV (1992) 177 CLR 106, 138 (Mason CJ); Nationwide News Pty Ltd v Wills (1992) 177 CLR 1, 70-72 (Deane and Toohey JJ); Leeth v The Commonwealth (1992) 174 CLR 455, 484 and 486 (Deane and Toohey JJ). See also, Kruger v The Commonwealth (1997) 190 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 247 ____________________________________________________________________________________ further step in reasoning, which does not necessarily follow. They have argued that the traditional legal basis of the Australian Constitution has been discarded because it can no longer sustain the perceived practical reality of a substituted basis; that is, the sovereignty of the Australian people. I agree with comments that such assertions amount to a 'radical relocation of sovereignty'35 and 'grossly exaggerate the impact of the Australia Act 1986 (UK)'.36 As Moshinsky has noted, it is not clear that the legal independence of Australia brought about by the passage of the Australia Acts has 'altered the source of the authority of our Constitution'.37 Independence does not necessarily imply a legal break. To be sure, although the Australia Acts did sever the future legal relationship between the United Kingdom and Australia, legal continuity was preserved and no constitutional void resulted. However, there certainly existed a gap in Australian domestic legislative power. The Acts dealt with this by regularising and recognising Australia's legal separation, and should therefore be correctly interpreted as a remedial redistribution of British legislative authority, to fill the gap in favour of the Australian parliaments. In effect, the supremacy of the Australian parliaments under the Constitution was substituted for the sovereignty of the Westminster Parliament.38 A critique - federal compact If one adopts the view that the Australia Acts created a void39 in constitutional authority, it might well be necessary to discern an 'alternative' (but maybe even only 'additional') local legal constitutional source.40 After all, it is recognised that our legal _____________________________________________________________________________________ CLR 1, 89 (Toohey J), where his Honour in effect repeated his and Deane J's view from Nationwide News; Ridgeway v The Queen (1995) 184 CLR 19, 91 (McHugh J); McGinty v Western Australia (1996) 186 CLR 140, 230 and 237 (McHugh J). Further Justices such as Brennan CJ (when on the bench) and Gaudron, Gummow and Kirby JJ are increasingly concerned to look for ways to protect individual rights, and all accept as a starting point that the people of Australia are sovereign. However, it would appear that neither Gaudron nor Gummow JJ (nor possibly Kirby J) have explicitly claimed that such sovereignty is now the legal basis of the Constitution. 35 Leighton McDonald, 'The Denizens of Democracy: The High Court and the 'Free Speech' Cases' (1994) 5 Public Law Review 160, 182. 36 Winterton, above n 16, 10, although Professor Winterton argues 'the Constitution has long been based on popular sovereignty', ibid, 9. 37 Moshinsky, above n 1, 144. See also, Daley, above n 19, ch 5.5.4: 'The attainment of Australian independence does not necessarily imply that authority for the entire legal system transfers to another source'; Peter Hanks and Deborah Cass, Australian Constitutional Law (1994) 18, arguing that such independence 'need not affect the original rationalisation for the paramountcy of the Commonwealth Constitution'; and Winterton, above n 16, 6. 38 Keith Mason, ‘The Rule of Law’ in Paul Finn (ed), Essays on Law and Government, Volume 1 (1995) 114, 123: ‘the parliament[s] may be supreme, but they are not sovereign in the sense that Dicey claimed that the British Parliament was sovereign. The distinction between supremacy and sovereignty is critical’. See also, Paul Finn, 'A Sovereign People, A Public Trust', ibid 1, 4, n 24 noting the view that: 'parliaments under our Constitutions [are] the 'Supreme Sovereigns' in this country'. 39 Professor Finn used the phrase 'apparent void' because 'divergent views can be taken on this matter', ibid. 40 See, Aroney, above n 33, 285 citing H W R Wade, 'The Basis of Legal Sovereignty' [1955] Cambridge Law Journal 172, 192: 'The Courts will then have to search for an autochthonous 248 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ system (and arguably constitution) must have a legal fons et origo (source and origin). However, popular sovereignty is only one possibility, it is not the 'default setting'. Others include authority derived from a divine being, or from the State itself, or from indigenous-non-indigenous reconciliation or even from provincial autonomy reflected in a federal compact.41 This article argues that if the traditional legal basis is to be discarded by the High Court, a federal compact between the colonies as polities, (or even the people of the colonies) is a more historically correct interpretation of federation than a social contract42 based upon popular sovereignty. Whilst the agreement between the colonies to federate was not legally binding because the Constitution obtained its juristic force from the United Kingdom Parliament, the absence of that parliament from Australia's constitutional arrangements might require a fresh analysis of the legal status of the agreement. Further, the potentially powerful effect of the unanimity evident in the passage of the Australia Act 1986 (Cth) and the resultant 'unanimity procedure' embodied in s 15 of the Act adds weight to the argument that the Constitution may now be seen as a compact. A similar view has recently been espoused by Nicholas Aroney: 'The Imperial Parliament abdicated its legislative capacity concerning Australia, and the unanimous action of the States took its place ... as the ultimate source of authority in the Australian federation… [T]he Constitution Act is now binding due to the unanimous agreement of the States…' 43 _____________________________________________________________________________________ source of bindingness'. See also, Michael Kirby, 'Constitutional Interpretation and Original Intent' (2000) 24 Melbourne University Law Review 1, 7. Unless Australians are prepared to accept Gilbert's notion of two grundnorms, the question may come down to either s 15 of the Australia Acts or s 128 as the source. See, Aroney, above n 33, 287: '[I]f the Imperial Parliament has now abdicated its legislative powers over Australia, legal theory seems to require that we understand, at least one of these powers as the source, rather than a tributary, of the stream'; Geoffrey Lindell, 'Why is Australia's Constitution Binding? - The Reasons in 1900 and Now, and the Effect of Independence' (1986) 16 Federal Law Review 29, 40; R D Lumb, 'The Bicentenary of Australian Constitutionalism: The Evolution of Rules of Constitutional Change' (1988) 15 University of Queensland Law Journal 3, 32 and Christopher Gilbert, 'Section 15 of the Australia Acts: Constitutional Change by the Back Door' (1989) 5 Queensland University of Technology Law Journal 55, 66-68. 41 Frank Scott, Essays on the Constitution: Aspects of Canadian Law and Politics (1977) 248-249. Michael Waite has suggested that in Sue v Hill (1999) 163 ALR 648, Gleeson CJ, Gummow and Hayne JJ regard the ultimate legal sovereignty as vested in the Crown thus, in some form, restoring a Dixonian constitutionalism; Waite above n 31, 72. 42 See also, Nationwide News, (192) 177 CLR 1, 70 (Deane and Toohey JJ); ACTV (1992) 177 CLR 106, 136 (Mason CJ), 210-211 (Gaudron J), 228 (McHugh J) cited by Nicholas Aroney, Freedom of Speech in the Constitution (1998) 253 n 30. Of the present Court, Kirby J appears the most prepared to canvas notions of fundamental and deep lying rights that have never been ceded by the people and that may even have been jealously reserved. See, Michael Kirby, ‘Deakin – Popular Sovereignty and the True Foundation of the Australian Constitution’ 1997 Deakin Law School Public Oration, delivered 28 January 1999 (copy on file with author); Durham Holding Pty Ltd v New South Wales (2001) 75 ALJR 501, 511. 43 Aroney, above n 33, 290-292. In this sense, the Australia Acts might be seen as 'a novation of the federal compact, a new fundamental agreement between [the] Commonwealth and States', Latham, above n 12, 527. 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 249 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Further, '[w]hile it has for many years been regarded as a heresy to refer to the Constitution as a compact',44 this view could, in light of the Australia Acts, be seen as unnecessarily restrictive. Greg Craven has made the point that '[a] compact theory of federation, is, if anything, rather more plausible in Australia after the collapse of Imperial supremacy than it was before that event'.45 Thus Aroney further comments that:46 [M]ost accounts of the search for the basic rule [of the Australian legal system] have been skewed by an (unhistorical) camber in favour of regarding the Australian 'people' as an undifferentiated (and rather undefined) whole, without regard to the States into which they are organised and, more importantly, without regard to the federative compact which, from an autochthonous and legal point of view, brought the federation into being.47 Therefore, it is now open for some to view the Constitution as a federal compact, as it is open for others to view it as social contract. Indeed, the federal compact view has a much stronger historical pedigree. James Thomson has noted: '[h]istorically, the Australian Constitution was not formally approved by the people acting as a collective entity. Rather it was endorsed by enfranchised citizens voting as members of individual and distinct colonies'.48 This views the people who voted to accept federation as inhabitants of their respective colonies (and of course British subjects), not citizens of the Commonwealth49 organised into a single national unit. A problem common to both 'social contract' and 'federal compact' paradigms, however, is that it might (although not necessarily) involve a preEngineers50 approach to interpretation. This might require 'an interpretation of the Constitution ... which is formed on a vague, individual conception of the spirit of the compact [or contract]'.51 Popular sovereignty In spite of the Australia Acts' limited mandate, many sponsors of popular sovereignty have cited their passage as the decisive and defining moment for the ascendancy of popular sovereignty and the acquisition of autochthony. Mason CJ in ACTV was emphatic that 'the Australia Act 1986 (UK) marked the end of the legal sovereignty of _____________________________________________________________________________________ 44 Zines, above n 16, 308. 45 Greg Craven, 'A Few Fragments of State Constitutional Law' (1990) 20 Western Australian Law Review 353, 362. 46 Aroney, above n 33, 288 (emphases added). 47 However, one problem is that for the federal compact to create an autochthonous Commonwealth, the colonies would need to be considered autochthonous. This might be difficult in light of the countervailing necessity to refer to Imperial legislation in their creation. For, how do the people voice their 'ultimate sovereignty' if not by some legally created mechanism (the colonies) and which body created that mechanism (The Imperial Parliament)? 48 Thomson, above n 16, 1201. 49 Finn, above n 38, 3, n 15. 50 Amalgamated Society of Engineers v Adelaide Steamship Co Ltd (1920) 28 CLR 129. 51 Ibid, 145 (Knox CJ, Isaacs, Rich and Starke JJ). 250 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ the Imperial Parliament and recognised that ultimate sovereignty resided in the Australian people'.52 On one level it is difficult to dispute the first proposition of Mason CJ's statement. However, does it necessarily follow that the beneficiary of this relinquishing of sovereign power is the Australian populace and not the Australian parliaments? Where is it recognised that this redistribution of Westminster sovereignty should become the property of, and 'embedded in'53 the Australian people? Neither version of the Australia Acts make any reference to 'the people of Australia', let alone anything that could be construed as an invocation of the 'people as a legislator', or even a declaration of popular sovereignty. Moreover, as the local version was not approved by referendum, the scheme of the Australia Acts could not be said to have taken place within a popular framework. In fact, the scheme took place within a federal framework, based squarely on state unanimity. The Australia Act 1986 (Cth) was enacted pursuant to s 51(xxxviii) of the Constitution, that is, by the Commonwealth Parliament at the request and concurrence of all the States. This unanimity then authorised the United Kingdom legislation (pursuant to s 4 of the Statute of Westminster) at the request and with the consent of, the Commonwealth Parliament and Government. Popular sovereignty is, in terms of Australia's constitutional arrangements, an ahistorical54 and nebulous55 concept. Many of its proponents, however, are not deterred by mere history (constitutional or otherwise) and consequently 'admit that the paradigm ... is not justified by history, but argue that this dissonance is irrelevant'.56 Many sponsors point to the fact that an unstated premise of the Australia Acts is that s 128 is now the only method of altering the Constitution, and that by _____________________________________________________________________________________ 52 (1992) 177 CLR 106, 138 (emphasis added). I assume that Mason CJ intends 'ultimate' to include political and legal. See, Zines, above n 16, 394: 'Mason CJ, therefore, spoke of the people as heirs to the British parliament.' 53 McGinty v Western Australia (1996) 186 CLR 140, 237 (McHugh J). 54 Justice Hutley has said, 'Australia does not have to pretend that power comes from the people. The polity has an historical legitimacy which America does not have'. Frank Hutley, 'The Legal Traditions of Australia as contrasted with Those of the United States' (1981) 55 Australian Law Journal 63, 64. 55 See, D A Smallbone, 'Recent Suggestions of an Implied 'Bill of Rights' in the Constitution, Considered as a Part of a General Trend in Constitutional Interpretation' (1993) 21 Federal Law Review 254, 269: 'In an age which has demonstrated that democracy can exist without constitutional recognition of the concept of popular sovereignty, there is no need to adopt so dangerous and unsatisfying a notion into the fundamental fabric of our Constitution'. Daley, above n 19, ch 5.6.1 notes that popular sovereignty is not even 'a desirable fiction'. Further, as Professor Zines has noted, '[i]t is difficult to be certain in clear legal terms what the notion of the sovereignty of the people means. The concept of sovereignty of the people ... must be regarded as either purely symbolic or theoretical', above n 16, 395-396. As Aroney has noted, '[i]n either case, there is a problem of definition, which must be addressed'. Aroney, above n 33, 288. See also Waite, above n 31, 72: ‘the vesting of sovereignty in the people is apt to create confusion.’ 56 Harley G A Wright, 'Sovereignty of the People – The New Constitutional Grundnorm?' (1998) 26 Federal Law Review 165, 184. 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 251 ____________________________________________________________________________________ virtue of its popular provisions, the people (as a single national unit) are now the legal source of constitutional authority.57 However, at least five points can be made in response: • First, the location of a power to amend the Constitution might not be the best indicium of municipal sovereignty - or of autochthony for that matter - and may be merely a 'procedural condition precedent'.58 In this sense, there appears to be some confusion between the 'source of the authority' of the Constitution and the 'location of the power to amend' the Constitution. Indeed, it might be thought convenient that the 'one body' would exercise both the powers to make and amend the Constitution, as McHugh J in McGinty has asserted.59 However, as demonstrated by George Winterton, this is not the case in Australia.60 The Australian people did not make the Constitution. Their role was limited to approving the original draft Constitution; 'albeit without legal effect'.61 • Secondly, the people's will in s 128 is expressed as residents of the component units of the federation, the States, and not in a conglomerate mass of national citizens.62 As such it is accepted that Australia enjoys popular sovereignty of some sort in s 128 of the Constitution. However, the preferable view is to adopt the words of Quick and Garran: In the Constitution of the Commonwealth of course there is no absolute sovereignty, but a quasi-sovereignty which resides in the people of the Commonwealth, who may express their will on constitutional questions through a majority of the electors voting and a majority of the States. 63 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 57 See below n 147 and accompanying text for other arguments suggested to sustain the theory of popular sovereignty as the source of authority of the Constitution; ie, approval of the Constitution by 'acceptance' and/or by 'referenda'. 58 See, Fraser, above n 18, 217: 'Section 128 establishes a procedural condition precedent to the exercise of the constituent power vested in the Commonwealth Crown-in-Parliament, not an alternative locus of sovereign authority'. Further, as Professor Winterton has noted, '[t]he s 128 electors derive their authority from the Constitution and, therefore, logically cannot constitute the source of its authority', above n 16, 7 n 47. 59 (1996) 186 CLR 140, 237. In this respect relying on Bryce's notion that 'ultimate sovereignty' resides with 'the authority (whether a Person or Body) which made and can amend the constitution', James Bryce, Studies in History and Jurisprudence (1901) Vol 2, 53. However Bryce might be thought to be equating 'ultimate' with 'political', because he further attributed 'legal sovereignty' to the legislature (conjointly with the amending body). 60 Winterton, above n 16, 4-5. Nor even in the US for that matter, where that popular constitution is 'amended by means other than a direct, popular vote', Aroney, above n 33, 272 citing Gilbert, above n 40, 67. 61 Winterton, above n 16, 5. See also, Sir John Latham, 'Interpretation of the Constitution' in R Else-Mitchell (ed) Essays on the Australian Constitution (2nd ed, 1961) 1, 4. 62 As such Greg Craven's 'perennial question [still] rings out: "Which people, and in what units?"', above n 45, 360. See also, Kirk, above n 25, 341. Gummow J in McGinty v Western Australia (1996) 186 CLR 140, 274-275 emphasised the federal considerations in s 128 which circumscribe the popular provisions. 63 John Quick and Robert Garran, The Annotated Constitution of the Australian Commonwealth (1st ed, 1901, 3rd ed, 1995) 988. See also, the recent comments of Aroney: '[I]f a theory of 'popular sovereignty' is presupposed by the federal constitutional system, it is a theory which contemplates various configurations of "people[s]" constituting their governments in their varying capacities.' Nicholas Aroney, 'Federal Representation and the Framers of the 252 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ • • • Thirdly, the plenary legal power which many seem to suggest resides in the people, does not in fact exist. Any sovereignty of the Australian populace is certainly not 'equivalent' to that formerly wielded by the Imperial Parliament.64 It is sufficient to note that the Australian people have only a joint legal role (with the Commonwealth Parliament and the Governor-General) under s 128.65 The Commonwealth Parliament must initiate constitutional change before the people are invited into the process to either approve or disapprove of the proposed alteration. The people also have a further continuing legal role which they exercise by directly electing both Houses of the Commonwealth Parliament at regular elections pursuant to ss 7 and 24 of the Constitution. As such, the people's express role is prescribed and entrenched by the terms of the Constitution, and it is neither necessary nor appropriate to imply any further constitutional role to them. To ascribe an additional legal role to the people adds nothing to the legal validity of the Constitution. Fourthly, s 128 cannot change everything in the Australian constitutional matrix. For example, it cannot be used to change the Constitution Act. In contrast, it is generally recognised that s 15 of the Australia Acts has completed Australia's ability to alter all of its constitutive arrangements. Moreover, although this is not likely to occur, s 15 (at least in its British version) might also provide for constitutional change without popular approval.66 In this sense, s 15 impairs the concept of popular sovereignty. Daley has argued, '[t]o the extent that British parliamentary sovereignty impaired popular sovereignty before 1986, s 15 of the Australia Acts appears to have transferred that power not to the people, but to the Commonwealth parliament'.67 Fifthly, the authority of s 128 is by no means constant or continuous. If one adopts a 'self-embracing' view, the view that the United Kingdom Parliament can limit or terminate its own powers,68 s 128 may confer the power of amendment on another body by means of self-reference. _____________________________________________________________________________________ Australian Constitution' in Gabriel Moens (ed) Constitutional and International Law Perspectives (2000) 13, 44. 64 See, Leslie Zines, 'The Sovereignty of the People' in Michael Coper and George Williams (eds) Power, Parliament and the People (1997) 91-107, 95: '[T]he sovereignty attributed to the people has a quite different effect, and probably a different meaning, from that previously possessed at Westminster'. 65 Daley has noted, '[i]f Australia has 'popular sovereignty' because the people have the power to amend, then to the same extent Australia has "Commonwealth Parliamentary sovereignty"', above n 19, ch 2.5.1. 66 Fraser, above n 18, 217: 'Far from establishing the 'ultimate sovereignty of the people' section 15 of the Australia Act (UK) actually made it possible for the Commonwealth and state parliaments acting together to bypass section 128'. See also, McGinty v Western Australia (1996) 186 CLR 140, 275 (Gummow J). 67 Daley, above n 19, ch 6.4.5. 68 Noted by Hart, above n 69, 149; Latham, above n 12, 533; Marshall, above n 19, 45-47 and I Jennings, The Law and the Constitution (5th ed, 1959) 151-172. 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 253 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Acquisition of Autochthony To achieve autochthony, an 'independent future [must be] irrevocably sealed off from the dependent past'.69 The difficulty of explaining, in an autochthonous sense, Australia's removal from the orbit of the United Kingdom legal system is seemingly aggravated by a number of interrelated factors. The primary concern is the dilemma posed by the question of whose actions should be seen as legally decisive: those of the parent or those of the offspring? Discussed in Part II is the dominance of the traditional understanding of parliamentary sovereignty as 'continuing'. This promotes the view that the parent 'cannot protect its statutes from repeal, because no one sovereign parliament could effectively bind a future sovereign parliament'.70 On this view the United Kingdom Parliament has not irrevocably ceded legal authority to Australia. However, an alternative to the traditional theory, the 'self-embracing' theory, mentioned above, recognises that the United Kingdom Parliament can limit or terminate its own powers, and therefore its actions can be seen as 'genuinely abdicative'. There is no absolute standard here. Both versions are comprehensible and neither can be logically preferred for all legal systems.71 Discussed in Part III is the dominance of a strict view that for any offspring to obtain autochthony, a break in legal continuity must occur. (This is really a corollary of the 'continuing' view of sovereignty). However, a less strict view emanating from the work of Geoffrey Marshall will also be canvassed.72 II. ACTIONS OF THE PARENT: HISTORY AS EQUIVOCAL AND INDEFINITE The continuing view Around the time the British Empire began reinventing itself into the more egalitarian Commonwealth of Nations,73 the traditional understanding of parliamentary _____________________________________________________________________________________ 69 Marshall, above n 19, 57. 70 Dicey, above n 25, 39-41 and 67-68. See also, H L A Hart, The Concept of Law (2nd ed, 1994) 149. R T E Latham pointed out (citing Dicey) that this is because 'established constitutional doctrine held that it was in strict law impossible for the Imperial Parliament to put it beyond its own power to repeal any of its own Acts' (emphasis added), Latham above n 12, 530. See also, Wheare, above n 2, 111 and Wade, above n 40, 187-189. 71 Peter Oliver, 'The 1982 Repatriation of the Constitution of Canada: Reflections on Continuity and Change' (1994) 28 La Revue Juridique Themis from web, 24/3/00, http://www.droit.umontreal.ca/pub/themis/94vol28n2-3/OLIVER.html; 17. A separate line of research might canvas whether there are intermediate positions. 72 Marshall, above n 19, 57-64. See text accompanying n 140 below. 73 The Balfour Declaration was the result of proceedings at the 1926 Imperial Conference. The declaration read in part: 'They [Great Britain and the Dominions] are autonomous communities within the British Empire, equal in status, [and] in no way subordinate one to another in any aspect of their domestic or external affairs'. The Statute of Westminster was a result of proceedings at the 1930 Imperial Conference. 254 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ sovereignty was often forcefully stated. In respect of s 4 of the Statute of Westminster it was said by way of obiter dicta:74 It is doubtless true that the power of the Imperial Parliament to pass on its own initiative any legislation that it thought fit extending to Canada remains in theory unimpaired: indeed the Imperial Parliament could, as a matter of abstract law, repeal or disregard s 4 of the Statute. As such, s 4 of the Statute was 'not an express abdication of power to legislate for the Dominions, but redefine[d] the legislature which [could] enact a statute extending to a Dominion … to include the relevant organ of the Dominion as well as the three parts of the British Parliament'.75 It therefore seemed possible to view the sovereignty of parliament as accepting restrictions of manner and form. Much more controversial however would be restrictions of substance. To be sure, the traditional theory's perceived inadequacies were only brought into sharp focus when the United Kingdom Parliament ultimately purported to divest itself of a portion of its sovereign power and abdicate76 its ability to legislate for the Dominions.77 By the time the British Parliament had terminated all legislative power for Canada in 1982, the 'continuing' view was under serious threat, though still undecided. In dealing with a challenge to the Canada Act 1982 (UK), Sir Robert Megarry V-C in Manuel v Attorney General78 made important observations which neatly emphasise the difficulty of considering autochthony at the hands of the parent. Megarry V-C referred to that 'abstract' part of traditional theory that holds that even if a 'convention had grown up that the United Kingdom Parliament would not legislate for that colony without the consent of the colony. Such a convention would not limit the powers of Parliament'.79 The Vice-Chancellor then referred, in obiter dicta, to the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 74 British Coal Corporation v The King [1935] AC 500, 520 (Viscount Sankey LC) (emphasis added). 75 George Winterton, 'The British Grundnorm: Parliamentary Supremacy Re-Examined' (1976) 92 Law Quarterly Review 591, 603. 76 According to the traditional theory of parliamentary sovereignty, the very fact of legislative abdication is disputed. A sovereign parliament cannot abdicate part of its sovereignty. It can only abdicate its sovereignty entirely, that is by dissolving itself, leaving no successor, or by transferring permanently its entire legislative authority to a new legislative body: Peter Oliver, 'Cutting the Imperial Link' in Phillip Joseph (ed) Essays on the Constitution (1995) 368-403, 394, n 145, quoting Marshall, above n 11, 209. See also, Wade, above n 40, 196, n 69 and D Lloyd, The Idea of Law (1964, rep 1987) 182. See also, Attorney-General (NSW) v Trethowan (1931) 44 CLR 394, 425-426 (Dixon J). However, H W R Wade has discussed a distinction between 'cession of territory' and 'cession of Parliament's powers, meaning the omnipotence of future Parliaments'. He views the former as uncontroversial and notes that 'Parliament has… repeatedly accepted limitations of its sovereignty in conferring independence…' However, if the latter were accepted a 'technical revolution' (albeit disguised or camouflaged) has taken hold. As such, the former may amount to a partial abdication of sovereignty: H W R Wade, 'Sovereignty – Revolution or Evolution?' [1996] 112 Law Quarterly Review 568, 573-575. 77 This occurred by means of a series of 'Independence Acts' commencing as early as 1947 with the Indian Independence Act 1947 (UK) s 6(4) and, in more patient quarters, by the Canada Act 1982 (UK) s 2, the Constitution Act 1986 (NZ) s 15(2) and the Australia Act 1986 (UK) and (Cth) s 1. 78 [1983] 1 Ch 77. 79 Ibid, 87. 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 255 ____________________________________________________________________________________ judgment of Viscount Sankey LC in British Coal Corporation v The King80 to suggest that the result would not be different even if the convention had matured into a provision within an Act of Parliament, and that even that provision could be repealed without consent. Such is the power of the traditional view taken to its logical conclusion. However, Megarry V-C had to admit that even though it would be 'correct in British law'81 to say that the United Kingdom Parliament 'could as a matter of abstract law' repeal a statute granting independence to a country,82 it could not do so effectively. This is because any such repeal 'will not make the country dependent once more; what is done is done, and is not undone by revoking the authority to do it'.83 Similar concerns were also recognised by Murphy J in Bistricic v Rokov84 where his Honour mooted that the United Kingdom Parliament 'could … repeal the Statute of Westminster … [and] the Constitution Act. But such repeals would have no effect in Australia'.85 However, there appear subtle variations in the respective reasoning. The Vice-Chancellor seems at pains to maintain the distinction between continuing 'legal validity' and 'practical enforceability' (for the United Kingdom), whilst Murphy J discards legal validity because it cannot conform to, or explain, practical reality.86 This discarding of legal concerns in favour of practically expedient ones (or the blurring of the two), seems to typify many of the judgments in the 'implied rights cases', which promote popular sovereignty as the new legal basis of the Australian Constitution. However, no matter what putative time is ascribed for the legal sovereignty of the Australian populace, there are both historical and legal problems, as well as 'considerable theoretical difficulties'. In the face of such criticisms, many sponsors see the need to conflate the distinction between 'legality' and 'legitimacy'.87 Professor Finn has noted, 'Dicey's two sovereignties appear to be coalescing as they did in the United States more than two centuries ago'.88 However, I would argue that while the 'two sovereignties' can be fused, such momentous problems require and demand a 'clear democratic decision' by the Australian people through the parliamentary democratic process. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 80 [1935] AC 500 81 Hart, above n 69, 121. 82 [1983] 1 Ch 77, 88-89. Not expressly overruled on this point, although the Court of Appeal appeared not to proclaim such a wide view of the traditional theory, [1983] 1 Ch 95, 105. 83 Ibid, 88. See also, Ndlwana v Hofmeyr [1937] AD 229, 237: 'Freedom once conferred cannot be revoked'. 84 (1976) 135 CLR 552. 85 Ibid, 567. 86 Murphy J stated that: 'In my opinion (notwithstanding many statements to the contrary) Australia's independence and freedom from United Kingdom legislative authority should be taken as dating from 1901': Ibid. See also, Deane J in Kirmani v Captain Cook Cruises Pty Ltd [No. 1] (1985) 159 CLR 351, 442 where his Honour intimated that 'it may be necessary at some future time to consider whether traditional legal theory can properly be regarded as providing an adequate explanation of the process which culminated in the acquisition by Australia of full "independence" and "Sovereignty"'. 87 See, Fraser, above n 18, 222: 'Those who insist that the "real" genesis of the Constitution lies in its acceptance by the Australian people have further eroded the already shaky boundary between law and politics'. 88 Finn, above n 38, 4. 256 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Further, no matter how forcefully legal considerations are eschewed by judges and jurists, theories such as continuing sovereignty, which may be 'suspect'89 as divorced from reality in their application to Australia, can still exercise considerable influence. This is because 'conventional and practical considerations seem precarious pegs on which to hang the independence of ... any ... modern legal system'.90 As Marshall has noted: '[W]e are operating at the untested limits of the traditional doctrine'.91 The self-embracing view Increasingly, many argue that the traditional understanding of sovereignty must give way to a new view described as 'self-embracing'. It is only by adopting this new view that a sovereign parliament (such as Westminster) could be deemed to have brought 'its omnipotence to an end',92 without the need for intervention by the offspring. Thus it would seem that if the notion of autochthony is to be assessed successfully and decisively in terms of the actions of the parent, the self-embracing view must prevail. Proponents of this theory suggest 'the better view is that without a break in legal authority, the UK Parliament can irrevocably cede authority over an area to a new constitutional structure'.93 Indeed, there now seems no theoretical or practical justification for the continuing authority of the United Kingdom Parliament. Such notions were tested when Canada cautiously addressed the exercise of independence, by 'patriating' the BNA Act 1867 (UK) in 1982.94 But even as late as 1981, the Supreme Court of Canada had acknowledged that the United Kingdom Parliament's powers to legislate for Canada were 'unimpaired' and 'undiminished'.95 However, as Peter Oliver has noted, the Court did not say, and was not asked to say, 'whether those powers were sovereign in a continuing or self-embracing sense'.96 The difficulty for Canadians was that patriation took the form of another United Kingdom statute - the Canada Act 1982 (UK) - which was of course 'the gift of the United Kingdom parliament, not the Canadian peoples'.97 As a result, patriation threw up the paradox that 'the legal continuity represented by Canada's strict adherence to existing legal procedure ... is widely assumed to have achieved a break in continuity'.98 According to Oliver, this paradox is only resolved by 'consider[ing] the matter not as a question of British constitutional theory ... but rather as a question of Canadian constitutional theory regarding the evolution of the ultimate legal principle of the Canadian legal system'.99 If such concerns are 'understood as a matter of British _____________________________________________________________________________________ 89 Murphy J in Bistricic v Rokov (1976) 135 CLR 552, 566-567 quoting and commenting on Viscount Sankey LC's judgment in British Coal Corporation v The King [1935] AC 500, 520. 90 Peter Oliver, 'Canada, Quebec, and Constitutional Amendment' (1999) 49 University of Toronto Law Journal 519, 561. See also, Oliver, above n 76, 394. 91 Marshall, above n 11, 209. 92 Marshall, above n 19, 45. 93 Daley, above n 19, ch 5.4.7. 94 The BNA Act was renamed the Constitution Act 1867. Like autochthony, 'patriation' is a troublesome concept with any one of a number of standards and definitions. 95 Reference re Amendment of the Constitution of Canada (Patriation Reference) [1981] SCR 753, 799, 801. 96 Oliver, above n 71, 3. 97 Joseph, above n 8, 70 and n 1, 412. 98 Oliver, above n 71, 2. 99 Ibid, 13. 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 257 ____________________________________________________________________________________ constitutional theory the answer could only be indefinite or qualified' because 'British legal opinion leaned and arguably still leans toward continuing sovereignty'.100 Oliver's argument is persuasive and achieves the desired autochthony by recognising that the 'ultimate rule of recognition' 101 of the Canadian legal system has evolved to the point where Westminster sovereignty can be viewed as self-embracing. This is because the ultimate rule of recognition can have a certain core (Parliament is sovereign) but an uncertain penumbra (is it continuing or self-embracing sovereignty?).102 Given that the penumbral question was always an open question, Oliver explicitly rejects the presence of any break in legal continuity in Canada's arrangements. Oliver therefore eschews the need to use Kelsen's grundnorm.103 To be sure, an appeal to Kelsen could not comfortably accommodate legal continuity while explaining Canada's legal escape from Westminster sovereignty. In Australia, much academic writing is supportive of the promotion of popular sovereignty into Australia's fundamental constitutional arrangements, but at the same time is paradoxically reticent about assessing the change as paradigmatic.104 Similarly, to my knowledge, no High Court Justice has expressly recognised, at least in curial writings, the need to presuppose a new Australian 'ultimate rule of recognition' (or grundnorm for that matter). This is in spite of the fact that some have been able to discern a new popular legal basis for the Constitution. Like Canada, Australia's independence could also be considered a 'gift of the United Kingdom Parliament, not the Australian peoples'. However, in one sense Australia has gone further than Canada, by re-enacting the Australia Act 1986 (UK). As a result, signs that the High Court is prepared to consider such notions in terms of _____________________________________________________________________________________ 100 Ibid, 19. See also, Oliver, above n 90, 562. 101 Whilst H L A Hart admitted that his thesis of an ultimate rule of recognition, providing authoritative criteria for the identification of valid legal rules, resembled Kelsen's grundnorm and Salmond's 'ultimate legal principle', validity for him, was a question of fact. Unlike Kelsen's grundnorm, which was a juristic assumption or postulation, the rule of recognition could be established by an appeal to the facts, ie, to the actual practice of the courts and officials of the system. See, Hart, above n 69, 292-293. See also, n 147 below and text accompanying. 102 Oliver, above n 76, 398. 103 The concept of a grundnorm was developed by Hans Kelsen as a pre-supposition in juristic thinking. It is the highest norm in any national legal order, and by identifying it, the jurist is able to interpret all subsidiary norms as valid, and as a non-contradictory field of meaning. All subsidiary norms can be traced hierarchically back to the grundnorm, each subsidiary norm being validated by the norm above it: Hans Kelsen, The Pure Theory of Law (2nd ed, 1970) 208. John Finnis in his seminal article has said that Kelsenian theory is 'incapable of explaining how a legal system might divide into two independent systems by process of law', John Finnis, 'Revolutions and Continuity in Law' in A W B Simpson, (ed) Oxford Essays on Jurisprudence (Second Series) (1973) 44-76, 60 (emphasis added). 104 See, Winterton, above n 16. But contrast some jurists have been prepared to assess the elevation of popular sovereignty as amounting to a change in the 'grundnorm of constitutional interpretation': Wright, above n 56, 165. See also, McDonald, above n 35, 161162. According to Mahoney P in Egan v Willis and Cahill (1996) 40 NSWLR 650, 685: 'The effect ... and purpose [of the Australia Act, was] to alter the grundnorm of the Australian legal system'; Waite above n 31, 70 commenting on Mason CJ’s Judgment in ACTV (1992) 177 CLR 106 and McHugh J’s judgment in McGinty (1996) 186 CLR 140 who argued that: 'these developments have, without overstatement, been described as revolutionary.' 258 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Australian, and not British constitutional theory can be found in the majority judgment in Sue v Hill.105 As pointed out by Anne Twomey, the majority made the assumption that 'the Australia Act 1986 (Cth) is fully effective and that the application of the Australia Act 1986 (UK) may be completely disregarded'.106 Chris Horan further points out: 'One consequence of [relying on the Commonwealth version of the Australia Act 1986 as effective to remove the last vestiges of Imperial authority] is to avoid the theoretical problems raised by the abdication of sovereignty from a United Kingdom viewpoint'.107 However, Marshall has suggested that it is the local re-enactment, not the British Act, that may be 'legally redundant'.108 So too, Professor Zines has noted a dispute over which version is operative, '[i]f s 51(xxxviii) did not support the Australia Act 1986 (Cth), the British Act by nature of its paramount force would'. Moreover, 'any attempt to regard the whole of the Australia Act as based on Commonwealth constitutional power is impossible'.109 Thus, while the basic precept of an abdicating Westminster Parliament may have gained many adherents, there does not seem to be unanimous agreement on what the 'self-embracing' theory represents. That is whether it can only truly be understood as a matter of Australian, not British, constitutional theory. Moreover, the pervasiveness and seemingly inextinguishable allure of the traditional theory should not be underestimated. For even though many would assert that practically the 'continuing' sovereignty of the United Kingdom Parliament is unlikely to make a difference, it would be surprising to leave a theoretical explanation of independence unresolved. If it transpires that the traditional view of the parent's sovereignty was to engender most support, the following view would probably obtain: 'Any measure of emancipation at the hands of the Imperial Parliament [for example, the Australia Act 1986 (UK)] ... suffer[s] from the vital flaw that it [is] revocable at the Imperial Parliament's pleasure ... [N]othing that Westminster could do would remove this taint from its gifts'.110 In the end the better view might be that, any legal consequences of the actions to date by the United Kingdom in respect of autochthony are at best equivocal. As a result, the search for autochthony would likely need to focus on the actions of the offspring, and possibly revolutionary (peaceful and legal) concerns to seal off the past. III ACTIONS OF THE OFFSPRING: HISTORY IN THE MAKING As demonstrated by increasing numbers of Australia's near neighbours, the rule of law can too often be a fragile construct. Australia is indeed fortunate to have seen a greater amount of this important constitutional value during its century of evolution from former Dominion to sovereign state. However, might there not be a time when a once _____________________________________________________________________________________ 105 (1999) 163 ALR 648, 665-666 (Gleeson CJ, Gummow and Hayne JJ). 106 Anne Twomey, 'Sue v Hill - The Evolution of Australian Independence' in Adrienne Stone and George Williams (eds) The High Court at the Crossroads (2000) 77-108, 100. 107 Chris Horan, 'Commentary' in Stone and Williams ibid, 109, 117-118. 108 Marshall, above n 11, 207. 109 Zines, above n 16, 305 and 308. Similarly, Gummow J in Kable v Director of Public Prosecutions (NSW) (1996) 189 CLR 51, 138-9 noted that it is unnecessary to decide whether 51(xxxviii) is sufficient to support the Australia Act 1986 (Cth) because 'the Constitution continues to speak to the present by taking into account the operation of the Australia Act 1986 (UK)'. 110 Latham, above n 12, 530. 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 259 ____________________________________________________________________________________ only peaceful (if tacit) breach, is required to bring to an end the emotive notion of Australia as a derivative of an Imperial ancestor? In contemporary Australia, the drive for autochthony is unlikely to be an isolated phenomenon. It will most likely be (although it does not have to be) connected with the desire to achieve republicanism. Other political forces, previously evident in other former self-governing Dominions, such as apartheid in South Africa, conflict with Britain in Ireland, and the drive for independence in India, are not present in Australia.111 Mark Moshinsky’s valuable discussion of possible methods of achieving autochthony identifies a number of methods by which the Constitution Act might be repealed and the Constitution re-enacted as an Act of the Australian Parliament. He concluded that a peaceful legal revolution is the most desirable way for Australia to reenact the Constitution. However, Moshinsky only discussed re-enacting the current monarchic Constitution as an Australian Act. He did not question the effect of removing the Crown in the search for autochthony, but for the purpose of his labours, 'assumed that the Constitution itself would be re-enacted in identical terms'.112 Whilst this is a possibility, it seems more likely that any Australian constitutionmaking in the twenty-first century will undoubtedly have a republican flavour. Any possible removal of the Crown and substitution with the sovereignty of the people adds another dimension to the task at hand. If this is achieved by unauthorised means there would be negative consequences for legal continuity, but positive consequences for autochthony. If this is achieved by authorised means the converse may be true.113 The strict view of Autochthony According to the strict view, to achieve autochthony, nothing less than a contrived break in legal continuity will suffice.114 This is usually undertaken by adopting new constitutional arrangements in a manner unauthorised by the pre-existing constitution. When an offspring initiates such a break (no matter what view the traditional theory takes of the parent's powers), such action may prove to be legally decisive. This is _____________________________________________________________________________________ 111 Moshinsky, above n 1, 151. 112 Ibid, 137. 113 By whatever means it is achieved, the people must be elevated to a legal constitutional role to replace the Crown, so that the arms of government are constantly reminded of where they derive their constitutional power. Many have noted that the ARM 'minimalist' model did away with the 'impartial' and 'apolitical' Law-Giver (the Crown) without replacement, or on another view, substituted a political one: the Commonwealth Parliament. See, Martyn Webb, 'Republicanism Means More Than Removing The Queen: Lessons from America 1776-1787' from web, 11/01/99, http://www.norepublic.com.au/Pages/Essay _Webb _No_Case_Paper.htm; 5-6. See also, Alan Atkinson, The Muddle-Headed Republic (1993) 51. 114 The strict view was espoused by Wheare above n 2, 111. It was also asserted by Stanley De Smith and Rodney Brazier (eds) Constitutional and Administrative Law (7th ed, 1994) 70; James A Thomson, 'Altering The Constitution: Some Aspects of Section 128' (1983) 13 Federal Law Review 323, 344-345; Enid Campbell, 'An Australian-made Constitution for the Commonwealth of Australia' in Report of Standing Committee D to the Executive Committee of the Australian Constitutional Convention (1974) 95, 100, and approved by Moshinsky, above n 1, 150-151, thereby requiring him to conclude that 'if constitutional autochthony is all important, only the [peaceful legal revolution] method will do'. 260 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ because the offspring has repudiated the very source of its autonomy. A revolutionary shift in the grundnorm occurs and the validity of the new constitutional order cannot be traced by a 'stream of authority' back to the parent. It must therefore be said that the strict view owes much to Kelsenian theory. Oliver cites the Irish Constitution as an example of a constitution 'no longer connected to Westminster; it now has a root in popular sovereignty'.115 He then continues, 'this transition was revolutionary (at least in the legal sense) or autochthonous'.116 So too, some New Zealand commentators (but especially F M Brookfield) have been able to discern a discontinuity by 'disguised revolution' in New Zealand's 1986 independence arrangements. Although sounding drastic, such a 'revolution' would, in the Australian context, be benign as 'all that is required is to change a legal principle without changing in any way the legal behaviour' 117 to replace the weary Imperial turtle with an Australian one. Before, during and after such a peaceful revolution, Australians would still recognise the Constitution as the supreme law of the Commonwealth, and that a 'once only breach in the rule of law is required'.118 But in enacting a truly autochthonous Constitution, the people should realise they are exercising both their political and legal sovereignty. As a result, the chain of legal continuity that can be traced back (with the exception being from 1649 to 1660) for almost one thousand years,119 would be broken. The problem with the strict view requiring a break in continuity is that Australians have shown an unfailing desire to conform to existing constitutional procedures for sanctioning legal change. As such, Australians seem unlikely to adopt a new constitution by unauthorised means. Even so, such conformity in no way prevents the achievement of an Australian republic. Australia's current constitutional arrangements are entirely adequate to facilitate republican change, (even if there is dispute over which particular procedures should be used). But, if autochthony is the goal, more is needed. To this end, is there a way for Australians to 'have their constitutional cake and eat it too?'120 Repeal of the Constitution Act to achieve autochthony (the strict view modifiedevolutionary in process but revolutionary in effect) What would be the effect of a Commonwealth Act passed pursuant to s 15(1) of the Australia Acts which purported to repeal - not merely amend - the Constitution Act?121 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 115 Oliver, above n 90, 560. Oliver is thus in agreement with Wheare above n 2, Joseph above n 1 and Moshinsky above n1. 116 Oliver, above n 90, 560. 117 Scott, above n 41, 249. 118 Oliver, above n 90, 608. 119 Justice Kirby has noted this (almost) unbroken legal lineage of a millennium. Michael Kirby, 'The Struggle for Simplicity, Lord Cooke and Fundamental Rights', paper delivered to the New Zealand Legal Research Foundation Conference, April 1997 from web, 29/01/99, http://www.hcourt.gov.au/cooke.htm; 2. Others would however suggest other discontinuities also, eg, 1688-89. 120 Oliver, above n 76, 392. 121 By repeal I mean repeal in toto. Only in this way might 'the current format of a national constitution contained in an Act of the Parliament of another country' be dispensed with, thus 'enhanc[ing] its status as a 'foundational' document': An Australian Republic, The Options-The Report, The Report of the Republican Advisory Committee (1993) Vol 1, 122. 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 261 ____________________________________________________________________________________ It is not explicitly clear that merely amending, or even repealing, s 8 of the Statute of Westminster will authorise the repeal of the Constitution Act.122 Stephen Gageler and Mark Leeming123 are of the opinion that the Constitution Act can be repealed (by the use of s 15 and other necessary provisions) as easily as it can be amended.124 Could such action secure autochthony? Moshinsky concluded that, according to the strict view, such an authorised process would not amount to a break in legal continuity and therefore could not achieve true autochthony.125 However, I would favour an interpretation that repeal of the Constitution Act by this process could secure autochthony. A repeal of the Constitution Act in toto would mean that it would be 'no longer possible for the [offspring] to invoke a logically prior [parental] legislative power'.126 _____________________________________________________________________________________ By contrast, it could be argued the Constitution Alteration (Establishment of Republic) 1999 (Cth) did not purport to deprive the Constitution Act of legal force. The Constitutional Convention had recommended that any provisions of the Constitution Act that have no continuing force or relevance, should be repealed However, the Constitution (Requests) Bill 1999 (Qld) requested the Commonwealth not to repeal either the long title, the enacting words, the short title (covering clause 1) and covering clause 9 which contains the Constitution itself. According to the Bill, only covering clauses 2 to 8 should be repealed (clauses 5 and 6 were in fact to be incorporated into the Constitution itself; ss 126 and 127) and the existing preamble omitted. The Commonwealth Parliament has not legislated in response to these requests and moreover, the Commonwealth was apparently relaxed about the need to delete the existing preamble (see, Constitutional Alteration (Preamble) Bill 1999 (Cth)) and most of the covering clauses. However, even in light of the more stringent requests from the States, the retention of the long and short titles meant that the Constitution Act would have remained in force, and further, still derived its legal authority from the Westminster Parliament. 122 This is due in part to the uncertainty surrounding the true scope and effect of s 2(2) of the Statute of Westminster and s 51(xxxviii) of the Constitution, although the better view might be to adopt an interpretation that promotes the 'completeness of Australian legislative power': Polyukhovich v Commonwealth (1991) 172 CLR 501, 638 (Dawson J). To amend the Constitution Act, the six State parliaments must first empower the Commonwealth (by the use of s 15(1) of the Australia Acts) to amend (not necessarily repeal, as Moshinsky and Gilbert suggested) s 8 of the Statute of Westminster to remove the limitation placed upon the Commonwealth. The limitation so removed, the Commonwealth Parliament would then be empowered by either s 2(2) of the Statute or s 51(xxxviii) of the Constitution, or both, to amend the Constitution Act. This was the method chosen by the States to implement changes to the covering clauses of the Constitution Act had the 1999 republican referendum been successful; see Constitution (Requests) Bill 1999 (Qld) and other uniform State request legislation. This also affirms the view that s 128 cannot amend anything outside what covering clause 9 of the Constitution Act defines as 'the Constitution of the Commonwealth'. 123 Stephen Gageler and Mark Leeming, 'An Australian Republic: Is a Referendum Enough?' (1996) 7 Public Law Review 143, 151. 124 If the repeal of the Constitution Act were considered unauthorised, the claim to autochthony would be automatically stronger. 125 Moshinsky, above n 1, 150-151. However, he also notes a less strict view: 'Even if legal continuity were preserved … so long as the enactment of the constitution took place in Australia, it would be legally homegrown'. Thomson's view of any such use of s 15(1) of the Australia Acts is that 'there would still exist an unbroken stream of authority flowing from the United Kingdom Parliament' above n 114, 344. 126 F M Brookfield, 'Kelsen, the Constitution and the Treaty' (1992) 15 New Zealand Universities Law Review 163, 171. 262 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Such repeal would repudiate the source of Australia's legislative autonomy and deny a legislative gift was ever made. The effect would be that the Constitution Act no longer has any legal force in Australia. With the Constitution Act removed from the constitutional landscape, the only claim to authority of the Australian Constitution would spring from within Australia itself. As a result, a claim could be made that a break in legal continuity took place. In other words, the process would be 'evolutionary' (not being based on a revolutionary assertion of power) but the effect would be 'revolutionary'.127 This accords with Marshall's view (to be discussed shortly) that an offspring may claim a break in legal continuity even though the process relied upon ultimately derived from an externally-prior legislative power. After all, whether legal continuity has been broken or not may well be the subject of differences of opinion. However, since the current constitutional arrangements do contain a significant democratic element, it would be necessary to obtain substantial popular approval. If popular approval was obtained in all the States,128 at least two benefits would result. First, it could be said that the now solitary Constitution (or any new constitution subsequently enacted) would have been adopted by the spontaneous will of the people. It 'would appear on its face to be an expression of the national will'129 but really expressed in the units of States. Secondly, the judiciary would not be placed in a difficult position as a popular 'majority in all six States would [effectively] place the legitimacy of the new order beyond doubt'.130 Further, Moshinsky has noted, 'a constitutional change designed to achieve autochthony has inherent validity'.131 Declaration of autochthony (a 'disguised' constitutional revolution) If Australians were of a mind to institute a 'technical' break in legal continuity, the following course might be undertaken. James Thomson cites Geoffrey Sawer as suggesting:132 Perhaps the best way of dealing with this is to put to the people as a constitutional amendment a declaratory provision stating that the sovereignty of the United Kingdom Parliament ends on a named future date and is replaced by that of the Australian people. This sort of proposal has a great deal to commend it. Had such a proposal been put to the people and accepted to take effect from 3 March 1986, the constitutional arrangements of Australia (in respect of grundnorm and autochthony issues) might no longer be in such hot academic debate. In the end, however, the Australia Acts alone could only achieve so much. By s 1 the sovereignty of the United Kingdom Parliament was brought to an end, thereby fulfilling the first proposition of Professor Sawer's proposal. However, their failure to use 'unauthorised means' spelt disaster for _____________________________________________________________________________________ 127 Joseph, above n 1, 122. See also, Oliver, above n 76, 391. 128 As Moshinsky, above n 1, 151 has noted: '[I]t would have to be considered whether popular approval need also be received from a majority of voters in each State as it is arguable that it is in units of States that the popular will is expressed in Australia as a federation'. (emphasis added) Thus Moshinsky concludes (and I agree) that to obtain popular approval in all the States would be politically 'cautious' and 'desirable'. So too, Aroney has said '[T]he ultimate reason for turning to unanimity for the alteration [and repeal] of the Constitution Act is that it embodies the formative basis of the federation': above n 33, 290. 129 Moshinsky, above n 1, 150. 130 Aroney, above n 33, 271. 131 Moshinsky, above n 1, 149. 132 Thomson, above n 114, 344-345, n 138 (emphasis added). 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 263 ____________________________________________________________________________________ autochthony, (but was a vindication for the most important constitutional value - the rule of law). Moreover, the failure to invest legal sovereignty democratically in the Australian people makes contestable the identity of the true beneficiary of the power formerly exercised by the United Kingdom Parliament. However, this does not mean that Australia cannot adopt such a course even today. A plebiscite (then referendum) question could include a declaratory provision similar to that suggested by Professor Sawer, along with a Constitution Alteration Bill for Australia to become a republic. The declaratory provision should assert that 'all the prerogatives of the Crown and the sovereignty of the Queen are transferred to the people'.133 Further, as Moshinsky has suggested: '[T]he Australian Parliament, probably after having secured popular approval, [could] declare the Constitution Act no longer has any legal force in Australia…'.134 This could be achieved by repealing the Constitution Act as discussed above, thereby enhancing the claim for autochthony. So too, the requirement for popular approval in all the States should be insisted upon.135 It is argued such a course of action could put to rest many of the strictly legal views noted throughout this article, and bring other opportunities forward. Primarily, the Crown is replaced with the sovereignty of the people, and as such the people constitute both the political and legal bases of the Constitution. In other words, the Constitution is proclaimed in the name of the people.136 Further, the whole process, including a successful plebiscite or referendum, the declaration, the repeal of the Constitution Act and the enactment of a new constitution, could be seen as a fundamental repudiation of the existing legal order thereby securing autochthony by a 'technical' break in legal continuity, and a 'disguised revolution'.137 At this point, I concede that some might consider it doubtful whether a declaration that is based on a United Kingdom derived power can be effectively revolutionary. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 133 Such an assertion of popular sovereignty might take in part, the following form: 'Whereas all the constitutional authority ever possessed by the monarchs of the Crown of England and later imposed by the monarchs of the Crown of the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Ireland, and of the Crown of the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland over the Commonwealth of Australia, such allegiance is hereby withdrawn, and is now vested in the sovereign people of the Commonwealth Republic of Australia.' (Adapted in small part from the Constitution of New Jersey 1776). 134 Moshinsky, above n 1, 149. 135 In terms of the Australian Commonwealth becoming a republic, such unanimity would in practice give one State the power of veto. Although on the other hand, for the sake of the unity of the federation, all the constituent elements should agree to become republican at the same time. 136 As a result, the people can deal with their fundamental rights as they wish. They can place their faith in whichever institution they believe will best protect their liberty; that is, a parliament or a court. Varying methods might be utilised to protect judicially enforceable rights. A Bill of Rights (constitutionally entrenched or statutory) might be enacted. Rights may even be reserved (as distinct from those surrendered) by provisions similar to the Ninth and Tenth Amendments to the United States Constitution. Australians could also embrace indigenous reconciliation issues in any new constitutional arrangements, perhaps reflected in a treaty. Although, as Professor Finn noted, collective popular sovereignty 'poses a direct obstacle to acceptance of sovereignty in indigenous Australians', above n 38, 5. 137 Wade, above n 40, 191-197. 264 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ This is because the old order is not intentionally violated by a revolutionary assertion of power. However, I argue that the important aspect to consider in the declaratory process is that the old order is violated not by unauthorised legislative means, but by the people withdrawing allegiance to the sovereign constitutional authority possessed by the current monarch. Lastly, as a consequence, academic observers of this process might be constrained to posit a new ultimate rule of recognition (or even grundnorm) in order to explain the validity of the new legal system. Professor Sawer also noted that if such a measure as the declaratory procedure is not adopted 'we may find yet the High Court in a suitable case ... doing it for us by a sort of judicial UDI, taking effect on the date of the decision'.138 It would appear that this scenario has exercised a marked attraction for some members of the High Court. As a result of some judgments in the 'implied rights cases', it could be asked whether the High Court has already altered Australia's constitutional arrangements.139 A less strict view of Autochthony: Marshall's criteria Geoffrey Marshall has argued that there is no need for an unauthorised break to secure autochthony. In his 1971 work he identified three criteria of autochthony. Further, according to Marshall, legal continuity (or more accurately, lack of it), is only one criterion. Thus, autochthony may still be achievable even without the enactment of new constitutional arrangements by unauthorised means. Marshall's criteria are:140 (i) (ii) whether all processes for constitutional change are locally operated; whether in the enactment [and arguably amendment and repeal] of constitutional provisions, legal continuity has been broken (or claims made that it has been broken); (iii) whether with or without (i) or (ii), the people or possibly the bench, regard the constitution as authoritative because of acceptance of it. Phillip Joseph and F M Brookfield have profitably applied these criteria to New Zealand, Joseph concluding that 'the Constitution would be autochthonous according to the first and third of Marshall's criteria'.141 Brookfield adds the temporal elements to _____________________________________________________________________________________ 138 Noted by Thomson, above n 114, 344-345, n 138. Professor Sawer's reference to a 'judicial UDI' is to Madzimbamuto v Lardner-Burke [1968] 2 SA 284 where the High Court of Southern Rhodesia held the usurping government (Smith's UDI) in Southern Rhodesia in 1965 to be a 'lawful' de-facto government. On appeal however, the Privy Council held that the 'rebel regime' could not be regarded as lawful, since the United Kingdom Government was still taking steps to regain control: [1969] 1 AC 645, 725 (Lord Reid). As Detmold has noted '[I]f in fact the revolutionary contest had been settled on the ground in favour of the new regime the Privy Council would have recognised it as legitimate': above n 15, 94. Marshall has noted that 'when a Commonwealth country asserts the homegrown nature of its legal system with Imperial approval and complicity, the sonorous label of autochthony is attached. However, if this assertion is contentious - as in Rhodesia - it is dubbed "UDI"': above n 11, 171. 139 This is not to downplay the role of courts. At last resort, it is the judiciary that must recognise and thereby legitimate legal change. Witness the recognition of the illegally convened (and constituted?) Convention-Parliament that offered the English crown to William and Mary. Brookfield, above n 125, 165. 140 Marshall, above n 19, 58-60 (emphasis added). 141 Joseph, above n 1, 412, 414. Hogg, above n 2 has applied Marshall's criteria to Canada. 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 265 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Joseph's claim,142 but also recognises the break in legal continuity brought about by the Constitution Act 1986 (NZ),143 referred to in the second criterion. The question of whether similar claims might be made for the present constitutional system of Australia is now considered. Australia's position as measured against the Criteria Criterion (i) 'Whether all processes for constitutional change are locally operated'. As Joseph has stated, '[w]hether all processes for constitutional change are locally operated ... appears to be an indicium of autonomy rather than autochthony'.144 Thus, as argued above, to equate the popular provisions in s 128 with the achievement of autochthony does not necessarily follow. However, even if this criterion is considered an indicium of autochthony, I nonetheless dispute the view that s 128 is the best measure of it. This is in view of s 128's inability to amend or alter the Constitution Act. In other words, the location of a power to amend the Constitution - in contrast to the power to amend all of Australia's basic constitutive documents - might not be the best indicium of autochthony. However, since s 15(1) of the Australia Acts (admittedly in conjunction with other provisions) can be used to amend and even repeal both the Constitution Act and the Constitution (with the appropriate popular support), s 15(1) is a better measure of both municipal sovereignty and autochthony.145 According to this view, Australia has been autochthonous since 1986. However, by virtue of the state unanimity required in s 15(1) it would be a type of autochthony based upon the federal compact not any form of social contract giving rise to popular sovereignty. Criterion (ii) 'Whether in the enactment of constitutional provisions, legal continuity has been broken (or claims made that it has been broken)'. Australia is not presently autochthonous as assessed against this criterion; legal continuity has not been broken. However, Marshall only requires the offspring to claim that continuity has been broken. It is not necessary to point to any specific unauthorised enactments. This criterion seems to accommodate the Canadian situation, where some make such a claim, but paradoxically there are no unauthorised procedures. In Australia, unless the assertions of popular sovereignty can be seen to _____________________________________________________________________________________ 142 Brookfield, above n 126, 172. In respect of the first criterion, Brookfield cites 1947. In respect of the third, he cites 'since the early 1970's if not well before', although not before noting 'some difficulties in the concept of acceptance'. 143 Section 26(1) of the Constitution Act 1986 (NZ) repealed inter alia the New Zealand Constitution (Amendment) Act 1947 (Imp). Brookfield notes that New Zealand was not authorised to conduct such a repeal, and when it did so, a legal break was secured: ibid, 171. As such, the Constitution Act 1986 (NZ) (unlike the Canada Act 1982 (UK) and the Australia Acts) is seen as a unilateral repudiation of United Kingdom legislative power. 144 Joseph, above n 1, 412-413: 'something more is required than a locally operating amendment process'. See also, Hogg, above n 2, 58. 145 In a recent article discussing the debate surrounding the possible methods of altering the Constitution Act, Aroney describes the 'orthodox or conventional view' as holding that the alteration power contained in s 128 'does not extend to the Constitution Act'. He then cites Gageler and Leeming's suggestion, above n 123, that, as a result of s 128's deficiency, 'to be safe one must turn to ss 51(xxxviii) and 15(1)'. See, Aroney, above n 33, 274. However, Aroney also acknowledges two kinds of arguments that propose an extended role for s 128: repugnancy-based arguments and theory-based arguments. 266 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ represent such a claim, more is required. However, this criterion could be used to explain the repeal of the Constitution Act (and a declaration of popular sovereignty) as outlined above.146 A claim that continuity had been broken could be made, even though the process utilised was authorised. Such a process might allow Australians to preserve both legality and legitimacy, while at the same time achieving autochthony. First, the use of s 15 of the Australia Acts would allow respect for the rule of law as represented by legal continuity. Secondly, requiring state unanimity in obtaining popular approval would allow respect for federalism and democracy. It remains to be seen whether Australians are as unwilling to claim breaks in legal continuity as they are unwilling to cause them. Criterion (iii) Acceptance by acquiescence: 'Whether the bench regards the Constitution as authoritative because of acceptance of it'. This criterion seems to encapsulate Hart's notion of a change in the rule of recognition.147 According to Hart, the rule of recognition 'could… change over time, in accordance with the courts' and officials' changing attitudes towards that which should be recognised as valid law in the legal system ... but Hart provided little insight into how that transformation might take place'.148 Joseph noted that each legal system must ask itself: 'What is the courts' and officials' internal viewpoint?'149 However, Hart devotes only one paragraph to the situation where 'the unity among officials [and courts] ... may partly breakdown'. He notes, '[i]t may be that, over certain constitutional issues ... there is a division within the official world ultimately leading to a division [over the content of the rule of recognition] among the judiciary'.150 All that could be done, according to Hart, 'would be to describe the situation ... and note it as a substandard, abnormal case containing within it the threat that the legal system will dissolve'.151 Although Hart's strong language was directed to the constitutional crisis that gripped South Africa in 1954,152 the 'persistent doctrinal confusion over the sources of legitimate constitutional authority in Australia' 153 could be seen as a 'partial failure of the normal conditions… [of] congruence…'.154 Further, it is not clear that a majority of Australians, including officials, view the original enactment of the Constitution in the Constitution Act as merely an 'historical fact'.155 This is despite Hart's assertions that a 'local root' is established when the Westminster Parliament no longer has the ability to legislate for a former Dominion.156 Moreover, while it is possible to discern a majority of High Court Justices that do _____________________________________________________________________________________ 146 See above nn 121 - 139 and accompanying text. 147 Joseph has pointed out that a new attitude of courts and officials also has a connection with Kelsen's grundnorm: above n 1, 121-122 and 398. However, it would seem that Marshall's reasoning is more comfortably understood in Hartian terms. 148 Oliver, above n 71, 15. 149 Joseph, above n 1, 414. 150 Hart, above n 69, 122. 151 Ibid, 123. 152 See Harris v Donges [1952] 1 TLR 1245. 153 Fraser, above n 18, 215-216. 154 Hart, above n 69, 122. Even on a Kelsenian analysis, a 'lack of symmetry' may exist: Lumb, above n 40, 6, noted by Aroney, above n 33, 270. 155 Hart, above n 69, 120. 156 Ibid. 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 267 ____________________________________________________________________________________ favour the promotion of a local root founded in popular sovereignty, unanimity is scarce regarding the symbolic or theoretical concept of popular sovereignty worthy of occupying the apex of the Australian constitutional system. In effect, uniform and coherent reasoning is markedly absent from the materials and statements. As such, 'until such a position is formally taken by a clear majority of the High Court … it is submitted that traditional legal principles should continue to be followed'.157 Criterion (iii) Acceptance by acquiescence: 'Whether the people regard the Constitution as authoritative because of acceptance of it'. Has there already been a peaceful legal revolution in Australia? Some lawyers now argue that the Constitution 'was' law because of its original embodiment in a British enactment, but because of British abdication in 1986, 'is now' law because of the acceptance by the Australian people of the Constitution, and their preparedness to live peaceably under it. In this sense the British Parliament is no longer regarded as standing behind Australia's constitutional institutions.158 Professor Zines has made this point: 'The basic constitutional instruments were law because they were enacted by a superior law-maker. They are now law because they are accepted as fundamental legal rules of [the] system and the basic constitutive documents of [the] community'.159 It was also made by the 1988 Constitutional Commission:160 As [the British] Parliament no longer has any authority in Australia, the legal basis of the Constitution no longer rests on any paramount rule of obedience to that institution. The legal theory that sustains the Constitution today is its acceptance by the Australian people as their framework of government. This 'acceptance' argument appears to be the second half of the argument utilised by Deane J in Theophanous v Herald & Weekly Times Ltd,161 which embraced both 'adoption' _____________________________________________________________________________________ 157 Twomey, above n 106, 101. 158 Marshall, above n 19, 58. It would appear the modern genesis of this notion can be traced to the horticultural comments made by Wheare about the Constitution being struck at Westminster but then transplanted to Australia, where it has since thrived: above n 2, 108109 and also Hart, above n 69, 120. 159 Leslie Zines, Constitutional Change in the Commonwealth (1991) 27. See also, Zines, above n 16, 318. However, Professor Zines indicates that this view does not necessarily elevate 'the People' to a fundamental legal norm: 'In other words [the Constitution] is our fundamental law and needs no further legal justification': Zines, above n 64, 93. Similar uncertainties that surround the legal basis of the Queensland Constitution are currently being addressed. The Queensland Constitutional Review Commission 'believes that such uncertainty should be brought to an end if possible… by making an unequivocal statement that the Queensland Constitution IS the fundamental law of the State by identifying it as the highest rule of the State's legal system': Queensland Constitutional Review Commission, Report on the Possible Reform of and Changes to The Acts and Laws that relate to the Queensland Constitution (2000) 24. Such a course would seem to overcome the difficulties surrounding the 'acceptance' argument and might also be considered for the Commonwealth Constitution. 160 First Report of the Constitutional Commission (1988), vol 1, 107. 161 (1994) 182 CLR 104, 171. In this respect Deane J seemed to follow Murphy J's reasoning in Kirmani v Captain Cook Cruises Pty. Ltd. [No. 1] (1985) 159 CLR 351 more closely than his own. Murphy J had stated, 383: 'The authority for the Australian Constitution then [1 January 1901] and now is its acceptance by the Australian people'. 268 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ by referenda (to be discussed shortly) and current 'acquiescence' as the touchstones of popular sovereignty. It is noted that Professor Zines's and the Commission's view have the attraction of recognising the original authority of the British Parliament.162 Professor Zines's view has the further attraction of not necessarily promoting a 'norm higher than the Constitution' itself.163 Geoffrey Lindell's view that the legally binding character of the Constitution is now derived from the will of the people has a further attraction. It is presented as an 'additional though not necessarily alternative, way of explaining the binding nature of the Constitution.’164 Justice Deane's view (in Theophanous), and Murphy J's view in Kirmani v Captain Cook Cruises Pty Ltd [No.1],165 have none of these attractions. Indeed, the correctness of Murphy J's view in Kirmani has been questioned as being inherently and manifestly improbable.166 Moreover, Deane J (in Theophanous) used Lindell's discussion as an alternative rather than additional argument, which Lindell specifically cautioned against.167 As such, this whole acceptance argument is not without difficulties. Even Marshall has noted the word 'acceptance' is ambiguous.168 Accordingly, the 'acceptance' or 'acquiescence' argument is to be given the short answer that at most it explains in political terms - not in legal terms - why the Constitution is binding. This is so for at least three interrelated reasons. The first reason has been consistently alluded to by Dawson J: there is a cogent argument for maintaining a firm distinction between 'legality' and 'legitimacy'. The legal reasons for obedience to the Constitution may not be the same as the moral reasons for obedience. As such, it is no contradiction for one to assert that, as a matter of legal theory, the legal basis of the Constitution is its passage through the Imperial Parliament, while at the same time one recognises that, as an abstract proposition of political theory, one actually accepts and obeys the Constitution because it is Australia's fundamental law.169 The motive for obeying the Constitution (the moral justification) is to be found in the study of political obligation (the concept of 'authority' is probably more helpful than 'sovereignty').170 However, the validity of the Constitution is to be found in the study of legal theory supported by history. In the language of Hart and Kelsen, the 'previous rule of recognition [or historically first constitution] remains a necessary means to identify the content of currently valid law'.171 Secondly, proponents of the 'acceptance' view can provide no empirical data to confirm such an assertion. In fact there is such data existing directly rebutting the theory: 'just under one in five Australians have some idea of what the Constitution _____________________________________________________________________________________ 162 So too does Deane J's recognition in Breavington v Godleman (1988) 169 CLR 41, 123 of 'the past authority of the United Kingdom Parliament'. 163 Zines, above n 64, 93. 164 Lindell, above n 40, 37 (emphases added). 165 (1985) 159 CLR 351, 383. 166 Noted by Greg Craven, Secession (1986) 138. See similar criticisms in China Ocean Shipping Co v South Australia (1979) 145 CLR 172, 181 (Barwick CJ). 167 Lindell, above n 40, 37, 44. See Lindell's recent concerns that his earlier 'additional' explanation has been developed in a way that may impact on constitutional interpretation: above n 16, 144. 168 Marshall, above n 19, 60. See also, Winterton, above n 16, 4 n 30. 169 See, ACTV (1992) 177 CLR 106, 181 (Dawson J). See also, Marshall, above n 19, 60. 170 See, Daley, above n 19. 171 Ibid, ch 4.1.2. 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 269 ____________________________________________________________________________________ contains ... [which] cannot amount to maintenance of the Constitution by the acquiescence of the people'.172 It would seem that to have any credence, the acceptance theory would need to at least show a 'bare majority of Australians' adhere to it. Consider a question posed to Australians as to why they still considered the Constitution as Australia's fundamental law? Some, if not many, might answer that the Constitution was, and still is law because it had been enacted by the United Kingdom Parliament.173 This would not be an incorrect answer.174 Thirdly, and as a corollary, one cannot be sure that the attitude of the Australian people has changed sufficiently to transform the rule of recognition to one based on popular acceptance. The complexity of explaining the acceptance of the Australian Constitution has been well noted.175 This is because the legal and political sources of constitutional authority are not one and the same. In the United States they are, and as a result, the notion of acceptance by a contemporary society seems especially applicable to the US Constitution. Even though the 'We The People' of today played no part in the adoption of the US Constitution, there is no other authoritative source to invoke but the 'mundane adherence to the status quo'. Thus in both legal and political theory 'the [US] Constitution is authoritative because [Americans] believe and act as if it is'.176 Criterion (iii) Adoption by referenda Daley has noted, '[i]f the crucial characteristic of popular will is the effective power to bring about legal change, then sovereignty must have been transferred much earlier than the passage of the Australia Acts'.177 However, arguments that promote the Australian populace as sovereign sometime before 1986, might represent 'very quaint aberration[s] ... of constitutional history'.178 Indeed, such arguments can be questioned on a number of levels. First, sponsors who assert that the popular vote approving the draft Constitution is the legal authority of the Constitution, have to contend with arguments that the vote was hardly popular.179 Secondly, even though the Constitution was on one level approved by the Australian electors, such action should only be seen as a 'mere antecedent historical circumstance'.180 The newly agreed upon _____________________________________________________________________________________ 172 George Williams, 'The High Court and the People' in Hugh. Selby (ed) Tomorrow's Law (1995) 271, 289. See also a poll conducted by I Saulwick in 1992 which found that 33 per cent of Australians did not even know that Australia has a written Constitution: referred to by Stephen Donaghue, 'The Clamour of Silent Constitutional Principles' (1996) 24 Federal Law Review 133, 146, n 87. It is admitted these figures may now be higher in light of the media coverage surrounding the 1999 referendum. 173 Craven, above n 166, 140. 174 Also noted by Wheare, above n 2, 109. 175 Ibid, 108. 176 Allan Ides, 'Judicial Supremacy and the Law of the Constitution' (1999) 47 UCLA Law Review 491, 505. 177 Daley, above n 19, ch 6.4.5. 178 China Ocean Shipping Co v South Australia (1979) 145 CLR 172, 181 (Barwick CJ). 179 Most women (all colonies except South Australia and Western Australia) and aboriginal Australians were denied the right to vote: noted by Zines, above n 16, 395-396. For a recent analysis of the categories of disqualification which plagued the franchise for the referenda, see, Anne Twomey, 'The Federal Constitutional Right to Vote in Australia' (2000) 28 Federal Law Review 125, 144. 180 Craven, above n 166, 76. Indeed, in this sense Australia's claim is much less than the referendum that approved the constitution of Eire in 1937. In that case, the approval of the 270 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ draft document remained just that, a consensual document, until it was enacted by the Westminster Parliament. Witness also the failure of the historic claim that the Imperial Parliament lacked legitimacy to amend the draft Constitution. Those involved in Federation 'were prepared to pay a real price for Imperial legitimacy',181 that is, Colonial Office interference in the form of s 74 of the Constitution which provided for the continuing supervision of the Privy Council over Australian Courts. Thirdly, if the people of Australia were truly sovereign, why did they (through their representatives) feel it necessary, in 1986, to go 'cap in hand' to request the United Kingdom Parliament to 'pass a statute concerning them at all?'.182 The simple answer might be that Australia's attainment of full independence was incomplete. Moreover, 'out of a perceived need for abundant caution'183 reversion to Westminster legislation was sought. But since 1986 more, not fewer, of Australia's constituent documents are to be found in the statute book of the United Kingdom.184 This action, far from recognising the popular basis of the Constitution, clearly demonstrated an acceptance of the 'legislative supremacy of the United Kingdom Parliament'.185 It further demonstrated that a peaceful legal revolution, accepted by the Australian people, to remove such legislative power, had not occurred any time before 1986. Fourthly, 'even if one supposes that the people did consent to the Constitution prior to Federation, this consent is irrelevant to obeying the Constitution today'.186 Summary of Marshall's Criteria At first blush, it would appear each of Marshall's criteria are distinct187 and if any one criterion is satisfied, autochthony is achieved. However, as Joseph has argued 'autochthony is most likely to be successfully asserted when all the criteria are satisfied'.188 Therefore, the better view would be that although Australia seems autochthonous by virtue of Marshall's criterion (i), the requirements of which are met by s 15(1) of the Australia Acts 1986, and possibly also by virtue of criterion (iii), the matter is inconclusive and still awaiting determination. It might also be said that Marshall was using the term 'autochthony' in a sense different from that employed by Wheare. Indeed, Hogg suggests '[Marshall] is really using it as equivalent to patriation'.189 In this sense one might use Marshall's criteria to _____________________________________________________________________________________ people 'constituted the enactment of the document': Wheare, above n 2, 94. Still further, Australia's claim is less than that asserted in 1922 by the founders of the constitution of the Irish Free State, who claimed they were sitting as a constituent assembly, and that the Irish Constitution was not 'passed' but merely 'registered' by the United Kingdom Parliament, L Kohn, The Constitution of the Irish Free State (1932) 91. 181 Daley, above n 19, ch 2.4.3, but cf Helen Irving, To Constitute a Nation (1997) 205. 182 Michael Kirby, Introduction (1996) 20 Melbourne University Law Review 949, 950. 183 Sue v Hill (1999) 163 ALR 648, 666 (Gleeson CJ, Gummow and Hayne JJ). 184 Also noted by Hogg in relation to Canada: above n 2, 54. 185 Craven, above n 166, 141. 186 Daley, above n 19, ch 6.3.2. 187 'The criteria are not synonymous': Joseph, above n 1, 412. 188 Ibid, 413: Even 'legal discontinuity is probably insufficient itself to establish a native legal root or local grundnorm'. 189 Hogg, above n 2, 55, n 44. 2001 The Legal Basis of the Australian Constitution 271 ____________________________________________________________________________________ secure patriation for the Australian Constitution, but as Aroney argues ''true' or 'complete' patriation requires autochthony'.190 CONCLUSION This article has noted an apparent confusion between autochthony and autonomy. Some might consider it 'unsatisfactory [and symbolically inappropriate]191 for the legal authority of the Constitution of an independent nation to be derived from an external source'.192 However, it is certainly not intrinsically illogical nor incongruous. Moreover, in Australia's constitutional arrangements, continued derivation does not imply continued subordination. If there is 'no national indignity in acknowledging legal continuity',193 one wonders why there is indignation in acknowledging legal derivation. 'The symbolism of deriving the Constitution's authority from another country is only superficially inappropriate. At a more mature level, such a derivation is inevitable'.194 Furthermore, Australia's autonomous arrangements are satisfactorily explained by this article's earlier emphasis on both complete independence and legal continuity. After all, it has been noted that 'legitimacy emerging over time can be at least as powerful as legitimacy expressed at a particular moment in a country's history'.195 However, it was also concluded that the search for autochthony is firmly in the hands of Australians. To rely on our British parent is unsatisfying and equivocal. Similarly, to rely on the High Court is unsatisfying, disturbingly undemocratic and at present highly confusing.196 The process should not be left to the judiciary alone to bring Australia's constitutional and legal arrangements into line with practical realities, even if that is thought necessary. It should involve all the constituent components of the federation including of course the vital popular element. Marshall's three criteria provide a guide for the attainment of autochthony. According to Marshall's first criterion (a local amending procedure), Australia may already be autochthonous on some level. Further, if one accepts the veracity of Marshall's second criterion (merely claiming a break in legal continuity), autochthony can be achieved without the necessity for a break in continuity. As such, if Australia was to repeal the Constitution Act,197 autochthony could be secured. However, in doing so Australians would need to claim that the effect was 'revolutionary'. This would be _____________________________________________________________________________________ 190 Aroney, above n 33, 271. Similarly Hogg concludes that 'if patriation means the securing of constitutional autochthony' patriation has not been achieved for the Canadian Constitution: above n 2, 55. 191 Aroney, above n 33, 271 noting Moshinsky, above n 1, 135. 192 Winterton, above n 16, 6. 193 Ibid 7. 194 Daley, above n 19, ch 5.6.1. 195 Oliver, above n 90, 551, noting J Beetz, 'Reflections on Continuity and Change in Law Reform' (1972) 12 University of Toronto Law Journal 129. 196 Winterton, above n 16, 2 has intimated that 'the outcome of constitutional litigation in the High Court [has become] highly unpredictable'. Similarly, Professor Zines has indicated that 'there is not… any general pattern or direction [in constitutional interpretation] at this stage': Leslie Zines, 'The Present State of Constitutional Interpretation' in Stone and Williams above n 106, 224-238, 238. 197 See, above nn 121-131 and accompanying text. 272 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ despite resorting to an 'evolutionary' process that relied on a power which in ultimate terms was externally-derived. Finally, if Australia was to declare autochthony based upon a declaration of popular sovereignty,198 autochthony could be secured by means of a peaceful legal revolution.199 Again 'the process is evolutionary but the effect revolutionary'.200 The people’s withdrawal of allegiance to the current monarch would violate the old order and institute a 'technical' break in continuity. However, if the first criterion does not apply, and the second criterion is not invoked, the issues may then be left to the High Court. If the traditional legal basis of the Constitution is then to be discarded, I have argued that the federal compact should be seen to be the substitute, not popular sovereignty. Further, if the issues are left to the High Court, autochthony could be achieved if the popular sovereignty thesis were 'sufficiently refined'201 (that is, clearly defined as to a theoretical or symbolic role, and unambiguous as to the true beneficiaries) and received the support of the majority as the legal basis of the Constitution. This would be because of the acceptance of the 'new attitude' probably according with Marshall's third criterion, and Hart's rule of recognition. The essential condition to determine whether constitutional arrangements have been annulled is the efficacy of the change. However, because of the largely inconclusive state of the authorities at present, it is impossible to predict with certainty whether or not the popular sovereignty revolution will succeed and if so, in what form.202 Until the content of the Australian grundnorm or rule of recognition is finally determined, and an Australian turtle is unequivocally installed, the Australian elephant may no longer be sure underfoot. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 198 See, above n 132-139 and accompanying text. 199 Wade, above n 40, 191-197: a 'disguised revolution'. 200 Joseph, above n 1, 122. 201 Craven, above n 45, 360. 202 Adapted from the judgment of Lord Reid in Madzimbamuto v Lardner-Burke [1969] 1 AC 645, 725 quoting in part Muhammed Munir CJ in The State v Dosso [1958] 2 PSCR 180, 185. THE MILITARY CALL-OUT LEGISLATION — SOME LEGAL AND CONSTITUTIONAL QUESTIONS Michael Head* Amid considerable public controversy, the Australian Labor Party combined with the Government of Prime Minister John Howard to pass military call-out legislation through both houses of the Commonwealth Parliament on 7 September 2000. Less than three months after it was first announced and introduced in the House of Representatives on 28 June, the Defence Legislation Amendment (Aid to Civilian Authorities) Act 2000 (Cth) came into force on 12 September, when it received royal assent by the Governor-General. Under the amended Defence Act 1903 (Cth) (the Act), the Federal Government now has the power to call out the armed forces on domestic soil against perceived threats to 'Commonwealth interests', with or without the agreement of a state government. Once deployed, military officers can order troops to open fire on civilians, as long as they determine that it is reasonably necessary to prevent death or serious injury. Soldiers will have greater powers than the police in some circumstances, including the right to shoot to kill someone escaping detention, search premises without warrants, detain people without formally arresting them, seal off areas and issue general orders to civilians. As will be examined in some detail in this article, the legislation authorises the Prime Minister, the Defence Minister and the Attorney-General, or 'for reasons of urgency', one of these 'authorising ministers', to advise the Governor-General (the Commander-in-Chief of the armed forces under the Constitution) to call out military personnel to deal with 'domestic violence'. The term 'domestic violence' is somewhat of an anachronism. It does not correspond to the modern sense of the phrase, which refers to violence within homes or families. It is a vague expression, undefined legislatively or judicially, found in s 119 of the Constitution, which provides that 'the Commonwealth shall protect every State against invasion and, on the application of the Executive Government of the State protect such State against domestic violence'. Both the Government and the Labor Party proposed minor amendments in an effort to meet certain objections from some state governments and to head off public concern about the impact on civil liberties, but the legislation's essential content remained the same: to authorise the use of the military to deal with civilian disturbances, including _____________________________________________________________________________________ * B Juris, LLB (Monash), LLM (Columbia), Coordinator, Community Law Program, Law Faculty, University of Western Sydney. Some aspects of this article are drawn from earlier reports published by the author on the World Socialist Web Site (www.wsws.org), see below n 10. 274 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ political and industrial unrest. The very fact that such legislation has been introduced and passed suggests a bipartisan expectation in official political circles that, in the coming period, troops will be required to deal with such disturbances that the police forces cannot contain. Until now, the deployment of troops within the country has been both politically contentious and clouded by legal uncertainties. In the words of one author, although Australia was established as a penal colony under military administration, 'with the passage of time, the evolution of the Australian political system ensured a clear distinction between military powers and civil powers'.1 During the 19th century, martial law was declared several times to deal with riots and rebellions, but the last clear exception to the military-civil division of power occurred in 1891 when the Queensland Government used troops to help the police suppress a sheep shearers' strike.2 This division of power was enshrined in the Constitution at federation in 1901. The military power was handed to the Commonwealth under s 51(xxxi), the colonial defence forces were transferred to the Commonwealth by s 69, and under s 114 the states were forbidden to raise military or naval forces without the consent of the Commonwealth Parliament. Residual authority over domestic law and order remained in the hands of the states and their police forces. The constitutional demarcation has, furthermore, become embedded in public consciousness. Domestic use of the armed forces has become widely regarded as conduct to be expected of a military or autocratic regime, not a democratic government. On the only occasion since federation that a Commonwealth government has called out the military in an urban situation — following a bomb blast outside a regional Commonwealth Heads of Government meeting at the Sydney Hilton Hotel in 1978 — the sight of armed soldiers patrolling highways and the streets of the New South Wales town of Bowral caused public consternation.3 THE PASSAGE OF THE LEGISLATION Despite the historic importance of the issue, the legislation was initially introduced without any publicity. With the support of the Opposition, the Bill was first passed through the House of Representatives in a single day on 28 June 2000. Neither Defence Minister John Moore nor Attorney-General Daryl Williams issued a media statement announcing the Bill, and no reports appeared in the mass media. Just one day before the Bill was tabled, the Government launched a public discussion paper, Defence Review 2000, in preparation for a Defence White Paper. The document canvassed an expanded role for the military, but made no mention of the Bill.4 Both the Government and the Opposition declared that it was necessary to have the legislation in place before the Sydney Olympic Games. Speaking in the House of _____________________________________________________________________________________ 1 Christopher Doogan, 'Defence Powers Under the Constitution: Use of Troops in Aid of State Police Forces — Suppression of Terrorist Activities' (1981) 31 Defence Force Journal 31. 2 Ibid 31. 3 See Tom Molomby, Spies, Bombs and the Path of Bliss (1986), and Jenny Hocking, Beyond Terrorism: The Development of the Australian Security State (1993). 4 See Defence 2000 — Our Future Defence Force, (2000) Department of Defence, <http://whitepaper.defence.gov.au> [accessed 27 June 2000]. 2001 The Military Call-Out Legislation 275 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Representatives, Labor's shadow defence minister, Stephen Martin, referred to the Olympics as the 'catalyst' for the Bill.5 He committed the Opposition to having the Bill passed before the Games. 'It is important that a spirit of bipartisanship be exhibited ... on something as important as this', he told the House. In the brief debate, references were made on both sides of the House to the need to counter possible terrorism at the Olympics, where some 4,000 military personnel were deployed.6 After expedited examinations by two Senate committees, whose recommendations for minor amendments were partially adopted,7 the legislation was ultimately passed on the last day of sitting before the 15 September opening of the Games. Despite this haste, the Act was not invoked during the Olympics.8 The implications of the legislation go far beyond the Sydney Olympics. The Act effects a permanent shift in the military's role. In the words of shadow attorney-general Robert McClelland: 'These measures should not be seen as simply a short-term measure that can be sunsetted after the Olympics. They are in themselves important measures that are certainly required'.9 The Government and the Opposition rejected amendments to insert a sunset clause that would revoke the legislation after the Games. Despite the initial lack of publicity, some media outlets began to report on the legislation, partly because of material prepared by this author.10 Newspapers received numerous letters protesting against the Bill, prompting a public statement from the government. In a joint news release on 23 August, Attorney-General Daryl Williams and Defence Minister John Moore asserted that the Bill did not change the conditions in which the armed forces could be called out: 'State, Territory and Commonwealth Governments have always had the power to request call out of the Defence Force in _____________________________________________________________________________________ 5 Commonwealth, Parliamentary Debates, House of Representatives, 28 June 2000, 18413 (Stephen Martin, MP, ALP). 6 See Michael Head, 'Olympic Security: Police and military plans for the Sydney Olympics — a cause for concern' (2000) 25 Alternative Law Journal 131. 7 See Senate Foreign Affairs, Defence and Trade Legislation Committee, Defence Legislation Amendment (Aid to Civilian Authorities) Bill 2000 (2000), The Parliament of the Commonwealth of Australia, <http://www.aph.gov.au/senate/committee/submissions/fadt_civbill.htm>; and Senate Standing Committee for the Scrutiny of Bills, Alert Digest No 10 of 2000, (16 August 2000). 8 It has since been revealed, however, that elite SAS personnel were deployed undercover in plain clothes, assisting the New South Wales police to monitor crowds during the Olympics, without approval by the Defence Minister or federal Cabinet. Cabinet's National Security Committee subsequently approved the deployment, without any reference to the Act. See The Sydney Morning Herald, 9 February 2001, 6. 9 Commonwealth, Parliamentary Debates, House of Representatives, 28 June 2000, 18420 (Robert McClelland, MP, ALP). 10 See, for example, Michael Head, 'Australian government uses Sydney Olympics to strengthen military powers' (2000) World Socialist Web Site <http://www.wsws.org/articles/2000/aug2000/olym-a05_prn.shtml>; Michael Head, 'Australian government seeks to push through revamped military call-out bill' (2000) World Socialist Web Site <http://www.wsws.org./articles/2000/aug2000/milita29_prn.shtml>; Michael Head, 'Sydney Olympics used as 'catalyst' for permanent military powers over civilian unrest' (2000) 25 Alternative Law Journal 192. 276 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Australia in rare situations where police need help to deal with an extreme emergency'.11 In the final hours of the parliamentary debate, Labor's spokesmen, Mr Martin and Senator John Faulkner, made similar statements. Mr Martin condemned those who had opposed the Act 'under the guise of protecting civil liberties', adding that people had been 'fooled by inaccurate and misleading reporting and cheap and populist politics'.12 He asserted that the legislation would not, in any way, add to the Government's power to call out the army. Instead, Mr Martin claimed, the Bill placed new restrictions on the use of the military. These statements are contradicted by the legislation itself. It seeks to add both to the government's call-out powers and to the powers of military personnel once they are called out. It provides that the utilisation and powers of the armed forces under its provisions shall be additional to any other lawful use of the military. The amended s 51Y of the Act states that 'this Part does not affect any utilisation of the Defence Force that would be permitted or required, or any powers that the Defence Forces would have, if this Part were disregarded'.13 Thus, the Act does not place new restrictions on the use of the military, but augments the government's previous call-out powers. Furthermore, the purpose of the legislation is to overcome definite legal and constitutional limits and restrictions that have, combined with political considerations, provided real constraints on the use of the armed forces in civilian settings. Thus, s 51A of the amended Act goes well beyond the previous s 51, which essentially mirrored s 119 of the Constitution. In the first place, the new section allows a military call-out where the three ministers are satisfied that domestic violence is occurring, 'or is likely to occur'. The latter phrase is an addition to s 119 and is therefore arguably unconstitutional. Secondly, the new section extends the call-out power to the protection of 'Commonwealth interests', regardless of whether there is a request by any state or territory government. The new s 51A(3) provides that 'the Governor-General may make the order whether or not the Government of the State or the self-governing Territory request the making of the order'. This provision, in so far as it purports to permit a military intervention without the consent of a state, also arguably contravenes s 119, which requires state assent to the use of troops on state soil. Section 51A(3) requires only that an authorising minister 'consult' the state or territory government before the Governor-General makes the order. Plainly, consultation does not mean assent. Moreover, under s 51A(3A), that proviso does not apply if the Governor-General is satisfied that 'for reasons of urgency, it is impracticable' to comply with it. Under s 51A(8A), an authorising minister must notify a state government that an order has been made but 'if this is not done, the validity of the making or revocation of the order is not affected'. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 11 John Moore and Daryl Williams, 'Further Safeguards for Defence Bill' (23 August 2000) Department of Defence <http://www.minister.defence.gov.au//2000/22900.htm> 12 Commonwealth, Parliamentary Debates, House of Representatives, 7 September 2000, 20511 (Stephen Martin, MP, ALP). 13 The Explanatory Memorandum states that s 51Y 'makes it clear that the new process for calling out members of the Defence Force does not in any way detract from the use of the Defence Force that would be permitted or required under any powers that the Defence Force would have if the new Part were not in place'. 2001 The Military Call-Out Legislation 277 ____________________________________________________________________________________ In seeking to by-pass s 119, as shall be discussed below, the legislation appears to rest on a combination of other Commonwealth constitutional powers — the defence, external affairs, incidentals, executive and Governor-General's powers — yet the Government has not specified upon which of these powers it is relying. Beyond the constitutional issues, the legislation is an attempt to overcome a variety of serious legal problems. Under existing legislative provisions and the common law, if military personnel kill or maim individuals, damage private property or interfere with people's liberty, they could be charged with criminal offences, including murder or manslaughter, or face civil action. Moreover, as commentators have pointed out, soldiers could not necessarily rely on a defence of obeying superior orders.14 In addition, military personnel lacked legislative powers to carry out searches, seizures and arrests. That is why, when troops were called out in 1974 to guard Darwin's petrol depots from looters after the destruction of Cyclone Tracy, General Stretton, the commander of the Natural Disaster Organisation, stipulated that troops not carry arms, that they be accompanied by a police officer and that the soldier's authority would stem from a citizen's duty under common law.15 The legislation confers such potentially far-reaching powers on the Government and the military, that the Australian Democrats' spokesperson, Senator Vicki Bourne, appealed to the Government to agree to Parliament being re-called within two days of a troop call-out.16 This would allow Parliament to assume political responsibility for any such decision, she argued. Likewise, the Australian Greens' representative, Senator Bob Brown, warned that if troops had to be brought in because a situation was so grave that a state police force and its tactical response group were unable to handle the crisis, 'the country would be in pandemonium. This would be a situation beyond anything in our last 100 years of history ... surely, in that situation, the Parliament should be recalled'. During the final two days of debate, the Government and the Labor Party together defeated a series of amendments from the minor parties to modify the call-out power. One measure would have required the military to obtain judicial warrants before searching homes. Another would have limited the right to shoot to kill a fleeing person, similar to a restriction placed upon the Australian Federal Police, and another would have allowed soldiers to claim conscientious objection to deployment against civilians. A further amendment would have required the tabling in Parliament of the manuals and protocols that will apply to military interventions. This proposal was raised after Senator Brown read out extracts from the then current Australian Army Manual of Land Warfare. Section 543 of that manual instructed military personnel in how to cover up the killing or wounding of 'dissidents'. The section stated: Dead and wounded dissidents, if identifiable, must be removed immediately by the police ... When being reported, dissident and own casualties are categorised merely as dead or wounded. To inhibit propaganda exploitation by the dissidents the cause of the casualties _____________________________________________________________________________________ Peter Brett and Peter Waller, Brett and Waller's Criminal Law: Text and Cases (1983) 654. Alan Stretton, The Furious Days (1976) 82-83. For these debates, see Commonwealth, Parliamentary Debates, Senate, 6 September 2000, 17389 (Vicki Bourne, Senator, NSW), and Commonwealth, Parliamentary Debates, Senate, 7 September 2000, 17536 (Vicki Bourne, Senator). 14 15 16 278 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ (for example, ‘shot') is not reported. A follow-up operation should be carried out to maintain the momentum of the dispersing crowd.17 Responding to Senator Brown, Special Minister of State Chris Ellison said the Army manual was 'under revision' and would be replaced with a new version once the Act was passed. He refused, however, to give any assurance that a similar clause would not appear in the rewritten document. Various state governments objected to parts of the legislation because it overrides their police powers and may cause clashes between the military and the state-run police forces. In the New South Wales Government submission to the Senate Foreign Affairs, Defence and Trade Legislation Committee, the Director General of the New South Wales Cabinet Office stated that the legislation could lead to 'conflict between State police and Commonwealth Defence Forces' and might 'override the national antiterrorist plan'. In the submission of the Victorian Department of Premier and Cabinet, Premier Bracks declared: 'Confusion and conflict could arise between state agencies and the Defence Force'.18 These concerns were reflected in several newspaper editorials and commentaries. 'The potential for State-Commonwealth conflict is obvious,' the Sydney Morning Herald editorialised on 18 August. 'For example, would the Federal Government have found it easier to use such a procedure to send troops in if it had thought the New South Wales Police were not up to the mark at the height of the 1998 waterfront dispute?' The use of troops in such politically-charged conditions — thousands of people joined picket lines during the 1998 waterfront strike — may provoke controversy, the newspaper warned. 'As a rule, the States and their police — who, after all, are better trained than troops for the job — are the ones to deal with civil disturbances'.19 Apart from providing for a state government to be 'consulted' before a call-out was ordered, the Government and the Opposition largely brushed these reservations aside. The final vote in the Senate was 46 to 10. When the legislation went back to the House of Representatives for one last vote, only two independent Members of Parliament were against its introduction. THE HISTORICAL CONTEXT The legislation challenges a political and legal tradition opposing the use of the military to suppress domestic unrest — a principle that dates back to the 17th century struggles against the absolutist monarchy in Britain. In the lead up to the English revolution of the 1640s, the 1628 Petition of Right demanded that Charles I remove the 'great companies of soldiers and mariners [who] have been dispersed into diverse counties of the realm … against the laws and customs of this realm and to the great grievance and vexation of the people'. The Petition is regarded as making it unconstitutional for the Crown to impose martial law on civilians.20 As a result of the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 17 Quoted by Senator Brown, Commonwealth, Parliamentary Debates, Senate, 6 September 2000, 17398 (Bob Brown, Senator, Tasmania). 18 For these and other submissions, see above n 7. 19 Editorial, The Sydney Morning Herald, 18 August 2000. 20 See W S Holdsworth, 'Martial Law Historically Considered' (1902) 18 Law Quarterly Review 117. 2001 The Military Call-Out Legislation 279 ____________________________________________________________________________________ 1688 settlement between the monarchy and the parliament, the Bill of Rights declared it illegal for the Crown to raise or keep an army without parliamentary consent.21 Doubt has surrounded the legal force of this taboo. Commenting on the public disquiet provoked by the 1978 Bowral call-out, Blackshield referred to a longstanding popular social tradition against the use of the armed forces within the realm in peacetime. 'But as soon as one asks whether this social tradition is reflected in any legal tradition that might be invoked as a constitutional restraint on the use of armed forces, one is plunged into an esoteric maze of uncertainties'.22 In spite of the critical issues at stake, relevant judicial comment has been rare. One exception occurred in the 1989 High Court case of Re Tracey; Ex parte Ryan,23 which considered the constitutionality of military courts martial. Justices Brennan and Toohey reviewed the history of the struggle for civilian supremacy over the armed forces, and spoke of the common law's concern to ensure that the existence of the armed forces 'as a permanent armed body under hierarchical command should not threaten the peace and civil order of the Realm'.24 Given that the use of troops against civilians was not tested in Australia during the 20th century, the position is still regarded as based on the British law. By the early 19th century, the emergence of mass protests fuelled by the conditions of the Industrial Revolution caused the British authorities to resort to military suppression at times. In the 1832 case of R v Pinney25 three officers were tried before a Grand Jury after riots in Bristol. Two officers who had refused to order the troops to fire without a magistrate's sanction were found guilty of neglect of duty, causing one to commit suicide. The third officer, who had fatally shot someone during the incident, was acquitted of manslaughter. Some general principles were laid down by the 1893 English Report of the Select Committee on the Featherstone Riots. Two people were killed when an infantry Captain ordered soldiers to fire on striking coal miners and their supporters after a local magistrate had read the proclamation from the Riot Act 1714. The Committee exonerated the Captain and his troops, although it warned that 'officers and soldiers are under no special privileges and subject to no special responsibilities as regards this principle of the law'. The taking of life must be shown to be necessary and resort to military assistance must be the 'last expedient' of the civil authorities, but when such a call was made, 'to refuse such assistance is in law a misdemeanour'.26 In addition, notwithstanding the 1628 Petition of Right, British law was also prepared to support recourse to the even more far-reaching imposition of martial law if the very existence of the state were threatened by civil unrest. According to Halsbury, martial law applies 'when a state of actual war, or of insurrection, riot, or rebellion amounting to war, exists'.27 Martial law has been somewhat loosely described _____________________________________________________________________________________ 21 See Steven Greer, 'Military Intervention in Civil Disturbances: The Legal Basis Reconsidered' [1983] Public Law 573. 22 AR Blackshield, 'The Siege of Bowral — The Legal Issues' (1978) 4 Pacific Defence Reporter 6. 23 (1989) 166 CLR 518. 24 Ibid, 562. 25 (1832) St Tr (1891), N S Vol 3; 5 C & P 254. 26 United Kingdom, Parl Papers Vol 17, (1893-94) 381. 27 Lord Hailsham (ed), Halsbury's Laws of England (4th ed, 1973–), vol 8(2), para 821. 280 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ as 'the right to use force against force within the realm in order to suppress civil disorder'.28 This formulation could justify the most dictatorial measures. Doubt exists as to the legal basis of martial law. It is said to be either an example of a common law right to employ force to repel force or, alternatively, a royal prerogative.29 Despite this fundamental uncertainty, the Privy Council in the 1902 Marais case on appeal from the Cape Colony, extended the doctrine of martial law to apply even where the ordinary civilian courts were still sitting.30 There has been no recorded case of martial law in Australia since federation in 1901 but it was invoked several times during the 19th century to suppress convicts, Aborigines and workers.31 In his work, Emergency Powers, Lee 'hazards a guess' that the power to resort to martial law continues in Australia as a creature of the common law. Remarkably, Lee considers that, while legislation is generally preferable, the doctrine of martial law should not be buried 'for in the face of an extraordinary crisis it may come in useful… it may be better to rely on a "shadowy, uncertain, precarious something" than nothing at all'.32 The great strike struggles of the 1890s did see troops mobilised against specific demonstrations and gatherings, with orders to shoot to kill strikers and their supporters. In one infamous incident, Colonel Tom Price issued the following instruction to a volunteer unit during the extended Australian maritime strike of 1890: Men of the Mounted Rifles, one of your obligations imposes upon you the duty of resisting invasion by a foreign enemy, but you are also liable to be called upon to assist in preserving law and order in the colony…To do your work faintly would be a grave mistake. If it has to be done effectively you will each be supplied with 40 rounds of ammunition, leaden bullets, and if the order is given to fire, don’t let me see any rifle pointed in the air; fire low and lay them out so that the duty will not have to be performed again.33 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 28 Robert Heuston, Essays in Constitutional Law (2nd ed, 1964) 152. 29 See, for example, Halsbury's Laws of England, above n 27, para 821. 30 D F Marais v The General Officer Commanding the Lines of Communication and the AttorneyGeneral of the Colony [1902] AC 109. 31 See S D Lendrum, 'The 'Corrong Massacre': Martial Law and the Aborigines at First Settlement' (1977) 6 Adelaide Law Review 26. See also Victor Windeyer, 'Certain Questions Concerning the Position of Members of the Defence Force When Called Out to Aid the Civil Power' in Robert Hope, Protective Security Review Report (1979) Appendix 9. 32 H P Lee, Emergency Powers (1984) 224. The quoted words are taken from R v Nelson and Brand (1867) F Cockburn Sp Rep 86, where Cockburn CJ stated: 'Martial law when applied to the civilian is no law at all, but a shadowy, uncertain, precarious something, depending entirely on the conscience, or rather on the despotic and arbitrary will of those who administer it.' 33 Quoted in Brian McKinlay, A Documentary History of the Australian Labor Movement, 18501975 (1979) 377. Such instructions — to 'fire low and lay them out' — are still mirrored in the Australian Military Regulations. Regulation 421(6) specifies that: 'Care shall be taken to fire only upon those who can be seen to be implicated in the disturbance'. Lee, above n 32, 242. Regulation 410 requires the commander of the forces to warn those present that, if the troops are ordered to fire, the fire will be effective. Call Out the Troops: an examination of the legal basis for Australian Defence Force involvement in 'non-defence' matters, Australian Parliamentary Research Paper 8 (1997-98) 5. 2001 The Military Call-Out Legislation 281 ____________________________________________________________________________________ The turmoil of the 1890s led to s 119 being inserted in the Constitution, to allow the military to be mobilised against an 'uncontrollable situation'.34 The expression 'domestic violence' was borrowed from article IV of the United States Constitution, s 4 of which specifies that the United States shall protect each State, on the application of its legislature, against 'domestic violence'. The statutory embodiment of this provision in 10 USC § 331 (1964) uses the more specific term 'insurrection', suggesting that an extremely serious level of rebellion must be involved — one that threatens the very existence of a state government.35 In the early years of the 20th century, Australian state governments requested military intervention on at least six occasions, to deal with such anticipated incidents as 'general strike riot and bloodshed', 'disturbances', wharf strike 'violence', 'labour troubles' and the 1923 Victorian police strike. On each occasion, it seems, the Federal Government declined on the basis that the state police were capable of dealing with the threat (although troops were sent to guard federal buildings, including post offices, during the Victorian police strike).36 Only one of those requests — by Queensland in 1912 — was formally made under s 119. Thus, s 119 has never been applied. In general, the invoking of 'military aid to the civil power' has been a relatively rare event in Australia, confined, at least as far as is known publicly, to unarmed and peaceful use in national emergencies, such as floods, cyclones and earthquakes. With little publicity, however, the Defence Forces do frequently provide technical and other assistance to the state, federal and territory police forces, most commonly for explosives disposal and logistical support.37 Troops were mobilised to break strikes on several occasions during the 20th century, mostly by Labor governments. The Chifley Government sent in soldiers against the coal miners’ strike of 1949, the Fraser Government used the RAAF to ferry passengers during the 1981 Qantas strike and the Hawke Government mobilised the airforce against striking pilots in 1989. These operations provoked bitter recriminations and questions as to their legality.38 In a lesser known case, the Menzies Liberal Government sent troops to break a wharf labourers' strike in Bowen, Queensland in 1953, but was forced to withdraw the soldiers after tensions involving strikers and state police, followed by a protest by the Queensland Government.39 On several occasions, soldiers were deployed for political purposes. In 1970-71, the Gorton Government called out troops to suppress secessionist agitation in Papua New Guinea, then an Australian colony. Since no state government request was involved, s 119 of the Constitution could not be invoked, nor could the defence power, since Papua New Guinea was regarded as Australian soil. It seems that on legal advice, the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 34 Blackshield, above n 22. 35 See generally M Cherif Bassiouni, The Law of Dissent and Riots (1971). 36 Lee, above n 32, 201. 37 See Call Out the Troops, above n 33, 42 — between January 1988 and September 1989, the Australian Defence Force provided assistance to police forces on 1,518 occasions. 38 Ibid 19. 39 See Call Out the Troops, ibid 19. 282 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Defence Minister Malcolm Fraser insisted on the issuing of a secret Order-in-Council to authorise the call-out, but its constitutionality remains questionable.40 The gravest political crisis came in 1975, when the Governor-General Sir John Kerr secretly placed the armed forces on alert after dismissing the Whitlam government.41 No troops were seen on the streets, however. In 1983, the Hawke Government authorised RAAF flights over Tasmania to photograph work being conducted by the Tasmanian Government in breach of Commonwealth regulations and in 1989, the same Government authorised the dispatch of troops to combat protesters at the Nurrungar joint Australian-United States military satellite base. Both deployments generated political controversy and legal uncertainty, particularly with regard to the potential use of soldiers to confront demonstrators outside the Nurrungar base perimeter.42 THE 1978 CALL-OUT The most dramatic military deployment occurred in 1978 when Prime Minister Malcolm Fraser and the New South Wales Premier Neville Wran called out nearly 2,000 soldiers in Sydney and the New South Wales Southern Highlands town of Bowral after the explosion outside the Commonwealth Heads of Government Meeting at the Sydney Hilton.43 The mass media and the federal and state governments declared that the 'age of terrorism' had arrived in Australia. Two ensuing reports by Justice Hope44 and one by former London police chief Sir Robert Mark45 recommended a significant boost to the powers of the Australian Security Intelligence Organisation (ASIO), the establishment of the Federal Police, wider domestic use of the army’s Special Air Services (SAS), and the creation of 'anti-terrorist' and SWAT-style squads in every state police force. In addition, Crisis Policy Centres were set up to facilitate the provision of 'military aid to the civil power'. They are police-military 'nerve centres', run by the Protective Security Co-ordination Centre (PSCC), which includes representatives of the Prime Minister’s National Security Council, the Office of National Assessments, ASIO and the Australian Secret Intelligence Service (ASIS, the external intelligence service), the military and the federal and state police.46 The Government's response to the Hilton bombing raised significant legal questions. Two inter-related issues arose: (1) Were such interventions constitutional and, if so, what was their precise constitutional basis? (2) What were the powers and rules of engagement of the military personnel and the rights of civilians in relation to _____________________________________________________________________________________ 40 Ibid 13. See also B D Beddie and Stanley Moss, 'Some Aspects of Aid to the Civil Power in Australia' (1982) Occasional Monograph No 2 (University of New South Wales Dept of Government) 55. 41 See 'The Canberra Coup', Workers News (1976). 42 See Call Out the Troops, above n 33, 14 -18. 43 See above n 4. 44 Robert Hope, The Royal Commission on Intelligence and Security, Reports I, II, III, IV (1977); Robert Hope, Protective Security Review Report (1979) and Appendix 9 to that report, Windeyer, above n 31. 45 Robert Mark, Report to the Minister for Administrative Services on the organisation of police resources in the Commonwealth area and other related matters (1978). 46 Mike Halliday, 'Crisis Policy Centres' (12, 19, 26 January 1980) Workers News Parts I, II, III. See also Hocking, above n 3, 177. 2001 The Military Call-Out Legislation 283 ____________________________________________________________________________________ the military? Neither question was addressed in the two formal documents ordering the military intervention, namely the joint statement by the Prime Minister and the New South Wales Premier, and the Executive Order issued by the Governor-General Sir Zelman Cowen.47 In his statement to Parliament, Prime Minister Fraser stated that the New South Wales Premier had concurred with the call-out but had not requested it. He did not specifically refer to s 119 of the Constitution, or explain the precise legal basis for the call-out, instead stating: The mechanism for the legal approach to the call-out was discussed with the Premier in two terms: In terms of a strict request from the State, and therefore in terms of aid to the civil power; or, secondly, in terms of the use of the Commonwealth's own authority and responsibility to protect people against possible acts of terrorism. For various reasons as I explained to the House I think yesterday, the second course was chosen, but the Premier had made it perfectly clear to me that if it was thought best to pursue it through the first mechanism, the Premier would certainly act in full cooperation.48 Three months later, after some speculation as to the legal basis for the Government's action, the Attorney-General Peter Durack confirmed that no recourse had been made to s 119 of the Constitution. This left several possibilities. One, asserted by Justice Hope in his 1979 Protective Security Review,49 commissioned by the Fraser Government, was that the Governor-General acted under s 68 of the Constitution, which states, without qualification, that: 'The commander-in-chief of the naval and military forces of the Commonwealth is vested in the Governor-General as the Queen’s representative'. Another possibility, canvassed by academic commentators, is that the Federal Government exercised its executive power, also formally exercisable by the GovernorGeneral, under s 61 of the Constitution to ensure the 'execution and maintenance of this Constitution, and of the laws of the Commonwealth'. References have also been made to the Commonwealth's defence power (s 51(vi) of the Constitution), combined with the external affairs power (s 51(xxix)), and the incidental powers (s 51(xxxix)). Other possibilities mentioned have been an 'inherent self-protecting' power of the Commonwealth, 'inherent law and order powers' and the Crown's prerogative power over defence and military matters.50 A 1978 note in the Australian Law Journal observed that the Hilton bombing call-out had 'exposed gaps, inadequacies, and uncertainties in the legal and constitutional powers of Commonwealth and State enforcement agencies'.51 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 47 For these documents, and general discussion, see Hocking, above n 3. 48 Commonwealth, Parliamentary Debates, House of Representatives, 23 February 1978, 159 (Malcolm Fraser, Prime Minister). 49 Hope, Protective Security Review Report, above n 44. 50 See 'Current Topics: Legal and constitutional problems of protective security arrangements in Australia' (1978) 52 Australian Law Journal 296, and P H Lane, An Introduction to the Australian Constitution (1974) 77. 51 (1978) 52 Australian Law Journal 296. Nevertheless, the author found sufficient constitutional support for the operation in the preamble to the Order of the Governor-General calling out the troops: 'Whereas I am satisfied, by reason of terrorist activities and related violence that have occurred in the State of New South Wales, that it is necessary — 284 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Despite this lack of constitutional clarity, no legislation was introduced to provide clear authority for military deployment. Quoting the 18th century conservative Edmund Burke, Justice Hope called for legislation, observing that: Use of the military other than for external defence, is a critical and controversial issue in the political life of a country and the civil liberties of its citizens. 'An armed disciplined body is in its essence dangerous to Liberty; undisciplined, it is ruinous to Society'. Given that there must be a permanent Defence Force, it is critical that it be employed only for proper purposes and that it be subject to proper control.52 Aware of the political sensitivity of the issue, the Fraser Government did not legislate. Instead, the only relevant legislative instruments remained the Australian Military Regulations and internal Defence Instructions, not all of which have been made public. Part 5 of the Regulations, 'Duties in Aid of the Civil Power During Domestic Violence', provides that a magistrate must accompany the defence forces into an area and 'read the Riot Act' before the troops move in. This, as Members of Parliament discussed in the House of Representatives, is now regarded in official circles as an impossibly cumbersome procedure. The Defence Instructions (General) on Defence Force Aid to the Civil Power remain classified documents,53 a highly unsatisfactory situation when the implications for civil liberties are great. Of equal concern is the fact that under the Act, the Instructions may be changed at any time without parliamentary or public scrutiny.54 Two decades after the 1978 call-out, and taking advantage of the Olympics, the Government has brought forward legislation that seeks to expand its military call-out power without addressing either the constitutional doubts or the civil liberties concerns. Just as the 1978 Hilton bombing became the occasion for claims that Australia had entered the 'age of terrorism', various police and military authorities claimed that the Olympics would be a 'magnet' for terrorists.55 The nature of the legislation, however, makes it apparent that the authorities are preparing not simply for terrorism, but for wider civil unrest that the police forces prove unable to quell. _____________________________________________________________________________________ (a) for the purpose of safeguarding the national and international interests of the Commonwealth of Australia; (b) for giving effect to the obligations of the Commonwealth of Australia in relation to the protection of internationally protected persons; and (c) for other purposes related to those matters, to call out the Defence Forces for and in relation to those purposes'. To rely upon such a preamble seems dubious in the light of the Communist Party Case (Australian Communist Party v Commonwealth (1951) 83 CLR 1). The High Court ruled unconstitutional an attempt by the Federal Government to outlaw the Communist Party, rejecting the Menzies Government's attempt to make its legislation valid by invoking various heads of power in a preamble to its legislation. 52 Hope, Protective Security Review, above n 44, 142. 53 Call Out the Troops, above n 33. 54 Bayne has questioned whether the Instructions might be subject to publication requirements under the Statutory Rules Publication Act 1903 (Cth) or be covered by s 9 of the Freedom of Information Act 1982 (Cth) — see Peter Bayne, 'Policy guidelines and the law: some intersections' (1991) 65 Australian Law Journal 607. 55 See my earlier article, above n 10. 2001 The Military Call-Out Legislation 285 ____________________________________________________________________________________ THE LEGISLATION The amended Act allows the three authorising ministers to call out the military in three circumstances. Where the ministers are satisfied that domestic violence is occurring or is likely to occur, the armed forces can be used to: (1) protect Commonwealth interests, where a State or Territory is 'not, or is unlikely to be, able to protect' those interests;56 (2) protect a State, where the State is not, or is unlikely to be, able to protect itself;57 and (3) protect a self-governing Territory, where the Territory is not, or is unlikely to be, able to protect itself.58 In the latter two cases, the government of the State or Territory must first make an application, but no such restriction applies to the first case. In each instance, neither the Emergency Forces nor the Reserves Forces can be called out or used in connection with an industrial dispute. These provisions will not prevent a government using the regular armed forces against strikers or as strikebreakers, as happened in 1949, 1953, 1981 and 1989.59 Once deployed, the military forces will have wide-ranging powers that they currently do not have in civilian situations. Under s 51I, any member of the Defence Force will be able to: • seize buildings, places and means of transport • detain people • search premises • seize possessions. Where these powers are exercised in connection with the recapture of a premises or means of transport, written authority for that recapture must first be obtained from an authorising minister, except where the member of the Defence Force 'believes on reasonable grounds that there is insufficient time to obtain the authorisation because a sudden and extraordinary emergency exists'. If the three ministers declare a 'general security area' under s 51K these powers will be expanded to include personal searches, erection of barriers and stopping means of transport. If a 'designated area' is declared within a general security zone under s 51Q, the powers will increase further. The military will be able to halt and control all movements of traffic and people, issue directions to individuals and 'compel' people to comply with directions. No criteria are specified for the declaration of general security zones and designated areas, but the declaration of a general security area must be published and both Houses of Parliament must be notified and recalled within six days. The most revealing measures are those contained in s 51T on the use of 'reasonable and necessary force'. Soldiers will be permitted to cause death or grievous bodily harm where they believe 'on reasonable grounds' that such action is necessary to protect the life of, or prevent serious injury to, another person — including the soldiers involved. Moreover, a person 'attempting to escape being detained by fleeing' may be killed or caused grievous bodily harm if they have been called on to surrender and a soldier _____________________________________________________________________________________ 56 Defence Legislation Amendment (Aid to Civilian Authorities) Act 2000 (Cth) s 51A. 57 Ibid s 51B. 58 Ibid s 51C. 59 See above pp 6-9. 286 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ believes on reasonable grounds that the person cannot be apprehended in any other way. Confronted by public hostility to its earlier unconditional endorsement of the Act, the Labor Party moved an amendment forbidding troops to 'stop or restrict any protest, dissent, assembly or industrial action, except where there is a reasonable likelihood of the death of, or serious injury to, persons'. The Government added a final clause 'or serious damage to property', which Labor accepted. The resulting s 51G opens the way for wide use of the call-out power. Likelihood of property damage can easily be alleged. As independent MP Peter Andren put it, 'a rock thrown through the front door of the Crown Casino [the venue of the 2000 World Economic Forum in Melbourne] could give rise to such a call-out'.60 As for the likelihood of injury, that could be created by a police attack on demonstrators. Another amendment, enshrined in s 51X, requires all members of Parliament to be sent a report of a military call-out within seven days of it ceasing, regardless of whether Parliament is sitting. It is difficult to imagine a more illusory form of parliamentary scrutiny. In effect, Parliament will only have the power to rubberstamp a military operation that has already taken place. Section 51XA provides for an 'independent review' with members to be appointed by the Defence Minister, or alternatively, a parliamentary committee, to examine the use of the legislation within six months of any military call-out or, if there is no callout, within three years of the commencement of the Act. These proposals also reduce parliamentary oversight to a postscript. CONSTITUTIONAL DOUBTS Doubts remain about the constitutional validity of the recent amendments to the Act, notwithstanding the fact that a number of authorities have taken a generous view of the Commonwealth's powers to call-out the military. I shall examine the possible constitutional bases for the legislation and critically review the positions taken by various authors. As noted above, in the discussion on the 1978 call-out, the relevant sections of the Constitution are ss 51(vi) (defence), 51(xxix) (external affairs), 51(xxxix) (incidental), 61 (executive), 68 (command of the military forces), and 119 (protection of states). Possibly combined with prerogative powers, some or all of these powers may give rise to an inherent power of self-protection or a 'nationhood' power. Section 119 Section 119 provides for the Commonwealth to protect a state, on the application of the state, 'against domestic violence'. Doubts may arise about the validity of the legislation, or its application, even if a state applies for protection, in anticipation of unrest. One immediate issue concerns the words 'or is likely to occur' in s 51A of the Act. On the face of it, these words go beyond s 119. Lee61 has supported Blackshield62 in asserting that a threat of domestic violence is sufficient to invoke s 119. In Blackshield's view, '[t]he key word is 'protect'; and obviously one can protect against threatened, as well as _____________________________________________________________________________________ 60 Commonwealth, Parliamentary Debates, House of Representatives, 7 September 2000, 18447 (Peter Andren, Independent MP). 61 Lee, above n 32, 204. 62 Blackshield, above n 22, 6. 2001 The Military Call-Out Legislation 287 ____________________________________________________________________________________ actual, aggressions'. This proposition is not self-evident. Lee makes the straightforward point that s 119 does not say, 'protect … against the threat of domestic violence'. Nonetheless, Lee ultimately accepts Blackshield's assertion on the basis that s 119 also covers protection from invasion and such protection cannot wait until an invasion has already occurred. If a threat of domestic violence were not treated in the same manner as a threatened invasion, Lee argues, that would lead to an 'internal inconsistency' in the construction of s 119. This argument is also flawed. Section 119 does not speak of protection against the threat of invasion either. If an invasion is threatened, there is likely to be palpable evidence in the form of military preparations. In that sense, the invasion will be underway already. This may not be so in the case of domestic violence. Moreover, a government might be more tempted to use the mere possibility of a disturbance to justify military repression. A more fundamental issue is whether the Federal Government can act to protect a state without a state application, that is, outside or in breach of the express precondition provided by s 119. According to the 1978 Australian Law Journal note referred to earlier, '[o]ne can read into s 119 the implication that the Commonwealth is at all times authorised to protect itself, as distinct from the States, against domestic violence'.63 Precisely how that implication arises was not explained. On the contrary, s 119 expressly states that a military call-out must be requested by a State. External affairs power — section 51(xxix) The external affairs powers may validate the legislation or its application where 'domestic violence' arises that threatens an aspect of foreign policy, diplomatic relations,64 a commitment under an international treaty or persons whom the Australian Government is obliged to protect.65 In the case of the 1978 call-out, the Hilton bomb blast affected a meeting of heads of government, who were defined as 'internationally protected persons' under the Prevention and Punishment of Crimes Against International Protected Persons Convention, which had been implemented by the Crimes (International Protected Persons) Act 1976 (Cth). This power would not apply, however, to a call-out where no such persons or foreign policy interests were involved. Defence power — section 51(vi) The defence power's scope in relation to internal security has not been specifically considered by the High Court. Instead, in the words of the Australian Law Journal note, commentators have engaged in the 'not very satisfactory process of elastically stretching certain of the dicta of Judges' in the Australian Communist Party v Commonwealth66 and Marcus Clark & Co Ltd v Commonwealth.67 According to s 51(vi), the Commonwealth Parliament may legislate with respect to: 'The naval and military defence of the Commonwealth and of the several States, and the control of the forces to execute and maintain the laws of the Commonwealth'. Most conjecture regarding internal security has focussed upon the second part of the section. The same Australian Law Journal note asserted that the words 'control of the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 63 (1978) 52 Australian Law Journal 296, 298. 64 R v Sharkey (1949) 79 CLR 121. 65 Commonwealth v Tasmania (1983) 158 CLR 1. 66 (1951) 83 CLR 1 ('Communist Party Case'). 67 (1952) 87 CLR 177. 288 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ forces to execute and maintain the laws of the Commonwealth' could extend 'to the preservation of general law and order so far as such order may be disturbed by general disobedience to the laws of the Commonwealth'.68 Such a proposition is so broad that it could apply to any 'general' breach of a federal law, say, for example, an election boycott. It is submitted that, given the clear federal-state demarcation drawn in the Constitution, the traditional distinction between military and police powers and the general principle of retaining the residual powers of the states, no such wide reading is warranted. In his book Emergency Powers, Lee also takes a wide view of the defence power, although he does not consider the issue at length.69 He notes that Justice Hope concluded that interference with a Commonwealth interest would generally involve a breach of a Commonwealth law, such as postal, crimes or electoral legislation, but also asserted that other valid Commonwealth interests might exist that are not protected by statute.70 Lee quotes Dixon J’s dictum from the 1949 sedition case, R v Sharkey,71 where Dixon J cited Quick and Garran’s annotated Constitution of the Australian Commonwealth as follows: The maintenance of order in a State is primarily the concern of the State, for which the police powers of the State are ordinarily adequate. But even if the State is unable to cope with domestic violence, the Federal Government has no right to intervene, for the protection of the State or its citizens, unless called upon by the State Executive. If, however, domestic violence within a State is of such a character as to interfere with the operations of the Federal Government, or with the rights and privileges of federal citizenship, the Federal Government may clearly, without a summons from the State, interfere to restore order. Thus if a riot in a State interfered with the carriage of the federal mails, or with interstate commerce, or with the right of an elector to record his vote at federal elections, the Federal Government could use all the force at its disposal, not to protect the State, but to protect itself. Were it otherwise, the Federal Government would be dependent on the Government of the State for the effective exercise of its powers.72 Several points must be made about this passage. Firstly, before quoting it, Dixon J made the following observation: Just as 'none of' the enumerated subjects with respect to which the Parliament may make laws 'relate to that general control over the liberty of the subject which must be shown to be transferred if it is to be regarded as vested in the Commonwealth' (Attorney-General for the Commonwealth v Colonial Sugar Refining Co. Ltd. (1914) AC, at p 255; 17 CLR 644, at p 654), so none of such subjects relate to public order, to the control of what is written, spoken or published, to the limits upon freedom of expression, to the maintenance of the King's peace or to social order. Section 119 of the Constitution provides that the Commonwealth shall protect every State against invasion and, on the application of the Executive Government of the State, against domestic violence. The reference to invasion explains the words 'and of the several States' in s 51 (vi), the defence power. But what is _____________________________________________________________________________________ 68 (1978) 52 Australian Law Journal 296, 298. 69 Lee, above n 32. 70 See Hope, Protective Security Review, above n 44, 151. 71 (1949) 79 CLR 121. 72 (1949) 79 CLR 121, 151. 2001 The Military Call-Out Legislation 289 ____________________________________________________________________________________ important is the fact that, except on the application of the Executive Government of the State, it is not within the province of the Commonwealth to protect the State against domestic violence. The comments made by Quick & Garran in Constitution of the Australian Commonwealth bring out clearly the distinction between matters affecting internal order and matters, which though in one aspect affecting internal order, concern the functions or operations of the Federal Government.73 Thus, Dixon J cited Quick and Garran to emphasise that the Commonwealth had no specific power to interfere with individual liberty, regulate public order, limit freedom of expression, uphold civil peace or maintain social stability — these being matters reserved for the States. The power of the Commonwealth would only extend to protecting the functions or operations of the national government. By seeking to authorise a military call-out to protect 'Commonwealth interests', without defining or limiting these interests, the recent amendments to the Act may well exceed this power by intruding into the very realms delineated by Dixon J. Incidental power — section 51(xxxix) After citing Quick and Garran, Dixon J also emphasised that the incidental power (the express form of which is found in s 51(xxxix) of the Constitution)74 could not be utilised to alter the federal-state demarcation. He stated: The power to legislate with respect to incidental matters has always been applied flexibly and liberally, as it must in a Constitution, but it cannot authorize legislation upon matters which are prima facie within the province of the States upon grounds of a connection with Federal affairs that is only tenuous, vague, fanciful or remote.75 I suggest that two inter-related conclusions follow. Firstly, a military call-out will only be valid in the event of interference with a clear, specific and identifiable Commonwealth function under the Constitution. Secondly, the incidental power cannot be used to intrude into the arena of domestic policing, which is clearly within the province of the States. Executive power — sections 61 and 68 Section 61 vests the executive power in the monarch, exercisable by the GovernorGeneral and s 68 specifically vests the command of the naval and military forces of the Commonwealth in the royal representative, the Governor-General. Lee asserts, somewhat tentatively, that '[a] reading of s 61 and s 68 would suggest some legal basis to justify the assertion that the power to invoke military aid unilaterally is also an attribute of the executive power'.76 Lee also argues that s 61 encompasses a judicially-recognised royal prerogative, referring to two Privy Council cases. In Chandler v Director of Public Prosecutions,77 Lord _____________________________________________________________________________________ 73 (1949) 79 CLR 121, 151 74 For the implied form of the power see Grannall v Marrickville Margarine Pty Ltd (1955) 93 CLR 55, 77. 75 (1949) 79 CLR 121, 151. See also Richard Lumb, The Constitution of the Commonwealth of Australia Annotated (1986) 210-2, where it is argued that the incidental power extends to the enactment of legislation that prohibits conduct directed against the Commonwealth, such as treason, treachery, sabotage, sedition and espionage. 76 Lee, above n 32, 206. 77 [1964] AC 763, 800. 290 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Hodson stated: 'The Crown has, and this is not disputed, the right as head of State to decide in peace and war the disposition of its armed forces'. In Burmah Oil Co Ltd v Lord Advocate,78 Lord Reid said: 'There is no doubt that control of the armed forces has been left to the prerogative … subject to the power of Parliament to withhold supply and refuse to continue legislation essential for the maintenance of a standing army'. It is remarkable that, some three centuries after the struggle for parliamentary and civilian supremacy over the British monarchy — and in a political system that professes to be democratic — the power of the government to call out the military is said to rest on vestiges of regal authority. Moreover, there is the problem, as Lee acknowledges, that these Privy Council cases relate to unitary systems of government. Under the Australian Constitution, the prerogative power must be 'divided' along federal-state lines. Lee argues that because s 114 of the Constitution forbids the States from raising or maintaining any naval or military force without the consent of the Commonwealth Parliament, 'the Crown' in the military context can only mean the federal executive power. But how is the prerogative divided when a State request is required under s 119? Furthermore, even if it is now accepted that the executive power extends beyond the express grant of legislative power set out in s 51 of the Constitution,79 in a critical passage in Victoria v Commonwealth & Hayden ('AAP Case'),80 Mason J pointed out that the scope of the executive power was not unlimited: In the words of s. 61, the executive power of the Commonwealth 'extends to the execution and maintenance of this Constitution, and of the laws of the Commonwealth'. Although the ambit of the power is not otherwise defined by Ch. II it is evident that in scope it is not unlimited and that its content does not reach beyond the area of responsibilities allocated to the Commonwealth by the Constitution, responsibilities which are ascertainable from the distribution of powers, more particularly the distribution of legislative powers, effected by the Constitution itself and the character and status of the Commonwealth as a national government. The provisions of s. 61 taken in conjunction with the federal character of the Constitution and the distribution of powers between the Commonwealth and the States make any other conclusion unacceptable. Moreover, it is a view of the executive power which is confirmed by the past decisions of this Court (see The Commonwealth v. Colonial Combing, Spinning and Weaving Co. Ltd. ('the Wooltops Case'); The Commonwealth v. Australian Commonwealth Shipping Board). 'Nationhood' In the AAP Case81 and New South Wales v Commonwealth,82 Barwick CJ sought to present the royal prerogative in modern clothing by referring to sovereignty that is 'inherent in the fact of nationhood and of international personality' and derives from 'the very formation of the Commonwealth as a polity and its emergence as an international State'. Mason J stated that the incidental power could add a 'further dimension' and that the Commonwealth enjoyed certain implied powers but cautioned that these implied _____________________________________________________________________________________ 78 [1965] AC 75, 100. 79 See, for example, Mason CJ, Deane and Gaudron JJ in Davis v The Commonwealth (1988) 166 CLR 79, 92-3. 80 (1975) 134 CLR 338 81 Ibid 361-2. 82 (1975) 8 ALR 1, 15-17. 2001 The Military Call-Out Legislation 291 ____________________________________________________________________________________ powers did not extend beyond 'internal security and protection of the State against disaffection and subversion': However, in ascertaining the potential scope of the power there are several important considerations which need to be kept steadily in mind. First, the incidental power contained in s. 51 (xxxix.) taken in conjunction with other powers, notably s. 61 itself, adds a further dimension to what may be achieved by the Commonwealth in the exercise of other specific powers. So in Burns v. Ransley and The King v. Sharkey, ss. 24A, 24B and 24D of the Crimes Act 1914-1946 (Cth) were held to be supported by the combination of ss. 51 (xxxix.) and 61. Secondly, the Commonwealth enjoys, apart from its specific and enumerated powers, certain implied powers which stem from its existence and its character as a polity (Australian Communist Party v. The Commonwealth). So far it has not been suggested that the implied powers extend beyond the area of internal security and protection of the State against disaffection and subversion. But in my opinion there is to be deduced from the existence and character of the Commonwealth as a national government and from the presence of ss. 51 (xxxix.) and 61 a capacity to engage in enterprises and activities peculiarly adapted to the government of a nation and which cannot otherwise be carried on for the benefit of the nation. In the context of arguably beneficial Commonwealth activity such as scientific research and public health, Mason J suggested a flexible approach to the functions considered to be constitutionally appropriate for a national government, but again cautioned against an interpretation that would radically transform federal-state relations: However, the executive power to engage in activities appropriate to a national government, arising as it does from an implication drawn from the Constitution and having no counterpart, apart from the incidental power, in the expressed heads of legislative power, is limited in scope. It would be inconsistent with the broad division of responsibilities between the Commonwealth and the States achieved by the distribution of legislative powers to concede to this aspect of the executive power a wide operation effecting a radical transformation in what has hitherto been thought to be the Commonwealth's area of responsibility under the Constitution, thereby enabling the Commonwealth to carry out within Australia programs standing outside the acknowledged heads of legislative power merely because these programs can be conveniently formulated and administered by the national government. These considerations weigh all the more heavily in the context of any infringement on democratic rights such as free speech, and the freedom to assemble and protest. Commenting on the Bowral call-out, Blackshield concluded that the Government invoked this 'nationhood' principle to rely upon a vague notion of national security. 'Since almost any social controversy can nowadays be injected with "national security" implications, it would seem that a way has been found of circumventing Section 119 and intervening in State affairs whenever the Commonwealth chooses'.83 The arbitrariness and potential breadth of such assertions of 'national security' presents real dangers to civil liberties and democratic rights. Using Mason J's dictum as a guide, a 1997-98 Parliamentary Library Research Paper84 reviewed the history of military call-outs in Australia, including the 1949 coalminers' strike; the 1953 Bowen waterfront stoppage; the 1971 Qantas strike; the 1978 Hilton bombing; the 1989 airline pilots' strike and the 1989 deployment of troops _____________________________________________________________________________________ 83 Blackshield, above n 22, 6. 84 Call Out the Troops, above n 33. 292 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ against anti-war protestors at the Nurrungar military base. With the possible exception of the 1953 Bowen confrontation, it concluded that the operations were valid as protecting essential Commonwealth interests, even if the constitutional grounds were not made clear at the time. Inherent power of self-protection Lane has suggested the conclusion that 'there is also an inherent self-protecting power in the Federal Government, as there is in any sovereign state', and therefore 'the Government could use the armed forces to maintain law and order and the running of the government'.85 This proposition would not even require an infringement of a federal law to justify a troop call-out.86 Dixon J’s comments in the Communist Party Case are regarded as providing the relevant principle: It is within the necessary power of the federal government to protect its own existence and the unhindered play of its legitimate activities. And to this end, it may provide for the punishment of treason, the suppression of insurrection or rebellion and for the putting down of all individual or concerted attempts to obstruct or interfere with the discharge of the proper business of government.87 Even applying this test, however, it is questionable whether an incident — say a protest or a bomb scare — at the Sydney Olympic Games would have in fact endangered or obstructed either the 'execution and maintenance of the Constitution' or 'the discharge of the proper business of government'.88 The Constitutional 'mesh' In Re Tracey; Ex parte Ryan,89 Brennan and Toohey JJ reaffirmed the principle that a law may be declared invalid if its scope or application potentially exceeds the Constitution: The submission was colourfully put on behalf of the Commonwealth that if the Parliament has power to cast the legislative net, the fact that the net catches more fish than the Parliament is entitled to take is irrelevant. The answer to this submission lies in the true scope of the principle on which it is founded. The principle is applicable when the Court is engaged in characterizing a law. Such an examination involves the operation of the law in the circumstances to which it applies. If the law is found to comprehend cases which have no connection with the subject-matter, that is a factor which affects the character attributed to the law. To adopt the fishing metaphor, the power to cast the legislative net depends on the mesh of the net.90 In the case of the military call-out legislation, it is submitted that the net has been cast too wide, with the mesh designed to catch cases that have no sufficient connection with the inherent functions of the Commonwealth. Both Dixon J in the Communist _____________________________________________________________________________________ 85 From P H Lane, An Introduction to the Australian Constitution (1974) 77. 86 Justice Hope in his Protective Security Review, above n 44, 27-30, also supported the notion of an inherent executive power of self-protection, as did Isaacs J in The King v Kidman (1915) 20 CLR 425, an opinion quoted with approval by Fullagar J in the Communist Party Case (1951) 83 CLR 1, 259. 87 (1951) 83 CLR 1, 188, citing Black's American Constitutional Law (2nd ed, 1910). See also Doogan, above n 1, 33. 88 See generally Hocking, above n 3. 89 (1989) 166 CLR 518. 90 Ibid 568. 2001 The Military Call-Out Legislation 293 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Party Case and Barwick CJ in the AAP Case, spoke in terms of self-protection or selfpreservation of the Commonwealth, not mere interference with its interests. As Johnston has observed, there is no definite judicial endorsement of the claim that the Commonwealth's power can extend beyond protecting itself against serious threats to its existence.91 LEGAL LIABILITY If the Act survives constitutional challenge, doubts will remain about aspects of the criminal and civil liability of military personnel in some circumstances, particularly if a state government or its police force have differences with the military call-out, leading to a lack of cooperation. Despite the wide powers that the Act grants to military personnel, it is not clear that the Act covers every instance in which an officer or soldier might otherwise be exposed to criminal liability or civil actions for assault, battery or false imprisonment. The Act itself does not specifically purport to provide a blanket legal protection, nor does it follow Justice Hope's recommendation that military personnel on call-out be granted the legal status of police officers. In so far as the Act purports to expand the military call-out power beyond the common law, the traditional canons of statutory interpretation provide that a court should presume that the Act is not intended to deprive members of the public of their civil liberties. Moreover, there is the issue of military commanders or individual soldiers whose actions breach the provisions of the Act. Many of the powers exercisable under the Act are subject to 'reasonable grounds' provisions. In addition, under s 51S members of the Defence Force exercising powers under the legislation must wear uniform and identification. Section 51W provides that: If, before, during or after exercising power under Division 2 or 3 or this Division, a member of the Defence Force fails to comply with any obligation imposed under any of those Divisions that relates to the exercise of the power, the member is not, or is taken not to have been, entitled to exercise the power. The dilemma identified by Brett and Waller may still therefore arise: The hardship upon soldiers is, that if a soldier kills a man in obedience to his officer's orders, the question whether what was done was more than was reasonably necessary to quell civil disturbance has to be decided by a jury, probably on a trial of murder. Whereas, if he disobeys his officer's orders to fire because he regards them as unlawful, the question where they were unlawful as having commanded something not reasonably necessary would have to be decided by a court-martial upon the trial of a soldier for disobeying orders, and for obvious reasons the jury and the court-martial are likely to take different views as to the reasonable necessity and therefore as to the lawfulness of such an order.92 Since Re Tracey, it has been reasonably clear that the defence power cannot be used to exempt military personnel from the general criminal and civil law for conduct for _____________________________________________________________________________________ 91 Peter Johnston, 'Re Tracey: Some Implications for the Military-Civil Authority Relationship' (1990) 20 Western Australia Law Review 73, 79. 92 Brett and Waller, above n 14, 654. 294 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ which they have already been tried for a 'service offence' under military law.93 Five members of the High Court in that case held invalid provisions of the Defence Force Discipline Act 1982 (Cth) that sought to do so, insisting that, after reviewing the history, a soldier remains a citizen and liable to the ordinary criminal law. In conclusion, the Act, as amended in 2000, provides even less certainty and protection for civil liberties than the previous obscure mixture of common law, delegated legislation and constitutional doctrine. However unsatisfactory the old legal morass, some underlying common law constraints on military power survived. The only thing made more certain by this legislation is that politicians of both major parties have combined to seek to expand military power. Whether that bid has been successful remains to be seen. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 93 See Re Tracey; Ex parte Ryan (1989) 166 CLR 518. COMMENT AND BOOK REVIEW THE HIGH COURT – LEGITIMACY AND CHANGE: REVIEW ESSAY: HAIG PATAPAN, JUDGING DEMOCRACY – THE NEW POLITICS OF THE HIGH COURT OF AUSTRALIA. Andrew Lynch* INTRODUCTION In the last ten years, the position of the High Court of Australia has undergone a remarkable transformation. The course of its decisions handed down from the early 1990s and the innovative, yet often perplexing, methodology upon which those decisions rested have garnered for the Court unprecedented attention and sparked a reconsideration of its place in the Australian polity. On many occasions this has taken the form of harsh criticism of the Court and its judges from representatives of the other arms of government and the media.1 In response to this barrage of criticism, and in light of the Commonwealth Attorney-General's sustained disinclination to fulfil his traditional role in representing and defending the judiciary,2 the High Court has increasingly been forced to justify its role and method – to a much more pronounced extent than at any earlier time in its history. The moves by the High Court to do this have taken a number of different forms. The letter written by Chief Justice Brennan to the Acting Prime Minister in 1997 at the _____________________________________________________________________________________ * Lecturer, Faculty of Law, University of Technology, Sydney. I wish to thank Mr Lawrence McNamara and Professor George Williams for their very helpful comments and suggestions on earlier drafts of this article. In respect of the comments made concerning Chief Justice Gleeson's support for 'strict and complete legalism' I also wish to acknowledge the role of discussions held with the Jurisprudence students at UTS in Spring semester, 2000 in stimulating some of the ideas contained herein. I alone am responsible for any flaws in this article. 1 Examples of such criticism are summarised in Michael Kirby, Through the World's Eye, (2000) 157-160. 2 Most recently given voice in Daryl Williams, 'Judges must conduct their own defence' The Australian Financial Review (Sydney), 27 April 2001, 57. 296 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ height of the public onslaught against the Court is but one notable example.3 Members of the Court have spoken out in numerous fora, seeking to explain the true nature of their role and illuminate the judicial method.4 In the efforts to defend itself, the High Court has made it clear that it is not suggesting that it is to be free of all criticism – rather it asks for less political vitriol and for more 'informed criticism'.5 It is in response to this invitation that Haig Patapan has produced Judging Democracy: The New Politics of the High Court of Australia.6 Judging Democracy is a remarkable book for several reasons. It is an intelligent evaluation of the High Court's signature work across the 1990s that never loses sight of the broader institutional framework in which the Court resides. As such, it represents a critique far removed from the outcome-obsessed sound-bites of politicians heard at the times when some of the Court's major decisions were handed down. Consequently, it is a more balanced and effective, and occasionally much more damning, assessment of the High Court across this period. Not the least of his many achievements in this book, is Patapan’s presentation of 'informed criticism' in accessible and elegant prose. The book may therefore receive a wider audience than the delegates at a legal conference or the readers of law journals. Those seeking clarification of the case law establishing implied rights (chapter 3) and native title (chapter 5) – probably the two most contentious areas explored by the Court in the last decade – will be treated to a lucid and rigorous exposition of the relevant judgments which seeks to examine their theoretical bases. Of course, this exercise is an eminently valuable one in itself and one which, on the whole, Patapan achieves with considerable adroitness. But it is the book's more ambitious aim as indicated by its subtitle that will secure it a lasting and significant place in the literature devoted to understanding the High Court of Australia. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 3 See Kirby, above n 1, 159-60. 4 Sir Gerard Brennan, 'The State of the Judicature' (Paper presented at the 30th Australian Legal Convention, Melbourne, 19 September 1997)(copy on file with author); Michael Kirby, 'Attacks on Judges: A Universal Phenomenon' (Paper presented at the American Bar Association, Maui, Hawaii, 5 January 1998)(copy on file with author); Michael Kirby, 'Judicial Activism' (1997) 27 Western Australian Law Review 1; Murray Gleeson, 'Legal Oil and Political Vinegar' (Paper presented at the Sydney Institute, Sydney, 16 March 1999) (copy on file with author); Murray Gleeson, 'Judicial Legitimacy' (Paper presented at the Australian Bar Association Conference, New York, 2 July, 2000) (copy on file with author); Murray Gleeson, Boyer Lectures 2000 – The Rule of Law and the Constitution (2000); Murray Gleeson, 'Occasional Address' (Paper presented at Griffith University, Brisbane, 20 April 2001) (copy on file with author); Michael McHugh, 'The Judicial Method', (1999) 73 Australian Law Journal 37; Kenneth Hayne, 'Letting Justice be Done Without the Heavens Falling' (Paper presented as the Fourth Fiat Justitia Lecture, Monash University, Melbourne, 21 March 2001) (copy on file with author); John Toohey, ''Without Fear or Favour, Affection or Ill-Will': The Role of Courts in the Community' (1999) 28 Western Australian Law Review 1. Perhaps the most memorable and publicly accessible attempt by the Court to present itself and its work for scrutiny was the participation of Chief Justice Brennan and Justices Toohey, Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne in a television documentary: The Highest Court, ABC, nationally broadcast 9.30pm, 26 May 1998. 5 Michael Kirby, 'Shocking level of civics ignorance', The Sydney Morning Herald (Sydney), 16 August 1997, 5. 6 Haig Patapan, Judging Democracy: The New Politics of the High Court of Australia (2000) xi. 2001 The High Court – Legitimacy and Change 297 ____________________________________________________________________________________ In his introductory chapter, Patapan considers the wider ramifications of the Court's recent forays into the areas of rights, citizenship, indigenous culture and government when he states: [I]f the High Court is now willing to, in effect 'judge democracy', we are compelled to ask whether its constitutional interpretations and common law decisions evince a coherent and comprehensive democratic vision of the Australian polity. Or are its decisions ad hoc, determined by the litigation before it, subject to the contingencies and exigencies of the Court as an institution influenced and limited by the discretion of individual judges, and constrained by the very process of adversarial adjudication?7 It is a fascinating question and one that provides the ensuing exploration of particular topics with a thematic drive sustained across the span of the book. Thus, the book operates in these two senses – discrete coverage of particular aspects of the High Court's recent work and also as an analysis of the Court's guiding jurisprudence across the Mason and Brennan eras. As a concerted whole, Judging Democracy invites reflection upon the role of the High Court and the parameters of judicial legitimacy – topics which have not lost their importance since the arrival of Murray Gleeson as Chief Justice in 1998. That the controversy surrounding the outcome of some of the High Court's high-profile decisions in the last decade prompted fresh discourse about the Court's operations and place in the Australian political landscape is not so surprising. Now that conversation has begun to move on from the noisy clamour which reached its zenith in 1997, the time is ripe for a sophisticated yet accessible appraisal of the recent methodology of the High Court and suggestions as to where this is likely to take the Court as it enters its second century. METHODS OF INTERPRETATION Patapan begins his evaluation of the High Court with an examination of the principles of interpretation which it has employed across its history (chapter 2). This is a logical starting point as the question of interpretation goes to the essence of how the Court perceives its role and also the nature of the Australian polity.8 It also enables Patapan to preface some of the underlying issues which are to surface in the more specific chapters that follow. Finally, his observations on the diversity of interpretative method are an important early salvo on the core issue of the nature of the Court's democratic vision. The Engineers Case, Legalism and Implications Inevitably, the discussion begins with the impact of the Engineers Case.9 The Court's decision in that case to turn away from a practice of reading of the Constitution in light of the social and political circumstances of its origin is portrayed by Patapan as a return to the self-understanding of the declaratory theory that had dominated the operation of the common law and enabled a degree of discretion without seeming to contradict the sanctity of the rule of law.10 The assertion of the Engineers Case that the ‘political’ and ‘legal’ were distinct and that the High Court's role as adjudicator was to _____________________________________________________________________________________ 7 Ibid 6. 8 Ibid 10. 9 Amalgamated Society of Engineers v Adelaide Steamship Co Ltd (1920) 28 CLR 129. 10 Patapan, above n 6, 13-14. 298 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ be confined to the domain of the latter certainly secured the Court's legitimacy over the following decades. There are two matters to note in respect of this. First, the decision in Engineers is itself a vital expression of the Court's politics. The point has been made elsewhere that the reasoning in Engineers relies, at least in part, upon an appreciation of the doctrine of responsible government and the common sovereignty of the British Empire.11 As Patapan makes clear, the decision conveyed the Court's respect for parliamentary sovereignty as a guiding principle of the Australian regime – thus justifying a selfimposed restriction to matters characterised as legal.12 This point is most starkly illustrated by the discussion of notions of citizenship in chapter 4. It is here that Patapan demonstrates the resilience of parliamentary sovereignty through his consideration of the decisions of McKinlay13 and McGinty v Western Australia14 wherein the majority of the Court is unwilling to read s.24 of the Commonwealth Constitution in such a way that would impose its own understanding of the requirements of representative democracy upon the Parliament. Instead, the adoption of a 'neutral and natural reading of the text assumes a political and theoretical conception of parliamentary and progressive democracy'.15 Second, while the method set forth in Engineers did indeed direct attention upon the legal in place of the political in order to secure the Court's legitimacy within the Australian system of governance, it is disappointing to see Patapan slip into a simplistic treatment of the interpretative legacy of Engineers. In particular, inadequate attention is given to the operation of implications within the legalistic method. This is illustrated particularly well by the following passage: A 'natural' reading of the text distinguished and characterised the legal method and was the essence of legal reasoning. Therefore a literal reading of the text justified judicial authority in Australia. In contrast, the resort to 'implications' betrayed an attempt to augment a clear legal reading with personal preference or opinion – it marked a movement from the legal to the unbounded political.16 This is a regrettable statement for several reasons. First, it glosses over the fact that the objection to the original High Court's use of the reserved state powers doctrine17 and the immunity of instrumentalities doctrine18 was not simply that they were implied, but that they were implications drawn from political necessity. This distinction actually supports with greater clarity the point that Patapan is making about the change in interpretation represented by the Engineers decision. The use of implications arising from the text or structure of the Constitution itself was expressly left open in Engineers19 and confirmed subsequently20 - a point which Patapan assumes without comment in his subsequent handling of implied rights.21 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 11 George Williams, Human Rights under the Australian Constitution (1999) 76; RTE Latham, 'The Law and the Commonwealth' quoted in Tony Blackshield and George Williams, Australian Constitutional Law & Theory – Commentary & Materials (2nd ed, 1998) 243. 12 Patapan, above n 6, 17. 13 Attorney-General (Cth); Ex rel McKinlay v Commonwealth (1975) 135 CLR 1. 14 McGinty v Western Australia (1996) 186 CLR 140. 15 Patapan, above n 6, 96. 16 Ibid 16. 17 R v Barger (1908) 6 CLR 1. 18 D'Emden v Pedder (1904) 1 CLR 91. 19 Above n 9, 155, (Knox CJ, Isaacs, Rich and Starke JJ). 2001 The High Court – Legitimacy and Change 299 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Second, and more crucially to Patapan's overall purpose, the question of implications and their acceptability within legal method is important, given that much of the recent criticism of the High Court stemmed from a failure to appreciate this particular aspect of its work. A clear picture of the role of implications must be drawn if the reader is to appreciate the purported limitations, yet practical flexibility, of the legalist method - and thus to grasp the points which Patapan is seeking to make about a shift in interpretation. The ability of the High Court to justify implications within a method of interpretation that prides itself on exclusion of non-textual concerns owes much to the old declaratory theory of the common law22 and was nicely typified by the claim of Windeyer J that the High Court's 'avowed task is simply the revealing or uncovering of implications that are already there'.23 While not wishing to dispute the emphasis which Patapan gives to the importance of the admissions of the High Court's law-making role which surfaced around the time of Sir Anthony Mason's elevation to Chief Justice, the abandonment of what has significantly been called the 'public rhetoric of technical legalism'24 arguably occurred quite some time after that method had already betrayed itself.25 Patapan acknowledges the sustained expansion of Commonwealth power that followed Engineers,26 though he seemingly does not share Galligan's view that legalism was a device deliberately intended by the Court, especially Isaacs and Higgins JJ, to mask a policy in pursuit of this objective.27 That may be understandable, but it is a shame that, in seeking to explain the ascendancy of legalism throughout much of the Court's history, more is not made by Patapan of those federal implications drawn after Engineers. In particular, the absence of any discussion concerning Dixon CJ's subtle reworking of the federal relationship through the use of implications is surprising.28 The statement by Patapan _____________________________________________________________________________________ 20 West v Commissioner for Taxation (NSW) (1937) 56 CLR 657. In Nationwide News Pty Ltd v Wills (1992) 177 CLR 1, 69, Deane and Toohey JJ stated that 'it has long been recognized that the 'notion' or 'dogma' which gained currency for a period after the decision in the Engineers' Case to the effect that the rejection of the doctrine of "immunity of instrumentalities" meant that no implications can be made in construing the Constitution was mistaken'. 21 Patapan, above n 6, 29 and Chapter 3 generally. 22 The significance of the declaratory mind-set of the common lawyer and its pervasive influence over the High Court for much of its life is noted by Patapan in numerous places: ibid 15; 27; 123-4; 140-1; 182-3. 23 Victoria v The Commonwealth (Payroll Tax Case) (1971) 122 CLR 353, 402. An example where Patapan does expose the claims of legalism very effectively is in his handling of Barwick CJ's judgment in Attorney-General (Cth); Ex rel McKinlay v Commonwealth (1975) which takes place in Chapter 4: see Patapan, above n 6, 77-80. 24 Brian Galligan, 'The Australian High Court's Role in Institutional Maintenance and Development' in Charles Sampford and Kim Preston (eds), Interpreting Constitutions – Theories, Principles and Institutions (1996) 200. 25 As Doyle CJ has said, 'It is not that previously the High Court did not make law but now it does. It is simply that during his [Mason's] time as Chief Justice that role was more openly avowed and, I believe, more frequently exercised.': John Doyle, 'Implications in Judicial Law-Making' in Cheryl Saunders (ed), Courts of Final Jurisdiction – The Mason Court in Australia (1996) 84. 26 Patapan, above n 6, 16-17. 27 See Galligan, above n 24, 200-201 and Patapan, above n 6, 15 (text accompanying n 24). 28 Specifically, Dixon J's role in the establishment of the Melbourne Corporation principle and the Cigamatic doctrine. The latter poses such an interesting challenge to the orthodoxy 300 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ that the making of implications was perceived as a movement from the legal field to improper involvement by the Court in the making of political and personal judgments would seem to invite at least fleeting consideration of how the Melbourne Corporation29 principle was justified within such a methodology.30 In his recent analysis of this topic, Jeremy Kirk has stressed that in order to understand the use and legitimacy of constitutional implications there are dangers in restricting the scope of one's inquiry: [T]he process of ascertaining implications is a fundamental and frequent part of constitutional interpretation. One legacy of the Engineers Case has been a marked judicial reluctance to admit that this is the case. The clearest acceptance of the role of implications came only where it was hard to deny, with the federal immunities. Even then, some judges sought to sidestep the issue, as others did for the implied nationhood power…Legitimacy issues do arise whenever judicial choice is involved, and judicial choice is almost invariably inherent in recognising implications. A concern about these matters is reflected in the traditional restrictive 'necessary implication' test, although such a separate test for implications cannot ultimately be justified. Instead, the question of whether or not to recognise an implication depends on the general approach adopted to constitutional interpretation, combined with such other guides as a theory of stare decisis…An awareness of the different types of implication may also offer some insight and assistance.31 Of course, any actual shift in interpretative method has nothing to do with the use of implications per se and Patapan does not say as such. But his examination of the approach of the Court in recent times is slightly diminished by insufficient clarity about the legitimacy of implications made in the past. To take the example of the implied freedom of political communication, Mason CJ in his judgment in Australian Capital Television v Commonwealth32 was at particular pains to refute the suggestion that the Engineers methodology was irreconcilable with the finding of an implied freedom of political communication, though not to the satisfaction of some of his colleagues.33 The fact that the Court ultimately grounded the implied freedom squarely upon particular provisions of the Constitution in Lange v Australian Broadcasting Corporation34 has been described as a conservative continuation of the 'commitment to textualism' _____________________________________________________________________________________ established by the Engineers Case it has been referred to as 'Dixon's heresy': see RP Meagher and WMC Gummow, 'Sir Owen Dixon's Heresy' (1980) 54 Australian Law Journal 25, 29. 29 Melbourne Corporation v Commonwealth (1947) 74 CLR 31. 30 For example, consider the brief but necessary comments of George Williams in respect of federal implications as a preface to his consideration of implied freedoms. George Williams, 'Judicial Activism and Judicial Review in the High Court of Australia' in Tom Campbell and Jeffrey Goldsworthy, Judicial Power, Democracy and Legal Positivism (2000) 418. In contrast, Patapan's only mention of this case occurs in n 29 of Chapter 2 as reviving the principle of intergovernmental immunities – which actually invites much more speculation from the novice reader than no reference at all! 31 Jeremy Kirk, 'Constitutional Implications (I): Nature, Legitimacy, Classification, Examples' (2000) 24 Melbourne University Law Review 645, 675-6. 32 (1992) 177 CLR 106, 133-5. 33 In particular McHugh J whose dissent in Theophanous v Herald & Weekly Times Ltd (1994) 182 CLR 104, 197-8, 202 indicates that he remained unconvinced that the freedom as conceptualised by some members of the Court at that time was consistent with the Engineers methodology. 34 (1997) 189 CLR 520. 2001 The High Court – Legitimacy and Change 301 ____________________________________________________________________________________ endorsed in Engineers.35 Indeed, it is clear that this was precisely what the Court was aiming for in order to secure the legitimacy of its recognition of the freedom.36 However, the method in respect of implications derived from the separation of judicial power was clearly not so strictly rooted in the 'text and structure' as that in respect of the implied freedom. Certainly some of the minority judgments in this area indicate what Patapan calls the 'potential for unbounded judicial discretion'37 in their interpretation of the Constitution. This difference is pertinent to both concerns about the legitimacy of those implications and also the view of the political regime which they reflect. Patapan's analysis in respect of these two matters is, as discussed below, particularly astute. However, the absence of any real critique of the varying acceptability of implications leaves something lacking in this chapter on the politics of interpretation. Law-making, values and popular sovereignty The complaint about implications aside, Patapan's evaluation of the Court's attempts to settle upon an interpretative direction after the quite candid claims of judicial lawmaking is illuminating. The international and institutional changes that preface this era are succinctly canvassed and the influence of the sociological jurisprudence of Roscoe Pound and Julius Stone upon those sitting on the High Court by the late 1980s is appropriately documented. In supplanting a merely legalistic method, the 'dynamic and progressive' interpretation that emerges in the Mason Court represents a disenchantment with the notion of parliamentary sovereignty as a cornerstone of the Australian political regime. It is not so surprising, as we shall see in the next section of this article, that the result was to produce a rights-based jurisprudence where none of significance existed before. But upon what did the new High Court method rely for its legitimacy? The point is made by Patapan in numerous places that in its admission of lawmaking, the High Court has sacrificed the security that legalism previously provided.38 In the need for legitimacy the Court has increasingly resorted to 'community values' as a basis for its supervision of the common law and its guardianship of the Constitution. In doing so, it has been able to distance itself from the fallacy of legalism, though without having 'expressly undermined the Engineers Case'.39 The tone of the Mason era was set by his rejection of legalism as a 'cloak for undisclosed and unidentified policy _____________________________________________________________________________________ 35 Adrienne Stone, 'The Limits of Constitutional Text and Structure: Standards of Review and the Freedom of Political Communication' (1999) 23 Melbourne University Law Review 668, 706. In this article, Stone argues forcefully that the insistence by the Court in limiting its understanding of that implied freedom by reference solely to the 'text and structure' of the Constitution presents real problems for its future application. Jeremy Kirk has also observed that the 'text cannot provide the requisite content of the constitutional requirement, nor determine the relevant boundaries': Jeremy Kirk, 'Constitutional Implications (II): Doctrines of Equality and Democracy' (2001) 25 Melbourne University Law Review 24, 52. 36 See Patapan, above n 6, 29; Stone, above n 35, 675; Williams, above n 11, 190; Andrew Lynch, 'Unanimity in a Time of Uncertainty: The High Court Settles its Differences in Lange v Australian Broadcasting Corporation' (1997) 6 Griffith Law Review 211. 37 Patapan, above n 6, 29. 38 Ibid 24, 150, 161, and 171 amongst others. 39 Williams, above n 11, 76. 302 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ values' and call for 'policy-oriented interpretation'40 or 'legal realism'.41 Necessarily, a focus upon 'community values' entails less significance being accorded to the intentions of the framers of the Constitution. The tension between attempting to accommodate community values and the intentions of the drafters has been the cause of much academic discussion.42 The fact that the Australian debate about originalism was only really ignited after the High Court admitted its law-making function and not before, demonstrates the firm grip of the legalist mythology. Some of the more popularly aired question marks over the legitimacy of the High Court's progressive interpretation based upon community values have stemmed from the persistent views put forward from the originalist camp. While there are very real concerns about the High Court ‘divining’ the values of the community,43 it would seem mistaken to suggest that looking to the founder's intentions necessarily provides much direction or restraint44 or even that there is much of worth to be found in the convention debates in respect of particular questions.45 Possibly signalling an end to this debate (or at least taking it into a new phase), Graeme Hill has recently suggested that the divide between originalist and progressive interpretations is not often determinative of the outcome of cases in the High Court.46 Patapan's assessment of the 'community values' basis for the High Court's approach to the Constitution and the common law is the most interesting aspect of this chapter. The pertinence of such a discussion is reinforced by recent remarks of Gleeson CJ that _____________________________________________________________________________________ 40 Sir Anthony Mason, 'The Role of a Constitutional Court in a Federation: A Comparison of the Australian and United States Experience' (1986) 16 Federal Law Review 1, 5. 41 Sir Anthony Mason, 'The Role of the Courts at the Turn of the Century' (1993) 3 Journal of Judicial Administration 156, 164. 42 See Greg Craven, 'Original Intent and the Australian Constitution: Coming to a Court Near You' (1990) 1 Public Law Review 166; Michael Stokes, 'Constitutional Commitments not Original Intentions: Interpretation in the Freedom of Speech Cases' (1994) 16 Sydney Law Review 250; Jeffrey Goldsworthy, 'Originalism in Constitutional Interpretation' (1997) 25 Federal Law Review 1; Michael Kirby, 'Constitutional Interpretation and Original Intent: A Form of Ancestor Worship' (2000) 24 Melbourne University Law Review 1; Jeffrey Goldsworthy, 'Interpreting the Constitution in its Second Century' (2000) 24 Melbourne University Law Review 677. 43 See discussion below accompanying nn 47-52. 44 Patapan, above n 6, 27-8; Haig Patapan, 'The Dead Hand of the Founders? Original Intent and the Constitutional Protection of Rights and Freedoms in Australia' (1997) 25 Federal Law Review 232-234; Kirk above n 35, 26-31. While Patapan contends that originalism will tend to restrain judicial activism, he does also suggest that 'by adopting a different perspective on the founders' understanding of progress and liberalism, it may be possible for originalism in Australia to accommodate a more activist judiciary': (1997) 233. 45 Williams, n 11, 25-45; 79-84 for a concise view of the unhelpfulness of the convention debates in respect of constitutionalising human rights. Williams writes, '[i]t is a mistake to overestimate the level or quality of debate at the Conventions, just as it is a mistake to believe that the records of the debates present the whole picture. Debate on fundamental constitutional concepts was unsophisticated and showed a lack of understanding by many speakers.' Williams, n 11, 34. 46 Graeme Hill, '"Originalist" vs "Progressive" Interpretations of the Constitution – Does it Matter?' (2000) 11 Public Law Review 159. This is supported by Patapan's statement that 'far from being the "dead hand" of the past, originalism in fact allows the greatest scope for political experimentation and innovation' : Patapan, above n 44 (1997) 233. 2001 The High Court – Legitimacy and Change 303 ____________________________________________________________________________________ continue to emphasise the role of values in the Court's work47 - which shall be considered more fully towards the end of this essay. But while values continue to receive recognition for their role in judicial reasoning, Patapan's assessment is that they provide little restraint: [T]he Court's recent decisions suggest that the notion of community values may not in fact provide the anticipated check on individual judicial discretion. Minority judgments regarding the common law, implied rights, separation of powers and sovereignty of the people reveal the extent to which these concepts are sufficiently supple and complex to harbour divergent and in some cases irreconcilable positions.48 This is a valuable, though unsurprising, observation. Although John Braithwaite has employed empirical research so as to attempt an identification of the values of the Australian community,49 the uncertain guidance provided by use of values has been the subject of much discussion.50 But even though the core criticism remains, as John Daley says, that '[t]here is little escape from the problem – be it epistemic or ontological – that it is difficult to provide sure answers to many controversial value choices',51 it is just as inescapable that such value choices must occasionally be made in order to address some issues which are incapable of being resolved through the application of legal logic.52 The significance of community values as an interpretative tool has been heightened by the shift towards recognition of popular sovereignty underlying Australian constitutionalism. The passage of the Australia Acts on the eve of the Mason era was doubtless a contributing factor in the ability of this idea to take hold after earlier statements had met with a sceptical reception.53 Popular sovereignty was advocated particularly strongly by Deane J,54 though he was by no means alone in his support of the principle.55 Most recently, Gleeson CJ has expressly rejected the operation of British parliamentary supremacy, saying that the ability of the Australian people to alter the Constitution means that 'the sovereignty of our nation lies with the people, both as a matter of legal principle and as a matter of practical reality'.56 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 47 Gleeson, The Boyer Lectures, above n 4, 98, 134. 48 Patapan, above n 6, 32. 49 John Braithwaite, 'Community Values and Australian Jurisprudence' (1995) 17 Sydney Law Review 351, 355-60. 50 In addition to Patapan, see Jeremy Kirk, 'Constitutional Implications from Representative Democracy' (1995) 23 Federal Law Review 37, 71-3; Klaus A Ziegert, 'Judicial DecisionMaking, Community and Consented Values: Some Remarks on Braithwaite's Republican Model' (1995) 17 Sydney Law Review 373; Martin Krygier and Arthur Glass, 'Shaky Premises: Values, Attitudes and the Law' (1995) 17 Sydney Law Review 385. 51 John Daley, 'Defining Judicial Restraint' in Campbell and Goldsworthy (eds), above n 30, 300. 52 Ibid. 53 In particular, see Kirmani v Captain Cook Cruises Pty Ltd (No 1) (1985) 159 CLR 351, 383, (Murphy J); though Deane J also discussed this, ibid 410. 54 For example, see Stevens v Head (1992) 176 CLR 433, 461; Theophanous v Herald & Weekly Times Ltd (1994) 182 CLR 104, 180. 55 Leeth v Commonwealth (1992) 174 CLR 455, 484 (Deane and Toohey JJ); Australian Capital Television v Commonwealth (1992) 177 CLR 106, 138, (Mason CJ); and McGinty v Western Australia (1996) 186 CLR 140, 230, (McHugh J). 56 Gleeson, The Boyer Lectures, above n 4, 6. 304 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Patapan is quick to highlight the implications of this shift and the consequences of any adoption of the social contract theory to the Australian constitutional story. It certainly bolsters the Court in the role of protector of the people after several decades of being the distant umpire in federal scuffles.57 But, more importantly, this invites reflection upon the theoretical basis of the entire polity and the Court's aptitude to both devise, and function within, a new conception of it: [T]he view of the Constitution as a type of social contract draws upon different political and theoretical traditions with major consequences for the character of the regime. It may well be that as an expression of Lockean liberal constitutionalism the Constitution secures natural rights, limited government and representative government. However, sovereignty of the people also opens up a world of fundamentally different aspects of sovereignty, from Hobbes' sovereign to Rousseau's general will, and different political visions, from communitarianism to republicianism. In these outer reaches the judicial task of interpreting and applying the law, of choosing the character of the political regime, becomes a delicate task more suited for the skills, abilities and discretion of a political philosopher and statesman.58 Chief Justice Gleeson's recent Boyer Lectures were suffused with the idea that individuals are protected by the rule of law as upheld in the courts - in this sense, he agrees with the view of both Patapan and Justice Kirby that the High Court can operate to shield individuals from the excesses of institutional power.59 However, he made no direct comment about how an appreciation of popular sovereignty may affect constitutional interpretation and the nature of the Australian political arrangement. Indeed, it can only be presumed that far from throwing open the sort of questions raised by Patapan, the Chief Justice considered that the derivation of constitutional authority from a base of popular sovereignty only goes further to justifying his trenchant faith in 'strict and complete legalism'.60 Recognition of the sovereign place of the people does not generate competing visions of governance but rather demands careful adherence to the terms of what was agreed: [u]ltimately, however, all Australians are controlled, not only by what the founders said in their written document, but also, and perhaps even more comprehensively, by what they did not say. In a sense, a good deal of argument about the scope for interpretation is relatively marginal. Silence, whether deliberate or not, binds us conclusively.61 History and Its Uses The topic of popular sovereignty brings us to one final point in discussing the new High Court's interpretative method. It is quite clear that a simplistic portrayal of the federation process as an exercise in popular sovereignty involves a degree of historical revisionism. This has been meticulously noted by Helen Irving, who surmises that 'the historical error (if that is what it is) committed by the High Court, is not to identify a 'popular' or national purpose in the Constitution, but to see this as the principal or overriding historical imperative'.62 Additionally, members of the Court have also _____________________________________________________________________________________ 57 Patapan, above n 6, 31 and Kirby, above n 1, 149-154. 58 Patapan, above n 6, 31. 59 Gleeson, The Boyer Lectures, above n 4, 3, 74-5. See also, Kirby, above n 1. 60 Ibid 85. 61 Ibid 55-6. 62 Helen Irving, 'The Australian Constitution and the Federal Compact', forthcoming paper delivered at Faculty of Law research seminar, University of Technology, Sydney, 2000, 12 (copy on file with author). 2001 The High Court – Legitimacy and Change 305 ____________________________________________________________________________________ expressed concern at its ability to pinpoint the evolution of the Australian polity with any reliable historical accuracy.63 In fact, the fidelity of the High Court to matters of historical record – including its own past – receives detailed attention by Patapan in his discussion of the Wik Peoples v Queensland64 decision in chapter 5. The topic of native title involves history at several levels. First, and most obviously, the ability to demonstrate connection to and use of land is crucial to success in establishing the existence of native title in respect of that land.65 Second, and more controversially, the majority decision in Wik demonstrates a perverse view of legislative history. The suggestion that the Queensland Parliament in enacting legislation granting pastoral leases in 1910 and 1962 did so without intending to extinguish native title is highly problematic as a matter of legal history, as the minority was keen to point out.66 Patapan likens the majority's ability to revise historical fact to the declaratory theory of the common law67 – a view affirmed by Gummow J's admission that the difficulties in establishing the 'independent truth' of the past are best sacrificed to the declaratory theory's ability to adjust principle in order to provide justice on the facts of an individual case.68 Although the operation of the declaratory tradition is not exclusive to the majority, having been so obviously employed in Mabo itself by Brennan and McHugh JJ (who are joined by Dawson J in the minority in Wik), the importance of certainty of principle and historical accuracy are clearly accorded different weight by members of the court in Wik. Leslie Zines has commented that 'the reasoning of all the judges in Wik was quite orthodox'69 and Patapan would seem to agree with this conclusion when he says 'the difference between the majority and minority in Wik turns not on formal rules of statutory interpretation, but on the more philosophical question of the way the past is to be interpreted – the way the Court deals with 'history''.70 The ability of the judges in Wik to operate within the legalist tradition yet divide on the extent to which they were prepared to sacrifice an understanding of the past to 'their perceived duty to be just',71 should be salutary to those persons looking to history, perhaps in preference to community values, to act as some kind of constraint upon the judicial method. The third instance of the Court's historical approach arising from the native title cases concerns the value it places on its own history. This is a significant theme _____________________________________________________________________________________ 63 See McGinty v Western Australia (1996) 186 CLR 140, 230 (McHugh J), and more forcefully, Sue v Hill (1999) 199 CLR 462, 571-2 (Callinan J). 64 Wik Peoples v Queensland (1996) 187 CLR 1. 65 Patapan, above n 6, 119. 66 Above n 64, 70-84 (Brennan CJ). 67 Patapan, above n 6, 140. 68 Above n 64, 179-84 (Gummow J). 69 Leslie Zines, 'Judicial Activism and the Rule of Law in Australia' in Campbell and Goldsworthy (eds), above n 30, 408. 70 Patapan, above n 6, 140. The division that can be caused over the act of balancing historical certainty with the declaratory theory is identified by Alder as an example of the type of incommensurable disagreement which leads to dissents in final courts. His discussion of the House of Lords' split over this faultline in Kleinwort Benson v Lincoln City Council [1998] 4 All ER 513 indicates that this problem is not peculiar to the High Court of Australia. See John Alder, 'Dissents in Courts of Last Resort: Tragic Choices?' (2000) 20 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 221, 230-1. 71 Patapan, above n 6, 141. 306 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ running throughout Judging Democracy, and Patapan demonstrates it particularly well in his examination of the Wik majority's rejection of the tenor of the Mabo decision in respect of pastoral leases. The casualness with which Brennan J's reversion principle (whereby the interest in land subject to a lease reverted wholly to the Crown upon its expiry, thus extinguishing native title) from the earlier case is discarded by the Wik majority is a strong reminder that the High Court's own history, and the views of its individual members, are very much subject to the demands of those judging in the immediate present. Of course, with the removal of ties to the Privy Council, this is more true now than it has been for much of the Court's existence, but it has long been recognised in the context of the Court's control over the development of constitutional law.72 But it is rare to see this perpetual uncertainty so vividly conveyed as when Patapan writes: Thus the Court's decisions are protean and slippery, each in a sense consuming and rewriting all that went before.73 RIGHTS AND JUSTICE – DEFINING THEIR BOUNDARIES Patapan's analysis of the native title cases clearly demonstrates how disagreement amongst the High Court is the product of the varying lengths to which its members perceive they are entitled to go in order to provide justice. For example, Dawson J's earlier dissent in Mabo should not be seen as a denial of the plight of indigenous Australians and their dispossession of land at the hands of European settlers — rather it is a rejection of the common law's culpability for this state of affairs and an insistence that it is not within the proper bounds of judicial power for the High Court to amend it.74 The dissent of Brennan CJ in Wik rests, not on such a stark demarcation of the 'legal' and the 'political', but rather on the extent to which he is willing to reassess past events and to allow recognition of native title to alter accepted tenets of the common law of property. The majority in Wik is prepared to pay this price in order to deliver a result which it believes is just. The difficulties which flow from a judge playing (her or his perception of) justice as a trump card are readily discernible.75 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 72 Australian Agricultural Co v Federated Engine-Drivers & Firemen's Association (1913) 17 CLR 261, 278 (Isaacs J). See also JW Harris, 'Overruling Constitutional Interpretations' in Sampford and Preston (eds), above n 24, 231-247; Bryan Horrigan, 'Towards a Jurisprudence of High Court Overruling' (1992) 66 Australian Law Journal 199; Patrick Keyzer, 'When is an issue of 'vital constitutional importance'? Principles which guide the reconsideration of constitutional decisions in the High Court of Australia' (1999) 2 Constitutional Law and Policy Review 13. 73 Patapan, above n 6, 139. 74 Mabo v Queensland (No 2) (1992) 175 CLR 1, 145; Patapan, above n 6, 128-31. 75 Another good example, in an area quite removed from those covered in Judging Democracy, is the High Court's development and application of the doctrine of unconscionable transactions in equity. From a perfectly acceptable doctrinal genesis and a clearly legitimate modern application in Commercial Bank of Australia v Amadio (1983) 151 CLR 447, the High Court has managed (through two decisions in particular - Louth v Diprose (1992) 175 CLR 621 and Bridgewater v Leahy (1998) 194 CLR 457) to create uncertainty and debate about the legitimate circumstances for the application of such relief – a point which has been noted in vigorous dissents in those cases. See the judgment of Toohey J in Louth; and the joint judgment of Gleeson CJ and Callinan J in Bridgewater. 2001 The High Court – Legitimacy and Change 307 ____________________________________________________________________________________ The rights particularly focussed upon by Patapan in Judging Democracy are those which were developed by means of constitutional implication in the 1990s. The implied nature of the freedom of political communication and some of the rights suggested in respect of Chapter III of the Australian Constitution meant not only that this new jurisprudence was vulnerable to external criticism – it was also particularly subject to the vagaries of individual Justices' perception of what was necessarily just. That the implications purportedly derived from the separation of judicial power are constitutionally less secure than the freedom of political communication reflects the Court's failure (at least so far) to ground the former more clearly in the text of the Constitution.76 Conversely, the ability of the High Court to reach consensus on the recognition and basis of an implied freedom of political communication between 1992 and 1997 displays remarkable commitment to ensuring the legitimacy of that freedom – especially when one considers the very disparate opinions given voice along the way.77 The Court's settlement upon constitutional text of ss 7 and 24 of the Commonwealth Constitution to ground this implied freedom 'is consistent with the common law notion of freedom as residual or negative, the area left uncontrolled by the law. It is also consistent with a constitutionalism that considered representative and responsible government as essential for human development and progress'.78 Therefore the unanimous judgment in Lange79 represents a consolidation, which is neither radical nor novel, but which accords with orthodox Australian constitutionalism. This point is well made by Patapan, but a seeming lack of clarity in respect of the Court's discussion regarding the difference between 'representative government' and 'representative democracy' confuses the issue in parts. For example, while it is quite true that 'the Court subsequently moved away from the notion of representative democracy as the conceptual basis for interpreting rights, preferring to rely on specific constitutional provision regarding the election of members of the House of Representatives and the Senate',80 we are later told that: '[i]nitially, the favoured institution is representative democracy. Lange augments this notion, with responsible government'.81 Most of chapter 4, dealing with the High Court's involvement in defining representative democracy is predicated on the basis that the concept of representative democracy is entrenched by ss 7 and 24.82 In fact, Lange sees the triumph of an insistence by some in earlier cases,83 that the freedom is to be implied from the system of representative and responsible government established by ss 7 and 24, rather than any notion of representative democracy which may be thought to underlie those sections. Far from augmentation, Lange sees a withdrawal from what it clearly perceives as the expanse – and _____________________________________________________________________________________ 76 Williams, above n 30, 420-3. 77 See n 36 and Leslie Zines, 'The Present State of Constitutional Interpretation' in Adrienne Stone and George Williams (eds), The High Court at the Crossroads – Essays in Constitutional Law (2000), 227. 78 Patapan, above n 6, 60. 79 (1997) 189 CLR 520. 80 Patapan, above n 6, 29. 81 Ibid 60. 82 Ibid 70, 74, 86 and 88. 83 Theophanous v Herald & Weekly Times, (1994) 182 CLR 104, 199-200 (McHugh J); McGinty v Western Australia (1996) 186 CLR 140, 169 (Brennan CJ). 308 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ consequent uncertainty – of 'representative democracy'. As with the earlier comments about the role of implications and shifts in interpretation, it is not suggested that Patapan's central argument and observations are consequently flawed, nor seriously undermined, by this feature of his treatment of the topic. The complaint is that his thesis would, in fact, be strengthened by an acknowledgment of this aspect of the Court's debate about the basis of its rights jurisprudence.84 It is also made with appreciation of the fact that there is a school of thought that the distinction between 'representative democracy' and 'representative government' is largely meaningless.85 Presumably Patapan is similarly inclined.86 The difficulty in arguing that those two phrases are interchangeable in describing the one concept, is that the High Court has clearly signalled that it does not take this view. In particular, the unanimous judgment in Lange, unlike those featured in the earlier political speech cases, contains no reference to 'representative democracy'. The fact that the Court cited with approval those very sources which McHugh J gave in Theophanous v Herald & Weekly Times to support a distinction would also seem to indicate that it now shares his view.87 Perhaps those sources are open to challenge, perhaps the Court has been misguided – but whilst arguments may be made on those grounds, the fact remains that the Lange judgment draws a distinction which, until such time as the Court changes its mind, should not be ignored or glossed over. Despite concerns about the long-term inability of textualism to sustain the development of the standards by which the implied freedom of political speech is to be applied,88 the acceptance of this development, which the High Court has managed to achieve through a concerted clarification of its method, is undeniable. It also raises an interesting comparison with the implications arising from the separation of judicial power, which have not received similar attention. That a consideration of the nature of judicial power necessarily involves measurement using standards of what is just and fair was highlighted most notably, but not exclusively, by the judgments delivered by Deane, Toohey and Gaudron JJ in cases across this period.89 The variety of opinion with respect to individual rights potentially derived from Chapter III of the Commonwealth Constitution illustrates Patapan's argument concerning the indeterminacy of community values and justice as a means of interpretation. In turn, it _____________________________________________________________________________________ 84 For example, the use of textualism as an indicia of judicial restraint was recently discussed in Daley, above n 51, 305. Whether or not there is a meaningful distinction to be drawn between the two concepts, my argument is that the Court's treatment of this issue is reflective of Zines' comment that it 'was the tone rather than the substance of the [Lange] judgment that seemed to presage a new more legalistic attitude': Zines, above n 77. 85 Kirk, above n 35, 45. 86 As, it seems, is Chief Justice Gleeson who has asserted that the 'establishment of representative parliamentary democracy as the method of government for our Federation has been held to carry implications for freedom of political debate and comment': Gleeson, The Boyer Lectures, above n 4, 60-1. 87 Essentially, Anthony Birch, Representative and Responsible Government: An Essay on the British Constitution, (1964) 17. 88 Stone, above n 35; Kirk, above n 35. 89 Specifically, Polyukhovich v Commonwealth (War Crimes Act Case) (1991) 172 CLR 501 (Deane J and Gaudron J); Dietrich v The Queen (1992) 177 CLR 292 (Deane J and Gaudron J); Leeth v Commonwealth (1992) 174 CLR 455 (Deane and Toohey JJ, Gaudron J). 2001 The High Court – Legitimacy and Change 309 ____________________________________________________________________________________ also explains why those opinions have 'failed to coalesce into a persuasive and stable jurisprudence'.90 The rights discourse which began in earnest on the High Court during the Mason era is hugely significant in consideration of Patapan's central questions about the Court's vision of the Australian legal and political regime and its place within it. The very limited number and nature of the express rights contained in the Constitution reflect the commitment of the drafters to the traditions of English constitutionalism and their faith in the wisdom of parliament.91 The republicanism of Andrew Inglis Clark found little favour with most of his contemporaries at the Constitutional Conventions of the 1890s.92 The original High Court, comprised of persons intimately familiar with the mood of the debates, may have drawn implications to support their conception of Australian federalism without hesitation. However, they had no impetus to do the same in respect of protecting human rights. The methodology laid down by the Court in Engineers and the insistence upon legalism certainly continued the Court's acceptance of parliamentary sovereignty as the theoretical core of the Australian polity. The Court's more recent change in interpretative method and its willingness to explore rights protection indicates an appreciation of its position and accountability as the final court of appeal in a member of the international legal community.93 But Patapan is keen to assert that, more fundamental than the influence of internationalism,94 is the Court’s growing awareness of the limitations of majoritarian rule which parliamentary sovereignty supports.95 This has necessarily affected how it conceives its role of judicial review.96 Over the last decade, the ire of politicians has been aroused not just by the result of matters before the Court, but also by the clear willingness of many of its members for the Court to act as a 'buffer between [arbitrary] governmental power and the people'.97 Though, as always, the degree to which they will insist upon this role is a source of contention. Clearly, Dawson J took a very restrained view of the Court's ability to intervene in righting the perceived wrongs of the people's representatives.98 At the other end of the spectrum, Patapan describes Deane, Toohey and Gaudron JJ's judgments in Mabo as revealing a 'fundamental distrust of Parliament and the people'.99 That these three justices tended to present the more progressive readings of the Constitution is not surprising – their clear preference for natural rights in the Kantian mould rather than a recognition of rights merely through a negativing of parliamentary power produced opinions that other members of the Bench considered _____________________________________________________________________________________ 90 Williams, above n 11, 249. 91 Patapan, above n 6, 41-5; see also Williams, above n 11, 82-4. 92 Helen Irving, To Constitute a Nation (1998) 69-72; Williams, n 11, 30-45; George Williams, 'A Republican Tradition for Australia?' (1995) 23 Federal Law Review 133, 144. 93 Patapan, above n 6, 17-20; 47-9. 94 Though on this topic, see Amelia Simpson and George Williams, 'International Law and Constitutional Interpretation' (2000) 11 Public Law Review 205. 95 Patapan, above n 6, 49-50. 96 In addition to the supporting extra-curial remarks cited by Patapan, see also John Toohey, 'A Government of Laws, and not of Men?' quoted in Galligan, n 24, 186; and Gleeson, The Boyer Lectures, above n 4, 68-71. 97 Williams, above n 11, 230. 98 See text accompanying n 73. 99 Patapan, above n 6, 132. 310 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ wholly irreconcilable with Australia's constitutional traditions. The reining in of these views from Theophanous100 to an adoption of the textualist basis for the implied freedom of political communication in Lange, and the McGinty majority's clear rejection of Toohey and Gaudron JJ's attempts to impose limits upon parliamentary control of the electoral system, represent a significant curtailment of the influence of republican theory in the High Court, at least for now. The legacy of judgments reliant upon popular sovereignty and republicanism in the field of implications arising from separation of judicial power remains to be seen.101 THE NATURE OF THE REGIME AND THE HIGH COURT'S PLACE WITHIN IT Judging Democracy is concerned with analysing the High Court's recent case law to determine how it conceives the polity within which it functions. The point has been made above, in respect of both interpretation and rights, that the founders were more heavily influenced by Westminster constitutionalism than the federalist and republican vision of the Americans. The faith in parliamentary sovereignty and responsible government explains the length of time for which the Court was held in the thrall of legalism. Although always demanding a strict separation of judicial power, the Court has acknowledged the influence of responsible government upon the greater mingling between the legislature and the executive powers.102 The admission of a law-making role for the courts introduces difficult notions into this setup. It directly challenges parliamentary power, it asks questions about accountability in a democratic society and, in so doing, it invites consideration upon the judiciary's claim to be separate from the other arms of government. The fierceness with which judicial separation continues to be guarded by the High Court was demonstrated particularly by the decisions in Brandy v HREOC103 and Wilson v Minister for Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Affairs.104 On what basis does the Court's continued claim for judicial independence rest? Patapan explores the mixed heritage of the United States' Federalist papers and Blackstone's Commentaries on the Laws of England and concludes that the separation of judicial power rests upon an amalgam of both, excessive reliance upon the former necessarily being precluded by the practical reality of responsible government in the Australian constitutional system. The Court's stated emphasis upon the protection of freedom of the individual in recent times, should not itself be seen as indicating a greater embrace of the American tradition of separation of powers. Though the federal structure of the Australian state provides a significant rationale justifying the separation of judicial power, Patapan says that 'the theoretical justifications for the Federalist conception of separation of powers never seriously engage the Court'.105 Instead, the recent focus upon liberty has been developed within Blackstone's conception of the role of separation of powers and the protection of ancient common _____________________________________________________________________________________ 100 Where Toohey and Gaudron JJ were joined in a joint judgment by Mason CJ. 101 See Williams, above n 11, 241-3, 249. 102 Victorian Stevedoring & General Contracting Co Pty Ltd & Meakes v Dignan (1931) 46 CLR 73. 103 (1995) 183 CLR 245. 104 (1996) 189 CLR 1. 105 Patapan, above n 6, 165. 2001 The High Court – Legitimacy and Change 311 ____________________________________________________________________________________ law rights. That said, the failure of the Court to reconcile reliance upon English notions of separate judicial power with its stated abandonment of Blackstone's declaratory theory has inevitably led to a perceptible lean towards the American constitutional concept of 'checks and balances'. The hostility with which the Court is now treated by the other arms of government, including the Attorney-General's refusal to speak for the courts, is strongly indicative of this changing constitutionalism.106 The Court's transition, from the legalist method and sovereignty of parliament toward a system of judicial review that more openly applies institutional restraints in light of community values, has not occurred smoothly nor without objections and difficulties – indeed it is almost certainly going too far to say that such a transition has actually occurred. Nevertheless, Patapan is able to describe the direction in which much of the Court's recent work seems to point: The regime is founded upon republican ideals, though popular sovereignty expresses its will through representative institutions such as parliament that are subject to liberaldemocratic ideals. Therefore certain core or fundamental principles are entrenched expressly or implicitly in the Constitution. These fundamental rights, which include freedom of speech and movement, of equality and non-discrimination, are jealously guarded by the judiciary which will supervise with suspicion – check and balance – other institutions such as Parliament and the executive who continually seek to augment their power and authority. The regime provides the greatest room for the play of human innovation and endeavour, assuring progress and prosperity. On the whole the polity is outward-looking, taking its cues and direction from international developments.107 Thus Patapan answers his initial question of the nature of the Court's democratic vision. The extent to which Australian constitutionalism is embracive of republican theory is a matter lying at the core of the present Bill of Rights debate. Yet, as George Williams argues, until such time that republicanism forms part of Australia's constitutional orthodoxy, its use by the High Court presents a 'danger for the integrity of the process of constitutional interpretation'.108 This would explain the controversial reception which met the Court's decisions handed down in the era under review by Patapan. The obvious breaking down of the division between law and politics that is caused by consideration of republican ideals within our existing constitutional tradition is clearly a development upon the Court's earlier practice and one which, like most periods of change, caused consternation and confusion. Having indicated the nature of the polity reflected in the High Court's recent decisions, Patapan turns his direct attention on the crucial question that has burned throughout the book – is this democratic vision the result of concerted group decisionmaking, or does it represent no more than the output of so much judicial discretion, indulgence and individualism? Interestingly, in his foreword to Judging Democracy, Sir Anthony Mason offers this 'caution to the reader': The High Court is not a monolithic institution. It is at any time a group of seven justices who are obliged to hear and determine, according to their individual judgment, particular cases. The justices may have conflicting views on the role of the Court as well as on the principles of law which should govern the case in hand. It would therefore be a serious mistake to assume that, in deciding a case, the Court as an institution embarks _____________________________________________________________________________________ 106 Williams, above n 2. 107 Patapan, above n 6, 190. 108 George Williams, 'A Republican Tradition for Australia?' (1995) 23 Federal Law Review 133, 143. 312 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ upon any general policy with a view to achieving a particular goal, political or otherwise, external to the disposition of that case.109 Patapan admits that perhaps he was 'too ambitious in looking for a comprehensive and consistent depiction of Australian democracy in the Court's judgments'.110 The judges of the High Court speak, as Mason has reminded us, primarily with their own voices. While unanimity may occur – and indeed did so comparatively frequently in the Mason and Brennan eras – it remains very much the exception to the usual practice. The difficulties posed by dissenting judgments and our lack of any conceptual framework so as to appreciate their significance in respect of a study of this sort is something which Patapan is keenly attuned to: [T]he very possibility of many judgments, of minority and majority views, entertains the promise of dissent and thereby legitimates the possibility of overruling. That the Court may reject its previous decision, albeit rarely and reluctantly, presents the awkward possibility of many Courts, even a right and a wrong Court, a better or worse Court, a Court that is more or less legitimate.111 This diversity of opinion plays a crucial role in the incremental development of the Court's jurisprudence: minority judgments often act as scouts of a possible future path, advancing the jurisprudence. At other times they are the corrective, rejecting such advances'.112 Thus, in spite of the restraints urged by precedent and the nature of litigation before it, Patapan maintains his rejection of any assertion that: [T]he Court has little or no discretion, that its decisions are simply ad hoc or dictated by the practical exigencies of each case, that what looks like judging democracy is in fact an accidental collage of thoughts and observations rather than a complete picture of the regime. The new politics of the High Court refutes this proposition: the disjunction and in some cases break from the Court's previous decisions, and the extra-curial claims of the justices themselves, indicated and promised a more ambitious plan.113 The last part of this passage is a strong response to the caveat applied by Sir Anthony Mason in his foreword – undeniably the Court shifted its outlook under his Chief Justiceship. The normally 'individualistic spirit of its members'114 makes it difficult to dismiss the developments and achievements of the High Court's work during this period as so little more than a coincidence of cases and personalities. Recent empirical work seems to indicate that Mason CJ was at the intellectual core of the Court over which he presided.115 Thus, ironically, his influence appears to have been pivotal in establishing whatever degree of institutional coherence can be discerned. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 109 Mason, 'Foreword' in Patapan, n 6, viii-ix. 110 Patapan, above n 6, 184. 111 Ibid 185. 112 Ibid 186–187. 113 Ibid 189. 114 Gleeson, The Boyer Lectures, above n 4, 89. 115 Russell Smyth, '"Some Are More Equal Than Others" – An Empirical Investigation into the Voting Behaviour of the Mason Court' (1999) 6 Canberra Law Review 193. 2001 The High Court – Legitimacy and Change 313 ____________________________________________________________________________________ THE POLITICS OF THE NEWEST HIGH COURT It is clear to all observers that the Court over which Gleeson CJ presides is markedly different from that of the Mason era.116 Thus Judging Democracy seems more a reflection on the heady days of the recent past than an analysis which encompasses much of the present Court's work. That said, Patapan's final recommendation still holds relevance in light of the lessons to be learnt from the 1990s. He urges the Court to better explain itself to its 'shadow court' – practitioners, academics, commentators and students. He is particularly concerned that the last group are not seduced by the easy appeal of a judicial method which is prepared to displace law in order to achieve what is perceived as just. Rather pointedly he identifies the 'example and ambitions of the 'Great Dissenter' on the Bench'117 as the source of this harm. This seems unfair in light of the analysis he has offered in earlier chapters of the excesses of the Theophanous and Wik majorities, to take just two examples. Interestingly, this is a topic which Gleeson CJ has also addressed. In his Boyer Lectures, the Chief Justice also stressed the importance of the 'shadow court' when he said: It is not sufficient for the Court to have the respect of lawyers; but it is absolutely necessary. Without that, the Court could never hope to sustain the respect of the public. Judges of final appeal primarily needs the confidence of the judges from whom they hear appeals, and of the legal profession as a whole. If the judiciary and the legal profession lacked confidence in the technical legal ability of the members of Australia's highest court, then it is impossible to expect that public confidence could be maintained.118 The Chief Justice has also eerily echoed Patapan's concern about hero worship of iconoclastic judicial officers by saying that '[o]nly someone given to mock heroics, or lacking a sense of the ridiculous, could characterise differences of judicial opinion in terms of bravery'.119 In fact, the Chief Justice's portrayal of judicial work as 'uniquely secure' and without 'risk of any personal, financial, professional, or social penalty'120 is difficult to reconcile with much of the venomous commentary upon the Court and its individual judges in recent years. Instead of simply communicating the strength of judicial independence, such sentiments seem more like a wistful attempt to revive the decades when the Court glowed in the respect of the other arms of government and was shrouded in mystery in the public mind. It is when one considers the recent statements on methodology that the difference between the present and the period under review in Judging Democracy seems most apparent. Through analysis of significant cases of the Gleeson period to date, Zines has been able to say that 'it cannot be said that there has been any sharp break with the recent past in judicial method so far as the majority of judges are concerned'.121 However, extra-judicial pronouncements by Gleeson CJ are in stark contrast to those which we have become accustomed to seeing emanate from the Court since the mid_____________________________________________________________________________________ 116 This is most attributable to the pronounced change in the Court's composition since 1995 rather than the arrival of any one particular Justice. 117 Patapan, above n 6, 192. 118 Gleeson, The Boyer Lectures, above n 4, 82. 119 Murray Gleeson, 'Judicial Legitimacy' Australian Bar Association Conference, New York, 2 July, 2000, reprinted in Gleeson, The Boyer Lectures, above n 4, 124-138 (this quote from 136). 120 Ibid. 121 Zines, above n 77, 231. 314 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ 1980s. The Chief Justice has stated that 'the members of the Court are expected to approach their task by the application of what Sir Owen Dixon described as 'a strict and complete legalism".122 Even in spite of the strong criticism of the Court since it acknowledged its law-making role and the distinct change in the Court's personnel in recent years, this is a surprising development. Are the new politics of the newest High Court, simply that it has no politics? Can it only be four years earlier that Doyle CJ confidently stated that 'the previously prevailing strict legalism has been abandoned. There is an open acknowledgment of the role of what I have called policy"?123 How are we to reconcile Gleeson CJ's apparent revival of legalism (or at least the rhetoric thereof) with the clear departure from it signaled by Mason J in 1986?124 It seems far too late in the day for a retreat to the safe haven of legalism without greater explanation - quite bluntly, values are out of the bag.125 Mason J argued that policy-oriented interpretation would expose the values underlying legal reasoning. Gleeson CJ tends to eschew the more common phrase 'community values' in preference to what he calls 'values inherent in the law'.126 Without wishing to enter a semantic debate about the similarities or distinction between values which 'inhere' and those which are 'underlying'– it seems clear that Sir Anthony Mason's recognition of values included those which are not necessarily purely legal in nature but which may rest upon a broader base of acceptance by the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 122 Gleeson, The Boyer Lectures, above n 4, 85. The original statement by Dixon CJ is found at (1952) 85 CLR xiv. 123 Doyle, above n 25, 95. 124 Mason, above n 40. I am conscious here of the arguments made by Bryan Horrigan that 'the proper meaning of strict legalism does not preclude reference to non-rule-based standards', Bryan Horrigan, 'Paradigm Shifts in Interpretation: Reframing Legal and Constitutional Reasoning' in Sampford and Preston (eds), above n 24, 42. Horrigan's view is predicated on the basis that there is a 'narrow' and 'wide' sense of 'strict legalism'. The original use of 'strict legalism' by Dixon CJ was in the latter sense and is not to be seen as irreconcilable with subsequent admissions of the role of policy. Horrigan's argument that 'Mason CJ's call for a change in judicial approach is not a complete renunciation of Dixonian strict legalism' (ibid, 64) is hard to square with the words of Sir Anthony Mason himself when he stated, 'As the High Court moves away from "strict and complete legalism" and toward a more policy oriented constitutional interpretation, it is a natural parallel that the Court place greater emphasis on the purposive construction of statutes.' Mason, above n 40, 5. This is not necessarily to resist the construction which Horrigan places upon the sense in which Dixon CJ employed the phrase 'strict legalism', but it would seem either that Mason CJ did not unquestioningly share that perception of what the phrase evoked or, more likely, that the slide from the 'wide' meaning to the 'narrow' which had crept into Australian law by 1986 simply rendered any use of 'strict legalism' no longer helpful as an attempt to explain judicial methodology. 125 In acknowledging inescapable policy considerations, Justice Sackville had this to say of the High Court's recent work, 'It is tempting to see recent developments as signalling a departure from the policy-oriented jurisprudence of the Mason Court. The inconvenient results flowing from cases like Re Wakim and Abebe and the emphasis on the primacy of the text of the Constitution suggest a retreat towards a "strict and complete legalism" in constitutional adjudication. But…this is too simplistic a view': Ronald Sackville, 'Foreword' in Stone and Williams, above n 77, vi. 126 Gleeson, above n 119, 134. 2001 The High Court – Legitimacy and Change 315 ____________________________________________________________________________________ community.127 In accordance with the sociological jurisprudence which Patapan has identified as an influence upon members of the Mason Court,128 the resort to these values does not automatically taint legal reasoning nor render it illegitimate. What are these 'values inherent in the law' and what is their relation to what other members of the court have called 'community values'? Other than saying that '[r]espect for precedent is itself one legal value, although there are times when it is outweighed by other legal values'129 the Chief Justice does not expand upon what these might be (though his choice of precedent as an example of the kind of values he has in mind is revealing in its conservatism), nor how they might operate, nor precisely where the line will be drawn between such values and those which are not to be properly classed as 'legal'. Thus, despite the apparently narrower range of 'values' that Gleeson CJ is prepared to recognise, he does not allay Patapan's concerns about their malleability in the hands of judges. In fact, passages from a speech delivered by the Chief Justice to the Australian Bar Association in New York last year highlight the tensions that lurk behind the cloak of the legalist tradition: If the High Court is not to resolve federal conflicts by a legalistic method, what other method is it to employ? Different lawyers have different ideas as to the techniques that are appropriate to strict and complete legalism, but who would care to suggest an alternative to legalism? A complaint that a judgment is literalistic is one that I can understand, and with which, on occasions, I may agree. But what exactly is the meaning of a complaint that a judgment is legalistic? Judges are appointed to interpret and apply the values inherent in the law. Within the limits of the legal method, they may disagree about those values. But they have no right to throw off the constraints of legal methodology. In particular, they have no right to base their decisions as to the validity of legislation upon their personal approval or disapproval of the policy of the legislation. When they do so, they forfeit their legitimacy.130 From this it is clear that room exists within 'strict and complete legalism' for diverse opinions as to methodology – in which case some discussion of these would be welcome.131 There is also scope for disagreement about legal values – thus giving them one of the significant defects already identified in respect of community values. Additionally, there would seem legitimate concern that application only of 'values _____________________________________________________________________________________ 127 Although the difficulties involved in the use of 'community values' were referred to earlier in this essay, two points need to be borne in mind before rejecting such a methodology, unpredictable as it may be, for 'strict and complete legalism'. First, it was also acknowledged that some disputes may only be resolved through use of non-legal considerations such as moral or political values. Second, the problems of uncertain identification and application are not substantially lessened by resort only to 'legal values' – especially when one considers Justice McHugh's opinion that 'what has been called community values has usually been a reference to values…which already inhere in the legal system': McHugh, above n 4, 46. 128 Patapan, above n 6, 20-22. 129 Gleeson, The Boyer Lectures, above n 4, 98. 130 Gleeson, above n 119, 134. 131 This would also seem to invite consideration of whether legalism can really be said to be 'strict' when it seems to offer such selectivity. 316 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ which inhere in the law' involves the judiciary projecting on to the wider community values which the latter does not entirely share.132 The New York speech makes it very difficult to discern Gleeson CJ's position on values as his Honour used that occasion expressly to endorse the work of McHugh J on the judicial method.133 Whilst it is true that McHugh J's writings on the technique of judging have much in common with the views expressed with more generality by the Chief Justice, there are important inconsistencies. In particular, how are we to reconcile Gleeson CJ's insistence that judicial legitimacy depends upon a legalist method using only those values which inhere in the law, with these two statements from McHugh J in 1999: Extrinsic values and practical experience derived from democracy, economics, science, social and political forces, public morality and contemporary conceptions of justice are often relevant factors in shaping the development of the law. [I]f the extra-legal values of the community are clear and the issues are "relatively discrete and manageable", there is no reason to disregard them as legitimate sources of the judicial law-making function.134 Gleeson CJ's reticence about the substance of the values he considers relevant is also an interesting feature of his writing. If we are to confine ourselves to 'legal values', and if the 'expertise which the members of the [High] Court are required to bring to bear…is their expertise as lawyers',135 then surely we can expect more precision about the content of those values? It may be that McHugh J provides the way forward when he says that he suspects that 'what has been called community values has usually been a reference to values such as freedom, equality before the law, good faith and reasonableness which already inhere in the legal system'.136 Perhaps then it is possible for the Gleeson Court to connect itself to the jurisprudence which immediately precedes it but then to develop and apply its own distinctive methodology which may take it in different directions.137 What is very clear is that assertions of a legalist methodology will not have the desired effects of making the Court's work any easier, nor guaranteeing greater public understanding and acceptance of the outcomes. Both Williams138 and Zines139 have pointed out that the methodology in Wik was amongst the most legally orthodox in the last decade yet the High Court managed to attract a 'torrent of abuse' for that _____________________________________________________________________________________ 132 Daley has said that 'judges tend to have an homogeneous background which emphasizes some values – particularly fair process and individual liberty – in ways which are not entirely rational': Daley, above n 51, 300. 133 Gleeson, above n 119, 129. 134 McHugh, above n 4, 46-7. 135 Gleeson, above n 119, 6 of original transcript of speech. Oddly, these words from the original version of the New York speech do not appear in the version found at the end of the Boyer Lectures book. The passage from which they originally came is found in The Boyer Lectures, above n 4, 134-5. 136 McHugh, above n 4, 46-7. 137 As another example of Justice McHugh's involvement in such a process, in his 1999 article he in fact forecast a diminished role for extra-legal values in the Court's future work: McHugh, above n 4, 46. 138 Williams, above n 30, 427-8 139 Zines, above n 68, 408. 2001 The High Court – Legitimacy and Change 317 ____________________________________________________________________________________ decision.140 Decisions from the last few years illustrate a high degree of flexibility, selectivity and inconsistency in judicial method amongst the Court – and indeed, in respect of individual justices from case to case.141 Apart from anything else it achieves, Patapan's Judging Democracy, by canvassing the strides in methodology and transparency made by the High Court since the mid-1980s, plays an important part in explaining why any retreat to 'strict and complete legalism' is unsustainable and unhelpful.142 CONCLUSION It is apparent from the foregoing that the arrival of Judging Democracy is particularly timely. The developments in the practice and outlook of the High Court since the appointment of Sir Anthony Mason as Chief Justice has long needed just such a general yet concise study. While the many changes in the law over recent years have received specific attention in published articles, it is refreshing to read an account which seeks to relate many of those developments to each other and to the core issues of judicial method. It is probably inevitable that in attempting such a task, the author is bound to dissatisfy some readers in respect of the depth or handling of particular matters. It is just as certain, that a book of this sort generates more points of debate than it answers – indeed, given the complexity of the material under discussion, it would be an indication of deficiency if this were otherwise. In providing a broad examination of the High Court's recent jurisprudence, Judging Democracy succeeds admirably. The selection and erudite treatment of topics by Patapan and the connections which he makes between them offers and invites reflections about many aspects of the Court's role and operations. This book will play a prominent part in our understanding of the High Court in the 1990s and our discussions about it in its second century. As such, it is ensured a welcome reception and a lasting importance. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 140 Ibid. 141 See generally the various analyses of the Court's recent work contained in Stone and Williams, above n 77. In the concluding chapter of that work, Zines finds no trend in the Court's constitutional interpretation: 'There is not, in my view, any general pattern or direction at this stage. The cases are a motley collection in which the Court and individual judges take varying approaches depending on the issue': Zines, above n 77, 238. 142 Horrigan, after arguing for the 'proper' understanding of 'strict legalism' in its 'wide' sense to be acknowledged, says, 'Australian constitutional reasoning, therefore, needs a conceptual framework for accommodating judicial reference to such 'deeper…conceptions of justice' as 'principles' (in something like their Dworkinian sense) or values underlying Australian constitutional law and for distinguishing impermissible from permissible references to 'policy' considerations, community values and other non-rule-based standards.' Above n 124, 61. In spite of his arguments about its true wider sense, the use of 'strict and complete legalism' seems ill-equipped to rise to this challenge. COMMENT BROWNLEE V THE QUEEN: METHOD IN THE MADNESS James Stellios* INTRODUCTION In Brownlee v The Queen1, the High Court was asked to consider whether the trial of the applicant pursuant to current legislative standards of trial practice in New South Wales was compatible with s 80 of the Constitution. Pursuant to provisions of the Jury Act 1977 (NSW)2, the jury was reduced during the course of the trial from twelve jurors to ten, and during jury deliberation, the jury members were allowed to separate at the end of each day. The applicant contended before the High Court that such practices were incompatible with the essential characteristics of a 'trial … by jury' in s 80 of the Constitution. The Court unanimously rejected that argument. Brownlee v The Queen provided the High Court with another opportunity to explore the scope of s 80 of the Constitution. It also provided the Court with another opportunity to develop an accepted method of constitutional interpretation. Despite the insistence by some Justices for the adoption of a particular label for constitutional interpretation, it would appear that, at least as far as the meaning of 'trial … by jury' in s 80 of the Constitution is concerned, the High Court has adopted an accepted framework. FACTS The applicant was charged with conspiracy to defraud the Commonwealth in contravention of s 86A of the Crimes Act 1914 (Cth). He was tried on indictment in the District Court of New South Wales and was convicted. The District Court had _____________________________________________________________________________________ * Lecturer, Faculty of Law, Australian National University. The author appeared as counsel for the Commonwealth of Australia at the hearing of Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180 before the High Court. The views expressed in this Comment are those of the author's. 1 (2001) 75 ALJR 1180. 2 Hereafter referred to as the Jury Act. 320 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ jurisdiction conferred on it to try and convict the applicant under s 68(2) of the Judiciary Act 1903 (Cth).3 The conferral of jurisdiction is expressed to be subject to s 80 of the Constitution. In accordance with s 68(1) of the Judiciary Act, the laws of New South Wales respecting the procedure for the trial and conviction on indictment were to be applied to the applicant's trial so far as they were applicable. During the course of the trial, two jurors were discharged. The relevant provision for the discharge of jurors is contained in s 22 of the Jury Act. Paragraph (b) of that section provides that in the case of criminal proceedings, where, in the course of any trial, any member of the jury dies or is discharged by the court (whether as being through illness incapable of continuing to act or for any other reason), the jury shall be considered as remaining properly constituted if the number of its members: (i) is not reduced below ten, (ii) is reduced below ten but approval in writing is given to the reduced number of jurors by or on behalf of both the person prosecuting for the Crown and the accused or each of the accused, or (iii) is reduced below ten but not below 8 and the trial has been in progress for at least 2 months. The first juror was discharged under s 22 of the Jury Act because continued jury duty would have clashed with prearranged travel commitments.4 The second juror was discharged because continued service would have imperilled his business. In accordance with s 22, the trial continued to conclusion with a jury of ten. On Wednesday, 3 July 1996, the jury retired to consider its verdict. Section 54(b) of the Jury Act provides that the jury in criminal proceedings, may, if the court so orders, be permitted to separate at any time after they retire to consider their verdict. Pursuant to this section, the jury was allowed by the trial judge to separate after each day's deliberation and over the weekend of 6 and 7 July.5 The jury returned its unanimous verdict of guilty on Monday, 8 July 1996. The trial judge then sentenced the applicant to a term of imprisonment. The applicant's appeal to the New South Wales Court of Criminal Appeal was dismissed.6 Grove J (with whom Bruce J and Cooper AJ agreed) held that neither the reduction of the jury from twelve to ten, nor the separation of the jury after the commencement of deliberation, was incompatible with s 80 of the Constitution. The applicant applied to the High Court for special leave to appeal. At the hearing of the special leave application, Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ referred to the Full Bench so much of the special leave application as raised the question of whether s 68 of the Judiciary Act operated at the trial of the applicant to 'pick up' (i) s 22 of the Jury Act _____________________________________________________________________________________ 3 Being a law investing any court of a State with federal jurisdiction: s 77(iii) of the Constitution. 4 See the judgment of Kirby J in Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1195-6 for a detailed account of the events leading up to the discharge of the two jurors. 5 Prior to the jury retiring, the jurors were not confined. They were permitted to separate after each day's hearing – see ibid, 1196 (Kirby J); 1212 (Callinan J). 6 R v Brownlee (1997) 41 NSWLR 139. 2001 Brownlee v The Queen 321 ____________________________________________________________________________________ and (ii) s 54(b) of that Act.7 That is, whether s 68 operated to apply those provisions to the trial of the applicant. Thus, it was not in issue that the trial of the applicant was a trial on indictment for the purposes of s 80. Neither was it in issue before the High Court whether the trial judge had properly exercised the discretionary powers under ss 22 and 54(b) of the Jury Act.8 The applicant's objection was to the application of ss 22 and 54(b) of the Jury Act by the trial judge because of their alleged incompatibility with s 80 of the Constitution. THE 'PICKING UP' OF THE STATE PROVISIONS The applicant was tried and convicted of an offence against a law of the Commonwealth and, therefore, the District Court of New South Wales was exercising federal jurisdiction conferred upon it by s 68(2) of the Judiciary Act.9 However, the vesting of that federal jurisdiction in a State court by s 68(2) is expressly subject to s 80 of the Constitution. Further, s 68(1) provides that State laws are 'picked up'10 only so far as they are applicable. Thus, this was not a case in which s 80 operated to invalidate a federal or state law.11 If the relevant state provisions were incompatible with s 80 of the Constitution, then the state laws should not have been 'picked up' and applied in federal jurisdiction. In short, if ss 22 and 54(b) were incompatible with s 80, the applicant's trial would not have been held in accordance with the command in s 80 and the conviction would be liable to be set aside. DECISION OF THE COURT Four separate judgments were delivered by the Court. Joint judgments were delivered by Gleeson CJ and McHugh J, and by Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ. Justices Kirby and Callinan each delivered a separate judgment. On the question of separation, the Court unanimously held that s 80 did not mandate an absolute rule that juries could not separate after the deliberation process had commenced.12 Their Honours also held unanimously that it was not an imperative of s 80 that the number of jurors remain at twelve after the trial has commenced.13 Thus, ss 22(a)(i) and 54(b) of the Jury Act were not incompatible with s 80 and were appropriately 'picked up' by s 68(1) of the Judiciary Act. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 7 See High Court transcript of proceedings, application for special leave to appeal, 11 February 2000. 8 See, for example, Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1184 (Gleeson CJ and McHugh J). 9 See the discussion by Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ, ibid, 1188. See also Kirby J, ibid, 1197. 10 Ibid, (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ). See also ibid, (Kirby J). 11 Ibid, 1189 (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ). See also Kirby J, ibid, 1198. Therefore, there was no question of s 68 of the Judiciary Act being invalid. 12 Ibid, 1186 (Gleeson CJ and McHugh J); 1193 (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ); 1211 (Kirby J); 1216 (Callinan J). 13 Ibid, 1185 (Gleeson CJ and McHugh J); 1193-4 (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ); 1209-10 (Kirby J); 1216 (Callinan J). 322 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ APPROACH TO CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION AND TO S 80 OF THE CONSTITUTION The Perennial Tension The application of s 80 of the Constitution to the facts in this case provided another opportunity for further debate on the proper method of constitutional interpretation. Brownlee v The Queen again raised the perennial tension between the view that the Constitution is to be interpreted as a statute,14 and the recognition that the Constitution is a special statute intended to endure and 'apply to the varying conditions which the development of our community must involve'.15 While this tension has existed since the establishment of the Court, very few High Court Justices have been prepared to engage in the debate of the proper judicial method for constitutional interpretation. Certainly, crude tools such as the connotation and denotation distinction have been used to resolve the tension in particular cases. However, as Professor Zines points out, surely this and similar distinctions merely restate the question.16 In recent years, McHugh J and Kirby J have debated their respective approaches over the course of a number of cases.17 Adopting an orthodox approach, McHugh J favours an approach that his Honour describes as textualism or semantic intentionalism.18 Such an approach looks to the objective intention of the framers of the Constitution. In his Honour's view, this approach neither involves a search for the subjective intention of the framers, nor does it result in the Constitution having a meaning fixed at 1900. His Honour is of the view that '[o]ur Constitution is constructed in such a way that most of its concepts and purposes are stated at a sufficient level of abstraction or generality to enable it to be infused with the current understanding of those concepts and purposes.'19 Justice Kirby, on the other hand, rejects any approach to constitutional interpretation that considers as crucial the intentions of the framers or the meaning of constitutional words and phrases at 1900. His Honour favours an approach that looks to the contemporary meaning of the Constitution.20 In fact, in his Honour's view, the Court in recent years has adopted the approach that his Honour advocates.21 Although a change of meaning has been accommodated by the use of the connotation/denotation distinction, in his Honour's view, that device merely disguises _____________________________________________________________________________________ 14 Most classically stated in Amalgamated Society of Engineers v Adelaide Steamship Co Ltd (Engineers' case) (1920) 28 CLR 129, but certainly adopted from the very beginning of the Court - see Tasmania v The Commonwealth and Victoria (1904) 1 CLR 329, 358-60 (O'Connor J). 15 Jumbunna Coalmine, No Liability v Victorian Coal Miners' Association (1908) 6 CLR 309, 368. 16 Leslie Zines, The High Court and the Constitution (4th ed, 1997) 19. 17 See, for example, Re Wakim; Ex parte McNally (1999) 198 CLR 511; Eastman v The Queen (2000) 74 ALJR 915; Grain Pool of Western Australia v Commonwealth (2000) 74 ALJR 648. 18 Eastman v The Queen (2000) 74 ALJR 915, 939. 19 Ibid, 940. 20 See, for example, his Honour's judgments in Grain Pool of Western Australia v The Commonwealth (2000) 74 ALJR 648; Eastman v The Queen (2000) 74 ALJR 915. 21 Grain Pool of Western Australia v The Commonwealth (2000) ALJR 648, 670. 2001 Brownlee v The Queen 323 ____________________________________________________________________________________ 'the fact that the Court's search has become one for the contemporary meaning of constitutional words, rather than for the meaning which those words held in 1900.'22 Other than McHugh and Kirby JJ, on the whole, the other Justices have been reluctant to enter into the debate explicitly.23 In submissions to the Court in Brownlee v The Queen, the Attorney-General of South Australia argued that judicial 'diffidence' to the adoption of a particular approach to constitutional interpretation was no longer appropriate, and urged the Court clearly to identify a proper approach. However, perhaps any 'diffidence' by some members of the High Court is to committing themselves to the adoption of a particular label to describe the proper method for constitutional interpretation. Perhaps, the search for a label obscures and complicates the interpretive task in a particular case. The decision in Brownlee v The Queen, provided an opportunity for the Court to respond to these questions. Method for interpreting the Constitution - Judgments in Brownlee v The Queen Gleeson CJ and McHugh J In contrast to other judgments in which McHugh J explained his approach in detail, his Honour's joint reasons with the Chief Justice provided very little elaboration of a general interpretive approach. Their Honours referred to the use of history by the Court in Cheatle v The Queen24 for the purpose of ascertaining the meaning of the expression 'trial … by jury', and noted that in determining its meaning, it was both proper and necessary for the Court to resort to historical considerations. In their Honours' view, such an inquiry 'was undertaken because the exercise upon which the Court was embarked involved ascertaining the meaning of an instrument which came into being in a certain manner, at a certain time, and for a certain purpose'.25 A consideration of the 'historical context' in which the Constitution was written and the 'genesis' of that instrument would be, in their Honours' view, 'potentially relevant to a question about the meaning of the instrument.'26 However, such a consideration of the historical context was not undertaken for the purpose of 'psychoanalysing the people who were involved in the framing the Constitution'.27 In their Honours' view, the subjective understanding of the framers is not the determining factor in a dispute about constitutional interpretation, but such an understanding may reflect the historical context in which the Constitution was written.28 Although their Honours clearly recognised that the historical context is relevant to the process of resolving a problem as to the interpretation of the Constitution, in their _____________________________________________________________________________________ 22 Ibid. 23 Although, if there is indeed a real difference between the approach advocated by McHugh J and that of Kirby J, there have been indications that the other Justices have accepted a more conventional approach as evidenced by the joint judgment in Grain Pool of Western Australia v The Commonwealth (2000) 74 ALJR 648. 24 (1993) 177 CLR 541. 25 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1183. 26 Ibid. 27 Ibid. 28 Ibid. 324 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Honours' view, 'the significance of the circumstances surrounding the framing of the instrument will vary according to the nature of the problem'.29 Despite the need to consider the historical context in which the document was written, their Honours recognised the enduring nature of the Constitution. Since the Constitution 'was brought into being as an instrument of government, which would need to respond to changing circumstances and conditions over time', in their Honours' view, it would be wrong to attribute to it a meaning 'frozen in time'.30 What appears to be missing from their Honours' interpretive framework is any reference to the objective intentions of the framers. In previous judgments, McHugh J had emphasised that in ascertaining the meaning of the Constitution, the 'search is always for the objective intention of the makers of the Constitution'.31 The fact that, in their Honours' view, the historical context might have a variable significance to the process of ascertaining the meaning of the Constitution, suggests that any reference to intention, whether objective or subjective, may only serve as a distraction from the true inquiry, that is, 'the meaning of the Constitution'. Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ The judgment of Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ does not expressly elucidate a general approach to constitutional interpretation. However, as will become apparent, their Honours clearly recognised that the task may require, as was the case in relation to s 80, a consideration of the historical context in which the Constitution was drafted. Ultimately, though, the task is to ascertain the meaning of the Constitution in a contemporary context. Kirby J Justice Kirby expressly recognised the tension between, on the one hand, the recognition that the Constitution is a statute and, thus, that its meaning is uncovered by general techniques of statutory construction and, on the other hand, the realisation that the Constitution is a statute of a special kind. Consistently with previous attempts, Kirby J sought in Brownlee v The Queen to elucidate his theory of constitutional interpretation. His Honour recognised the submission of the Attorney-General of South Australia that without an established approach to constitutional interpretation, decisions inevitably will be inconsistent 'reflecting no more that the intuitive responses to the text of the Constitution by different Justices (or of the same Justices at different times).'32 In his Honour's view, constitutional expressions must be given their contemporary meaning. Only such an approach would befit 'the character of a national basic law, which is extremely resistant to formal amendment, but which must, of necessity, apply to new, unforeseen and possibly unforeseeable circumstances'.33 His Honour then attempted to illustrate the inappropriateness of adopting a 1900 criterion for ascertaining the content of 'trial … by jury' in s 80. His Honour noted that at 1900, all jurors were male; they had to have property qualifications of some kind; _____________________________________________________________________________________ 29 Ibid. 30 Ibid. 31 Eastman v The Queen (2000) 74 ALJR 915, 940. 32 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1203. 33 Ibid, 1203. 2001 Brownlee v The Queen 325 ____________________________________________________________________________________ and exemptions from jury service were designed to single out characteristics thought, at that time, to be essential to the type of 'right thinking man' for jury service.34 His Honour noted that the decision in Cheatle v The Queen considered gender and property qualifications as undesirable and incompatible with 'a contemporary institution' or 'modern democratic society'. Thus, his Honour reasoned that the Court in Cheatle v The Queen must have adapted the institution of trial by jury to modern Australian conditions. His Honour argued that once such considerations are adopted for modifying features of the trial by jury that were considered essential at 1900, then such an approach must be adopted consistently when considering other features of trial by jury. As his Honour states, '[e]ither one adheres to the historical notions of 1900, and takes the mind back to what the framers knew and understood about jury trial, or one accepts that the constitutional expression must be given a "contemporary" meaning, as befits a "modern democratic society".'35 Indeed, in his Honour's view, since the framers lived in a different world, the search for the framers' intention would be misleading and prone to result in serious error. Notwithstanding that conclusion, his Honour does not entirely dismiss historical considerations. In his Honour's view, a consideration of history, as in the debates that preceded adoption of the Constitution, might not be 'wholly irrelevant', but has limited utility when the search is for the contemporary meaning of words and phrases.36 His Honour concluded his discussion on interpretive method by rejecting the approach to constitutional construction that would limit the meaning to be given to the expression 'trial … by jury' in s 80 to the notions held about the mode of trial by the framers of the Constitution in 1900. His Honour recognised that it will 'take time for the search for constitutional meaning by reference to the imputed "intention of the framers" in 1900 to be abandoned in favour of a search for the essential characteristics of the words and phrases having enduring constitutional operation'.37 The remaining judge, Justice Callinan, did not seek to elucidate a general approach to constitutional interpretation. Interpretation of Section 80 This in fact was an easy case. Even by federation, there was no clearly established universal rule preventing the reduction of jurors from twelve to ten after the trial had begun.38 Similarly, by federation, there were already inroads being made into the strict common law rule that a jury could not separate until verdict.39 Thus, having briefly _____________________________________________________________________________________ 34 Ibid, 1204. 35 Ibid. 36 Ibid. 37 Ibid, 1207. 38 There was legislation in Victoria, Queensland, Western Australia and New Zealand which permitted a jury to continue with fewer than twelve jurors – see ibid, 1184-5 (Gleeson CJ and McHugh J); 1192 (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ); 1206 (Kirby J); 1215 (Callinan J). In fact, prior to federation, even the common law position was not entirely clear – see ibid 1184 (Gleeson CJ and McHugh J); 1192 (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ); 1215 (Callinan J). 39 Although at federation jurors could not separate after they had retired for deliberation, the strict common law rule against separation prior to deliberation had been relaxed progressively by 1900 – see ibid, 1185 (Gleeson CJ and McHugh J); 1191-2 (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ); 1216 (Callinan J). 326 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ surveyed relevant case law and legislation, both British and colonial, Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ concluded that, at the time of federation, the 'absolute sequestration of the jury was no longer regarded as an essential element of trial by jury; likewise, the necessity to swear in a fresh jury if a juror died or was taken ill.'40 Therefore, even on a strict originalist approach to interpreting the Constitution, those characteristics could not have been considered by the framers to be central to the concept of a trial by jury. However, their Honours proceeded to consider how s 80 should be interpreted to reflect the enduring nature of the Constitution. It is clear that the Court has affirmed the distinction between essential and nonessential elements of a trial by jury employed by the Court in Cheatle v The Queen for the purposes of determining which characteristics of a 'trial … by jury' are constitutionally entrenched.41 For example, Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ described the task as the identification of whether the provisions of the Jury Act merely changed the inessential elements of the trial process, or destroyed an essential or fundamental feature of the institution.42 Their Honours then quoted, with apparent approval, from an article by Professor A W Scott:43 Only those incidents which are regarded as fundamental, as inherent in and of the essence of the system of trial by jury, are placed beyond the reach of the legislature. However, the Court in Brownlee v The Queen refined the constitutional analysis further. The Court recognised that the institution of trial by jury performs a particular constitutional function and is designed to achieve certain ends or purposes.44 Thus, as stated by Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ, the classification of essential features of the institution of trial by jury involves an appreciation of the objectives that institution advances or achieves.45 In other words, to perform that function in a constitutionally compatible manner, the institution must be characterised by certain essential functional attributes.46 History reveals the ends or purposes sought to be achieved by the institution and that its essential attributes might be achieved by different rules of practice and procedure depending on the social context.47 Rules which may be seen at one time to be indispensable to the achievement of the essential objectives of the institution might, at a later time, not be characterised as central to, or even compatible with, those essential objectives. Thus, the Court has retained the distinction between essential and inessential attributes of the institution of a trial by jury, but has applied this distinction in a more sophisticated way that results in a differentiation between the essential functional _____________________________________________________________________________________ 40 Ibid, 1192. 41 Ibid, 1184 (Gleeson CJ and McHugh J); 1190 (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ); 1207 (Kirby J); 1216 (Callinan J). 42 Ibid, 1190. 43 AW Scott, 'Trial by Jury and the Reform of Civil Procedure' (1918) 31 Harvard Law Review 669, 671. 44 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1183 (Gleeson CJ and McHugh J); 1190 (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ); 1208 (Kirby J). 45 Ibid, 1190. 46 Ibid, 1185 (Gleeson CJ and McHugh J); 1191 (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ); 1209 (Kirby J). 47 Ibid, 1184 (Gleeson CJ and McHugh J); 1191 (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ). 2001 Brownlee v The Queen 327 ____________________________________________________________________________________ attributes of a trial by jury and the means by which those functional attributes are achieved. Any difference among the members of the Court48 lies in the extent to which the social context and history bear upon this analysis. The joint judgments of Gleeson CJ and McHugh J, and Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ, consider that the contemporary social context is relevant to the question of whether contemporary practice is compatible with the essential functional attributes. Indeed, that assessment can only be made in a contemporary context. But, for their Honours, the essential attributes themselves cannot be determined by contemporary standards. In other words, the function of the institution cannot be ascertained by reference to contemporary standards. As Gleeson CJ and McHugh J said: If the meaning of 'trial … by jury' is to be determined solely by reference to contemporary standards, there is nothing to argue about. Contemporary standards are reflected in the Jury Act.49 On the face of Kirby J's judgment, it appears that his Honour rejects such an approach. His Honour's approach searches for the: [E]ssential characteristics of 'trial … by jury', referred to in s 80 of the Constitution, as that expression is to be understood as a constitutional requirement, viewed in its context in Ch III and from the perspective of contemporary considerations that identify the essential characteristics of that mode of trial in Australia.50 However, on closer analysis, his Honour's approach may properly be seen as consistent with the views expressed in the joint judgments.51 His Honour certainly rejects any 'approach to constitutional construction that would limit the meaning to be given to jury trial in s 80 to the notions held about that mode of trial by the framers of the Constitutional in 1900.'52 However, in truth, that is not what the joint judgments seek to do. The joint judgments seek to identify the essential functional attributes of a trial by jury by reference to the historical inception of that institution, but the assessment of compatibility of laws with those functional attributes is an exercise undertaken in a contemporary context. Indeed, Kirby J implicitly recognises the immutable character of the functional attributes when his Honour describes the task of interpretation as 'a search for the essential characteristics of the words and phrases having enduring constitutional operation'.53 The use of history and a reference to the framers' intention might also be said to distinguish Kirby J's approach to the interpretation of s 80 and the approach of the joint judgments. However, such apparent differences cannot really be said to withstand closer analysis. As to the use of history, first, Kirby J recognises that history is not 'wholly irrelevant'.54 Secondly, and more fundamentally, the joint judgments do not seek to _____________________________________________________________________________________ 48 Other than Callinan J who did not undertake an extensive jurisprudential analysis. 49 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1183. 50 Ibid, 1207. 51 Graeme Hill has noted that there 'may be very little difference, in practice, between McHugh and Kirby JJ's approaches to interpretation' - see '"Originalist" vs "Progressive" Interpretations of the Constitution – Does it Matter?' (2000) 11 Public Law Review 159, 162. 52 Ibid. 53 Ibid (emphasis added). 54 Ibid, 1204. 328 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ employ history as a mechanism for entrenching rules of practice. Their Honours look to history as a means for gaining some insight into what the essential functional attributes of a trial by jury are. As the Court stated in Cheatle v The Queen: It is well settled that the interpretation of a constitution such as ours is necessarily influenced by the fact that its provisions are framed in the language of the English common law, and are to be read in the light of the common law's history.55 The consideration of history might reveal the procedural means (that is, the rules of practice) that were once considered necessary for the achievement of the functional attributes, but it does not fix the words 'trial … by jury' in s 80 with those temporal understandings. In fact, a consideration of history might reveal that rules of practice, while consistent with the essential functional attributes at 1900, are incompatible with a contemporary understanding of those functional attributes. Thus, gender and property qualification are incompatible with modern understandings of the institution.56 Similarly, inflexible rules preventing a reduction in jurors from twelve to ten and preventing separation of jurors might be seen in a contemporary context as incompatible with the functional attributes. Moreover, any difference in the judgments by reason of the use of the framer's intention is more apparent than real. Certainly, Kirby J rejects any approach that considers as important the intention of the framers. But, subject to one exception to be mentioned below, the joint judgments also do not place any such reliance on the framer's intention. First, Gleeson CJ and McHugh J emphasise that the subjective understanding of the framers is only relevant to the meaning of the Constitution because it may reflect 'the historical context in which [the] instrument was written.'57 Thus, the framer's subjective intentions do not give content to the essential functional attributes of the institution of trial by jury. The joint judgment of Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ, with one unfortunate exception, does not give any regard to the intention of the framers. The exception appeared when their Honours dealt with the question of whether the jury can be permitted to separate. In that context, their Honours referred with approval to an extract from the judgment of Grove J in the court below. Grove J held that: [A]n understanding and construction should be given to the words in s 80 that the framers of the constitutional guarantee intended that a jury exercise its function without fear or favour and without undue influence in the context of community standards and expectations as current from time to time.58 It is unclear whether this was a conscious reference to the intention of the framers. However, if it was, it is clear that their Honours could not have meant the subjective intentions of the framers. No reference was made by their Honours to the debates. To the extent that their Honours intended to refer to the objective intention of the framers, it is merely another means of identifying the task before the Court, that is, one of finding the essential functional attributes of an institution that existed at common law. That inquiry is not advanced by reference to the notion of objective intention and, indeed, can only serve to mislead and distract attention from the proper inquiry. In fact, even McHugh J refrained from using such language. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 55 (1993) 177 CLR 541, 552. 56 Cheatle v The Queen (1993) 177 CLR 541. 57 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1183. 58 (1997) 41 NSWLR 139, 145-6. 2001 Brownlee v The Queen 329 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Thus, at the very least, five Justices have settled on a framework for the interpretation of the words 'trial … by jury' in the s 80. It may in fact be that Kirby J's approach can also be reconciled with the approach expressed in the two joint judgments. The Court will search for the essential functional attributes of the institution of a 'trial … by jury', and assess contemporary trial standards by reference to those essential attributes. In determining which elements are essential, the Court will look to the function performed by a jury trial. As to what those essential functional attributes might be, the various Justices made the following observations. Gleeson CJ and McHugh J agreed with the observations of White J in Williams v Florida59 that the purpose of the jury trial is to prevent oppression by the government. Given this purpose, White J was of the view that 'the essential feature of a jury obviously lies in the interposition between the accused and his accuser of the commonsense judgment of a group of laymen, and in the community participation and shared responsibility that results from that group's determination of guilt or innocence'.60 Undoubtedly based on these observations, their Honours identified essential functional attributes of a 'trial … by jury' as independence, representativeness and randomness of selection, and the need to maintain the prosecution's obligation to prove its case beyond reasonable doubt.61 Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ made similar observations. Their Honours also identified the purpose of a 'trial … by jury' as directed to the determination of guilt according to law, with the interposition between the accused and the prosecution of the 'commonsense judgment of a group of laymen'.62 For the achievement of this purpose, the jury must be able to 'deliberate upon its verdict uninfluenced by an outsider to the trial process'63. In short, the jury must be independent. In the context of jury size, their Honours observed that the jury must be 'large enough to promote measured deliberation and [indicate] to the community sufficient participation by its members to vindicate the outcome'.64 Justice Kirby also identified the prevention of oppression as an important purpose of a trial by jury.65 His Honour identified a list of essential functional attributes. As to jury size, essentially, it must be large enough to promote group deliberation66 and to ensure that a cross-section of community opinion will be expressed67. His Honour also noted that because s 80 takes its place in Chapter III of the Constitution, 'it is essential that it should continue to hold public confidence and "through the involvement of the _____________________________________________________________________________________ 59 399 US 78 (1970). 60 Ibid, 100. 61 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1185. 62 Ibid, 1192 quoting from White J in Williams v Florida 399 US 78, 100 (1970). As their Honours noted, it is an 'instrument in the administration of justice' ibid, 1190 quoting from Ex parte Peterson (1920) 253 US 300, 309-10 (Brandeis J). 63 Ibid, 1193. Or, as put by Grove J in the Court below, and approved by their Honours, 'that a jury exercise its function without fear or favour and without undue influence …' ibid. 64 Ibid, 1193. 65 Ibid, 1209. 66 Which might include guarding against the force of strong personalities on the jury – see ibid. 67 This would include the objective of ensuring that the jury composition reflects the variety of opinions that exist in the community concerning society, the law and public authority, and minorities within the community – see ibid. 330 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ public, societal trust in the system as a whole"'.68 Additionally, his Honour noted that given that contemporary trials can be extremely complex and lengthy, the inconvenience to the community, to jurors and the cost to the parties should not needlessly be incurred by unnecessary termination and re-litigation of jury trials where jurors die, fall ill or are otherwise incapable of continuing to act.69 This last consideration appears not to be an essential functional attribute, but rather a consideration to be taken into account when assessing contemporary standards of practice against essential functional attributes. Justice Callinan also appears to identify as essential attributes, first, the independence of the jury from influences70 and, secondly, in terms of jury size, the representativeness of the community.71 The Justices were unanimously of the view that allowing separation after retirement for deliberation, and the reduction in jury size from twelve to ten during the course of the trial, were contemporary practices that were not incompatible with the essential features of a 'trial … by jury'. The essential functional feature of independence did not require an absolute rule barring separation. In fact, as noted by Gleeson CJ and McHugh J it would be 'an unnecessarily oppressive means of achieving the desired end'.72 Neither was it incompatible with the attribute of group deliberation. As Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ said, 'strict confinement may have retarded rather than encouraged measured group deliberation and, in former times, appeared to be calculated to pressure jurors to reach a unanimous verdict and to do so with expedition'.73 Moreover, Kirby J noted that the representativeness of the jury would be diminished if such an absolute rule resulted in the exclusion of some cross-sections of the community.74 As to the reduction in number of jurors from twelve to ten during the trial, Gleeson CJ and McHugh J concluded, with little elaboration, that such a system is not inconsistent with the objectives of independence, representativeness and randomness of selection, or with the need to maintain the obligation of proof beyond a reasonable doubt.75 Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ considered that starting with twelve jurors was necessary to ensure a size large enough to promote deliberation and to indicate to the community sufficient participation by its members.76 However, their Honours noted _____________________________________________________________________________________ 68 Ibid. His Honour quoted from the Canadian Supreme Court decision in R v Sherratt [1991] 1 SCR 509, 524. 69 Ibid. 70 Ibid, 1216. 71 Ibid. 72 Ibid, 1186. 73 Ibid, 1192-3. Such an assessment was undertaken in a contemporary context, in particular, taking into account the greater trust placed in modern jurors 'to heed the directions of the presiding judge' ibid, 1193. Kirby J also noted that strict rules of sequestration would result in circumstances that were not conducive to the proper performance of the jury function ibid, 1210. 74 For example, parents with young children or persons caring for sick and elderly relatives ibid, 1210. 75 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1185. 76 Ibid, 1193. 2001 Brownlee v The Queen 331 ____________________________________________________________________________________ that history at the time of federation showed that a reduction to ten jurors was seen as compatible with the need to ensure observance of the deliberative process required by the institution of trial by jury.77 The legislation in place at the time of federation had already adapted the institution to the perceived needs of the time, 'whilst retaining the substantial character of the institution as an efficient instrument in the administration of justice'.78 Their Honours concluded that current legislation that allowed a reduction to ten jurors was not incompatible with s 80 of the Constitution. This conclusion was reinforced by the contemporary context of lengthy and complex trials.79 Their Honours accepted the observations by Gleeson CJ and Hayne J in Wu v R80 to the effect that requiring a full complement of twelve jurors for the whole trial would place considerable burden not only on the accused, but also upon the witnesses and juries.81 Thus, their Honours were concerned to ensure that the institution remained 'an efficient instrument in the administration of justice'.82 Justice Kirby noted the dangers in allowing a reduction in jury size from the traditional number of twelve. A reduction in number would increase the risk that the jury might not be representative of the community.83 There would also be a 'danger to the community's perception of the impartiality of the jury …'.84 However, like Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ, Kirby J considered the longer length of modern criminal trials, and the greater complexity and expense involved.85 In his Honour's view, '[n]othing would be more likely to undermine the survival of jury trial'86 than an inflexible rule that the jury reach its verdict with twelve members. Justice Callinan considered the reduction to ten jurors to be valid because 'there is no reason in principle why a jury of twelve persons should necessarily be considered more representative of the community than a jury of 10 persons or 14 …'.87 Consequently, their Honours unanimously upheld the application of ss 22(a)(i) and 54(b), although their Honours did not justify their conclusions by reference to the same essential functional characteristics. Although the differences were not significant in the circumstances of this case, it is clear that such differences might be crucial to other legislative provisions prescribing rules of practice and procedure for jury trials.88 _____________________________________________________________________________________ 77 Ibid. 78 Ibid, 1193-4 adopting the words of Brandeis J in Ex parte Peterson 243 US 300, 309-310 (1920), quoted by Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ at ibid, 1190. 79 In their Honours' view, this reflected 'not only the increased complexity of the substantive issues to be tried but the expansion of procedural rights favouring the accused' - Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1193. 80 (1999) 199 CLR 99, 106. 81 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1193. 82 Ibid, 1194. 83 Ibid, 1208. 84 Ibid. 85 Ibid, 1209. 86 Ibid, 1210. 87 Ibid, 1216. 88 See the similar observations made in relation to Grain Pool of Western Australia v The Commonwealth (2000) 74 ALJR 648; see Hill above n 54, 160. 332 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ COMMENT ON CONSTITUTION THE METHOD FOR INTERPRETING THE Only Kirby J and, to some extent, Gleeson CJ and McHugh J, accepted the invitation from the Attorney-General of South Australia to set out a general approach to interpreting the Constitution. Thus, the decision in Brownlee v The Queen does not appear to progress the debate much further in the sense that the other Justices have not committed themselves to adopting a particular label to describe the proper interpretive method. However, there is a clear recognition that application of an interpretive method critically depends on the constitutional provision being interpreted. For instance, when speaking of the role of history in the interpretation of the Constitution, Gleeson CJ and McHugh J said that the 'significance of the circumstances surrounding the framing of the instrument will vary according to the nature of the problem.'89 Thus, when interpreting s 80, it is important to recognise that s 80 takes its place in Chapter III of the Constitution. It encapsulates a particular manifestation of an organ or institution of government, the judiciary: specifying what form that organ or institution should take in the circumstances described in s 80. Therefore, when interpreting the meaning of the expression 'trial … by jury' in s 80 of the Constitution, it is essential to appreciate the purposes for which the institution was entrenched in the Constitution. It is by reference to those purposes that the institution's essential character may be determined, and it is by reference to those purposes that the scope of the constitutional requirements may be ascertained. The positioning of s 80 in Chapter III has a number of consequences. First, in determining which legislative provisions contravene the requirements of s 80, due regard must be had to the constitutional division of power. Thus, when comparing contemporary standards with the requirements of s 80, the content of the constitutional requirements cannot be ascertained by reference to legislative initiatives. There is danger in an approach that focuses exclusively on contemporary standards. There is much force in the comments of Gleeson CJ and McHugh J that '[i]f the meaning of "trial … by jury" is to be determined solely by reference to contemporary standards, there is nothing to argue about. Contemporary standards are reflected in the Jury Act.'90 If Kirby J's approach were confined to giving content to the expression 'trial … by jury' by reference to contemporary standards in isolation, his Honour would be in danger of ignoring the constitutional division of power. However, in truth, his Honour's approach is more sophisticated: it searches for enduring essential functional attributes, and applies those attributes to the legislative provisions in question in a contemporary context. Secondly, the positioning of s 80 in Chapter III helps define the essential functional attributes. Thus, the maintenance of rules of practice that undermine public confidence in the judiciary, or undermine the survival of the institution of jury trial, would clearly not be required by s 80. Thirdly, along with all courts vested with judicial power, a trial by jury is an institution of government. As such, it must reflect constitutional values. In other words, it must not be characterised by attributes that are incompatible with a _____________________________________________________________________________________ 89 Ibid, 1183. 90 Ibid. 2001 Brownlee v The Queen 333 ____________________________________________________________________________________ 'contemporary institution' or a 'modern democratic society'.91 It is partly for this reason that gender and property qualifications for jurors are incompatible with s 80. Such requirements are offensive to constitutional values. It would be intolerable for similar qualifications to be imposed on the people for entitlement to vote for Parliament. Thus, it is intolerable for the same qualification to be placed upon the people when they participate more directly in the governmental institution of 'trial … by jury'. Certainly, the decision in Cheatle v The Queen can be explained simply on the basis that gender and property qualifications were incompatible with the essential functional attribute of representativeness. However, arguably, that functional attribute is, itself, a reflection of constitutional values. Although the Court has not unanimously and explicitly assigned a label to the approach it has adopted to the interpretation of the Constitution, it has at the very least recognised that the approach adopted for the interpretation of the Constitution will depend upon the provision in question. Although not expressed in these terms, the Justices appear to accept that the interpretation of s 80 must depend upon the fact that a 'trial … by jury' is a judicial institution of government. It was included in the Constitution for certain purposes, and its essential attributes must be determined by reference to the constitutional function that it performs. Indeed, it may be that the search for a particular label for the approach to be adopted might be a distraction from the interpretive task to be performed. Reduction of Jury Below Ten Paragraphs 22(a)(ii) and (iii) of the Jury Act allow the number of jurors to be reduced below ten in certain circumstances. On the facts in this case, it was not necessary for the Court to consider whether s 22(a)(ii) and (iii) are compatible with s 80 of the Constitution.92 Nevertheless, Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ indicated that 'a real question arises'93 as to whether a reduction below ten might be incompatible with s 80. Their Honours suggest that ten is the minimum to which a jury could be reduced consistently with the maintenance of the requisite deliberative process.94 However, it is not clear what conclusion the other Justices would reach. When identifying the essential features of a jury, Gleeson CJ and McHugh J referred, with apparent approval, to the judgment of White J in Williams v Florida.95 In the passage extracted in the judgment of Gleeson CJ and McHugh J, White J held that a jury of six would satisfy the functional attributes of a jury trial identified by Gleeson CJ and McHugh.96 Applying the functional attribute of representativeness, Callinan J saw no reason in principle why twelve should be more representative of the community than ten or fourteen. His Honour left open the possibility of a number lower than ten being _____________________________________________________________________________________ 91 Cheatle v The Queen (1993) 177 CLR 541, 560. 92 See for example the judgment of Gaudron, Gummow and Kirby JJ in Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1189. To the extent that a reduction could be made with the consent of the accused under s 22(a)(ii), the question of waiver arises. This will depend upon whether the decision in Brown v The Queen (1986) 160 CLR 171 is overruled by the Court. 93 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1194. 94 Ibid, 1193. 95 399 US 78 (1970) cited at (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1185. 96 Their Honours noted that White J's observations applied 'with even greater force' to a system allowing a reduction from twelve to ten – ibid. 334 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ compatible with s 80.97 In assessing compatibility with s.80, no distinction was drawn in the judgment of Gleeson CJ and McHugh J, or by Callinan J, between the requisite number of jurors at the commencement of the trial and the number to which a jury could be reduced. There is nothing to suggest that their Honours considered the distinction to be a material one in this respect. Justice Kirby also recognised the inevitable task of drawing lines.98 But his Honour did not assess the question of a reduction in the number of jurors against the functional attributes of maintaining the deliberative process or representativeness. His Honour recognised the inherent risk to the degree of representativeness by a reduction in jury size.99 However, that risk was outweighed by the threat to the institution of jury trial if a strict rule were adopted prohibiting any reduction in number. Thus, the question for Kirby J will be whether a rule prohibiting the reduction below ten would be likely to 'undermine the survival of jury trial'.100 Thus, it is not entirely clear whether the other provisions of s 22 of the Jury Act allowing for a reduction below ten would be held to be valid. Jury of Less Than Twelve The question of whether a jury could be comprised initially of less than twelve jurors was also not before the Court. Although Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ recognised that the constitutionality of empanelling a jury of less than twelve was not in issue101, nevertheless, their Honours were prepared to assume that it is 'a central characteristic of trial by jury and mandated by s 80 of the Constitution'102 that a jury of twelve be empanelled. Their Honours held that such a requirement was supported on 'utilitarian' grounds: '[i]t ensures that the trial gets underway with fact-finding entrusted to a group of laymen which is large enough to promote measured deliberation and indicates to the community sufficient participation by its members to vindicate the outcome'.103 However, the requirement of a proper deliberative process has no obvious relevance at commencement of the trial. The question as to the proper size of the jury for the purposes of ensuring a proper deliberative process only arises once the jury retires to deliberate. In light of their Honours' conclusion that a jury size of ten at the time of deliberation ensures 'observance of the deliberative process required by the institution of trial by jury',104 it is unclear how a jury of the same size at a time anterior to the deliberation process would undermine the process of deliberation. At the time of deliberation, the nature of the deliberative process of ten jurors is logically the same whether the trial commences with twelve or ten. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 97 Ibid, 1216. His Honour acknowledged that a line had to be drawn, but did not speculate as to where that line might be drawn – ibid. 98 Ibid, 1210. 99 Ibid, 1208. 100 Ibid, 1210. 101 Ibid, 1188. 102 Ibid, 1193. See also ibid, 1194. 103 Ibid, 1193. 104 Ibid. 2001 Brownlee v The Queen 335 ____________________________________________________________________________________ As indicated though, their Honours also referred to the 'utilitarian' ground of ensuring that the jury commences with twelve so as to indicate to the community sufficient participation by its members to vindicate the outcome. Although the community participates in a trial from its commencement, surely the relevant concern of the community to ensure sufficient participation to vindicate the outcome extends for the duration of trial until verdict. Whether there has been sufficient community participation to vindicate the outcome must be assessed at the time the jury deliberates on its verdict, not at the time the trial commences. Thus, this 'utilitarian' ground appears to be inconsistent with their Honours' finding that a jury of ten (reduced from twelve) at the verdict stage is compatible with s 80. The joint judgment of Gleeson CJ and McHugh J, and the judgment of Callinan J, appear to be more receptive to the idea that a jury commencing with ten is compatible with s 80. As indicated, Gleeson CJ and McHugh J quote, with apparent approval, from the judgment of White J in Williams v Florida.105 The passage extracted states that a jury comprised of six members would be compatible with the functional attributes identified by Gleeson CJ and McHugh J. Callinan J also observes that there is no reason in principle why a jury of twelve would be more representative that a jury of ten.106 It is in Kirby J's judgment that a reason may be found for distinguishing, for the purposes of s 80, between the reduction in number from twelve to ten, and starting with a jury of ten. His Honour did not directly address the question of whether a jury could start with ten other than to comment that such a practice would be a departure 'both from longstanding English and Australian legal prescription'.107 However, his Honour's reasons for holding s 22(a)(i) of the Jury Act to be valid are also illuminating in this respect. As indicated above, his Honour acknowledged the inherent erosion of representativeness by reducing the jury from twelve to ten, but held that the erosion in that essential functional attribute was warranted for the purpose of preserving the public confidence in the jury and, thus, preserving the survival of the jury trial. Such a justification would warrant a mechanism for allowing the trial to continue with a jury reduced in number from twelve to ten, but may not justify a jury starting with ten. Reserve Jurors In Ah Poh Wai v The Queen,108 the Western Australian Court of Criminal Appeal upheld the use of 'reserve jurors' pursuant to s 18 of the Juries Act 1957 (WA). The Western Australian system allows up to six reserve jurors to hear the evidence and participate in the trial process. However, reserve jurors do not deliberate with the other jurors unless one or more of the original twelve jurors is unable to continue. Reserve jurors can only replace jurors prior to the time the jury retires for deliberation. If a reserve juror is not called upon to replace a juror at the time the jury retires to consider its verdict, that reserve juror is discharged. Thus, under the system, the verdict is delivered by a panel of twelve jurors.109 The Court of Criminal Appeal (Malcolm CJ, _____________________________________________________________________________________ 105 399 US 78 (1970) cited at (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1185. 106 Ibid, 1216. 107 Ibid, 1209. 108 (1995) 15 WAR 404. 109 Section 646 of the Criminal Code (WA) allows a trial judge to reduce the number of jurors from twelve to ten in certain circumstances. However, s 646 does not apply if there are 336 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Pidgeon and Steytler JJ) held that the system of reserve jurors prescribed by s 18 of the Juries Act 1957 (WA) was not incompatible with the essential features of a 'trial … by jury' in s 80 of the Constitution. An application for special leave to appeal to the High Court from that judgment was refused by a majority of the Court.110 Announcing the decision of the Court, Dawson J said: By a majority the Court is not persuaded that the Western Australian Court of Criminal Appeal was in error in reaching the conclusion, which it did, that the participation of reserve jurors did not infringe any requirement of s 80 of the Constitution.111 In their joint judgment in Brownlee v The Queen, Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ noted that nothing in their Honours' reasons for judgment called into question under s 80 the use of reserve jurors. On the analysis in each of the judgments, this conclusion must be correct. The availability of additional jurors, in the event that one or more of the original twelve is unable to continue, in no way compromises the essential functional attributes of a trial emphasised in the various judgments. Such a system results in a verdict being given by a full complement of twelve jurors and thus maintains the representativeness of the jury and ensures the observance of the deliberative process. Such a system also minimises the 'needless and accidental termination of many jury trials'112 and, thus, satisfies Kirby J's concern that the institution should continue to hold public confidence. Requirement of Leave to Re-Open a Case The Attorney-General of the Commonwealth sought leave to re-open the decision in Brown v The Queen.113 As Gleeson CJ and McHugh J state in their judgment, '[h]e accepted that he needed leave'.114 During the course of the hearing, a majority of the Court refused leave to re-open Brown v The Queen.115 The premise underlying the refusal of leave to re-open a case is that leave to re-open is required. A question arises as to whether the requirement that leave be obtained is incompatible with the Constitution. Justice Kirby was the only judge to consider this issue. His Honour was of the view that leave is not required as such a procedure is incompatible with the Constitution.116 His Honour was echoing similar comments made by Deane J in Evda Nominees Pty Ltd v Victoria.117 Given the nature of the Constitution as an enduring document, Kirby J was of the view that 'it is imperative to keep the mind open to the possibility that a new context, presenting different needs and circumstances and fresh insights, may _____________________________________________________________________________________ sufficient reserve jurors to have a jury of twelve persons including replacements – see s 18(5) of the Juries Act 1957 (WA). 110 See High Court transcript of proceedings, application for special leave to appeal, 5 August 1996. The Court comprised Dawson, McHugh and Kirby JJ for the hearing of the special leave application. 111 Ibid. 112 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1210 (Kirby J). 113 (1986) 160 CLR 171. 114 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1186. 115 Ibid (Gleeson CJ and McHugh J); 1189 (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ); 1216 (Callinan J); 1199 (Kirby J dissenting). 116 Ibid, 1199. 117 (1984) 154 CLR 311, 316. 2001 Brownlee v The Queen 337 ____________________________________________________________________________________ convince the Court, in later times and of later composition, that its predecessors had adopted an erroneous view of the Constitution'.118 His Honour continued: It is a party's right to advance before this Court any argument that may assist the Court to reach the correct exposition of the meaning of the Constitution. It is incompatible with the constitutional function of the Court to impose on a party a procedural obstacle that might impede that party's submissions to the Court on such a subject.119 Justice Kirby's choice of words in restricting the right to a 'party' was deliberate. His Honour was not convinced that the position of the interveners would be the same. However, since the Commonwealth Director of Public Prosecutions adopted the Commonwealth's submissions as to the re-opening of Brown v The Queen, it was not necessary for his Honour to explore the question of an intervener's right further.120 If leave to re-open a case is not required, it is unclear why the position would differ depending upon whether the leave is sought by a party or an intervener. If the objective is to reach 'the correct exposition of the meaning of the Constitution', then surely this goal can be facilitated by an intervener in the same way as it can be achieved by a party. This is especially so in light of the important role of the AttorneysGeneral of the Commonwealth and States in constitutional cases as reflected in s 78A of the Judiciary Act 1903 (Cth). Re-Opening of Brown v The Queen As indicated, the Attorney-General for the Commonwealth applied for leave to reopen the High Court's decision in Brown v The Queen.121 A majority of the Court in Brown v The Queen held that a trial by jury could not be waived by an accused. It was argued by the Attorney-General for the Commonwealth that the applicant in Brownlee v The Queen had waived his right to a trial by jury by not objecting to the discharge of the first juror, and by applying to have the second juror discharged. Because of the way that the Justices (other than Kirby J) resolved the issues, it was unnecessary for their Honours to consider the question of whether the applicant had waived his right to a trial by jury and, thus, it was unnecessary for their Honours to consider whether Brown v The Queen should be overruled. Justice Kirby, however, approached the issues from the other end. In his Honour's view, if a trial by jury could be waived, and if the applicant had in fact waived that right, then it would be unnecessary to consider whether the trial received by the applicant conformed with the constitutional description of a 'trial … by jury' in s 80. As a question of fact, his Honour held that the applicant had waived his right to a 'trial … by jury'.122 His Honour accepted that the applicant at trial had raised no objection to the discharge of the first juror and had joined in the request that the second juror be discharged. As far as separation of the jury was concerned, his Honour noted that the applicant did not object to that course of action. Thus, his Honour was of the view that a waiver of a right to a 'trial … by jury' could be effected by an inference from a failure to act. Given that his Honour considered that the 'guarantee' in s 80 is a _____________________________________________________________________________________ 118 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1200. 119 Ibid. 120 Ibid. 121 (1986) 160 CLR 171. 122 Brownlee v The Queen (2001) 75 ALJR 1180, 1201. 338 Federal Law Review Volume 29 ____________________________________________________________________________________ 'fundamental law',123 it appears inconsistent with such a view that the right could be waived in the absence of a clear indication by an accused. Indeed, his Honour recognised the possibility that the want of objection by the applicant might have been explained by oversight.124 Having concluded that the applicant in fact waived his right, his Honour turned to consider whether such a waiver was constitutionally possible. Thus, his Honour turned to consider the correctness of the Court's decision in Brown v The Queen. His Honour held that the existence of a privilege to waive 'trial … by jury' is not 'incompatible with the essential characteristics of jury trial or with the purposes for which s 80 of the Constitution provides that mode of trial'.125 Given that the applicant had, in his Honour's view, waived his right to the constitutionally prescribed 'trial … by jury', then it was unnecessary for his Honour to consider whether the trial received by the applicant conformed with the constitutional description of a 'trial … by jury' in s 80. Therefore, strictly, his Honour's comments on those issues were obiter dicta. Only five Justices of the Court sat to hear Brown v The Queen, and the majority comprised three separate judgments. This is an unsatisfactory precedent for such a central issue to s 80. The framework for the consideration of the compatibility between a law and s 80 has now developed from those adopted by the Justices in Brown v The Queen. As Kirby J has illustrated, there is at least an argument within this new framework that the waiver of s 80 is not incompatible with s 80. To the extent that the institution of a 'trial … by jury' is intended to be 'an efficient instrument in the administration of justice'126, the following passage by McHugh J in Cheng v The Queen is pertinent: Many accused persons would not regard the mandatory requirement of a jury trial as conferring any benefit on them. Those charged with offences likely to arouse public indignation, such as cases involving sexual or other crimes against children, for example, of those accused who have raised mental illness as a defence, often prefer trial by judge to trial by jury when they are able to elect for trial by judge. To some accused, trial by jury is not a boon.127 It is hoped that the High Court will accept the opportunity to reconsider Brown v The Queen when that opportunity next arises. CONCLUSION It would appear that the Court has developed a generally accepted framework for the consideration of what constitutes a 'trial … by jury' for the purposes of s 80 of the Constitution. Such a framework differentiates between essential functional attributes and the means adopted for the achievement of those essential attributes. The task of identifying those functional attributes is undertaken by reference to the purposes for which the institution of jury trial was included in s 80. Whether a current practice or procedure for jury trial is compatible with the constitutional concept of 'trial … by jury' is an inquiry undertaken in the contemporary context, but it is undertaken by reference to an institution that has enduring functional attributes. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 123 Ibid, 1194. 124 Ibid, 1201. 125 Ibid, 1203. 126 Ibid, 1194 (Gaudron, Gummow and Hayne JJ). 127 Cheng v The Queen (2000) 74 ALJR 1482, 1508. 2001 Brownlee v The Queen 339 ____________________________________________________________________________________ Most of the Justices did not take up the invitation to elucidate a general approach to constitutional interpretation. However, the Court implicitly has recognised that the wider task of constitutional interpretation will depend upon the provision being interpreted. Thus, any attempt to assign a label to that inquiry may unnecessarily 'distract'128 attention from the task at hand, that is, to ascertain the meaning of the relevant provisions of the Constitution. How the Court approaches that task necessarily must depend on the precise provision being interpreted. Therefore, when interpreting s 80 of the Constitution, it is essential to bear in mind that s 80 takes its place in Chapter III of the Constitution: it is an institution of government included in the Constitution for certain purposes and to achieve certain ends. _____________________________________________________________________________________ 128 In other contexts, the High Court has emphasised the need to focus on the task at hand and to avoid unnecessary 'distractions' – John Pfeiffer Pty Ltd v Rogerson (2000) 74 ALJR 1109, 1114 (Gleeson CJ, Gaudron, McHugh, Gummow and Hayne JJ).