John O`Dea University of Tokyo
Transcription
John O`Dea University of Tokyo
Representational Primitives in Perception Towards a general theory of perceptual constancy John O’Dea University of Tokyo Although I believe that the table is of the same colour all over, the parts that reflect the light look much brighter than the other parts...Here we have the beginning of one of the distinctions that cause most trouble in Philosophy - the distinction between appearance and reality. -- Russell, Problems of Philosophy (1912) 1. What is Perceptual Constancy? “The perception of objects as constant in size, shape, color, and other properties despite changes in their retinal image. Berstein et al, Psychology (8th edition, 2008) 2. A Theory of Color Constancy 4. Towards a General Theory Red lines in Figure 3 describe the range of possible perceptual experience given the different stimuli (in this case, the corner of a uniformly coloured wall), supposing that surface colour and illumination are inseparably experienced and co-determining. The image is normally seen either as uniformly illuminated or as uniformly coloured. It is possible to switch between these experiences in a topdown way (as for ambiguous images), though normally the visual system automatically chooses, perhaps in Bayesian fashion, the most likely interpretation. The capacity for top-down, deliberate interpretive switching creates the false impression that both experiences are simultaneously present. 3. The Refrigerator Light Illusion Fig. 1. Size constancy: objects in the distance are not usually perceived as smaller. Fig. 2. Shape constancy: orientation does not usually affect the shape things look to be. It is possible to see an ʻapparentʼ difference in surface colour in a context of varied lighting. This is standardly assumed to be a continuous part of visual experience, albeit not normally noticed. I claim that it is actually an unstable, transitory experience involving a Gestalt-like switch. The veridical experience and the false experience (which Russell calls the “appearance”) cannot occur simultaneously, but the ability to switch at will creates the illusion otherwise. Fig. 4. The apparent size of an object depends on how far it appears to be. Size and distance are also co-primitive - to see the size of an object at all is to see it at some distance or other. Fig. 3. Colour constancy: the white wall looks different in different lighting conditions. A New Characterisation The standard definition is indistinguishable from mere successful perception. Rather, perceptual constancy is best characterised as: A pair of properties; One intrinsic and one extrinsic; which are Representationally and computationally linked (ʼco-primitiveʼ); and Fig. 5 The apparent shape of an object depends on its apparent orientation, and conversely. Shape and orientation are co-primitive in my sense. To see a shape at all is to see it at an orientation. Amenable to some degree of conscious, top-down manipulation. The Problem of Constancy: Experiential Difference On the one hand, perceptual experiences are paradigm cases of intentionality; different perceptual experiences plausibly have, thereby, different accuracy conditions. However, due to perceptual constancy, one and the same object can appear different without appearing to be different. Plausibly, a white experience is simply an experience that represents an object as being white. The problem of phenomenal variation arises because objects can look to be white, and and yet that whiteness looks different in different lighting (see Fig. 1). The Myth of the Simple Colour Experience Seeing the Light (and Dark) Colour is a property not only of objects but also of the illumination. The amount (and quality) of illumination is represented explicitly in perceptual experience Several theorists recently argue persuasively for the importance of this in accounting for the apparent remainder (see Matthen, Hilbert, Mausfeld). But how are illumination and surface colour related in perceptual experience? x x A common approach, both in philosophy and psychology. The experiential variation is attributed to sense data, a visual field, a non-representational “qualitative” difference, et. Example: Peacocke, Sense and Content (1983) Imagine that you are in a room looking at a corner formed by two of its walls. The walls are covered with paper of a uniform hue, brightness and saturation. But one wall is more brightly lit that the other. In these circumstances, your experience can represent both walls as being the same colour: it does not look to you as if one of the walls is painted with brighter paint than the other. Yet it is equally an aspect of your visual experience itself that the region of the visual field in which one wall is presented is brighter than that in which the other is presented. Hilbertʼs “Simple Solution” Hilbert suggests that illumination might be regarded as a dimension of colour, alongside or partly replacing hue, saturation and brightness (HSB). Some reasons to reject this approach: Illumination is explicitly visible, but not HSB. Perceptual matching is not possible for HSB separately (illustration the patches below (left) are composed of only two hues, but this is not visibly obvious. In contrast, the two colours composing the right figure are visibly apparent) This approach is not generalizable. Orientation is not plausibly a dimension of shape; distance is not plausibly a dimension of size. Some reasons to reject this approach: Incompatible with a powerful approach to perceptual experience: the idea that the experiential qualities of a perceptual experience are its intentional contents. There is no convincing account of the nature of the postulated mental remainder. There is a better alternative (see above). A perceptually represented property is primitive iff it is explicitly represented in perception and it is not the case that there is some other property in virtue of the representation of which it has that particular content. Neither surface colour nor illumination are “primitive” in this sense. No surface ever looks simply coloured - the experience will also specify some illumination. Surface colour and illumination are only jointly primitive in the above sense. Hence, trivially, an un-illuminated object is not visible. This is not only a practical truism; rather, it is a deep phenomenological fact, the neglect of which is, I claim, the root cause of our failure to understand constancy. What is the apparent experiential remainder? A merely mental remainder? A (stipulative) definition of “primitive”: References Matten, Mohan (2010) “How Things Look” in Perceiving the World; OUP. Mausfeld, Rainer (2003) “The Dual Coding of Colour” in Colour Perception: Mind and the Physical World; OUP. Hilbert, David (2005) “Color constancy and the complexity of color” in Philosophical Topics, 33. Kelly, Sean (2008) “Content and Constancy: phenomenology, psychology, and the content of perception” in PPR LXXVI (3). Objection: It is completely obvious that we see shadows and shading. How could this be so misleading? Ambiguity as a Feature of Constancy Differences in the amount of reflected light can mean either differences in the light absorbed by the surface, or differences in the light received by the surface (or both). Just as the conscious (or ʻtop-downʼ) manipulation of perceptual experience is possible in the case of ambiguous scenes, it is also possible the case of non-ambiguous scenes, such as the white wall, where one interpretation is clearly more plausible/ To see a scene such as the the wall in Fig.3 as receiving uniform illumination (for example, by supposing it to be flat) is to see a difference in surface colour (see Kelly 2008 for a similar proposal). Because the “alternative” way of seeing can be experienced whenever one tries to do so, it gives the impression of being a continual part of the visual experience of the table. This is a version of the refrigerator light illusion Acknowledgments: The paper on which this poster is based was presented at the Philosophy departments of Monash University, the University of Singapore and the University of Tokyo, and was greatly improved by feedback from participants, especially Jakob Howhy and Ben Blumson. Photographs: Figure 2 is © 2009 sinkdd (Flickr username), used under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial license; the same license applies to the Face/Vase (© solsken (Flickr username)) and the Refrigerator Light (© Zen Sutherland).