Dec. 2009 - Connecticut Law Review
Transcription
Dec. 2009 - Connecticut Law Review
CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW VOLUME 42 DECEMBER 2009 NUMBER 2 CONTENTS ARTICLES IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH..................................... Andy G. Olree 365 HOW TO ANALYZE THE ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY IN A CRIMINAL CASE ................... Richard A. Wise, Clifford S. Fishman & Martin A. Safer 435 PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES: A DEADLY LEGAL FICTION ................................................ David B. Kopel 515 ESSAY DEMOSPRUDENCE, INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM, AND TWENTY YEARS OF SHEFF V. O’NEILL ........................... Justin R. Long 585 NOTES GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET .................................................. Jeffrey M. Dressler 611 CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT: HOW REGULATORY INADEQUACIES IMPAIRED THE FED’S BAILOUT OF BEAR STEARNS ........................... Bryan J. Orticelli 647 THE ROLE OF PARENTS INVOLVED IN THE COLLEGE ADMISSIONS PROCESS ...................... Michael P. Pohorylo 693 The Connecticut Law Review (ISSN 00106151, USPS 664-550) is published in February, May, July, November, and December by the Connecticut Law Review Association, University of Connecticut School of Law, 65 Elizabeth Street, Hartford, Connecticut 06105-2290, and printed by Western Newspaper Publishing Company, Inc., 537 East Ohio Street, Indianapolis, Indiana 46204. Periodicals postage paid at Hartford, Connecticut and additional mailing offices. Postmaster: Send address changes to the Connecticut Law Review, 65 Elizabeth Street, Hartford, Connecticut 06105-2290. The subscription price is $40.00 per year for U.S. addresses and $60.00 for international addresses. Absent timely notice of termination, subscriptions are renewed annually. Please address all subscriptions and inquiries to the Business Manager at the publication office, or telephone at (860) 570-5331. Advertising rates quoted upon request. Individual back issues and volumes are available from William S. Hein & Co., Inc., 1285 Main Street, Buffalo, New York 14209 (800-828-7571). Microfilms of all issues are available from University Microfilms, 300 North Zeeb Road, Ann Arbor, Michigan 48106. It is the policy of the University of Connecticut to prohibit discrimination in education, employment, and the provision of services on the basis of race, religion, sex, age, marital status, national origin, ancestry, sexual preference, status as a disabled veteran or veteran of the Vietnam Era, physical or mental disability or record thereof, or mental retardation. University policy also prohibits discrimination in employment on the basis of a criminal record that is not related to the position being sought, and complies with all state and federal civil rights statutes whether or not specifically cited within this statement. University policy prohibits discrimination in education and in the provision of services on the basis of a criminal record. Copyright © 2009 by the Connecticut Law Review, all rights reserved. CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW VOLUME 42 DECEMBER 2009 Editor-in-Chief DREW K. BARBER Managing Editor COURTNEY C. SCALA Assistant Managing Editor JOSEPH W. MORALES Membership Manager Executive Editors Notes and Comments Editors Articles Editors Business Manager AILLA WASSTROM-WELZ STEPHEN HEUSSLER CHRISTOPHER M. HODGE BRYAN J. ORTICELLI RENÉE VANDEN WALL BAKE JILLIAN R. CALACETO JEFFREY P. GRIFFIN ERIC B. MILLER NATHAN MURPHY JEANNE M. HAYES BRENDAN J. KEEFE MICHAEL P. POHORYLO A. JACOB WERRETT GABRIEL J. VIDONI Commentary Editor EMILEE MOONEY SCOTT Symposium Editors JOHN LANGMAID PATRICK M. MURPHY CONNtemplations Editor Alumni Affairs Editor Competition Editor Circulation Manager Senior Associate Editor SARAH A. DOWNEY ALLISON E. CANTOR REBECCA MURPHY TAYLOR A. DENIS CLAUDIO W. GUALTIERI Associate Editors TIMOTHY BIBEAU ERICA M. CARROLL MICHAEL COSTELLO JEFFREY M. DRESSLER DAVID GRECO NUMBER 2 CHRISTOPHER A. HOUCK DANIELLE K. IVES YESHAKE YILMA JULIA C. ZAJAC Associate Members FLYNN BOONSTRA MARGARET BUDNIK KAITLIN CANTY AMANDA M. CAPRARI CRISTINA COPERSINO JENNIFER F. DALENTA ROBERT DEARINGTON SARAH DRONEY JOHN J. DUGUAY DANIEL E. GOREN GRAYSON COLT HOLMES BOLAM KIM MELISSA KNAPP MEGHANN E. LAFOUNTAIN JAMES M. LEVA YAMUNA MENON KRISTOPHER I. MOORE PATRICK G.H. MOTT MATTHEW P. NETTLETON CAROLINE B. PARK NICOLAS F. PERRY ELISABETH A. PIMENTEL BJ PIVONKA GREIL ROBERTS ASHLEY J. SCHAEFER ROBYN R. SCHWARTZ CHRISTOPHER R. SHEA KAITLIN D. SHEA JOHN O. SHEEHY JENNIFER L. SNOW JESSICA H. STEIN ANGELICA WILSON JONATHAN C. ZELLNER Faculty Advisor ALEXANDRA D. LAHAV UNIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT SCHOOL OF LAW FACULTY AND OFFICERS OF ADMINISTRATION FOR THE ACADEMIC YEAR 2009–2010 Officers of Administration Michael J. Hogan, M.A., Ph.D., President, University of Connecticut Peter J. Nicholls , Ph.D., Provost and Executive Vice President for Academic Affairs Jeremy Paul, J.D., Dean, School of Law Anne Dailey, J.D., Associate Dean for Academic Affairs Michael Fischl, J.D., Associate Dean for Research and Faculty Development Darcy Kirk, J.D., Associate Dean for Library and Technology Ann Crawford, M.Ed., Acting Associate Dean for Finance and Administration Ellen K. Rutt, J.D., Associate Dean for Admissions, Student Finance and Career Services Karen L. Demeola, J.D., Assistant Dean for Admissions and Student Finance Faculty Emeriti Robert L. Bard, B.A., M.A., LL.B., J.S.D., Professor of Law, Emeritus Phillip I. Blumberg, A.B., J.D., LL.D. (Hon.), Dean and Professor of Law and Business, Emeritus John C. Brittain, B.A., J.D., Professor of Law, Emeritus Clifford Davis, S.B., LL.B., Professor of Law, Emeritus Nell J. Newton, B.A., J.D., Dean and Professor of Law, Emeritus Howard Sacks, A.B., LL.B., Dean and Professor of Law, Emeritus George Schatzki, A.B., LL.B., LL.M., Dean and Professor of Law, Emeritus Craig Shea, A.B., LL.B., LL.M., Professor of Law, Emeritus Phillip Shuchman, B.A., M.A., LL.B., Professor of Law, Emeritus Eileen Silverstein, A.D., J.D., Professor of Law Emeritus Lester B. Snyder, B.S., LL.B., LL.M., Professor of Law, Emeritus Terry Tondro, A.B., LL.B., M.Phil., Professor of Law, Emeritus Nicholas Wolfson, A.B., J.D., George and Helen England Professor of Law, Emeritus Faculty of Law Jill Anderson, B.A., University of Washington; J.D., Columbia University; Visiting Assistant Professor of Law Paul Bader, B.A., Duke University; J.D., Mercer University Walter F. George School of Law; Assistant Clinical Professor of Law Robin D. Barnes, B.A., J.D., State University of New York at Buffalo; LL.M., University of Wisconsin; Professor of Law Jon Bauer, A.B., Cornell University; J.D., Yale University; Clinical Professor of Law Loftus E. Becker, Jr., A.B., Harvard College; LL.B., University of Pennsylvania; Professor of Law Bethany Berger, B.A., Wesleyan University; J.D., Yale University; Professor of Law Robert Birmingham, A.B., J.D., Ph.D. (Econ.), Ph.D. (Phil.), University of Pittsburgh; LL.M., Harvard University; Professor of Law William Breetz, B.A., Dartmouth College; LL.B., University of Virginia; Executive Director, Connecticut Urban Legal Initiative, Inc. Sara Bronin, B.A., University of Texas; M.Sc., University of Oxford (Magdalen College); J.D., Yale University; Associate Professor of Law Deborah A. Calloway, B.A., Middlebury College; J.D., Georgetown University; Professor of Law Marcia Canavan, B.A., University of California, Los Angeles; MPH., University of California, Los Angeles; J.D., Golden Gate University School of Law and University of Colorado School of Law; Assistant Clinical Professor of Law Paul Chill, B.A., Wesleyan University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Clinical Professor of Law Anne C. Dailey, B.A., Yale University; J.D., Harvard University; Evangeline Starr Professor of Law and Asssociate Dean for Academic Affairs Steven M. Davidoff, B.A., University of Pennsylvania; M.A., London Business School; J.D., Columbia University; Associate Professor of Law Geoffrey Dellenbaugh, A.B., Princeton University; M.A., Stanford University; Ph.D., University of Pittsburgh; J.D., University of Chicago; Assistant Clinical Professor of Law Timothy H. Everett, B.A., M.A., Clark University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Clinical Professor of Law Todd D. Fernow, B.A., Cornell University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Professor of Law and Director, Clinical Programs Richard Michael Fischl, B.A., University of Illinois; J.D., Harvard University; Professor of Law and Associate Dean for Research and Faculty Development Hillary Greene, B.A., J.D., Yale University; Associate Professor of Law and Director, Intellectual Property Clinic Kaaryn Gustafson, A.B., Harvard University; Ph.D., J.D., University of California, Berkeley; Associate Professor of Law Mark W. Janis, A.B., Princeton University; B.A., M.A., Oxford University; J.D., Harvard University; William F. Starr Professor of Law Richard S. Kay, A.B., Brandeis University; M.A., Yale University; J.D., Harvard University; Wallace Stevens Professor of Law Darcy Kirk, A.B., Vassar College; M.S., M.B.A., Simmons College; J.D., Boston College; Professor of Law and Associate Dean for Library & Technology Peter R. Kochenburger, A.B., Yale University; J.D., Harvard University; Park Associate Clinical Professor and Director of Graduate Programs Lewis S. Kurlantzick, B.A., Wesleyan University; LL.B., Harvard University; Zephaniah Swift Professor of Law Alexandra Lahav, B.A., Brown University; J.D., Harvard University; Professor of Law Leslie C. Levin, B.S.J., Northwestern University; J.D., Columbia University; Professor of Law Diana L. Leyden, B.A., Union College; J.D., University of Connecticut; LL.M., Georgetown University; Associate Clinical Professor of Law and Director, Tax Clinic Peter L. Lindseth, B.A., J.D., Cornell University; M.A., M. Phil, Ph.D, Columbia University; Professor of Law Justin Long, A.B., Harvard University; J.D., University of Pennsylvania; Visiting Assistant Professor of Law Hugh C. Macgill, B.A., Yale University; LL.B., University of Virginia; Oliver Ellsworth Research Professor of Law and Dean Emeritus Neysun Mahboubi, A.B., Princeton University; J.D., Columbia University; Visiting Assistant Professor of Law Jennifer Brown Mailly, B.A., Brown University; J.D., Ohio State University; Assistant Clinical Professor of Law Margaret Martin, B.A., Boston University; J.D., Columbia University; William R. Davis Clinical Teaching Fellow Ruth Mason, B.A., Columbia University; J.D., Harvard University; Associate Professor of Law Patricia A. McCoy, B.A., Oberlin College; J.D., University of California, Berkeley; Director of Insurance Law Center and George J. and Helen M. England Professor of Law Barbara McGrath, B.A., Yale University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Assistant Director, Connecticut Urban Legal Initiative, Inc. Willajeanne F. McLean, B.A., Wellesley College; B.S., University of Massachusetts; J.D., Fordham University; LL.M., Free University of Brussels; Professor of Law Thomas H. Morawetz, A.B., Harvard College; J.D., M.Phil., Ph.D., Yale University; Tapping Reeve Professor of Law and Ethics Lily Neff, B.S.E.E, City College of New York; J.D., Pace University; Assistant Clinical Professor of Law R. Kent Newmyer, B.A., Doane College; Ph.D., University of Nebraska; Professor of Law and History Angel R. Oquendo, A.B., M.A., Ph.D., Harvard University; J.D., Yale University; Olimpiad S. Ioffe Professor of Law Leonard Orland, B.A., Rutgers University; LL.B., University of Pennsylvania; Oliver Ellsworth Research Professor of Law Sachin Pandya, B.A., University of California, Berkeley; M.A., Columbia University; J.D., Yale University; Associate Professor of Law Richard W. Parker, A.B., Princeton University; J.D., Yale University; D.Phil., Oxford University; Professor of Law Jeremy Paul, A.B., Princeton University; J.D., Harvard University; Dean and Thomas F. Gallivan, Jr. Professor of Real Property Law Ellen Ash Peters, B.A., Swarthmore College; LL.B., Yale University; LL.D., Yale University; University of Connecticut; et al.; Visiting Professor of Law Richard D. Pomp, B.S., University of Michigan; J.D., Harvard University; Alva P. Loiselle Professor of Law Jessica S. Rubin, B.S., J.D., Cornell University; Assistant Clinical Professor of Law Susan R. Schmeiser, A.B., Princeton University; J.D., Yale University; Ph.D., Brown University; Professor of Law Peter Siegelman, B.A., Swarthmore College; M.S.L., Ph.D., Yale University; Roger Sherman Professor of Law James H. Stark, A.B., Cornell University; J.D., Columbia University; Professor of Law and Director, Mediation Clinic Martha Stone, B.A., Wheaton College; J.D., LL.M., Georgetown University; Director, Center for Children’s Advocacy Kurt A. Strasser, B.A., J.D., Vanderbilt University; LL.M., J.S.D., Columbia University; Phillip I. Blumberg Professor of Law Colin C. Tait, A.B., Cornell University; LL.B., Yale University; Oliver Ellsworth Research Professor of Law Stephen G. Utz, B.A., Louisiana State University; J.D., University of Texas; Ph.D., Cambridge University; Professor of Law Carol Ann Weisbrod, J.D., Columbia University; Ellen Ash Peters Professor of Law Robert Whitman, B.B.A., City College of New York; J.D., Columbia University; LL.M., New York University; Professor of Law Steven Wilf, B.S., Arizona State University; Ph.D., J.D., Yale University; Professor of Law Richard A. Wilson, BSc., Ph.D., London School of Economics and Political Science; Professor of Law Adjunct Faculty of Law Peter G. Austin, B.S., University of Connecticut; M.S., University of Hartford; Adjunct Professor of Law Morris W. Banks, A.B., Dartmouth College; LL.B., Columbia University; LL.M., New York University; Adjunct Professor of Law Anne Davis Barry, B.S., University of Connecticut; M.S., Union College; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Richard Baxter, B.A., Bucknell University; M.A., Yale University; J.D., Duke University; Lecturer in Law James W. Bergenn, B.A., Catholic University; J.D., Columbia University; Adjunct Professor of Law Hon. David M. Borden, B.A., Amherst College; LL.B., Harvard University; Adjunct Professor of Law John Buchanan, A.B., Princeton, B.A., Oxford; J.D., Harvard; Lecturer in Law Michael A. Cantor, B.S., J.D., University of Connecticut; Adjunct Professor of Law Christine Chabot, B.A., Northwestern University; J.D., Notre Dame Law School; Lecturer in Law James N. Cohen, B.A., J.D., Harvard; Lecturer in Law Gary Collins, B.A., State University of New York, Buffalo; J.D., Vanderbilt University; Lecturer in Law David W. Cooney, B.A., Rutgers University; M.A., Wesleyan University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Dean M. Cordiano, B.A., State University of New York at Binghamton; J.D., Duke University; Lecturer in Law Michelle Cruz, B.A., M.A., Mount Holyoke College; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Renee M. Dailey, B.A., J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law John G. Day, A.B., Oberlin College; J.D., Case Western Reserve University; Professor in Residence Raymond DeMeo, B.A., Williams College; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Mark Dubois, B.A., College of the Holy Cross; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Gerald P. Dwyer, A.B., Colgate University; J.D., Gonzaga University; LL.M., Georgetown University; Lecturer in Law Paul Eddy, B.A., Ohio Wesleyan University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Thomas Farrish, B.A., J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Rebecca Flanagan, B.A., M.A., University of Connecticut; J.D., University of North Carolina; Lecturer in Law Evan D. Flaschen, B.A., Wesleyan University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Adjunct Professor of Law Charles W. Fortune, B.A., University of Rochester; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Michael A. Gailor, B.A., Cornell University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law William Goddard, B.A., M.B.A., Dartmouth; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Ira H. Goldman, B.A., Cornell University; J.D., Yale University; Adjunct Professor of Law Daniel L. Gottfried, B.A., J.D., University of Connecticut, Lecturer in Law Andrew S. Groher, B.A., University of Virginia; J.D., University of Connecticut; Adjunct Professor of Law Albert B. Harper, B.A., University of Texas; J.D., Ph.D., University of Connecticut; Adjunct Professor of Law John Harris, B.S.E., Princeton; J.D., University of Wisconsin; Adjunct Professor of Law Wesley Horton, B.A., Harvard University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Adjunct Professor of Law John Houlihan, B.A., Providence College; J.D., St. John’s University; Lecturer in Law Daniel Klau, B.A., University of California, San Diego; J.D., Boston University; Lecturer in Law Charles H. Klippel, B.A., M.Ed., M.P.H., J.D., Harvard University; Lecturer in Law Barry Kramer, B.Ch.E., Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute; J.D., New York University; Lecturer in Law John H. Lawrence, Jr., B.S., Washington and Lee University; J.D., University of Virginia; Lecturer in Law Henry C. Lee, B.S., John Jay College of Criminal Justice; M.S., Ph.D., New York University; Dr.Sci. (Hon.), University of New Haven; Dr.Hum. (Hon.), St. Joseph College; Adjunct Professor of Law Erik T. Lohr, B.S., Thomas A. Edison State College; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law James Lotstein, B.S., Northwestern University; J.D., University of Connecticut, Lecturer in Law Joseph A. MacDougald, B.A., Brown University; M.B.A., New York University; J.D., University of Connecticut; M.E.M., Yale University; Lecturer in Law Robert G. Madden, B.S.W., Providence College; M.S.S.W., Columbia University School of Social Work; J.D., University of Connecticut, Lecturer in Law Thomas S. Marrion, A.B., College of the Holy Cross; J.D., University of Connecticut; Adjunct Professor of Law James F. Meehan, B.A., University of Arizona; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Dwight Merriam, B.A., University of Massachusetts, M.R.P., University of North Carolina, J.D., Yale University; Lecturer in Law Jamie L. Mills, B.A., Eastern Connecticut State University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Joseph Mirrione, B.A., Marist College; J.D., Vermont Law School; Lecturer in Law Derek L. Mogck, B.A., Gordon College; M.S., University of Massachusetts; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Umar F. Moghul, B.A., M.A., University of Pennsylvania; J.D., Temple University; Lecturer in Law Thomas B. Mooney, B.A., Yale University; J.D., Harvard University; Adjunct Professor of Law Ronald T. Murphy, B.S., Springfield College; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Henry F. Murray, B.A., Yale University; J.D. University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Kevin O’Connor, B.A., University of Notre Dame; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Andrew J. O’Keefe, B.S., College of the Holy Cross; J.D., University of Connecticut; Adjunct Professor of Law Cornelius O’Leary, B.A., Williams College; M.A., Trinity College; J.D., University of Connecticut; Adjunct Professor of Law and Mark A. Weinstein Clinical Teaching Fellow John Pagini, B.A., Central Connecticut State University, M.P.A., University of Hartford; Lecturer in Law Rosemarie Paine, B.S., Southern Connecticut State University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Humbert J. Polito, Jr., A.B., College of the Holy Cross; J.D., University of Connecticut; Adjunct Professor of Law Elliott B. Pollack, A.B., Columbia College; LL.B., Columbia Law School; Lecturer in Law Hon. Elliot D. Prescott, B.A., University of Massachusetts; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Renee C. Redman, B.A., Michigan State University; J.D., Brooklyn Law School; Lecturer in Law Leah Reimer, B.S., J.D., Ph.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Roger Reynolds, B.A., Macalester College; J.D., New York University; Lecturer in Law Barbara Rezner, B.A., Gettysburg College; J.D., Washington and Lee University; Lecturer in Law Louis Ricciuti, B.A., Boston College; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Tracy Rich, B.A., Union College; J.D., New York University School of Law; L.L.M., Boston University School of Law; Lecturer in Law James K. Robertson, Jr., B.A., Yale University; M.A., Hartford Seminary; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Morgan Paul Rueckert, B.A., J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law and Mark A. Weinstein Clinical Teaching Fellow Patrick J. Salve, B.S., J.D., University of Pennsylvania; Adjunct Professor of Law Hon. Michael R. Sheldon, A.B., Princeton University; J.D., Yale University; Adjunct Professor of Law Sandra L. Sherlock-White, B.A., Central Connecticut State College; J.D., Western New England College; Lecturer in Law Jay. E. Sicklick, B.A., Colgate University; J.D., Boston College; Adjunct Professor of Law Douglas Simpson, A.B., Dartmouth College; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law Mark H. Taylor, B.A., Drew University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law James R. Turcotte, B.A., Boston University; J.D., Western New England College; Lecturer in Law Stefan Underhill, B.A., University of Virginia; B.A., Oxford University; J.D., Yale University; Lecturer in Law Arthur Webster, B.A., Bradley University; J.D., Georgetown University; Adjunct Professor of Law William Wilcox, B.A., University of Connecticut; J.D., Suffolk University; Lecturer in Law Michael Wilder, B.A., Yale University; LL.B., Harvard University; Lecturer in Law Paul B. Zolan, B.A., Trinity College, J.D., University of Connecticut; Lecturer in Law CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW VOLUME 42 DECEMBER 2009 NUMBER 2 Article Identifying Government Speech ANDY G. OLREE The U.S. Supreme Court has interpreted the Speech Clause of the First Amendment to mean that when the government distributes money or other resources to private speakers, it generally may not discriminate among speakers based on viewpoint. The government is, however, allowed to express its own viewpoint, even if it enlists the aid of private parties to get the message out, as long as the communication does not violate some separate legal restriction, such as the Establishment Clause. Together, these understandings form the core of what has become known as the “government speech doctrine.” This doctrine signals that distinguishing between government speech and private speech will become crucial in many cases involving either the Speech Clause or the Establishment Clause. While the Court has announced the distinction in general terms and has decided cases based on it—including a notable case this term involving Ten Commandments monuments—the Court has yet to announce a standard by which judges can reliably identify government speech across a range of cases. After examining several attempts by others to formulate such a standard, this Article suggests that the Court has now identified three basic types of government speech. Accordingly, the Article proposes a three-factor test for identifying government speech, demonstrating how the test could function as a unifying explanation of precedent, and a uniform method of resolving future cases. 365 ARTICLE CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION .......................................................................................... 367 II. THE ORIGINS OF THE GOVERNMENT SPEECH DOCTRINE ............. 374 III. THE BINARY APPROACH USING A SINGLE-FACTOR TEST............ 379 IV. THE BINARY APPROACH USING THE FOUR-PRONGED TEST ....... 386 A. THE TENTH CIRCUIT FORMULATES THE FOUR-PRONGED TEST .................. 386 B. THE FOURTH CIRCUIT ADOPTS THE FOUR-PRONGED TEST......................... 388 C. THE NINTH CIRCUIT ADOPTS THE FOUR-PRONGED TEST ........................... 391 D. THE SEVENTH CIRCUIT JOINS IN—OR DOES IT? ........................................ 392 E. THE EIGHTH CIRCUIT APPLIES THE FOUR-PRONGED TEST TO ANSWER “ONE KEY QUESTION” ...................................................... 394 F. DIFFICULTIES WITH THE FOUR-PRONGED TEST .......................................... 395 V. THE “HYBRID” OR “MIXED” SPEECH APPROACH ............................. 400 A. JUDGES WHO HAVE ADVOCATED THE “HYBRID” OR “MIXED” SPEECH APPROACH ............................................................... 401 B. PROFESSOR CORBIN’S “MIXED SPEECH” APPROACH.................................. 405 C. DIFFICULTIES WITH THE “HYBRID” OR “MIXED” SPEECH APPROACH MORE GENERALLY ............................................................. 409 VI. AN ALTERNATIVE APPROACH: THREE KINDS OF GOVERNMENT SPEECH ................................................................... 410 A. THE GOVERNMENT’S OWN INDEPENDENT IDEA ......................................... 411 B. A FORMAT CONTROLLED AND RESERVED BY THE GOVERNMENT .............. 415 C. A CLEAR LITERAL SPEAKER EMPLOYED BY THE GOVERNMENT................. 420 VII. USING THE THREE-PART TEST TO UNDERSTAND PAST AND FUTURE CASES ................................................................... 422 A. EXPLAINING SUPREME COURT PRECEDENTS .............................................. 422 B. FUTURE APPLICATIONS—SPECIALTY LICENSE PLATES .............................. 430 VIII. CONCLUSION......................................................................................... 433 Identifying Government Speech ANDY G. OLREE* I. INTRODUCTION One of the most familiar axioms in all of First Amendment law is the general rule that the government is not allowed to restrict private expression based on viewpoint.1 The axiom applies even when speakers use governmental resources to get their message out. From time to time, the government actually facilitates expression by private persons—for example, by subsidizing a variety of speakers, by offering public land or other property as a forum for those who wish to speak, or by providing people some means of accessing a variety of private information sources and opinions. In these and other similar contexts, government is not allowed to deny access to public property or support on the basis of the speaker’s viewpoint.2 The government may grant access to its aid selectively, but the access criteria must be viewpoint-neutral. However, government itself sometimes wishes to express its own particular viewpoint, and it is generally allowed to do so. Governments often attempt to influence behavior and thought, not only by coercively penalizing certain behaviors or expressions, but by expressing viewpoints designed to affect the social milieu or to persuade people to think and act * Professor of Law, Faulkner University, Thomas Goode Jones School of Law. See Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819, 828 (1995) (“It is axiomatic that the government may not regulate speech based on its substantive content or the message it conveys.” (citing Police Dep’t of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U.S. 92, 96 (1972))). 2 See Good News Club v. Milford Cent. Sch., 533 U.S. 98, 106–07 (2001) (finding that government cannot restrict speech on the basis of viewpoint and that any restriction must be reasonable); Legal Servs. Corp. v. Velazquez, 531 U.S. 533, 541–42 (2001) (finding that a viewpointbased funding restriction was unconstitutional); Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 829–31, 834 (“The government must abstain from regulating speech when the specific motivating ideology or the opinion or perspective of the speaker is the rationale for the restriction.”); Lamb’s Chapel v. Ctr. Moriches Union Free Sch. Dist., 508 U.S. 384, 392–94 (1993) (finding that the government may control access to a nonpublic forum “so long as the distinctions drawn are reasonable in light of the purpose served by the forum and are viewpoint neutral”); Bd. of Educ. v. Pico, 457 U.S. 853, 870–71 (1982) (plurality opinion) (finding that the Board of Education has discretion in determining the content in school libraries, but the “discretion may not be exercised in a narrowly partisan or political manner” such that certain ideas would be suppressed); see also United States v. Am. Library Ass’n, 539 U.S. 194, 236 (2003) (Souter, J., dissenting) (“[I]n extreme cases [one could] expect particular [book acquisition] choices [by public libraries] to reveal impermissible reasons (reasons even the plurality would consider to be illegitimate), like excluding books because their authors are Democrats or their critiques of organized Christianity are unsympathetic.”); Nat’l Endowment for the Arts v. Finley, 524 U.S. 569, 587 (1998) (“[E]ven in the provision of subsidies, the Government may not ‘ai[m] at the suppression of dangerous ideas.’” (second alteration in original) (quoting Regan v. Taxation with Representation of Wash., 461 U.S. 540, 550 (1983))); Perry Educ. Ass’n v. Perry Local Educators’ Ass’n, 460 U.S. 37, 45–46 (1983) (noting that when governmental property functions as any kind of expression forum, whether public or nonpublic, the government may not “suppress expression [in the forum] merely because public officials oppose the speaker’s view”). 1 368 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 3 differently. Government then becomes one of a host of speakers competing in the marketplace of ideas. Our notion of freedom of speech has not demanded that the government abstain from such a role, nor have we required government to endorse all viewpoints equally as it sends its messages.4 In other words, most citizens would likely agree with the courts that the government may send the message “Say no to drugs” without offending the First Amendment and without having to send the alternative message “Say yes to drugs.”5 Viewpoint neutrality is not usually required of the government when it is sending its own messages.6 Hence, when courts examine viewpoint-based restrictions involving governmental property or resources, one distinction makes all the difference—if the speech is the government’s own speech, the viewpoint restrictions are permissible, but if the speech is private speech facilitated by government resources, viewpoint restrictions are generally impermissible. Classifying the speech as either government speech or private speech becomes a crucial question—often the crucial question—in deciding these speech cases. When claims involve the Establishment Clause rather than the Speech Clause, identifying government speech is often just as crucial, although the effects of the identification are reversed. In this sort of claim, someone has alleged that the government’s message constitutes governmental support of, or opposition to, religion, in violation of the Establishment Clause. Although private parties may send their own messages approving or disapproving of religion, the Supreme Court sometimes interprets the Establishment Clause to forbid the government from doing so.7 So if the 3 See MARK G. YUDOF, WHEN GOVERNMENT SPEAKS: POLITICS, LAW, AND GOVERNMENT EXPRESSION IN AMERICA 5–10, 13–15 (1983) (discussing the “government’s increasing influence on and involvement in communications networks”); Randall P. Bezanson & William G. Buss, The Many Faces of Government Speech, 86 IOWA L. REV. 1377, 1380–81, 1384–87 (2001) (identifying the capacities in which government speaks); Gia B. Lee, Persuasion, Transparency, and Government Speech, 56 HASTINGS L.J. 983, 983–84, 986–87, 992 (2005) (arguing for greater transparency when government is promoting a particular message). 4 See Johanns v. Livestock Mktg. Ass’n, 544 U.S. 550, 553, 559–61 (2005) (holding that a federal program that finances advertising to promote an agricultural product is government speech); Velazquez, 531 U.S. at 541 (“[V]iewpoint-based funding decisions can be sustained in instances in which the government is itself the speaker . . . .”); Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 833 (“[W]hen the government appropriates public funds to promote a particular policy of its own it is entitled to say what it wishes.”); Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U.S. 173, 194 (1991) (noting that the government did not “discriminate[] on the basis of viewpoint when it [chose] to fund a program dedicated to advanc[ing] certain [] goals”). 5 See DKT Int’l, Inc. v. U.S. Agency for Int’l Dev., 477 F.3d 758, 761 (D.C. Cir. 2007) (“In sponsoring Nancy Reagan’s ‘Just Say No’ anti-drug campaign, the First Amendment did not require the government to sponsor simultaneously a ‘Just Say Yes’ campaign.”). 6 Governmental messages regarding religion may be an exception to this rule, at least sometimes. See infra note 7 and accompanying text. 7 See, e.g., McCreary County v. ACLU of Ky., 545 U.S. 844, 860 (2005) (“By showing a purpose to favor religion, the government ‘sends [an impermissible] message to . . . nonadherents’” (quoting Santa Fe Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Doe, 530 U.S. 290, 309–10 (2000))); Santa Fe Indep. Sch. Dist., 530 U.S. at 302 (“[T]here is a crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 369 message constitutes government speech rather than private speech, the government may be violating the Establishment Clause. Identifying government speech becomes more difficult as governments become more and more involved in facilitating private speech, on the one hand, and in sending their own messages, on the other. When a private speaker uses governmental property or support as she sends her message, who is really speaking? How can we tell? The higher the level of governmental support and involvement, the more the speech looks like the government’s own speech, particularly because governments now send so many messages of their own, and because this government may have made some affirmative decision to permit this particular speaker to use governmental resources, a decision similar in many respects to the decision to speak. But private speech does not become government speech simply because the government allows the speaker to use governmental resources to get the message out.8 Judges must distinguish the government’s own messages from those of others, particularly in the contexts of Speech Clause claims, in which a finding of government speech is a point in the government’s favor, and Establishment Clause claims, in which a finding of government speech is a strike against the government. A uniform test for identifying government speech in these various contexts seems desirable, but lower courts are struggling mightily to come up with one. A salient example is the set of cases dealing with specialty license plate programs,9 in which, for an additional fee, a state allows motorists obtaining license plates to choose from a menu of unique designs Typically, private in lieu of the state’s standard plate design.10 Exercise Clauses protect.” (citing Bd. of Educ. v. Mergens, 496 U.S. 226, 250 (1990))); County of Allegheny v. ACLU, 492 U.S. 573, 600–01 (1989) (holding that the Establishment Clause prohibited a county’s display of a crèche because by permitting the display under the circumstances, “the county sends an unmistakable message that it supports and promotes the Christian praise to God that is the creche’s religious message”). 8 See supra note 2 and accompanying text for examples of courts not allowing the government to deny access to public property or support on the basis of the speaker’s viewpoint. 9 See Roach v. Stouffer, 560 F.3d 860, 862, 869–70 (8th Cir. 2009) (holding that Missouri’s specialty license plate program violated the First Amendment); Choose Life Ill., Inc. v. White, 547 F.3d 853, 863 (7th Cir. 2008) (holding that messages on specialty license plates do not constitute government speech); Ariz. Life Coal. Inc. v. Stanton, 515 F.3d 956, 965–66 (9th Cir. 2008) (holding that messages conveyed through specialty license plates primarily represent private speech), cert. denied, 129 S. Ct. 56 (2008); ACLU of Tenn. v. Bredesen, 441 F.3d 370, 376–77 (6th Cir. 2006) (holding that specialty license plates represent government speech for the purposes of the Free Speech Clause); Henderson v. Stalder, 407 F.3d 351, 352 (5th Cir. 2005) (finding that the court did not have jurisdiction over a suit over a specialty license plate program that diverted excess charges to organizations endorsed by the legislature); Planned Parenthood of S.C., Inc. v. Rose, 361 F.3d 786, 794 (4th Cir. 2004) (holding that specialty license plates were neither purely government speech nor purely private speech); Women’s Emergency Network v. Bush, 323 F.3d 937, 943–45 (11th Cir. 2003) (holding that individual residents did not have taxpayer standing to challenge Florida’s specialty license plate program under the Establishment Clause). 10 For a discussion of various states’ specialty license plate programs, their general features, and some differences between them, see Leslie Gielow Jacobs, Free Speech and the Limits of Legislative Discretion: The Example of Specialty License Plates, 53 FLA. L. REV. 419, 424–41 (2001); Amy Riley 370 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 organizations must apply in advance to the state for permission to add their own design to the menu of options. Many states have approved a lengthy menu of choices, but occasionally a state will deny a particular application because of the viewpoint represented by the applicant group or its proposed plate design.11 If the approved specialty plate designs are viewed as government speech, a viewpoint-based denial can be upheld as a governmental decision not to speak; but if the designs are viewed as private speech using government property, any viewpoint-based denial is presumptively unconstitutional, even though the plates are owned and issued by the government. These cases have been giving federal courts fits over the past decade. Two circuits have refused to decide such cases on the constitutional merits,12 but the circuits that have addressed the First Amendment arguments have employed widely varying analyses. One circuit has viewed specialty plates as purely government speech;13 at least two have viewed the plates as private speech;14 one has viewed the plates Lucas, Comment, Specialty License Plates: The First Amendment and the Intersection of Government Speech and Public Forum Doctrines, 55 UCLA L. REV. 1971, 2007–09, 2011–13, 2017 (2008). 11 There is some dispute in some of these cases as to whether the state’s denial was driven by an intent to exclude a particular viewpoint or an entire subject matter. If (as the Seventh Circuit has recently concluded with respect to Illinois’s specialty plate program) the state’s denial is truly the product of a reasonable desire to exclude from specialty plates all points of view related to a particular subject matter, the denial might be construed as viewpoint-neutral and is somewhat more defensible, even if the plates are not deemed to be government speech. Compare Choose Life, 547 F.3d at 865–67 (concluding that Illinois’s denial of an application for a “Choose Life” license plate was founded in a viewpoint-neutral state policy of refusing to issue plates for all groups expressing opinions on the subject matter of abortion), with Arizona Life Coal., 515 F.3d at 971–72 (concluding that Arizona’s denial of an application for a “Choose Life” license plate was founded in a state policy of refusing to issue plates for groups weighing in on the issue of abortion because it was so controversial, but that this fact demonstrated the state’s viewpoint discrimination, since the state’s statutes did not exclude controversial messages in general or the subject of abortion in particular, and the denial was based on the divisiveness of the proffered viewpoint). This Article, however, focuses on situations in which viewpoint discrimination is present or assumed. See, e.g., Sons of Confederate Veterans, Inc. v. Comm’r of the Va. Dep’t of Motor Vehicles, 288 F.3d 610, 623–26 (4th Cir. 2002) (finding viewpoint discrimination where the state disapproved an organization’s proposed specialty plate design containing a Confederate flag because of the viewpoint represented by the flag). In such cases, the crucial judicial task usually will be to distinguish government speech from private speech. In other words, courts must determine whether the viewpoint discrimination represents the government’s attempt to control its own message or instead to disadvantage a disfavored private viewpoint. 12 The Eleventh Circuit has dismissed a specialty plate complaint for lack of standing. See Women’s Emergency Network, 323 F.3d at 940. And the Fifth Circuit has held that the specialty plate fee is a tax and that therefore the federal Tax Injunction Act forbids federal court jurisdiction over specialty plate complaints. See Henderson, 407 F.3d at 352. 13 See Bredesen, 441 F.3d at 375–76 (Sixth Circuit) (holding that a “Choose Life” specialty license plate was government speech because the state had “final approval authority over every word used”). 14 See Roach, 560 F.3d at 868 (Eighth Circuit) (finding that “under all the circumstances a reasonable and fully informed observer would recognize the message on the ‘Choose Life’ specialty plate as the message of a private party, not the state”); Arizona Life Coal., 515 F.3d at 968 (Ninth Circuit) (finding that specialty plates are private speech because the state did not “bear[] ultimate responsibility for the content of the speech”); see also Sons of Confederate Veterans, 288 F.3d at 621– 22 (Fourth Circuit) (finding, in a case decided two years before Rose, that specialty plates constituted private speech); infra note 17 and accompanying text (noting that the Seventh Circuit has rejected the 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 371 as a hybrid of both governmental and private speech, requiring the court to impose a sort of intermediate scrutiny in evaluating viewpoint-based denials of specialty plate applications;15 and one, claiming that “privatespeech rights are implicated” by the plates and denying that the plates are government speech,16 has applied conventional forum analysis to the plates—as if they are private speech—without saying whether they constitute private speech or some form of hybrid speech.17 A clarification of the government speech doctrine would surely aid in the uniform resolution of such cases. On the Establishment Clause side, the identification of government speech can prove just as troublesome. For example, the circuit courts have often been asked to identify government speech in cases involving inanimate displays in city parks. One familiar bone of contention is the nativity scene or crèche erected on public property during the Christmas season.18 If a nativity scene is displayed on public property under circumstances suggesting that the government itself was “send[ing] an unmistakable message” endorsing Christianity, the display is forbidden by the Establishment Clause.19 But if such displays are donated or loaned to the government by private organizations, could they be viewed as private speech and thus immunized from Establishment Clause challenges?20 Ten Commandments monuments, often donated to state or local government by a private religious or charitable group, represent another familiar type of inanimate display. Some circuit courts have struck down such displays as violations of the Establishment Clause.21 The U.S. contention that specialty plates were government speech and analyzed them using conventional forum analysis as if they constituted private speech, but refused to say whether they constituted private speech or hybrid speech). 15 At least two of the judges on the Fourth Circuit’s three-judge panel in Rose reached this conclusion in separate opinions, although there was no opinion for the court. See Planned Parenthood of S.C., Inc. v. Rose, 361 F.3d 786, 794–95 (4th Cir. 2004); id. at 800 (Luttig, J., concurring in judgment); see also id. at 801 (Gregory, J., concurring in judgment) (suggesting that specialty plate programs “have elements of both private and government speech”). 16 Choose Life, 547 F.3d at 864 (Seventh Circuit). 17 Id. at 864–67. 18 See, e.g., Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668, 671 (1984). 19 See County of Allegheny v. ACLU, 492 U.S. 573, 600 (1989); cf. id. at 601 (“[B]y prohibiting government endorsement of religion, the Establishment Clause prohibits . . . the government’s lending its support to the communication of a religious organization’s religious message.”). 20 One circuit has suggested that donated permanent displays in city parks constitute private speech in a public forum. See Summum v. Pleasant Grove City, 483 F.3d 1044, 1047 n.2, 1050–52 (10th Cir. 2007), rev’d, 129 S. Ct. 1125, 1132–34 (2009) (holding that the placement of a permanent monument in a public park is a form of government speech); Summum v. City of Ogden, 297 F.3d 995, 1002, 1004–06 (10th Cir. 2002) (holding that permanent monuments were a nonpublic forum because property was “not by tradition or designation a forum for public communication” (quotations omitted)). 21 See, e.g., Adland v. Russ, 307 F.3d 471, 481–82, 490 (6th Cir. 2002) (holding that the Commonwealth, by displaying a Ten Commandments monument, “emphasize[d] a single religious influence to the exclusion of all other religious and secular influences” in violation of the Establishment Clause); Books v. City of Elkhart, 235 F.3d 292, 307–08 (7th Cir. 2000) (holding that a Ten Commandments monument on city property improperly advanced or endorsed religion in violation of 372 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 Supreme Court and some other circuits have held that governmental display of such monuments is sometimes permissible, but the opinions were not grounded in any assumption that the monuments constituted private speech rather than government speech.22 Yet the Tenth Circuit held in 2002 that donated monuments of this sort do constitute private speech.23 Reasoning from that precedent, a competing religious group later convinced the circuit that a city displaying a donated Ten Commandments monument in the city’s park is operating a traditional public forum for private speech and must therefore also accept and display the group’s own unique donation to the city: a monument to the Seven Aphorisms of Summum.24 Recently, the U.S. Supreme Court reversed the Tenth Circuit’s decision, unanimously holding that donated Ten Commandments monuments constitute government speech.25 While clarifying the law with respect to certain monuments, however, the Court did not venture a method for identifying government speech in other circumstances.26 Lower courts are increasingly required to identify government speech in a wide variety of free speech and religious establishment cases, and the circuits are reaching a wide variety of conclusions about how this ought to be done. The confusion has led some commentators to suggest that the two-category approach itself is the problem. Following the lead of the Fourth Circuit in its most recent specialty plates case, commentators are increasingly calling for an end to the rigidly binary government speech/private speech distinction, claiming that much speech falls somewhere in between and arguing for the creation of a third category of the Establishment Clause); see also Staley v. Harris County, 461 F.3d 504, 514–15 (5th Cir. 2006) (holding that a county monument commemorating a local citizen and located on courthouse grounds violated the Establishment Clause because it contained an open Bible and had been recently refurbished for the purpose of calling attention to the Bible), vacated en banc as moot and unripe, 485 F.3d 305 (5th Cir. 2007), cert. denied, 128 S. Ct. 647 (2007); Glassroth v. Moore, 335 F.3d 1282, 1284 (11th Cir. 2003) (holding that the Establishment Clause was violated when the chief justice of the state supreme court erected a Ten Commandments monument, built with private funds, in a state judicial building). 22 See Van Orden v. Perry, 545 U.S. 677, 691–92 (2005) (ruling that the display of a Ten Commandments monument on the grounds of the state capitol did not violate the Establishment Clause); Card v. City of Everett, 520 F.3d 1009, 1020–21 (9th Cir. 2008) (holding that a city’s display of a Ten Commandments monument was permissible because, inter alia, “nothing apart from the monument’s text suggests a religious motive on the City’s part”); ACLU Neb. Found. v. City of Plattsmouth, 419 F.3d 772, 776–78 (8th Cir. 2005) (holding that the city’s display of a Ten Commandments monument did not violate the Establishment Clause because the monument made passive use of the Commandments “to acknowledge the role of religion in our Nation’s heritage”). 23 City of Ogden, 297 F.3d at 1004–06. 24 Pleasant Grove City, 483 F.3d at 1047, 1050–55. 25 Pleasant Grove City v. Summum, 129 S. Ct. 1125, 1129 (2009); id. at 1141 (Souter, J., concurring in judgment). See infra notes 299–306 and accompanying text for further discussion of Pleasant Grove and the Supreme Court’s holding that the government speaks when it accepts, embraces, and communicates a donated message. 26 See Pleasant Grove City, 129 S. Ct. at 1132 (“There may be situations in which it is difficult to tell whether a government entity is speaking on its own behalf or is providing a forum for private speech, but this case does not present such a situation.”). 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 373 “hybrid” or “mixed” speech, restrictions on which would qualify for some medium degree of scrutiny or an ad hoc balancing of the competing interests involved.27 The hybrid approach is alluring, but in this Article, I will argue that it leads to inconsistent results and that it may insufficiently protect free speech rights; furthermore, I will argue, the hybrid approach is in tension with the whole notion of government speech as developed by the Supreme Court. I will also argue that, while the traditional binary approach is preferable, the tests developed by some circuits to categorize speech within that binary framework are flawed and likewise misstate the law. I believe Supreme Court precedents can be distilled into the notion that government speech arises in one of three basic ways. I will propose this three-factor test as a preferable method of consistently identifying government speech in both expression cases and establishment cases. I do not argue that the Court has formally or intentionally embraced this test—only that the test provides a useful way of understanding what the Court has done and predicting what it will do. My purpose is thus to explain the results in a variety of the Court’s speech and establishment cases, and also, secondarily, to provide a few reasons why the Court’s approach, understood in this way, might be preferable to alternatives.28 Part II briefly describes the development of the government speech doctrine by the Supreme Court. Part III discusses one approach used by the Sixth Circuit to identify government speech, an approach that in effect considers a single factor to be determinative. Part IV analyzes a fourpronged test for identifying government speech which has been more commonly used by various circuits. Part V discusses the proposal by a few judges and recent commentators that courts should recognize a third “hybrid” or “mixed” category of speech. Part VI suggests an alternative approach which I believe explains and reconciles the key Supreme Court precedents while also providing a more complete and consistent protection of private speech. Finally, Part VII suggests ways in which this approach might be used in understanding Supreme Court precedents and resolving some current legal controversies in both free speech and establishment contexts. 27 For the most extended recent discussion, see Caroline Mala Corbin, Mixed Speech: When Speech Is Both Private and Governmental, 83 N.Y.U. L. REV. 605, 675–77 (2008). Other recent commentators have also suggested or assumed this approach, albeit without extended consideration of alternatives. See, e.g., Lucas, supra note 10, at 2013, 2022; Helen Norton, The Measure of Government Speech: Identifying Expression’s Source, 88 B.U. L. REV. 587, 620–21 (2008). 28 My primary purpose is descriptive. While I do provide a very limited defense of the Court’s approach—partly in the form of a critique of existing alternatives—a fuller normative evaluation must await another article. I likewise save for another day the development of a unifying theory that might explain why the Court sees government speech in each of these three particular situations and not others. 374 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 II. THE ORIGINS OF THE GOVERNMENT SPEECH DOCTRINE According to accepted wisdom, the government speech doctrine, as articulated by the U.S. Supreme Court, had its genesis in Rust v. Sullivan.29 In Rust, federal law prohibited the distribution of certain federal “family planning project[]” funds to entities that provided abortion counseling or referrals, or which otherwise encouraged abortion.30 The Court rejected the claim that the government had selectively withheld funds from a handful of private speakers due to its disfavor of their viewpoint; instead, the Court upheld the program as a permissible decision by the federal government about how it would design its own programs and spend its own money.31 “‘[A] legislature’s decision not to subsidize the exercise of a fundamental right,’” said the Court, “‘does not infringe the right.’”32 The Court saw the funding limitation as a decision about how to use limited subsidy resources—not as discrimination against a disfavored viewpoint, but as the inevitable result of defining the scope and limits of a governmental spending program.33 The Court itself seems to have accepted the common view that the government speech doctrine originated in its opinion in Rust. Ten years after Rust, the Court described the case’s implications as follows: The Court in Rust did not place explicit reliance on the rationale that the counseling activities of the doctors . . . amounted to governmental speech; when interpreting the holding in later cases, however, we have explained Rust on this understanding. We have said that viewpoint-based funding decisions can be sustained in instances in which the government is itself the speaker . . . or instances, like Rust, in which the government “used private speakers to transmit specific information pertaining to its own program.”34 Lower courts have widely adopted this understanding of Rust as a leading case on the government speech doctrine—or at least have noted that the Court has done so.35 According to this accepted wisdom, the government prevailed in Rust because the funded speech at issue, although conveyed by private parties, 29 500 U.S. 173 (1991). Id. at 178–80. 31 Id. at 193–94. 32 Id. at 193 (quoting Regan v. Taxation With Representation, 461 U.S. 540, 549 (1983)). 33 Id. at 194–95. 34 Legal Servs. Corp. v. Velazquez, 531 U.S. 533, 541 (2001) (quoting Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819, 833 (1995)). 35 E.g., Sons of Confederate Veterans, Inc. v. Comm’r of the Va. Dep’t of Motor Vehicles, 288 F.3d 610, 617–18 (4th Cir. 2002); Wells v. City & County of Denver, 257 F.3d 1132, 1140 (10th Cir. 2001); see also ACLU of Tenn. v. Bredesen, 441 F.3d 370, 378 (6th Cir. 2006) (referring to the Supreme Court’s holding in Rust as authority when deciding a government speech doctrine case). 30 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 375 was government speech rather than private speech. The funding rules were part of a larger governmental program to encourage or discourage some private activity—in Rust, a program to discourage abortion and to encourage family planning using alternative methods. The funds were allocated so as to ensure that private speakers would “transmit specific information”—the government’s message—in support of the governmental program.36 The “family planning without abortion” message was the government’s own message, crafted in advance by the government, and the funds at issue were part of a program designed to promote that kind of family planning rather than speech in general;37 therefore, the government was not required to fund messages by private speakers expressing other viewpoints, conveying other information, or offering other services. The viewpoint restriction could stand. The government speech doctrine clearly continues in full strength. In a pair of subsequent cases alleging compelled speech by means of a forced subsidy,38 the Court signaled that the presence of government speech would be determinative.39 These cases involved the claim that the government had compelled the claimants to pay fees or taxes which were used in part to fund messages with which the claimants disagreed. In one of the cases, public university students were forced to pay a student activity fee, a portion of which was later distributed to student groups conveying messages that certain students found objectionable.40 The objecting students claimed they were being compelled to speak, in violation of their First Amendment rights.41 Although the messages were deemed private speech, the Court upheld the program to the extent that the government’s criteria for distribution were viewpoint-neutral;42 the Court noted in dicta, however, that if the objectionable messages had constituted government speech, viewpoint neutrality in the distribution might not be required because the government is allowed to tax even dissenting parties to pay for its own speech.43 In the other case, decided only four years ago, the Court turned this dictum into law, upholding the disputed tax precisely because the Court 36 Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 833. See Rust, 500 U.S. at 178–79 (stating that Congress passed Title X to ensure that funds would only be used for preventive family planning and not for abortion). 38 Johanns v. Livestock Mktg. Ass’n, 544 U.S. 550, 555–56 (2005); Bd. of Regents of Univ. of Wis. Sys. v. Southworth, 529 U.S. 217, 221 (2000). 39 A line of compelled speech precedents holds that the First Amendment Speech Clause forbids the government under some circumstances to force private parties to pay a subsidy to support the speech of other private parties with whom the payer disagrees. E.g., United States v. United Foods, Inc., 533 U.S. 405, 410 (2001); Keller v. State Bar of Cal., 496 U.S. 1, 14 (1990); Abood v. Detroit Bd. of Educ., 431 U.S. 209, 233–35 (1977). 40 Southworth, 529 U.S. at 222–27. 41 Id. at 226–27. 42 Id. at 233–34. 43 Id. at 229. 37 376 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 found the funded messages, conveyed by private parties, to be government speech.44 The federal government had taxed sales and imports of cattle to fund “beef-related projects” such as “promotion and research.”45 A substantial amount of the money was used to fund beef advertising, including ads containing the familiar slogan “Beef. It’s What’s for Dinner.”46 Some beef producers did not like the ads and complained that the tax effectively compelled them to speak against their will, in violation of the First Amendment.47 The Court upheld the tax, however, on the ground that the ads at issue constituted government speech.48 The Court was able to reach this conclusion because: The message set out in the beef promotions is from beginning to end the message established by the Federal Government. . . . Congress and the Secretary [of Agriculture] have set out the overarching message and some of its elements, and they have left the development of the remaining details to an entity whose members are answerable to the Secretary . . . . Moreover . . . the Secretary exercises final approval authority over every word used in every promotional campaign.49 Importantly, the Court said that the finding of government speech would be the same even if a reasonable viewer would not attribute the message to the government.50 Meanwhile, in other cases where the government used viewpoint as a criterion for allocating funds, the Court struck down the funding program when it found that the funded messages constituted private speech rather than government speech. In Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of University of Virginia,51 a public university required the payment of a student activity fee which was collected in a fund and distributed to student groups conveying various messages.52 The Court struck down the program upon finding that the government’s criteria for distributing the funds were not viewpoint-neutral and that the messages themselves constituted private speech.53 The Court distinguished Rust—which had also involved criteria that were not viewpoint-neutral—by noting that in Rust, the funded 44 Johanns v. Livestock Mktg. Ass’n, 544 U.S. 550, 553, 560–64 (2005). Id. at 554. 46 Id. 47 Id. at 555–56. 48 Id. at 553, 560–64. 49 Id. at 560–61. 50 Id. at 564 n.7. 51 515 U.S. 819 (1995). 52 Id. at 823–25. 53 Id. at 833–35. 45 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 377 messages constituted government speech because “the government did not create a program to encourage private speech but instead used private speakers to transmit specific information pertaining to its own program.”54 A few years later the Court extended this reasoning in a case involving federal funding for legal services.55 Federal laws authorized funding for private organizations providing free legal assistance to indigent clients in certain kinds of cases, but denied such funding if the organization made “an effort to amend or otherwise challenge existing welfare law.”56 The Court struck down the funding limitation, finding that this restriction operated as a denial of funding based on the expressed viewpoint of wouldbe recipients.57 The government argued that its funding program was a program of government speech indistinguishable from the one upheld in Rust, but the Court found that the program had more in common with the funding program struck down in Rosenberger: [T]he salient point is that, like the program in Rosenberger, [this] program was designed to facilitate private speech, not to promote a governmental message. . . . The advice from the attorney to the client and the advocacy by the attorney to the courts cannot be classified as governmental speech even under a generous understanding of the concept.58 The Court refused to find that the legal services funding program had created any kind of forum for private expression,59 but this did not change the outcome. The funding restriction was not a governmental decision about what message it wanted to pay others to send on its behalf, but rather a decision to suppress a disfavored message originating with private speakers: [I]n the context of this statute there is no programmatic message of the kind recognized in Rust and which sufficed there to allow the Government to specify the advice deemed necessary for its legitimate objectives. This serves to distinguish [the statute here] from any of the Title X program restrictions upheld in Rust . . . .60 Thus, the Court in this line of Speech Clause cases has provided some 54 Id. at 833. Legal Servs. Corp. v. Velazquez, 531 U.S. 533, 547–48 (2001). 56 Id. at 536–37. 57 Id. at 547–49. 58 Id. at 542–43. 59 See id. at 544 (“As this suit involves a subsidy, limited forum cases . . . may not be controlling in a strict sense . . . .”); id. at 542 (“[T]he LSC program differs from the program at issue in Rosenberger in that its purpose is not to ‘encourage a diversity of views’ . . . .” (quoting Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 834)). 60 Id. at 548. 55 378 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 guidance about how to identify government speech. But the guidance has not often been explicitly applied in other contexts, such as Establishment Clause claims, in which the Court needed to distinguish between government speech and private speech. When members of the local clergy deliver prayers at public school graduation exercises,61 when a private nonprofit group donates a Ten Commandments monument to a state which then displays the monument on the grounds of the state capitol,62 when a student delivers prayers over a loudspeaker to begin each home game of a public high school’s football season63—in these and other scenarios evoking Establishment Clause claims, the Court has been called to decide whether a particular religious message is government speech or private speech. For the most part, the Court has not set forth unique rules for identifying government speech in all Establishment Clause cases, nor has it often referenced the government speech doctrine emanating from Rust and the other Speech Clause cases. Instead, the approach has been less unified and intentional. The Court has addressed the issue using fluctuating descriptors as it evaluated the unique circumstances of each case: from time to time the Court has expressed concern over the “degree of school [or governmental] involvement” in the message,64 the degree of governmental “endorsement” of the message,65 the degree of governmental “entanglement” in the message,66 the degree to which the government is “lending its support to the communication of a religious organization’s religious message,”67 and/or the degree to which a “reasonable observer” would attribute the message to the government.68 61 Lee v. Weisman, 505 U.S. 577, 580 (1992). Van Orden v. Perry, 545 U.S. 677, 682 (2005). Santa Fe Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Doe, 530 U.S. 290, 294 (2000). 64 Id. at 305 (quoting Lee, 505 U.S. at 590). 65 See Santa Fe, 530 U.S. at 305, 307–08, 315–16 (analyzing the specific facts of the case and holding that the school district’s policy involves both perceived and actual endorsement of student prayer); County of Allegheny v. ACLU, 492 U.S. 573, 592–94 (1989) (citing cases involving governmental “endorsement” of religion and how the Establishment Clause prohibits government from appearing to take a position on religious issues). 66 See Santa Fe, 530 U.S. at 305–06 (noting that petitioner school district “attempted to disentangle itself from the religious messages by developing the two-step student election process”); Agostini v. Felton, 521 U.S. 203, 232–34 (1997) (examining whether New York City’s Title I program resulted in an excessive entanglement between church and state). 67 County of Allegheny, 492 U.S. at 601. 68 See, e.g., McCreary County v. ACLU, 545 U.S. 844, 866 (2005) (quoting Capitol Square Review & Advisory Bd. v. Pinette, 515 U.S. 753, 780 (1995) (O’Connor, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment); Santa Fe, 530 U.S. at 315 (noting that “reasonable observers have reasonable memories” which will cause observers to note the context in which the policy arose); id. at 308 (finding that a pregame prayer would “unquestionably” be perceived as “stamped with [the] school’s seal of approval”); see also County of Allegheny, 492 U.S. at 593–94 (O’Connor, J., concurring) (“The Establishment Clause, at the very least, prohibits government from appearing to take a position on questions of religious belief . . . .” (emphasis added) (quoting Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668, 687 (1983))). But see Pinette, 515 U.S. at 765–68 (rejecting the contention that the Establishment Clause is violated whenever a reasonable observer might mistake private religious speech for the government’s own speech). 62 63 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 379 Nevertheless, in freedom of speech cases, lower courts have accepted the Rust-inspired government speech doctrine and seem to be aware that when the government has a message to send, such a message need not be viewpoint-neutral, and other messages need not receive governmental support. The difficulty has come in recognizing when the message is the government’s message. Accepting (and sometimes expanding) the limited guidance of the Supreme Court regarding the government speech doctrine, lower courts and commentators have advocated varying approaches for identifying government speech. Some of these approaches, which this Article labels “binary approaches,” more closely track the teaching of the Supreme Court’s Speech Clause cases by assuming that any particular message must be either government speech or private speech; they then proceed to classify it as one or the other. Other approaches, however, find this binary classification system unnecessarily restrictive and unrealistic; they allow for a third category of “hybrid” or “mixed” speech—unrecognized thus far by the Supreme Court—which carries its own unique implications for judging the powers and duties of government. The binary approaches, in turn, differ from one another on the question of which factors to consider in classifying a message as governmental speech. III. THE BINARY APPROACH USING A SINGLE-FACTOR TEST Like most federal appellate courts that have addressed the issue, the Sixth Circuit has adopted a binary approach to classifying speech: a message may constitute either government speech or private speech, but not both.69 In one recent case, however, the Sixth Circuit parted ways with most of these other courts when it held that a message constitutes government speech whenever “the government determines an overarching message and retains power to approve every word disseminated at its behest.”70 While this standard might at first appear to encompass two distinct factors—whether “the government determines an overarching message” and whether the government “retains power to approve every word disseminated at its behest”71—the Sixth Circuit largely ignored the first of those factors, effectively reducing the test for government speech to 69 When invited to recognize a third category of “mixed speech” in a specialty license plate case, as the Fourth Circuit had previously done, the Sixth Circuit refused to do so. See ACLU of Tenn. v. Bredesen, 441 F.3d 370, 376, 380 (6th Cir. 2006). 70 Id. at 375 (citing Johanns v. Livestock Mktg. Ass’n, 544 U.S. 550, 559–67 (2005)). It is currently somewhat unclear whether the Sixth Circuit views this test as controlling in every case. See Grosjean v. Bommarito, 302 F. App’x 430, 436 (6th Cir. 2008) (favorably citing Bredesen’s test, but noting that “the two factors identified in [the Supreme Court case upon which Bredesen relied] were not . . . held to be exhaustive,” and suggesting in dicta that another relevant factor might be “whether the speech is attributed to a particular private actor”). 71 Bredesen, 441 F.3d at 375 (citing Johanns, 544 U.S. at 559–67). 380 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 a question of how much power the government had to approve or veto the wording and design of the message before it was disseminated. The case before the court, ACLU of Tennessee v. Bredesen,72 involved specialty license plates.73 The state of Tennessee had authorized its Department of Safety to issue specialty plates to motorists willing to pay a surcharge, and the menu of available plates was continually expanding; the general rules were that the Department could make a new specialty plate available whenever (1) the legislature authorized the particular plate by name;74 (2) the state commissioner of revenue approved a design for that plate submitted by a private sponsor;75 and (3) the state received at least one thousand advance orders for that plate.76 In routine practice, apparently, when a private organization desired a specialty plate of its own, the organization lobbied the state legislature to introduce and pass a bill authorizing the plate.77 By the time of the litigation, the state legislature had authorized over one hundred different specialty plates, including a “Choose Life” plate,78 but had rejected a bill, for which Planned Parenthood lobbied, that would have authorized a “Pro-Choice” plate.79 Recognizing that the key question in the case was whether the “Choose Life” message constituted government speech, the Sixth Circuit held that the recent Supreme Court opinion in Johanns80 had established a new standard for identifying government speech, and that this standard was controlling. “Johanns stands for the proposition,” said the court, “that when the government determines an overarching message and retains power to approve every word disseminated at its behest, the message must 72 441 F.3d 370 (6th Cir. 2006). For a brief description of specialty license plates and the legal issues involved, see supra notes 9–17 and accompanying text. 74 In general, each plate was required to be explicitly listed in a state statute, which of course required that the legislature approve each particular plate; however, the legislature was only approving them in concept (such as “Choose Life plates,” “NASCAR plates,” “Mothers Against Methamphetamine (MAMA) plates,” etc.), usually leaving the particular design to be worked out between the private sponsoring organization and the state commissioner of revenue, who was granted veto power over the design. See TENN. CODE. ANN. § 55-4-201 (2009) (outlining requirements of cultural, specialty earmarked, and new specialty earmarked license plates); id. § 55-4-202 (providing examples of specialty earmarked license plates); id. § 55-4-210 (“The department is authorized to administratively issue personalized plates to qualified applicants.”); id. §§ 55-4-305 to 307 (providing legislative authority for “Choose Life plates,” “NASCAR plates,” and “Mothers Against Menthamphetamine (MAMA) plates”); Bredesen, 441 F.3d at 372 (noting that Tennessee law allows special logotypes on license plates and that the Tennessee legislature authorized the “Choose Life” logotype); Bredesen, 354 F. Supp. 2d at 772 (discussing Tennessee law to issue specialty plates). 75 TENN. CODE ANN. § 55-4-201(b)(4) (2009); Bredesen, 354 F. Supp. 2d at 772. 76 TENN. CODE ANN. § 55-4-201(h)(1) (2009); Bredesen, 441 F.3d at 372. 77 See Bredesen, 354 F. Supp. 2d at 773 n.4 (“[P]articipants in the license plate scheme . . . . must find legislators willing to sponsor a bill.” (quoting Henderson v. Stalder, 265 F. Supp. 2d 699, 717 (E.D. La. 2003))); Bredesen, 441 F.3d at 372 (noting that Planned Parenthood unsuccessfully “lobbied for an amendment authorizing a ‘Pro-Choice’ specialty license plate”). 78 Bredesen, 441 F.3d at 372, 376. 79 Id. at 372; Bredesen, 354 F. Supp. 2d at 772. 80 See supra notes 44–50 and accompanying text. 73 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 381 81 be attributed to the government for First Amendment purposes.” After a rather conclusory observation that Tennessee had chosen an “overarching message” in this case because the legislature “spelled out in the statute that these plates would bear the words ‘Choose Life,’”82 the court spent most of its time on the latter portion of the Johanns formulation, arguing that the commissioner’s veto power over plate design meant that the state “retain[ed] power to approve every word disseminated at its behest.”83 While admitting that motorists’ “voluntary dissemination [of the ‘Choose Life’ message] itself qualifies as expressive conduct,”84 the court found that the plates themselves contained only government speech and did not constitute any sort of government-created forum for private speech.85 The court offered the following support for this finding: (1) the Supreme Court once characterized the New Hampshire state motto “‘Live Free or Die’ as ‘the State’s ideological message’” when that motto was embossed on all New Hampshire license plates;86 (2) Johanns and Rust show that the government does not necessarily create a speech forum every time it uses private volunteers (or hired hands) to disseminate a governmental message;87 and (3) finding a forum in cases like this would “render unconstitutional a large swath of government actions that nearly everyone would consider desirable and legitimate,” such as government-produced “Register and Vote” pins worn by private citizens, or postage stamps that say “Win the War.”88 The court’s reasons for refusing to find a forum seem weak. In Wooley v. Maynard,89 the New Hampshire “Live Free or Die” case, “Live Free or Die” was the state motto, and it was embossed on all standard-issue plates. No motorists paid extra for them or selected that message over others; in fact, the state required all noncommercial vehicles to bear that message on their license plates.90 This message was not one of over one hundred stateallowed options for motorists, as in Bredesen;91 rather, it was not optional at all. Under such circumstances, it is easy to conclude that the message “Live Free or Die,” which was, after all, the state motto, was government speech rather than private speech, and that no speech forum had been 81 Bredesen, 441 F.3d at 375 (citing Johanns v. Livestock Mktg. Ass’n, 544 U.S. 550, 559–67 (2005)). 82 Id. at 376. 83 Id. at 375. 84 Id. at 377. 85 Id. 86 Id. at 377–78 (quoting Wooley v. Maynard, 430 U.S. 705, 715 (1977)); see Wooley, 430 U.S. at 717 (holding that New Hampshire could not constitutionally prosecute car owners for obscuring the motto “Live Free or Die” on their license plates). 87 Bredesen, 441 F.3d at 378. 88 Id. at 378–79. 89 430 U.S. 705 (1977). 90 Id. at 707. 91 See Bredesen, 441 F.3d at 376. 382 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 created simply by embossing all standard-issue license plates with this message. But that says very little about whether a message represented in one design appearing on a long menu of various specialty plate designs—a message that will never be communicated at all unless a motorist chooses to pay for it—constitutes private speech, or whether such a specialty plate program creates a forum of some kind for private speakers. Wooley is simply inapposite. Moreover, while Johanns and Rust may indeed suggest that the government can use private parties—even volunteers—to disseminate a message without creating a forum, Johanns and Rust do not show that the government’s use of private volunteers precludes a finding that the government program is a forum—only that the use of volunteers by itself does not make it so. In other words, and perhaps unsurprisingly, the volunteer element is not alone determinative of whether a forum has been created, although every forum will include volunteers conveying messages. But of course, there are several other elements common to specialty plate programs, elements not present in the governmental programs at issue in Johanns, Rust, or Wooley, which might indicate the presence of a speech forum.92 These considerations suggest serious logical flaws in each of the court’s first two reasons for refusing to find a forum. One suspects, then, that the driving force behind the Sixth Circuit’s rejection of forum analysis may have been its third reason: the fear of a slippery slope. This fear alone, however, is a rather unsatisfying basis for denying that the government had established a forum. Moreover, the court’s concerns seem overblown, since government pins, stamps, and the like do not present many indicators of a speech forum and could be readily distinguished from specialty plates on that basis.93 Of course, the Sixth Circuit had to dispose of the forum argument in order to stand by its prior conclusion that the message “Choose Life” constituted purely government speech.94 In reaching that prior conclusion, the court assumed Johanns had changed the law, or at least clarified it, 92 These elements might include, inter alia, the fact that the government widely invites (explicitly or implicitly) private parties endorsing various unknown messages to apply for governmental permission to use governmental property in sending those messages, the fact that the government does not tax anyone or spend its own money to promote any particular message, the fact that the impulse to communicate each message originates outside the halls of government, and the fact that the messages actually sent under the program are numerous, varied, and sometimes (at least somewhat) contradictory. Id. at 381–85 (Martin, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (reasoning that the program allows for a variety of views and is designed to promote private speech rather than to convey a government message). 93 For example, it seems likely that messages appearing on government pins and stamps— messages such as “Win the War” and “Register and Vote”—originated with the government, not private applicants. One also suspects that it was not the government’s historic practice to allow dozens (or hundreds) of private organizations to emblazon their own unique advertising on the government’s pins and stamps. 94 See supra notes 80–88 and accompanying text. 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 383 95 with respect to all sorts of speech. As understood by the Sixth Circuit, the Johanns test for government speech, regardless of the content or context of the message, required a simple determination of whether the government had (1) “determine[d] an overarching message” and (2) “retain[ed] power to approve every word disseminated at its behest.”96 But the Sixth Circuit never seriously applied the first prong. The court found, without further elaboration, that the first prong was satisfied because “Tennessee set the overall message and the specific message when it spelled out in the statute that these plates would bear the words ‘Choose Life.’”97 Aside from the paucity of the court’s discussion, there are at least two problems with this analysis under the first prong, suggesting that the first prong was effectively meaningless as applied. First, the court inexplicably refused to consider the purpose or message of the specialty plate program as a whole; instead, it considered only the message reflected in the short statutory provision authorizing “Choose Life” plates.98 The “Choose Life” message, reflected in this single statute, was only one of many messages disseminated by the state’s specialty plate program.99 In Johanns, the Supreme Court found that the government had “determine[d] an overarching message”100 only after the Court had considered the program of which the message was a part—and there was no indication in those cases that the larger government program involved numerous messages on varied topics. In Rust, the relevant program was considered to be “the Title X program,” which was designed “to encourage family planning” without encouraging abortions;101 the Title X program funded services and messages consistent with this unitary purpose.102 In Johanns, the relevant program was a tax-and-spend scheme designed to “promot[e] the marketing and consumption of ‘beef and beef products,’”103 and some program funds were spent on sending messages consistent with 95 See Bredesen, 441 F.3d at 380 (rejecting the Fourth Circuit’s approach to specialty plates because, inter alia, “the Fourth Circuit opinions . . . are in tension with the intervening case of Johanns. Johanns sets forth an authoritative test for determining when speech may be attributed to the government for First Amendment purposes. [The Fourth Circuit] relied instead on a pre-Johanns fourfactor test . . . .”). 96 See supra note 70 and accompanying text. 97 Bredesen, 441 F.3d at 376. 98 See id. at 375–77 (analyzing the questions about government speech and the existence of a forum by reference only to the portion of the Tennessee Code authorizing “Choose Life” license plates, not other statutes authorizing other specialty license plates). 99 See supra notes 74–79 and accompanying text (discussing the numerous types of specialty plates and how the number of specialty plates was continually expanding). 100 See Bredesen, 441 F.3d at 375 (discussing the Supreme Court’s holding in Johanns). 101 Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U.S. 173, 193 (1991). 102 Id. at 179–80, 192–93. 103 Johanns v. Livestock Mktg. Ass’n, 544 U.S. 550, 553 (2005) (quoting The Beef Promotion and Research Act of 1985, Pub. L. No. 99–198, § 2, 99 Stat. 1597, 1598 (1985) (codified as amended at 7 U.S.C. § 2901(b))). 384 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 104 this purpose. In Bredesen, however, the “Choose Life” message was not sent as part of some state program designed to encourage adoptions or discourage abortions; rather, it was sent as part of a specialty license plate program—and over one hundred different messages, on various topics, were sent under the auspices of that program.105 Yet the Sixth Circuit refused to take account of that program in deciding whether the government had crafted an “overarching message,” or in defining the message itself.106 Judging the government’s purpose or message by reference to the “Choose Life” statute, in isolation, ignores the governmental program of which that message was a part: it ignores the governmental actions and operational context which made such statutes and messages possible. Second, in finding that the government had “determine[d] an overarching message” by authorizing “Choose Life” plates, the Sixth Circuit ignored the true origins of the message, instead resting its finding of governmental “determin[ation]” on the mere evidence that the state legislature had passed a statute approving dissemination of a message by private parties willing to pay.107 This obscures the reality that the message “Choose Life” originated, not with the state legislature, but with one or more private sector organizations that lobbied for this particular message and stood to benefit directly from its dissemination.108 This certainly was not the case in Rust. And in Johanns, while some associations of beef producers may have lobbied for the establishment of a pro-beef program in general terms, the messages themselves were crafted only after the government had established the program, and those producers’ ties to those messages were quite indirect.109 Unlike the federal government in Rust and 104 Id. at 553–55. See supra notes 74–79 and accompanying text (explicating the conditions under which Tennessee could authorize a new specialty plate). 106 See supra note 98 and accompanying text. 107 ACLU of Tenn. v. Bredesen, 441 F.3d 370, 375 (6th Cir. 2006). 108 In Tennessee, the “principal direct financial beneficiary of the ‘Choose Life’ license plate plan” was a nonprofit organization called New Life Resources, Inc., which filed a successful motion to intervene in the Bredesen case. ACLU of Tenn. v. Bredesen, 354 F. Supp. 2d 770, 772 (M.D. Tenn. 2004). As of late 2009, twenty-one states offered “Choose Life” specialty plates, and all but one of these states directed funds from the specialty plate purchase to private organizations; in the remaining state, purchasers of the “Choose Life” plate were allowed an opportunity to contribute to such organizations at the time of purchase. Guttmacher Institute, State Policies in Brief: “Choose Life” License Plates (Dec. 1, 2009), available at http://www.guttmacher.org/statecenter/spibs/spib_ CLLP.pdf; see also Sons of Confederate Veterans, Inc. v. Comm’r of the Va. Dep’t of Motor Vehicles, 288 F.3d 610, 614 (4th Cir. 2002) (finding that, in a Virginia specialty plate program in which “plates must be specifically authorized by statute,” the ordinary practice was that “a group or organization that would like to have a special license plate made available to its members contacts a member of the General Assembly to request that a bill be introduced which, if enacted, would authorize the issuance of a special plate”). 109 Most importantly, producers did not receive a monetary payment every time the ads ran, or every time a consumer chose to display the message “Beef. It’s What’s for Dinner.” Moreover, only a select few producers—some of whom were chosen by the government—participated in designing the 105 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 385 in Johanns, the Tennessee government “determine[d] an overarching message” of “Choose Life” (among many others) only after that exact message had already been “determine[d]” and proposed to the government by one or more private organizations, who hoped to gain the government’s approval of their fundraising plan.110 Thus, Tennessee’s involvement could reasonably be characterized as the mere perfunctory approval of a message presented to the state from the private sector. Arguably, this is not what the Supreme Court had in mind in Johanns when it characterized government speech by noting that “from beginning to end [it is] the message established by the Federal Government.”111 These problems with the Sixth Circuit’s approach suggest that the court largely ignored the governmental determination of the message, and allowed the second prong of its Johanns formulation, regarding governmental veto power over the final wording, to dictate the classification of this speech as government speech. Thus, the Sixth Circuit’s method of identifying government speech in Bredesen represents a binary approach, using what is in essence a single-factor test. The court determined that there were two possibilities here—the message was either government speech, or private speech—and then the court considered only one factor in making the classification: did the government retain power to approve the final wording of the message? Indeed, this determinative prong—whether the government “retain[ed] power to approve every word disseminated at its behest”—did, in isolation, point in the direction of government speech. Like the federal government in Johanns, the Tennessee government (or its agents) held veto power to approve or disapprove the final wording and design of the “Choose Life” message in advance of dissemination.112 And this factor, in those cases where it is combined with the sort of pervasive governmental involvement present in Johanns,113 makes the message look like government speech. Without that pervasive governmental involvement, however—involvement which was not present in Bredesen—governmental veto power over the final wording of a message could simply be evidence of prior restraint or message; indeed, some producers and producer associations did not like the ads. Johanns v. Livestock Mktg. Ass’n, 544 U.S. 550, 553–56 (2005). And while many of the ads did say “Funded by America’s Beef Producers,” no preexisting private entity was explicitly named in the ads, as they are on many specialty plates. Id. at 555. See, e.g., TENN. CODE ANN. § 55-4-307 (2008) (Mothers Against Methamphetamine plates); id. § 55-4-311 (Tennessee Performing Arts Center plates). 110 ACLU of Tenn. v. Bredesen, 441 F.3d 370, 375 (6th Cir. 2006); see supra 74–79 and accompanying text (noting that by the time of the litigation, the legislature already authorized over 100 specialty plates, one of which was “Choose Life”). 111 Johanns, 544 U.S. at 560–61. 112 See ACLU of Tenn. v. Bredesen, 354 F. Supp. 2d 770, 772 (M.D. Tenn. 2004) (“The plate is effectively designed by its private sponsor, New Life Resources, Inc., and approved by the State.”). 113 See supra notes 44–50, 103–104, 109, and accompanying text (detailing the extent to which the government was involved in the messaging of the program). 386 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 114 censorship in violation of the Speech Clause. This is the central problem with identifying government speech solely by reference to whether the government exercised veto power over the message. In contexts where the government did not come up with the idea of reaching an audience with this particular message, and instead merely came up with the idea of granting licenses for the private originators of approved messages to express those messages on government property, any such “approved” message looks most unlike the government speech present in Rust and Johanns. In fact, the message looks like private speech, and the licensing scheme like a government-created forum for speech. Under such circumstances, the additional fact that the government held veto power over the message’s final wording seems to indicate censorship of private speech, not editorial control of the government’s own speech. Surely, evidence that the government exercised editorial control over a private speaker’s message in advance of dissemination should not, by itself, convert otherwise private speech into government speech and convince judges that a forum never existed. This is especially easy to see if we imagine the Sixth Circuit applying its approach in other speech contexts, such as speech in city parks or other traditional public forums. IV. THE BINARY APPROACH USING THE FOUR-PRONGED TEST Like the Sixth Circuit, most of the other circuits addressing government speech issues have used a binary approach—that is, they have assumed that any given message must be either government speech or private speech—but they do not adopt the Sixth Circuit’s single-pronged classification test that prioritizes government approval of the final wording. Instead, most of them have identified government speech by using some version of a four-pronged test, originally enunciated as such by the Tenth Circuit.115 A. The Tenth Circuit Formulates the Four-Pronged Test According to the Tenth Circuit’s formulation, when classifying a message as either government speech or private speech, the four factors to be considered are (1) whether the central purpose of the governmental program facilitating the message is to promote private views; (2) who exercises editorial control over the content of the message; (3) who is the 114 At least one federal court has reached a similar conclusion. See WV Ass’n of Club Owners & Fraternal Servs., Inc. v. Musgrave, 512 F. Supp. 2d 424, 436 (S.D.W. Va. 2007) (finding that an inquiry into the degree of a state’s editorial control “confuses rather than clarifies the analysis” in cases where the central purpose of the government program at issue was not to disseminate a governmental message). 115 See Wells v. City & County of Denver, 257 F.3d 1132, 1141 (10th Cir. 2001) (outlining the four prongs of the test). 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 387 literal speaker of the message; and (4) who bears ultimate responsibility for the content of the message.116 The Tenth Circuit claimed to draw the fourpronged test from principles articulated in an Eighth Circuit opinion involving donor recognitions aired on National Public Radio and, to a lesser extent, from principles in a Ninth Circuit opinion involving a public school teacher’s postings on a school bulletin board.117 The court noted that the Eighth Circuit had alluded to such considerations in finding that donor acknowledgements, read on the air by employees of a local public radio station during the station’s broadcast of National Public Radio’s “All Things Considered” program, constituted government speech, and that therefore the station could exclude particular would-be donors and their messages based on viewpoint.118 And the Ninth Circuit had used somewhat similar considerations to conclude that where a public school had created a bulletin board for the purpose of supporting Gay and Lesbian Awareness Month, postings on that board by faculty or staff members constituted government speech and need not be viewpoint-neutral or represent a variety of views on the subject.119 The Tenth Circuit used the four-pronged test to evaluate a city’s holiday display. In Wells v. City and County of Denver, the city and county governments erected on the steps of a government building a display including “a creche, tin soldiers, Christmas trees, . . . an array of lights, . . . a shed containing Santa Claus and his elves,” and other decorations,120 all of which were owned and maintained by the government.121 Importantly, the city had built a large sign, which it erected as a part of the display, containing the message “Happy Holidays from the Keep the Lights Foundation and the sponsors that help maintain the lights at the City and County Building,”122 and then listing six corporate sponsors.123 A private organization, the Freedom from Religion Foundation, asked permission to have its own “Winter Solstice” sign erected within the display, but the government would not agree.124 The Foundation claimed that the “plain language of the [city’s] sign” indicated that the display as a whole was speech by the Keep the Lights Foundation and the other private sponsors, rather than government speech, and that the Freedom from Religion Foundation should have the right to have its 116 Id. See Downs v. Los Angeles Unified Sch. Dist., 228 F.3d 1003, 1011–12 (9th Cir. 2000); Knights of the Ku Klux Klan v. Curators of the Univ. of Mo., 203 F.3d 1085, 1093–94 (8th Cir. 2000); see also Wells, 257 F.3d at 1141 (citing Downs, 228 F.3d at 1011–12). 118 Knights, 203 F.3d at 1087–93. 119 Downs, 228 F.3d at 1005–07, 1011–12. 120 Wells, 257 F.3d at 1137. 121 Id. at 1139. 122 Id. at 1137. 123 Id. at 1140 n.4. 124 Id. at 1137–38. 117 388 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 125 message included. The court, however, applied the four-pronged test and found that the display, including the sign, constituted government speech.126 In applying the first prong—asking whether the central purpose of the governmental program facilitating the message is to promote private views—the court inexplicably focused on the “purpose of the sign” rather than the purpose of any possible governmental program, such as the current year’s display or the “program” of erecting holiday displays.127 In this case, however, the variation probably did not affect the court’s conclusion; the court found that the sign’s purpose had nothing to do with promoting private views, and the display “program” as a whole seems even less connected to private messages than the sign alone.128 In determining that the sign was not intended to promote private views or messages, the court pointed to “the City’s complete control over the sign’s construction, message, and placement,” along with a government official’s testimony (which the lower court had credited, despite the sign’s actual wording) that the sign’s purpose was to express the government’s thanks to the sponsors.129 As to the second and third prongs, the court found that the government exercised editorial control over the content of the message and also was the literal speaker because “the City built, paid for, and erected the sign.”130 Finally, applying the fourth prong of the test, the court found that the government bore ultimate responsibility for the content of the display as well as the sign, since the government had provided security and a fence for the display and was in fact defending the display in this litigation.131 The court refused to add to the test a fifth factor suggested by the dissent—“who the listener believes to be the speaker”—but argued that even if this were one relevant factor, an informed and reasonable observer would conclude under all the circumstances that the display was government speech.132 Since Wells was decided, other circuits have adopted its four-pronged test in deciding whether to classify a message as government speech. Several of these cases have involved specialty license plates. B. The Fourth Circuit Adopts the Four-Pronged Test The earliest of these specialty license plate cases was a Fourth Circuit case in which Virginia had approved a specialty plate for the Sons of 125 Id. at 1140. Id. at 1142–43. See id. at 1141–42 (discussing the purpose of the sign). 128 Id. 129 Id. 130 Id. at 1142. 131 Id. 132 Id. at 1142–43. 126 127 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 389 Confederate Veterans (“SCV”) organization but refused to emboss the plates with the organization’s logo, which included the Confederate flag.133 Although the state routinely approved logos for other organizations’ plates, it was apparently unwilling to allow the Confederate flag to appear on license plates because of the message the flag conveys.134 SCV objected, claiming viewpoint discrimination in violation of the First Amendment’s Speech Clause.135 The Fourth Circuit panel unanimously held that the messages on Virginia’s specialty plates constituted private speech, not government speech.136 While noting that the four-pronged test might not “constitute an exhaustive or always-applicable list,” the court applied the test anyway and found that all four prongs indicated private speech rather than government speech.137 Under the first prong the court examined the “‘purpose’ of the special plate program” and found that the purpose was to generate revenue for the state while allowing “the private expression of various views.”138 The court found under the second prong that editorial control over the content of specialty plate messages rested, as a practical matter, with the private organizations associated with each plate; whatever legal power the state had to design or control content was rarely if ever exercised until this case.139 The court discussed the third and fourth prongs together in a relatively truncated analysis of who is literally speaking on a specialty plate and who bears ultimate responsibility for those messages. After confessing that neither prong suggested a clear outcome in the context of specialty plates,140 the court progressed to the rather unremarkable observations that while the government owned the plates at all times, the plates were mounted on private vehicles, and the Supreme Court had suggested in Wooley v. Maynard that “license plates . . . implicate private speech interests”; from these observations, the court concluded that the third and fourth prongs, like the first and second, 133 Sons of Confederate Veterans, Inc. v. Comm’r of the Va. Dep’t of Motor Vehicles, 288 F.3d 610, 613 (4th Cir. 2002). 134 See id. at 623 (“Although the logo restriction itself makes no reference to the Confederate flag . . . it was the inclusion of the Confederate flag in the SCV’s logo that led to the prohibition against the use of the logo on the SCV’s special license plate.”); Sons of Confederate Veterans, Inc. v. Holcomb, 129 F. Supp. 2d 941, 946 (W.D. Va. 2001) (“[T]he motivation behind the Commonwealth’s ban of logos or emblems was to avoid controversy by preventing Plaintiffs from designing a plate that displays the Confederate battle flag. Out of hundreds of specialty plates in existence, only that bearing the Sons’ logo is targeted.”); Corbin, supra note 27, at 621 (“[T]he Virginia legislature probably did not want the divisive image of the Confederate flag linked to the State.”). 135 Sons of Confederate Veterans, 288 F.3d at 622. 136 Id. at 621. 137 Id. at 619–21. 138 Id. at 619. 139 Id. at 621. 140 Id. (“The ‘literal’ speaker here might be said to be the license plate itself . . . and who bears ‘ultimate responsibility’ for the speech is unclear.”). 390 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 141 indicated private speech rather than government speech. Although the Supreme Court has never adopted the four-pronged test for identifying government speech, former Justice Sandra Day O’Connor has very recently applied it in a unanimous opinion she wrote while sitting by designation on a Fourth Circuit panel, thus demonstrating the Fourth Circuit’s application of the four-pronged test outside the specialty plate context.142 Importantly, the court did not recognize the existence of any third category of “mixed” or “hybrid” speech, but once again assumed a binary classification scheme, under which speech was either government speech or private speech.143 In this case, a city council, which traditionally had begun each of its meetings with an opening prayer offered by a council member, implemented a policy requiring all such prayers to be “nondenominational.”144 One of the council members claimed that the new policy violated several of his First Amendment rights, including freedom of speech.145 The court rejected this claim, however, on the ground that the prayers constituted government speech rather than private speech. Applying the four-pronged test, the court was first required to determine the purpose of the program in which the speech occurred. The relevant “program,” according to the court, was not one particular prayer or one speaker’s prayers, but rather the policy of having council members offer prayers at council meetings.146 As to that program, the court readily concluded that the purpose was governmental because the meetings themselves served a governmental purpose and the prayers were listed on the agenda as an “official part” of every meeting; moreover, the content of the prayers usually included calls for the council to be granted wisdom and guidance as they performed their official duties.147 The court analyzed the second and third prongs together, concluding that the new policy itself evidenced that the government exercised “substantial editorial control” over the prayers and concluding that the government was the literal 141 Id. (citing Wooley v. Maynard, 430 U.S. 705, 717 (1977)). Wooley, of course, did not involve specialty plates; the case involved a motorist’s claim that a state motto, embossed on all standard-issue plates, was a form of compelled speech as to those motorists who were required to purchase and display the plates. See supra notes 89–91 and accompanying text (discussing the Court’s decision in Wooley). 142 Turner v. City Council of Fredericksburg, 534 F.3d 352, 354 (4th Cir. 2008), cert. denied, 129 S. Ct. 909 (2009). 143 Id. at 354–55. Justice O’Connor’s opinion for the court cited Sons of Confederate Veterans but ignored Planned Parenthood of South Carolina, Inc. v. Rose, 361 F.3d 786 (4th Cir. 2004). Rose was an intervening specialty plate case in which a Fourth Circuit panel had applied the four-pronged test but had suggested, in at least two of the three separate opinions, that the test showed that messages on specialty plates constitute neither purely government speech nor purely private speech, and thus fit into a putative third category called “hybrid” speech. Planned Parenthood of S.C., 361 F.3d at 792–93, 800–01. For a discussion of Rose, see infra notes 215–216, 228–248, and accompanying text. 144 Turner, 534 F.3d at 353–54. 145 Id. at 354. 146 Id. 147 Id. 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 391 speaker because anyone offering such a prayer was only allowed to speak “by virtue of his role as a Council member.”148 The most difficult question to answer, said the court, was the fourth prong question of who bears ultimate responsibility for the content of the message.149 The court noted that the council members who offered prayers did “take some personal responsibility for their [council] prayers.”150 But without pursuing this analysis further or reaching an explicit conclusion under the fourth prong, the court concluded that on the whole, “given the focus of the prayers on government business . . . we agree with the District Court that the prayers at issue are government speech.”151 C. The Ninth Circuit Adopts the Four-Pronged Test Quite recently, the Ninth Circuit was called to distinguish government speech from private speech in the specialty plate context, and it too assumed a binary approach and applied the four-pronged test.152 As in the Bredesen case,153 “Choose Life” plates were at issue here; but in this case, rather than disallowing pro-choice plates, the state of Arizona disallowed “Choose Life” plates.154 Arizona had not authorized any kind of prochoice plates, either, although no evidence showed that any group had requested them.155 The state government contended that it denied the application for “Choose Life” plates because it wished to keep all messages about abortion and abortion rights off of specialty plates.156 The government further contended that such a restriction was permissible because any messages on specialty plates (or any other license plates) were government speech and, in the alternative, that the restriction was a reasonable, viewpoint-neutral limitation on the use of the specialty plate forum.157 Applying the four-pronged test, the Ninth Circuit panel unanimously found that messages on specialty plates constituted private 148 Id. at 354–55. Id. at 355. Id. 151 Id. The court provided additional support for this conclusion by citing Simpson v. Chesterfield County Board of Supervisors, 404 F.3d 276, 279, 288 (4th Cir. 2005) (holding that similar prayers at county board meetings, when offered by members of the local clergy selected by the board, constituted government speech). Curiously, the Simpson case did not mention or apply the four-pronged test adopted earlier in Sons of Confederate Veterans, nor did it acknowledge the existence of a third, “hybrid” category of speech, as had been suggested by various opinions in Rose. See supra note 143 (demonstrating that two of the three separate opinions suggested that the four-pronged test showed that speech on specialty plates was neither purely private nor purely governmental). 152 Ariz. Life Coal. Inc. v. Stanton, 515 F.3d 956, 965–68 (9th Cir. 2008), cert. denied, 129 S. Ct. 56 (2008). 153 See supra notes 69–88 and accompanying text (discussing the Bredesen case, in which the court found “Choose Life” specialty plates to contain purely government speech). 154 Ariz. Life Coal., 515 F.3d at 960–62. 155 Id. at 961, 971. 156 Id. at 972. 157 Id. at 965, 971. 149 150 392 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 158 speech, and then went on to conclude that the state’s exclusion of all viewpoints about abortion and abortion rights was not a viewpoint-neutral restriction.159 In applying the first prong of the government speech test, the court analyzed neither the purpose of all license plates nor the purpose of a single specialty plate design, but the purpose of the “specialty license plate program as a whole.”160 The court found the purpose of that program to be “revenue raising”161 and also “providing a forum in which philanthropic organizations . . . can exercise their First Amendment rights in the hopes of raising money to support their cause.”162 On the second prong’s question of editorial control, the court again found for the private organization, noting that “the idea of a ‘Choose Life’ license plate originated with Life Coalition,” who also “determined the substantive content of their message,” despite the state’s authority to set “guidelines for gaining access to the license plate forum.”163 Regarding the third prong, the court found that the evidence, while somewhat conflicting, predominately favored classifying private parties as the literal speakers, despite the government’s ownership of the plates; the court drew on Wooley for its primary support.164 And the court concluded under the fourth prong that private organizations bore ultimate responsibility for the message, since their organization’s motto and name would appear on the plates and the program placed the “burden . . . on the nonprofit organization” to “take the affirmative step of submitting an application” before any message would be authorized or communicated.165 Thus each of the prongs, according to the court, supported a finding of private speech. D. The Seventh Circuit Joins In—Or Does It? The Seventh Circuit claimed to have employed the four-pronged test— albeit in a truncated formulation—in a similar specialty plate case decided at the end of 2008, in which the state of Illinois disallowed a private organization’s application for “Choose Life” plates.166 Considering and then rejecting the Sixth Circuit’s approach in Bredesen,167 the Seventh Circuit found: 158 Id. at 965–68. Id. at 972. Id. at 965 (emphasis omitted). 161 Id. at 966. 162 Id. at 965. 163 Id. at 966. 164 Id. at 967. 165 Id. at 967–68. 166 Choose Life Ill., Inc. v. White, 547 F.3d 853, 855–56 (7th Cir. 2008). 167 Id. at 862–63. For a discussion of Bredesen, see supra Part III (discussing how the Sixth Circuit held that a message constitutes government speech whenever the government retains the power to approve every word of the message). 159 160 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 393 [T]he approach of the Fourth and Ninth Circuits [is] more persuasive. Their multi-factor test can be distilled (and simplified) by focusing on the following inquiry: Under all the circumstances, would a reasonable person consider the speaker to be the government or a private party? Factors bearing on this analysis include, but are not limited to, the degree to which the message originates with the government, the degree to which the government exercises editorial control over the message, and whether the government or a private party communicates the message.168 In using this test, the court does not seem to have applied the above factors one by one, so much as generally kept them in mind as it listed a number of characteristics of the specialty plate program, some of which indicated government speech and some private speech.169 In the end, the court determined only that “there are enough elements of private speech here to rule out the government-speech doctrine.”170 In fact, the very language of the Seventh Circuit’s “test” conceals more than it reveals. The “approach of the Fourth and Ninth Circuits,” which the Seventh Circuit purported to adopt, was the four-pronged test; yet the Seventh Circuit refused explicitly to endorse that test.171 Even more confusingly, after applying its own formulation—a somewhat open-ended “reasonable person” attribution test—the Seventh Circuit framed its conclusion negatively: “[T]here are enough elements of private speech here to rule out the government-speech doctrine; the messages on Illinois specialty license plates are not government speech.”172 But what are they? The court held that “private-speech rights are implicated” by the specialty plate program, but stopped short of saying whether the messages on specialty plates constituted private speech, hybrid speech, or something else entirely.173 Nevertheless, the court went on to employ forum analysis as if the messages constituted private speech, ultimately deciding that specialty plates were a nonpublic forum174 and yet upholding the state’s restriction in this case as a reasonable, viewpoint-neutral subject matter limitation within that forum.175 168 Choose Life, 547 F.3d at 863. Id. at 863–64. Id. at 864. 171 Id. at 863. 172 Id. at 863–64. 173 Id. at 864. 174 Id. at 864–65. 175 Id. at 867. 169 170 394 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 E. The Eighth Circuit Applies the Four-Pronged Test to Answer “One Key Question” Most recently the Eighth Circuit, which the Tenth Circuit credited with originating the four-pronged test, has applied the test in deciding its own specialty plate case involving a state’s refusal to issue “Choose Life” plates.176 In doing so, however, the court followed the lead of the Seventh Circuit in characterizing its analysis as a mere inquiry into attribution: Our analysis boils down to one key question: whether, under all the circumstances, a reasonable and fully informed observer would consider the speaker to be the government or a private party. Notwithstanding the Sixth Circuit’s conclusion to the contrary, we now join the Fourth, Seventh and Ninth Circuits in concluding that a reasonable and fully informed observer would consider the speaker [of the message appearing on a specialty plate] to be the organization that sponsors and the vehicle owner who displays the specialty license plate.177 But unlike the Seventh Circuit, the Eighth Circuit answered the “one key question” of attribution by applying, explicitly and in order, the elements of the four-pronged test.178 Beginning with the first prong, the court determined that “[t]he primary purpose of Missouri’s specialty plate program is to allow private organizations to promote their messages and raise money and to allow private individuals to support those organizations and their messages.”179 Next, the court applied the second prong in pointing out that “[u]nder the Missouri statute, both the state and the sponsoring organization exercise some degree of editorial control over the messages on specialty plates.”180 Finally, the court applied the third and fourth prongs: after noting that private organizations submitted “a general description of the plate” for approval or rejection by a state legislative committee, and that the plates thus approved were designed by the organization and produced without further input from the state regarding content, the court concluded that “the organizations that sponsor the specialty plates and the vehicle owners who choose to purchase and display them are the literal speakers who bear the ultimate responsibility for the message.”181 Then, going beyond the four-pronged test, the court went on to point 176 Roach v. Stouffer, 560 F.3d 860, 871 (8th Cir. 2009); see also Summum v. City of Ogden, 297 F.3d 995, 1004–05 (10th Cir. 2002) (discussing how the Eighth Circuit developed the test in Knights). 177 Roach, 560 F.3d at 867. 178 Id. at 867–68. 179 Id. at 867. 180 Id. 181 Id. at 867–68. 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 395 out two other factors that would likewise lead a reasonable observer to attribute specialty plate messages to private speakers. The first of these was the sheer number and types of different specialty plates issued by the state: “With more than 200 specialty plates available to Missouri vehicle owners, a reasonable observer could not think that the State of Missouri communicates all of those messages.”182 The second additional factor was the absence of state compulsion: While Missouri requires a vehicle to display a license plate, the State does not compel anyone to purchase a specialty plate. . . . The sponsoring organization must apply for the specialty plate, and the vehicle owner must choose to purchase it. Because the “Choose Life” plate is different from the standard Missouri license plate, a reasonable observer would understand that the vehicle owner took the initiative to purchase the specialty plate and is voluntarily communicating his or her own message, not the message of the state.183 In the end, based on the four-factor test and the two additional factors, the court was convinced that specialty plate messages constituted private speech. Again departing from the Seventh Circuit’s example, the Eighth Circuit made this conclusion explicit and unequivocal by stating that “the messages communicated on specialty plates are private speech, not government speech.”184 Without determining what type of speech forum the plates constituted, the court found that Missouri’s specialty plate program was facially unconstitutional because it allowed state officials to exercise viewpoint discrimination, which is forbidden in every type of forum, as they approved or disapproved applications for specialty plates.185 F. Difficulties with the Four-Pronged Test As the foregoing history demonstrates, recent applications of the fourpronged test raise a few nagging concerns about it, in either its original or modified formulations. First, some of the prongs seem to be unclear, or at least susceptible to varying definitions. The first prong of the test—the central purpose of the program giving rise to the message—provides an example. Although it did not apply the four-pronged test, the Sixth Circuit in Bredesen had to consider a factor similar to the first prong as it applied Johanns, and held that the relevant “program” was the particular statute 182 Id. at 868. Id. 184 Id. 185 Id. at 868–70 & n.4. 183 396 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 186 authorizing “Choose Life” plates; in contrast, the Fourth, Eighth, and Ninth Circuits, applying the first prong of the four-pronged test, considered the relevant “program” to be the specialty license plate program;187 and the state has sometimes urged that the relevant “program” is the set of all policies regarding license plates.188 The four-pronged test apparently does not specify which program is the relevant one. Another example of ambiguity can be found in the third prong of the test, requiring courts to determine who is the “literal speaker.”189 In some speech contexts the term “literal speaker” will no doubt have a clear meaning, but in many of the more troublesome cases, one suspects, it will not. Specialty license plates provide a perfect illustration of the difficulty. Who is the “literal speaker” of the message on a specialty plate: the motorist, who installed the plates and drives the car on which they are displayed; the state, who owns and prints the plates, who regulates their format, and whose name is emblazoned across the top; or the nonprofit organization, who likely designed the plate’s background and whose name, logo, and message are displayed there? Or is the “literal speaker,” as the Fourth Circuit once suggested with a hint of frustration, the “license plate itself”?190 The words “literal speaker” are not self-defining in such contexts and tend to create more difficulties than they resolve. A second concern, related to the first, is that some prongs of the fourpronged test seem often to point in multiple directions. The “literal speaker” prong, as noted above, is flawed in this way. As another example, consider the fourth prong: the determination of who bears ultimate responsibility for the content of the message. A number of facts might reasonably bear on that question of “ultimate responsibility,” facts which may often point in different directions. If “ultimate responsibility” is simply a question about attribution by a reasonable or average viewer/listener, we will want to assign “responsibility” to the entity whose name is affixed to the message (if any, and only one, is so affixed);191 if, 186 ACLU of Tenn. v. Bredesen, 441 F.3d 370, 375–77 (6th Cir. 2006); see also supra notes 98– 106 and accompanying text (discussing the Sixth Circuit’s refusal to conclude that the specialty plate program was the relevant program). 187 See Roach, 560 F.3d at 867; Ariz. Life Coal. Inc. v. Stanton, 515 F.3d 956, 965 (9th Cir. 2008); Sons of Confederate Veterans, Inc. v. Comm’r of the Va. Dep’t of Motor Vehicles, 288 F.3d 610, 619 (4th Cir. 2002); supra notes 138, 160, 179, and accompanying text (discussing the cases that held that the relevant program was the specialty plate program). 188 See, e.g., Ariz. Life Coal., 515 F.3d at 965. 189 Sons of Confederate Veterans, 288 F.3d at 621. 190 Id. 191 See Ariz. Life Coal., 515 F.3d at 967 (finding that Life Coalition bore ultimate responsibility for the message, “Life Coalition submitted its motto to be placed on a specialty license plate that would also identify the organization by name”); see also Choose Life Ill., Inc. v. White, 547 F.3d 853, 863 (7th Cir. 2008) (noting that the entire four-pronged test “can be distilled (and simplified) by focusing on the following inquiry: Under all the circumstances, would a reasonable person consider the speaker to be the government or a private party?”). 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 397 however, this is also a question about who stands to lose financially if the message falls on deaf ears, that might suggest another entity altogether;192 if it is also a question of who is liable if the message constitutes a tort or other actionable wrong, that may suggest a third entity;193 if it is also a question of who paid for the message or provides protection of the message, that might suggest yet other groups.194 In light of such ambiguities, it is perhaps unsurprising that reasonable judges can and do disagree on outcomes under the four-pronged test. The Tenth Circuit, for example, which originated the test in its four-part formulation,195 has recently divided over how to apply the test in the context of a Ten Commandments monument donated to a city by a private nonprofit group and now owned and displayed by the city in a city park. Shortly after the Tenth Circuit announced the four-pronged test in Wells,196 the court applied the test to such a donated monument and concluded that the monument constituted private speech.197 This determination was adopted by the court, without discussion or application of the four-pronged test, in another case involving a similar monument five years later;198 Judge McConnell, however, joined by Judge Gorsuch, dissented from a denial of rehearing en banc in that case, arguing that the Wells four-factor test showed that such monuments constitute government speech.199 The court’s decision in that case has now been reversed by the Supreme Court (without any discussion or application of the four-pronged test),200 but the disagreement among the judges of the Tenth Circuit illustrates some of the ambiguities inherent in the elements of the fourpronged test. Judge McConnell believed that the second and fourth prongs indicated government speech because the government “exercised total ‘control’ over the monuments . . . [and] bore ‘ultimate responsibility’ for 192 For example, given the facts of Knights of the Ku Klux Klan v. Curators of the University of Missouri, 203 F.3d 1085, 1089–90 (8th Cir. 2000), one could argue that NPR’s donors bear “ultimate responsibility” for the donor acknowledgements that NPR broadcasts, precisely because it is the donor who stands to win or lose financially based on how favorably the message is received by NPR’s listeners. 193 See Wells v. City & County of Denver, 257 F.3d 1132, 1142 (10th Cir. 2001) (stating that “this litigation [in which the City is a named defendant] is itself an indication that the City bears the ultimate responsibility for the content of the display”). 194 See id. (finding that the City bore “ultimate responsibility” for the message because, inter alia, it provided “security for the display, including a fence to guard against theft and protect citizens from possible electrical hazards, . . . video cameras, . . . motion detectors, . . . and a security guard”). 195 See supra notes 115–132 and accompanying text (discussing the four-pronged test). 196 See id. 197 Summum v. City of Ogden, 297 F.3d 995, 1004–06 (10th Cir. 2002). 198 Summum v. Pleasant Grove City, 483 F.3d 1044, 1047 n.2 (10th Cir. 2007), rev’d, 129 S. Ct. 1125 (2009). 199 Summum v. Pleasant Grove City, 499 F.3d 1170, 1175–77 (10th Cir. 2007) (McConnell, J., dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc). 200 Pleasant Grove City v. Summum, 129 S. Ct. 1125 (2009). 398 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 201 the monuments’ contents and upkeep.” The court had disagreed, holding that the second prong indicated private speech because “the [private donor organization] exercised complete control over the content of the Monument, turning over to the City of Ogden a completed product.”202 And the court thought that while the government might have had “ultimate responsibility” for the content of the monument after it was donated, the other three prongs of the test indicated private speech and outweighed the fourth prong conclusion.203 In particular, the court thought that the first prong indicated private speech because “the central purpose of the Ten Commandments monument is to advance the views of the [private donor organization] rather than those of the City of Ogden.”204 Judge McConnell did not apply the first prong explicitly, but considering the language of that prong as quoted in Wells itself,205 one could surely object to the court’s decision to examine the purpose of the monument rather than the purpose of the “program”—perhaps the city’s policy about all the monuments displayed in its parks—which gave rise to the message.206 Finally, Judge McConnell seems to have thought “ownership” of the “speech”—a factor not expressly listed in the four-pronged test—should be a determinative factor by itself in cases, like that of the donated monument, where ownership is not in dispute.207 This approach, however, raises its own questions. First, is “ownership of the speech” demonstrated merely by ownership of the medium through which the speech is expressed (here, the monument and perhaps the park)? If not, what counts as “ownership of the speech,” such that we can be certain the city owned the speech here? On the other hand, if ownership of the medium is enough, then Knights, the Eighth Circuit case that Judge McConnell said represented a more questionable case of ownership, should have been another easy case of government ownership of the message (and thus government speech), because the government owned the radio station used to communicate the message (and probably the paper upon which the message was written). And specialty license plates would represent another easy case of 201 Pleasant Grove City, 499 F.3d at 1177 (McConnell, J., dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc). 202 City of Ogden, 297 F.3d at 1004. Id. at 1005–06. 204 Id. at 1004. 205 See Wells v. City & County of Denver, 257 F.3d 1132, 1141 (10th Cir. 2001) (“[T]he Eighth Circuit relied on a number of factors: (1) that ‘the central purpose of the enhanced underwriting program is not to promote the views of the donors’. . . .” (emphasis added) (quoting Knights of the Ku Klux Klan v. Curators of the Univ. of Mo., 203 F.3d 1085, 1093–94 (8th Cir. 2000))). 206 See, e.g., Ariz. Life Coal. Inc. v. Stanton, 515 F.3d 956, 965 (9th Cir. 2008) (stating that “we must address [the] specialty license plate program as a whole”); Sons of Confederate Veterans, Inc. v. Comm’r of the Va. Dep’t of Motor Vehicles, 288 F.3d 610, 619 (4th Cir. 2002) (considering entire specialty plate program under first prong analysis). 207 Summum v. Pleasant Grove City, 499 F.3d 1170, 1176 (10th Cir. 2007) (McConnell, J., dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc). 203 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 399 government speech, simply because the government clearly owns the plates. These results seem too easy. Second, and more fundamentally, why should government ownership of the medium, by itself, convert otherwise private speech into government speech? If a city makes microphones available for any speakers who wish to speak in the city park, one would not typically assume that the speech is government speech, although the government clearly owns the media of communication.208 Even if each of the four prongs were unambiguous by itself, the disagreement among the Tenth Circuit judges also reminds us that the test as a whole still leaves room for judicial doubt in the case of a “prong split.” How many of the factors must point in the same direction before we can reach a conclusion? Conveniently, and perhaps not entirely by accident, courts most often seem to find that the prongs all point in the same direction;209 but if the result under one prong is an outlier, do the other three always outweigh it?210 What if two prongs indicate government speech and two indicate private speech—how are we to break the tie?211 These problems with the four-pronged test are largely practical problems of implementation. But a more fundamental flaw might lie in what the test actually measures. Indeed, it is not at all clear that the fourpronged test would lead to a finding of government speech even on the facts of Rust itself,212 which suggests that the test functions rather poorly as 208 See also id. at 1179 (Tacha, J., responding to dissent from denial of rehearing en banc) (“No one thinks The Great Gatsby is government speech just because a public school provides its students with the text.”). 209 See, e.g., Ariz. Life Coal., 515 F.3d at 965–68; Sons of Confederate Veterans, 288 F.3d at 619– 21; Wells, 257 F.3d at 1141–42; Knights, 203 F.3d at 1093–94. 210 See, e.g., Summum v. City of Ogden, 297 F.3d 995, 1005 (10th Cir. 2002) (explaining that when three of the four prongs indicated private speech, the court resolved “[a]ny doubt” by taking account of “the after-the-fact nature of the [government’s] effort to claim adoption of that speech”); Turner v. City Council of Fredericksburg, Va., 534 F.3d 352, 355 (4th Cir. 2008) (finding that a message constituted government speech when three prongs indicated government speech and evidence under fourth prong was equivocal). 211 Compare Pleasant Grove City, 499 F.3d at 1176–77 (McConnell, J., dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc) (arguing that the second and fourth prongs, indicating government speech, would be dispositive by themselves, regardless of the outcome under the first and third prongs), with Planned Parenthood of S.C., Inc. v. Rose, 361 F.3d 786, 793–94 (4th Cir. 2004) (arguing that when the first and second prongs indicate government speech and third and fourth prongs indicate private speech, a message constitutes “mixed speech” under four-pronged test). 212 In Rust, federal law prohibited the distribution of certain federal “family planning project[]” funds to entities that provided abortion counseling or referrals, or which otherwise encouraged abortion. Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U.S. 173, 178–80 (1991). Under the second prong, the government surely did not exercise much “editorial control” over any given statement by a doctor or employee of the recipient clinics; private persons were deciding all the details about what to say, except that they were not to speak about abortion. Under the third prong, the “literal speaker” was clearly the private physician or clinic staffer. Under the fourth prong, “ultimate responsibility” for whatever was said about family planning—in the eyes of the law or in the mind of an average listener—arguably rested with the clinic rather than the federal government. The majority of the four prongs thus indicate private speech, not government speech. And the first prong, assessing the “central purpose of the program in which the speech occurred,” might indicate either governmental or private speech, depending on 400 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 an estimation of government speech law. In a way, the shortcomings of the four-pronged test are not surprising. In announcing and applying these factors originally, the Eighth Circuit was focused on evidence that seemed relevant to decide the case before it; the court does not seem to have considered or intended that these factors would be used to identify government speech across a range of cases.213 But the Supreme Court has never given a very clear test for identifying government speech, so when other circuits were subsequently forced to differentiate government speech from private speech, they latched onto the Eighth Circuit’s factors, formulated them into a four-pronged test, and applied that test in a variety of contexts.214 The move is somewhat understandable; courts obviously prefer to have clear law to apply. But close inspection of the test shows that it is neither “clear” nor the “law” as so far announced by the Supreme Court. V. THE “HYBRID” OR “MIXED” SPEECH APPROACH Separate from, and perhaps prior to, the question of whether to employ the four-pronged test is the question of whether to adopt a binary approach to classifying speech. Most circuits have embraced such an approach, assuming any given speech is either government speech or private speech. At least one circuit case, however, suggests that speech might be more complex, so that in some situations both governmental and private elements are present and the speech cannot be classified as one or the other.215 The proposed solution is the recognition of a new category of blended, “hybrid,” or “mixed” speech, denoting speech that is simultaneously governmental and private.216 A few commentators, too, have recently embraced this third category of speech.217 While some who have adopted this approach favor the four-pronged test for classifying whether the “program” is defined as the federal grant program or a particular clinic’s program of family planning services. See supra note 116 and accompanying text (stating the four prongs of the test). 213 See Knights of the Ku Klux Klan v. Curators of the Univ. of Mo., 203 F.3d 1085, 1093–94 (8th Cir. 2000); supra note 118 and accompanying text; see also Wells, 257 F.3d at 1155 (Briscoe, J., dissenting) (“[I]t is not clear whether the court in Knights of KKK was creating a test to be applied in all government speech cases, or whether it was identifying the factors that evidenced government speech in that case.”). 214 See supra Parts IV.A.–D. (discussing the formulation of the four-pronged test). 215 See Rose, 361 F.3d at 794. 216 See id. at 794 (Michael, J.) (finding specialty license plates to be “mixed speech” which is “neither purely government speech nor purely private speech”); id. at 800 (Luttig, J., concurring in judgment) (finding that “speech can indeed be hybrid in character” because “some speech acts constitute both private and government speech”); see also id. at 801 (Gregory, J., concurring in judgment) (finding that “license plate programs . . . ‘really have elements of both private and government speech’” and that “government speech interests . . . are implicated in the vanity license plate forum” (quoting Sons of Confederate Veterans, Inc. v. Comm’r of the Va. Dep’t of Motor Vehicles, 305 F.3d 241, 252 (4th Cir. 2002) (Gregory, J., dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc))). 217 See supra note 27. 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 218 speech into one of the three categories, somewhat different set of factors.219 401 others advocate considering a A. Judges Who Have Advocated the “Hybrid” or “Mixed” Speech Approach Among federal judges, perhaps the earliest to suggest something like a hybrid speech category was Judge Mary Beck Briscoe of the Tenth Circuit, who asserted as she dissented in Wells that “the holiday display is not solely government speech, but contains private speech . . . .”220 If she had in mind a distinct third category of speech, however, Judge Briscoe did not elaborate on it. The leader of the judicial charge to recognize explicitly a hybrid speech category has been Michael Luttig, who was at the time sitting on the Fourth Circuit. As early as 2002, in considering a request for rehearing in the Sons of Confederate Veterans case dealing with specialty license plates,221 Judge Luttig wrote separately to assert that while “to this point, the Supreme Court has always held that speech is either private or governmental,” this binary approach was the result of “doctrinal underdevelopment.”222 Judge Luttig continued: [A]lthough the doctrine may not have previously recognized such, speech in fact can be, at once, that of a private individual and the government . . . I believe that, with time, intellectual candor actually will force the Court . . . to fully recognize this fact doctrinally . . . . I am [also] convinced that our court in turn will, upon reflection, conclude that at least the particular speech at issue in this case is neither exclusively that of the private individual nor exclusively that of the government, but, rather, hybrid speech of both. Indeed, as I have thought about the matter, I believe that the speech that appears on the so-called “special” or “vanity” license plate could prove to be the quintessential example of speech that is both private and governmental because the forum and the message are essentially inseparable . . . .223 Two years later, in the Rose case involving specialty plates, Judge Luttig 218 See, e.g., Rose, 361 F.3d at 792–94. See, e.g., Corbin, supra note 27, at 627 (discussing the possibility of a five-prong test). 220 Wells v. City & County of Denver, 257 F.3d 1132, 1154 (10th Cir. 2001) (Briscoe, J., dissenting). 221 See supra notes 133–39 and accompanying text (discussing Sons of Confederate Veterans). 222 Sons of Confederate Veterans, 305 F.3d at 245 (Luttig, J., respecting denial of rehearing en banc). 223 Id. 219 402 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 continued to defend his conception of hybrid speech—this time bringing one or two other Fourth Circuit judges along with him—but did not further explain the contours or implications of the hybrid speech category.224 The significance of recognizing a hybrid speech category depends on how such a category will be used. What legal standards apply to hybrid speech? In Sons of Confederate Veterans, Judge Luttig disclaimed any intent “to foretell those limitations here,”225 but nevertheless opined that viewpoint discrimination by the government should be forbidden as to hybrid speech if three factors were present: (1) “the government has voluntarily opened up for private expression property that the private individual is actually required by the government to display publicly”; (2) the private speech component of the hybrid speech is “significant”; and (3) the government interest is “less than compelling.”226 Believing all three factors to be present with respect to specialty license plate programs, Judge Luttig agreed that it was unconstitutional for the state to deny, on the basis of viewpoint, an organization’s request to include the Confederate flag in its specialty plate design.227 Subsequently in Rose, Judge Luttig did not take any further steps in developing a standard to apply to hybrid speech, instead simply citing his earlier position in Sons of Confederate Veterans that viewpoint discrimination should be forbidden with respect to the particular form of hybrid speech appearing on specialty license plates.228 His colleague on the Rose panel, Judge Blane Michael, provided a fuller discussion. In his own separate opinion, Judge Michael applied the four-pronged test from Sons of Confederate Veterans, found that the first two prongs pointed toward government speech and the last two prongs pointed toward private speech, and concluded from this that the specialty plate speech was “mixed speech” which was “neither purely government speech nor purely private speech.”229 Without specifying a test that could be applied to all such mixed speech, Judge Michael pointed to three factors, quite different from Judge Luttig’s, which led him to conclude similarly that viewpoint discrimination would be impermissible with regard to this particular form of mixed speech: (1) the specialty plates constituted a limited forum for expression which the state had created; (2) the government had favored itself as a speaker within that forum; and (3) the state’s one-sided advocacy might not be apparent to average viewers of 224 225 See supra note 216. Sons of Confederate Veterans, 305 F.3d at 247 (Luttig, J., respecting denial of rehearing en banc). 226 Id. Id. Planned Parenthood of S.C., Inc. v. Rose, 361 F.3d 786, 800–01 (4th Cir. 2004) (Luttig, J., concurring in judgment). 229 Id. at 793–94 (Michael, J.). 227 228 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 403 230 the plates. Judge Michael’s opinion raises some troubling questions. First, while proceeding on the assumption that the four-pronged test is legally binding, Judge Michael used the test to reach a “mixed speech” conclusion that was never recognized as a possibility in the precedents which had created the test.231 Along the same lines, the opinion gives no indication of what showing is necessary under the four-pronged test to qualify particular speech as “mixed.” In this case, two prongs were said to point in one direction and two in the other;232 but is this necessary, or sufficient, for a finding of “mixed speech”? Was the decisive factor which particular prongs pointed in a single direction, or the fact that two did, or the fact that not all did? The opinion leaves all of this unclear. More important, perhaps, are the particular standards Judge Michael applied to mixed speech in concluding that viewpoint discrimination was forbidden. First, there is the finding of a forum: he noted that the government’s restriction of this mixed speech was suspicious because the government, in creating a specialty plate program, had created a limited forum for expression.233 But by definition, one might assume, a speech forum is a place that contains some purely private speech.234 If the only messages in the “forum” are mixed speech containing some governmental component, that in itself might well be proof that no forum exists—at least not of the sort known to precedent. Judge Michael’s finding of a forum was based primarily, if not exclusively, on the fact that those carrying the mixed speech on their cars were volunteers who were not “enlist[ed]” by the state, as were the doctors in Rust.235 But then why was their speech in the specialty plate “forum” not purely private speech? Putting aside the question whether the actual message-bearers in Rust (the doctors)236 or in Johanns (the media outlets)237 were any less “volunteers” than the motorists in Rose, one wonders how the finding that the motorists were volunteers can be held to indicate that the government intentionally created a forum for speech, but not to indicate the presence of any purely private speech. Can there be such a thing as a “mixed speech forum,” a forum 230 Id. at 795–96 (Michael, J.). These precedents are Knights of Ku Klux Klan v. Curators of University of Missouri, 203 F.3d 1085 (8th Cir. 2000), Wells v. City & County of Denver, 257 F.3d 1132 (10th Cir. 2001), and Sons of Confederate Veterans, Inc. v. Commissioner of the Virginia Department of Motor Vehicles, 288 F.3d 610 (4th Cir. 2002). See supra notes 117–43 and accompanying text. 232 Rose, 361 F.3d at 793–94. 233 See supra note 230 and accompanying text. 234 See, e.g., U.S. v. Am. Library Ass’n, 539 U.S. 194, 204–06 (2003) (plurality opinion); Int’l Soc’y for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee, 505 U.S. 672, 678–83 (1992); Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Def. & Educ. Fund, Inc., 473 U.S. 788, 802–06 (1985) (noting the presence of purely private speech in a variety of speech forums). 235 Rose, 361 F.3d at 798 (Michael, J.). 236 Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U.S. 173, 179–81 (1991). 237 Johanns v. Livestock Mktg. Ass’n, 544 U.S. 550, 554–55 (2005). 231 404 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 containing only mixtures of governmental and private speech? If all the speech includes some governmental component, in what sense is there a public forum—or a forum of any kind?238 Second, there is the focus on attribution: Judge Michael claimed that in a mixed speech context, when a state has “favored itself”239 as a “privileged speaker” within a limited forum (in this case, by authorizing a plate that promotes the government’s view and refusing to authorize a plate promoting a competing view)240 and average viewers do not readily attribute the one-sided message to the state, viewpoint discrimination is forbidden.241 Since viewpoint discrimination would presumably be inherent in the governmental component of any mixed speech, this boils down to the assertion that a government crafting messages for mixed speech in a forum must clearly identify itself as a speaker. This command, however, seems contrary to Supreme Court precedent, as it would elevate attribution to the status of a determinative factor in certain situations. The Supreme Court, by contrast, has not focused on attribution as a key factor in identifying government speech or in determining whether viewpoint discrimination is permissible—in fact, quite the opposite. No doubt viewpoint discrimination would be less likely if the average listener would be readily able to link the speech to the government; but the Supreme Court has pointedly allowed viewpoint discrimination even where the public does not attribute the message to the government, noting that “the correct focus is not on whether the ads’ audience realizes the government is speaking, but on the [government program’s] purported interference with respondents’ First Amendment rights.”242 True, the Court in that case had found the presence of pure government speech.243 But under Judge Michael’s analysis, the speech there might well have qualified as mixed speech instead: the government had funded pro-beef ads that were designed by a combination of governmental and private actors; the ads were conveyed through private media outlets as literal speakers; and the ads often carried a statement announcing that they were “Funded by America’s Beef Producers,” making no mention of governmental involvement.244 On any reasonable understanding, the government was speaking covertly and the ads were not viewpoint-neutral; yet the Court upheld the arrangement as government speech, rather than striking it down 238 Cf. Am. Library Ass’n, 539 U.S. at 206 (finding that neither a public library nor the internet terminals it provided constituted a public forum because such a library “provides Internet access, not to ‘encourage a diversity of views from private speakers,’” but for other reasons (quoting Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819, 834 (1995))). 239 Rose, 361 F.3d at 795. 240 Id. at 798. 241 Id. at 795–96, 799. 242 Johanns, 544 U.S. at 564 n.7. 243 Id. at 563–64. 244 Id. at 553–55, 560–61. 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 405 245 as forbidden viewpoint discrimination regarding mixed speech. Judge Luttig’s approach is also problematic, though for different reasons. His proposal for limiting government control of “hybrid” speech was tailored to situations in which “the government has voluntarily opened up for private expression property that the private individual is actually required by the government to display publicly.”246 In such situations— assuming the private speech component of the hybrid speech was “significant”—he would only allow viewpoint discrimination if the government had a “compelling” interest.247 It is difficult to imagine what speech would be governed by this rule aside from specialty or vanity license plates.248 What other government property is legally required to be displayed by private citizens and also serves as a government-designated forum for their speech? In fact, one might well argue that even vanity and specialty plates do not constitute property that any private individual is required to display publicly; although vehicle owners are required to display a license plate of some kind, no owner is required to display a vanity or specialty plate, containing some element of her own speech.249 At best, then, Judge Luttig’s prescription seems to provide guidance for how to treat hybrid speech only in the narrow context of specialty plates, and hinges the permissibility of viewpoint discrimination on the somewhat arbitrary standard of a compelling governmental interest; at worst, it provides no guidance even in the context of specialty plates. B. Professor Corbin’s “Mixed Speech” Approach Some commentators have likewise embraced the hybrid or mixed category for speech.250 Providing the most extended defense of this approach, Caroline Mala Corbin has recently proposed the recognition of a “mixed speech” category, setting forth a five-factor test for classifying speech as governmental, private, or mixed: “(1) Who is the literal speaker? (2) Who controls the message? (3) Who pays for the message? (4) What is the context of the speech (particularly the speech goals of the program in which the speech appears)? (5) To whom would a reasonable person attribute the speech?”251 As Professor Corbin conceives this test, there is 245 Id. at 560–67. Sons of Confederate Veterans, Inc. v. Comm’r of the Va. Dep’t of Motor Vehicles, 305 F.3d 241, 247 (4th Cir. 2002) (Luttig, J., respecting denial of rehearing en banc); see supra note 226 and accompanying text. 247 Id. 248 Indeed, Judge Luttig disclaimed any intention of fashioning a broad rule for all hybrid speech. See Sons of Confederate Veterans, 305 F.3d at 246–47. 249 See Roach v. Stouffer, 560 F.3d 860, 868 (8th Cir. 2009) (“[W]e note that the messages communicated through specialty plates are voluntary, not compulsory. While Missouri requires a vehicle to display a license plate, the State does not compel anyone to purchase a specialty plate.”). 250 See supra note 27. 251 Corbin, supra note 27, at 627. 246 406 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 no worry regarding indeterminate factors or a division of conclusions among factors, for “unless all factors point exclusively to private speech or exclusively to government speech, the speech is mixed.”252 Applying this test to specialty license plates, Professor Corbin (perhaps unsurprisingly) finds the plates to be mixed speech, “fall[ing] squarely in the middle of the private/government speech spectrum.”253 The literal speaker, she finds, is “both the government and the private car owner”;254 control over the message is exercised to a “substantial degree[]” by “both the government and the individual car owner”;255 funding for the speech rests primarily with private speakers, “though the government plays a funding role as well”;256 the speech goals of the program are “inconclusive and difficult to evaluate,”257 as “is often the case for both government-subsidized speech and speech in a nonpublic forum”;258 and finally, “[a] reasonable person is unlikely to attribute the message . . . solely to private speakers or solely to the government.”259 In short, four of the five factors lead to inconclusive results, failing to indicate that either the government or a private entity was speaking alone, and the other factor shows that private speech elements predominate over admittedly present governmental speech elements. One suspects this sort of result will not be unusual in applications of Professor Corbin’s five-pronged test. For example, she asserts that “religious speech in private schools, such as prayers led by parochial school teachers, becomes mixed speech when the schools accept government vouchers.”260 The Supreme Court, of course, has held that such speech is not attributable to the government in any way, because the government’s money was distributed to private individuals who then voluntarily chose to give it to a religious school rather than a secular one.261 What of religious universities that accept federal grant and loan funds, such as Pell Grants—does all speech in religious universities (even speech by the students) become mixed speech because the universities accept government funds that effectively enable the speech? The beef ads in Johanns, characterized by the Supreme Court as government speech, would apparently become mixed speech,262 as would all government252 Id. at 628. Id. at 640. 254 Id. 255 Id. at 641. 256 Id. at 642. 257 Id. at 643. 258 Id. at 643 n.199. 259 Id. at 646. 260 Id. at 624. 261 See Zelman v. Simmons-Harris, 536 U.S. 639, 652–53 (2002). 262 The beef ads were funded by a federal government program to encourage beef consumption and were communicated to the public through private media outlets. The government was seemingly not the “literal speaker” (prong one) and would not be associated with the speech in the public mind (prong five), but funded the speech (prong three) and exercised significant control over it (prong two). 253 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 407 subsidized “private” speech, including the student publications at issue in Rosenberger.263 Federal and state tax exemptions presumably help to “pay for” speech in churches too—does all speech from the pulpit become mixed speech because of prong three? Other prongs in the five-prong formulation appear to be almost guaranteed to produce equivocal results (and therefore result in an overall finding of mixed speech): the first prong, for example, requires judges to determine the identity of the “literal speaker,” a term which is all too unclear in many speech applications.264 Prong four, analyzing the speech goals of the program in which the speech appears, includes the nebulous terms “program”265 and “speech goals.”266 By the terms of the test, of course, the inability to reach a clear result under any single prong requires a finding of mixed speech.267 Thus, Professor Corbin’s approach means at least this: much speech that courts have previously determined to be “private” or “governmental” would now be treated as “mixed.” Professor Corbin admits that her definition of mixed speech “cuts a wide swath and [would] significantly change First Amendment jurisprudence.”268 Effectively, however, the change would only be as drastic as her prescription for what to do with mixed speech once it has been classified. Along these lines, she proposes applying “some intermediate level of scrutiny to measures that constitute viewpoint discrimination on mixed speech.”269 Her test would allow the government to impose such restrictions only if “(1) it has a closely tailored, substantial interest that is clearly and publicly articulated; (2) it has no alternate means of accomplishing the same goal; and (3) private speakers have alternate means of communicating to the same audience.”270 Applying this “rigorous intermediate scrutiny”271 to specialty license plates, she concludes that most types of viewpoint restrictions would not pass the test, See supra notes 44–50 and accompanying text (providing relevant factual references for Johanns v. Livestock Marketing Association, 544 U.S. 550 (2005)). 263 See Corbin, supra note 27, at 690 n.474 (“The Rosenberger Court’s characterization of the student publication as purely private speech is itself debatable.”). For a brief discussion of Rosenberger, see supra notes 51–54 and accompanying text. 264 See supra note 189 and accompanying text. Professor Corbin, in fact, cautions those applying this prong to be aware that some anonymous speech is hard to trace to any literal speaker, and some ostensibly literal speakers may in fact be working as agents for someone else—in which case, presumably, the literal speaker analysis may change. Corbin, supra note 27, at 629–30. 265 For the difficulties inherent in defining the relevant “program,” see supra notes 186–88 and accompanying text. 266 Professor Corbin notes that for “government-subsidized speech” as well as any “speech in a nonpublic forum,” the results under this prong will “often” be “inconclusive and difficult to evaluate”—which means the speech must be classified as mixed. Corbin, supra note 27, at 643 n.199. 267 Id. at 628. 268 Id. 269 Id. at 675. 270 Id. 271 Id. 408 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 but regulations prohibiting hate speech and religious endorsements would;272 she also suggests that prohibitions on certain other “distasteful” speech, such as “sexually provocative messages,” might pass the test, although she does not explicitly apply intermediate scrutiny to those restrictions.273 In any event, she avers, much of the benefit of intermediate scrutiny would be to force judges to do explicitly what she believes they already do implicitly; applying intermediate scrutiny to a wide range of mixed speech “renders transparent the inevitable balancing [of governmental and private interests] that courts perform.”274 Applying intermediate scrutiny to such a large class of speech restrictions, however, is problematic. First, the many forms of speech that would be swept into this mixed speech category differ from one another in important ways. There are important differences, for example, between a federal grant program funding beef ads that is designed to promote beef consumption,275 on the one hand, and a public university program funding student pamphlets that is designed to foster the expression of diverse student views on campus,276 on the other. The former program is a part of a class of programs in which government has determined to reach an audience with a particular message and has paid private parties to carry that message;277 the latter program is a part of a very different class of programs in which the government has determined to provide resources for private parties to create and convey their own messages.278 These differences might be important enough to justify categorical deference to the government’s viewpoint restrictions within the former type of program and categorical suspicion of such restrictions within the latter type.279 Second, it is not self-evident that the traditional categorical treatment 272 Id. at 681–91. Id. at 687–89. 274 Id. at 691. 275 Johanns v. Livestock Mktg. Ass’n, 544 U.S. 550, 553–55 (2005). 276 Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819, 823–27 (1995). 277 Johanns, 544 U.S. at 560–61. 278 Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 828–29. 279 Indeed, this has been the Supreme Court’s approach to date, as it has applied the government speech doctrine and forum doctrine, respectively, to these cases. See, e.g., Legal Servs. Corp. v. Velazquez, 531 U.S. 533, 541–42 (2001) (contrasting the application of government speech doctrine in Rust with the application of forum doctrine in Rosenberger). And even Professor Corbin does not advocate abandoning the private speech and government speech categories entirely. See Corbin, supra note 27, at 671, 692 n.480 (noting that “where the private or government components are sufficiently attenuated, courts may fairly categorize the speech as purely private or purely governmental”). This is curious if, as she asserts, those categories simply allow judges to mask a secret ad hoc decision process. See id. at 677–78 (stating that “categorizing mixed speech as private or governmental” is problematic because it allows judges to “make a value-informed decision” to label the speech without articulating how they are balancing the competing interests). In other words, if it is so important for judges to balance explicitly the competing interests in mixed speech cases, why should they not do so in all speech cases? Why not subject all speech restrictions to intermediate scrutiny? Might the judgment in a particular case that “private or government components are sufficiently attenuated” itself be masking a behind-the-scenes, value-informed balancing process that is never articulated? 273 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 409 simply masks ad hoc judicial balancing that already goes on behind the scenes—or that if it does, imposing intermediate scrutiny on restrictions of mixed speech will cause judging to be more forthright or consistent. In an effort to force judges to show their cards in mixed speech cases, Professor Corbin would require them to consider explicitly whether a given restriction is supported by a “substantial” governmental interest and whether the government could accomplish the same goal by other means.280 But her evaluation of specialty license plates under this test provides a perfect illustration of the possibility of continued subterfuge. It turns out that, in her view, government reasons for banning particular plate designs are not “substantial” enough unless the designs would endorse religion (such as, perhaps, a “God Bless America” plate) or convey hate speech (such as a Nazi plate). Which governmental interests are prioritized, and which devalued, in reaching such conclusions?281 The ranking of governmental interests in such an analysis is necessarily tied to a behind-the-scenes ranking of the harmfulness of particular viewpoints. Some viewpoints, apparently, are deemed more harmful than others, making the state interest in restriction (or disassociation) more “substantial” for some messages than for others. On what basis would a judge rank various viewpoints according to harmfulness? And would any judge articulate such a ranking? It seems fanciful to expect that intermediate scrutiny will force judges to do so; moreover, a ranking of this sort by a judge or other government official runs directly contrary to the First Amendment value of viewpoint neutrality toward speech. C. Difficulties With the “Hybrid” or “Mixed” Speech Approach More Generally The “hybrid” or “mixed” speech approach is intuitively appealing because it recognizes the overlap at the margins between the conceptual categories of government speech and private speech. By forcing all speech into one of these two categories, we are bound to generalize and, in the process, ignore some key differences. But the hybrid speech category does this, too. In fact, it is the function 280 Corbin, supra note 27, at 675–76 (using the case of specialty license plates to illustrate the application of the “intermediate scrutiny” test and the resulting advantages of its application in the courtroom). 281 Regarding the hypothetical rejection of “God Bless America” plates, the state’s interest in complying with the Establishment Clause probably cannot count as a “substantial” interest, since the Court has suggested that such governmental endorsements of “God” do not violate the clause. See Van Orden v. Perry, 545 U.S. 677, 686–92 (2005) (holding that the placement of a monument inscribed with the Ten Commandments is not a violation of the Establishment Clause); County of Allegheny v. ACLU, 492 U.S. 573, 602–03, 657, 671–74 (1989) (Kennedy, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (joined by Rehnquist, C.J., and White & Scalia, JJ.) (cautioning against placing too much weight on a few religious words that have been used throughout the United States’ heritage). Indeed, our national motto is “In God We Trust.” 36 U.S.C. § 302 (2000). 410 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 of jurisprudential categories to generalize, and the fact that two (or even three) categories do so is not in itself a reason to create a third (or fourth), particularly if the newly minted category does not give judges much guidance for deciding who wins when speech falls within that category. Moreover, there is value, confirmed by long experience, in setting up a presumption against viewpoint restrictions directed against the messages of private speakers. But to apply that presumption effectively, we must distinguish between the messages of private speakers and the messages of public speakers. Arguably, the mixed speech category is not a serious attempt to do that; it looks more like giving up. A broad “mixed” or “hybrid” speech category may even allow government to game the system by actually creating one of the mixedspeech factors in order to convert private speech into mixed speech, thus forcing increased judicial deference to viewpoint restrictions. For instance, when the government wants to oppose a private point of view, it could simply give itself prior approval authority over private speech in some venue and thus claim that the speech is mixed speech because, under prong two, the government exerts substantial “control” over the message. In that case, the restriction itself is being used as evidence that the message is partially the government’s and that the government therefore has a greater interest in imposing the restriction. This is circular. It is not impossible to conceptualize the two-category approach. A government may deny resources to a few disfavored speakers—and even forge alliances with competing speakers—without really intending to send any message of its own. Judges need not sense some element of “government speech” in such arrangements or shield such viewpointbiased discrimination from normal free speech scrutiny. The danger that government will use discriminatory allocations of its property to silence a certain viewpoint or skew debate is no less real when some of the private competing viewpoints (predictably enough) conspire with the government to accomplish this result, or at least to advance their own preferred messages. VI. AN ALTERNATIVE APPROACH: THREE KINDS OF GOVERNMENT SPEECH Assuming we wish to continue allowing the government to send its own messages, it is plainly necessary for judges to be able to identify government speech across a wide range of Speech Clause cases. Additionally, to the extent government may violate the Establishment Clause with its own expression, judges need to be able to identify 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 411 282 government speech in that context as well. It seems desirable to use one uniform test for identifying government speech in all contexts, since there is no obvious reason to define the term differently in Speech Clause and Establishment Clause cases. As noted in Parts IV and V, neither the fourpronged test nor the hybrid speech approach shows much promise of helping judges make more uniform or objective decisions, nor do these approaches track closely the jurisprudence of the Supreme Court in the area of government speech. This section suggests a simpler approach to identifying government speech, a test which explains and reconciles the holdings of the Supreme Court across the gamut of its speech and establishment cases. Additionally, this section argues that this simpler test offers a more accurate measurement of what matters in the definition of government speech and, because it is less subjective than the alternatives, is likely to result in more judicial consistency as well. The Supreme Court has found government speech to be present in perhaps three key circumstances. Accordingly, the proposed test would pose three questions: (1) Did the government independently generate the idea of reaching an audience with this particular message in this medium? (2) Was the message expressed in a medium or format effectively owned and controlled by government and clearly reserved for the purpose of expressing only those messages the government regards as its own, never opened to multiple private speakers for the purpose of raising revenue or supporting their speech or welfare? (3) Is there a clear literal speaker who is employed by the government to send messages on this subject in this format? If any of the above questions must clearly be answered in the affirmative, then the message is government speech; otherwise, the message is private speech. The remainder of this section explains each of these three circumstances in more detail. A. Did the Government Independently Generate the Idea of Reaching an Audience with This Particular Message in This Medium? A central concept in the whole notion of government speech is the idea 282 See infra notes 381–88 and accompanying text (discussing Establishment Clause violations caused by certain kinds of government speech). 412 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 283 that government should be free to express its own messages. But how do we know whether the message is really “its own message” or, instead, that of a private party? This first factor focuses on the most obvious meaning of “its own message”: that the government came up with the message in the first place, or at least embraced it enough to generate the idea of communicating it to an audience in this medium. In Rust v. Sullivan—the case which, according to the Supreme Court, contained the first exposition of the government speech doctrine— Congress came up with the idea of reaching an audience (the clients of family planning clinics) with a particular message (encouraging family planning without abortion) through the “medium” of the advice rendered by physicians and staff working in the clinics.284 The Court clearly believed all of this was Congress’s idea, a finding which was crucial in classifying the message as government speech: “The Government can, without violating the Constitution, selectively fund a program to encourage certain activities it believes to be in the public interest, without at the same time funding an alternative program which seeks to deal with the problem in another way.”285 The Court later described the Rust opinion as showing that the government can “use[] private speakers to transmit specific information pertaining to its own program” and “to promote a particular policy of its own.”286 Similarly in Johanns, the Court’s conclusion that the beef ads constituted government speech was anchored in the finding that “[t]he message set out in the beef promotions is from beginning to end the message established by the Federal Government.”287 The fact that the literal speakers were private entities, and the fact that some private actors exercised some editorial control in the creation of the ads, were factors of secondary importance, at most: “When, as here, the government sets the overall message to be communicated and approves every word that is disseminated, it is not precluded from relying on the government-speech doctrine merely because it solicits assistance from nongovernmental sources in developing specific messages.”288 The fact that the government “sets the overall message” is surely crucial to a finding of government speech. Just as certainly in other cases, the fact that the government did not “set the overall message” was an important factor in the Court’s determination that the message constituted private speech. Hence, in 283 See Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819, 833 (1995) (“[W]e have permitted the government to regulate the content of what is or is not expressed when it is the speaker or when it enlists private entities to convey its own message.”). 284 Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U.S. 173, 178–81, 193–94 (1991). 285 Id. at 193. 286 Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 833 (emphasis added). 287 Johanns v. Livestock Mktg. Ass’n, 544 U.S. 550, 560–61 (2005) (emphasis added). 288 Id. at 562 (emphasis added). 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 413 Rosenberger, the Court found viewpoint restrictions on university-funded student speech to be improper because the government had not crafted or “favor[ed]” any particular message but instead had “expend[ed] funds to encourage a diversity of views from private speakers.”289 Similarly, in Southworth, although the university made no claim that the statesubsidized student extracurricular speech was government speech, the Court recognized that viewpoint discrimination might be permissible if “the state-controlled University’s . . . own funds [were being used] to advance a particular message.”290 And in Velazquez, while recognizing that the federal funding program for legal services attorneys was not designed with the purpose of “encourag[ing] a diversity of views,” the Court emphasized that viewpoint discrimination was improper because the program was not designed “to promote a governmental message.”291 The attorneys receiving this governmental funding would in fact be representing clients in claims against the government; therefore, the government could not have intended these attorneys to convey a particular message set by the government, “even under a generous understanding of the concept [of governmental speech].”292 Governments might conceivably “set the overall message” either by crafting the message themselves or by adopting a message or slogan originally developed by others. In this latter case, however, it is important to be sure that the government has in some meaningful sense originated the communication, rather than just selectively subsidizing private communication, a move that would skew private debate and perhaps run afoul of existing forum doctrine.293 The origination question attends to this concern by asking whether it was the government’s idea to use this medium to reach an audience with the particular message being sent. For example, if the government wants to embrace the privately originated slogan “Just Do It” as part of a government program to encourage fitness, the fact that Nike originally crafted the slogan should not prevent a finding of government speech when the government pays for the development and broadcast of television ads containing the slogan. Assuming Nike and the government reached an agreement as to the government’s use of the slogan, the crucial factor to consider is whether the government intentionally embraced the slogan and originated the idea of running these television ads containing it. If so, then those ads constitute government 289 290 Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 834. Bd. of Regents of Univ. of Wis. Sys. v. Southworth, 529 U.S. 217, 229 (2000) (emphasis added). 291 Legal Servs. Corp. v. Velazquez, 531 U.S. 533, 542 (2001). Id. at 542–43. 293 See supra note 2 and accompanying text. 292 414 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 294 speech. On the other hand, this kind of government speech will not include the types of messages that the Supreme Court has held to be private speech in a government forum. For example, a message expressed by demonstrators in city streets and parks will not be deemed government speech under question one because it was the private speakers’ idea, not the government’s, to reach an audience with this particular message.295 The government’s idea was not to send an “overall message,” but rather to open up public property for the expression of various yet-to-be-determined private messages. Likewise, the messages expressed in student group publications on public university campuses will not constitute government speech under question one, because it was not the school’s idea to reach an audience with the particular messages contained in the publications.296 If these messages do not count as government speech under the other two questions either, then the messages would be private speech, and it follows that governmental viewpoint discrimination in such contexts would be impermissible.297 By the same token, messages endorsing religion in such forums would raise no Establishment Clause concerns because there would be no state action embracing the particular message; the governmental role was limited to opening up government resources to private speakers on a viewpoint-neutral and religion-neutral basis.298 294 Of course, other ads featuring the slogan “Just Do It” would not be government speech, to the extent that Nike and not the government came up with the idea of reaching an audience with those particular ads. 295 See, e.g., Capitol Square Review & Advisory Bd. v. Pinette, 515 U.S. 753, 757–60 (1995) (holding that the placement of unattended holiday displays in a state-owned plaza known for public events was protected private speech); Hague v. CIO, 307 U.S. 496, 515–16 (1939) (“Wherever the title of streets and parks may rest, they have immemorially been held in trust for the use of the public and . . . have been used for purposes of assembly, communicating thoughts between citizens, and discussing public questions.”). 296 See Bd. of Regents of Univ. of Wis. Sys. v. Southworth, 529 U.S. 217, 229 (2000) (holding that the government’s rights were not at issue because the expression sprang “from the initiative of the students, who alone give it purpose and content,” and not the state-controlled university); Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819, 833–35 (1995) (noting a difference between permissible government regulation of state university speech and impermissible viewpoint discrimination against private student speech, even when it receives university funding). 297 See Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 828–30, 834 (reviewing cases in which the Court struck down viewpoint discrimination against private speech); Capitol Square, 515 U.S. at 761 (holding that while the state may regulate the “time, place, and manner” of private speech in public forums, it is sharply restricted in regulating “content”); see also Int’l Soc’y for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee, 505 U.S. 672, 678–79 (1992) (noting that governmental discrimination based on viewpoint is forbidden in all speech forums). 298 See Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 839–42 (noting the acceptability of state university funding directed to a student religious publication when the university funded all student journals); Capitol Square, 515 U.S. at 762–63 (reiterating the maxim that private religious speech in a public forum does not equal the government endorsement of religion). 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 415 B. Was the Message Expressed in a Medium or Format Effectively Owned and Controlled by Government and Clearly Reserved for the Purpose of Expressing Only Those Messages the Government Regards as Its Own, Never Opened to Multiple Private Speakers for the Purpose of Raising Revenue or Supporting Their Speech or Welfare? While the first question of the three-question test will likely be sufficient to identify the majority of government speech, a relatively small amount of what the Court has considered government speech does not arise in that way. In fact, in an opinion just issued in Pleasant Grove City v. Summum, the Supreme Court has clarified that government speech can also be created when a government accepts, embraces, and communicates a donated message.299 Private entities may originate messages and design communicative media containing those messages, and then donate the media/messages to the government. If the government chooses to reject the donation, as it surely would have a right to do,300 then presumably no government speech arises from the attempted donation;301 but if the government chooses to accept and display the donated property, the government now owns and controls the property and may have embraced communication of the message so strongly that the message of that particular display ought to be regarded as governmental speech.302 This would seem particularly true if the display, or the property on which it is erected, has been clearly reserved for the expression of government messages rather than being opened to multiple private speakers. A common scenario is the donated monument. Suppose a private civic group designs and pays for construction of a six-foot-tall granite monument containing the text of the Ten Commandments, and then offers to donate the monument to a state government for display on the grounds of the state capitol building, where nearly forty other state-owned historical monuments and markers are displayed over twenty-two acres.303 The state chooses to accept the donation and allow the display, so the state selects the precise site for the monument, and the group pays for the erection of 299 Pleasant Grove City v. Summum, 129 S. Ct. 1125, 1138 (2009). See, e.g., Knights of the Ku Klux Klan v. Curators of the Univ. of Mo., 203 F.3d 1085, 1089, 1093–95 (8th Cir. 2000), cert. denied, 531 U.S. 814 (2000) (holding that a publicly owned radio station was permitted to reject the donation of funds from the Ku Klux Klan, and refuse to acknowledge such donation on air, based on viewpoint and reputation of the Klan). 301 See id. In Knights, the Eighth Circuit found that the government’s on-air acknowledgements of underwriters constituted government speech—but of course, the Klan’s particular message did not constitute government speech, since the government rejected the donation and refused to acknowledge the Klan. See id. at 1093. 302 Again, the same message on a different, privately owned display on private property would not be government speech under this factor, just as a privately originated “Just Do It” ad would not count as government speech under the first factor. E.g., supra note 294 and accompanying text. 303 The facts presented here are taken from Van Orden v. Perry, 545 U.S. 677, 681–82 (2005) (plurality opinion). 300 416 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 the monument there and also adds an inscription naming the group and specifying that the group “presented” the monument to “the people and youth” of the state.304 The first question of this Article’s three-factor test will not clearly indicate in this scenario that the monument is government speech, because it was the private organization, not the government, that independently generated the idea of reaching an audience with this particular message in this medium. The government did not come up with the idea for the monument independently, but only erected it at the suggestion of the private group. Answering the second question, however, clarifies that the monument is indeed government speech; the media, both the monument and the capitol grounds, were owned and controlled by the government and clearly reserved for expressing only those messages that the government regarded as its own. The media and format are important. Here, although the government may (at least implicitly) invite private speakers to demonstrate in person in its parks or other public spaces, the city has not even implicitly invited private parties to erect unattended, permanent monuments there. The format of the park and the monuments standing in it strongly indicate that unattended park monuments are reserved for government messages. The Supreme Court focused on exactly these considerations while addressing very similar facts in Pleasant Grove.305 The Court noted that one could assume the public grounds were never opened generally to private speakers’ monuments for the purpose of encouraging private speech or raising revenue, and the government did not actively encourage donations of monuments; every donated monument had likely been screened by the government, not just to assure that no distasteful message was present, but to assure that the message was something the government wanted to say—something “worthy” of being displayed on the grounds.306 The donated monument may have begun as private speech, but under these circumstances, when the government accepted and displayed it, it became government speech. The upshot of this determination is that no private speech rights are violated when the government refuses to accept and display some other group’s donation; and on the other hand, any religious endorsements on successfully donated and displayed monuments must be considered the state’s expression for Establishment Clause purposes. This, indeed, seems to be the way the Supreme Court has viewed such monuments even before the most recent term—although in 2005 the Court determined, on one set of facts involving Ten Commandments monuments, 304 Id. Pleasant Grove City v. Summum, 129 S. Ct. 1125, 1132–35 (2009). 306 Id. at 1132–34. 305 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 417 307 that such a state expression did not violate the Establishment Clause. Moreover, the reasoning in Pleasant Grove suggests that a “donated” display could be considered government speech even if legal ownership of the donated property itself were less clear, as long as the other considerations noted above were still present and the government exercised a sort of effective ownership and control over the display. Thus if a monument were designed and funded by a private group, and the group then asked the government for permission to erect it as a permanent fixture on government property in front of the county courthouse,308 the government’s affirmative grant of permission would arguably convert the monument’s message into government speech, whether or not the government ever became the legal owner of the monument.309 Similarly, the Supreme Court has found an improper governmental endorsement of religion—which indicates that the government was expressing something—when a government agreed to allow a private organization to display a crèche on government property and to store the crèche in a governmental storeroom when it was not being displayed.310 This case involved both a crèche and a menorah. The crèche was technically the property of a private Catholic organization called the Holy Name Society,311 and the menorah was technically the property of a private Jewish organization called Chabad,312 but both the crèche and the menorah remained at all times on government property, being stored and maintained by the government even when not on display, and were decorated by government employees during the holiday season.313 The menorah was even assembled, erected, and disassembled by government employees,314 307 See Van Orden, 545 U.S. at 691–92 (plurality opinion) (referring to monuments on the grounds of Texas State Capitol as “[Texas’s] Capitol grounds monuments” and upholding the display of a Ten Commandments monument because “Texas’ display of this monument” did not violate Establishment Clause (emphasis added)); id. at 702 (Breyer, J., concurring in judgment) (“[T]he State sought to reflect moral principles.”). While I assert that Ten Commandments monuments under these circumstances constitute government speech, and also that a majority of justices suggested as much in Van Orden, I express no opinion here regarding the ultimate outcome in Van Orden or the proper application of the Establishment Clause to such monuments. 308 See Staley v. Harris County, 461 F.3d 504, 506–07 (5th Cir. 2006), vacated as moot, 485 F.3d 305 (5th Cir. 2007) (referring to the placement of a privately constructed monument at the main entrance of a courthouse). 309 The Fifth Circuit found that such a display, which contained an open Bible, violated the Establishment Clause because “the monument . . . had come to have a predominately religious purpose.” Id. at 515. Since private entities and their messages cannot violate the Establishment Clause, the opinion seems to be premised on the assumption that the government was speaking by displaying this monument. The opinion nowhere mentions who legally owned the monument after it was erected—perhaps because no one knew. The consideration seems to have been irrelevant. 310 ACLU v. County of Allegheny, 842 F.2d 655, 657 (3d Cir. 1988), aff’d in part, rev’d in part, 492 U.S. 573 (1989). 311 Id. at 657. 312 County of Allegheny v. ACLU, 492 U.S. 573, 587 (1989) (Blackmun, J., joined by Stevens & O’Connor, JJ.). 313 ACLU, 842 F.2d at 657–58. 314 Id.; County of Allegheny, 492 U.S. at 587 (Blackmun, J., joined by Stevens & O’Connor, JJ.). 418 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 and the crèche was flanked by a plaque stating that the crèche had been “‘Donated by the Holy Name Society.’”315 A majority of the Court found that, under the circumstances, the government had impermissibly endorsed religion by allowing display of the crèche;316 while a different majority found that by allowing display of the menorah, flanked by a large Christmas tree and a sign saluting liberty, the government had either endorsed something besides religion,317 or had endorsed religion permissibly.318 But in any case, the analysis suggests that both displays involved government speech—that is, governmental endorsement of something—notwithstanding the fact that the crèche and the menorah were technically owned by private groups.319 Although it is a closer case, the government’s broadcast of the messages written by donors in Knights probably also gave rise to government speech.320 In that case, a government-owned radio station received monetary donations from a variety of private entities and was required under federal law to “acknowledge[] on air any individual or group source of funding for a particular broadcast matter,” although the acknowledgements had to be “value neutral” and could not “promote” the donor.321 The announcement might be drafted in the first instance by the donor itself or by the government, but the wording of all such underwriting announcements had to be approved by the government before being read on air by a government employee.322 Not all speech broadcast by public stations is the same type of speech. The Supreme Court noted two years prior to Knights that “[w]hen a public broadcaster exercises editorial discretion in the selection and presentation of its programming, it engages in speech activity,” and that “[such] programming decisions . . . constitute communicative acts.”323 The Court also held in that case, however, that “candidate debates [broadcast by 315 County of Allegheny, 492 U.S. at 580 (Blackmun, J., joined by Stevens & O’Connor, JJ.). Id. at 601–02 (Blackmun, J., joined by Brennan, Marshall, Stevens, & O’Connor, JJ.). Id. at 616 (Blackmun, J.). 318 Id. at 662–63, 670–71 (Kennedy, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (joined by Rehnquist, C.J., and White & Scalia, JJ.). 319 See infra notes 381–82 and accompanying text; see also Wells v. City & County of Denver, 257 F.3d 1132 (10th Cir. 2001), supra Part IV.A. (discussing Wells). The holiday display in Wells seems to have been the property of the government, either donated by private entities or partially funded by them. See id. at 1137–38. But even if the components of the display, including the sign, had all been created by private sponsors and donated to the city for display on public property, it is difficult to believe the court would have concluded under the four-pronged test that the message involved private and not government speech. See id. at 1141–43 (applying the test and concluding that the display constituted government speech). And this result would be the same under the second question of the test this Article proposes for identifying government speech. 320 Knights of the Ku Klux Klan v. Curators of the Univ. of Mo., 203 F.3d 1085, 1087–89 (8th Cir. 2000) (stating the facts of the case). 321 Id. at 1088. 322 Id. at 1088, 1094 n.10. 323 Ark. Educ. Television Comm’n v. Forbes, 523 U.S. 666, 674 (1998). 316 317 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 419 324 public broadcasters] present the narrow exception to the rule” and constitute a nonpublic speech forum.325 These results are predictable under the test this Article suggests. When public broadcasters choose what to broadcast, the content choices are government speech under question one of the three-question test, because the government came up with the idea of reaching an audience in this medium with that content. In analyzing candidate debates, however, the focus shifts to the particular messages delivered by each candidate. The government in no way endorses what each candidate says, simply by broadcasting the debate. The debate—to the extent it is broadcast by a public broadcasting station—thus constitutes a government-provided speech forum of some type for private speakers. Applying the three-question tests yields the same result: the government did not independently generate the idea of reaching an audience with a particular candidate’s message (say, decreasing taxes or building a new road); nor was the literal speaker a government employee; and while the medium and format in which the messages appeared were effectively owned by the government, the medium and format were not clearly reserved for the purpose of expressing government-approved messages. The more difficult question is the classification of the underwriting announcements in Knights. The Eighth Circuit found the messages to constitute government speech.326 The second factor of the three-factor test suggests this result as well. Factor one would not indicate government speech because the government did not come up with the idea of reaching an audience with the particular message drafted by, say, the Smith Charitable Trust. But under the circumstances, the second factor is probably satisfied because the government-owned medium and format here were clearly reserved for the purpose of expressing government messages, not to raise revenue or encourage private speech. The revenue-raising part of the analysis is the closest call, but on the whole, the acknowledgement program does not seem to have been put in place to encourage donations to the station, but rather to satisfy legal requirements, and perhaps secondarily, to give donors a “free gift”—akin to the ubiquitous tote bag offered to donors by a number of charitable organizations.327 The “message,” in the form of written words on a piece of paper, may or may not have been “donated” by a private group along with its money, but the government’s affirmative decision to accept and read the donated message—along with all the other facts present here, including government ownership and control of the medium—makes this look like government 324 Id. at 675. Id. at 676. Knights, 203 F.3d at 1093. 327 See id. (noting that the program is enforced by federal statute and is an “acknowledgement” and not a promotion). 325 326 420 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 speech. In addition, the fact that private speakers were never allowed to speak freely on public radio underwriting spots—value bias and promotion of products or organizations being forbidden by the government—makes this program substantially different from governmental programs widely inviting the public to buy ad space to promote private groups and messages,328 and suggests that even privately composed underwriting messages constitute government speech when they are accepted, approved, and read on air by government employees in order to comply with federal law. C. Is There a Clear Literal Speaker Who Is Employed by the Government to Send Messages on This Subject in This Format? The first and second questions of the proposed test will likely identify most of the speech the Supreme Court has called “government speech” in its cases to date. But the Supreme Court has suggested in Garcetti v. Ceballos329 that there may be one further way a message could be deemed government speech. Hence, the third question is included here. In Garcetti, a deputy district attorney wrote a memorandum to his supervisors recommending dismissal of a pending criminal case due to misrepresentations contained in an affidavit that had been used to obtain a critical search warrant.330 His supervisors decided to proceed with the prosecution anyway, and the trial court later rejected the defense’s challenge to the warrant.331 In a subsequent action invoking his rights under the Speech Clause, the deputy district attorney claimed that after these events he was subjected to a series of adverse employment actions which were designed to retaliate against him for the memorandum.332 The Court rejected his First Amendment claim on the ground that “his expressions were made pursuant to his duties as a calendar deputy” and therefore did not constitute protected private speech: “[W]hen public employees make statements pursuant to their official duties, the employees are not speaking as citizens for First Amendment purposes . . . .”333 In other words, those statements are government speech, not private speech. This holding fits tolerably well with the government speech doctrine, at least if one may assume that government employees who speak “pursuant to their official duties” have been hired by their employers to convey the government’s messages. In such cases, the employee’s governmental superiors must be allowed to approve the messages even 328 For a discussion of such programs, see infra notes 354–62 and accompanying text. 547 U.S. 410, 421 (2006). 330 Id. at 413–14. 331 Id. at 414–15. 332 Id. at 415. 333 Id. at 421. 329 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 421 before they are released, as well as to discipline the employee after publication if she failed to tailor the message to the government’s expectations about the content of what is, after all, its own message.334 On the other hand, if the message does not arise from the employee’s messagesending duties—if the speaker is not employed to send messages on this subject in this medium—then the message might well constitute private speech, particularly if it concerns a matter of public interest.335 And of course, if it is unclear who the “literal speaker” is, the speech cannot be the kind of speech that the Court found in Garcetti.336 The third factor of the proposed government speech test is designed to make sure Garcetti speech is identified as government speech, assuming there might be cases where neither of the first two factors clearly indicate this. Of course, the speech appearing within a calendar deputy’s disposition memo will constitute government speech under the first factor if “the government” may be said to have come up with the idea of rendering the particular advice contained in the memo; but where a government employee expresses a viewpoint at odds with that of his supervisors, as in Garcetti, it will be difficult to reach such a conclusion. Under the second factor of my test, the memo will constitute government speech if the medium and format (here, intra-office memos sent by government employees within a government office) were effectively owned and controlled by the government and reserved for the purpose of expressing government-approved messages, not private speech. It might well be thought that the Garcetti facts indicate precisely this kind of government speech. But on the other hand, one might argue, the very fact 334 I do not intend to express any view about the difficult cases that may arise in particular applications of the Garcetti rule—for example, when employment status or duties are unclear. See id. at 424–25 (noting that the scope of an employee’s duties could be a matter for “serious debate” in future cases, and noting that speech by academics that is “related to scholarship or teaching” could present an especially difficult case); id. at 436, 438–39 (Souter, J., dissenting). In such cases, the third question might not indicate government speech. Similarly, the third question would not indicate government speech if the identity of the “literal speaker” were unclear in a particular case. For a discussion of some of the difficulties in identifying “literal speakers,” see supra notes 189–90 and accompanying text. 335 See Garcetti, 547 U.S. at 419 (“[S]o long as employees are speaking as citizens about matters of public concern, they must face only those speech restrictions that are necessary for their employers to operate efficiently and effectively.” (internal citations omitted)); Pickering v. Bd. of Educ. of Twp. High Sch. Dist. 205, 391 U.S. 563, 568, 573–74 (1968) (“Statements by public officials on matters of public concern must be accorded First Amendment protection despite the fact that the statements are directed at their nominal superiors.”). 336 No doubt “literal speakers” are difficult to identify in many situations. See supra notes 189–90 and accompanying text (illustrating this difficulty). But this poses no difficulty in prong three of the proposed test, because whenever a literal speaker cannot clearly be identified, the solution is clear: there can be no finding of government speech under this prong. In other words, unlike the fourpronged test, the test does not require the identification of a “literal speaker” of every message; the “literal speaker” factor is not serving as one of several factors to be weighed together in distinguishing between government and private speech in every situation. Question three merely sniffs out one kind of government speech: the kind arising when there clearly is a literal speaker employed by the government and having particular job responsibilities. 422 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 that “rogue memos” like this one are sent belies effective governmental control of the medium and indicates that not all messages sent in this medium and format are “government-approved.” Additionally, it might be argued, the Garcetti Court did not focus on government ownership and control of the medium, but upon the employment status and duties of the literal speaker.337 Accordingly, the third factor is offered here to cover the instance of the employee paid by the government to send government messages, who then sends messages contrary to the government’s wishes; the purpose is to make doubly sure that speech sent pursuant to such duties—even noncompliant speech—is classified as government speech in cases where employment status and duties to send government messages are clear.338 Not only does this treatment accord with Supreme Court precedent, but it is probably necessitated by the whole notion of government speech. The government needs to be able to assure that those it employs to convey government speech are doing so accurately; if the government cannot control the content of its intended messages, the government speech doctrine would become a nullity.339 VII. USING THE THREE-PART TEST TO UNDERSTAND PAST AND FUTURE CASES A. Explaining Supreme Court Precedents The three-part test for identifying government speech is intended to be descriptive. I have suggested the test, not just as a straightforward way of measuring what seems to be the essence of government speech, but also as a method of describing what the Supreme Court has actually found to be government speech. In other words, the three-factor test provides a method of reconciling the Supreme Court precedents. Applying the test to the Court’s establishment and free speech cases yields results that mirror those reached by the Court. 1. Private Speech As a starting point, the Court has been clear that governmental funding of speech does not always create government speech. The Court has squarely held that “even in the provision of subsidies, the government may 337 See Garcetti, 547 U.S. at 420–22 (noting that a “controlling factor” in Ceballos’s case was that his speech was made pursuant to his duties “as a calendar deputy”). 338 See supra note 334 (discussing this aspect of the third factor). 339 See Garcetti, 547 U.S. at 422–23 (“Official communications have official consequences, creating a need for substantive consistency and clarity. [Governmental] [s]upervisors must ensure that their employees’ official communications are accurate, demonstrate sound judgment, and promote the employer’s mission.”). 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 423 340 not ‘ai[m] at the suppression of dangerous ideas,’” a holding that only makes sense if government-funded speech sometimes constitutes private, not government, speech. Hence, when a federal program disbursed grants to fund only art which program administrators considered to be of sufficient artistic merit and sufficiently representative of “general standards of decency,” the art thus subsidized was deemed private speech and the funding restrictions were required to be viewpoint-neutral, although no forum for speech was created.341 Similarly, when a federal program disbursed grants to pay legal services attorneys to represent private clients in claims against the federal government, the subsidized attorneys’ speech was deemed private speech and the funding restrictions were required to be viewpoint-neutral, although no forum for speech was created.342 And when the government expends its own funds to acquire books, internet connections and terminals, or other materials and resources for a public library or public school library, the Court has indicated that the messages contained in the materials and resources thus acquired still constitute private and not government speech, although the library is not a forum for speech.343 Decisions to remove materials from an existing library collection therefore must be viewpoint-neutral,344 although the Court has 340 Nat’l Endowment for the Arts v. Finley, 524 U.S. 569, 587 (1998) (quoting Regan v. Taxation With Representation of Wash., 461 U.S. 540, 550 (1983)). 341 See Finley, 524 U.S. at 586–87 (“If the NEA were to leverage its power to award subsidies on the basis of subjective criteria into a penalty on disfavored viewpoints, then we would confront a different case.”); see also id. at 611 (“The Government freely admits . . . that it neither speaks through the expression subsidized . . . nor buys anything for itself with its . . . grants.”) (Souter, J., dissenting); FCC v. League of Women Voters, 468 U.S. 364, 366 (1984) (holding that a federal statute violated the Speech Clause by forbidding public broadcasting grants to be distributed to broadcasting stations that “engage in editorializing”; such editorials are private speech protected by the Speech Clause; and the funding restriction was too coercive); Hannegan v. Esquire, Inc., 327 U.S. 146, 148–58 (1946) (finding that a postmaster violated the Speech Clause when he exercised authority to revoke second-class mailing privileges for publications he deemed to be insufficiently advancing public welfare; although speech contained in second-class mailings was subsidized by government, it was still private speech protected by the First Amendment, and the postmaster’s content rules were too arbitrary and restrictive); cf. Ysursa v. Pocatello Educ. Ass’n, 129 S. Ct. 1093, 1100–01 (2009) (finding that a state law prohibiting public employee payroll deductions to fund a union’s political activities did not violate the Speech Clause; although the union’s political activities constituted private speech, the payroll restriction was viewpoint-neutral); Regan, 461 U.S. at 540 (federal tax regulations did not violate the Speech Clause by denying certain beneficial tax status to private organizations that devoted a substantial part of their activities to political lobbying; although the lobbying messages constituted private speech protected under First Amendment, the regulations were viewpoint-neutral). 342 Legal Servs. Corp. v. Velazquez, 531 U.S. 533, 541–43, 547–49 (2001). 343 See United States v. Am. Library Ass’n, Inc., 539 U.S. 194, 203–07 (2003) (plurality opinion) (noting that internet access, in a public library, bought with public funds, facilitates communication by private parties but does not constitute a public forum for such speech); see also id. at 236 (Souter, J., dissenting) (“[I]n extreme cases [one could] expect particular [book acquisition] choices [by public libraries] to reveal impermissible reasons (reasons even the plurality would consider to be illegitimate), like excluding books because their authors are Democrats or their critiques of organized Christianity are unsympathetic.”); Bd. of Educ. v. Pico, 457 U.S. 853, 866–72 (1982) (plurality opinion). 344 See Pico, 457 U.S. at 870–72 (holding that “local school boards may not remove books from school library shelves simply because they dislike the ideas contained in those books”). 424 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 suggested that heightened judicial scrutiny is inappropriate in the context of decisions, necessitated by limited funds, whether to acquire certain materials in the first place.345 The three-factor test would likewise indicate private speech in each of the instances above, even if no forum was created. In none of these cases did the government independently generate the idea of reaching an audience with any of the particular subsidized messages; nor were the funded messages expressed in a medium or format effectively owned by government and clearly reserved for government messages; nor was the literal speaker a governmental employee. But varying the facts slightly could yield a different result. For example, if the government expends funds as a patron commissioning particular works of art for display to the public on public property, the funded artwork might well constitute government speech, for two independently sufficient reasons: (1) the government may have independently come up with the idea for the particular work of art and for its ultimate display in this medium, before the work was commissioned; and (2) when the artwork was finally displayed, the medium and format of the display would be effectively owned by the government and likely reserved for governmental messages, not opened to multiple private speakers.346 Of course, when the government does create or maintain a speech forum, at least some speech within that forum will be private speech,347 and the restrictions on use of the forum must be viewpoint-neutral.348 Unfortunately, the Court has not been entirely clear about what counts as a “forum” for these purposes. The Court has distinguished between the “traditional public forum,” the “designated public forum, whether of a limited or unlimited character,” and “all remaining public property.”349 Since that enumeration, the Court has also suggested, logically enough, that there is an important distinction to be made within the latter category between a “nonpublic forum” and other public property which is not a 345 See Am. Library Ass’n, 539 U.S. at 205 (“Just as forum analysis and heightened judicial scrutiny are incompatible with the role of public television stations and the role of the National Endowment for the Arts, they are also incompatible with the discretion that public libraries must have to fulfill their traditional missions.”); see also Pico, 457 U.S. at 871–72 (“[N]othing in our decision today affects in any way the discretion of a local school board to choose books to add to the libraries of their schools . . . . [O]ur holding today affects only the discretion to remove books.”). 346 See Finley, 524 U.S. at 610–11 (Souter, J., dissenting) (noting the permissibility of viewpoint discrimination in such contexts). 347 See supra notes 233–38 and accompanying text. 348 See, e.g., Perry Educ. Ass’n v. Perry Local Educators’ Ass’n, 460 U.S. 37, 45–46 (1983) (noting that when governmental property functions as any kind of speech forum, whether public or nonpublic, the government may not “suppress expression [in the forum] merely because public officials oppose the speaker’s view”). 349 See, e.g., Int’l Soc’y for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee, 505 U.S. 672, 678–79 (1992) (defining each of the three types of forums). 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 425 350 forum of any type. The distinction is important because the existence of a forum—even a nonpublic one—will suggest the presence of private speech351 and the requirement of viewpoint neutrality,352 which will not be the case with all public property. The Court has not always used forum language precisely, a fact which sometimes poses challenges for understanding the Court’s conclusions and reconciling those with the government speech doctrine. In Lehman v. City of Shaker Heights,353 a leading Supreme Court case about governmental programs to sell advertising space, a city sold ad space on public transit cars to a variety of commercial and non-commercial speakers.354 In upholding a city rule excluding political advertising from the ad space, a plurality of the Court stopped short of characterizing the ads as some kind of government speech, but did state flatly that “[n]o First Amendment forum is here to be found.”355 Taken literally, that means the ad space did not constitute even a nonpublic forum. But Lehman was decided a decade before the forum doctrine was fully announced in Cornelius356 and Perry Education Association,357 and the literal reading does not square well with later opinions suggesting that forums are created when public property is opened to a variety of private speakers, such as advertisers358 or political candidates.359 Indeed, lower courts have subsequently interpreted the statement in Lehman to mean “no public forum is here to be found,” and that advertising spaces such as those at issue in Lehman constitute nonpublic forums.360 Even the Supreme Court itself has suggested this 350 See Ark. Educ. Television Comm’n v. Forbes, 523 U.S. 666, 676 (1998) (noting that when a public television station aired a debate among political candidates, “the . . . debate was a forum of some type” and that “[t]he question of what type must be answered by reference to our public forum precedents” (emphasis added)); see also id. at 677 (“Other government properties are either nonpublic fora or not fora at all.”). 351 See supra notes 233–38 and accompanying text. 352 See supra note 348 and accompanying text. 353 418 U.S. 298, 303 (1974) (plurality opinion). 354 Id. at 300–01. 355 Id. at 304. 356 Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense & Educ. Fund, Inc., 473 U.S. 788, 804–06 (1985) (holding that solicitation in the context of the Combined Federal Campaign is speech in a nonpublic forum). 357 Perry Educ. Ass’n v. Perry Local Educators’ Ass’n, 460 U.S. 37, 45–46 (1983) (finding that an interschool mail system was a nonpublic forum). 358 See Int’l Soc’y for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Lee, 505 U.S. 672, 675, 679 (1992) (finding airport terminals to be “generally accessible to the general public,” to contain “various commercial establishments such as restaurants, snack stands, bars, newsstands, and stores of various types,” and to be “nonpublic fora” for expression); see also Cornelius, 473 U.S. at 806 (finding that an annual fundraising drive in the federal workplace constituted “a nonpublic forum”). 359 See Ark. Educ. Television Comm’n v. Forbes, 523 U.S. 666, 675–76 (1998) (holding that a publicly owned television station did not violate the First Amendment when it refused to allow a candidate to participate in the nonpublic forum of a televised debate). 360 See DiLoreto v. Downey Unified Sch. Dist. Bd. of Educ., 196 F.3d 958, 965–67 (9th Cir. 1999) (citing Lehman as support for the holding that the advertising space on a public high school’s baseball field fence was a nonpublic forum); N.Y. Magazine v. Metro. Transp. Auth., 136 F.3d 123, 426 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 361 interpretation in a later case. Probably the best reading of Lehman, then, is that the Court found the approved ads to constitute private speech in a nonpublic forum. The three-factor test would likewise suggest that the ads constituted private speech: The government did not come up with the idea to promote a certain brand of cigarettes or a certain church on public transit cars;362 nor were the ad spaces clearly reserved for government-endorsed messages; nor was the literal speaker a government employee. Many times, of course, the existence of a forum is more obvious. Hence when a city maintains a public square and allows a variety of religious and non-religious private demonstrators to express themselves there, the demonstrators’ messages are private speech (notwithstanding their location on public property and amidst public buildings), and as such do not raise Establishment Clause concerns when they endorse religion.363 Moreover, when a public university subsidizes a fund which pays for the speech of a variety of student groups, the university has created a speech forum, the funded speech is private speech, and the funding restrictions must be viewpoint-neutral.364 And when a public school offers its facilities to a variety of private groups for “social, civic, or recreational uses” but denies use “by any group for religious purposes,”365 the school has created a speech forum, the speech in the forum is private speech, and the restriction forbidding religious uses cannot stand because it is not viewpoint-neutral.366 The three-factor test would likewise indicate private speech in each of these instances involving forums. The government did not independently generate the idea of reaching an audience with any particular message 129 (2d Cir. 1998) (noting that the Court in Lehman “ha[d] considered the forum non-public”). Sometimes, where past governmental policies have allowed broad access to the government’s ad space, courts have even distinguished Lehman and have found the space to constitute a designated public forum. See Christ’s Bride Ministries, Inc. v. Southeastern Pa. Transp. Auth., 148 F.3d 242, 255 (3d Cir. 1998) (“SEPTA has no long-standing practice of prohibiting ads like [the ones at issue in the case] . . . nor does it have any policy pursuant to which [the] ads were removed . . . . Because we find that SEPTA has created a designated public forum, content-based restrictions on speech that come within the forum must pass strict scrutiny to comport with the First Amendment.”); Planned Parenthood Ass’n/Chicago Area v. Chicago Transit Auth., 767 F.2d 1225, 1232, 1233 (7th Cir. 1985) (holding that public transportation advertising space became a public forum because the government maintained “no system of control” over advertisements selected and had “allowed its advertising space to be used for a wide variety of commercial, public-service, and political ads”). 361 See Cornelius, 473 U.S. at 801 (noting that in Lehman, “the Court treated the advertising spaces on the buses as the forum” (emphasis added)). 362 See Lehman v. Shaker Heights, 418 U.S. 298, 300 (listing cigarette companies and churches as two of the groups that had advertised in the ad spaces). 363 Capitol Square Review & Advisory Bd. v. Pinette, 515 U.S. 753, 760–63 (1995). 364 Bd. of Regents of Univ. of Wis. Sys. v. Southworth, 529 U.S. 217, 229–33 (2000); Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819, 829–30 (1995). 365 Lamb’s Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free Sch. Dist., 508 U.S. 384, 387 (1993) (holding that denying a church access to school premises to show a religious film series violates the Freedom of Speech Clause). 366 Id. at 391–94. 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 427 appearing in the forum; nor was the literal speaker a governmental employee; and while the messages were likely expressed in some medium or format effectively owned by government, the status of that property as a forum makes it unlikely that the medium and format were clearly reserved for government messages. The examples above illustrate that government support and funding of a message do not always create government speech, but the waters may be muddied further when it is unclear who really provided the funding. Much depends on whether we are looking for the immediate source or some ultimate source. The Court has determined that the source should be identified as the most immediate one we can find who had real control over fund allocation. In Zelman v. Simmons-Harris,367 a case involving public funding of an educational voucher program which allowed parents to direct the vouchers to private religious or non-religious schools if they wished, challengers asserted that the program violated the Establishment Clause because the program allowed public money to be used to fund religious expression in those recipient schools that were religious.368 The Court rejected the claim, holding in essence that the religious expression was private speech funded with private money, since parents chose whether to fund it.369 Of course, the money had come to the parents from the government at an earlier time; but if the parents’ spending choices were truly voluntary, the source of the religious schools’ funding was the parents, and the religious speech by private school teachers remained private. The result is identical under the three-factor test: The government did not come up with the idea of praising God in the classroom; the religious message was not expressed in a medium or format effectively owned by government; and the literal speaker was not a government employee. The physical setting or environment of speech can also make it difficult to determine whether the speech is governmental or private. Occasionally private speech can be identified even in settings of extensive governmental control, although the Court has sometimes been sympathetic to the government’s need to censor such private speech. For example, when a journalism course in a public high school requires students in the course to produce a school newspaper, the Court has said that the studentwritten articles in the newspaper constitute private speech370 and the 367 536 U.S. 639 (2002). Id. at 644–48. 369 See id. at 652–55. 370 See Hazelwood Sch. Dist. v. Kuhlmeier, 484 U.S. 260, 270–72 (1988) (referring multiple times to the issue as one involving “student speech” and “personal expression”); id. at 273 (referring to articles at issue as “student speech in school-sponsored expressive activities”). 368 428 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 371 newspaper might constitute a nonpublic forum, although it does not constitute a public forum.372 The Court held that the school is allowed to exercise a great deal of control over the content of such speech,373 but it is still private speech. The three-factor test probably points to the same result, but it is admittedly a bit more difficult to apply here. Government speech would not be indicated by factors one or three: it was the student’s idea, not the government’s, to write a newspaper story about the particular subject (in this case, students’ experiences with pregnancy and divorce),374 and the literal speaker (the student author) was not a government employee. But factor two is a closer call. Because the government effectively owned the medium and format of communication (the school newspaper and school grounds), the question would boil down to whether this medium and format were clearly reserved for the purpose of expressing only governmental messages and not opened to multiple private speakers for their own expression. If the newspaper often contained student opinions, it would probably be difficult to say the medium and format were clearly reserved, and on balance this factor would not indicate government speech either. Even if the conclusion under this factor went the other way in this close case, however, the error might well be harmless, because of the Court’s determination that private speech in a public school newspaper can be subjected to extensive governmental censorship375—the same result which would obtain if the speech were regarded as government speech. 2. Government Speech Where the Supreme Court has found the presence of government speech, the speech is one of the three kinds listed in the three-factor test. Some cases of this sort have already been mentioned above.376 In addition to those, consider a handful of recent Establishment Clause cases in which the Court found the Clause was violated because of a message.377 Whether 371 See id. at 270 (describing actions of school officials with regard to school newspaper by saying that “they ‘reserve[d] the forum for its intended purpos[e]’” (quoting Perry Educ. Ass’n v. Perry Local Educators’ Ass’n, 460 U.S. 37, 46 (1983) (emphasis added))). 372 See Kuhlmeier, 484 U.S. at 267–70. 373 Id. at 271–73 (noting that when a public school regulates expressive activities that “may fairly be characterized as part of the school curriculum,” the restriction may be broad and need only be “reasonably related to legitimate pedagogical concerns”). 374 Id. at 263 (noting content of articles at issue). 375 See supra note 373 and accompanying text. 376 See supra notes 284–88 and accompanying text; notes 303–39 and accompanying text. 377 I do not mean to suggest that this is the only possible kind of Establishment Clause violation. It may well be possible for the government to violate the Clause without “government speech.” What I am arguing is that if the Clause is violated by a message, then that message must constitute “government speech.” 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 378 429 379 the standard used is the Lemon test, the endorsement test, or the coercion test,380 private speech alone cannot violate the Establishment Clause;381 a message cannot violate the Clause unless it was the government’s message.382 In cases where the Court has found that a particular message violated the Establishment Clause, the three-factor test would identify the message as government speech. For example, when a public school scheduled public prayers into the agenda of its graduation ceremonies and invited a local clergyman to deliver the prayers, even advising him on the wording of the prayers, the prayers could be characterized as government speech under the first factor: the government (that is, a government employee—the school principal—acting in his official capacity) independently came up with the idea of reaching an audience with this message in the graduation ceremonies.383 Likewise, when a county erects a “Foundations of American Law and Government” 378 Lemon v. Kurtzman, 403 U.S. 602, 612–13 (1971) (providing that the test requires the governmental action to satisfy three independent requirements: (1) it “must have a secular legislative purpose”; (2) “its principal or primary effect must be one that neither advances nor inhibits religion”; and (3) it “must not foster ‘an excessive governmental entanglement with religion’” (internal citations and quotation marks omitted)). See McCreary County v. ACLU, 545 U.S. 844, 859–65, 881 (2005) (applying the Lemon test); Santa Fe Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Doe, 530 U.S. 290, 314–17 (2000) (applying the Lemon test). 379 See Santa Fe Indep. Sch. Dist., 530 U.S. at 307–10 (providing a recent application of the endorsement test). 380 See id. at 310–12 (providing a recent application of the coercion test). 381 See, e.g., id. at 302 (“‘[T]here is a crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect.’” (quoting Bd. of Educ. of Westside Cmty. Sch. (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U.S. 226, 250 (1990) (plurality opinion))); Capitol Square Review & Advisory Bd. v. Pinette, 515 U.S. 753, 760 (1995) (“[P]rivate religious speech, far from being a First Amendment orphan, is as fully protected under the Free Speech Clause as secular private expression.”). 382 Justice O’Connor, joined by Justices Souter and Breyer, has stated a view that at first sounds contrary to the one I am asserting, but upon investigation, the contradiction is largely illusory. In one Establishment Clause case, she wrote, “I believe that an impermissible message of endorsement can be sent in a variety of contexts, not all of which involve direct government speech or outright favoritism.” Capitol Square Review & Advisory Bd., 515 U.S. at 774 (O’Connor, J., concurring in part). On its face, this statement raises a question as to the meaning of “direct government speech.” If “direct” is not a significant qualification, one wonders how a government can possibly send any “message of endorsement” without “speech.” Later in the opinion, however, she clarified her view somewhat: Where the government’s operation of a public forum has the effect of endorsing religion, even if the governmental actor neither intends nor actively encourages that result, the Establishment Clause is violated. This is so not because of . . . mistaken attribution of private speech to the State, but because the State’s own actions [in administering the forum], and their relationship to the private speech at issue, actually convey a message of endorsement. Id. at 777 (internal citations omitted). Thus, in such situations, Justice O’Connor apparently believes the state is acting to send a message separate from the message of the private speaker, a message that endorses what the private speaker is saying. On this understanding, violation of the Establishment Clause still comes from government speech—in this case, the governmental message of endorsement sent by the government’s actions in administering the forum. Without necessarily endorsing Justice O’Connor’s view of how endorsement is to be identified in public forums, I think in the end she is saying what I am saying: messages that violate the Establishment Clause constitute government speech. 383 See Lee v. Weisman, 505 U.S. 577, 587–89 (1992). 430 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 display in its courthouse, consisting of a framed copy of the Ten Commandments and eight other framed historical documents of equal size,384 it is relatively easy to characterize the display as government speech under factor one and factor two as well, whether or not the elements of the display were donated to the county.385 Less clear, perhaps, was the nature of a student-led prayer at a public school football game. In that case, however, the Court emphasized the unique history of the school’s policies governing such messages. For many years this public high school had scheduled student-led public prayers at home football games, and only later—after litigation—adopted a policy to allow students to vote on whether to have a popularly-elected student deliver “a brief invocation and/or message” to begin the games.386 The school also promulgated content rules applying to any message thus delivered.387 A student was elected under this policy and delivered prayers at the games.388 Under these circumstances, the Court found that the “prayers bear ‘the imprint of the State’”389 and did not constitute private speech.390 The outcome would likely be the same under factor one of the three-factor test: the history at this school indicated that the government independently came up with the idea of reaching an audience with prayers over the loudspeaker at home football games, and the latest policy was not an effort to create a forum for private speakers, but merely the government’s attempt to assure that the prayers continued.391 B. Future Applications—Specialty License Plates A uniform method of identifying government speech would prove especially useful in one set of cases that has recently divided the federal courts of appeals: the cases involving specialty license plate programs.392 These programs have already been discussed to some extent,393 but it might be useful to apply the three-factor test to them more directly and suggest the proper legal resolution of these cases. License plates vary, as do the state programs established to regulate them. The proper answer to the government speech question will likely 384 See McCreary County v. ACLU, 545 U.S. 844, 851–56 (1992). See supra notes 302–19 and accompanying text for a discussion of governmental monuments and displays and the application of the three-factor test to them. 386 Santa Fe Indep. Sch. Dist., 530 U.S. at 295–98 & n.6. 387 Id. at 298 n.6. 388 Id. at 298. 389 Id. at 305 (quoting Lee v. Weisman, 505 U.S. 577, 590 (1992)). 390 Id. at 310. 391 See id. at 306–07, 309–11, 315 (reaching similar conclusions after analyzing history and context of policy). 392 See supra note 9. 393 See supra notes 9–17 and accompanying text; notes 72–114 and accompanying text; notes 133–41 and accompanying text; notes 152–85 and accompanying text. 385 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 431 depend on the type of license plate, or even the type of specialty plate program, at issue. With regard to any particular program or type of plate, we will want to know whether it involves one of the three types of government speech thus far recognized by the Supreme Court. As to standard-issue plates, it is difficult to view the messages contained there as anything but government speech. Motorists do not choose to display those messages, since presumably the law requires that they must; moreover, the government crafted the message and also came up with the idea of putting it on standard-issue plates. If a private motorist disagrees with the message, the state has to allow him not to display it— this is the teaching of Wooley v. Maynard394—but the Court did not reach this result because the message “Live Free or Die” included some component of private speech; rather, the Court held that private speech rights are violated when the government compels a private motorist personally to convey the government’s own message.395 The messages contained in the alphanumeric combinations on vanity plates, by contrast, ought to be regarded as private speech. Although the government owns the license plate and the government’s name is embossed on it, no one— including the government—views the alphanumeric combinations (or all elements of all license plates, for that matter) as a medium or format clearly reserved for the government’s own messages. And of course the government did not come up with the idea of putting any of the particular chosen messages on a license plate. Specialty plates are the most difficult case of all, but calling them hybrid speech merely hides the ball. It would be more accurate, perhaps, to say that specialty plates (like vanity plates) contain some government speech and some private speech on each plate. The elements of government speech would include the state name, any state motto or other design that the state has required for all license plates, and the overall dimensions, materials, and construction of the plate (to the extent these elements could be deemed expressive). These are elements which are present only because the government came up with the idea of making license plates in this way with these messages. It might also be that messages honoring or identifying a particular group selected by the state— say, Purple Heart recipients or firefighters396—could be considered 394 430 U.S. 705, 717 (1977). See id. at 715 (“New Hampshire’s statute in effect requires that appellees use their private property as a ‘mobile billboard’ for the State’s ideological message—or suffer a penalty.” (emphasis added)). 396 Tennessee, for example, offers both these plate designs. The state groups its specialty plates into categories, including “Clubs/Groups,” “Collegiate Plates,” “Disabled Plates,” “Emergency Management,” and “Military/Veterans.” See Tennessee Department of Revenue, Specialty License Plates, http://tennessee.gov/revenue/vehicle/licenseplates/specialty.htm (last visited Aug. 31, 2009). The Purple Heart plate is classified within the “Military/Veterans” category and is available only to Tennessee residents who can prove that they have been awarded the Purple Heart; there is no charge to 395 432 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:365 government speech, assuming that these groups did not petition the government for issuance of the plates and the government was not trying to give these groups a way to raise money and public awareness for some cause.397 But when a particular organization’s logo or design appears on a plate only because the organization came up with the idea of trying to qualify for the issuance of a specialty plate bearing that design, the design is not properly viewed as government speech; those logos and designs are private speech. For one thing, the government did not independently come up with the idea of putting that particular message on a specialty plate, or even with some “overall message” to be conveyed by its specialty plate program. For another, assuming the program allows or encourages private applications of some sort (whether through legislative lobbying or through paperwork filed with a state bureaucratic office), the medium or format of specialty plate designs are not clearly reserved for government messages; instead, they are open to multiple private speakers for the purpose of raising revenue for the state and the organization and, to a lesser extent, for encouraging the speech of private organizations and motorists. Finally, it is clear that the literal speaker, whoever that may be, is not a government employee whose job it is to send messages on license plates concerning subjects like adoption or NASCAR. These sorts of specialty plate programs are not reasonably viewed as the state’s bully pulpit for sending its own messages, but rather as a stateregulated forum for the expression of a variety of private messages. The fact that any such messages must be approved in advance by the state suggests, not government speech, but the possibility of improper viewpoint discrimination among private speakers. Using such evidence to show either government speech or a governmental component of hybrid speech is to use evidence of viewpoint discrimination as a justification for the motorist for this plate. See Tennessee Department of Revenue, Specialty License Plates— Military/Veterans: Purple Heart, http://tennessee.gov/revenue/vehicle/licenseplates/militaryveterans/ militarydesc.htm#purpleheart (last visited Aug. 31, 2009). The Firefighter plate is classified within the “Emergency Management” category and is available only to Tennessee residents who can prove that they are current or retired members of a “bona fide” “firefighting unit.” The charge for this plate is $21.50, which is the same as the charge for a standard plate. See Tennessee Department of Revenue, Specialty License Plates—Emergency Management: Firefighter, http://tennessee.gov/revenue/vehicle/ licenseplates/emergency/emergdesc.htm#firefighter (last visited Aug. 31, 2009). The standard plate is listed as “Automobile/Motor Home” within the “Miscellaneous” category. See Tennessee Department of Revenue, Specialty License Plates—Miscellaneous, http://tennessee.gov/revenue/vehicle/ licenseplates/misc/miscdesc.htm#automobile (last visited Aug. 31, 2009). 397 To the extent a qualified private motorist chooses such a plate instead of a standard-issue plate, the message “I am a Purple Heart recipient” or “I am a firefighter” would also be the private speech of the motorist. This might be the closest thing to true “hybrid speech.” But that should not affect the analysis. The fact that the government’s predetermined message happens to be endorsed by a private speaker should not mean that the government is speaking any less or that it is less free to specify which of these sorts of messages it will issue in this way. Nor should any of this affect our analysis under the Establishment Clause; the private speaker has a First Amendment right to endorse religion, but no First Amendment right to demand that the government endorse religion first, thereby allowing her to join in. 2009] IDENTIFYING GOVERNMENT SPEECH 433 viewpoint discrimination. VIII. CONCLUSION First Amendment principles require judges to differentiate between the messages of the government and those of private parties. Messages endorsing religion cannot violate the Establishment Clause unless the government crafts or adopts the message as its own. And governmental restrictions on a message’s viewpoint cannot violate the Speech Clause unless the message is someone else’s. The distinction between government speech and private speech makes sense because we want to allow the government to send its own messages as a participant in the marketplace of ideas, but we do not want to allow the government to allocate its vast resources discriminatorily so as to hobble whatever private viewpoints it disfavors. If this distinction between government and private speech makes sense, then it should be recognized—even in the hard cases in the middle. Thus far, the Supreme Court has recognized the distinction but has given only limited guidance about how to identify government speech in questionable cases. Still, what the Court has said can be largely distilled to three factors that independently indicate the presence of government speech. Compared to the single-prong, four-pronged, and mixed speech approaches developed over the past decade by federal judges and commentators, these three factors seem not only somewhat less subjective, but also more closely tied to the essence of government speech. In short, the presence of any one of these three factors tends to show that the government has developed or adopted, in the words of the Court, a “programmatic message of the kind recognized in Rust . . . .”398 Governments that do this are indeed sending their own messages. 398 Legal Servs. Corp. v. Velazquez, 531 U.S. 533, 548 (2001). CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW VOLUME 42 DECEMBER 2009 NUMBER 2 Article How to Analyze the Accuracy of Eyewitness Testimony in a Criminal Case RICHARD A. WISE, CLIFFORD S. FISHMAN & MARTIN A. SAFER This Article describes a method for analyzing the accuracy of eyewitness testimony that will significantly enhance the ability of the criminal justice system to assess eyewitness accuracy. The method consists of the following components: First, ascertain whether law enforcement conducted the eyewitness interviews in a manner that obtained the maximum amount of information from the eyewitness, did not contaminate the eyewitness’s memory of the crime, or artificially increase the eyewitness’s confidence. Next, determine whether the identification procedures in the case were fair and unbiased. Finally, evaluate what eyewitness factors during the crime are likely to have increased or decreased the accuracy of the eyewitness testimony. The Article discusses scientific guidelines for assessing the fairness of eyewitness interviews and identification procedures, and a list of eyewitness factors that most commonly affect eyewitness accuracy in criminal trials. The Appendix contains a form that will aid participants in the criminal justice system in applying this method to eyewitness testimony in criminal cases. By implementing this method, the criminal justice system will significantly reduce wrongful convictions from eyewitness error. 435 ARTICLE CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION................................................................................................. 437 II. THE CURRENT STATE OF THE LAW ............................................................ 443 A. B. C. D. PRETRIAL AND IN-COURT IDENTIFICATIONS ..................................................... 443 ASSESSMENT OF THE SUPREME COURT’S APPROACH TO EYEWITNESS ERROR.... 448 HOW EYEWITNESS ISSUES ARE LITIGATED ....................................................... 450 EXPERT TESTIMONY REGARDING EYEWITNESS IDENTIFICATION ....................... 452 III. THE CAUSES OF EYEWITNESS ERROR ...................................................... 454 A. B. C. D. E. F. G. THE NATURE OF HUMAN MEMORY................................................................... 455 EYEWITNESS BIAS ............................................................................................ 456 MISINFORMATION EFFECT ................................................................................ 457 SOURCE MONITORING ERRORS ......................................................................... 457 HINDSIGHT BIAS ............................................................................................... 458 EYEWITNESS OVERCONFIDENCE........................................................................ 458 EYEWITNESSES TEND TO MAKE A RELATIVE JUDGMENT IN MAKING AN IDENTIFICATION ..................................................................................... 460 H. LINEUPS ARE FREQUENTLY CONDUCTED IN A MANNER THAT DRAWS THE EYEWITNESS’S ATTENTION TO THE SUSPECT......................................... 461 I. LACK OF KNOWLEDGE OF MEMORY AND EYEWITNESS FACTORS ........................ 463 IV. WHY JUDGES AND ATTORNEYS NEED A METHOD FOR ASSESSING EYEWITNESS ACCURACY IN CRIMINAL CASES .............. 464 V. A METHOD FOR ANALYZING THE ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY .......................................................................... 470 VI. EVALUATING THE EYEWITNESS INTERVIEWS ...................................... 474 A. FACTORS THAT MAXIMIZE EYEWITNESS INFORMATION .................................... 475 B. FACTORS THAT PREVENT THE “CONTAMINATION” OF EYEWITNESS MEMORY.... 480 C. FACTORS THAT PREVENT THE INCREASE OF EYEWITNESS CONFIDENCE ............. 482 VII. GUIDELINES FOR EVALUATING THE FAIRNESS OF IDENTIFICATION PROCEDURES ................................................................ 485 VIII. COMMON EYEWITNESS FACTORS THAT AFFECT EYEWITNESS ACCURACY DURING A CRIME ................................................................... 497 A. EYEWITNESS CHARACTERISTICS ....................................................................... 498 B. PERPETRATOR CHARACTERISTICS ..................................................................... 502 C. CRIME CHARACTERISTICS................................................................................. 504 IX. ADMISSIBILITY OF EYEWITNESS IDENTIFICATIONS AT TRIAL ......... 506 X. CONCLUSION ................................................................................................... 508 APPENDIX .............................................................................................................. 512 How to Analyze the Accuracy of Eyewitness Testimony in a Criminal Case RICHARD A. WISE, CLIFFORD S. FISHMAN & MARTIN A. SAFER* I. INTRODUCTION In July of 1984, Jennifer Thompson, a 22-year-old college student, awoke around 3:00 a.m. to find someone in her apartment. When she asked who was there, a man jumped on her, pinned her arms to the side of her head, put a knife to her throat, and raped her. Despite her terror, she was determined to identify her rapist so he would pay for his crimes. Once her eyes adjusted to the dark, she used the light coming through her blinds and bedroom window, as well as her nightlight to see if he had any tattoos, scars, unusual jewelry, how he parted his hair, what he was wearing, and anything else that would be useful in identifying him. She made sure that when he allowed her to stand up she stood close to him so she could determine how tall he was.1 During her long ordeal, Jennifer tried maneuvering him into different positions where she could best use the available light in her apartment to see him. At one point, he bent down and turned on her stereo, and a blue light from the stereo illuminated his face. When he permitted Jennifer to go to the bathroom, she turned on the light and had an opportunity for a moment to get a good look at his face. She also managed to briefly turn on a lamp in the bedroom before he ordered her to turn if off. Jennifer told her assailant that she was thirsty so she would have an excuse to go to the kitchen. In the kitchen, she turned on the light, which gave her another opportunity to see her assailant. Summoning her courage, wrapped only in a blanket, Jennifer ran from her kitchen to a neighbor’s house. The rapist * Richard A. Wise, Assistant Professor of Psychology, University of North Dakota (B.A. summa cum laude, John Carroll University, 1975; J.D. cum laude, Cleveland-Marshall College of Law, 1979; Ph.D. in Clinical Psychology, The Catholic University of America, 2003; Postdoctoral Fellowship in Forensic Psychology, University of Southern California, 2004); Clifford S. Fishman, Professor of Law, The Catholic University of America (B.A., University of Rochester, 1966; J.D., Columbia University, 1969); Martin A. Safer, Professor of Psychology, The Catholic University of America (B.S., University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee, 1968; Ph.D., University of Wisconsin-Madison, 1978). From 1990–96, Professor Wise served as an Assistant County Prosecutor in the Criminal Division of the Cuyahoga County (Cleveland, Ohio) Prosecutor’s Office; from 1969–77, Professor Fishman served as an Assistant District Attorney in the New York County District Attorney’s Office and as Chief Investigating Assistant District Attorney in New York City’s Special Narcotics Prosecutor’s Office. The authors express their gratitude to Bryan C. Clark, J.D. 2010, The Catholic University of America Law School, for his assistance in preparing this Article. 1 MARK COSTANZO, PSYCHOLOGY APPLIED TO LAW 170 (2004); Helen O’Neill, The Power of Faith: Eleven Years After Jennifer Thompson’s Mistaken Testimony Sent Him to Jail, Ronald Cotton’s Spirit of Forgiveness Let Them Be Friends, NEWSDAY, Nov. 7, 2000, at B06. 438 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 did not follow, but that same night, he broke into another apartment and raped a second woman.2 With the help of a police sketch artist, Jennifer created a composite drawing of the rapist: an African American, in his twenties with short hair and a thin moustache. The police widely circulated the composite drawing and received several calls from people who thought they recognized the rapist. Based on the calls, the police created a six-person photo array for Jennifer, including all the suspects they had in the case. After studying the photo array for a few minutes, Jennifer identified Ronald Cotton, an employee at a local seafood restaurant, as the rapist. The police responded: “We thought this might be the one,” because Ronald Cotton had a prior conviction for sexual assault, and they knew that he liked white women.3 When Ronald Cotton learned that the police were looking for him, he went to the police station to clear up the matter. Unfortunately, Ronald Cotton did not help himself during his interrogation. He was nervous; he got his dates mixed up, and his alibi did not check out. Furthermore, a piece of foam was missing from one of his shoes, and a similar piece of foam from a shoe was found at the crime scene. The police arrested him for both rapes and placed him in a seven person lineup. Jennifer had little difficulty identifying him from the lineup, but the second rape victim identified a foil from the lineup. The police informed Jennifer that she had identified the same man from the lineup whose photo she had picked out from the photo array a few days earlier.4 At trial, the only physical evidence the prosecution produced to connect Ronald Cotton to the crime was the piece of foam found at the crime scene and that he owned a flashlight that resembled the one used by the rapist. Jennifer, however, was a “terrific witness.” During the crimes, she had made every possible effort to see her rapist, and she had identified him twice, once from a photo array and once from a lineup. Moreover, she was completely confident that she had the right man and told the jury that she had no doubt that Ronald Cotton was the rapist. The jury found Ronald Cotton guilty of rape. On January 17, 1985, when Cotton was sentenced to life in prison, Jennifer toasted his sentence with champagne. She said that “[i]t was the happiest day of [her] life.”5 After spending two years in prison, Ronald Cotton learned from an inmate that another inmate, Bobby Poole, was bragging that he was the man who had raped Jennifer Thompson and the other woman. Cotton was eventually granted a new trial because the North Carolina Supreme Court ruled that the trial court had erred in not permitting the jury to learn that 2 COSTANZO, supra note 1, at 170. Id.; O’Neill, supra note 1. 4 COSTANZO, supra note 1, at 170; O’Neill, supra note 1. 5 COSTANZO, supra note 1, at 170–71; O’Neill, supra note 1. 3 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 439 6 the second rape victim had failed to identify him from the lineup. In November of 1987, Cotton was retried, this time for both rapes, because the second rape victim had decided by the time of the second trial that Cotton was her rapist despite her failure to pick him out of a lineup several years earlier. Both Jennifer and the second rape victim told the jury that they were positive that Ronald Cotton was the rapist. The judge excluded testimony during the trial that Bobby Poole had admitted to committing the rapes. The jury found Ronald Cotton guilty, and he was given two life sentences. Cotton’s appellate attorney failed to assert that the trial court’s exclusion of Poole’s confession constituted prejudicial error. Cotton’s new convictions were affirmed.7 For the next eight years, Cotton wrote letters to anyone he thought might help him get his convictions overturned. He likely would have died in prison if Richard Rosen, a law professor and attorney, had not decided to investigate his case. Rosen and another attorney filed a motion for appropriate relief on the basis of inadequate representation during his second appeal. They also filed a motion for DNA testing, which was granted in October of 1994. The DNA evidence from one victim was too deteriorated to be conclusive, but the DNA samples from the other victim showed that Cotton was not the rapist. At his defense attorneys’ request, the DNA samples were sent to the state’s DNA database, which contains DNA from all convicted felons in North Carolina. The DNA samples from the crimes matched the DNA of Bobby Poole. After learning of the DNA results, the district attorney joined with Cotton’s defense attorneys in moving to dismiss all charges against Ronald Cotton. In July of 1995, the Governor of North Carolina officially pardoned Ronald Cotton.8 Having spent two years wracked with guilt after learning that she identified the wrong man, Jennifer asked the detective in charge of the case to arrange a meeting for her with Ronald Cotton. An Associated Press reporter described their meeting: A few weeks later, she drove 50 miles to a church in the town where she was raped. She asked her husband and the pastor to leave. Trembling, she opened the door. She had prayed for the strength to face this moment. She had prayed for the strength to face this man. “I’m sorry,” she said. “If I spent every day for the rest of my life telling you how sorry I am, it wouldn’t come close to what I feel.” Ronald Cotton was calm and quiet, and Thompson thought he seemed so very 6 State v. Cotton, 351 S.E.2d 277, 280 (N.C. 1987); O’Neill, supra note 1. State v. Cotton, 394 S.E.2d 456, 457, 460 (N.C. Ct. App. 1990); see also O’Neill, supra note 1. See EDWARD CONNORS ET AL., U.S. DEP’T JUST., CONVICTED BY JURIES, EXONERATED BY SCIENCE: CASE STUDIES IN THE USE OF DNA EVIDENCE TO ESTABLISH INNOCENCE AFTER TRIAL 44 (1996), available at http://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles/dnaevid.pdf. 7 8 440 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 tall. Finally, he spoke. “I’m not mad at you,” he said softly. “I’ve never been mad at you. I just want you to have a good life.” Tears falling, Thompson looked into his eyes and knew she would never see him in her nightmares again.9 This case produced several tragedies. Jennifer endured the terrible ordeal of the rape; she is still afraid sometimes, especially at night when she is alone, and she had to deal with the guilt of convicting the wrong man. Ronald Cotton was imprisoned for eleven agonizing years for crimes he did not commit. Additional crimes could have been prevented if Bobby Poole had been arrested earlier. The prosecutor, police, defense attorneys, jurors, and judges have to live with the knowledge that they are responsible for sending an innocent man to prison for eleven years. This case illustrates both the power and the danger of erroneous eyewitness testimony.10 Each year, thousands of men and women in the United States are wrongfully convicted of felonies that they did not commit.11 Experts estimate that eyewitness error plays a role in half or more of all wrongful felony convictions.12 A study published in 2006 showed that eyewitness 9 O’Neill, supra note 1. Jennifer Thompson and Ronald Cotton became good friends. She said of Ronald Cotton, “He is an amazing human being. He has been a real good teacher for me.” Id. Jennifer Thompson has become a strong opponent of the death penalty and frequently speaks about the unreliability of eyewitness testimony. Id. 10 See COSTANZO, supra note 1, at 171–72; CONNORS ET AL., supra note 8, at 43–44; What Jennifer Saw, Transcript from Interview with Frontline, http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/pages/frontline/ shows/dna/interviews/cotton.html (last visited Aug. 27, 2009) (discussing the case and Cotton’s experience with the North Carolina judicial system). 11 Richard A. Wise & Martin A. Safer, A Survey of Judges’ Knowledge and Beliefs About Eyewitness Testimony, 40 CT. REV. 6, 6 (2003) (explaining that estimates of the number of wrongful felony convictions range from 5000 to as many as 100,000 per year with DNA exoneration cases suggesting that the number of wrongful felony convictions is closer to the upper limit of this estimate); see also D. Michael Risinger, Innocents Convicted: An Empirically Justified Factual Wrongful Conviction Rate, 97 J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 761, 780 (2007) (discussing a study that used the DNA exoneration cases to estimate that in 3.3% to 5% of the capital rape-murder convictions in the U.S. from 1982–89, the defendants were innocent). If this percentage of wrongful convictions were applicable to other types of crimes, there would be 33,000 to 50,000 wrongful felony convictions per year in the United States. 12 See C. Ronald Huff, Wrongful Convictions: Societal Tolerance of Injustice, 4 RES. IN SOC. PROBS. & PUB. POL’Y 99, 103 (1987) (“In our own database, eyewitness error was involved in nearly 60 percent of the cases.”); Arye Rattner, Convicted but Innocent, 12 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 283, 289 (1988); see also Garrett L. Berman & Brian L. Cutler, Effects of Inconsistencies in Eyewitness Testimony on Mock-Juror Decision Making, 81 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 170, 170 (1996) (“False eyewitness identifications . . . appear to be one of the leading causes of erroneous conviction.” (citations omitted)); Amy L. Bradfield et al., The Damaging Effect of Confirming Feedback on the Relation Between Eyewitness Certainty and Identification Accuracy, 87 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 112, 112 (2002); Jacqueline McMurtrie, The Role of the Social Sciences in Preventing Wrongful Convictions, 42 AM. CRIM. L. REV. 1271, 1275 (2005) (quoting United States v. Wade, 388 U.S. 218, 229 (1967)); Gary L. Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures: Recommendations for Lineups and Photospreads, 22 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 603, 605 (1998) (“In addition to the experimental literature, cases of proven wrongful convictions of innocent people have consistently shown that mistaken eyewitness identification is responsible for more of these wrongful convictions than all the other causes combined.”); Northwestern Univ. Sch. of Law, Ctr. on Wrongful Convictions, How Mistaken and 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 441 error occurred in seventy-five percent or more of the first 180 DNA exoneration cases.13 In several of the DNA cases, more than one eyewitness made an erroneous identification, and a number of the defendants were sentenced to death.14 Unfortunately, DNA testing can correct only a small fraction of eyewitness misidentifications because it is only available in a small number of criminal cases.15 One of the principal reasons that eyewitness error is the leading cause of wrongful convictions is because it is one of the most powerful types of evidence that can be presented against a criminal defendant.16 As the United States Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit wrote in Kampshoff v. Smith: There can be no reasonable doubt that inaccurate Perjured Eyewitness Identification Testimony Put 46 Innocent Americans on Death Row, http://www.law.northwestern.edu/wrongfulconvictions/aboutus/ (last visited Aug. 31, 2009) [hereinafter Ctr. on Wrongful Convictions]. Indeed, Edwin Borchard identified erroneous eyewitness identification as a leading cause of false conviction over seventy years ago. EDWIN M. BORCHARD, CONVICTING THE INNOCENT xiii (1932). 13 Gary L. Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, Improving Its Probative Value, 7 PSYCHOL. SCI. PUB. INT. 45, 48 (2006); see also Donald A. Dripps, Miscarriages of Justice and the Constitution, 2 BUFF. CRIM. L. REV. 635, 638–39 (1999) (“A Department of Justice study found that, out of a sample of more than 21,000 cases, DNA testing exonerated the suspect in 23% of the cases.”). Since DNA evidence was first introduced into the criminal justice system, it has exonerated more than 144 people who were wrongfully convicted of crimes. Samuel R. Gross et al., Exonerations in the United States, 1989 Through 2003, 95 J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 523, 524 (2005). “In 64% percent of these exonerations (219/340) at least one eyewitness misidentified the defendant.” Id. at 542. Eighty-eight percent of the rape exonerations involved eyewitness misidentification. Id. at 530; see also Gary L. Wells & Elizabeth A. Olson, Eyewitness Testimony, 54 ANN. REV. PSYCHOL. 277, 278 (2003) (stating that more than 100 convicted felons have been exonerated by DNA evidence). 14 The Northwestern University School of Law Center on Wrongful Convictions released a study in 2001 involving wrongful convictions in capital cases throughout the United States. Of the eighty-six cases studied, the Center found that “53.5%[] had been predicated in whole or part on mistaken or perjured eyewitness testimony. In thirty-three of the cases, the eyewitness testimony was the sole basis of the conviction.” Ctr. on Wrongful Convictions, supra note 12; see also WAYNE WEITEN, PSYCHOLOGY: THEMES AND VARIATIONS, BRIEFER VERSION 230 (7th ed. 2008) (describing the nearconviction of an innocent priest based on the testimony of seven eyewitnesses); Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 605 (stating that of forty cases overturned by DNA evidence in the 1990s, five of the exonerated inmates were on death row, and “36 (or 90%) involved eyewitness identification evidence in which one or more eyewitnesses falsely identified the person”). 15 See Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 49 (“In contrast to sexual assault cases, only a small fraction of murders (more than 16,000 reported in 2004) and almost no robberies (more than 400,000 reported in 2004) or aggravated assaults (more than 850,000 reported in 2004) result in biologically rich trace evidence left behind.”); Gary L. Wells et al., From the Lab to the Police Station, A Successful Application of Eyewitness Research, 55 AM. PSYCHOLOGIST 581, 589 (2000) (“Perpetrators of murders, drive-by shootings, convenience store robberies, muggings, and other common crimes almost never leave DNA trace evidence that could exonerate someone who has been the [sic] mistakenly identified by an eyewitness.”). 16 As one study on eyewitness testimony explained: An eyewitness who says “That is the person I saw pull the gun” is providing direct evidence of guilt in the sense that the criminal act and the defendant are directly linked. In contrast, physical evidence such as fingerprints indicate only that the suspect touched a given surface at some point in time, perhaps for reasons unrelated to the crime, and hence is circumstantial evidence. Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 604. 442 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 eyewitness testimony may be one of the most prejudicial features of a criminal trial. Juries, naturally desirous to punish a vicious crime, may well be unschooled in the effects that the subtle compound of suggestion, anxiety, and forgetfulness in the face of the need to recall often has on witnesses. Accordingly, doubts over the strength of the evidence of a defendant’s guilt may be resolved on the basis of the eyewitness’ seeming certainty when he points to the defendant and exclaims with conviction that veils all doubt, “[T]hat’s the man!”17 The prevalence of eyewitness error poses a major dilemma for the criminal justice system because it is frequently the only or primary evidence available in a criminal case. For instance, a 1987 study estimated that in 77,000 criminal trials each year in the United States, the primary or sole evidence against a defendant is eyewitness testimony.18 As evidenced by the Ronald Cotton case described in this Introduction, criminal cases where eyewitness testimony is the sole or primary evidence pose the greatest risk that eyewitness error will result in a wrongful conviction.19 Therefore, it is essential that the criminal justice system institute reforms to increase the reliability and accuracy of eyewitness testimony. As is explained below, improving judges’ and attorneys’ abilities to assess the accuracy of eyewitness testimony would significantly reduce eyewitness error. This Article delineates a method for analyzing the accuracy of eyewitness testimony that will enable judges and attorneys to achieve this vital goal. Part II of this Article describes the current state of the law concerning eyewitness identifications. Part III examines the major causes of eyewitness error. Part IV explains why the ability to assess the accuracy of eyewitness testimony in criminal cases is essential to the proper performance of judges’ and attorneys’ duties. Part V describes a three-part method for analyzing the accuracy of eyewitness testimony that will significantly enhance judges’ and attorneys’ abilities to evaluate eyewitness accuracy. This method consists of the following components: (1) judges and attorneys determine if law enforcement conducted the eyewitness interviews in a manner that obtained the maximum amount of 17 18 C1. Kampshoff v. Smith, 698 F.2d 581, 585 (2d Cir. 1983) (citation omitted). Daniel Goleman, Studies Point to Flaws in Lineups of Suspects, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 17, 1995, at 19 Richard A. Wise et al., A Tripartite Solution to Eyewitness Error, 97 J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 807, 842 (2007); see also Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 609 (stating that the only safeguard that has demonstrated any efficacy in educating jurors about eyewitness testimony—expert testimony—is often not used by defendants because of its cost). For further discussion of the difficulties in using expert testimony, see infra notes 84–90 and accompanying text. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 443 information from the eyewitness, did not contaminate the eyewitness’s memory of the crime, or artificially increase the eyewitness’s confidence; (2) they ascertain if the identification procedures in the case were fair and unbiased; and (3) they examine the eyewitness factors during the crime that likely increased or decreased the accuracy of the eyewitness testimony. Part VI sets forth scientific guidelines for evaluating whether an eyewitness interview obtained the maximum amount of information from the eyewitness, did not contaminate an eyewitness’s memory of a crime, or artificially increased the eyewitness’s confidence. Part VII details scientific guidelines for appraising the fairness of identification procedures. Part VIII describes common eyewitness factors present during crimes that affect eyewitness accuracy. Part IX sets forth a modified standard for determining when eyewitness identifications should be admissible at trial. Part X makes some concluding remarks about using this method to analyze the accuracy of eyewitness testimony. The Appendix to this Article contains a form that will aid judges and attorneys in applying this method when evaluating eyewitness accuracy in criminal cases. II. THE CURRENT STATE OF THE LAW Between 1967 and 1977, the United States Supreme Court rendered several decisions that considered the constitutional implications of various identification procedures. The Court has not rendered any significant decisions on identification procedures since then. As a result, certain principles are firmly established in the case law, while other issues are addressed only briefly or not at all. A. Pretrial and In-Court Identifications: Legal Categories and Principles In the typical criminal case in which the defendant denies he or she was the perpetrator, two evidentiary issues will generally arise whenever the prosecutor calls an eyewitness at trial.20 First, will the prosecutor be permitted to elicit testimony about the eyewitness’s pretrial identification(s) of the defendant?21 Second, will the eyewitness be permitted to make an in-court identification during the trial?22 These 20 Similar issues sometimes arise regarding an eyewitness’s ability to recognize and identify a defendant’s voice, but that subject is beyond the scope of this Article. For a detailed discussion of this topic, see CLIFFORD S. FISHMAN & ANNE T. MCKENNA, 2 WIRETAPPING & EAVESDROPPING: SURVEILLANCE IN THE INTERNET AGE §§ 38:4–38:5 (3d ed. 2008). 21 Such testimony might come from the eyewitness or from the police officer who conducted the pretrial identification procedure, or both. 22 The in-court identification may be a moment of high drama, but its evidentiary value is suspect because anyone familiar with an American courtroom will, in most cases, be able to identify the defendant simply by observing where he or she is sitting. 444 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 23 issues are generally resolved in a hearing prior to the trial. The Supreme Court has long been aware of the dangers posed by suggestive identification procedures.24 Yet, rather than create a single set of rules and standards to govern such cases, the Court has divided identification issues into two categories, one quite narrow and the other quite broad, and has applied very different legal principles to each. The narrow category involves only pretrial identification procedures which (a) were corporeal in nature, i.e., the witness viewed the defendant “live”; (b) were conducted after the defendant was arraigned on the charge in question; and (c) were conducted in the absence of the defendant’s attorney. The second, broader category includes all other pretrial identification procedures: corporeal identifications prior to arraignment and photo identifications, whether before or after arraignment. 1. Corporeal, Post-Arraignment Identifications Held in the Absence of Counsel: United States v. Wade and Gilbert v. California Once a defendant has been arraigned, the defendant enjoys the right, guaranteed by the Sixth Amendment, to have counsel present during all “critical stages” of the case, whether they occur prior to or during the trial.25 In 1967, in United States v. Wade26 and Gilbert v. California,27 the Supreme Court held that a lineup or other identification procedure in which the defendant is forced to participate is a “critical stage,” and that to hold such a lineup in the absence of defense counsel violates that right.28 If that right is violated, the Court held that the prosecutor is not 23 See discussion infra Part II.C. “The vagaries of eyewitness identification are well-known; the annals of criminal law are rife with instances of mistaken identification.” United States v. Wade, 388 U.S. 218, 228 (1967); see also Manson v. Brathwaite, 432 U.S. 98, 107 (1977); Neil v. Biggers, 409 U.S. 188, 199–200 (1972); Stovall v. Denno, 388 U.S. 293, 301–02 (1967); Gilbert v. California, 388 U.S. 263, 264 (1967). 25 The Court first used the phrase “critical stage” in connection with the right to counsel in Parker v. Illinois, 333 U.S. 571, 575 (1948), and first specified that counsel must be provided to a defendant at a “critical stage” of a criminal prosecution in Hamilton v. Alabama, 368 U.S. 52, 54–55 (1961). The phrase occurs with regularity in discussions of the right to counsel: a December 2008 Westlaw search of the Supreme Court database, “‘critical stage’ w/p counsel attorney,” produced 65 “hits.” 26 Wade was convicted of robbing a federally insured bank. Wade, 388 U.S. at 218. 27 Gilbert was convicted of robbing a state bank, and of murdering a police officer who happened to enter the bank during the robbery. Gilbert, 388 U.S. at 263. 28 Wade, 388 U.S. at 236–37; Gilbert, 388 U.S. at 272. “[T]he confrontation compelled by the State between the accused and the victim or witnesses to a crime to elicit identification evidence is peculiarly riddled with innumerable dangers and variable factors which might seriously, even crucially, derogate from a fair trial.” Wade, 388 U.S. at 228. After discussing the risks of misidentification and, particularly, the risks involved in suggestive identification procedures, the Court commented: It is a matter of common experience that, once a witness has picked out the accused at the line-up, he is not likely to go back on his word later on, so that in practice the issue of identity may (in the absence of other relevant evidence) for all practical purposes be determined there and then, before the trial. Id. at 229 (citation omitted). 24 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 445 29 permitted to elicit testimony about the lineup at trial. Moreover, an eyewitness who identified the defendant at a post-arraignment lineup conducted in the absence of counsel will not be permitted to make an incourt identification at trial, unless the prosecutor can “establish by clear and convincing evidence that the in-court identifications were based upon observations of the suspect other than the lineup identification.”30 In other words, the prosecutor must establish by clear and convincing evidence that the eyewitness remembered the defendant from the crime itself and was not relying on his or her memory of the lineup to make the in-court identification.31 2. All Other Pretrial Identification Procedures: The “Due Process” Standard In subsequent decisions, the Supreme Court has considered the constitutional implications of identification procedures in a variety of contexts not covered by the Wade and Gilbert decisions. In Kirby v. Illinois, police conducted a pre-arraignment one-person corporeal “showup.”32 The Court declined to apply the Wade-Gilbert rule to this situation because the Sixth Amendment right to counsel does not exist prior to arraignment.33 Instead, the Court enunciated a different test, based on the Due Process Clause of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments.34 In United States v. Ash, the Court likewise declined to apply the Wade-Gilbert rule to a post-arraignment use of a photo array35 because the use of photos does not involve an actual, live “confrontation” between the defendant and law enforcement officials and their witnesses.36 29 “Only a per se exclusionary rule as to such testimony can be an effective sanction to assure that law enforcement authorities will respect the accused’s constitutional right to the presence of his counsel at the critical lineup.” Gilbert, 388 U.S. at 273. 30 Wade, 388 U.S. at 240. 31 See id. at 242. 32 Kirby v. Illinois, 406 U.S. 682, 684–85 (1972). In a “showup” the eyewitness is only shown the suspect. In contrast, in a lineup, the suspect is one of several people standing in an array, and the eyewitness is asked if the perpetrator is in the lineup. See Neil v. Biggers, 409 U.S. 188, 198 (1972). In Kirby, a police officer escorted a robbery victim to a room in a police station where Kirby, a codefendant, and two police officers were seated. The escorting officer asked if they were the robbers and the victim said that they were. Kirby, 406 U.S. at 684–85. 33 Kirby, 406 U.S. at 689–90. Four Justices dissented, with Justice Brennan accusing the plurality of valuing the “mere formalism” of the pre- vs. post-arraignment distinction over what he considered the fundamental unfairness of the result the Court permitted. Id. at 698–99 (Brennan, J., dissenting) (citations omitted). 34 The Court held that due process of law “forbids a lineup that is unnecessarily suggestive and conducive to irreparable mistaken identification.” Id. at 691. 35 A photo array is like a lineup; an eyewitness is shown photographs of several individuals and is asked whether the perpetrator’s picture is among them. 36 United States v. Ash, 413 U.S. 300, 314 (1973). The Court also cited a second reason: defense counsel has no right to be present when a prosecutor prepares his or her eyewitnesses to testify, and showing photographs to an eyewitness was simply one aspect of such preparation. Id. at 317–18. Justice Brennan, joined by Justices Marshall and Douglas, dissented: “[T]oday’s decision marks simply another step towards the complete evisceration of the fundamental constitutional principles 446 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 In Simmons v. United States and Manson v. Brathwaite, the Court considered the constitutional implications of pre-arraignment, highly suggestive photograph identifications.37 In Simmons,38 the Court held that a due process test should be applied to determine whether the suggestive pretrial procedure should prohibit the eyewitness from making an in-court identification at trial.39 In Brathwaite, the Court held that even if the photo identification was highly and unnecessarily suggestive,40 a due process test should be applied to assess the admissibility of both the pretrial and incourt identifications.41 In Neil v. Biggers, a pre-indictment, corporeal showup case,42 the Court issued its most elaborate commentary on “the relationship between suggestiveness and misidentification,”43 and on the due process to be applied in cases not covered by the Sixth Amendment Wade-Gilbert rule. As to “suggestiveness,” the Court stated: It is, first of all, apparent that the primary evil to be avoided is “a very substantial likelihood of irreparable misidentification.” While the phrase was coined as a standard for determining whether an in-court identification would be admissible in the wake of a suggestive out-of-court identification, with the deletion of “irreparable” it serves equally well as a standard for the admissibility of testimony concerning the out-of-court identification itself. It is the likelihood of misidentification which violates a defendant’s right to due process. . . . Suggestive confrontations are disapproved because they increase the likelihood of misidentification, and unnecessarily suggestive ones are established by this Court, only six years ago, in United States v. Wade.” Id. at 326 (Brennan, J., dissenting) (footnote and citations omitted). The first step, in Justice Brennan’s view, was the Kirby decision. See id. at 326 n.1. 37 See Simmons v. United States, 390 U.S. 377, 381–82 (1968); Manson v. Brathwaite, 432 U.S. 98, 103–04 (1977). 38 Shortly after a bank robbery, Simmons became a suspect. FBI agents obtained from relatives several photos of Simmons and others and showed them to eyewitnesses, who identified him as one of the robbers. Simmons, 390 U.S. at 380–81. At trial, the eyewitnesses made in-court identifications, but the prosecutor did not offer evidence about the pretrial photo identifications. Id. at 382. 39 Id. at 384. 40 An undercover officer purchased narcotics from a man he had never seen before, then described him to a back-up officer. That officer, believing Brathwaite fit the description, left a mug shot of Brathwaite for the undercover officer, who identified him as the seller. Brathwaite, 432 U.S. at 99– 101. 41 Id. at 113–14. 42 Seven months after she was raped by a stranger, the complainant identified the defendant at a station-house showup. She had gotten a good look at the perpetrator during her ordeal, and in the intervening time, had viewed, in showups, lineups, and photographs, numerous other suspects, without identifying any of them. The police conducted a showup of Biggers after making efforts to find lookalikes for a lineup, efforts which the Supreme Court found unimpressive. Neil v. Biggers, 409 U.S. 188, 193–95, 199 (1972). 43 Id. at 198. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 447 condemned for the further reason that the increased chance of misidentification is gratuitous. But . . . the admission of evidence of a showup without more does not violate due process.44 The Court also delineated in Biggers five factors that should be considered in assessing whether the facts present “a very substantial likelihood of irreparable misidentification”45 and based on these factors concluded that it did not. Thus, it held that testimony about the showup and the in-court identification were both admissible, despite the unnecessarily suggestive nature of the showup.46 The Court subsequently affirmed the Biggers rule in Brathwaite, its most recent significant identification case.47 In essence, therefore, the due process standard is an all-or-nothing test. If the pretrial identification process for an eyewitness was suggestive and the totality of the circumstances convinces the judge that it created a substantial likelihood of misidentification, then no evidence of that eyewitness’s pretrial identification of the defendant can be introduced at trial; nor can that eyewitness make an in-court identification of the defendant.48 On the other hand, if the judge concludes that the eyewitness made the identification based on his memory of the crime, then even if the pretrial identification procedure was suggestive, the judge will deny the motion, and permit both testimony about the eyewitness’s pretrial identification of the defendant, and the in-court identification.49 3. The Supreme Court’s Discussion of Accuracy Factors In Neil v. Biggers and Manson v. Brathwaite, the Supreme Court held that the reliability of an eyewitness’s identification is to be determined by the “totality of the circumstances.”50 In these decisions, the Supreme Court delineated five eyewitness factors that the trier of fact should consider when evaluating eyewitness accuracy: (1) the eyewitness’s opportunity to 44 Id. at 198 (quoting Simmons, 390 U.S. at 384). The prosecutor in Simmons did not offer evidence of the photo identification. 45 Biggers, 409 U.S. at 198; see infra text accompanying note 50 (setting forth the “totality of the circumstances” test from Biggers and Brathwaite). 46 Biggers, 409 U.S. at 198–99. 47 Manson v. Brathwaite, 432 U.S. 98, 106, 113–14 (1977). See supra notes 40–41 and accompanying text (describing the facts of the case and the holding). 48 The Court found identification procedures to violate due process in Foster v. California. 394 U.S. 440, 443 (1969). An eyewitness failed to identify Foster the first time he confronted him, despite a suggestive lineup, and could only make a tentative identification at a showup, then made a positive identification at yet another lineup. The Court held it was error to allow any identification testimony in the case. Id. at 442–43. 49 Thus, in Kirby, Biggers, and Brathwaite, the Court held that, despite suggestiveness, pretrial and in-court identifications were both permissible. See Kirby v. Illinois, 406 U.S. 682, 690 (1972); Biggers, 409 U.S. at 199–200; Brathwaite, 432 U.S. at 115–16. In Foster, by contrast, the Court held that neither should have been admitted. Foster, 394 U.S. at 442–43. 50 Brathwaite, 432 U.S. at 113 (quoting Stovall v. Denno, 388 U.S. 293, 302 (1967)); Biggers, 409 U.S. at 199. 448 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 view the perpetrator during the crime; (2) the length of time between the crime and the subsequent identification; (3) the level of certainty demonstrated by the witness at the identification; (4) the accuracy of the eyewitness’s prior description of the criminal; and (5) the eyewitness’s degree of attention during the crime.51 In the years immediately following these decisions, courts in most states adopted the approach enunciated in Biggers and Brathwaite.52 B. Assessment of the Supreme Court’s Approach to Eyewitness Error In its case law concerning eyewitness identifications, the Supreme Court considered four issues. First, when does a defendant have a right to the presence of counsel at an eyewitness identification procedure? Second, what rule should govern the admissibility of an unnecessarily suggestive eyewitness identification procedure? Third, what factors should a court consider in deciding whether to admit testimony about a pretrial eyewitness identification, and an in-court identification of the defendant by the eyewitness? Fourth, what burden of proof should the prosecutor satisfy to secure the admissibility of eyewitness identifications? We will not address the first issue in this Article.53 As to its resolution of the other three issues, the Court’s decisions about them predated the vast majority of scientific research on eyewitness testimony.54 For example, the factors listed in Biggers and Brathwaite “constitute ‘educated guesses’ by the Court on how [these five eyewitness factors] affect identification accuracy.”55 Subsequent scientific research has shown that many of these five factors do not affect eyewitness 51 Brathwaite, 432 U.S. at 114; Biggers, 409 U.S. at 199–200. See, e.g., State v. Bracy, 703 P.2d 464, 474 (Ariz. 1985); Chism v. State, 853 S.W.2d 255, 261 (Ark. 1993); People v. Clark, 833 P.2d 561, 612 (Cal. 1992); People v. Weller, 679 P.2d 1077, 1083 (Colo. 1984); State v. Miller, 522 A.2d 249, 253–54 (Conn. 1987); Younger v. State, 496 A.2d 546, 550 (Del. 1985); Turner v. United States, 622 A.2d 667, 672 (D.C. 1993); State v. Bennett, 610 P.2d 502, 507–08 (Haw. 1980); State v. Hoisington, 657 P.2d 17, 25 (Idaho 1983); People v. Miller, 626 N.E.2d 1350, 1356–57 (Ill. App. Ct. 1993); Hamlet v. State, 490 N.E.2d 715, 720 (Ind. 1986); State v. Hunt, 69 P.3d 571, 575 (Kan. 2003) (citing Holden v. State, 602 P.2d 452, 455–56 (Alaska 1979)); State v. Warren, 635 P.2d 1236, 1240–41 (Kan. 1981); Wilson v. Commonwealth, 695 S.W.2d 854, 857 (Ky. 1985); State v. Robinson, 386 So. 2d 1374, 1377 (La. 1980); State v. Rolls, 599 A.2d 421, 423 (Me. 1991); State v. Johnson, 674 P.2d 1077, 1079 (Mont. 1983); State v. Whittey, 591 A.2d 1326, 1327–28 (N.H. 1991); State v. Maes, 665 P.2d 1169, 1173 (N.M. 1983); State v. Richardson, 402 S.E.2d 401, 404–05 (N.C. 1991); State v. Packineau, 423 N.W.2d 148, 149–50 (N.D. 1988); State v. Classen, 590 P.2d 1198, 1203–04 (Or. 1979); State v. Gomes, 604 A.2d 1249, 1253 (R.I. 1992); State v. Stewart, 272 S.E.2d 628, 629–30 (S.C. 1980); Collins v. State, 626 So. 2d 991, 992 (Fla. Dist. Ct. App. 1993); State v. Short, 698 S.W.2d 81, 83 (Tenn. Crim. App. 1985); State v. Maupin, 822 P.2d 355, 360–61 (Wash. Ct. App. 1992); State v. Mosley, 307 N.W.2d 200, 210 (Wis. 1981). 53 We believe the Court decided this issue correctly. The Sixth Amendment right to counsel attaches only after arraignment and should not be read to require a prosecutor to invite defense counsel to his office during the prosecutor’s pretrial preparations with an eyewitness. See supra note 31. This issue, however, is beyond the scope of this Article, and no further discussion of it is offered herein. 54 Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 815. 55 Id. 52 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 449 56 accuracy the way the Supreme Court believed they do. These five factors are also deficient because they do not include many other eyewitness factors that affect eyewitness accuracy.57 Additional serious flaws in Biggers and Brathwaite include that: (1) the decisions do not take into account how the eyewitness interviews impacted eyewitness accuracy; (2) the decisions mistakenly assume that in all cases it can be determined whether an identification from a suggestive identification procedure is reliable; (3) three of the criteria (certainty, view, and attention) are selfreported by the eyewitness, and a suggestive identification procedure can increase an eyewitness’s confidence, cause the eyewitness to believe that he or she paid more attention to the perpetrator during the crime, and had a better view of the crime than he or she actually had;58 and (4) the decisions ignore that both eyewitness memory and confidence are highly malleable.59 This theme is developed more fully in Parts III and VII of this Article. In sum, the due process standard and procedures the Supreme Court promulgated in Kirby, Ash, Biggers, and Brathwaite for assessing identification accuracy in criminal cases, including its five factor test, are seriously flawed and in fact may contribute to, rather than reduce, the number of wrongful convictions.60 In recognition of these flaws and shortcomings, a number of states have moved away from the Supreme Court’s due process approach.61 Some state courts, applying their state constitution’s due process clause, have revised the Biggers-Brathwaite standards.62 Other states have 56 Id. at 816–18. Id. at 818–19. Gary L. Wells & Deah S. Quinlivan, Suggestive Eyewitness Identification Procedures and the Supreme Court’s Reliability Test in Light of Eyewitness Science: 30 Years Later, 33 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 1, 1 (2009). 59 See discussion infra Part VI (addressing the importance of analyzing eyewitness interviews to determine if law enforcement obtained the maximum amount of information from the eyewitness, contaminated the eyewitness’s memory of the crime, or increased the eyewitness confidence, and why the harmful effects of a biased eyewitness interview or identification procedure cannot be corrected). 60 Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 819. 61 The discussion in the rest of this paragraph is based in part on Wells & Quinlivan, supra note 58, at 18–21. 62 For example, in State v. Long, Utah’s Supreme Court observed that “several of the criteria listed by the Court are based on assumptions that are flatly contradicted by well-respected and essentially unchallenged empirical studies.” 721 P.2d 483, 491 (Utah 1986). Relying on the due process clause of the state constitution, the court adopted a somewhat different list of factors: (1) the opportunity of the witness to view the actor during the event; (2) the witness’s degree of attention to the actor at the time of the event; (3) the witness’s capacity to observe the event, including his or her physical and mental acuity; (4) whether the witness’s identification was made spontaneously and remained consistent thereafter, or whether it was the product of suggestion; and (5) the nature of the event being observed and the likelihood that the witness would perceive, remember and relate it correctly. This last area includes such factors as whether the event was an ordinary one in the mind of the observer during the time it was observed, and whether the race of the actor was the same as the observer’s. 57 58 450 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 63 rejected the Kirby-Ash-Brathwaite due process doctrine and applied the Wade approach to all pretrial identification procedures, those conducted before as well as after the right to counsel has attached: If the pretrial procedure was unnecessarily suggestive, testimony about it is excluded per se, and the eyewitness is permitted to make an in-court identification only if the prosecution establishes by clear and convincing evidence that the eyewitness will be able to make the identification at trial based solely on his or her memory of the crime itself, independent of the suggestive pretrial procedure.64 As the rest of this Article demonstrates, this latter approach is much more consistent with what is now known about human memory and eyewitness identifications, and therefore is far more consistent with the ultimate goals of the criminal justice system: to convict those who are guilty, and avoid convicting those who are innocent.65 C. How Eyewitness Issues Are Litigated66 Soon after a defendant is arraigned, the defense attorney files a motion for discovery.67 Included in the motion is a request for information about Id. at 493. Although similar in some respects to the Biggers-Brathwaite list, this test differs dramatically in some ways. For example, it eliminates as a factor “the level of certainty demonstrated by the witness at the confrontation” and places much greater emphasis on the suggestiveness of the identification procedure. Neil v. Biggers, 409 U.S. 188, 199 (1972). In Long, the court held that the trial judge should instruct the jury about these factors in evaluating eyewitness identification. Long, 721 P.2d at 487. In State v. Ramirez, the Court held that if the identification procedure was highly suggestive, the trial judge should consider these factors in deciding whether to admit such testimony at all. 817 P.2d 774, 782–83 (Utah 1991). In State v. Hunt, the Kansas Supreme Court adopted Utah’s Ramirez approach. 69 P.3d 571, 576–77 (Kan. 2003). Massachusetts’s highest court likewise rejected the Biggers-Brathwaite factors. In Commonwealth v. Johnson, the court rejected Manson v. Brathwaite and instructed state courts to continue to apply the following factors: (1) the extent of the witness’s opportunity to observe the defendant at the time of the crime; prior errors, if any, in (2) description, (3) identifying another person, or in (4) failing to identify the defendant; (5) the receipt of other suggestions, and (6) the lapse of time between the crime and the identification. 650 N.E.2d 1257, 1261–62 (Mass. 1995). Thus, Massachusetts has also rejected the eyewitness’s degree of certainty as a relevant factor. 63 For discussion of this doctrine, see supra Part II.A.2. 64 Johnson, 650 N.E.2d at 1261; People v. Riley, 517 N.E.2d 520, 525 (N.Y. 1987); State v. Dubose, 699 N.W.2d 582, 596 (Wis. 2005); see also State v. Herrara, 902 A.2d 177, 182 (N.J. 2006) (hinting that the court considered the issue a valid one but declining to address it because the defendant had failed to raise it at trial). 65 Generally, if an eyewitness’s memory is contaminated by a suggestive or biased identification procedure, the error cannot be correct by subsequently conducting a fair lineup. See infra Parts V, IX. Consequently, there are very limited circumstances where the prosecutor will be able to show that the eyewitness’s in-court identification of the defendant is not tainted by the prior, biased out of court identification procedure. See infra Part V. 66 This section is based on Professor Fishman’s and Professor Wise’s experiences as prosecutors, and on Professor Fishman’s discussion of the matter with current prosecutors, defense attorneys, and judges, and his reading of more court opinions on the subject than he cares to remember, let alone count. The procedures described herein will vary slightly from jurisdiction to jurisdiction, but the basic outline is the same. 67 See, e.g., FED. R. CRIM. P. 16 (setting forth the rules for information subject to disclosure). 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 451 any and all pretrial identifications of the defendant by any eyewitness. In response, the prosecutor informs defense counsel of the details: which eyewitnesses identified the defendant, the kind of procedure used, and so on.68 At an appropriate time prior to trial, defense counsel moves to suppress the eyewitness evidence. Where there have been pretrial identifications, the motion will allege that the identifications were suggestive, and will lead to a misidentification at trial. The defense attorney will request that the judge suppress testimony about the pretrial identifications and also preclude the eyewitnesses from making in-court identifications.69 Often the judge will order a hearing on the motion.70 If the eyewitness testifies at the hearing,71 the prosecutor will ask the eyewitness questions designed to establish that the eyewitness had a good opportunity to see the perpetrator (e.g., time, lighting), to note his or her appearance, and to fix it firmly in the eyewitness’s mind.72 The prosecutor will then ask the eyewitness to describe the identification procedure, again structuring his or her questions to elicit the strongest impression of nonsuggestiveness that the facts legitimately allow. Ideally, the eyewitness will testify that as soon as he or she saw the defendant, the eyewitness recognized the defendant as the perpetrator, based on the eyewitness’s memory of seeing the defendant commit the crime; that the eyewitness was sure that his or her identification was accurate; and that he or she so informed the officer. On cross-examination, defense counsel will seek to undercut each aspect of the eyewitness’s direct testimony. Defense counsel may challenge the eyewitness’s estimation of how long he or she had an opportunity to view the defendant, and question whether the eyewitness’s powers of perception or memory were diminished by drink, drugs, lack of sleep, fear, focus on a weapon, or other distractions. The defense attorney may emphasize any discrepancies between the description the eyewitness 68 In some jurisdictions, prosecutors provide this information voluntarily, without requiring defense counsel to file a motion. 69 Defense counsel will file a motion to suppress whether the procedure involved was absurdly and unnecessarily suggestive, or apparently was as completely non-suggestive and as perfect as is humanly possible. This occurs because, even if the judge ultimately denies the motions to suppress (which, as every trial lawyer and judge knows, is the result in the vast majority of cases), a hearing on the motion will require the prosecutor to call at least some of his or her witnesses at the hearing, and give defense counsel an opportunity to cross-examine them—a type of pretrial discovery that, though common in civil litigation, is fairly unusual in criminal cases. 70 In some jurisdictions, the defendant is entitled to a hearing as a matter of course. In others, the judge will grant a hearing only if defense counsel first submits affidavits or other proof that make out a prima facie case that the pretrial identification was suggestive. 71 The prosecutor may decide not to call an eyewitness at the hearing to prevent the defense attorney from discovering the eyewitness’s testimony prior to trial, relying instead on the testimony of the police officers who conducted the identification procedure. Some jurisdictions, however, may permit the defense attorney to call the eyewitness to testify at the hearing if the prosecutor does not. 72 To the extent that it will be helpful, the prosecutor’s questions will track the reliability factors discussed by the Supreme Court in Biggers and Brathwaite. See supra text accompanying note 51. 452 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 gave to the police and the defendant’s actual appearance. Counsel may probe for evidence of suggestiveness in the lineup, showup, or photo identification. Counsel may question the eyewitness about any previous lineups, showups, or photo identifications at which the eyewitness picked out someone else as the perpetrator.73 If the procedure was a lineup, the prosecutor may introduce a photograph or video of the lineup to impress upon the judge that it was fair and non-suggestive. If the eyewitness was shown a number of photographs in addition to the defendant’s, the prosecutor, for the same reason, may introduce the entire photo array into evidence. Depending on the circumstances, one or more officers who conducted the identification procedure may also testify.74 If the identification procedure was a corporeal one, defense counsel may put the defendant on the stand at the hearing to contest the prosecutor’s version of how the lineup or showup was conducted. Occasionally, other eyewitnesses may be available to contradict the prosecutor’s eyewitnesses’ description of the identification procedure. After both sides rest and argue the issues, the judge, applying the appropriate standard (Wade-Gilbert or due process), will rule on what identification testimony, if any, the eyewitness will be permitted to give. D. Expert Testimony Regarding Eyewitness Identification For decades, psychologists and defense attorneys have maintained that eyewitness testimony can be notoriously unreliable, and courts, including the United States Supreme Court, have recognized this fact.75 The development of DNA evidence has confirmed what many observers and participants in the criminal justice system have long suspected, namely, that the number of innocent people who are convicted of crimes is distressingly high, and in many such cases, eyewitness identification testimony played a significant role in their wrongful convictions. To combat such testimony, defense attorneys have sought to introduce expert testimony outlining the weaknesses and shortcomings of eyewitness testimony.76 There is sharp division among courts whether such testimony meets the requirements governing expert evidence. As a general rule, expert testimony on any given subject is admissible 73 On the other hand, if it is obvious that the judge will deny the motion to suppress identification evidence at trial, defense counsel may not use some of this information at the hearing, hoping to surprise the eyewitness and the prosecutor with it at the trial itself. 74 If the prosecutor decides not to call the officer as a witness at the hearing, defense counsel may choose to do so. 75 See supra note 24 and accompanying text. 76 For a detailed discussion of the law governing admissibility of expert testimony concerning eyewitness identification, see CLIFFORD S. FISHMAN & ANNE T. MCKENNA, JONES ON EVIDENCE §§ 41:41–41:48 (7th ed., Appendix of New Chapters, 2008). 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 453 77 only if several criteria are satisfied. First, the subject matter of the testimony must be one recognized as a valid one for expert testimony, based on reliable principles and methodology.78 Second, the expert must be qualified as an expert on that subject.79 Third, the expert’s testimony must have an adequate factual basis.80 Fourth, the expert must apply “the principles and methods reliably to the facts of the case.”81 Finally, the testimony must “assist the trier of fact to understand the evidence or to determine a fact in issue . . . .”82 Courts generally accept that a properly qualified expert can satisfy the first four requirements.83 But many courts have been reluctant to admit expert testimony on the weaknesses of eyewitness testimony. Courts cite two reasons to justify this reluctance. First, many courts have held that that such testimony “will not aid the jury because it addresses an issue of which the jury already generally is aware, and it will not contribute to their understanding of the particular factual issues posed.”84 Second, comments can be found throughout the case law that the “proposed testimony intrudes too much on the traditional province of the jury to assess witness credibility.”85 The perceived risk, that the jury will be confused or place undue emphasis on the expert’s testimony, is therefore seen as outweighing what is viewed as the limited probative value of the evidence. Courts that accept this reasoning appear to give jurors both too much credit, and not enough. Such reasoning ignores scientific research showing that jurors have limited knowledge of eyewitness factors and that the effect of many factors on eyewitness accuracy is not a matter of common sense.86 It also reflects concern that wily experts will induce naïve and susceptible jurors to reject eyewitness testimony that is reliable. Furthermore, it ignores jurors’ tendency to be skeptical of experts, especially defense experts, whose testimony goes against what they consider simple common 77 See, e.g., FED. R. EVID. 702 (identifying the elements necessary for expert testimony to be admitted into evidence). 78 Thus, in the language of Federal Rule of Evidence 702, the subject of the testimony must consist of “scientific, technical, or other specialized knowledge [that is] . . . the product of reliable principles and methods . . . .” FED. R. EVID. 702. 79 See id. (“[The] witness [must be] qualified as an expert by knowledge, skill, experience, training, or education . . . .”). 80 See id. (“[T]he testimony [must be] based upon sufficient facts or data . . . .”). 81 Id. 82 Id. 83 See FISHMAN & MCKENNA, supra note 76, § 41:44. 84 United States v. Daniels, 64 F.3d 311, 315 (7th Cir. 1995) (quoting United States v. Larkin, 978 F.2d 964, 971 (7th Cir. 1992)); see also State v. Lawhorn, 762 S.W.2d 820, 823 (Mo. 1988) (“[T]he introduction of expert testimony would be ‘a superfluous attempt to put the gloss of expertise, like a bit of frosting, upon inferences which lay persons were equally capable of drawing from the evidence.” (citation omitted)). 85 United States v. Lumpkin, 192 F.3d 280, 289 (2d Cir. 1999). 86 Michael R. Leippe, The Case for Expert Testimony About Eyewitness Testimony, 1 PSYCHOL. PUB. POL’Y & L. 909, 921 (1995); Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 824–25. 454 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 87 sense. A number of courts, however, have held that it is an abuse of discretion to exclude expert testimony about eyewitness identifications where the prosecutor’s case rests solely or primarily on eyewitness identification, particularly if it is of uncertain accuracy or sharply contested.88 Furthermore, as Fishman and McKenna state: Even where a court is receptive to such testimony, it is generally agreed that the most that should be permitted is general testimony about the relevant types of difficulties with eyewitness testimony and that an expert witness should not be permitted to give an opinion on the accuracy of a particular eyewitness’s testimony, on the ground that such testimony constitutes impermissible comment on credibility.89 III. THE CAUSES OF EYEWITNESS ERROR There are several reasons why an eyewitness’s testimony can be erroneous even though, like Jennifer Thompson, the eyewitness is 87 CHARLES PATRICK EWING, TRIALS OF A FORENSIC PSYCHOLOGIST: A CASEBOOK 18 (2008) (“[I]n criminal trials jurors often regard prosecution witnesses as objective professionals doing a public service, while they see defense experts as hired guns who would say anything for the right amount of money.”). 88 See Skamarocius v. State, 731 P.2d 63, 66–67 (Alaska Ct. App. 1987) (noting that corroboration may come from substantial physical evidence or a codefendant’s confession); People v. McDonald, 690 P.2d 709, 726 (Cal. 1984) (en banc), overruled in part by People v. Mendoza, 4 P.3d 265 (Cal. 2000); People v. Sanders, 905 P.2d 420, 435 (Cal. 1995); Cook v. State, 734 N.E.2d 563, 571 (Ind. 2000); State v. Schutz, 579 N.W.2d 317, 320 (Iowa 1998) (holding that it is within the trial judge’s discretion to admit such testimony); Commonwealth v. Santoli, 680 N.E.2d 1116, 1119–20 (Mass. 1997) (noting that when corroborating evidence is available, the exclusion of expert testimony is not an abuse of discretion); State v. Abraham, 451 S.E.2d 131, 148–49 (N.C. 1994) (holding that where substantial evidence corroborates eyewitness identification, it is not an abuse of discretion to deny defense counsel’s request that the court appoint an expert witness on eyewitness identification); People v. Lee, 750 N.E.2d 63, 66–67 (N.Y. 2001) (holding that the trial judge has discretion to admit such testimony, and that where significant corroborating evidence exists, it is not an abuse of discretion to reject the expert’s testimony). Even in such cases, however, some courts have opined that problems with eyewitness identification testimony are unlikely to arise where the eyewitness is a police officer or someone else trained to observe and professionally accustomed to stressful situations. See, e.g., United States v. Langan, 263 F.3d 613, 624 (6th Cir. 2001). In Langan, the eyewitness had served in the Air Force National Guard where “she received training in identifying individuals attempting to enter unauthorized areas” and on “the need to remain calm and focused during the attempted takeovers.” Id. The court concluded that, “[i]n light of this specialized training, [the defense expert’s] generalized testimony regarding such distracting factors as stress and the presence of a gun would not necessarily have helped the jury in evaluating [the witness’s] identification of Langan.” Id. Similarly, in Webster v. United States, the court held that expert testimony should not be admitted where the eyewitness was an undercover police officer with considerable training in recognizing and identifying others. 623 A.2d 1198, 1204 n.15 (D.C. 1993). But see infra Part VIII.A.3. (stating that scientific research shows that police officers are no better at identifying perpetrators of crimes than lay eyewitnesses). 89 FISHMAN & MCKENNA, supra note 76, § 41:46 (citing State v. Nordstrom, 25 P.3d 717, 731 (Ariz. 2001) (en banc)); see also Johnson v. State, 526 S.E.2d 549, 553 n.3 (Ga. 2000); State v. Buell, 489 N.E.2d 795, 804 (Ohio 1986); State v Hubbard, 48 P.3d 953, 960 (Utah 2002). 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 455 testifying in good faith and with a high degree of confidence, and the police have attempted to conduct a fair and thorough investigation. A. The Nature of Human Memory Although human memory can be reasonably accurate, it does not work like a video camera.90 Consequently, an eyewitness’s memory of a crime is not stored liked a videotape that the eyewitness can replay to produce an exact record of the crime. It frequently does not contain the degree of detail sought by criminal investigators.91 Instead, when an eyewitness recalls a crime, he or she unconsciously reconstructs his or her memory of the crime.92 In unconsciously reconstructing his or her memory of the crime, the eyewitness unknowingly fills in the gaps in his or her factual memory of the crime based on such factors as the eyewitness’s expectations, attitude, beliefs, and knowledge of similar events.93 These different sources of information are automatically blended together in the 90 John C. Brigham & Robert K. Bothwell, The Ability of Prospective Jurors to Estimate the Accuracy of Eyewitness Identifications, 7 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 19, 20 (1983); John C. Brigham et al., Disputed Eyewitness Identification Evidence: Important Legal and Scientific Issues, 36 CT. REV. 12, 13 (1999) (“Contrary to popular belief, human perception does not work like a camera or video recorder. Rather, what is perceived and stored in memory is often incomplete or distorted as a result of the individual’s state of mind or nature of the event observed.”). 91 Daniel L. Schacter, The Seven Sins of Memory: Insights from Psychology and Cognitive Neuroscience, 54 AM. PSYCHOLOGIST 182, 197 (1999); see also Richard A. Wise et al., A Survey of Defense Attorneys’ Knowledge and Beliefs About Eyewitness Testimony, CHAMPION, Nov. 2007, at 23 (“Although memory can be reasonably accurate, it frequently does not contain the degree of detail sought by criminal investigators and is fragile and subject to changes in subtle ways by new information.”). 92 See CURT R. BARTOL & ANNE M. BARTOL, PSYCHOLOGY AND LAW: THEORY, RESEARCH AND APPLICATIONS 228 (3d ed. 2004). Bartol and Bartol state that: Memory, especially for complex or unusual events, involves the integration of perceptual information with preexisting experiences, as well as with other subjective relevant information that may be introduced later. In this sense, memory is very much a reconstructive, integrative process that develops with the flow of new experiences and thoughts. This perspective is called the reconstructive theory of memory. Id. 93 COSTANZO, supra note 1, at 180. For example, researchers conducted a study that determined that people have shared “scripts” for common types of crimes, such as a convenience store robbery, bank robbery, or mugging. “Scripts are widely held beliefs about sequences of actions that typically occur in particular situations.” Id. They found that people’s scripts for a convenience store robbery consist of the following elements: The robber cases the store, plans the robbery, enters the store, observes who is in the store, acts like a customer, waits for an opportunity, approaches the cash register, pulls out a gun, demands money, takes the money, exits the store, and drives away. Id. In a follow-up study, researchers had participants listen to a mock criminal trial that involved a convenience store robbery where evidence was omitted for three key elements: the casing of the store, using a gun, and taking the money. Id. Most participants in the study, nonetheless, erroneously recalled hearing evidence during the trial that indicated that the three missing elements occurred during the alleged crime. Id. This study demonstrates that an eyewitness’s expectations, attitudes, beliefs, and knowledge will influence what an eyewitness perceives, encodes, stores, and retrieves about a crime. Id. at 181; see also Wise & Safer, supra note 11, at 15 (stating that when witnesses recall crimes, they fill in the blanks with information based on expectancies and information obtained after the crime). 456 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 eyewitness’s memory to produce an account of the crime that is apparently seamless and coherent but that may contain inaccuracies.94 B. Eyewitness Bias An eyewitness’s expectations, attitudes, beliefs, and knowledge not only influence what an eyewitness recalls about a crime, but also what the eyewitness perceives about a crime.95 For example, if a hair stylist witnesses a crime, he or she may pay more attention to the perpetrator’s hair than other eyewitnesses would. In addition, these factors influence what an eyewitness encodes about a crime.96 Encoding refers to the process by which an eyewitness transforms what he or she perceives about a crime into a stored memory.97 Normally, the eyewitness is unaware of the process of encoding.98 Because encoding involves interpretation and inference, what is stored in memory is not just what the eyewitness saw during the crime, but also the meaning the eyewitness gave to what occurred.99 Furthermore, the meaning that an eyewitness gives to the crime is influenced by his or her expectations, attitudes, beliefs, and knowledge.100 Factors present during a crime such as a high level of stress, a weapon, or a disguise may further hamper an eyewitness’s ability to accurately encode important details of the crime.101 Forgetting the details of the crime can occur rapidly.102 New faces, pictures, and events experienced after the crime can also interfere with the eyewitness’s memory of the crime.103 94 See BARTOL & BARTOL, supra note 92, at 228 (“[E]ven the most well-intentioned eyewitnesses may err and unconsciously distort their recall and identification. In part, this explains the radically different accounts of the same event that are provided by witnesses who are ‘absolutely positive’ about what they saw.”). 95 Id.; Wise & Safer, supra note 11, at 8, 15. There are four stages to memory: perception, encoding, storage, and retrieval. EDIE GREENE ET AL., WRIGHTSMAN’S PSYCHOLOGY AND THE LEGAL SYSTEM 129–32 (6th ed. 2007). 96 See Wise & Safer, supra note 11, at 8 (“Expectancies can exert a powerful influence on attention and recall of relevant information.”). 97 WEITEN, supra note 14, at 205–06. 98 BARTOL & BARTOL, supra note 92, at 228. 99 Id. 100 Id. 101 See Kenneth A. Deffenbacher et al., A Meta-Analytic Review of the Effects of High Stress on Eyewitness Memory, 28 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 687, 694 (2004); K. E. Patterson & A. D. Baddeley, When Face Recognition Fails, 3 J. EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOL.: HUM. LEARNING & MEMORY 406, 410 (1977); Peter N. Shapiro & Steven D. Penrod, Meta-Analysis of Facial Identification Studies, 100 PSYCHOL. BULL. 139, 139–51 (1986); Nancy Mehrkens Steblay, A Meta-Analytic Review of the Weapon Focus Effect, 16 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 413, 414, 420–21 (1992). 102 See Kenneth A. Deffenbacher, A Maturing of Research on the Behaviour of Eyewitnesses, 5 APPLIED COGNITIVE PSYCHOL. 377, 381 (1991) (“With single-trace fragility theory, trace decay is by far the greater contributor to forgetting in the first minutes and hours after initial encounter of a face, but the amount of forgetting due to this source decreases per unit of time.”). 103 WEITEN, supra note 14, at 218. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 457 C. Misinformation Effect Because an eyewitness’s memory of a crime is a reconstructive process, it can be altered by information that the eyewitness learns after the crime from other sources such as other eyewitnesses, the police, the prosecutor, and the media.104 The eyewitness generally does not know that his or her memory of the crime has been changed and updated by postevent information, which may or may not be accurate.105 Moreover, the post-event information not only affects an eyewitness’s memory of the crime, but it may also impair his or her ability to identify the perpetrator of the crime.106 D. Source Monitoring Errors Eyewitnesses can become confused about where they learned information about a crime or where they saw an individual. Accordingly, eyewitnesses may misattribute information to observing a crime when in fact they learned it from another source such as the media, a police officer, a prosecutor, or another eyewitness.107 They also sometimes identify as the perpetrator of a crime an individual who was a bystander to the crime or whom they saw in another situation or context.108 For example, a rape victim identified a psychologist, Dr. Donald Thompson, as her rapist.109 At the time of the rape, however, Dr. Thompson was in a television studio giving a live interview, ironically, about the fallibility of eyewitness memory.110 The rape victim had seen part of the interview of Dr. 104 Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 844–45; see also BARTOL & BARTOL, supra note 92, at 229 (stating that police officers do not recognize that a person’s memory can be contaminated by “careless interviewing and misleading commentary”); Ronald P. Fisher, Interviewing Victims and Witnesses of Crime, 1 PSYCHOL. PUB. POL’Y & L. 732, 740 (1995) (“There is little argument, however, that the phenomenon of postevent suggestibility exists, that it is robust, and perhaps most important, that witnesses truly believe that they observed an event that was only suggested.”). 105 See BARTOL & BARTOL, supra note 92, at 228 (“Moreover, there are ample opportunities for witnesses to encounter additional information after the event and then integrate it unknowingly into their original memories.”). 106 See Elizabeth F. Loftus & Edith Greene, Warning: Even Memory for Faces May Be Contagious, 4 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 323, 333 (1980) (“The verbal expressions and other postevent information to which a witness is exposed will not only appear in the verbal reports of witnesses but will also influence future recognition of persons who have been seen before.”). 107 See Schacter, supra note 91, at 188 (“First, people may remember correctly an item or fact from a past experience but misattribute the fact to an incorrect source. For instance, individuals sometimes recall encountering a bit of trivia in the newspaper that, in fact, they acquired from the experimenter.”). 108 See, e.g., COSTANZO, supra note 1, at 178–79 (“Robert Buckhout, one of the first psychologists to conduct systematic research on eyewitnesses, staged a series of thefts and assaults in his classroom. Of the students who witnessed the mock crime, 39% showed the unconscious transference effect. These witnesses incorrectly identified a person who had been in the classroom the day of the crime.”) 109 Id. at 179. 110 Id. 458 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 Thompson and in her memory unconsciously transferred his face from the interview to the rape.111 E. Hindsight Bias When an individual knows how an event turned out, this knowledge affects both the individual’s memory of the event and his or her memory of what they were thinking when the event occurred.112 Therefore, once an eyewitness learns that a suspect has been indicted and is going to be tried for a crime, this information alters an eyewitness’s memory of the crime and what the eyewitness remembers about what he or she was thinking when the crime occurred.113 F. Eyewitness Overconfidence in the Accuracy of His or Her Perceptions and Memory and the Malleability of Eyewitness Confidence People tend to overestimate the accuracy of their perceptions and memory.114 Thus, eyewitnesses are likely to be overconfident about the accuracy of their account of the crime and their identification of the suspect as the perpetrator of the crime.115 In addition, not only is an eyewitness’s memory of a crime highly malleable, but so is an eyewitness’s confidence in the accuracy of his or her memory of the crime.116 Many factors can increase eyewitness confidence, but do not in any way improve the accuracy of an eyewitness’s identification.117 For instance, questioning of an eyewitness by the police and prosecutor, confirmation feedback from a lineup administrator (e.g., “Good! You have identified the suspect.”), and learning that another eyewitness has also identified the suspect all increase an eyewitness’s confidence but not his or 111 Id. WEITEN, supra note 14, at 230–31. 113 Id. 114 Id. at 231. 115 Id. 116 See Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 624 (“Confidence malleability refers to the tendency for an eyewitness to become more (or less) confident in his or her identification as a function of events that occur after the identification.”). 117 See Michael R. Leippe & Donna Eisenstadt, Eyewitness Confidence and the ConfidenceAccuracy Relationship in Memory for People, in 2 HANDBOOK OF EYEWITNESS PSYCHOLOGY, MEMORY FOR PEOPLE 377, 417–18 (Rod C. L. Lindsay et al. eds., 2007). Leippe and Eisenstadt write: The ready malleability of confidence by feedback, co-witness information, deliberate or inadvertent communication by police investigators, repeated questioning, lawyer briefings, and other events make it clear that confidence statements made following an immediate post-identification confidence judgment will inevitably be hopelessly undiagnostic of memory accuracy. Short of being restricted to a hermetically sealed room until the trial, it is hard to imagine an eyewitness not being subjected to manipulative influences on his or her confidence. Id.; see also Saul M. Kassin et al., On the “General Acceptance” of Eyewitness Testimony Research, A New Survey of the Experts, 56 AM. PSYCHOLOGIST 405, 410 (2001); Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 586. 112 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 459 118 her accuracy. Post-event information has its greatest effect on the eyewitness’s confidence in erroneous information.119 The eyewitness is generally unaware that his or her confidence has been increased by these factors.120 Furthermore, when the eyewitness is asked at trial how confident he or she was in the accuracy of the identification at the time of the lineup, the eyewitness tends to report his or her present level of confidence. Eyewitnesses tend to make this error because they cannot recall at trial how confident they were in the accuracy of their identification at the time they made it.121 Artificially increasing eyewitness confidence can cause wrongful convictions because studies show eyewitness confidence is generally the most important factor that the trier of fact relies on when evaluating the accuracy of eyewitness 118 See John S. Shaw III & Kimberley A. McClure, Repeated Postevent Questioning Can Lead to Elevated Levels of Eyewitness Confidence, 20 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 629, 630 (1996). Shaw and McClure state: For example, Wells, Ferguson, and Lindsay found that briefing witnesses about the nature of an impending cross-examination can lead to higher confidence ratings during the subsequent examination, and Luus and Wells demonstrated that providing information to an eyewitness about a co-witness’s identification decision (e.g., whom the witness picked from a lineup) can alter that eyewitness’s confidence about her or his own choice. Recent research by Shaw suggests that a common police investigation procedure—repeated questioning of witnesses—may also result in changes in witness confidence independently of eyewitness accuracy. Id. (internal citations omitted); see also Gary L. Wells & Amy L. Bradfield, “Good, You Identified the Suspect”: Feedback to Eyewitnesses Distorts Their Reports of the Witnessing Experience, 83 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 360, 374 (1998). “[A] casual comment from a lineup administrator following eyewitnesses’ identification can have dramatic effects on their reconstructions of the witnessing and identification experience.” Id. For example, such a comment caused the witness to state that the defendant’s face “just ‘popped out’ to them, that their memorial image of the gunman is particularly clear, and that they are adept at recognizing faces of strangers. These effects were very robust, with effect sizes that exceed what are normally considered large effects in psychology.” Id. 119 See Donald P. Judges, Two Cheers for the Department of Justice’s Eyewitness Evidence: A Guide for Law Enforcement, 53 ARK. L. REV. 231, 249 (2000) (“Research has found that the confidence-inflating impact of post-event questioning was the largest for inaccurate responses, including responses to questions about the witnesses’ memory for an object that did not even exist in the original event. . . .”). 120 Wells & Bradfield, supra note 118, at 373. 121 Id. at 362. Wells states that: That is, eyewitnesses do not form clear impressions at the time of the event about how good or poor their view is, how much attention they are paying, how confident they are in their identification, and so on. Instead, people’s memories for cognitive processes operating during an event (in this case the witnessed event as well as the event of making an identification) are, like other memories, reconstructions. Hence, answers to these questions are postcomputed (later) by eyewitnesses when the relevant question is asked of them. When later asked to judge how good their view was, for example, the eyewitness does not recall an impression or judgment but rather forms one. Id.; see also Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 635–36 (“The only way to know how confident the eyewitness was at the time of the identification is to have asked the eyewitness at the time of the identification.”). 460 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW testimony. [Vol. 42:435 122 G. Eyewitnesses Tend to Make a Relative Judgment in Making an Identification Eyewitnesses are likely to make a relative judgment when they select a lineup participant,123 particularly when law enforcement uses a simultaneous lineup (where all lineup participants are presented at once) rather than a sequential lineup (where lineup participants are presented individually).124 In other words, eyewitnesses generally select the lineup participant who most closely resembles their memory of the perpetrator of the crime.125 A sequential lineup is more likely to prompt the eyewitness to compare each participant in the lineup to the eyewitness’s memory of the perpetrator of the crime (i.e., make an absolute judgment), rather than compare the participants to each other (i.e., make a relative judgment).126 Relative judgments frequently result in erroneous eyewitness identification, especially in lineups that do not include the perpetrator of the crime.127 Eyewitnesses tend to make relative judgments for several 122 Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 620 (stating that eyewitness confidence “is the most powerful single determinant of whether or not observers of that testimony will believe that the eyewitness made an accurate identification”). 123 Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 585–86. 124 See id. (“The standard police lineup presents the eyewitness with all lineup members (e.g., six or eight persons) at one time. Under these conditions, eyewitnesses tend to compare lineup members with each other to determine which one most closely resembles the perpetrator relative to the others, a process called relative judgment.”). In contrast, sequential lineups decreased the probability that the eyewitness will make a relative judgment: In sequential lineups, the witness views the lineup members one at a time and is asked to make an identification decision after viewing each one. The witness is instructed that each lineup member will be presented only once and is not told how many lineup members will be presented. The lineup stops when the witness identifies someone or has seen all the lineup members without identifying anyone. Reliably fewer false identifications are obtained with sequential than with simultaneous presentation. Veronica Stinson et al., How Effective Is the Motion-to-Suppress Safeguard? Judges’ Perceptions of the Suggestiveness and Fairness of Biased Lineup Procedures, 82 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 211, 212 (1997); see also discussion infra Part VII.6. (discussing sequential lineups). 125 Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 613 (“There is good empirical evidence to indicate that eyewitnesses tend to identify the person from the lineup who, in the opinion of the eyewitness, looks most like the culprit relative to the other members of the lineup.”). 126 In one study, Lindsay and Wells found that: Although the eyewitness [viewing a sequential lineup] could decide that the person being viewed currently looks more like the perpetrator than did the previous person, the eyewitness cannot be sure that the next (not yet viewed) person does not look even more like the perpetrator than did the one being viewed currently. Lindsay and Wells reasoned that this would force eyewitnesses to use a more absolute criterion (i.e., “Is this the perpetrator or not?”) rather than the relative-judgment criterion (i.e., “Is the person more similar to the perpetrator than the other lineup members?”). Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 586. 127 See Rudolf Koch, Note, Process v. Outcome: The Proper Role of Corroborative Evidence in Due Process Analysis of Eyewitness Identification Testimony, 88 CORNELL L. REV. 1097, 1104–05 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 461 reasons. First, they logically assume that law enforcement would not conduct a lineup if they did not have a suspect.128 Second, many eyewitnesses feel pressure from law enforcement, relatives, friends, and themselves to make an identification.129 In addition, many eyewitnesses feel like a failure if they cannot make an identification during an identification procedure.130 H. Lineups Are Frequently Conducted in a Manner that Draws the Eyewitness’s Attention to the Suspect (e.g., The Lineup-as-Experiment Analogy) Scientists have long known that safeguards are necessary to ensure that they do not unintentionally influence participants in an experiment.131 Unintentional influence is often a problem because people unconsciously tend to test their hypotheses in a manner that confirms them and because of the self-fulfilling nature of expectations.132 Thus, scientists implement safeguards to ensure that the results of their experiments are the product of the independent variable (i.e., the variable the experimenter manipulates to try to produce an effect) and not the experimenter’s bias or some other extraneous factor.133 By analogy, in lineups, the “independent variable” is the eyewitness’s memory and the desired result is that the eyewitness either does or does not identify the suspect as the perpetrator of the crime based solely on his or her memory of the perpetrator of the crime. Professors Garrioch and Brimacombe explain how a lineup administrator’s bias that the suspect is the perpetrator can affect the fairness of a lineup: Like a researcher with a specific hypothesis (i.e., that a particular lineup [participant] is the suspect), the detective is (2003) (stating that erroneous eyewitness identifications decreased forty-three percent when eyewitnesses were warned prior to the lineup that the perpetrator might not be in the lineup). 128 See Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 630. 129 Brigham et al., supra note 90, at 15. 130 Gunter Koehnken et al., Forensic Application of Line-Up Research, in PSYCHOLOGICAL ISSUES IN EYEWITNESS IDENTIFICATION 205, 208–09 (Sigfried Ludwig Sporer et al. eds., 1996). 131 See Judges, supra note 119, at 249–50. 132 Bradfield et al., supra note 12, at 118 (stating that in scientific research, “[t]he only acceptable safeguard became the ‘double-blind’ experiment, in which neither the experimenter nor the participant knew what the hypothesis was” and that this safeguard is necessary to prevent the experimenter from unintentionally influencing the participant to respond in a manner that was consistent with the experimental hypothesis). 133 See Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 627 (“The confirmation bias in human reasoning and behavior is the seed that gives birth to the self-fulfilling prophecy phenomenon in which a person’s assumption that a phenomenon will happen leads to behaviors that tend to make the phenomenon happen.”); WEITEN, supra note 14, at 38 (“An independent variable is a condition or event that an experimenter varies in order to see its impact on another variable.”); see also id. at 38–40, 48–50 (noting safeguards that scientists use to ensure that the results of experiments are not influenced by the experimenter’s bias). 462 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 now in a position to exert tremendous influence in administering the lineup. A lineup administrator’s knowledge of the suspect’s identity can increase the likelihood that the witness will identify the suspect.134 Professor Wells and his colleagues further elaborate on how lineups resemble experiments: [T]he police have a hypothesis (that the suspect is the culprit); they collect materials that could be used to test the hypothesis (e.g., picture of the suspect and filler pictures), they create a design (e.g., placing suspect’s picture in a particular position in an array), instruct the subject(s) (eyewitness or eyewitnesses); run the procedure (show the lineup to the eyewitness), record the data (identification of the suspect or not); and interpret the hypothesis in light of the data (decide whether the identification decision changes their assessment of whether the suspect is the culprit).135 The lineup-as-experiment analogy helps us to identify procedural errors in lineups that are likely to cause eyewitness misidentifications. They include: [T]he presence of demand characteristics (e.g., pressuring the eyewitness to make a choice), the influence of confirmation biases (e.g., asking the eyewitness specifically about the suspect while not asking those same questions about the distractors), the facilitation of response biases (e.g., encouraging a loose recognition criterion threshold in the eyewitness), making inferences from small sample sizes (e.g., making strong judgments of validity based on only one eyewitness), not using control groups (e.g., failing to see if even people who did not witness the crime [but who have the eyewitness’s description of the perpetrator] can identify the suspect),[136] selective recording and interpretation of data (e.g., finding significance in an identification of the suspect, but ignoring the outcome if the eyewitness makes a nonidentification), leaking of the hypothesis (e.g., making it 134 Lynn Garrioch & C.A. Elizabeth Brimacombe, Lineup Administrators’ Expectations: Their Impact on Eyewitness Confidence, 25 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 299, 300 (2001) (internal citations omitted). 135 Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 618. 136 Id. Among other concerns, Wells and his colleagues mention the use of “mock witnesses” as a solution to the problem of biased lineups: “Mock witnesses are people who have never seen the culprit but are given the eyewitness’s verbal description of the culprit, shown a picture of the lineup or photospread, and asked to select the person they think is the suspect in the case.” Id. at 631. If after reading the eyewitness’s description of the perpetrator the mock witnesses select the suspect from the photo array at greater levels than chance, the lineup is likely biased. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 463 obvious to the eyewitness which person in the lineup is the suspect), and a host of other possible confounds.137 Accordingly, to avoid eyewitness error, law enforcement must conduct lineups so that an eyewitness identification of a suspect is a product of the eyewitness’s memory and not how the lineup was conducted.138 It is also useful to view eyewitness evidence as a type of trace evidence such as fingerprints, DNA, and firearm patterns.139 Similar to other types of trace evidence, eyewitness evidence has a physiological basis (i.e., biochemical changes in the eyewitness’s brain).140 Therefore, its accuracy depends in part on the use of proper scientific procedures to extract the evidence.141 In sum, before ruling on the admission of eyewitness evidence at trial, a judge should evaluate whether proper scientific procedures were used in collecting it, and if they were not used, that fact should weigh heavily against admitting the testimony.142 Unfortunately, as is discussed below, most lineups do not comply with scientific guidelines for conducting fair and unbiased lineups nor does law enforcement generally follow scientific guidelines when engaged in other procedures for collecting eyewitness evidence, such as eyewitness interviews.143 I. Lack of Knowledge of Memory and Eyewitness Factors Police officers, attorneys, judges, and jurors lack knowledge about how memory works and how eyewitness factors affect identification 137 Id. at 618. See id. at 618–19 (noting the importance of proper extraction of an eyewitness’s memory). 139 See id. at 618 (“Some forms of forensic evidence, such as fingerprints, DNA, and firearms patterns are subject to criticism for not following scientific principles in the collection and analysis of the evidence. We see no reason why eyewitness identification evidence should not be treated in a similar fashion.”). 140 For example: Eyewitness evidence can be construed as a type of trace evidence except that, unlike blood or fingerprints, the trace is in the brain of a human observer in the form of a memory. This memory trace even has some physical properties in the sense of being located as a neurological trace in the brain. Like physical evidence, the critical issue is how to extract the evidence in a way that is maximally diagnostic of identity. Id. at 618–19. 141 Id. 142 See id. at 617–19 (analogizing good methods for conducting an experiment with good methods for conducting lineups); see also Wells & Quinlivan, supra note 58, at 21 (“Today, police carry out very complex evidence collection procedures with physical evidence such as blood, hair, and fiber that have to conform to precise protocols and careful documentation. Clearly, police would be capable of carrying out careful non-suggestive protocols with eyewitness identification evidence as well if courts were more assertive in demanding it.”). 143 Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 604; Ronald P. Fisher & Nadja Schreiber, Interview Protocols to Improve Eyewitness Memory, in 1 HANDBOOK OF EYEWITNESS PSYCHOLOGY: MEMORY FOR EVENTS 53, 55 (Michael P. Toglia et al. eds., 2007). 138 464 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 144 accuracy. Their lack of knowledge about the nature of memory and eyewitness factors makes it difficult for them to prevent eyewitness error and to determine when it has occurred.145 IV. WHY JUDGES AND ATTORNEYS NEED A METHOD FOR ASSESSING EYEWITNESS ACCURACY IN CRIMINAL CASES It is vital that judges, prosecutors, and defense attorneys know how to correctly evaluate the accuracy of eyewitness testimony. Such knowledge is essential so that they can properly assess the probative value of eyewitness testimony in criminal cases and help prevent wrongful convictions that might result from erroneous eyewitness testimony. For example, trial judges need this skill when determining if they should admit testimony about a pretrial eyewitness identification, allow an in-court identification by the eyewitness, admit eyewitness expert testimony, permit other legal safeguards to educate jurors about eyewitness testimony, in ruling on eyewitness evidentiary issues, and in bench trials when they must evaluate the accuracy of eyewitness testimony.146 Appellate judges must know how to evaluate the accuracy of eyewitness testimony when they decide if the trial court abused its discretion by excluding expert testimony about potential weaknesses of eyewitness testimony. Such knowledge will also help appellate judges determine whether the eyewitness testimony in a case is sufficiently reliable to affirm a guilty verdict on appeal. Prosecutors have to assess if the eyewitness testimony in a case is sufficiently accurate to indict a suspect and take a case to trial.147 Prosecutors also need this skill when preparing the state’s eyewitnesses for cross-examination, arguing eyewitness evidentiary issues, and attempting to persuade the trier-of-fact that the state’s eyewitness testimony is reliable.148 Knowing how to evaluate the accuracy of eyewitness testimony is also 144 Tanja Rapus Benton et al., Has Eyewitness Testimony Research Penetrated the American Legal System? A Synthesis of Case History, Juror Knowledge, and Expert Testimony, in 2 HANDBOOK OF EYEWITNESS PSYCHOLOGY: MEMORY FOR PEOPLE 453, 475–76, 484–87 (Rod C. L. Lindsay et al. eds., 2007). 145 See Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 843–48 (discussing common errors that law officers make during eyewitness identification procedures). Wise et al., as part of their tripartite solution to eyewitness error, advocate educating the principal participants in the criminal justice system about eyewitness testimony to sensitize them to the effects of error. Id. at 822. They also describe the many benefits that would accrue to the criminal justice system if the principal participants in the criminal justice system were knowledgeable about eyewitness testimony. Id. at 866–67. 146 GREENE ET AL., supra note 95, at 144. 147 Cf. Richard A. Wise et al., What US Prosecutors and Defense Attorneys Know and Believe About Eyewitness Testimony, 23 APPLIED COGNITIVE PSYCHOL. 1266 (2009) (describing a study involving prosecutors and defense attorneys and finding that prosecutors often overestimate the reliability of eyewitness testimony and jurors’ knowledge of eyewitness testimony). 148 Id. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 465 critical to defense attorneys. This knowledge will enable them to more effectively cross-examine an eyewitness at a pretrial identification hearing and at trial, advise a defendant whether to accept a plea bargain, decide whether to offer an eyewitness expert at trial, and argue to the trier of fact that the state’s eyewitness testimony in a case is unreliable or wrong.149 Although the ability to evaluate the accuracy of eyewitness testimony is essential to legal professionals, scientific studies show that prosecutors,150 defense attorneys,151 and even judges have limited knowledge of eyewitness factors.152 For example, Wise and Safer surveyed 160 judges about a wide range of eyewitness factors and procedures that affect identification accuracy.153 Some of the questions in the survey were the same or similar to those used in an earlier survey of eyewitness experts.154 For those questions, the judges’ answers were compared to experts’ answers.155 The judges also indicated for a subset of questions how they believed the average juror would respond to the question and what legal safeguards they would permit attorneys to use to educate jurors about eyewitness factors.156 These latter questions are important because research has consistently shown that jurors are unaware of many of the factors that affect identification accuracy and cannot distinguish between accurate and inaccurate eyewitnesses.157 Yet one of 149 See supra Part II.C. (discussing how eyewitness issues are litigated). John C. Brigham & Melissa P. WolfsKeil, Opinions of Attorneys and Law Enforcement Personnel on the Accuracy of Eyewitness Identifications, 7 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 337, 346 (1983) (“In general, prosecuting attorneys and law enforcement officers were similar in their responses to most of the survey questions. These individuals consistently indicated that they regard eyewitness identification as relatively accurate and feel that its importance is appropriately emphasized by judges and jurors.”); Wise et al., A Survey, supra note 91, at 20. 151 See Brigham & WolfsKeil, supra note 150, at 342–47; George L. Rahaim & Stanley L. Brodsky, Empirical Evidence Versus Common Sense: Juror and Lawyer Knowledge of Eyewitness Accuracy, 7 L. & PSYCHOL. REV. 1, 8–11 (1982); Veronica Stinson et al., How Effective Is the Presence-of-Counsel Safeguard? Attorney Perceptions of Suggestiveness, Fairness, and Correctability of Biased Lineup Procedures, 81 J. APPLIED PSCHOL. 64, 72 (1996); Wise et al., A Survey, supra note 91, at 22; A. Daniel Yarmey & Hazel P. Jones, Is the Psychology of Eyewitness Identification a Matter of Common Sense?, in EVALUATING WITNESS EVIDENCE 37–39 (Sally M.A. Lloyd-Bostock & Brian R. Clifford eds., 1983). 152 Wise & Safer, supra note 11, at 13. 153 Id. at 7. 154 Id. at 8. 155 Id. at 9–11. 156 Id. at 8. 157 See John C. Brigham & Robert K. Bothwell, The Ability of Prospective Jurors to Estimate the Accuracy of Eyewitness Identifications, 7 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 19, 29 (1983) (finding that jurors would benefit from eyewitness expert testimony on eyewitness factors); Thomas Dillickrath, Expert Testimony on Eyewitness Identification: Admissibility and Alternatives, 55 U. MIAMI L. REV. 1059, 1062–63 (2001) (advocating for expert testimony given jurors’ general lack of knowledge of eyewitness testimony); Saul M. Kassin & Kimberly A. Barndollar, The Psychology of Eyewitness Testimony: A Comparison of Experts and Prospective Jurors, 22 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 1241, 1243–45 (1992) (showing that student mock jurors’ answers in a study were significantly different from those of eyewitness experts); R. C. L. Lindsay et al., Mock Juror Belief of Accurate and Inaccurate Witnesses, 13 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 333, 337–38 (1989) (discussing a study in which mock jurors were unable to 150 466 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 the most common reasons judges exclude eyewitness expert testimony at trial is their beliefs that jurors are knowledgeable about eyewitness factors.158 The study showed that the judges had limited knowledge of eyewitness testimony as they averaged only fifty-five percent correct on the fourteenitem knowledge scale.159 Thus, many judges in the survey were unaware that eyewitness confidence is not related to eyewitness accuracy at trial, that sequential lineups are more effective than simultaneous lineups in reducing erroneous eyewitness identifications, and that several studies indicate jurors cannot differentiate between accurate and inaccurate eyewitness testimony.160 The judges’ answers compared to those of the eyewitness experts differed significantly on five of the eight questions where they answered the same or similar questions.161 In addition, the judges were substantially less skeptical than the experts of jurors’ distinguish between accurate and inaccurate eyewitnesses). Scientific studies have delineated the deficiencies in jurors’ knowledge of eyewitness testimony: Using a variety of methods to test jurors’ knowledge of eyewitnesses, researchers have found that: (1) jurors have limited knowledge of the factors that influence eyewitness accuracy, such as the effects of the perpetrator wearing a hat or using a weapon on identification accuracy; (2) jurors rely on factors which are not good indicators of eyewitness accuracy, such as eyewitness confidence, memory for minor or trivial details, and inconsistencies in eyewitness testimony; (3) jurors overestimate the ability of eyewitnesses to make accurate identifications; and (4) jurors in mock trials cannot distinguish accurate from inaccurate eyewitnesses. Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 824–25. 158 For a discussion of the reasons courts generally give for excluding eyewitness expert testimony, see FISHMAN & MCKENNA, supra note 76, §§ 40:22–40:25. Leippe, supra note 86, at 911– 12; and Gregory G. Sarno, Annotation, Admissibility, at Criminal Prosecution, of Expert Testimony on Reliability of Eyewitness Testimony, 46 A.L.R. 4TH 1047, 1054–58 (1986). Judges are hostile to eyewitness expert testimony for several reasons: First, they are not knowledgeable about eyewitness testimony, and therefore do not realize that the effect of many eyewitness factors on identification accuracy is not a matter of common sense. They also appear to be concerned about the time and expense that would result from permitting expert testimony. Finally, they seem to believe that jurors will perfunctorily follow the opinion of the expert resulting in guilty defendants going free. Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 823 n.121; see also United States v. Daniels, 64 F.3d 311, 315 (7th Cir. 1995) (citing United States v. Larkin, 978 F.2d 964, 971 (7th Cir. 1992)) (“[B]ecause it addresses an issue of which the jury already generally is aware . . . it will not contribute to their understanding of the particular factual issue posed.”). 159 Wise & Safer, supra note 11, at 13. In a follow-up study, undergraduates and law students completed the same eyewitness questionnaire that was administered to the judges. Richard A. Wise & Martin A. Safer, A Comparison of What U.S. Judges and Students Know and Believe About Eyewitness Testimony, J. APPLIED SOC. PSYCHOL. (forthcoming) (on file with authors). The results of the study showed that judges were no more knowledgeable about eyewitness testimony than the undergraduates and slightly less knowledgeable than the law students. Id. These results occurred even though the judges on average had practiced law for fourteen years, been on the bench for twelve years, and seventy-six percent of judges had been a prosecutor, defense attorney, or both prior to becoming a judge. Id. 160 Wise & Safer, supra note 11, at 9–11, 13; see also discussion infra Part VII.6. (noting the importance of using sequential lineups). 161 Wise & Safer, supra note 11, at 9–11. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 467 162 knowledge of eyewitness testimony. The judges in the survey were reluctant to permit expert testimony to educate jurors about eyewitness testimony even though expert testimony is the only legal safeguard that has demonstrated any effectiveness in educating jurors about eyewitness testimony.163 Other studies of judges’ knowledge of eyewitness testimony have yielded similar results.164 Attorneys’ and judges’ lack of knowledge of eyewitness testimony is not surprising. The effect of many of these eyewitness factors on eyewitness accuracy is not a matter of common sense, and in fact may be quite counter-intuitive, and attorneys and judges receive little training about eyewitness testimony.165 Moreover, even experienced judges and attorneys are unaware of these factors, probably because they do not receive feedback on which eyewitnesses gave inaccurate testimony during trials and what eyewitness factors caused their inaccuracies.166 Furthermore, even if judges and attorneys were knowledgeable about eyewitness factors, it would still be difficult for them to assess the accuracy of eyewitness testimony. This result would likely occur because the ability to assess accuracy of eyewitness testimony is not just a matter of knowledge but also of integration.167 Integration is the ability to apply relevant knowledge when making a decision.168 As Cutler and Penrod 162 See id. at 11. Id. See Tanja Rapus Benton et al., Eyewitness Memory Is Still Not Common Sense: Comparing Jurors, Judges, and Law Enforcement to Eyewitness Experts, 20 APPLIED COGNITIVE PSYCHOL. 115, 126 (2006) (finding that jurors, judges, and law enforcement officers had limited knowledge of eyewitness testimony); Pär Anders Granhag et al., Eyewitness Testimony: Tracing the Beliefs of Swedish Professionals, 23 BEHAV. SCI. & L. 709, 723 (2005); Svein Magnussen et al., What Judges Know About Eyewitness Testimony: A Comparison of Norwegian and US Judges, 14 PSYCHOL. CRIME & L. 177, 185 (2008) (“The results of the present study, in conjunction with the Wise and Safer study, show that judges in Norway and the US have limited knowledge of eyewitness factors, and they harbour beliefs and opinions that are at odds with current scientific knowledge as defined by the opinions of eyewitness experts.” (citations omitted)). 165 See Wise & Safer, supra note 11, at 13 (finding that seventy-five percent of judges thought they should receive more training on eyewitness testimony). 166 Id. 167 Brian L. Cutler et al., The Eyewitness, the Expert Psychologist, and the Jury, 13 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 311, 313 (1989). 168 Cutler also states: Sensitivity comprises two components: knowledge and integration. Knowledge refers to awareness how units of information should be combined to form a judgment; for example, knowledge of what witnessing and identification factors are important and how these factors should be combined in the evaluation of eyewitness identification accuracy. Integration refers to the ability to form judgments that reflect the unit combinatorial scheme about which the judge is knowledgeable; for example, ability to integrate eyewitness evidence in accordance with the judge’s knowledge of what witnessing and identification factors are important. Theoretically, knowledge and integration skills can vary independently. Id. The method for analyzing eyewitness testimony described in this Article not only informs attorneys and judges about many different types of factors that affect eyewitness accuracy, but it also helps them 163 164 468 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 note, decision making research in a variety of psychological domains shows that integration is quite difficult to achieve, even by trained experts.169 Accordingly, what judges and attorneys need to assess the accuracy of eyewitness testimony is not merely greater knowledge about eyewitness testimony, but also a method of analyzing eyewitness testimony that enables them to apply the relevant eyewitness factors to the facts of a case. That is what this Article offers. TABLE 1: METHOD FOR ANALYZING THE ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY Step 1: Evaluating the Eyewitness Interviews A. Did the interviews obtain the maximum amount of information from the eyewitness? B. Did the interviews contaminate the eyewitness’s memory? 1. Did they contaminate the eyewitness’s memory of the crime? 2. Did they contaminate the eyewitness’s memory of the perpetrator of the crime? C. Did the interviews, identification procedures, other eyewitnesses, the prosecutor, the media, or some other factor significantly increase the confidence of the eyewitness prior to taking a statement of the eyewitness’s confidence in the accuracy of his or her identification? Step 2: Evaluating the Identification Procedures and Identification Accuracy A. Did one of the following circumstances occur that would make the eyewitness’s identification of the defendant presumptively inaccurate? 1. Was the eyewitness interview significantly biased and did the bias pertain to information concerning the description or identity of the perpetrator? 2. Was an identification procedure significantly biased? overcome the problem of integrating that knowledge into their analyses of eyewitness accuracy. See discussion infra Part V (describing the method for analyzing eyewitness testimony). 169 Steven D. Penrod & Brian Cutler, Preventing Mistaken Convictions in Eyewitness Identification Trials, The Case Against Traditional Safeguards, in 10 PSYCHOLOGY AND LAW, THE STATE OF THE DISCIPLINE 89, 114 (Ronald Roesch et al. eds., 1999). 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY B. Because of the nature of memory, the effects of biased interviews and identification procedures on identification accuracy cannot be corrected by later conducting a fair interview and identification procedure. Accordingly, if an eyewitness’s memory of the perpetrator of a crime has been significantly contaminated, identification by the eyewitness of the defendant should be considered presumptively inaccurate. C. Does one of the two exceptions apply to the general rule that an eyewitness’s identification is presumptively inaccurate if an eyewitness interview or identification procedure was significantly biased? 1. Did some unusual circumstance exist that overcomes the presumptive inaccuracy of the identification (e.g., the eyewitness knew the perpetrator prior to the crime or had prolonged repeated exposure to the perpetrator)? 2. Was there reliable, valid corroborating evidence that establishes the veracity of the eyewitness testimony? D. Were the eyewitness interviews and identification procedures fair and impartial or did one of the exceptions to biased interviews and identification procedures apply? If so, go on to Step 3. If not, the eyewitness’s identification should be presumed to be inaccurate. Step 3: Evaluating the Eyewitness Factors Present During the Crime A. What eyewitness factors during the crime likely increased the accuracy of the eyewitness identification and testimony? B. What eyewitness factors during the crime likely decreased the accuracy of the eyewitness identification and testimony? Step 4: Conclusions A. Was the maximum amount of information obtained from the eyewitness during the interviews? B. Was a statement of the eyewitness’s confidence in the accuracy of his or her identification obtained prior to the eyewitness receiving any feedback? C. Is there a high, medium, or low probability that the eyewitness’s testimony was accurate? D. Is there a high, medium, or low probability that the eyewitness identification was accurate? 469 470 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 V. A METHOD FOR ANALYZING THE ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY Professor Wise has developed a method of analyzing eyewitness testimony that enables judges and attorneys to apply the relevant eyewitness factors to the facts of the case so they can better evaluate the accuracy of eyewitness testimony. This method of analyzing eyewitness testimony consists of three components. First, judges and attorneys determine if law enforcement officials (a) conducted the eyewitness interviews in a manner that obtained the maximum amount of information from the eyewitness; (b) did not contaminate the eyewitness’s memory of the crime with post-event information; or (c) artificially increased the eyewitness’s confidence. (See Table l, Step 1) Obtaining the maximum amount of accurate information from eyewitnesses is an important factor in preventing wrongful convictions. For instance, a comprehensive study of criminal investigations by the Rand Corporation indicated that the most important determinant of whether a case is solved is the completeness and accuracy of the eyewitness testimony in the case.170 In addition, the trier of fact is more likely to render a correct verdict if detailed and accurate accounts of the crime are presented at trial.171 Detailed and accurate eyewitness accounts further contribute to the just resolution of criminal cases because they help law enforcement obtain confessions from guilty suspects and also permit defense attorneys to more effectively represent innocent defendants.172 (See Table 1, Step 1.A.) Assessing whether law enforcement interviews have contaminated an eyewitness’s memory with post-event information is vital because scientific research shows that post-event information not only affects an eyewitness’s verbal reports of the crime, but also his or her ability to recognize the perpetrator of a crime.173 (See Table 1, Step 1.B.2.) Determining whether an eyewitness’s confidence has been artificially increased during an interview, an identification procedure, or by other means, is also essential. If this has occurred prior to taking a statement of the eyewitness’s confidence in the accuracy of his or her identification, the statement of confidence has little or no probative value in assessing 170 Fisher, supra note 104, at 732; Fisher & Schreiber, supra note 143, at 53. Fisher, supra note 104, at 732. 172 See id. (“On the one hand, it reduces the need to conduct extensive interrogations with suspects, because they are more likely to admit guilt when faced with thorough eyewitness information . . . . On the other hand, the more evidence defense attorneys can marshal, the better they can defend their clients. In short, all concerned profit from having more complete and accurate eyewitness evidence.” (citations omitted)). 173 Loftus & Greene, supra note 106, at 333. 171 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 471 174 identification accuracy. Because eyewitness confidence is the factor that jurors and judges rely on most heavily when evaluating the accuracy of eyewitness testimony, they need to know when the eyewitness’s confidence has been artificially increased by a law enforcement interview or other means prior to taking a statement of the eyewitness’s confidence in the accuracy of his or her identification.175 (See Table 1, Step 1.C.) Scientific guidelines for evaluating the fairness and completeness of eyewitness interviews are discussed below.176 The second component of the method for analyzing eyewitness accuracy is for judges and attorneys to ascertain if the identification procedures in the case were fair and unbiased. (See Table 1, Step 2) This assessment can be made by applying the scientific principles that are delineated later in this Article.177 The final component of the method for analyzing eyewitness accuracy requires judges and attorneys to evaluate which eyewitness factors during the crime likely increased or decreased the accuracy of the eyewitness testimony and identification. (See Table 1, Steps 3.A.–B.) A list of the most common eyewitness factors that affect eyewitness accuracy during a crime are described in a subsequent section.178 If judges or attorneys determine that the eyewitness interview or identification procedures were significantly biased, then the accuracy of the eyewitness’s identification is highly questionable unless the eyewitness conditions were exceptionally good (e.g., the eyewitness victim was kidnapped and had prolonged, repeated exposure to his or her abductor) or there is reliable, valid corroborating evidence establishing the accuracy of the eyewitness testimony. As Koehnken, Malpass, and Wolfgater stated: Valid implementation of eyewitness identification using lineups and photo spreads demands especially careful preparation. Once a mistake it made, it cannot be corrected. An identification of a suspect under suggestive conditions early in an investigation cannot simply be rectified by later conducting a fair line-up. Various psychological mechanisms result in the witness retaining the effects of errors made in 174 See Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 855 (“Several studies have identified post-event factors that significantly increase the confidence, but not the accuracy, of eyewitness testimony. These factors include post-event questioning, confirming feedback, and repeating questions of witnesses. Thus, by the time of trial, eyewitness confidence has little probative value in assessing eyewitness accuracy because of the many factors that affect eyewitness confidence but not accuracy.” (footnotes omitted)). 175 Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 620. 176 See infra Part VI (discussing guidelines for evaluating the fairness of eyewitness interviews). 177 See infra Part VII (discussing guidelines for evaluating the fairness of identification procedures). 178 See infra Part VIII (providing a list of the common eyewitness factors during a crime that affect eyewitness accuracy). 472 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 previous recognition tests. There are no procedures that can reliably rule out the possibility that earlier mistakes will be maintained at a later identification.179 In short, once law enforcement has contaminated an eyewitness’s memory of the perpetrator of the crime by conducting a biased eyewitness interview or identification procedure, the error cannot be corrected by subsequently conducting fair procedures.180 (See Table 1, Step 2.B.) Therefore, not only should an identification of a suspect that is a product of biased interview or identification be presumed to be inaccurate, but any subsequent identification by the eyewitness whose memory has been contaminated should also be presumed to be inaccurate even if it results in a fair identification procedure later. In contrast, if law enforcement conducted fair and unbiased eyewitness interviews and identification procedures, then the eyewitness identification and testimony is more likely to be accurate even if the eyewitness conditions were somewhat less than ideal. Accordingly, when assessing the accuracy of eyewitness testimony, judges and attorneys should always first analyze the eyewitness interviews and identification procedures. (See Table 1, Steps 1.–2.) Of course, no method can definitively determine if an eyewitness has made an accurate identification. This method, however, provides a comprehensive analytical framework for identifying and organizing the myriad of disparate factors that affect the accuracy of eyewitness testimony. It also alerts judges and attorneys to the many different types of eyewitness factors that affect identification accuracy. Perhaps most importantly, it also provides judges and attorneys with a method for integrating their knowledge of eyewitness factors into their decisions about the accuracy of eyewitness testimony. Accordingly, the use of this method substantially increases the probability that attorneys and judges will correctly assess eyewitness accuracy. There are other advantages to using this method. It emphasizes the importance of the State conducting fair and unbiased interviews and identification procedures. The method’s emphasis on fair and unbiased procedures is justified not only because it is logical (if the methodology of an investigation is invalid, then its results are likely to be invalid) and supported by empirical evidence, but also because the fairness of the eyewitness interviews and identification procedures are generally within 179 Koehnken et al., supra note 130, at 208; see also Susan R. Klein, Identifying and (Re)Formulating Prophylactic Rules, Safe Harbors, and Incidental Rights in Constitutional Criminal Procedure, 99 MICH. L. REV. 1030, 1065 (2001); Wells & Quinlivan, supra note 58, at 15 (setting forth a different hypothesis on how contamination affects an eyewitness’s memory); Michael S. Wogalter et al., A National Survey of US Police on Preparation and Conduct of Identification Lineups, 10 PSYCHOL. CRIME & L. 69, 78 (2004). 180 Wogalter et al., supra note 179, at 78. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 473 the State’s control and can easily be documented by videotaping them.181 On the other hand, the State cannot control the eyewitness factors that affected the eyewitness’s ability during a crime to make an accurate identification.182 Moreover, there is generally no objective record of the crime or of the eyewitness factors that affected the accuracy of the eyewitness testimony. This method also provides the State with a strong incentive to conduct fair interviews and identification procedures because they can significantly strengthen the State’s case at trial. Furthermore, the State can achieve the goal of conducting fair and unbiased eyewitness interviews and identification procedures without incurring either an unreasonable financial or administrative burden.183 This emphasis in the method is further warranted because the best way to prevent and reduce eyewitness error is 181 Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 582; Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 864–65. In effect, the method for analyzing the accuracy of eyewitness testimony delineated in this Article distinguishes between system variables and estimator variables. System variables are factors “over which the justice system has control, whereas . . . estimator variables are beyond the control of the justice system.” Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 582. “The number of foils [i.e., known innocent members] in a line-up, the selection of line-up members, and questioning techniques are examples of system variables.” Douglas J. Narby et al., The Effects of Witness, Target, and Situational Factors on Eyewitness Identifications, in PSYCHOLOGICAL ISSUES IN EYEWITNESS IDENTIFICATION 23–24 (Siegfried Ludwig Sporer et al. eds., 1996). “Some examples of estimator variables are the level of stress experienced by the witness during the crime, and the degree to which the witness was distracted from attending to a perpetrator’s characteristics.” Id. at 23. The estimation of how much these variables influence the accuracy of identifications is subject to biases and error. Id. at 24. Thus, in the method for analyzing eyewitness accuracy discussed in this Article, the factors pertaining to whether law enforcement during the eyewitness interview obtained the maximum amount of information from the eyewitness, contaminated the eyewitness’s memory of the crime, or artificially increased eyewitness confidence, and whether the identification procedures were fair and unbiased are all system variables because they generally are within the control of the criminal justice system. See Table 1, Steps 1–2. In contrast, the factors during the crime that likely increased or decreased eyewitness accuracy are all estimator variables. See Tbl. 1, Step 3. 182 See Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 582 (discussing the difference between system variables and estimator variables: system variables are eyewitness factors that the criminal justice system can generally control while estimator variables are eyewitness factors that it cannot control). 183 See Michael R. Headley, Note, Long on Substance, Short on Process: An Appeal for Process Long Overdue in Eyewitness Lineup Procedures, 53 HASTINGS L.J. 681, 700 (2002); Amy Klobuchar et al., Improving Eyewitness Identifications: Hennepin County’s Blind Sequential Lineup Pilot Project, 4 CARDOZO PUB. L. POL’Y & ETHICS 381, 409 (2006) (discussing how a pilot project that implemented double-blind, sequential lineup procedures was “extremely efficient” and, as Minnetonka Police Chief Joy Rikala noted: “There [are] no cost implications of this. It’s negligible.”). Fisher and Schreiber state that Britain has adapted national standards for interviewing eyewitnesses based on the cognitive interview. Fisher & Schreiber, supra note 143, at 56. They also point out: [T]raining practices differ widely across countries. The most advanced and rigorous training is found in Britain, where police often collaborate with academic researchers to develop and evaluate training programs . . . as have Australia, New Zealand, and Israel. We find it interesting that the United States and Canada, which have produced many of the leading theoretical advances in the psychology of memory, have not kept pace with their western counterparts by incorporating this knowledge into police training programs. Id. at 57. The widespread use of the cognitive interview in several different countries supports the proposition that its implementation is both practical and cost efficient. 474 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 for the State to conduct fair and unbiased interviews and identification procedures.184 Finally, though the method provides scientific guidelines for assessing eyewitness accuracy, as is discussed in Part IX, we also recognize that there are some limited circumstances where policy considerations may require the admission of an eyewitness identification at trial even though the method indicates that the identification should be presumed to be inaccurate.185 In the next three sections, scientific guidelines for assessing the fairness of eyewitness interviews and identification procedures and a list of eyewitness factors that commonly affect eyewitness accuracy in criminal trials are discussed. The Appendix contains a form that will aid judges and attorneys in applying this method to eyewitness testimony. VI. EVALUATING THE EYEWITNESS INTERVIEWS (THE “COGNITIVE INTERVIEW”): TABLE 1, STEP 1 Law enforcement officers are generally not trained to interview eyewitnesses, but rather only to interrogate suspects.186 Accordingly, when law enforcement officers conduct interviews of eyewitnesses they often make three types of errors: (1) they fail to obtain much of the information that an eyewitness knows about a crime; (2) they contaminate an eyewitness’s memory of the crime; and (3) they create an unwarranted increase in an eyewitness’s confidence in the accuracy of his or her testimony and identification.187 In the 1980s, Ronald Fisher and Edward Geiselman began developing an interviewing technique which reduces the errors that law enforcement officers generally make when interviewing eyewitnesses.188 Scientific studies of their cognitive interview in the laboratory and in field studies 184 Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 864–65. We are referring to situations where the police are acting in good faith, but necessity requires them to use a suggestive identification procedure. One example is using a showup with an eyewitness when the police believe that they have apprehended the perpetrator shortly after the crime has occurred. See infra note 347. In such instances, where possible the police should follow proper procedures in conducting the showup. See NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, U.S. DEP’T OF JUSTICE, EYEWITNESS EVIDENCE: A TRAINER’S MANUAL FOR LAW ENFORCEMENT 30–31 (2003), available at http://www.ncjrs.gov/nij/ eyewitness/188678.pdf [hereinafter NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE]. 186 Fisher, supra note 104, at 733; Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 583. 187 Fisher, supra note 104, at 755; Judges, supra note 119, at 249, 250, 252. For example, in Florida: The “standard police interview” was characterized by constant interruptions, excessive use of a predetermined list of questions with an expectation that witnesses could provide answers, and questions that were timed inappropriately . . . if the witness was describing one of the perpetrators, the officer, might switch the line of questioning to the actions of another perpetrator. Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 55 (citations omitted). 188 Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 582–83. 185 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 475 show that it increases the amount of accurate information obtained from eyewitnesses by thirty-five to seventy-five percent over standard police interviews.189 It also decreases the probability of contaminating the eyewitness’s memory of the crime or artificially inflating their confidence.190 The cognitive interview forms the basis for the interviewing techniques that the National Institute of Justice recommended in its Training Manual for Law Enforcement.191 The following scientific guidelines derived from the above mentioned sources can be used by judges and attorneys to assess whether law enforcement obtained the maximum amount of information from the eyewitness; whether they contaminated the eyewitness’s memory of the crime; and whether they increased the eyewitness’s confidence in the accuracy of his or her identification. The factors for maximizing the amount of information obtained from the eyewitness are divided into three categories: pre-interview preparation, conducting the interview, and concluding the interview. Brief explanations follow for each guideline and the guidelines are in bold. A. Factors Relevant to Maximizing the Information Obtained from the Eyewitness 1. Pre-Interview Preparation a. When circumstances permit, the interview should be held as soon as possible after the crime.192 Scientific studies show that eyewitnesses begin to forget the details of the crime very quickly, so the interview should be conducted as soon as the eyewitness is physically and emotionally capable of being interviewed and the exigencies of investigating the crime permit.193 b. The interviewer should review all information about the crime prior to the interview. This guideline allows an interviewer to conduct a more thorough and complete interview.194 189 Id. at 584. Fisher, supra note 104, at 752. 191 See Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 590; NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 10–12. 192 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 13; Wise & Safer, supra note 11, at 11. 193 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 13; see also Fisher & Schreiber, supra note 143, at 69 (discussing another reason for conducting the eyewitness interview as soon as possible after the crime: “The more likely prophylactic approach to minimizing the influence of suggestive questioning is to conduct an effective witness interview shortly after the critical event, before the witness has been exposed to the influence of the misleading suggestions.”). 194 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 13. 190 476 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 c. The interview should be conducted in a comfortable environment, and distractions and interruptions should be minimized. An eyewitness who is comfortable and relaxed and is not distracted or interrupted is likely to recall more information about the crime.195 d. The resources needed to conduct the interview (e.g., pens, notepad, video recorder) should be obtained prior to the interview so it does not have to be interrupted to get these items. Interruptions interfere with the eyewitness’s ability to remember the crime.196 e. The eyewitness interview should be videotaped. Videotaping ensures that judges, attorneys, and jurors can evaluate the interview and that there is an accurate and complete record of the eyewitness testimony prior to his or her exposure to post-event information. It also allows the interviewer to focus on what the eyewitness is saying rather than on note taking.197 Finally, it provides the eyewitness with an effective way of refreshing his or recollection before testifying at trial. 2. Conducting the Interview When conducting the interview, the interviewer should: 195 Id. Law enforcement rarely meets this guideline. Fisher, supra note 104, at 756. For example, patrol officers, who usually conduct the initial interview of eyewitnesses, do so under very poor conditions, such as “general confusion and background noise, high witness arousal, severe time pressure, etc. They are pressed by their supervisors to file their reports quickly, even if at the cost of diminished information.” Id. 196 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 13. 197 Id. at 21; see also Fisher, supra note 104, at 745 (stating that videotaping a witness’s response minimizes “information-overload”). Unfortunately, law enforcement does not generally record eyewitness interviews. See Fisher, supra note 104, at 755 (“The value of tape recording interviews is obvious in terms of exposing police errors. One ought to be able to uncover, at lease in theory, whether an item of knowledge was ‘constructed’ by the interview process or whether it was based on the witness’s earlier perception of the original event.”). Sometimes, however, the characteristics of the ideal eyewitness interview conflict with one another, or may need to yield to more compelling considerations. Take the frequent circumstance where a police officer interviews an eyewitness or victim at the crime scene only minutes after the crime. Time is of the essence: the quicker the officer can obtain a description of the perpetrator, the quicker the police can begin searching for the perpetrator, hopefully before he or she has gotten too far from the crime scene. At-the-scene interviewing minimizes the time between the crime and the interview, but may make it impractical for the officer to learn anything about the crime prior to the interview, or to transport the eyewitness to a comfortable environment, or to videotape the interview. The situation may be even more exigent if the interview must be conducted while the eyewitness is receiving medical treatment, or the eyewitness is about to be taken to the hospital. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 477 a. Establish and maintain rapport with the eyewitness and minimize his or her anxiety. Relaxed eyewitnesses provide more information and eyewitnesses are often traumatized by the crimes they witnessed.198 b. Inquire about the eyewitness’s condition. This question helps build rapport and alerts the interviewer to any condition that might impair the eyewitness’s ability to remember the crime (e.g., intoxication, shock, drugs).199 c. Instruct the eyewitness to: (1) volunteer information;200 (2) report all details they remember about the crime even if the information seems trivial and unimportant;201 and (3) inform the eyewitness about the type and degree of detail of information the interviewer needs.202 These rules encourage the eyewitness to be active during the interview. This is vital because it is the eyewitness, not the interviewer, who has information about the crime, and unprompted information tends to be more accurate than These information given in response to questions.203 instructions also increase the likelihood that the eyewitness will not withhold any information about the crime and understands the kinds of information and the degree of detail that the interviewer needs.204 d. Ask the eyewitness to mentally recreate the crime. This can be done by asking the eyewitness to think about his 198 See NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 14 (“The development of rapport between the witness and interviewer will make the witness more comfortable during the interview process. Comfortable witnesses will generally provide more information.”); Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 56. Police officers often have difficulty establishing rapport with eyewitnesses. See Fisher, supra note 104, at 755. Fisher notes that “I have found in the various interviewing workshops I have conducted that women were generally more effective interviewers than men.” Id. at 756. 199 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 11. 200 Id. at 16. 201 Id. at 20; Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 57. 202 Fisher, supra note 104, at 747; Fisher & Schreiber, supra note 143, at 62. 203 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 16, 19. Fisher and Schreiber propose: Interviewers can induce witnesses to take more active roles and to volunteer information by (a) explicitly requesting them to do so, (b) asking open-ended questions, (c) not interrupting witnesses during their narrative responses, and (d) constructing the social dynamic so that witnesses perceive themselves to be the experts and therefore the dominant person in the conversation. This last point is especially important when children are being interviewed. Fisher & Schreiber, supra note 143, at 61. 204 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 19. 478 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 205 or her thoughts and feelings during the crime. By mentally recreating the crime, the eyewitness will be able to recall more information about the crime.206 e. Use primarily open-ended questions during the interview (e.g., What did the perpetrator look like?).207 Open-ended questions give the eyewitness control of the interview.208 They also furnish the eyewitness with his or her best chance to fully disclose the details of a crime.209 In addition, responses to opened-ended questions tend to be more accurate than responses to other types of questions and promote more attentive listening by the interviewer.210 f. Ask close-ended questions only when they are needed to augment open-ended questions (e.g., What color was the perpetrator’s hair?). Open-ended questions are preferable because close-ended questions limit the amount and scope of the information obtained from the eyewitness.211 Nonetheless, close-ended questions are appropriate when the eyewitness has not disclosed important information in his or her responses to open-ended questions.212 205 Id. at 20. Wells suggests that an officer can have an eyewitness mentally recreate the crime by: “asking them to form an image or impression of the environmental aspects of the original scene (e.g., the location of objects in a room); to comment on any emotional reactions and feelings (e.g., surprise, anger) at the time; and to describe any sounds, smells, and physical conditions (e.g., hot, humid, smoky) that were present.” Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 57. 206 Fisher & Schreiber, supra note 143, at 59; NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 20. 207 See NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 11 (“An open-ended question allows for an unlimited response from the witness in his/her own words (e.g., ‘What can you tell me about the perpetrator?’ or ‘Tell me in your own words what happened’).”). 208 Id.; Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 843. 209 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 11. 210 Id. 211 Id. The National Institute of Justice’s Training Manual indicated that [a]lthough it is preferable to use open-ended questioning, the investigator should follow with more directed questions if the witness is unresponsive to open-ended questions or provides imprecise responses. If, for example, when answering an open-ended question, the witness states that the perpetrator was dressed in ‘shabby’ clothing, the investigator should ask the witness to elaborate on the type of clothing (e.g., “What do you mean by ‘shabby’?”). Id.; Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 57. 212 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 11. The National Institute of Justice’s Training Manual, however, suggests: For each new topic of information being sought, the investigator should begin with open-ended questions and augment them with closed-ended questions if necessary. For example, if, after having elicited all information from the witness about the perpetrator, the next topic of information is the getaway car, the investigator should begin this line of inquiry with open-ended questions about the car. Id. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY g. Avoid interrupting the eyewitness. Interruptions disrupt memory and discourage the eyewitness from volunteering information.213 h. Allow for pauses when an eyewitness stops talking and before asking the next question. This ensures that the eyewitness has completed his or her response.214 i. Tailor questions to the eyewitness’s narrative rather than asking a standard set of questions. Each eyewitness’s mental representation of a crime is unique; therefore, the interviewer’s questions should correspond to the eyewitness’s memory of the crime.215 For example, if the eyewitness is describing the perpetrator’s car, the interviewer should not be asking questions about the perpetrator’s appearance.216 j. Encourage nonverbal communications from the eyewitness such as drawings and gestures, especially from children eyewitnesses or eyewitnesses who are not fluent in English.217 Some information is difficult to express verbally and some aspects of events are expressed better nonverbally. Moreover, some eyewitnesses have limited verbal skills. k. Ask the eyewitness, “Is there anything else I should have asked you?” This question helps insure that the eyewitness has disclosed all the information he or she knows about the crime.218 3. Concluding the Interview a. The eyewitness should be encouraged to contact the 213 Id. at 16. Id. at 17. 215 Id.; Fisher & Schreiber, supra note 143, at 59. 216 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 17. 217 Id. at 20. Fisher & Schreiber stated: Ideally the response format should be compatible with the witness’s mental representation of the event, thereby minimizing the need to transform the mental representation into an overt response. For example, if an event is inherently spatial (e.g., locations of objects within a room), then witnesses should respond spatially, for example, by drawing a sketch of the room or by placing model objects within a (model) room. Fisher & Schreiber, supra note 143, at 62 (internal citations omitted). 218 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 19. 214 479 480 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 interviewer if he or she remembers additional facts about the crime. Eyewitnesses frequently recall additional facts about the crime after the interview is over.219 b. The interviewer should review written documentation with the eyewitness and ask the eyewitness if there is anything he or she wishes to change, add, or emphasize. Doing this helps insure that the information has been accurately recorded and allows the eyewitness to recall more information about the crime.220 c. Thank the eyewitness for his or her time and cooperation. Expressing gratitude to the eyewitness strengths rapport with the eyewitness and encourages future cooperation.221 B. “Contamination” of the Eyewitness’s Memory To prevent contaminating the eyewitness’s memory and to assess whether the eyewitness’s memory has been contaminated, the interviewer should (See Table 1, Step 1.B.2.): 1. Separate the eyewitnesses and tell them not to discuss the details of the crime with other eyewitnesses222 and to avoid media accounts of the crime.223 If an eyewitness hears another eyewitness’s or the media’s account of the crime, this could alter the first eyewitness’s memory of the crime and create a false consensus among the eyewitnesses about details of the crime.224 2. Determine if an eyewitness has spoken to another eyewitness or anyone else about the crime or been exposed to media accounts of the crime. Exposure to these sources could mean that the eyewitness’s memory of the crime has been altered by post-event 219 Id. at 20; Fisher & Schreiber, supra note 143, at 63. NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 21. Fisher and Schreiber suggest that “[t]he interviewer should also point out in a nonchallenging way any ambiguities or contradictory statements within the witness’s statement and ask the witness to clarify these matters, even if that means indicating that the witness is not certain about the matter.” Fisher & Schreiber, supra note 143, at 63. 221 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 21. 222 Id. at 12. 223 Id.; Fisher & Schreiber, supra note 143, at 60. 224 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 12. 220 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 481 225 information. 3. Ascertain the nature of the eyewitness’s prior law enforcement contact related to the crime being investigated. This includes any prior interviews by law enforcement or participation in any type of identification procedure. This information puts the eyewitness’s information into context and allows the interviewer to determine if post-event information or a biased identification procedure contaminated the eyewitness’s memory of the crime.226 4. Avoid volunteering any perpetrator or the crime. information about the Doing so could alter the eyewitness’s memory about the crime.227 5. Tell the eyewitness not to guess and to indicate if he or she feels any uncertainty about an answer. Guessing can alter the eyewitness’s memory.228 6. Refrain from (a) using suggestive or leading questions (e.g., “Was the car red?”);229 (b) disclosing information to the eyewitness about the crime the interviewer learned from other sources; or (c) using multiple choice questions. All these responses supply post-event information to an eyewitness, which can alter an eyewitness’s memory of the crime. Moreover, post-event information not only affects an 225 Id. If two or more eyewitnesses are victimized by or observe a crime, it is understandable that they may discuss what happened while waiting for the police to arrive. Clearly no blame should be placed on the police for what the eyewitnesses did before the police had an opportunity to intervene; nor can any blame be assigned to the eyewitnesses, who do not know that discussing the matter with each other may contaminate their memories of what happened. Thus, the occurrence of such a discussion prior to the first police interview cannot by itself mandate suppression of eyewitness testimony; but it is a factor for the judge to consider, in making an overall assessment of the accuracy and reliability of their testimony. Moreover, if the eyewitnesses make an in-court identification at trial, defense counsel should be permitted to elicit that the eyewitnesses had discussed the facts among themselves, and to elicit expert testimony about the resultant risk of contamination and inaccuracy. 226 Id. at 14; see also Brigham et al., supra note 90, at 14 (discussing how “witnesses are highly susceptible to suggestions regarding their memory for the previously viewed event”); Shaw & McClure, supra note 118, at 647 (discussing how repeated questioning of an eyewitness can increase the risk of contaminating the eyewitness’s memory); Gary L. Wells & Amy L. Bradfield, Distortions in Eyewitnesses’ Recollections: Can the Postidentification-Feedback Effect Be Moderated?, 10 PSYCHOL. SCI. 138, 138 (1999). 227 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 23; Fisher & Schreiber, supra note 143, at 60. 228 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 20; Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 57. 229 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 11. 482 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 eyewitness’s memory of the crime, but it can also impair an eyewitness’s ability to recognize the perpetrator of the crime.230 C. Eyewitness Confidence To prevent increasing the confidence of the eyewitness and to determine if it has been artificially increased, the interviewer should (See Table 1, Step 1.C.): 1. Use the cognitive interview. It minimizes the probability that the interviewer will increase the eyewitness’s confidence.231 2. Avoid disclosing to the eyewitness: (a) that another eyewitness has identified the same suspect; (b) what another eyewitness said about the crime or the perpetrator; or (c) that there is other evidence that confirms the eyewitness’s testimony or identification. All these factors confidence.232 artificially increase eyewitness 3. Determine if the eyewitness had contact with other eyewitnesses, the media, or other law enforcement officers and the nature of that contact to assess whether it has increased the eyewitness’s confidence (e.g., the eyewitness has been told that another eyewitness also identified the suspect).233 4. Avoid giving the eyewitness any type of confirming feedback (e.g., “Good, you have identified the suspect”) or exposing the eyewitness to unnecessary, repeated questioning. 230 Id. at 23; see also Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 846 (“Law officers can convey post-event information to eyewitnesses in a variety of ways, from overtly volunteering information to the eyewitness, to asking leading questions, to encouraging guessing by the eyewitness, to offering confirming feedback.” (footnotes omitted)). 231 For a discussion of the cognitive interview, see supra Part VI. See also RONALD P. FISHER & R. EDWARD GEISELMAN, MEMORY-ENHANCING TECHNIQUES FOR INVESTIGATIVE INTERVIEWING, THE COGNITIVE INTERVIEW 38–39 (1992); Pär Anders Granhag et al., The Cognitive Interview and Its Effect on Witnesses’ Confidence, 10 PSYCHOL., CRIME & L. 37, 50 (2004). 232 Helen M. Paterson & Richard I. Kemp, Comparing Methods of Encountering Post-Event Information: The Power of Co-Witness Suggestion, 20 APPLIED COGNITIVE PSYCHOL. 1083, 1098 (2006); Wells & Bradfield, supra note 118, at 362. 233 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 12 (“Media information may contaminate the witness’s memory. Media requests for a story or offers of compensation may encourage a witness to fabricate information. . . . Witnesses should not hear others’ accounts because they may be influenced by that information.”). 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 483 234 These factors significantly increase eyewitness confidence. 5. Take a statement of the eyewitness’s confidence in the accuracy of his or her identification of the suspect as the perpetrator of the crime immediately after the identification procedure and prior to the eyewitness receiving any feedback about his or her identification.235 Eyewitness confidence is highly malleable; therefore, a statement of the eyewitness confidence should be taken immediately after the identification.236 This guideline recognizes that at some point the eyewitness is likely to receive positive or confirming feedback.237 Indeed, law enforcement officials may have legitimate reasons for These providing such feedback to the eyewitness.238 234 Bradfield et al., supra note 12, at 113; Shaw & McClure, supra note 118, at 630; Andrew E. Taslitz, Convicting the Guilty, The ABA Takes a Stand, 19 CRIM. JUST. 18, 23 (2005); Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 626; Wells & Bradfield, supra note 118, at 374. 235 Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 635. The authors support this suggestion, stating: This recommendation is based on the observation that confidence statements from eyewitnesses can be affected dramatically by events occurring after the identification (postidentification events) that have nothing to do with the witness’s memory. As noted earlier, the confidence that an eyewitness expresses in his or her identification during testimony is the most powerful single determinant of whether or not observers will believe the eyewitness made an accurate identification. By recording the eyewitness’s confidence at the time of the identification, postidentification factors (which have little to do with the witness’s memory) will not yet have influenced the confidence judgment. If the confidence that an eyewitness expresses at trial is noticeably higher than it was at the time of the identification, then fact finders should consider the possibility that this inflation of confidence came from sources other than the goodness of the eyewitness’s memory. Id.; see also Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 864. 236 Leippe & Eisenstadt, supra note 117, at 417; Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 586; see also supra Part III.F. (discussing eyewitnesses’ tendency to be overconfident in the accuracy of their identifications and the malleability of eyewitness confidence); WEITEN, supra note 14, at 230–31. 237 The eyewitness learning that the person he or she identified was subsequently indicted is likely to boost the eyewitness’s confidence that he or she picked out the “right” person. If the eyewitness learns that the defendant is also charged with committing other, similar crimes (a fact that is accessible to the public at large), this, too, will boost his or her confidence. 238 The rights and concerns of the eyewitness must also be taken into account. Eyewitnesses (and particularly victims) often complain that they are ignored or treated without courtesy or respect by investigators, attorneys, and the court. See John Hagan, Victims Before the Law: A Study of Victim Involvement in the Criminal Justice Process, 73 J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 317, 324–28 (1982); Deborah P. Kelly, Delivering Legal Services to Victims: An Evaluation and Prescription, 9 JUST. SYS. J. 62, 76 (1984) (reporting that the suggested reform witnesses requested most often was that police should provide them with more information about the investigation); Deborah P. Kelly, Victims’ Perceptions of Criminal Justice, 11 PEPP. L. REV. 15, 19 (1984); Dean G. Kilpatrick & Randy K. Otto, Constitutionally Guaranteed Participation in Criminal Proceedings for Victims: Potential Effects on Psychological Functioning, 34 WAYNE L. REV. 7, 22 (1987) (reporting witness dissatisfaction with how they are treated by the criminal justice system); Peggy M. Tobolowsky, Victim Participation in the Criminal Justice Process: Fifteen Years After the President’s Task Force on Victims of Crime, 25 NEW ENG. J. ON CRIM. & CIV. CONFINEMENT 21, 103 (1999). Simple compassion for an eyewitness’s 484 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 concerns underscore the importance of asking the eyewitness to estimate his or her degree of certainty immediately after the eyewitness’s identification of the defendant (and videorecording that statement), as a check against a subsequent increase in the eyewitness’s confidence from outside sources. If an eyewitness’s confidence in the accuracy of the identification increases by the time of trial, the judge should permit the defense attorney to use the eyewitness’s earlier statement of confidence to impeach the eyewitness’s current statement of confidence.239 Moreover, the trial judge should consider permitting expert testimony that explains how an eyewitness’s confidence can increase over time, and why this does not indicate that the identification is correct.240 TABLE 2: SCIENTIFIC GUIDELINES FOR FAIR AND IMPARTIAL IDENTIFICATION PROCEDURES 1. Whenever possible, law enforcement should use photo arrays and lineups only when there is probable cause to believe the suspect committed the crime. 2. Before conducting an identification procedure, it should be determined whether the eyewitness has previously seen the suspect. 3. Only one suspect should be included in every identification procedure. 4. The number of lineup participants should be increased. 5. The suspect should not stand out from the foils. 6. Law enforcement should use sequential identification procedures. 7. The lineup administrator should not know the identity of the suspect. 8. Eyewitnesses should be given cautionary instructions. feelings might dictate that he or she be provided at least some additional information about the case; law enforcement officials may have a legitimate concern that the failure to do so might so offend the victim or eyewitness that he or she will refuse to subject him or herself to the ordeal of reliving the crime in the courtroom and, in particular, cross-examination that may prove upsetting or embarrassing. 239 Where a prior statement by an eyewitness is inconsistent with that eyewitness’s testimony at trial, the prior statement should be admitted to impeach the testimony. See, e.g., FED. R. EVID. 613(b); CLIFFORD S. FISHMAN, 4 JONES ON EVIDENCE § 26:2 (7th ed. 2000). A complete, 180-degree contradiction is not required; it suffices that the prior statement leaves a significantly different impression than the testimony being impeached. Id. § 26:15. To preclude a defendant from bringing out such inconsistencies can constitute a violation of the right, guaranteed by the Sixth Amendment to confront and cross-examine witnesses. See Pennsylvania v. Ritchie, 480 U.S. 39, 51 (1987). 240 See supra Part II.D. (discussing expert testimony concerning eyewitness identification). 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 485 9. All identification procedures should be videotaped. 10. An eyewitness should make a clear statement of his or her confidence at the time of the identification and prior to receiving any feedback. 11. Once a mistake is made in an identification procedure, it cannot be corrected. VII. GUIDELINES FOR EVALUATING THE FAIRNESS OF IDENTIFICATION PROCEDURES The following eleven guidelines, derived from scientific studies of identification procedures, can be used to objectively evaluate whether a photo array or lineup was conducted in a fair and unbiased manner.241 For detailed guidelines on the proper use of mug books, composite images, and showups, consult the National Institute of Justice’s Training Manual.242 The guidelines for conducting fair and unbiased photo arrays and lineups are in bold and a brief rationale for each guideline is included. 1. Whenever possible, law enforcement should use a lineup or photo array only when there is probable cause to believe the suspect committed the crime.243 Most erroneous eyewitness identifications result from identification procedures that do not include the perpetrator of the crime.244 If law enforcement conducts photo arrays and lineups only when probable cause exists that the suspect committed the crime, the number of perpetrator-absent lineups and photo arrays, and therefore the number of erroneous identifications of an innocent suspect, will be significantly reduced.245 “Probable cause” is the quantum of suspicion that is required before the police may lawfully arrest someone and 241 Some of these procedures are already practiced by law enforcement officials; we include them here not to suggest otherwise, but because they belong in any description of best practices that should be followed. 242 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 25–27, 30–32. 243 Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 856. 244 See Wells & Olson, supra note 13, at 286 (“Research repeatedly shows that culprit-absent lineups present great problems for eyewitnesses.”). 245 See Steven Penrod, Eyewitness Identification Evidence: How Well Are Witnesses and Police Performing?, 18 CRIM. JUST. 36, 46 (2003); Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 856 (“[L]aw enforcement agencies should distinguish between those eyewitnesses used to produce investigatory leads and those used to establish a defendant’s guilt. An eyewitness used to generate leads in a case should not also be used to establish a defendant’s guilt at trial.”); see also Wells & Olson, supra note 13, at 286 (protesting that “investigators will place a suspect in a lineup for the slightest of reasons (e.g., a mere hunch)”). 486 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 246 charge him or her with a specific crime. Thus, if the suspect has already been lawfully arrested for the crime in question, the probable cause standard suggested here imposes no burdens or restrictions on law enforcement. When police, however, believe that a suspect committed the crime, but lack sufficient evidence to establish probable cause, including such a suspect in a photo array247 or lineup248 can be a highly 246 See Maryland v. Pringle, 540 U.S. 366, 369–70 (2003). Although the term is codified in the Fourth Amendment (“[A]nd no Warrants shall issue, but upon probable cause . . . .”) and has been the subject of countless court decisions since the ratification of the Amendment, no clear definition of it exists. The Supreme Court has observed that “[t]he probable-cause standard is incapable of precise definition or quantification into percentages because it deals with probabilities and depends on the totality of the circumstances.” Id. at 371; see also Illinois v. Gates, 462 U.S. 213, 231 (1983); Brinegar v. United States, 338 U.S. 160, 175 (1949). Moreover, “‘the quanta . . . of proof’ appropriate in ordinary judicial proceedings are inapplicable to” determinations of probable cause. Gates, 462 U.S. at 235 (citation omitted). Thus, “[f]inely tuned standards such as proof beyond a reasonable doubt or by a preponderance of the evidence, useful in formal trials, have no place in the [probable-cause] decision.” Id. Rather, “[t]he substance of all the definitions of probable cause is a reasonable ground for belief of guilt.” Pringle, 540 U.S. at 371 (citation omitted). A search or seizure of a person “must be supported by probable cause particularized with respect to that person.” Id. (citing Ybarra v. Illinois, 444 U.S. 85, 91 (1979)). 247 Not only is a photo array much easier to arrange than a lineup, but law enforcement officials may also conduct photo arrays before or after arraignment without first obtaining judicial authorization, and without notice to the suspect or his attorney. See United States v. Ash, 413 U.S. 300, 318–21 (1973); supra notes 35–36 and accompanying text. 248 This is appropriate when: (1) A suspect could voluntarily participate in a lineup. (2) Where the suspect is already in custody on other charges, at least one court has held that he can be forced to participate in a lineup regarding additional crimes if the police have at least a “reasonable suspicion” that he is guilty of those crimes. United States v. Allen, 408 F.2d 1287, 1288–89 (D.C. Cir. 1969). “Reasonable suspicion” requires less evidence or information than probable cause, and permits only temporary detention and, sometimes a frisk, rather than a custodial arrest and full search. See Terry v. Ohio, 392 U.S. 1, 9–11 (1968). Reasonable suspicion exists, the Court has held, when “the detaining officers . . . have a particularized and objective basis for suspecting the particular person . . . of criminal activity.” United States v. Cortez, 449 U.S. 411, 417–18 (1981). For a detailed discussion of the difficulties in defining or distinguishing probable cause and reasonable suspicion, see WAYNE R. LAFAVE, 4 SEARCH AND SEIZURE 470–77, § 9.5(a) (4th ed. 2004). (3) At least one court permitted police to compel such a suspect to participate in other-crime lineups without first showing either probable cause or reasonable suspicion as to the other crimes. See State v. Wilks, 358 N.W.2d 273, 277–78 (Wis. 1984). (4) A prosecutor might persuasively argue by analogy to other Supreme Court decisions upholding grand jury subpoenas (for which no preliminary showing of reasonableness is needed) compelling a suspect to provide a handwriting exemplar or a voice exemplar. See United States v. Mara, 410 U.S. 19, 22 (1973); United States v. Dionisio, 410 U.S. 1, 13–14 (1973); see also Hayes v. Florida, 470 U.S. 811, 816–17 (1985) (suggesting that a court might have authority to order a suspect to submit to being fingerprinted where the police have shown “reasonable suspicion” that he is the culprit). Placing a suspect in a lineup without probable cause, however, probably does not occur very often. The police may not know where the suspect is, or may not want to alert him or her that he or she is a suspect. Moreover, conducting a lineup requires far more preparation than showing an eyewitness a series of photographs, and may be more intimidating to the eyewitness. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 487 useful step in acquiring sufficient evidence to establish probable cause. Thus a conflict often arises between legitimate investigative concerns, on the one hand, and the need to safeguard against an increased risk of erroneous identifications, on the other. A variety of solutions exist to this dilemma. Sometimes it is practical to postpone a photo array or lineup while the Where there are several police investigate further.249 eyewitnesses to a crime, police might show a photo array to one eyewitness; if he or she identifies the defendant as the perpetrator, the identification establishes probable cause, which justifies an arrest and, thereafter, a lineup at which other eyewitnesses will (hopefully) identify the defendant as well.250 Where a pre-probable cause lineup is necessary, the risk of an erroneous identification can be reduced if the police scrupulously follow the guidelines set forth in this Article: a sequential lineup, conducted by an officer who does not know the identity of the suspect, with at least twelve participants, preceded by appropriate cautionary instructions, and so on. Similarly, if police need an eyewitness to attempt a pre-probable cause photo identification, using a photo array has the same shortcomings as a lineup. It should be permissible, however, to ask the eyewitness to look at a large collection of photos or mug-shots, if they are presented in a fair and unbiased manner, and the eyewitness is warned that the perpetrator’s picture may not be among them.251 Doing so would reduce, though not eliminate, the risk that the eyewitness will select the suspect’s photo merely because, of the photos shown, his photo most closely resembles the perpetrator.252 If these procedures are followed, a court 249 If the suspect is already incarcerated on other charges, for example, there may be little concern that he or she will commit additional crimes before an arrest is made in the pending investigation. 250 The second eyewitness’s identification of the defendant would circumstantially corroborate the reliability of the first eyewitness’s identification at the pre-probable cause photo array, thereby giving assurance of its reliability—provided, of course, that both the photo array and the lineup were fair and unbiased. 251 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 29–35 (describing the procedures that should be used when the police show mug-shots to eyewitnesses). 252 At least one scholar urges that an eyewitness who police use to generate leads in a case should not be permitted to make an identification at trial. See Penrod, supra note 245. The reasons for this assertion are that once an eyewitness identifies someone as the perpetrator, it is very unlikely that the eyewitness will change his or her mind because of the commitment effect and the reconstructive nature of memory. Accordingly, if the police place a suspect in a lineup based only on a hunch, there is a much greater chance that they are conducting a culprit-absent lineup, and if the eyewitness chooses the 488 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 should have fewer qualms about allowing that eyewitness to make an in-court identification at trial. 2. Before conducting an identification procedure, it should be determined whether the eyewitness has previously seen the suspect before or after the crime.253 Studies strongly indicate that if an eyewitness has previously seen the suspect, such as in a mug-shot, this substantially increases the probability that the eyewitness will select the suspect in a subsequent identification procedure even if the suspect is innocent.254 3. Only one suspect should be included in every identification procedure.255 Studies show that including more than one suspect in an identification procedure increases the probability that an erroneous eyewitness identification will occur.256 This increased error rate occurs because multiple suspects decrease the number of fillers257 (i.e., known innocent participants) and increase the frequency with which an eyewitness will select someone whom the police think is suspect, it is unlikely the eyewitness will later change his or her mind. See NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 25–30 (stating procedures that should be followed for mug books). 253 Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 857. 254 See Evan Brown et al., Memory for Faces and the Circumstances of Encounter, 62 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 311, 311–18 (1977) (discussing the results of three experiments showing that people are much better at recognizing a face than remembering where they saw the face, and that this tendency makes it more likely for eyewitnesses to identify an innocent suspect as the perpetrator if the eyewitness has previously seen the innocent suspect’s mug-shot); Koehnken et al., supra note 130, at 217 (“Research shows that identification errors may increase from previous exposure to a photograph of the suspect. . . . Once a witness comes to a decision and expresses it, he or she may feel committed and may be less willing to change the decision later.”). 255 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 35 (“In multiple-suspect lineups, the probability of a possible mistaken identification rises as the number of suspects in a lineup increases.”). Wise et al. also advocate for this procedure, stating: Many lineups in the United States contain more than one suspect, even when there is only one perpetrator who committed the crime. Research has shown that the use of multiple suspects in identification procedures significantly increases the risk of erroneous identifications. This increased risk occurs because multiple suspects decrease the proportion of fillers in the lineup and increase the number of correct responses. Putting more than one suspect in a lineup significantly increases the probability that an eyewitness will choose an innocent suspect. Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 857–58 (footnotes omitted). 256 Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 593; see also R. C. L. Lindsay & Gary L. Wells, Improving Eyewitness Identifications from Lineups: Simultaneous Versus Sequential Lineup Presentation, 70 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 556, 557 (1985). 257 A lineup or photo array contains a suspect and several known innocent individuals. Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 584. The innocent members of an identification procedure are referred to either as distractors, foils, or fillers. Id. at 584–85. The term “fillers” is used in this Article because it is the term that is most commonly used by law enforcement. Id. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 489 258 guilty. 4. The number of lineup participants should be increased in identification procedures.259 In the United States, the typical photo array or lineup contains five or six members.260 Even if a five or six person identification procedure is conducted in a manner that is completely fair and unbiased, studies show that the chances of an erroneous eyewitness identification is still substantial.261 Studies also indicate that increasing lineup size from six to twelve members in the United States could reduce false identifications by fifty percent without a significant drop in accurate identifications.262 5. The suspect in an identification procedure should not 258 Id. In other words, in the typical six-person lineup, if you have two suspects, you have decreased the number of foils from five to four and have increased the number of “correct” choices (i.e., the two suspects) from one to two, thereby substantially increasing the risk of an erroneous identification. 259 Taslitz argues: Lineups and photo spreads should also use a sufficient number of foils to reasonably reduce the risk of an eyewitness selecting a suspect by guessing rather than by recognition. The reason for this is straightforward. If there are six lineup participants, none of whom is guilty, there is a one-in-six chance that a guessing eyewitness will wrongly select the suspect. If there is a 10-person lineup, the risk of a mistake falls to one in ten. There is no indisputable basis for selecting one number over another. What is clear is that bigger is better. Researchers in the area have roundly condemned the six-person lineup common in the United States, recommending a 10-person size. The United Kingdom’s standard is a nine-person lineup, a size that has not proven impracticable for the police to achieve. The same principle applies to photo spreads, and the ABA policy does not make any recommendation preferring lineups over photo spreads or vice-versa. Taslitz, supra note 234, at 21 (internal citations omitted); see also Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 858. 260 Avraham M. Levi & R. C. L. Lindsay, Lineup and Photo Spread Procedures: Issues Concerning Policy Recommendations, 7 PSYCHOL. PUB. POL’Y & L. 776, 787 (2001); Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 62; see also ROY S. MALPASS, EYEWITNESS IDENTIFICATION RESEARCH LABORATORY, UNIV. OF TEX. AT EL PASO, A LINEUP EVALUATION “DO-IT-YOURSELF KIT” FOR ATTORNEYS AND LAW ENFORCEMENT 4–5, available at http://eyewitness.utep.edu/Documents/ DIY%20Kit.pdf. Malpass sets forth a mathematical formula for evaluating the functional size of a lineup (i.e., if certain fillers fail to draw or draw too few choices from mock witnesses or certain fillers draw too many choices from mock witnesses). Id. 261 Levi & Lindsay, supra note 260, at 787. 262 See Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 62 (“Thus, adding six additional members to a six-person lineup reduces the chances of mistaken identification from 16.7% to 8.3% (i.e., among those making an identification).”); see also Levi & Lindsay, supra note 260, at 787 (arguing that the use of nine- or ten-person lineups in England and twelve in Canada suggests that the use of larger lineups will not inhibit identifications: “Available research evidence shows no decline in correct identification from simultaneous lineups of at least 20 persons. Mug shot research suggests that even larger lineups may not compromise correct identification rates.” (internal citations omitted)); Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 63 (finding that eyewitnesses could view over 300 photos without a drop in the number of accurate identification and arguing that an increase in lineup size could play an important role in reducing eyewitness error). 490 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 263 stand out from the foils. If a suspect stands out from the foils in an identification procedure, it cannot be reliably determined if the eyewitness’s identification of the suspect is due to the eyewitness’s memory or the manner in which the lineup was When this occurs, it may substantially conducted.264 diminish or even eliminate the validity of the identification as evidence of the defendant’s guilt.265 There are several procedures that are necessary to prevent this type of error. First, the foils should generally match the eyewitness’s description of the perpetrator of the crime.266 Second, suspects should be placed in different positions in each lineup by having the suspect’s position in the lineup randomly determined.267 Random positioning of the suspect rather than placing a suspect always in the same position prevents a suspect’s position in an identification procedure from becoming common knowledge among law enforcement and 263 Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 859 (“Likewise, in an identification procedure where the suspect stands out, it cannot be determined if the eyewitness selected the suspect because he or she recognized the suspect as the perpetrator of the crime, or because of the biasing effect of the fillers in the indentification procedure.”). 264 Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 63; see also MALPASS, supra note 260, at 2 (delineating a mathematical test for evaluating lineup bias produced by filler selection). 265 Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 63; see also MALPASS, supra note 260 at 2. 266 The National Institute of Justice’s Training Manual states that police should: Select fillers who generally fit the witness’s description of the perpetrator. When there is a limited/inadequate description of the perpetrator provided by the witness, or when the description of the perpetrator differs significantly from the appearance of the suspect, fillers should resemble the suspect in significant features. This does not mean that the fillers must closely resemble the suspect . . . If the description does not fit the suspect on some characteristic (e.g., the witness described dark hair, yet the suspect has light hair), then the fillers should match the suspect on that characteristic rather than matching the description on that characteristic so that the suspect does not stand out. NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 36; Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 62 (“The general recommendation for selecting fillers for lineups has been to use the eyewitness’s description of the target and take any additional measures needed to make sure that the suspect does not stand out in the lineup.”). For detailed procedures in selecting fillers when the suspect does not match the eyewitness’s description, the suspect has unique non-described features, the suspect has common non-described features, the eyewitness description of the perpetrator is unique, or there is more than one eyewitness, see Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 632–34. 267 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 36 (“If specific investigators consistently choose the same lineup location for the suspect, this can become common knowledge among both law enforcement officers and the general public. This could lead a witness to pick the person in that position for reasons other than recognizing the suspect.”); see also Wogalter et al., supra note 179, at 72 (“Most officers report that they usually place the suspect in the middle of both live (87%) and photographic lineups (81%) as opposed to the beginning (left) and end (right) positions, but approximately one-half (47%) of those who construct live lineups said that they allow suspects to choose their location.”). 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 491 268 the general public. Third, fillers should not be reused with the same eyewitness.269 When the same fillers are used with a new suspect they make the suspect stand out because the suspect is the only person not appearing in a previous identification procedure.270 Finally, the manner in which the lineup is conducted should not draw the eyewitness’s attention to the suspect.271 6. Law enforcement should use sequential identification procedures.272 In a simultaneous lineup, an eyewitness views all participants in the lineup at the same time.273 In a sequential lineup, members are presented individually to the eyewitness.274 Each lineup participant in a sequential lineup is shown only once, and the eyewitness must decide before seeing the next lineup participant if he or she is the perpetrator.275 Furthermore, the eyewitness is not told how many participants there are in the lineup.276 Compared to simultaneous lineups, sequential lineups reduce eyewitness error because they tend to force an eyewitness to make an absolute rather than a relative judgment when making an identification.277 When an eyewitness employs an absolute 268 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 36. Id. at 36–37 (“Using the same fillers with a new suspect can make the suspect stand out as the only one not appearing in a previous lineup. This could be considered a suggestive procedure. Also, the witness might recognize one of the fillers (from seeing him/her in a previous lineup) and misidentify the filler as the perpetrator.”). 270 Id. 271 COSTANZO, supra note 1, at 185. For example, the suspect should not be the only lineup member to repeat what the perpetrator said during the crime. See Koehnken et al., supra note 130, at 211 (explaining how other biased conditions of a lineup could make the suspect stand out from the foils, for example, if the suspect was the only one wearing handcuffs). 272 Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 860. 273 Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 63. 274 Id. 275 Id. 276 Id.; see also Stinson et al., supra note 124, at 212 (explaining how a sequential lineup is conducted). 277 Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 586; NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 44. The State of New Jersey requires sequential lineups, and a New York court ordered a double-blind sequential lineup in at least one case. Headley, supra note 183, at 699–700. Moreover: New Jersey’s reforms have influenced other states to examine the possibility of adopting similar lineup protocols. In 2002, Illinois Governor George H. Ryan’s Commission on Capital Punishment, charged with ensuring the accuracy and justness of capital punishment in Illinois, recommended the implementation of eyewitness identification reforms. The North Carolina Actual Innocence Commission created a series of recommendations in 2003 for state law enforcement officers, including a comprehensive lineup protocol. In early 2005, the Avery Task Force made similar recommendations for the Wisconsin criminal justice system. The Virginia General Assembly also instructed the Virginia State Crime 269 492 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 judgment, the eyewitness identifies the suspect because his or her appearance matches the eyewitness’s memory of the perpetrator of the crime and not because the suspect most closely resembles the perpetrator.278 Although one study, conducted in Illinois, suggested that sequential identification procedures were of dubious value, the results of that study are flawed because of a design defect: double blind lineups were used only for the sequential lineups and not for simultaneous lineups.279 Commission to create guidelines for improving lineup procedures in the commonwealth. Klobuchar et al., supra note 183, at 386–87 (footnotes omitted). 278 Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 613–14 (“Under [simultaneous lineup] conditions, the relative judgment process will nevertheless yield a positive identification because there will always be someone who looks more like the culprit than do the remaining lineup members. The problem . . . therefore, is that it includes no mechanism for deciding that the culprit is none of the people in the lineup.”); Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 61. 279 In a recent study, conducted on behalf of the State of Illinois, however, Sheri H. Mecklenburg found that the use of sequential lineups did not reduce erroneous identifications. SHERI H. MECKLENBURG, REPORT TO THE LEGISLATURE OF THE STATE OF ILLINOIS: THE ILLINOIS PILOT PROGRAM ON SEQUENTIAL DOUBLE-BLIND IDENTIFICATION PROCEDURES iv (2006), available at http://www.psychology.iastate.edu/FACULTY/gwells/IllinoisReport.pdf (“Surprisingly, the Illinois data did not bear out the research experiments that sequential, double-blind lineups produce a lower rate of known false identifications. Instead, the sequential, double-blind procedures resulted in an overall higher rate of known false identifications than did the simultaneous lineups.”). Gary L. Wells, a leading eyewitness researcher and a developer of the sequential lineup, pointed out an important design flaw in the Illinois study: My main reaction to this report is disappointment and concern that the design of the study does not permit any clear conclusions. The reason that it does not permit clear conclusions is because the simultaneous lineups never used the double-blind procedure whereas the sequential lineups always used the double-blind procedure. This is extremely problematic because the failure to use double-blind procedures with the simultaneous lineups leaves open several “lineup-administrator influenced” means by which filler identifications could be suppressed and identifications of the suspect enhanced. These lineup-administrator influences were not available for the sequential because the sequential was conducted using double-blind procedures. Gary L. Wells, Gary L. Wells’s Comments on the Mecklenburg Report 1 (2006), available at http://www.psychology.iastate.edu/FACULTY/gwells/Illinois_Project_Wells_comments.pdf (last visited Feb. 25, 2009). Wells continues, stating: I was shocked when I learned of the failure of the study to include a double-blind control for the simultaneous lineups, a fact I learned only when I read the final report. Nancy Steblay clearly states that she too had no idea that this study would have this design flaw. I have asked Sherri [sic] Mecklenburg to correct this misperception, but no corrections have yet been made as far as I am aware. Id. Nancy Steblay, another prominent eyewitness expert, states, “My primary concern with the Illinois report is that its conclusion appears to [have] . . . minimal appreciation of the underlying reasons for these outcomes or the broader context of what is known about eyewitness fallibility.” NANCY STEBLAY, OBSERVATIONS ON THE ILLINOIS LINEUP DATA 6 (May 3, 2006), available at http://web.augsburg.edu/~steblay/ObservationsOnTheIllinoisData.pdf. She also reports that “[Hennepin County]’s conclusion is that the blind-sequential procedure is working well in Minnesota. Acceptable suspect ID rates and lower filler rates suggest a protocol that will help to convict the guilty and protect the innocent.” Id. at 7. The experience of the pilot project [in Hennepin County] indicates that the double- 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 493 7. The lineup administrator should not know the identity of the suspect.280 Scientific studies show that when the lineup administrator knows the suspect’s identity in an identification procedure, he or she can intentionally or unintentionally cause the eyewitness to choose the suspect through verbal and non-verbal cues.281 The eyewitness is generally unaware that the lineup administrator has influenced his or her identification of the suspect.282 blind sequential protocol is workable for police in both large and small departments without undercutting the ability to solve cases. At the same time, the protocol elicits valuable new information for the effective investigation and prosecution of criminal cases. Klobuchar et al., supra note 183, at 413. Commenting on the Mecklenburg Report and comments by Wells and Steblay, several prominent psychologists remarked: If it is the case that the better outcome from the non-blind/simultaneous procedure is partly or entirely attributable to subtle, unintentional cues provided by the administrator, then the Illinois result may simply underscore that the present procedure produces a biased outcome that may ultimately result in the increased conviction of innocent individuals. Daniel L. Schacter et al., Policy Forum: Studying Eyewitness Investigations in the Field, 32 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 1, 4 (2008). The State of Wisconsin also decided not to change its new eyewitness procedures in response to the Illinois report, stating that “the design of the program does not seem to support [the] inference or conclusion [that the higher rate of filler identification is due to the sequential procedure].” BUREAU OF TRAINING AND STANDARDS FOR CRIMINAL JUSTICE, WIS. DEP’T OF JUSTICE, RESPONSE TO CHICAGO REPORT ON EYEWITNESS IDENTIFICATION PROCEDURES 3–4 (2006), available at http://www.doj.state.wi.us/dles/tns/ILRptResponse.pdf. It further states that “the extensive prior laboratory research revealing that the double-blind and sequential procedures are superior remains the best scientific information available.” Id. at 4. 280 Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 862. 281 See Bradfield et al., supra note 12, at 112, 118 (“A lineup administrator who is invested in the outcome of a witness’s identification cannot be expected to have the same reaction (verbally or nonverbally) to a filler identification that he or she has to an identification of the suspect. Even if investigators are cautioned against giving feedback to eyewitnesses, involuntary reactions to a witness’s selection are difficult to conceal.”); Sarah M. Greathouse & Margaret Bull Kovera, Instruction Bias and Lineup Presentation Moderate the Effects of Administrator Knowledge on Eyewitness Identification, 33 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 70, 80 (2009) (advocating for a double-blind lineup procedure); Taslitz, supra note 234, at 21; Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 63; see also Ryann M. Haw & Ronald P. Fisher, Effects of Administrator-Witness Contact on Eyewitness Identification Accuracy, 89 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 1106, 1106 (2004) (“Despite research findings showing its benefits, police are resistant to using double-blind testing because they perceive it as a loss of control and as a suggestion that they cannot conduct fair lineups.”). In a double-blind lineup, neither the eyewitness nor the lineup administrator knows the identity of the suspect. Bradfield et al., supra note 12, at 118. Double-blind lineups also preclude the eyewitness from looking to the lineup administrator for clues as to the identity of the suspect or for confirmation that the eyewitness has chosen the suspect. Id. Finally, they prevent the lineup administrator from artificially increasing the eyewitness’s confidence. Id.; see infra Part VII.8. (discussing that eyewitnesses should be given cautionary instructions). 282 See Haw & Fisher, supra note 281, at 1110 (“Witnesses were most confident when their lineup selection confirmed the administrator’s beliefs. Nevertheless, almost none of the witnesses (4.7%) or lineup administrators (0%) were aware of the lineup administrator’s influence.”); Wells & Bradfield, supra note 118, at 374 (“These data suggest that the eyewitness who is asked at trial whether the comments of a lineup agent is influencing the way they are answering the questions at trial is in fact 494 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW 8. Eyewitnesses instructions.283 should be given [Vol. 42:435 cautionary The lineup administrator should provide the eyewitness with the following cautionary instructions. First, he or she should be told that it is just as important to clear innocent suspects as it is to identify guilt suspects.284 This instruction emphasizes to the eyewitness that not identifying a lineup participant may be the correct decision.285 Second, the eyewitness should be advised that the perpetrator’s appearance may have changed since the crime.286 Many physical characteristics such as hair are changeable and perpetrators frequently alter their appearance when they participate in an identification procedure.287 Third, the eyewitness should be informed that the person who committed the crime may not be in the photo array or lineup.288 Research shows that this instruction significantly reduces eyewitness error with a minimal reduction in correct identification.289 Fourth, the eyewitness should be instructed that the lineup administrator does not know the identity of the suspect.290 This prevents the eyewitness from looking to the unable to accurately report on that influence.”). An Illinois study criticized the use of the double-blind method, however, as previously indicated, claiming that the design of that study was seriously flawed. See discussion supra note 279 (criticizing the Mecklenburg study for its design flaw of failing to use double-blind administrations with both sequential and simultaneous lineups). 283 Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 863. 284 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 40 (“This advice helps emphasize that failure to identify the suspect might be, in some cases, the appropriate outcome. Clearing an innocent suspect from suspicion can help refocus the investigation on developing other suspects.”). 285 Id. at 39. 286 The National Institute of Justice notes: Many physical characteristics are changeable. Hair, for instance, can be restyled, colored, cut, or grown longer; facial hair can be grown or cut; and so forth. Witnesses need to keep in mind that the suspect’s appearance on these changeable features might have been different at the time of the photo than it was at the time of the crime. Id.; see also Narby et al., supra note 181, at 35–36 (discussing natural and deliberate changes in a perpetrator’s appearance since the commission of the crime). 287 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 40; Narby et al., supra note 181, at 35–36. 288 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 40; Taslitz, supra note 234, at 21; see also Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 615 (finding that an instruction that the perpetrator might or might not be present “has the effect of reducing identifications when the perpetrator is absent from the lineup while having no effect on identifying the perpetrator when the perpetrator is in the lineup”). 289 See Nancy Mehrkens Steblay, Social Influence in Eyewitness Recall: A Meta-Analytic Review of Lineup Instruction Effects, 21 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 283, 287–94 (1997). Steblay’s study aggregated the results of twenty-two prior studies on this topic using 2588 participants. The results showed that a cautionary instruction warning that the perpetrator may not be in the lineup reduced the rate of erroneous identifications by forty-two percent in culprit-absent identification procedures. It reduced the rate of accurate identifications in culprit-present identification procedures by only two percent. Id. 290 Wells supports this safeguard, arguing: 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 495 lineup administrator for clues as to the identity of the suspect or to confirm that he or she has chosen the suspect from the lineup.291 Finally, the eyewitness should be advised that the investigation will continue regardless of whether the eyewitness makes an identification.292 This instruction decreases the pressure on an eyewitness to make an identification and lets the eyewitness know that the success of the investigation does not depend on his or her identification of the suspect.293 9. All identifications should be videorecorded.294 Videorecording of identification procedures is essential to ensure that there is a complete, accurate record of the identification procedures so that attorneys, judges, and jurors can evaluate their fairness of the identification procedure.295 The person who administers the lineup should not only be blind as to which person in the lineup is the suspect, but should also be perceived (by the eyewitness) to be blind as to which person is the suspect. The rationale is simply to prevent eyewitnesses from looking to the lineup administrator for cues as to which person to select or for cues as to whether the person they selected is the “right person.” Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 630; see also Garrioch & Brimacombe, supra note 134, at 306; Taslitz, supra note 234, at 21 (“The lineup administrator must instruct witnesses . . . that they should not assume the administrator knows who is the suspect . . . .”). 291 Garrioch & Brimacombe, supra note 134, at 306; Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 630; see also Taslitz, supra note 234, at 21 (stating that the eyewitness should be informed that the administrator does not know the identity of the suspect to reduce the risk of the eyewitness guessing the suspect’s identity). 292 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 39. 293 Id. 294 Saul M. Kassin, Eyewitness Identification Procedures: The Fifth Rule, 22 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 649, 649 (1998); Taslitz, supra note 234, at 22. Videorecording preserves any record of error or suggestiveness: Because most initial identifications of criminal suspects are done with photographs (and a large percentage of jurisdictions in the U.S. use only photographs and never use live lineups), the discovery of any ephemeral suggestive events that were embedded in the photographic lineup remains almost entirely dependent on the testimony of the case detective and the witness. Often, it is unclear that the witness and the detective who administered the photographic lineup are properly motivated to report suggestiveness. But, even if the witness and detective are motivated to report any suggestiveness, they would have had to explicitly notice its significance at the time, interpret it as a suggestive event, remember it for the weeks or sometimes months that pass before being questioned, and then articulate it to the questioning party. The scientific psychology literature is replete with evidence supporting the conclusion that people are poor at being able to accurately report on the variables that influence their responses and generally think that their actions are self-directed. The general point is there are vey good reasons to believe that the actual prevalence of suggestiveness in eyewitness identification procedures greatly exceeds the ability of defense counsel to prove it. Wells & Quinlivan, supra note 58, at 16 (internal citations omitted); see also Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 863–64 (stating that videorecording allows juries, judges, and attorneys to evaluate the fairness of an identification procedure). 295 Kassin, supra note 294, at 650. 496 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 Moreover, the other safeguards are of dubious effectiveness if there is no objective, complete record of how the identification procedures were conducted.296 Although the failure to videorecord a lineup should not mandate suppression of an eyewitness’s testimony, in a case where there were no practical barriers to videorecording it, a judge should be skeptical of police assurances that no suggestiveness occurred. Furthermore, if the eyewitness is allowed to testify, the judge should permit expert testimony about the kinds of suggestiveness that might intentionally or unintentionally occur at a lineup and should instruct the jury that they should be cautious about relying on the testimony of an eyewitness who made a prior identification at a lineup that was not videorecorded. 10. “An eyewitness should make a clear statement of his or her confidence at the time of the identification and prior to receiving any feedback.”297 As we have seen, eyewitness confidence is the factor that the trier of fact relies on most heavily in evaluating the accuracy of eyewitness identification.298 Because eyewitness confidence is highly malleable and because many factors can increase confidence but not eyewitness accuracy, by the time of trial, eyewitness confidence has little probative value in In contrast, if an assessing eyewitness accuracy.299 eyewitness’s statement of confidence is taken immediately after an identification of a suspect and prior to any feedback, it generally has a moderate, positive relationship to eyewitness accuracy, at least for those eyewitnesses who choose a suspect.300 Accordingly, statements of eyewitness 296 Id. at 652; Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 863–64. Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 864. 298 Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 620. 299 Andrew E. Taslitz states: Videotaping witness confidence statements at the time of the lineup or photo spread discourages upward confidence drift over time, or at least enables defense counsel to counter a witness’s sincere insistence at trial of perfect confidence in his or her earlier identification of the defendant. For similar reasons, police are urged to obtain confidence statements from witnesses at the time that they make the identification. Taslitz, supra note 234, at 22–23; Wells & Bradfield, supra note 118, at 375; Wells et al., Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 635; see also Klobuchar et al., supra note 183, at 390–91 (advocating for a double-blind procedure for eyewitness identifications). 300 See Gary L. Wells & Donna M. Murray, Eyewitness Confidence, in EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY: PSYCHOLOGICAL PERSPECTIVES 155, 168–69 (Gary L. Wells & Elizabeth F. Loftus eds., 1984) (finding that studies on eyewitness confidence generally indicate that highly confident eyewitnesses are only somewhat more likely to make accurate identifications than less confident eyewitnesses); Wells et al., 297 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 497 confidence should be taken immediately after the eyewitness makes an identification and before extraneous factors can influence it.301 11. Once a mistake is made in an identification procedure, it cannot be corrected. Because of the nature of memory, the effects of a suggestive lineup procedure cannot be corrected by later conducting a fair identification procedure.302 VIII. COMMON EYEWITNESS FACTORS DURING A CRIME THAT AFFECT EYEWITNESS ACCURACY Strong empirical evidence demonstrates that the following eyewitness factors, which arise frequently during crimes, have a significant effect on eyewitness accuracy. The effect of some of the eyewitness factors on identification accuracy may appear obvious and simply a matter of common sense. Nonetheless, because many eyewitness factors have a counterintuitive effect on identification accuracy, we believe it is important to include these common sense eyewitness factors as well. This list is not comprehensive. Accordingly, judges and attorneys should consult an eyewitness expert or the relevant scientific literature especially when handling criminal cases where the primary or sole evidence of the defendant’s guilt is eyewitness testimony. The eyewitness factors are divided into three types: (1) eyewitness characteristics; (2) perpetrator characteristics; and (3) and crime characteristics. Eyewitness Identification Procedures, supra note 12, at 626 (“The facts [sic] that eyewitness identification confidence is given great weight by jurors, that confidence is only modestly related to accuracy under pristine conditions, and that confidence is malleable are all matters of considerable importance.”). Although some more recent studies show that under some conditions eyewitness confidence may have a greater relationship to eyewitness accuracy than earlier studies indicated, researchers warn that substantial CA [confidence accuracy] obtained in this study and in some others . . . should not be construed as evidence that the confidence witnesses display in court predicts the accuracy of their identification testimony. Myriad social, cognitive, and statistical factors likely greatly attenuate the CA relationship over the months between when a crime was witnessed and when the witness testifies. It is not to courtroom testimony to which the current findings may generalize, but rather to initial identification decisions made in nonbiased testing situations shortly after a witnessed event. D. Stephen Lindsay et al., Witnessing-Condition Heterogeneity and Witnesses’ Versus Investigators’ Confidence in the Accuracy of Witnesses’ Identification Decisions, 24 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 685, 695 (2000) (internal citations omitted). 301 NAT’L INST. OF JUSTICE, supra note 185, at 39–40. 302 Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 852; see also supra Parts III.A., V (discussing the nature of eyewitness memory and why a biased identification procedure cannot be corrected by later conducting a fair identification procedure). 498 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 TABLE 3: COMMON EYEWITNESS FACTORS DURING A CRIME THAT AFFECT IDENTIFICATION ACCURACY A. Eyewitness Characteristics 1. Child eyewitnesses 2. Elderly eyewitnesses 3. Law enforcement officers 4. Alcoholic intoxication 5. Minor details 6. Unconscious transference B. Perpetrator Characteristics 1. Cross-race bias 2. Disguises 3. Face distinctiveness 4. Weapon focus C. Crime Characteristics 1. Exposure time 2. Forgetting curve and retention interval 3. Lighting 4. Stress A. Eyewitness Characteristics 1. Child Eyewitnesses When asked open-ended questions, children provide reasonably accurate accounts of crime though they provide less information and somewhat less accurate information than adults.303 Young children are more likely than adults to be influenced by suggestion, peer pressures, and other social influences.304 Therefore, it is essential with a child eyewitness not to use suggestive questioning, repeated questioning, praise or rewards for desired answers, criticism or disapproval for unfavorable responses, or provide other forms of post-event information to the child.305 Children are also about as accurate as adults at making identifications 303 COSTANZO, supra note 1, at 183. Id.; see also Joanna D. Pozzulo, Person Description and Identification by Child Witnesses, in 2 HANDBOOK OF EYEWITNESS PSYCHOLOGY: MEMORY FOR PEOPLE 283, 296 (Rod C. L. Lindsay et al. eds., 2007) (stating that children are more eager to please the interviewer than adults and so they are more likely to give answers that they think the interviewer wants them to give than adults). 305 COSTANZO, supra note 1, at 183. 304 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 499 306 provided the perpetrator is present in the identification procedure. If the perpetrator is absent from the lineup, however, children make more erroneous eyewitness identifications because of their greater suggestibility.307 2. Elderly Eyewitnesses Like children, elderly eyewitnesses perform nearly as well as young adults in identifying the perpetrator when he or she is present in the lineup.308 Thus age appears to have little effect on the accuracy of recognition memory.309 When a lineup does not contain the perpetrator, however, like children, they make more mistaken identifications than young adults.310 Elderly adults also appear to recall fewer details about a crime than young adults.311 Some of this difference may, however, may be a product of elder adults’ greater caution and less confidence than young adults in their ability to recall the facts of a crime.312 3. Law Enforcement Officers Although law enforcement officers are more skilled than lay eyewitnesses at remembering the details or a crime, studies indicate they are not better than lay eyewitnesses at identifying the perpetrator of a 306 See id.; see also Pozzulo, supra note 304, at 302 (“On a positive note, children as young as 5 years old can accurately identify a guilty suspect from a simultaneous lineup at the same rate as adults.”). 307 COSTANZO, supra note 1, at 183; see also Pozzulo, supra note 304, at 302 (“Unfortunately, in those cases where police have arrested an innocent suspect, children, even over 12 years of age, are more likely than adults to make an identification of an innocent person.”). 308 James C. Bartlett & Amina Memon, Eyewitness Memory in Young and Older Adults, in 2 HANDBOOK OF EYEWITNESS PSYCHOLOGY: MEMORY FOR PEOPLE 309, 333 (Rod C. L. Lindsay et al. eds., 2007) (“Within the lineup task, age-related deficits in correct rejections of target-absent lineups are larger and more consistent than age-related deficits in correct identifications from target-present lineups, a finding in line with a good deal of evidence from standard laboratory paradigms.”). 309 BARTOL & BARTOL, supra note 92, at 250. There is a limited amount of research on elderly eyewitnesses. Thus, some of the present conclusions may have to be revised or modified as more research is conducted. Id.; see also Kassin et al., supra note 117, at 408 tbl.1, 411, 412 tbl.4 (noting that only fifty percent of the sixty-four eyewitness experts in their survey agreed with the eyewitness statement that “elderly eyewitnesses are less accurate than are younger adults”). 310 Kassin et al., supra note 117, at 412. 311 See BARTOL & BARTOL, supra note 92, at 250–51 (“Older subjects do appear to be less adept at free recall of an incident than younger adults; a finding also reported for children.”). One study found: Where straightforward comparisons have been made between different age groups, young adults have been found to be significantly superior to old adults in their accuracy of recall for perpetrator characteristics, environmental details, and details of actions and events. This applies to both free recall (where the witness provides a narrative account from his or her own perspective) and to cued recall (where the witness responds to interviewer questions . . .). Bartlett & Memon, supra note 308, at 312 (citations omitted). 312 See BARTOL & BARTOL, supra note 92, at 251. 500 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 313 crime. This result occurs because though people can be trained to give more detailed accounts of crimes, their ability to identify faces cannot be improved.314 4. Alcoholic Intoxication and Marijuana Use Victims and eyewitnesses are frequently intoxicated when a crime is committed.315 The limited research available on intoxicated eyewitnesses316 indicates that alcohol primarily reduces memory for the details of a crime and the ability of an eyewitness to identify the perpetrator by interfering with his or her ability to perceive and encode the crime rather than by affecting retrieval.317 In other words, though an 313 See Brigham et al., supra note 90, at 16 (stating that research has failed to show that officers are better at identifying faces than ordinary citizens); Deffenbacher, supra note 102, at 379 (“Police . . . may even have a pronounced bias to identify someone from a lineup.”). For example: Yuille has shown that although both police trainees and veteran officers do not recall more correct sequential action facts that [sic] do lay persons, they do recall more correct descriptive facts about persons and scene details, and are more resistant to the effects of suggestion concerning salient details, at least. Id. at 380 (internal citations omitted). 314 Id. at 379; Narby et al., supra note 181, at 30. 315 See Jennifer E. Dysart et al., The Intoxicated Witness: Effects of Alcohol on Identification Accuracy from Showups, 87 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 170, 170 (2002) (“Given the frequency of criminal activity in alcohol-abundant environments, understanding the possible effects of alcohol on eyewitness memory is critical.”); Narby et al., supra note 181, at 40 (“Evidence from police files suggests that intoxicating substances, particularly alcohol, go hand in hand with many crimes. Both perpetrators and witnesses are often intoxicated at the time of the event.” (internal citation omitted)); Sal A. Soraci et al., Psychological Impairment, Eyewitness Testimony, and False Memories: Individual Differences, in 1 HANDBOOK OF EYEWITNESS PSYCHOLOGY: MEMORY FOR EVENTS 261, 282 (Michael P. Toglia et al. eds., 2007) (“The question itself is also relevant because it is well known that events of forensic importance, indeed the majority of violent assaults and other crimes, very often occur in the context of substances that alter psychological and physiological processes of perpetrators, victims, and witnesses.” (citations omitted)). 316 See BARTOL & BARTOL, supra note 92, at 242; Soraci et al., supra note 315, at 282 (“However, the psychological literature on the effects of these substances on recollections of complex events is sparse, and, as a result, the specific memorial consequences of the ingestion of most drugs are not well understood.”). 317 See BARTOL & BARTOL, supra note 92, at 242 (noting that ninety percent of the sixty-four eyewitness experts in Kassin’s survey agree with the following statement: “Alcoholic intoxication impairs an eyewitness later ability to recall persons and events.”); Kassin et al., supra note 117, at 408 tbl.1, 412 tbl.4. Laboratory research has shown that alcohol consumption inhibits the encoding process when administered beforehand and thereby impairs subsequent recall of information. However, research has been somewhat limited in examining the influence of alcohol or drug usage on the accuracy or completeness of eyewitness descriptions. One of the few empirical studies examining the effect of alcohol consumption on witness recall was conducted by Yuille and Tollestrup. In general, the authors found that consumption of alcohol significantly impaired participants’ ability to recall details (in both frequency and accuracy of recall) of the event and/or target person, regardless of whether the participant recalled immediately (and under the continued influence of alcohol) or 1 week later. Read, Yuille, and Tollestrup subsequently found similar effects. In his archival analysis, Sporer also found that when witnesses had consumed alcohol they were less able to report details about the perpetrator’s appearance. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 501 intoxicated eyewitness will remember less about the crime and the perpetrator, the information an intoxicated eyewitness recalls about a crime tends to be almost as accurate as that recalled by a sober eyewitness.318 Because the intoxicated eyewitness remembers less about a crime, he or she is more likely to make an erroneous identification than a sober eyewitness when the perpetrator is not present in the photo array or lineup.319 Furthermore, intoxicated eyewitnesses may be more susceptible to suggestion and post-event information than sober eyewitnesses.320 Accordingly, it may be especially important to avoid suggestion and postevent information when questioning eyewitnesses who were intoxicated at the time of the crime.321 Finally, one study suggested that if an intoxicated eyewitness experiences a high degree of stress or arousal during the crime, this tends to reduce the negative effects of moderate levels of alcohol consumption on eyewitness memory.322 Only one study has assessed the effects of marijuana on eyewitness testimony. The results indicated that when marijuana is consumed in moderation, its effects on memory appear to be fairly small and temporary.323 Christian A. Meissner et al., Person Descriptions as Eyewitness Evidence, in 2 HANDBOOK OF EYEWITNESS PSYCHOLOGY: MEMORY FOR PEOPLE 3, 11 (Rod C. L. Lindsay et al. eds., 2007) (internal citations omitted); see also Narby et al., supra note 181, at 41 (“Empirical evidence supports the importance of alcohol consumption as a variable that affects both the quality and quantity of recall, as well as affecting identification tasks.”); J. Don Read et al., Recollections of a Robbery: Effects of Arousal and Alcohol upon Recall and Person Identification, 16 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 425, 434 (1992) (“With rare exception alcohol has been demonstrated not to impair retrieval processes and, in this context, an effect of alcohol expectancy upon retrieval alone would be surprising.”); Soraci et al., supra note 315, at 285 (“For the most part, investigations of the effects of drugs on memory have focused on the encoding and storage stages, rather than retrieval. The reason is simple: the largest effects of drugs are observed at these stages.”). 318 John C. Yuille & Patricia A. Tollestrup, Some Effects of Alcohol on Eyewitness Memory, 75 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 268, 271 (1990) (“The accuracy of the information recalled was high in both alcohol and control groups, although slightly lower when alcohol was consumed.”). 319 For example, a study found the following: In the target-absent conditions, participants in the low-blood-alcohol-level condition were more likely to make a correct rejection (.78) than were those in the high-blood-alcohol-level condition (.48). In the target-present conditions, participants in the high-blood-alcohol-level group were as likely to make a correct identification (.62) as participants in the low-blood-alcohol-level group (.68). Dysart et al., supra note 315, at 173 (internal citations omitted); see also Yuille & Tollestrup, supra note 318, at 272 (“Alcohol had no effect on the ability of witnesses to identify correctly a picture of the thief 1 week later. However, alcohol did influence the number of incorrect choices when the thief’s picture was not included in the photospread.”). 320 Soraci et al., supra note 315, at 288 (“Finally, it is likely that individuals who have consumed alcohol may be less resistant to the effects of suggestion and post-event information. If true, more precautions need to be taken during their interviews and interrogation.”). 321 Id. 322 See id. at 287 (stating that there is “some support for the lay idea that fear or stress can serve to ‘sober up’ someone who has been drinking, at least at moderate levels of consumption”). 323 John C. Yuille et al., An Exploration on the Effects of Marijuana on Eyewitness Memory, 21 INT’L J.L. & PSYCHIATRY, 117, 124 (1998). 502 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 5. Minor Details A witness’s ability to recall minor or peripheral details about a crime is not related to identification accuracy.324 In fact, an eyewitness’s memory for minor or peripheral details of a crime is inversely related to eyewitness accuracy because an eyewitness who attends to peripheral details has fewer cognitive resources available to encode the perpetrator’s face.325 6. Unconscious Transference326 Eyewitnesses sometimes identify as the perpetrator a bystander to the crime or an individual they saw in a different context or situation.327 For example, an eyewitness who viewed a mug-shot of a suspect who later appears in a lineup may identify the suspect as the perpetrator of a crime even though the suspect is innocent.328 Accordingly, it is always important for law enforcement officials to determine prior to conducting an identification procedure whether the eyewitness saw the suspect before or after the crime.329 B. Perpetrator Characteristics 1. Cross-Race Bias330 Eyewitnesses make more accurate identifications of perpetrators of their own race than other races.331 324 Gary L. Wells & Michael R. Leippe, How Do Triers of Fact Infer the Accuracy of Eyewitness Identifications? Using Memory for Peripheral Detail Can Be Misleading, 66 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 682, 684 tbl.1 (1981). 325 Id. 326 This Article uses the term “unconscious transference” to refer to a specific type of source monitoring error that occurs when the eyewitness misidentifies as the perpetrator of a crime a bystander to a crime or a person they saw in another situation or context (e.g., identify an innocent suspect in a lineup as the perpetrator because they previously saw the suspect’s mug-shot). See discussion supra Part III.D. (concerning the source monitoring error and its contribution to erroneous eyewitness testimony). 327 COSTANZO, supra note 1, at 178. 328 See Brown et al., supra note 254, at 315–16; Koehnken et al., supra note 130, at 217; see also discussion supra Part III.C. This error may occur because the suspect in the lineup looks familiar since the eyewitness earlier examined his or her mugshot. See discussion supra Part III.C. In short, the eyewitness makes a source monitoring error and concludes that the familiarity of the suspect in the lineup results from the eyewitness having observed the suspect commit the crime rather than because he or she previously saw the suspect’s mugshot. See discussion supra Part III.D. (regarding the source monitoring error). 329 See discussion supra Part VII.2. (regarding the importance of determining whether an eyewitness has seen the suspect before or after the crime). 330 The term “bias” as used here does not mean racial animosity; rather, as many scientific studies show, it means a person of a particular race is likely to be better at identifying a perpetrator of his or her own race than he or she would be if the perpetrator was of a different race. 331 See Christian A. Meissner & John C. Brigham, Thirty Years of Investigating the Own-Race Bias in Memory for Faces, A Meta-Analytic Review, 7 PSYCHOL. PUB. POL’Y & L. 3, 21 (2001). Meissner and Brigham found in a study that the probability of a mistaken identification is 1.56 times greater when a witness makes an other-race identification than when a witness makes a same-race 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 503 2. Disguises Even simple disguises such as a hat can make it significantly more difficult for an eyewitness to make an accurate identification.332 A hat decreases eyewitness accuracy because it conceals the perpetrator’s hair and facial shape, which are important cues to identifying a person.333 3. Face Distinctiveness Distinctive faces (e.g., faces that are highly attractive or unattractive) are more likely to be recognized than faces that are non-distinctive.334 4. Weapon Focus The presence of a weapon impairs an eyewitness’s ability to accurately identify the perpetrator’s face.335 This occurs because the eyewitness tends to focus on the weapon, which leaves less attention available to the identification. Id. at 15. If this experimental finding carries over to real cases, then an innocent African-American suspect has a fifty-six percent greater chance of being misidentified by a Caucasian than an African-American eyewitness. See John C. Brigham et al., The Influence of Race on Eyewitness Memory, in 2 HANDBOOK OF EYEWITNESS PSYCHOLOGY: MEMORY FOR PEOPLE 257, 257– 58 (Rod C. L. Lindsay et al. eds., 2006) (“The cross-race effect (CRE), also known as the own-race bias or other race-effect, refers to the consistent finding that adults are able to recognize individuals of their own race better than faces of another, less familiar race.”); Narby et al., supra note 181, at 42 (“[T]here is little doubt that the own-race bias in recognition is reliable and appreciable in magnitude, but the theoretical underpinnings of the effect are elusive.”). 332 Narby, Cutler, and Penrod made such a finding: In our own research, we examined the effects of masking a target’s hair cues on subsequent identification accuracy. In these experiments, participants viewed a videotaped robbery and later attempted an identification from a line-up parade. In half of the robberies the robber wore a knit pullover cap that covered his hair and hairline. In the other half, the robber did not wear a hat. In these experiments identification accuracy was appreciably reduced for subjects exposed to disguised targets. For example, in one of the experiments, 45% of the participants gave correct judgments on the line-up test if the robber wore no hat during the robbery, but only 27% gave a correct judgment if the robber wore the hat during the robbery. Narby et al., supra note 181, at 35 (citations omitted); see also Patterson & Baddeley, supra note 101, at 416; Shapiro & Penrod, supra note 101, at 145; Wells & Olson, supra note 13, at 281. 333 Brian L. Cutler et al., Improving the Reliability of Eyewitness Identification: Putting Context Into Context, 72 J. APPLIED PSYCHOL. 629, 635 (1987); Brian L. Cutler et al., The Reliability of Eyewitness Identification, The Role of System and Estimator Variables, 11 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 233, 240 (1987). 334 Narby et al., supra note 181, at 34; Wells & Olson, supra note 13, at 281. 335 See Elizabeth F. Loftus et al., Some Facts About “Weapon Focus,” 11 L. & HUM. BEHAV. 55 (1987). In one study: [S]ubjects who viewed a simulated armed robbery spent more time looking at the weapon than control subjects who saw a virtually identical scene involving a check. They made more eye fixations on the gun, and those fixations were of longer duration. One consequence was a reduced ability to recognize the individual holding the weapon. In the second experiment, subjects who saw the event containing a weapon were not only less likely than controls to accurately identify the perpetrator, but they were less accurate when they answered specific questions about him. Id. at 61; see also Kerri L. Pickel, Unusualness and Threat as Possible Causes of “Weapon Focus,” 6 MEMORY 277, 278 (1998); Steblay, supra note 101, at 416. 504 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 336 eyewitness to observe the perpetrator’s face. C. Crime Characteristics 1. Exposure Time The less time an eyewitness has to witness a crime, the less information the eyewitness will remember about it.337 In general, however, the time an eyewitness has to view the crime is not as important as the type or amount of attention the eyewitness paid to the crime.338 “Indeed, a meta-analysis of facial recognition studies found that ‘quality of viewing,’ which focused centrally on the type of attention that participants paid to the face . . . was the most important determinant of facial identification performance.”339 336 See COSTANZO, supra note 1, at 178; Meissner et al., supra note 317, at 10 (“[S]tudies of the ‘weapon focus’ effect have generally demonstrated a significant influence of the presence of a weapon on person description accuracy.” (internal citation omitted)). 337 See Meissner et al., supra note 317, at 9 (“Yarmey, Jacob, and Porter conducted a study in which participants interacted with a target person for 5 seconds or 30 seconds and were subsequently asked to describe the encounter. As expected, their results indicated that person descriptions . . . were superior when participants had a longer time to observe the target person.” (internal citation omitted)); see also Narby et al., supra note 181, at 37 (“Although some investigations show a linear increase in face recognition accuracy with exposure time, others show a logarithmic relationship. That is, as exposure duration increases, face recognition accuracy improves, but the improvements become smaller at long durations. This finding was supported in the Shapiro and Penrod meta-analysis.” (internal citations omitted)). The first of the Biggers criteria is the opportunity of the witness to view the criminal at the time of the crime. This post-dictor concerns both quantity and quality of view. Intuitively, jurors should be confident in eyewitnesses who had long and unobstructed views of the criminals. Much work in facial recognition has shown that one aspect of the opportunity to view the criminal, namely, increasing the amount of time a person views another individual’s face, leads to boosts in recognition accuracy. However, two caveats apply to these findings. First, facial recognition studies have tended to assess memory with the exact same photographs that the person originally studied. More recent experiments have shown that using different and dissimilar photographs reduces the impact of exposure time on recognition accuracy. Second, at times, the only way to gauge how much time a witness had to view the culprit is to ask the witness to estimate it. People, unfortunately, tend to overestimate the duration of events. Deanna D. Caputo & David Dunning, Distinguishing Accurate Eyewitness Identification from Erroneous Ones: Post-Dictive Indicators of Eyewitness Accuracy, in 2 HANDBOOK OF EYEWITNESS PSYCHOLOGY: MEMORY FOR PEOPLE 427–29 (Rod C. L. Lindsay et al. eds., 2006) (internal citations omitted). 338 Caputo & Dunning, supra note 337, at 429 (“There are many different ways that witnesses can attend to a culprit, and the seriousness and depth of this attention can influence identification accuracy in significant ways.”); see also Wells & Olson, supra note 13, at 282 (“In general, the amount of time a culprit’s face is in view is not as critical for eyewitness identification accuracy as the type or amount of attention given by the witness.”). 339 Caputo & Dunning, supra note 337, at 429. Making physical determinations about a perpetrator’s appearance does not necessarily lead to an accurate identification. If witnesses make abstract judgments about a perpetrator’s appearance, they tend to more clearly recall that perpetrator later on. As would be expected, the amount of time a culprit’s face is in view affects the 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 505 2. Forgetting Curve and Retention Interval Research has demonstrated that memory loss for a crime or other event is highest immediately after the crime occurs and then slows over time.340 Accordingly, eyewitness interviews and identification procedures should be conducted as soon as possible after a crime. 3. Lighting Poor lighting conditions negatively impact an eyewitness’s ability to make an accurate identification.341 4. Stress Very high levels of stress during a crime impair eyewitness accuracy.342 Scientific research shows that different levels of stress can have multiple, sometimes subtle, effects on eyewitness memory. As stress increases, a tunnel memory effect is likely to occur.343 This effect causes some information, such as a weapon, to be vividly remembered while causing other information, such as the color of a perpetrator’s shirt, to be poorly recalled.344 Moreover, very high levels of stress are likely to cause a major deterioration in memory.345 High levels of stress tend to substantially impair eyewitness memory because the stress activates the eyewitness’s fight or flight response, which interferes with the chances that the eyewitness can identify the person later. However, this relationship depends less critically on the eyewitness’s opportunity to view per se and more on the amount and type of attention that the witness directs at the culprit. Given equal exposure time to a face, people are more likely to be able to recognize that face later if they make abstract inferences about it. . . . (e.g., does this person have a large or small nose?). Presumably, this effect occurs because the abstract inferences require holistic processing of the face whereas the physical judgments require feature processing. Wells & Olson, supra note 13, at 282 (internal citations omitted). 340 See Caputo & Dunning, supra note 337, at 432 (“Studies looking at memory decay over time have shown that memory for unfamiliar faces does decrease over time. Indeed, the amount of decay tends to be far greater than people expect. As a consequence, identifications after a significant delay can be quite problematic.” (internal citations omitted)); Deffenbacher, supra note 102, at 380; Meissner et al., supra note 317, at 11–12 (“For example, Ellis, Shepherd, and Davies had participants describe one face immediately after viewing it, and another either 1 hour, the next day, or 1 week following exposure. Participants remembered significantly fewer details after 1 week compared with the two shorter retention intervals . . . .” (internal citation omitted)). 341 See Wells & Olson, supra note 13, at 282 (“Clearly, at the extreme of low light levels there is a point at which a face cannot be perceived well enough to be recognized later.”). 342 See Deffenbacher et al., supra note 102, at 699 (noting that the authors’ meta-analysis supported the hypothesis that high levels of stress negatively affect both identification accuracy and the eyewitness’s ability to recall crime details). 343 See Martin A. Safer et al., Tunnel Memory for Traumatic Events, 12 APPLIED COGNITIVE PSYCHOL. 99, 99–100 (1998) (explaining that “tunnel vision” refers to a narrowing of attention to particular aspects of a situation, which often occurs in stressful situations). 344 Id. 345 See Deffenbacher et al., supra note 102, at 699. 506 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW eyewitness’s ability to pay attention and process information. [Vol. 42:435 346 IX. THE ADMISSIBILITY OF EYEWITNESS IDENTIFICATIONS AT TRIAL The previously discussed scientific findings about eyewitness testimony also support several changes in current practices for when eyewitness identifications should be admitted at trial. These changes include the following: 1. If a pretrial identification was made at a procedure that included significant risk of contamination,347 the prosecutor should not be permitted to introduce evidence of it at trial,348 unless the use of that procedure was prompted by investigative necessity.349 2. A prosecutor should be precluded from offering evidence of a subsequent pretrial identification by the eyewitness whose memory has been contaminated at an earlier procedure, even if the later identification procedure was fair and nonsuggestive.350 3. Where significant risk of contamination occurred, the judge should preclude the eyewitness from making an incourt identification unless the prosecutor persuades the judge that the identification will be the product of the eyewitness’s memory of the crime, unaffected by the contamination.351 The Supreme Court has made it clear that the trial judge has a 346 See WEITEN, supra note 14, at 289–90. Perfection cannot be demanded or expected, but courts should insist that the police or prosecution avoid substantial bias or suggestiveness in their procedures. 348 Defense counsel should be permitted to introduce evidence of a pretrial identification procedure that had a significant risk of contamination to show how its suggestiveness tainted the eyewitness’s trial testimony. 349 Investigative necessity may arise, for example, during a street showup: shortly after the crime, the police apprehend someone nearby who fits the description the eyewitnesses gave of the perpetrator. In this situation, police need to know quickly whether to arrest the suspect, or release him with apologies and continue to search for the perpetrator. Such necessity may also arise where a key eyewitness is too ill to attend a lineup, and a hospital-room showup is necessary. See, e.g., Stovall v. Denno, 388 U.S. 293, 295 (1967) (noting that, to obtain an identification, the police arranged with the surgeon of a stabbing victim to bring the alleged assailant into the victim’s hospital room). The Supreme Court acknowledged that though the procedure was exceptionally suggestive, it was nonetheless justified by exigent circumstances, given concerns that the eyewitness-victim might die. Id. at 302. 350 Substantial research documents that once an eyewitness’s identification of a suspect has been contaminated, the damage cannot be repaired. See Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 582– 83; Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 845–47; see also supra Table 1, Step 2.B. Indeed, the Supreme Court acknowledged this in 1967. See United States v. Wade, 388 U.S. 218, 228–29 (1967). 351 For example, the prosecutor could argue that the viewing conditions were exceptionally good because the kidnapping victim had prolonged repeated exposure to the perpetrator or the eyewitness knew the perpetrator prior to the crime. See supra Table 1, Step 2.C. 347 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 507 constitutional duty to protect against convictions based on unreliable evidence.352 Given what is now known about the irreparability of contaminated identifications353 and the frequency with which erroneous convictions are based on contaminated identification testimony,354 a strong argument exists to preclude any eyewitness from giving identification testimony when a serious risk exists that contamination has occurred355—even if that contamination resulted from investigative necessity, rather than sloppy police work or reliance on discredited procedures. We decline to adopt that position for now. But courts must do more than pay lip service to their responsibility of vetting the reliability of eyewitness identifications. If a judge does permit an eyewitness to make an in-court identification after he or she has identified the defendant at a seriously flawed pretrial identification procedure, the judge should inform the jury of the risks involved in the eyewitness’s in-court testimony— either by permitting the defense to call an eyewitness expert,356 or by instructing the jury that they should be cautious about accepting an eyewitness’s in-court identification where there had been a seriously flawed pretrial identification,357 or both. Where a judge admits eyewitness identification testimony despite a pretrial identification process that was unnecessarily and significantly suggestive, such an instruction should 352 See discussion supra Part II.A.2. See supra note 348. 354 See Wade, 388 U.S. at 229 (“‘[T]he influence of improper suggestion upon identifying witnesses probably accounts for more miscarriages of justice than any other single factor—perhaps it is responsible for more such errors than all other factors combined.”). 355 See supra note 346 and accompanying text. 356 The current judicial skepticism or antagonism toward expert testimony on this subject is no longer justified. See supra Part II.D. Nevertheless, expert testimony is a problematic solution in many cases, first, because there are not enough experts to provide such testimony in every case where it would be relevant, and second, because many defendants would be unable to afford even a modest fee for the expert. Finally, eyewitness expert testimony in its current form frequently results in increasing juror skepticism rather than increasing juror sensitivity to the relevant eyewitness factors in a case. See Wise et. al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 840. Accordingly, the most potent means available to the criminal justice system to prevent eyewitness error is to conduct fair and unbiased eyewitness interviews and identification procedures. Id. at 865. 357 As a rule, the weight to be given to any eyewitness’s testimony is for the jury, not the judge, to decide. See, e.g., Chesapeake & Ohio Ry. Co. v. Martin, 283 U.S. 209, 216 (1931); Dunbar v. United States, 156 U.S. 185, 196 (1895); see also CLIFFORD S. FISHMAN, JONES ON EVIDENCE §§ 3:33 (civil cases), 5:15 (criminal cases) (7th ed. 1992); 1 JOHN WILLIAM STRONG ET AL., MCCORMICK ON EVIDENCE § 328 (West Publishing Co., 4th ed. 1992); 81 AM. JUR. 2D Witnesses § 995 (2004). In criminal cases, however, it is common for the judge to admonish a jury to view certain eyewitnesses’ testimony with particular caution. Many jurisdictions, for example, require a judge to give a cautionary instruction when an erstwhile accomplice testifies for the state against the defendant. See FISHMAN & MCKENNA, supra note 76, § 5:55. Similarly, some courts permit or require a judge to give a cautionary instruction if the eyewitness is a drug addict. 2 BARBARA E. BERGMAN & NANCY HOLLANDER, WHARTON’S CRIMINAL EVIDENCE § 9:9 (15th ed. 1998). The same is true if the witness is a young child. Id. § 7:16. 353 508 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 include an admonition that because an eyewitness’s memory and confidence are highly malleable, an eyewitness may not be able to accurately recall at trial (1) the quality of his or her view of the crime; (2) the amount of attention he or she was able to pay to the crime; (3) how much he or she remembers about the details of the perpetrator’s face; (4) his or her reason for selecting the suspect at the pretrial identification procedure; (5) how quickly or easily he or she identified the suspect at that procedure; (6) his or her degree of confidence in the accuracy of the identification when the identification was made; and (7) whether the lineup administrator influenced his or her selection of the suspect.358 X. CONCLUSION The method described in this Article provides judges and attorneys with a practical and comprehensive means of analyzing the accuracy of eyewitness testimony. Defense attorneys and prosecutors can also use this method when seeking either to bolster or attack the accuracy of eyewitness testimony at trial. Thus, prosecutors can use it to analyze eyewitness testimony in a case to determine the factors that likely increased the accuracy of the eyewitness testimony. For example, they can argue at trial that the eyewitness testimony in the case is likely to be accurate because proper procedures were followed in conducting the eyewitness interviews and identification procedures. In addition, the prosecutor can point out to the trier of fact the eyewitness factors during the crime, such as good lighting, the absence of a disguise, and the long time the eyewitness had to observe the perpetrator, that support the likely accuracy of the eyewitness’s testimony. This method also provides defense attorneys with a method for systematically and comprehensively analyzing the weaknesses of the State’s eyewitness evidence. Thus, a defense attorney can specify the factors that made the eyewitness interview and identification procedures unfair and biased and the eyewitness factors present during the crime that probably decreased the eyewitness’s accuracy, such as a weapon, a disguise, and a high level of stress. In addition, this method, by emphasizing the importance of conducting fair and unbiased eyewitness interviews and identification procedures, exerts pressure on the legal system to take steps to improve the fairness of 358 For studies documenting these difficulties, see Wells & Bradfield, supra note 118, at 374; Wise et. al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 869. Lawyers frequently question whether juries are able to understand or follow cautionary or limiting instructions, and experience may prove that they are little help in the eyewitness identification context, but use of such instructions is an experiment worth trying—particularly where the alternatives are either categorical exclusion of a particular eyewitness’s identification testimony, on the one hand, or acquiescence in the high percentage of wrongful convictions based on erroneous eyewitness identification testimony, on the other. 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 509 interviews and identification procedures. Because improving the fairness of eyewitness interviews and identification procedures is the most potent means available to the legal system to prevent eyewitness error, this method can encourage changes in interviews and identification procedures that will significantly reduce eyewitness error.359 This method is also congruent with evidentiary rules that provide that trace evidence is admissible at trial only if the State followed proper scientific procedures in collecting the evidence.360 Using this method for analyzing the accuracy of eyewitness testimony is not limited to attorneys and judges. Law enforcement officers and jurors can also use it to assess the likely accuracy of eyewitness testimony. Moreover, jurors’ use of this method may not only produce more accurate assessments of eyewitness testimony, but it may also reduce the need for eyewitness expert testimony in criminal cases and, when used in conjunction with expert testimony, may enhance its effectiveness.361 In applying the guidelines in this Article, it is important to remember that researchers are continually making new discoveries about the causes and remedies for eyewitness error. Accordingly, the guidelines and eyewitness factors delineated in this Article will undoubtedly have to be modified in the future to accommodate new research findings. For example, some research has shown that certain factors, such as how quickly an eyewitness makes an identification and the manner in which an eyewitness identifies a suspect, may be useful indicators of eyewitness accuracy.362 If additional research confirms the usefulness of these or other 359 Wise et al., Tripartite Solution, supra note 19, at 865. FED. R. EVID. 403, 702, 901. See Penrod & Cutler, supra note 169, at 114–15. As Cutler and Penrod stated, even experts have difficulty applying their knowledge to the facts of a case. Id. The method discussed in this Article would give jurors a means for applying the relevant eyewitness factors discussed by an eyewitness expert to the facts of a criminal case. Therefore, it might improve the effectiveness of expert testimony in helping jurors to assess eyewitness accuracy. 362 Caputo & Dunning, supra note 337, at 435–36. For example, Caputo and Dunning point out that some researchers have found that eyewitnesses who make an identification of a suspect between ten and twelve seconds after being exposed to a lineup tend to be more accurate than eyewitnesses who take longer to make an identification. Id. at 436–37. There is, however, as they point out, other research that has not supported this conclusion. Id. at 437. “More recent research . . . has shown that the 10–12 second rule is not stable across variations in witnessing and lineup conditions.” Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 67. “Weber et al. found that maximally discriminating time ranged from 5 seconds to 29 seconds across variations in conditions. Furthermore, eyewitnesses who responded faster than the optimal time boundaries did not show particularly high probabilities of being accurate . . . .” Id. at 67–68 (citations omitted). Research has also indicated that eyewitnesses tend to be more accurate when their identifications are “automatic and absolute” rather than “conscious, effortful, and relative.” Caputo & Dunning, supra note 337, at 434. Identifications are automatic when an eyewitness makes the identification without any conscious effort. Id. “Absolute” means that the eyewitness made the identification because the suspect matched their memory of the perpetrator of the crime rather than choosing the suspect because he or she most closely resembles the perpetrator. Wells et al., From the Lab, supra note 15, at 585–86. As Caputo and Dunning point out, however, the determination of the manner in which an eyewitness makes an identification can be difficult to accurately assess because self-reports of the method used to make an identification are frequently 360 361 510 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 post-dictors in a wide array of eyewitness conditions, they can be incorporated into the present method for analyzing eyewitness accuracy.363 The method discussed in this Article also suggests that there needs to be a paradigm shift in the thinking of law enforcement and prosecutors about eyewitness testimony. Law enforcement frequently conducts eyewitness interviews and identification procedures in a manner that unintentionally contaminates the eyewitness’s memory of the crime and impairs the eyewitness’s ability to identify the perpetrator of the crime. In addition, eyewitnesses often observe crimes under poor eyewitness conditions.364 Because of these limitations in many criminal cases, this method indicates that the State needs to minimize the number of criminal cases that it brings where the sole or primary evidence of the defendant’s guilt is eyewitness testimony. Furthermore, in criminal cases that rely heavily on eyewitness testimony for proof of the defendant’s guilt, the State needs to be especially careful that its eyewitness interviews and identification procedures are fair and unbiased and that the eyewitness conditions during the crime were conducive to an accurate identification. This method also suggests that law enforcement and prosecutors need to pay more attention to instances where an eyewitness either misidentifies a filler in a lineup as the perpetrator or determines that the perpetrator is not in the lineup. Such misidentifications and non-identifications frequently provide useful information that should cause law enforcement and prosecutors to consider the possibility that the suspect is innocent rather than elicit a reflexive response that the eyewitness made an error.365 inaccurate. “It has long been known that people are notoriously unskilled at accurately describing how they reach their decisions. In the eyewitness context, researchers have observed participants comparing photographs, only to be told by participants later that no comparison had occurred.” Caputo & Dunning, supra note 337, at 436 (citations omitted); Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 68. Overall, it appears that postdiction has not been highly successful for eyewitness identification . . . . This underscores the primary message of the system-variable approach—namely, that it would be better to use procedures that help prevent mistaken identifications from occurring in the first place than to try to detect errors after the fact. Id. This is another reason why the present method for assessing eyewitness accuracy discussed in this Article emphasizes the importance of law enforcement conducting fair and unbiased eyewitness interviews and identification procedures. 363 If additional empirical research establishes that these or other postdictors are useful and practical indicators of eyewitness accuracy, they could be incorporated into the current method by evaluating them after the fairness of the eyewitness interview and identification procedures are examined and before assessing the eyewitness factors during the crime that may have affected identification accuracy. 364 See Wells et al., Eyewitness Evidence, supra note 13, at 45 (“Many of the experiments conducted in the late 1970s and throughout the 1980s resulted in articles by psychologists . . . [explaining that] the validity of eyewitness reports depends a great deal on the procedures that are used to obtain those reports and that the legal system was not using the best procedures.”). 365 See Caputo & Dunning, supra note 337, at 438 (“Depending on the circumstances . . . positive identification of [an irrelevant] distractor [in a lineup might actually be worthwhile] evidence that the suspect is innocent.”); see also Steve Charman & Gary L. Wells, Applied Lineup Theory, in 2 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY 511 The most egregious error any legal system can make is to convict an innocent defendant. Moreover, a wrongful conviction is not just a tragedy for the innocent defendant and his or her family, but also for the victims of crimes that occur because the true perpetrator of a crime was never brought to justice. Wrongful convictions also undermine the credibility of a legal system, especially when it fails to implement safeguards that could help prevent them.366 By using the method described in this Article for analyzing the accuracy of eyewitness testimony, judges and attorneys can take a major step in reducing the number of wrongful convictions from eyewitness error. HANDBOOK OF EYEWITNESS PSYCHOLOGY: MEMORY FOR PEOPLE 219 (Rod C. L. Lindsay et al. eds., 2006). “For example, it is quite possible that criminal investigators too readily dismiss nonidentifications for their exonerating qualities while readily accepting identifications of the suspect for their incriminating qualities.” Id. at 220–21. “When properly designed and interpreted, a lineup procedure has not only incriminating powers, but exonerating powers as well. In fact, there is clear proof using mathematical formulations that any lineup that has incriminating value from the identification of the suspect must also have exonerating value from a nonidentification.” Id. at 222. 366 As Risinger explains: When the wrongful conviction is the product of an official inquiry by a court even in a petty criminal or quasi-criminal context, it not only imposes pain that has a moral claim to our recognition, but it is also seriously corrosive to the respect for law of the wronged individuals, and that of all those around them who believe the convicted were in fact innocent. Risinger, supra note 11, at 789. 512 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:435 APPENDIX FORM FOR EVALUATING THE ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY I. EYEWITNESS INTERVIEW (Evaluate separately each interview of an eyewitness.) A. Factors that Indicate the Interview Was Complete, Fair, and Did Not Increase Eyewitness Confidence 1. List Factors that Indicate the Interview Obtained the Maximum Amount of Information from the Eyewitness 2. List Factors that Indicate the Interview Was Fair and Did Not Contaminate the Eyewitness’s Memory of the Crime 3. List Factors that Indicate the Interview Did Not Increase Eyewitness Confidence B. Factors that Indicate the Interview Was Incomplete, Biased, and Increased the Eyewitness’s Confidence 1. List Factors that Indicate the Interview Did Not Obtain the Maximum Amount of Information from the Eyewitness 2. List Factors that Indicate the Interview Was Biased and Contaminated the Eyewitness’s Memory of the Crime 3. List Factors that Indicate the Interview Increased the Eyewitness’s Confidence II. IDENTIFICATION PROCEDURES (Conduct a separate analysis for each identification procedure.) A. List Factors that Indicate the Identification Procedure Was Fair and Impartial B. List Factors that Indicate the Identification Procedure Was Biased 2009] ACCURACY OF EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY C. If the interviews and identification procedures were substantially fair and unbiased or an exception applies (e.g., the eyewitness knew the perpetrator prior to the crime or had prolonged, repeated exposure to the perpetrator, or there is reliable, valid corroborating evidence of the accuracy of the eyewitness testimony), go on to Part III. If an interview or an identification procedure was significantly unfair and biased, and no exception applies, the eyewitness testimony or any subsequent identification of the defendant by the eyewitness has no probative value and should not be considered in the determination of the defendant’s guilt. III. EYEWITNESS FACTORS DURING THE CRIME THAT LIKELY AFFECTED IDENTIFICATION ACCURACY A. List Eyewitness Factors During the Crime that Likely Increased Eyewitness Accuracy B. List Eyewitness Factors During the Crime that Likely Decreased Eyewitness Accuracy IV. CONCLUSIONS A. Was the maximum amount of information obtained from the eyewitness during the interviews? 1. Yes 2. No B. Was a statement of the eyewitness’s confidence in the accuracy of the identification obtained prior to any feedback? 1. Yes 2. No C. Is there a high, medium, or low probability that the eyewitness testimony was accurate? 1. High 2. Medium 3. Low D. Is there a high, medium, or low probability that the eyewitness identification was accurate? 1. High 2. Medium 3. Low 513 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW VOLUME 42 DECEMBER 2009 NUMBER 2 Article Pretend “Gun-Free” School Zones: A Deadly Legal Fiction DAVID B. KOPEL Most states issue permits to carry a concealed handgun for lawful protection to an applicant who is over twenty-one years of age, and who passes a fingerprint-based background check and a safety class. These permits allow the person to carry a concealed defensive handgun almost everywhere in the state. Should professors, school teachers, or adult college and graduate students who have such permits be allowed to carry firearms on campus? In the last two years, many state legislatures have debated this topic. School boards, regents, and administrators are likewise faced with decisions about whether to change campus firearms policies. This Article is the first to provide a thorough analysis of the empirical evidence and policy arguments regarding licensed campus carry. Whether a reader agrees or disagrees with the Article’s policy recommendations, the Article can lay the foundation for a better-informed debate, and a more realistic analysis of the issue. 515 ARTICLE CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................... 517 II. THE LEGAL AND FACTUAL SETTING ............................................ 518 A. WHAT DOES THE CONSTITUTION REQUIRE? ....................................... 521 B. THE PUSH FOR CARRY RIGHTS ON CAMPUSES .................................... 522 III. REAL-WORLD PROGRAMS .............................................................. 525 A. B. C. D. SCHOOLS IN THE UNITED STATES ....................................................... 527 ISRAEL ................................................................................................ 531 THAILAND ........................................................................................... 533 NORWAY ............................................................................................. 535 IV. EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE OF DEFENSE AND DETERRENCE ....... 536 A. DETERRENCE ...................................................................................... 536 B. NEED FOR SPEED IN RESPONDING TO ACTIVE SHOOTERS.................... 540 C. WHEN HAVE CITIZENS STOPPED MASS KILLERS AT SCHOOLS? .......... 544 V. OBJECTIONS TO CAMPUS DEFENSE .............................................. 546 A. B. C. D. CAMPUS CARRY IS UNNECESSARY ..................................................... 546 SELF-DEFENSE WILL FAIL .................................................................. 553 FACULTY AND ADULT STUDENTS ARE INCIPIENT KILLERS ................. 564 ACADEMIC FREEDOM.......................................................................... 581 VI. CONCLUSION ..................................................................................... 583 Pretend “Gun-Free” School Zones: A Deadly Legal Fiction DAVID B. KOPEL* I. INTRODUCTION This Article analyzes the law and policy regarding the licensed carrying of firearms in K–12 schools and in colleges and universities. The Article suggests that absolute bans have proven to be extremely dangerous because they turn schools into uniquely attractive targets for mass murderers. The Article focuses on prohibitions applied to people who have already been licensed to carry a handgun for lawful protection in public places. The Article does not address the bans as applied to persons who have not obtained or could not obtain such a permit—such as those under the age of twenty-one—in most states. Part II of this Article surveys the legal, factual, and political background. Part III describes current programs, in the United States and elsewhere, in which teachers or students are allowed or required to carry firearms for defense. Part IV examines empirical evidence about whether armed defenders can deter or interrupt mass killers at schools, and whether armed defenders have done so. Part V analyzes various objections to campus defense, with particular attention to the argument that faculty and/or adult students are so dangerous that they should not be allowed to carry arms. Part V also addresses the issue of unarmed victims being told never to fight back. This Article does not argue in favor of one particular method for authorizing already-licensed people to carry firearms on campus. On the one hand there is Utah’s law, which allows firearms carrying and possession by anyone with a concealed handgun carry permit—including in dormitories for students aged twenty-one or over.1 On the other hand, there was the Nevada Board of Regents proposal to allow carry only by full-time staff who have undergone the same training as deputy sheriffs, * David Kopel is Adjunct Professor of Advanced Constitutional Law at Denver University Sturm College of Law, Research Director of the Independence Institute in Golden, Colorado, and Associate Policy Analyst with the Cato Institute in Washington, D.C. He has also served as an Assistant Attorney General for the State of Colorado and an Adjunct Professor of Law at New York University School of Law. He received his B.A. with highest honors from Brown University, and his J.D., magna cum laude, from the University of Michigan Law School. He is the author or co-author of twelve books, including the only law school textbook on firearms law and policy, Gun Control and Gun Rights, published by NYU Press. The author would like to thank Nicholas Johnson, Don & Che Kates, Henry Schaffer, and Eugene Volokh for helpful suggestions. 1 See infra note 76 and accompanying text. 518 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 2 and who have actually been deputized. There are many options in between the Utah and Nevada models. This Article suggests that complete prohibition of armed defense on school campuses by all faculty and by all adult students is irrational and deadly. II. THE LEGAL AND FACTUAL SETTING During most of America’s history, there were no particular restrictions on the possession of firearms on school property. It was not uncommon for students to bring guns to school, stored in their lockers or automobiles, to use for hunting or target shooting after school.3 When Antonin Scalia was growing up in New York City in the 1950s, he would carry a rifle on the subway on his way to school, for use as a member of his school’s rifle team.4 However, in recent decades, many legislatures and school administrators have banned the possession of firearms on school property. All of the state laws apply to K–12 public schools, and almost all of them also apply to K–12 private schools. Some of the laws also apply to public institutions of higher education, and a few even apply to private higher education. Almost all of the laws allow gun possession pursuant to authorization from the governing body of the school or, depending on the state, from a school principal or other administrator. Accordingly, in almost all states, school officials could—and this Article suggests should—allow some on-campus carrying of firearms by properly trained and licensed persons. In addition, legislatures, regents, and school boards have the authority to set broad policies for public education institutions, and this Article advocates that those policies should authorize on-campus carry by at least some people who are already authorized under state law to carry in public. In the public debate over campus carry, a frequently-mentioned but mostly irrelevant law is the federal Gun-Free School Zone Act (“GFSZA”). The law, enacted in 1990, sharply restricted guns at K–12 2 See infra text accompanying notes 67–69. See, e.g., John Lane, Permit Guns in School to Stop Massacres, CHARLOTTE OBSERVER, Jan. 22, 2008, http://web.archive.org/web/20080127100554/http://www.charlotte.com/171/story/456971.html. Lane observes: I grew up in the 1940s and 1950s. . . . [F]or one “show and tell” I brought to school a Walther PPK pistol . . . . Later, when we were older, it was not uncommon for several of us to have shotguns in our vehicles while at school. Usually they were there because we had been in the woods at sun-up hunting. We didn’t have time to take them home before school, so we left them in our trunks. . . . In researching this column, I attempted to find a “school shooting” from that era. I came up empty. Id. 4 See Associated Press, Scalia Says Don’t Link Guns Only to Crime, SEATTLE TIMES, Feb. 27, 2006, http://community.seattletimes.nwsource.com/archive/?date=20060227&slug=scalia27 (reporting Scalia’s speech to an annual meeting of the National Wild Turkey Federation). 3 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 519 5 schools and within a one thousand-foot radius around the schools. In the 1995 case United States v. Lopez, the U.S. Supreme Court found the GFSZA unconstitutional because it was based on Congress’s power to regulate interstate commerce, but the regulated activity had no meaningful connection to interstate commerce.6 In 1996, Congress re-enacted the law, this time limiting its application to guns which at some point after their manufacture had been moved in interstate commerce7—that is, virtually all guns. The federal law contains several exceptions. For example, the ban within the one thousand-foot radius does not apply on private property.8 Even on the property of a private K–12 school, carrying is allowed under federal law if the carrier has a state-issued handgun carry permit.9 Critics of the GFSZA point out that before the 1990 law, there had been only seven shootings at American schools in the previous 214-year history of the United States. In the seventeen years following the adoption of the GFSZA, there were seventy-eight such incidents.10 However, it seems unlikely that the GFSZA itself dramatically changed lawful firearms possession at schools. By the time it was enacted, many states and school districts had already imposed their own bans, so the federal ban was superfluous. Along with gun bans at schools, another type of gun law was enacted in many states in the 1980s and 1990s: objective standards for the issuance of permits to carry handguns for lawful protection (referred to as “Shall Issue” laws).11 The first state to enact an objective licensing law was Washington in 1961.12 The trend became national after Florida adopted a similar law in 1988.13 Today, in forty states, an adult who passes a fingerprint-based background check and, in most states, a safety class can obtain a permit to carry a handgun for lawful protection. In those forty states, a permit cannot be denied simply because the official in charge of issuing the permits does not think that people should be allowed to carry 5 18 U.S.C. §§ 921(a)(25), 922(q) (2008) (defining “school zone” and restricting guns in school zones). 6 United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549, 551 (1994); see David B. Kopel & Glenn H. Reynolds, Taking Federalism Seriously: Lopez and the Partial Birth Abortion Ban Act, 30 CONN. L. REV. 59, 68– 70 (1997) (analyzing the interstate Commerce Clause issues raised by Lopez). 7 18 U.S.C. § 922(q)(1)(B)–(C), (G), (I), (2)(A), (3)(A) (2008) (containing new language restricting law’s application to a person with a “firearm that has moved in or that otherwise affects interstate or foreign commerce”). 8 Id. § 922(q)(2)(B)(i). 9 Id. § 922(q)(2)(B)(ii). 10 Disarmed in “Gun-Free School Zone,” HARD CORPS REP., Sept./Oct. 2007, at 4. 11 See Clayton E. Cramer & David B. Kopel, “Shall Issue”: The New Wave of Concealed Handgun Permit Laws, 62 TENN. L. REV. 679, 742 (1995); David B. Kopel, The Licensing of Concealed Handguns for Lawful Protection: Support from Five State Supreme Courts, 68 ALB. L. REV. 305, 334–35 (2005). 12 See WASH. REV. CODE ANN. § 9.41.070(1)–(4) (West 2006). 13 See FLA. STAT. ANN. § 790.06(1)–(3) (West 2007). 520 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 14 guns for lawful self-defense. In contrast to the forty “Shall Issue” states with objective standards for license issuance, there are eight states where the issuing authorities have unlimited discretion.15 In some of these eight states (e.g., California and New York), permit issuance varies widely from county to county.16 In other such states (e.g., New Jersey), it is essentially impossible for anyone except a retired police officer to obtain a permit.17 In Illinois and Wisconsin, there are no permits issued for gun carrying; carrying is lawful without a permit when engaged in certain activities (e.g., hunting),18 in certain places (e.g., in one’s domicile),19 or for persons of a certain legal status (e.g., security guards and detectives).20 In each of the forty-eight states that issue permits to carry handguns for protection, one may presume that the permit is valid throughout the state. Most states list at least a few places, such as courthouses, where the permits are not valid. In some states, K–12 schools are specifically excluded from the right to carry, and some states also exclude colleges and 14 Thirty-five states follow the standard “Shall Issue” model. In Alaska and Vermont, a permit is not necessary, but a person may still apply for a permit (since having a permit issued by one state allows for carrying in other states which have reciprocal recognition of licenses issues by some other states). Alabama, Connecticut, and Iowa have statutes which nominally give greater discretion to the issuing authority; in practice, in these “Do Issue” states, almost all adults (Alabama, Connecticut) or most adults (Iowa) who would qualify for a “Shall Issue” permit are issued the slightly discretionary permits. See Posting of David Kopel to The Volokh Conspiracy, http://volokh.com/archives/archive_ 2006_03_26-2006_04_01.shtml#1143873304 (Apr. 1, 2006, 12:35 EST). 15 These states are California, Delaware, Hawaii, Maryland, Massachusetts, New Jersey, New York, and Rhode Island. See N.J. STAT. ANN. § 2C: 58-4 (West 2005); Cramer & Kopel, supra note 11, at 684; Kopel, supra note 11, at 305. The situation in Rhode Island is somewhat more complicated, with the state having two separate licensing statutes, one discretionary and one mandatory—but the latter one has been effectively nullified by the Rhode Island Attorney General. Kopel, supra note 11, at 325–26. 16 See Cramer & Kopel, supra note 11, at 683–85 (discussing “haphazard” issuance standards in California and New York); see also Blog O’Stuff, http://blogostuff.blogspot.com/2004/12/percentageof-adults-with-carry.html (Dec. 21, 2004, 09:29 EST) (providing state statistics related to adults with licenses to carry). 17 See In re Preis, 573 A.2d 148 (N.J. 1990) (denying permits to former police officers who were working for private detective agencies on behalf of a tugboat company during a violent labor conflict: Someone had already fired a bullet through a tugboat window. Permits denied because “a need to protect property alone” is not a “justifiable need” for carrying a handgun.); Siccardi v. State, 284 A.2d 533, 538 (N.J. 1971); Doe v. Township of Dover, 524 A.2d 469, 471 (N.J. Super. Ct. App. Div. 1987) (denying a permit for a jeweler who had to carry diamonds in an area where other jewelers had been robbed); EVAN P. NAPPEN, NAPPEN II: NEW JERSEY GUN, KNIFE & WEAPON LAW 84 (2000); John C. Lenzen, Note, Liberalizing the Concealed Carry of Handguns by Qualified Civilians: The Case for “Carry Reform,” 47 RUTGERS L. REV. 1503, 1516–17 (1995). 18 720 ILL. COMP. STAT. ANN. § 5/24-2(b) (West 2003). 19 Id. § 5/24-1(a)(4); see also WIS. STAT. ANN. § 941.23 (West 2005); Kopel, supra note 11, at 323–24 (discussing a Wisconsin Supreme Court ruling that concealed carry ban could not constitutionally be applied in a person’s home or place of business because of state constitutional right to keep and bear arms). 20 720 ILL. COMP. STAT. ANN. § 5/24-2(a) (West 2003). 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 521 21 universities. In other states, there may not be a specific statutory exclusion, but school boards or higher education administrators have imposed their own bans. Thus, in forty-eight states, it has been agreed that there is some category of adults who can be trusted to be responsible about carrying a concealed handgun for lawful protection in almost all public places. This Article does not argue for or against these laws, but takes them as a given. Rather, the Article focuses on a particular question: Once society has concluded that it is not harmful and may be beneficial for some people to be licensed to carry handguns for protection, does it make sense to carve out educational institutions as special “no-carry” zones, or is such a policy harmful? The argument is most relevant in the forty “Shall Issue” states, where public policy has already determined that the vast majority of adults should be authorized to carry almost everywhere in public—provided that they pass a safety class and a fingerprint-based background check. Because this Article focuses on educational institutions, it is important to note that in the large majority of “Shall Issue” states the minimum age for being able to apply for a permit is twenty-one. There are six “Shall Issue” states in which the minimum age is eighteen.22 A. What Does the Constitution Require? In 2008, the Supreme Court ruled that the District of Columbia’s handgun ban violated the Second Amendment.23 Whether the Second Amendment is incorporated into the Fourteenth Amendment, and therefore binds state and local governments, remains to be resolved. Even without incorporation, the issue of Second Amendment rights in schools is relevant to schools in the District of Columbia and other federal property and territories where the Bill of Rights directly applies. The school issue was directly addressed in District of Columbia v. Heller: “[N]othing in our opinion should be taken to cast doubt on longstanding prohibitions on the possession of firearms by felons and the mentally ill, or laws forbidding the carrying of firearms in sensitive places such as schools and government buildings . . . .”24 At oral argument, 21 E.g., CONN. GEN. STAT. § 53a-217b (2009) (providing for a general ban on guns at K–12 schools, with no exception for licensed carry); FLA. STAT. § 790.06(12) (2006) (stating that handgun carry permits are not valid on college and university property). 22 See IND. CODE ANN. § 35-47-2-3(g)(2) (West 2004); ME. REV. STAT. ANN. tit. 25, § 2003(1)(A) (2007); MONT. CODE ANN. § 48-8-321(1) (2007); N.D. CENT. CODE § 62.1-02-01(1)(d) (Supp. 2009); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS § 23-7-7.1(1) (Supp. 2009). New Hampshire’s statute does not list a minimum age for licensed carry. N.H. REV. STAT. ANN. § 159:6 (2009). However, the state does prohibit the sale of firearms to minors. Id. § 159:12. A number of states allow open carry at age eighteen, without need for a permit, but they are irrelevant to this Article, which focuses on concealed carry licensees. 23 District of Columbia v. Heller, 128 S. Ct. 2783, 2821–22 (2008). 24 Id. at 2816–17. 522 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 Justice Stevens asked if the Second Amendment would allow guns to be banned in college dormitories; Alan Gura, the lawyer arguing against the D.C. handgun ban, affirmed that a dormitory ban would possibly be constitutional.25 It would not make sense to read the Supreme Court’s dicta as if it were a statute. There might be some circumstances in which a gun ban for a school would obviously be unconstitutional—such as a ban on guns at specialized private institutions that teach defensive gun use or that teach hunting skills. For the purposes of this Article, it will be assumed that (1) the Second Amendment does not generally constrain policy makers’ choices regarding firearms at most schools, and (2) the forty-four state constitutional rights to arms also impose no constraints on policy choices.26 B. The Push for Carry Rights on Campuses The night after the massacre of thirty-five unarmed students and teachers at Virginia Tech University in April 2007, an activist organization called Students for Concealed Carry on Campus (“SCCC”) was formed.27 The group has grown very rapidly. As of September 2009, it had over 35,000 supporters on its Facebook page, plus more than 350 chapters at colleges and universities.28 There are approximately 300 additional campuses where the group has members but not an established chapter.29 SCCC has attracted significant media attention, including an interview on ABC’s Good Morning America,30 and an article in Newsweek.31 The group holds annual “empty holster” protests, in which students wear empty holsters on campus in order to protest the campus gun bans. In November 2007, there were 110 such protests nationwide.32 25 See Transcript of Oral Argument at 76–77, Heller, 128 S. Ct. 2783 (No. 07-290). The author was one of three attorneys joining Gura at the Supreme Court counsel table for the presentation of the oral argument. 26 For the text of these state constitutional right to bear arms provisions, see David B. Kopel, What State Constitutions Teach About the Second Amendment, 29 N. KY. L. REV. 827, 829–50 (2002). 27 Students for Concealed Carry on Campus Frequently Asked Questions, http://www.concealed campus.org/faq.php (follow “How was the SCCC started” hyperlink) (last visited Sept. 8, 2009). 28 Id. 29 Kimberly Miller, Guns on Campus? FAU Students Push for Advocacy Group, PALM BEACH POST, Aug. 15, 2008, at 1A. 30 Good Morning America: Right to Bear Arms? Do Guns Belong on Campus? (ABC Television Broadcast, Feb. 16, 2008), available at http://abcnews.go.com/video/playerIndex?id=4300805. 31 Ben Whitford, Armed for Class, NEWSWEEK, Aug. 11, 2008, at 62. 32 See, e.g., Eric Ferreri, Holster-Packin’ Students Protest, NEWS & OBSERVER (Raleigh, N.C.), Apr. 25, 2008 (describing a protest at UNC-Chapel Hill); Steve Fry, Students Armed with Words in Guns-on-Campus Protest, TOPEKA CAPITAL-JOURNAL, Apr. 24, 2008, at 1A (describing a protest at Washburn University and three other Kansas colleges); Adriana Garza, Holsters on Campus Put Gun Topic on Forefront, CORPUS CHRISTI CALLER TIMES, Apr. 25, 2008, at 1 (describing the protest at Texas A&M); Michelle Roberts, Members of Student Group Push for the Right to Carry Concealed Weapons on College Campuses, ASSOCIATED PRESS FIN. WIRE, Nov. 21, 2007 (describing the widespread nature of protests); College ‘Empty Holster Protest’ Hits Campuses, Draws Attention, GUN WEEK, Nov. 15, 2007, at 4; Some UW Students Want to Carry Guns, SEATTLE POST-INTELLIGENCER, 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 523 SCCC has played an unusual role in the national gun control debate. Usually, the public campaigns to change gun control laws are initiated by professional “pro-gun” organizations (such as the National Rifle Association or Gun Owners of America) or professional “anti-gun” organizations (such as the Brady Campaign or the Violence Policy Center). The campus carry issue is different in that it has been brought into the public debate by a spontaneously self-organized, amateur group of citizen activists. The professional pro/anti-gun lobbies have found themselves playing catch-up. In 2007, bills to authorize licensed carry at state institutions of higher education or in public schools were introduced in Alabama,33 Michigan,34 Nevada,35 Ohio,36 South Carolina,37 and Washington.38 In 2008, bills were introduced in Alabama,39 Arizona,40 Georgia,41 Idaho,42 Indiana,43 Kentucky,44 Louisiana,45 Ohio,46 Oklahoma,47 South Dakota,48 Tennessee,49 Apr. 24, 2008, http://seattletimes.nwsource.com/html/localnews/2004370761_apwacampusguns. html?syndication=rss (describing a protest at the University of Washington). 33 Pauline Vu, Va. Tech Shooting Spurs Changes at Colleges, STATELINE.ORG, Sept. 6, 2007, http://www.stateline.org/live/details/story?contentId=237774. 34 Id. 35 See infra text accompanying notes 67–69. 36 Vu, supra note 33. 37 Id. 38 See S.B. 6860, 2007 Leg., 60th Reg. Sess. (Wash. 2007) (prohibiting municipal bodies like public colleges from adopting campus bans). 39 S.B. 18, 2008 S., Reg. Sess. (Ala. 2008) (applying to universities, for students in ROTC with no misdemeanor or felony convictions); S.B. 27, 2008 S., Reg. Sess. (Ala. 2008) (applying to professors only); S.B. 271, 2008 S., Reg. Sess. (Ala. 2008) (applying to professors only). 40 S.B. 1214, 48th Leg., 2d Reg. Sess. (Ariz. 2008); H.B. 2628, 48th Leg., 2d Reg. Sess. (Ariz. 2008) (repealing law against licensed carry on school grounds). 41 H.B. 915, 149th Gen. Assem., Reg. Sess. (Ga. 2008). 42 S.B. 1381, 59th Leg., 2d Reg. Sess. (Idaho 2008) (sponsored by Senator Curt McKenzie). 43 S.B. 12, 116th Gen. Assem., 1st Reg. Sess. (Ind. 2008). 44 H.B. 114, 2008 H.R., Reg Sess. (Ky. 2008) (applying to parking lots for university employees). 45 H.B. 199, 2008 H.R., Reg. Sess. (La. 2008) (allowing universities to establish policies for authorizing licensed carry, while affirming that universities can regulate storage of guns on campus). The bill passed the House Criminal Justice Committee 11-3. Editorial, Tote Books, Not Guns, TIMESPICAYUNE, May 3, 2008, at 6. It was pulled from the House floor after Rep. Ernest Wooton estimated that he would have only forty-six of the necessary fifty-three votes to pass the bill through the 105 member chamber. Ed Anderson, Campus Weapons Proposal Pulled; Sponsor Says He’ll Keep Pushing Plan, TIMES-PICAYUNE, June 10, 2008, at 2. 46 S.B. 318, 127th Gen. Assem., Reg. Sess. (Ohio 2008). 47 H.B. 2513, 51st Leg., 2d Sess. (Okla. 2008). The bill would allow people with a law enforcement or military background over age twenty-one to carry on public college campuses. The bill passed the House 65-36, but stalled in the Senate. Mick Hinton & Barbara Hoberock, Senate Holsters Gun Bill, TULSA WORLD, Apr. 1, 2008, at A1. 48 H.B. 1261, 83rd Leg. Assem., Reg. Sess. (S.D. 2008). The bill to allow licensed carry on state university campuses passed the House of Representatives by a 63-3 vote, but was defeated in the Senate 14-17. Michele Linck, No Guns on South Dakota Campuses, for Now, SIOUX CITY J., Feb. 16, 2008, http://www.siouxcityjournal.com/articles/2008/02/16/news/local/660b198e85dff68a862573f100 16cba7.txt. 49 H.B. 3014, 105th Gen. Assem., 2d Sess. (Tenn. 2008) (allowing full-time faculty or staff at schools and universities to carry pursuant to a permit). 524 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW 50 [Vol. 42:515 51 Virginia, and Washington. In 2009, bills were introduced in Indiana,52 Louisiana,53 Michigan,54 Texas (with over seventy cosponsors),55 South Carolina,56 South Dakota,57 and North Dakota.58 In many states, the bills have been passed out of committee, and in some states they have passed in one chamber, but defeated in the other. Conversely, some states have seen the introduction of bills to ban guns on college campuses, or in student apartments, and those bills have also been defeated.59 In 2009, the Arizona legislature enacted a law to forbid employers from prohibiting employee guns in locked cars in parking areas.60 Accordingly, the regents of Arizona’s public colleges and universities changed their campus regulations to permit such guns.61 To avoid conflict with state law, Michigan State University’s governing board has authorized persons with concealed carry licenses to carry guns while walking or driving through campus, but not to bring the guns into buildings or stadiums.62 Texas Governor Rick Perry has endorsed college students and public 50 H.B. 1371, 2008 H.R., 2008 Sess. (Va. 2008) (applying to faculty and adult students); H.B. 424, 2008 H.R., 2008 Sess. (Va. 2008) (applying to full-time faculty). Delegate Robert Marshall, whose two sons attend George Mason University, said that he introduced the bill after a George Mason police officer contacted him with concerns that the campus police could not fully defend the school. Dorn Peterson, a physics professor at James Madison University, favored the bill. Pete DeLea, Should Profs Pack Pistols?, DAILY-NEWS REC. (Harrisonburg, Va.), Jan. 17, 2008. 51 S.B. 6860, 2008 S., 2d Sess. of the 60th Reg. Sess. (Wash. 2008). 52 S.B. 12, 116th Gen. Assem., 1st Reg. Sess. (Ind. 2009). 53 H.B. 27, 2009 H.R., Reg. Sess. (La. 2009). 54 S.B. 747, 95th Leg., 1st Reg. Sess. (Mich. 2009). 55 H.B. 1893, 81st Leg. (Tex. 2009). For the list of sponsors and cosponsors, see Texas Legislature Online, 81(R) Authors for H.B. 1893, http://www.legis.state.tx.us/billlookup/Authors.aspx? LegSess=81R&Bill=HB1893 (last visited Oct. 3, 2009). 56 S.B. 347, 118th Gen. Assem., 1st Reg. Sess. (S.C. 2009). 57 S.B. 82, 84th Leg. Assem., 2009 Reg. Sess. (S.D. 2009). 58 H.B. 1348, 61st Leg. Assem. (N.D. 2009). The bill would allow gun possession in campus apartments (but not dormitories) and their associated parking lots by persons who have been issued a concealed carry permit, or who have passed a hunter safety class. It passed the North Dakota House of Representatives by a 48-46 vote. Janell Cole, N.D. House Narrowly Passes Campus Gun Bill, GRAND FORKS HERALD, Feb. 19, 2009, http://www.grandforksherald.com/event/contentEmail/id/107174/type/ article/. The bill was defeated in the Senate. See Journal of the Senate of North Dakota for 2009, at 1238. 59 See S.B. 6841, 2008 S., 2d Sess. of the 60th Reg. Sess. (Wash. 2008) (banning carry on college campuses, including private ones); Jordan Blum, Bill Would Allow Guns on College Campus, ADVOCATE (Baton Rouge, La.), Mar. 29, 2008, at A1 (explaining that Louisiana colleges ban guns in dormitories as a matter of policy, and that violating the rule could get a student expelled, but that such storage is not a crime; a bill to criminalize dormitory possession was defeated in 2007); Chet Brokaw, House Panel OKs Bill Allowing Guns on Campuses, RAPID CITY J., Jan. 30, 2008, http://www.rapidcityjournal.com/articles/2008/01/30/news/local/doc47a0dd2608aab504773184.txt (stating that a bill to create a statutory ban on guns on South Dakota college campuses was unanimously defeated in a state House committee); Vu, supra note 33 (“Louisiana lawmakers killed a bill that would have banned guns in college dorms . . . .”). 60 ARIZ. REV. STAT. ANN. § 12-781 (2009). 61 Becky Pallack, Concealed Guns in Locked Cars Are OK at AZ Public Colleges Beginning Today, ARIZ. DAILY STAR, Sept. 30, 2009, http://www.azstarnet.com/sn/education/311182. 62 See Robin Erb, Guns on Campus, DETROIT FREE PRESS, June 20, 2009, at 1A. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 525 school teachers being able to carry on campus. At least in Texas, things are moving his way. In August 2008, the school district in Harrold, Texas authorized licensed carry by school teachers.63 District Superintendent David Thweatt said, “When the federal government started making schools gun-free zones, that’s when all of these shootings started. Why would you put it out there that a group of people can’t defend themselves? That’s like saying ‘sic ’em’ to a dog.”64 A year later, there had been no problems at the school, although a methamphetamine lab had been discovered in a house fifty feet away from school property, indicating that criminals with guns may have been much closer to the school than anyone realized.65 Michigan is hardly as “pro-gun” a state as Texas. Its gun control laws are much stricter, and it was among the last of the forty states to enact a “Shall Issue” law. Yet even in Michigan, a survey of public middle and high school principals found that one-third favored the idea of allowing teachers to carry concealed firearms at school. That third was evenly split between principals who simply favored the proposal and those who favored the proposal along with restrictions.66 III. REAL-WORLD PROGRAMS A standard tactic of opponents of campus carry is to unleash a litany of frightened speculation. For example, in 2007, the Board of Regents for Nevada’s public universities considered, but ultimately did not adopt, a Regent’s proposal which had been brought forward by the four police chiefs of the state’s eight campus university system.67 Under the campus police chief’s proposal, university faculty or staff members could volunteer to be trained and armed as members of a special reserve officers corps.68 A volunteer would have to pass a physical and psychological examination and a comprehensive background check. The volunteer would then pay to take classes on firearms, defensive tactics, and juvenile justice at Nevada’s Law Enforcement Training Academy. The volunteer would also pay for 63 See James C. McKinley, Jr., In Texas School, Some Teachers Carry Books, Chalk and Pistols, N.Y. TIMES, Aug. 29, 2008, at A1 (“The school board decided that teachers with concealed guns were a better form of security than armed peace officers, since an attacker would not know whom to shoot first . . . . Teachers have received training from a private security consultant, and will use special ammunition designed to prevent ricocheting . . . .”). 64 North Texas School District Will Let Teachers Carry Guns, HOUSTON CHRON., Aug. 15, 2008, http://www.chron.com/disp/story.mpl/front/5945430. 65 Ann Work, Harrold Marks Year of Guns in Schools, TIMES REC. NEWS (Wichita Falls, Tex.), Aug. 5, 2009, http://www.timesrecordnews.com/news/2009/aug/05/harrold-marks-year-of-guns-inschools. 66 Weapons in Schools Strike a Nerve, GRAND RAPIDS PRESS, Sept. 12, 2007, at A1. 67 Lenita Powers, Nevada, Other States Eye Guns on Campus, RENO GAZETTE-J., Mar. 7, 2008, at A1; see also Vu, supra note 33 (“In Nevada, the Board of Regents approved a plan by the university system’s four police chiefs to train and deputize faculty and staff volunteers to have more guns on campus to combat a shooter.”). 68 Kevin Johnson, Universities Rethink Unarmed Police, USA TODAY, Sept. 20, 2007, at 1A. 526 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 his or her academy uniforms and equipment. Upon completion of the Law Enforcement Training Academy curriculum, the professor or staffer would receive $3000 annually in extra pay as an auxiliary law enforcement officer and would be authorized to carry a handgun on state university property.69 In the Nevada legislature, a bill for a similar auxiliary police training system to K–12 teachers was introduced but defeated.70 Now consider one teacher’s objection to the proposal: On reading the “Teachers who get police training could get extra pay, carry guns” article Wednesday, I was astounded! Having been a teacher for 40 years, I am a product of the “old school,” which stressed that teachers are to be impeccable models for their students. That Clark County School District teachers would be encouraged to aspire to be eligible candidates for serving as reserve campus police officers by being paid an additional sum of $3,000 is an insult to academia. This idea would be turning our schools into war zones. The concept is barbaric! It is illogical! It is sick! Youth wishing to prove their manhood would find a way to challenge those teachers with guns. Would students feel respect or fear for the teachers with guns? Would the students who are in gangs not feel even more threatened and retaliate? Would not district schools be adding fuel to the fire by bringing additional guns to the school campuses? These are but a few of the arguments against the proposal that certain district teachers carry guns into their classrooms.71 The above response is by no means atypical of objections to campus carry. That is to say, the objection amounts to a list of worst-case scenarios, asserted as if they are near-certainties. One can find similar conjectural objections in many newspaper editorials opposing licensed carry on campus. When policy makers must make decisions, especially decisions which could have life or death consequences, pure speculation is unlikely to be helpful. A better approach is to examine empirical evidence to see whether 69 Emily Richmond, Teachers Who Get Police Training Could Get Extra Pay, Carry Guns, LAS VEGAS SUN, Aug. 8, 2007, http://www.lasvegassun.com/news/2007/aug/08/teachers-who-get-policetraining-could-get-extra-p/. 70 Id. 71 Mary Gafford, Letter to the Editor, Teachers + Guns = A Very Bad Idea, LAS VEGAS SUN, Aug. 14, 2007, http://www.lasvegassun.com/news/2007/aug/14/letter-teachers-guns-a-very-bad-idea. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 527 a particular policy has been tried elsewhere, and if so, what the results have been. In fact, there are many real-world experiments where defensive policies have already been tried. In these places, there is not a single example of even one of the hypothetical objections ever coming true. This Article now examines the policies which have been adopted at some schools in the United States as well as in Israel, Thailand, and Norway. A. Schools in the United States In 2003, the Alliance for Justice (a leftist legal advocacy organization) surveyed the 150 largest colleges and universities in the United States regarding gun possession by students.72 Slightly over half (eighty-two) of the institutions had comprehensive gun bans. Twenty-five schools allowed student guns, but required that the guns be stored in particular places. Twenty-seven allowed guns only for specific activities, such as a competitive shooting team, ROTC, or another campus program. Twentytwo required prior authorization for bringing a gun on campus. Five simply required that the gun be registered (but two of the five also required designated storage).73 The Alliance for Justice survey did not ask about gun possession or carrying by faculty or other staff. In the United States, one can find schools as diverse as Dartmouth College and Boise State University where gun carrying by faculty is permitted.74 At Virginia’s public colleges and universities, the governing bodies have banned licensed carrying by staff and students, but they do not have the legal authority to ban carry by campus visitors.75 Thus, everyone with a Virginia state permit can carry at the Virginia public universities except for staff and students. 1. Utah In Utah, anyone with a concealed handgun permit may carry at any K– 12 public school, and at any of the nine campuses in the Utah state college system, including in dormitories.76 Utah’s “Shall Issue” statute was enacted in 1995. The concealed handgun permit is issued by the Criminal 72 Alliance for Justice, National Survey of College Campus Gun Possession Policies (2003), available at http://web.archive.org/web/20060213203944/http://www.allianceforjustice.org/student/ student_resources/college_survey.html. 73 Id. 74 John R. Lott, Jr., Editorial, Columbine to Va. Tech to NIU: Gun-Free Zones or Killing Fields?, INVESTOR’S BUS. DAILY, Feb. 25, 2008, http://www.ibdeditorials.com/IBDArticles.aspx?id= 288832885191506. 75 See Jeff Branscome, NRA: Let Students Carry, FREE-LANCE STAR (Fredericksburg, Va.), Apr. 25, 2008, available at http://fredericksburg.com/News/FLS/2008/042008/News/FLS/2008/042008/ 04252008/374535 (noting the situation at the University of Mary Washington). 76 See UTAH CODE ANN. § 76-10-505.5(3) (2008) (creating an exception to firearms prohibition in school zones for, among others, persons authorized to possess firearms by virtue of a concealed carry permit). 528 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 Investigations and Technical Services Division of the Department of Public Safety. The licensee must be at least twenty-one years old and must pass a safety class and a fingerprint-based background check.77 For people who do not have permits, guns are prohibited from school zones in Utah.78 School zones are broadly defined to include kindergartens through universities, as well as any parks, stadiums, or the like being used by a school, and a one thousand-foot radius therefrom.79 There are exceptions to the Utah school zone weapons ban, including gun possession on private property (e.g., in a home or automobile within one thousand feet of a school), or with approval from school administrators. Most important, there is a complete exception for any person who has a valid concealed carry permit.80 Thus, under Utah law, since 1995, any person with a concealed carry permit has been able to carry a handgun in Utah K–12 public schools. Lawful carriers include teachers, as well as any other licensed adult, such as a parent visiting the school to pick up a child. Although the 1995 Utah statute specifically authorized licensed carry in school zones, the University of Utah persisted in prohibiting licensed carry on campus. In 2004, the Utah legislature enacted supplemental legislation making it clear that the state university was required to follow the same carry statutes applicable to all other public educational institutions in Utah.81 The University of Utah sued, claiming that the statute violated academic freedom.82 It was something of a stretch to assert that “academic freedom” means that government schools can violate the constitutional rights of students or faculty,83 and the Utah legislature had made it clear that licensed carry is part of the Utah constitutional right to arms.84 Did the law requiring the university to allow licensed gun carrying amount to a violation of the university’s academic freedom to express its viewpoint about guns? The argument was difficult to reconcile with the 77 Id. § 53-5-704. Id. § 76-10-505.5. 79 Id. § 76-3-203.2. 80 Id. § 76-10-505.5. 81 Id. § 53-5A-102(2). 82 Univ. of Utah v. Shurtleff, 144 P.3d 1109, 1112 (Utah 2006). For an argument in favor of the university policy, see Kathy L. Wyer, Comment, A Most Dangerous Experiment? University Autonomy, Academic Freedom, and the Concealed-Weapons Controversy at the University of Utah, 2003 UTAH L. REV. 983, 985, 1007–08 (2003) (arguing that the state university has a right to autonomy, even against an express legislative enactment, and that the university is not bound to comply with the opinions of the state Attorney General). 83 Cf. Coal. to Defend Affirmative Action v. Granholm, 473 F.3d 237, 247–48 (6th Cir. 2006) (rejecting claim that academic freedom includes the power to violate the state constitution’s prohibition on racial discrimination). 84 See UTAH CODE ANN. § 53-5a-102(2) (2008) (“The individual right to keep and bear arms being a constitutionally protected right under Article I, Section 6 of the Utah Constitution, the Legislature finds the need to provide uniform civil and criminal firearm laws throughout the state.”) 78 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 529 U.S. Supreme Court’s decision in Rumsfield v. Forum for Academic and Institutional Rights.85 There, the Court held that when the government compels the law school to allow on-campus interviews by military recruiters, the government has compelled conduct, not speech, on the part of the law school.86 Thus, even though military recruiters speak when on campus, the mere act of allowing them to rent space in an on-campus recruiting room was not compelled “speech” by the law school. A fortiori, when the government requires colleges to allow people to carry concealed firearms on campus, the college has not been forced to propound any “speech” in violation of its academic freedom. After losing in the Utah Supreme Court, the university filed suit in federal district court. The lawsuit was withdrawn in 2007 after the legislature passed a bill allowing students in university dormitories to choose a roommate who does not have a firearm.87 Among the groups who lobbied for campus carry in Utah were Second Amendment Students at the University of Utah.88 However, thus far, hardly any students have exercised the option to be guaranteed a disarmed roommate.89 Thus, faculty at Utah public universities may possess licensed handguns in their offices or automobiles, and may carry those handguns on campus.90 Students aged twenty-one years or older, the minimum age for a concealed handgun permit, may do the same, and may keep their handguns in their dorm rooms.91 The data from Utah campuses reveal no incidents of the slightest misuse of a firearm by a person with a legal permit.92 Nor is there any record of misuse of a firearm by a permit holder in a K–12 school anywhere in Utah. There have been no instances of attempted mass murders at any school in Utah. One might argue that Utah is an atypical state. Sixty percent of Utah’s 85 547 U.S. 47 (2006). Id. at 61. 87 S.B. 251, 57th Leg., 2007 Gen. Sess. (Utah 2007) (amending UTAH CODE § 53B-3-103); Sheena McFarland, U of U Guns-on-Campus Suit Dismissed, SALT LAKE TRIB., Mar. 14, 2007. 88 Brian Maffly, Pro-Gun Students Push for Right to Openly Carry Firearms on U. Campus, SALT LAKE TRIB., Dec. 7, 2007; Sheena McFarland, Stats Show Few Guns Found on Utah College Campuses, SALT LAKE TRIB., Aug. 27, 2007. 89 McFarland, supra note 87; Brian Maffly, U. Gun Policy: Student Whose Roommate Has Gun Permit May Ask for a Reassignment, SALT LAKE TRIB., Dec. 10, 2007 (on file with author). 90 At Weber State University, anthropology Professor Ron Holt teaches the safety course in the Continuing Education Program (not for credit) for members of the university community, as well as other qualified adults, which is necessary for CCW applicants. John Hollenhorst, Weber State University Offering Concealed Weapons Class, KSL-TV, Oct. 21, 2007, http://www.ksl.com/index. php?nid=148&sid=2012831. A more advanced course, “Use of Force and Judgement Training,” is taught at Lehigh Carbon Community College, in Pennsylvania. It too is a non-credit course. Genevieve Marshall, Don’t Shoot . . . ! . . . Without Training. LCCC Offers Simulation, MORNING CALL (Allentown, Pa.), Mar. 2, 2009, at B1. 91 There is one remaining subject of contention. The Utah carry licensing statute allows the licensee to carry concealed or openly. The University of Utah, however, forbids licensed open carry. Maffly, Pro-Gun Students, supra note 88. 92 McFarland, supra note 87. 86 530 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 93 population is Mormon, and members of the Church of Jesus Christ of Latter Day Saints are not supposed to consume alcohol.94 Accordingly, one might expect that the risk of alcohol-related gun misuse by students would be lower in Utah than in other states. This is undoubtedly true, but it should also be noted that a rather large percentage of Utah’s population (and, presumably, its public college and university students), is not Mormon, and there is no evidence of any gun misuse by the licensed nonMormon students either. Moreover, there are many situations in which Mormons’ abstemious practices in regards to alcohol are irrelevant. For example, one can see from personal observation that in the United States, it is very rare for a public school teacher (whatever his or her religion might be) to show up at school under the influence of alcohol. Accordingly, one might expect that Utah public school teachers are drunk at work about as often—that is, almost never—as teachers everywhere else. There are no known cases of any Utah public school teachers who legally have guns in school ever threatening a student. Nor are there any known cases of Utah high school students taking guns to school because they are afraid of their teachers. Nor are there any reports of any student, teacher, or professor at any educational institution anywhere in Utah reporting that they felt less willing to speak up in a classroom because they were afraid of licensed gun permitees. In sum, there has been a natural experiment which has lasted fourteen years in the Utah public schools, and for the same length of time in the Utah public colleges, except for one recalcitrant school, which finally started complying with the law several years ago. There have been zero instances of the slightest evidence of any harm to academic freedom, let alone any case of misuse of a firearm by a licensed permit holder. Accordingly, when someone unleashes the parade of horribles that would supposedly result from allowing licensed carry on campus, then a legitimate follow-up question would be “Why are professors, schoolteachers, or higher education students in this state more irresponsible than their counterparts in Utah?” Perhaps someone could offer reasons to believe that high school teachers in Oregon are more likely to commit gun crimes than high school teachers in Utah; that college professors at the University of Missouri are more likely to shoot students than are professors at Weber State; or that the graduate students at the University of Connecticut are more likely to get drunk and cause a gun accident than are 93 Utah’s Mormon Population Declines, ASSOCIATED PRESS, Nov. 20, 2008. DOCTRINES & COVENANTS OF THE CHURCH OF JESUS CHRIST OF LATTER-DAY SAINTS 89:5–7 (“That inasmuch as any man drinketh wine or strong drink among you, behold it is not good, neither meet in the sight of your Father, only in assembling yourselves together to offer up your sacraments before him. And, behold, this should be wine, yea, pure wine of the grape of the vine, of your own make. And, again, strong drinks are not for the belly, but for the washing of your bodies.”) 94 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 531 their non-Mormon counterparts at the University of Utah. This Article does not suggest that such arguments could not be persuasively offered— just that over a decade of empirical experience in Utah suggests that if a person cannot persuasively show that the relevant group in the other state is less likely to be responsible than their Utah counterparts, then there is little reason to fear adverse consequences from licensed campus carry in that other state. It is also important to remember that the comparison is not for entire state populations (e.g., Florida vs. Utah). Rather the comparison is for only a small percentage (under ten percent and usually under five percent)95 of the Utah and other state population which has been granted a permit to carry a handgun for lawful protection. As discussed in Part IV, this is a population subgroup that in every state is far more law-abiding than is the general population. There is some empirical evidence that people at campuses outside Utah are capable of matching the virtues of Utah citizens—at least for the simple virtue of not committing gun crimes even when the person has a gun. At Colorado State University (whose campus in Fort Collins, Colorado has 25,000 students), licensed carry by faculty, students, and visitors is allowed. The only difference from Utah is that students may not keep guns in dormitories. Licensed carry is also allowed for faculty, students, and visitors at Blue Ridge Community College—which has three campuses and an enrollment of about 4000 at the largest campus—in rural Virginia. Colorado’s “Shall Issue” law was enacted in 2003, and Virginia’s in 1995. Again, there are no reported instances of gun misuse by licensees at these institutions.96 B. Israel From kindergarten through graduate school, the schools of Utah have been safe from any attempted attack by mass murderers. The same is true of Colorado State and Blue Ridge. Of course it is impossible to know for sure whether the licensed carry policies at these campuses have had a deterrent effect. There is another place, however, where arming teachers plainly has saved lives. The nation with the most experience in preventing mass murders in schools is Israel. Palestine Liberation Organization (“PLO”) attacks on Israeli schools began during Passover 1974. The first attack was aimed at a school in Galilee. When the PLO terrorists found that the school was closed because of Passover weekend, they murdered several people in a nearby apartment 95 Cramer & Kopel, supra note 11. Telephone interview with Colorado State University campus security head (Nov. 5, 2007); Podcast: The Virginia Tech Tragedy: Shedding Light on Campus Carry (Mar. 16, 2009), available at http://audio.ivoices.org/mp3/iipodcast271.mp3 (interview with Virginia Tech SCCC chapter leaders). 96 532 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 building. Then, on May 15, 1974, in Maalot: Three PLO gunmen, after making their way through the border fence, first shot up a van load full of workers returning from a tobacco factory (incidentally these people happened to be Galilee Arabs, not Jews), then they entered the school compound of Maalot. First they murdered the housekeeper, his wife and one of their kids, then they took a whole group of nearly 100 kids and their teachers hostage. These were staying overnight at the school, as they were on a hiking trip. In the end, the deadline ran out, and the army’s special unit assaulted the building. During the rescue attempt, the gunmen blew their explosive charges and sprayed the kids with machine-gun fire. 25 people died, 66 wounded.97 Israel at the time had some severe anti-gun laws, which were left over from the days of British colonialism, when the British rulers tried to prevent the Jews from owning guns. After vigorous debate, the government began allowing army reservists to keep their weapons with them. Handgun carry permits were given to any Israeli with a clean record who lived in the most dangerous areas: Judea, Samaria, and Gaza. All over Israel, guns became pervasive in the schools: Teachers and kindergarten nurses now started to carry guns, schools were protected by parents (and often grandpas) guarding them in voluntary shifts. No school group went on a hike or trip without armed guards. The Police involved the citizens in a voluntary civil guard project “Mishmar Esrachi,” which even had its own sniper teams. The Army’s Youth Group program, “Gadna,” trained 15–16 year old kids in gun safety and guard procedures and the older high school boys got involved with the Mishmar Esrachi. During one noted incident, the “Herzliyah Bus massacre” (March ’78, hijacking of a bus, 37 dead, 76 wounded), these youngsters were involved in the overall security measures in which the whole area between North Tel Aviv and the resort town of Herzlyiah was blocked off, manning roadblocks with the police, guarding schools kindergartens etc.98 97 Proven Solutions To ENDING School Shootings: A Telephone Interview with Dr. David Th. Schiller, Anti-Terror Expert, JEWS FOR THE PRESERVATION OF FIREARMS OWNERSHIP (1999), available at http://www.jpfo.org/filegen-n-z/school.htm. Schiller was born in West Germany and moved to Israel, where he served in the military as a weapons specialist. He later returned to Germany, and was hired as a counterterrorism expert by the Berlin police office, as well as by police forces of other German cities. For a while he worked in the terrorism research office of the RAND corporation, and for several years he published a German gun magazine. Id. 98 Id. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 533 After a while, “[w]hen the message got around to the PLO groups and a couple infiltration attempts failed, the attacks against schools ceased.”99 Although the PLO gave up its school attacks, there was at least one subsequent instance of a lone terrorist targeting a school. On May 31, 2002, a terrorist threw a grenade and began shooting at a kindergarten in Shavei Shomron. Then, instead of closing in on the children, he abruptly fled the kindergarten and began shooting around the nearby neighborhood. Apparently he realized that the kindergarten was sure to have armed adults, and that he could not stay at the school long enough to make sure he actually murdered someone.100 Unfortunately for the terrorist, “David Elbaz, owner of the local mini-market, gave chase and killed him with gunshots. In addition to several grenades and the weapon the terrorist carried on him, security sweeps revealed several explosive devices that he had intended to detonate during the thwarted attack.”101 The Israeli policy shows a strong deterrent effect. But Israel’s policy went vastly further than the current American campus carry proposals. Israel essentially guaranteed that all schoolchildren would be protected at all times by armed defenders. The American proposals would allow for possibility of protection, but would not guarantee it. It is true that in “Shall Issue” states, when there is a large enough crowd, it becomes statistically very likely that at least one and probably several people in the crowd will have concealed carry licenses, and that some of them may be carrying at that moment. But this is not the same as ensuring that all schools are protected all the time. It is well known that many terrorists have no intention of surviving their terror attack. Yet the Israeli experience does suggest that even people who are intent on dying can be deterred. After all, their objective is to kill as many innocent victims as possible. If a potential target is well-protected by civilian defenders, then the terrorists seem to abandon that target. Accordingly, the Israeli experience demonstrates that even attacks on schools by suicidal people can be deterred, if the schools are protected by armed citizen defenders. Because the Israeli defense system was so comprehensive, one cannot say for sure whether a much more casual defensive system in American schools would have such a strong deterrent effect. C. Thailand Muslim extremists in Thailand’s southern provinces of Narathiwat, Yala, and Pattani have been carrying out a terrorist campaign, seeking to 99 Id. See Terrorist Attack Foiled in Shavei Shomron, ISRAEL NAT’L NEWS, May 31, 2002, http://web.archive.org/web/20060924230716/www.israelnationalnews.com/news.php3?id=24440. 101 Id. 100 534 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 create a Taliban-style Islamic state independent of Thailand, whose population is predominantly Buddhist. Most teachers are Buddhists, and they have been a key target of the terrorists.102 On April 27, 2004: Interior Minister Bhokin Bhalakula ordered provincial governors to give teachers licenses to buy guns if they want to even though it would mean bringing firearms into the classrooms when the region’s 925 schools reopen May 17 after two months of summer holiday. . . . Pairat Wihakarat, the president of a teachers’ union in the three provinces, said more than 1,700 teachers have already asked for transfers to safer areas. Those who are willing to stay want to carry guns to protect themselves, he said.103 Gun-control laws in Thailand are extremely strict and were tightened even more because of three school shootings (perpetrated by students) that took place in a single week in June 2003; two students were killed.104 While Thailand’s government is hostile to gun ownership in general, it has recognized that teachers ought to be able to safeguard their students and themselves.105 As of 2006, thousands of teachers in the three southern provinces were carrying guns, according to Sanguan Jintarat, head of the region’s Teachers’ Association. Because the permitting process takes months, many teachers were carrying illegally, without a permit. The government, for its part, was running defensive handgun combat training classes for teachers, and selling them 9mm Steyr semi-automatic pistols for one-fourth of the street price. Teachers’ determination to be armed intensified after a July 2006 murder of a teacher. According to the Associated Press, “Prasarn Martchu, a 46-year-old Buddhist, was standing at his blackboard teaching a morning Thai-language class when a gunman walked in disguised as a student, fired twice and escaped while the two armed guards on duty were scared off by the gunfire, according to school officials.”106 The government has also allowed villages in the south to form citizen militias to patrol the area, and to protect their village from terrorist attacks. The militias are supplied with rifles donated by the government. “I don’t care what anyone says,” said Thailand’s Queen Sirikit, according to one of 102 Thailand Allows Teachers in Restive South to Carry Guns for Protection, ASSOCIATED PRESS, Apr. 27, 2004. 103 Id. 104 David Kopel, Follow the Leader, NAT’L REV., Sept. 2, 2004, http://www.nationalreview.com/ kopel/kopel200409022215.asp. 105 Jocelyn Gecker, Teachers in Thailand Under Fire—And Learning to Shoot Back, ASSOCIATED PRESS, Sept. 11, 2006. 106 Id. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 535 her advisors. “We must help the people there to survive. If they need to be trained, train them. If they need weapons, give them weapons.” 107 “Give them weapons” is exactly what the government has been doing. In March 2009, the Bangkok Post reported that “[t]he Royal Aide-de-Camp Department plans to buy 4700 pistols and rifles for use by teachers, security officers and village defence volunteers working in the troubled South.”108 Culturally, it is not surprising to hear that there are many people in Israel, Utah, Colorado, or Virginia who are comfortable with a culture of defensive handgun carrying. However, few people think of Buddhist school teachers in Thailand as ranking high among the world’s “pro-gun” constituencies. The fact that permits in Thailand are sought by Buddhist teachers indicates that the strong desire to protect oneself and one’s students is something of a universal trait. The Thailand example shows that armed teachers are not necessarily, by themselves, sufficient to fully protect schools. As of September 2008, the terrorists had destroyed three hundred schools with arson and bomb attacks.109 By early 2009, the terrorist violence had declined significantly, as the terrorists had alienated most of the local Muslim population, and been ground down as the military and police captured terrorist leaders. But the armed teachers policy did not lead to an instant end to the murder of teachers.110 Nor did the armed protection program in Israel lead to the instant cessation of attacks on schools.111 Both Israel and Thailand faced large, well-organized, and internationally funded terrorist organizations. Fortunately in the United States, schools have not (at least not yet) come under attack from such groups. If they did, the Israel and Thailand experience suggests that an armed teachers program might be an important component of increasing school safety, but that such a program should not be expected to result in an instant halt in attacks by terrorist organizations. D. Norway In upper Norway’s Svalbard archipelago, a ban on polar bear hunting has led to a surge in the polar bear population—and some people have 107 Thomas Fuller, Southern Thai Towns Increasingly Rely on Militias, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 19, 2007, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2007/03/19/world/asia/19iht-thai.4958722.html. 108 Defence Plans to Arm Teachers, BANGKOK POST, Mar. 27, 2009, http://www.bangkokpost. com/news/local/14053/defence-plans-to-arm-teachers. 109 Slow Motion Violence, STRATEGY PAGE, Sept. 19, 2008, http://www.strategypage.com/ qnd/thai/articles/20080919.aspx. 110 See Eye on the Problem, STRATEGY PAGE, Mar. 9, 2009, http://www.strategypage.com/ qnd/thai/articles/20090314.aspx (noting that terrorists are suspected in murder of two college students); Power to the People, STRATEGY PAGE, Feb. 28, 2009, http://www.strategypage.com/qnd/thai/articles/ 20090228.aspx. 111 See supra text accompanying note 97. 536 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 been killed by polar bear attacks. Accordingly, students are required to carry shotguns when traveling to and from school, and to take shooting classes at school.112 The University Centre in Svalbard is the northernmost institution of higher education in the world. There, students are mandated to practice rifle shooting.113 IV. EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE OF DEFENSE AND DETERRENCE Part III of this Article described situations in the United States and around the world where professors, teachers, and students participate in programs to carry guns for lawful protection; the research found no evidence that the gun-carriers have harmed or threatened anyone (other than terrorists or man-eating bears). But the argument of Students for Concealed Carry on Campus is not simply that “We won’t hurt you.” Rather, the argument is that “We will make you safer.” That is, a college professor, public school teacher, or adult college/graduate student who has a lawful concealed handgun, and who happens to be present when an attack begins, would make the situation better rather than worse, from the viewpoint of innocent victims. This section presents evidence indicating that campus carry would likely improve campus safety.114 First, American data show that ordinary violent criminals—the type who might perpetrate an attack in a campus parking lot—are significantly deterred by the risk of confronting an armed victim. Second, police studies show that mass killers who attack schools kill so rapidly that waiting for the police to arrive is guaranteed to lead to mass death; further, mass killers who attack schools tend to kill themselves as soon as they face armed resistance (because they are cowardly, and because they are intent on suicide anyway). Third, there are three cases in which an armed teacher, student, or nearby adult have stopped mass killers on an American campus. A. Deterrence We know that, in general, criminals are deterred by armed citizens. Intending to build the case for comprehensive federal gun restrictions, the Carter administration awarded a major National Institute of Justice (“NIJ”) research grant in 1978 to University of Massachusetts sociology professor 112 Nina Berglund, Armed for First Day of School, AFTENPOSTEN (Norway), Aug. 20, 2007, http://www.aftenposten.no/english/local/article1948234.ece. 113 Agence France Press, Svalbard, Where Man and Polar Bears Share the Art of Living, SPACE DAILY, Mar. 16, 2008, http://www.spacedaily.com/reports/Svalbard_where_man_and_polar_bears_ share_the_art_of_living_999.html; The University Centre in Svalbard, http://www.unis.no (last visited Oct. 2, 2009) (noting that the campus is “the world’s northernmost higher education institution”). 114 Arguments that campus carry would cause other problems are addressed infra Part V. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 537 115 James Wright and his colleagues Peter Rossi and Kathleen Daly. Wright had already editorialized in favor of much stricter controls.116 Rossi would later become president of the American Sociological Association.117 Daly would later win the Hindelang Award, the highest prize bestowed by the American Society of Criminology, for her feminist perspectives on criminology.118 When the NIJ authors rigorously examined the data, they found no persuasive evidence in favor of banning handguns for selfdefense.119 Wright and Rossi produced another study for the NIJ. Interviewing felony prisoners in eleven prisons in ten states, Wright and Rossi discovered that: 34% of the felons reported personally having been “scared off, shot at, wounded or captured by an armed victim.” 8% said the experience had occurred “many times.” 69% reported that the experience had happened to another criminal whom they knew personally. 40% had personally decided not to commit a crime because they thought the victim might have a gun. 56% said that a criminal would not attack a potential victim who was known to be armed. 74% agreed with the statement that “One reason burglars avoid houses where people are at home is that they fear being shot.”120 Notably, “the highest concern about confronting an armed victim was registered by felons from states with the greatest relative number of privately owned firearms.”121 Furthermore: The authors concluded “the major effects of partial or total handgun bans would fall more on the shoulders of the ordinary gun-owning public than on the felonious gun abuser of the sort studied here . . . . [I]t is therefore also possible that 115 See JAMES D. WRIGHT, PETER H. ROSSI & KATHLEEN DALY, UNDER THE GUN: WEAPONS, CRIME, AND VIOLENCE IN AMERICA xi (1983). 116 Id. at xiv–xv. 117 See American Sociological Association, Peter H. Rossi, http://www.asanet.org/cs/root/leftnav/ governance/past_officers/presidents/peter_h_rossi (last visited Oct. 2, 2009). 118 See American Society of Criminology, Michael J. Hindelang Award, http://www.asc41.com/ mjaward.html (last visited Oct. 2, 2009). 119 See WRIGHT, ROSSI & DALY, supra note 115, at 149, 321. 120 See JAMES D. WRIGHT & PETER H. ROSSI, ARMED AND CONSIDERED DANGEROUS: A SURVEY OF FELONS AND THEIR FIREARMS 146 tbl.7.1, 155 tbl.7.5 (expanded ed. 1994). 121 Id. at 151. 538 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 one side consequence of such measures would be some loss of the crime-thwarting effects of civilian firearms ownership.122 The survey of criminals provides strong evidence that allowing people on campuses to have licensed handguns for protection would deter some crimes. Whether “Shall Issue” laws in general lead to statistically significant reductions in crime is a topic that has been the subject of extensive debate among econometricians.123 Notably, research indicates that “Shall Issue” laws led to an eighty-nine percent drop in multiplevictim (two or more fatality) public shootings.124 However, this finding depends on a narrow definition of such shootings—a definition which excludes shootings that are part of another crime (e.g., a robbery in which the victims are killed) or which are gang-related (e.g., a drive-by shooting).125 Although there is debate on whether there is a statistically significant crime reduction as a result of “Shall Issue” laws, there is unanimity that there is no statistically significant increase in crime caused by the acts of the licensees.126 There is also extensive evidence of particular cases in which licensees have used their permitted handguns to save their own lives, or the lives of other people, or to thwart other serious violent crimes.127 Even if these life-saving acts are not statistically significant, they are immensely significant for the victims and their families. Saving even one 122 Id. at 238. See, e.g., JOHN R. LOTT, JR., MORE GUNS, LESS CRIME: UNDERSTANDING CRIME AND GUNCONTROL LAWS 19−20 (1998) (noting statistically significant reductions in all homicide, assault, rape, and robbery); NAT’L RESEARCH COUNCIL, FIREARMS AND VIOLENCE: A CRITICAL REVIEW 2 (2005) (stating that the current level of research does not allow strong conclusions about whether “Shall Issue” laws have positive effects); Ian Ayres & John J. Donohue III, Shooting Down the “More Guns, Less Crime” Hypothesis, 55 STAN L. REV. 1193, 1201–02 (2003) (noting no statistically significant effects); Carlisle E. Moody & Thomas B. Marvell, The Debate on Shall-Issue Laws, 5 ECON J. WATCH 269, 288 (2008) (reviewing other articles that had critiqued or supported Lott’s research; noting that adding additional years and variables to the Ayers-Donohue analysis indicates that the only statistically significant long-term effect is a reduction in assault). 124 John R. Lott, Jr. & William M. Landes, Multiple Victim Public Shootings, Bombings, and Right-to-Carry Concealed Handgun Laws: Contrasting Private and Public Law Enforcement 9, 32 (Univ. of Chi. Law Sch. John M. Olin Law & Econ. Working Paper No. 73, 1999). A revised version of this paper is incorporated in JOHN R. LOTT, THE BIAS AGAINST GUNS: WHY ALMOST EVERYTHING YOU’VE HEARD ABOUT GUN CONTROL IS WRONG 108−14 (2003). 125 LOTT, BIAS AGAINST GUNS, supra note 124, at 104. 126 For the argument that licensees are dangerous, see infra Part V.C.1. 127 See ROBERT A. WATERS, THE BEST DEFENSE: TRUE STORIES OF INTENDED VICTIMS WHO DEFENDED THEMSELVES WITH A FIREARM 109−11, 211 (1998) (reviewing stories of victims using selfdefense); Buckeye Firearms Association, Ohio CHL-Holders Acting in Self-Defense, http://www.buckeyefirearms.org/printable/node/4546 (last visited Nov. 16, 2009) (providing summaries of self-defense cases reported in the newspapers in which the paper identified the defender as having an Ohio Concealed Handgun License). For another compilation of self-defense cases involving concealed carry permitees, see Clayton Cramer’s “Civilian Gun Self-Defense Blog,” discussed infra at notes 204–05. 123 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 539 life, or thwarting even one other violent crime, is a very good thing. Accordingly, allowing licensed carry on campuses makes sense for the purpose of general reduction in violent crime. Of course if the harms of this crime reduction outweighed the gains, then we would have a different answer, but as detailed in Parts II and V, there is no evidence that selfdefense laws are harmful, including in the campus context. But what about deterring mass killers? It is sometimes claimed that such people are undeterrable because they are mentally ill. Whatever else may be said about the mental states of such killers, most of them have demonstrated their ability to be quite rational and calculating in planning the details of their attack. For example, the murderer at Virginia Tech planned the killing over many months, and among the tools he brought for his murder spree was a heavy chain lock for doors, which significantly increased the time it took for the police to get into the part of the building where the killer was active.128 Likewise, the Columbine murderers planned their crime for at least a year, and successfully executed a plan to use explosives and fire alarms to create confusion among the victims; they also started their attack when the school resource officer was off-campus having lunch—an indication that they preferred not to confront armed resistance.129 It is also important to remember that although some mass killers, such as the ones at Columbine, attack a school because of personal animosity toward students or teachers, other mass killers are adults who have no connection to the school. These would include the thirty-year-old who attacked a second-grade classroom in Winnetka, Illinois in 1988,130 or the 128 See VA. TECH REVIEW PANEL, MASS SHOOTINGS AT VIRGINIA TECH 26 (2007), available at http://www.governor.virginia.gov/TempContent/techPanelReport-docs/FullReport.pdf. 129 See David B. Kopel, What If We Had Taken Columbine Seriously?, WEEKLY STANDARD, Apr. 24, 2000, at 20. The murders began outside an entrance to the school. Early in the attack, outside the school building, the School Resource Officer returned from lunch, and engaged in a long-distance exchange of gunfire with the killers. The killers retreated into the building, and then began killing people inside. Instead of pursuing the killers, the officer stayed outside, and took no further action against the killers. Inside the building, in the school library, students were told by a 911 operator to stay where there were and not to leave (even though the library had its own exit directly to the outside). As a result, most of the people at Columbine who died were those who were methodically executed in the library. Because of the open 911 line, the police officers who had arrived at the scene knew what was going on the library, but they stood idle several feet away, outside the building. The police were acting under the standard doctrine of the time, which placed officer safety above all other values. The doctrine stated that only a S.W.A.T. team should enter the building, and that even the S.W.A.T. should not search for the killers immediately, but should methodically establish a perimeter, and then slowly tighten that perimeter room by room. Id. 130 JOEL KAPLAN, GEORGE PAPAJOHN & ERIC ZORN, MURDER OF INNOCENCE: THE TRAGIC LIFE AND FINAL RAMPAGE OF LAURIE DANN 228−35 (1990). This Article purposely avoids mentioning the names of the killers, except when necessary to do so in a citation. Mass killers are frequently motivated by the desire for posthumous publicity, and the mass media’s providing of such publicity often has a direct effect leading to more mass murders. See LOREN COLEMAN, THE COPYCAT EFFECT: HOW THE MEDIA AND POPULAR CULTURE TRIGGER THE MAYHEM IN TOMORROW’S HEADLINES 1−5 (2004) (noting the epidemics of similar behaviors after suicides and school shootings); Clayton E. 540 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 pederast who murdered sixteen kindergarteners and a teacher in Dunblane, Scotland.131 One reason why some adult sociopaths choose to attack schools— schools to which they have no particular connection—is that schools are easy targets. It is not surprising that police stations, hunting-club meetings, NRA offices, and similar locations known to contain armed adults are rarely attacked. B. Need for Speed in Responding to Active Shooters Whenever there is a public debate on campus defense against mass murderers, there is almost certain to arise a vast amount of commentary from people who have no expertise with defensive tactics, yet who announce with certitude that campus police or security guards, or police arriving at the campus, will always provide sufficient protection. The view of actual experts is somewhat different. The Police Marksman is a professional periodical for police officers that focuses almost entirely on police tactics involving firearms. It presents close analysis of incidents in which officers were attacked by armed assailants, and the tactics that did or did not work in response. The Police Marksman also covers topics such as police sniper work in hostage situations, and other issues involving police use of firearms to protect the public. A 2007 issue of the magazine was devoted to the problem of the “active shooter.” Before Columbine, the standard police tactic for dealing with an armed criminal inside a building was to establish a perimeter, and then gradually constrict the perimeter, safely clearing one room at a time.132 That was the tactic used at Columbine, with the result that eleven of the thirteen people who were murdered (including teacher Dave Sanders, who bled to death over the course of several hours) were killed while the police were methodically setting up the perimeter outside.133 Cramer, Ethical Problems of Mass Murder Coverage in the Mass Media, 9 J. MASS MEDIA ETHICS 26, 29 (1994) (providing a case study indicating that coverage by media sources encourages copy cat behavior). On the Jewish holiday of Purim, the Book of Esther is read. The story is about a thwarted plot to kill all the Jews living in the Babylonian empire. Whenever the would-be genocidaire’s name is read, the audience drowns it out with noisemakers and shouts. This is a better policy than putting a mass killer’s publicity video of himself on national television news and publishing a still photo from that video on the front page of most newspapers—as the American media irresponsibly did after the Virginia Tech murders. See Dave Kopel, Airing, Publishing Killer’s Photos, Rants Reckless; Publicity a Fresh Inducement to Mass Murderers, ROCKY MOUNTAIN NEWS, Apr. 21, 2007, at 30. 131 SANDRA UTTLEY, DUNBLANE UNBURIED 14 (2006) (explaining how sixteen children and their teacher were murdered, and another twelve children and three teachers injured, during a school shooting). 132 See Kopel, supra note 129. 133 Id. In 1993, a mass killer attacked a law firm at 101 California Street in San Francisco. The killer committed suicide when he heard the police coming. The police found his body in a stairwell, 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 541 Many more people might have been killed if the Columbine perpetrators had not committed suicide. Post-Columbine, police tactics began to change in regards to the “active shooter”—the term used by defense experts for Columbine-type attackers. Establishing and constricting the perimeter might be fine in a case where a bank robber is holding hostages inside a building. It is not the right response to the active shooter who is killing one person after another. In the article Rapid Deployment: Version 2.0, police trainer Dick Fairburn details the problem of effective police response to the active shooter. While the active shooter phase of Columbine lasted thirteen minutes, [m]any of the active shooter incidents we examined were over in three to four minutes, much quicker than four officers could be assembled as a rapid deployment team and hope to find and neutralize the shooter. This suggests that the only hope for stopping the shooter and saving lives in most active shooter events, will come from someone who is at the scene when the shooting starts.134 Simply put, by the time the S.W.A.T. team arrives, it will be too late. This means that neutralizing the active shooter will be up to a single School Response Officer (“SRO”) already stationed at the high school, or the college campus police, or perhaps a nearby patrol officer who quickly arrives at the scene. Fairburn’s article states that sometimes, armed citizens may be the right, and only, response: Lacking an SRO or first arriving officer, the only hope for saving lives may fall to citizens who are on-scene when the attack begins. . . . [A]ctive shooters have been stopped by untrained citizens. In states where concealed carry is legal, the odds of a citizen being equipped to deal with an active shooter are enhanced. The Virginia Tech officials have been criticized for banning concealed weapons permits on their campus. Many universities still refuse to arm their campus police officers. The [Columbine killers’] generation that wreaked havoc in high schools are now at universities—this but did not realize he was the perpetrator. Accordingly, they sealed off the area and refused to allow emergency medical personnel to enter. As a result, victim Deborah Fogel bled to death over the course of an hour. Leslie Goldberg, Did Victim Have to Die? Family Sues for Answer: SFPD Must Defend Actions in Tragedy at 101 California, S.F. EXAMINER, Mar. 26, 1995, http://www.sfgate.com/cgibin/article.cgi?f=/e/a/1995/03/26/NEWS5499.dtl&hw=arrived&sn=215&sc=130. 134 Richard Fairburn, Rapid Deployment: Version 2.0, POLICE MARKSMAN, Sept./Oct. 2007, at 21, available at http://www.policeone.com/pc_print.asp?vid=1675030. 542 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW is a dangerous time. [Vol. 42:515 135 Another article in the same issue observes that “[t]he sooner someone—anyone—effectively intervenes through an act of courage, the fewer funerals will result. In past incidents, active shooters have been thwarted by police officers, security guards and school teachers.”136 A police study describes some consistent patterns of active shooters. The report, released by the Force Science Research Center at Minnesota State University-Mankato, observes that the average post-Columbine “rapid mass murder episode” lasts about eight minutes.137 The short time period makes it close to impossible for police to use the preferred tactic of deploying a four-man team, and makes it unlikely that even a two-officer team will be available in time.138 But “[u]nlike conventional criminal predators, who often have no reluctance about attacking police,” active shooters are “cowardly.” Report author Ron Borsch explains: They choose unarmed, defenseless innocents for a reason: They have no wish to encounter someone who can hurt them. They are personally risk- and pain-avoidant. The tracking history of these murderers has proved them to be unlikely to be aggressive with police. If pressed, they are more likely to kill themselves.139 Accordingly, the tactics that make sense in most situations, such as a gun battle with an armed robber or kidnapper trying to escape, are not appropriate for an active shooter. Instead, even a lone officer should “close in and finish the fight with aggression . . . . The idea is to keep the adversary off-balance by always forcing him to react to your actions, rather than, after contact, reacting to him.”140 The challenge of a single officer finding the killer in a large building may be complex. But once the killer is located, Borsch explains, officers should understand that “this bad guy is one of the easiest man-with-gun encounters they will ever have.”141 Indeed, “[m]ost officers have already faced worse opponents from a personal safety standpoint . . . .”142 Or as another article, analyzing the 2007 murders at an Amish schoolhouse in 135 Id. at 21. This Article alters the quote to avoid printing the killers’ names. See supra note 130. Dan Marcou, 5 Phases of the Active Shooter Incident, POLICE MARKSMAN, Sept./Oct. 2007, at 31, available at http://www.policeone.com/pc_print.asp?vid=1672491. 137 Ohio Trainer Makes the Case for Single-Officer Entry Against Active Killers, POLICEONE.COM, May 14, 2008, http://www.policeone.com/pc_print.asp?vid=1695125 (reprinting a report from Force Science News). In 2008, Police Marksman ceased print publication, and its subscribers were transferred to the PoliceOne website, which deals with police tactics and training. 138 Id. 139 Id. 140 Id. 141 Id. 142 Id. 136 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 543 Pennsylvania, suggests, “[a] running gun-battle at the early stages of an armed invasion is preferable to allowing a murderous predator unrestricted control of the environment.”143 In short, by far the best response to an active shooter is for someone to start shooting back. If there is a policeman nearby who can start shooting back, wonderful. But if the killer has selected the targeted victims in a way so there is no police officer immediately at the scene, lives will be saved if one or more victims starts shooting back. But what if someone misses a shot? Well, if we only think about that risk, then the proper response to an active shooter would be to make sure that no police officers ever go to the scene. After all, police officers only hit their targets eight percent of the time,144 or a third of the time,145 or less than twenty percent of the time.146 So the police officer who is shooting at the killer might miss and hit an innocent bystander. Of course, the idea of not calling the police is self-evidently absurd. The tangible risk that the policeman’s shot might hit an innocent is far outweighed by the enormous danger of allowing the killer to act at will. Moreover, the missed shot rate is not really the point; the miss rate may be high, but the number of misses which hit an innocent bystander, let alone kill him, is much smaller. The data about police accuracy should also be considered in light of the fact that police who engage a target are trained to do so while staying fairly distant—twenty to thirty feet away. For personal self-defense situations, a defensive shot from a civilian is usually fired at a distance of shorter than seven feet—a distance from which it is much easier to hit a stationary target. If the victims fire back several shots from a longer distance, it is likely that some would miss the killer, but extremely unlikely that any would kill an innocent person. Even if the latter risk were much greater, that risk is small compared to the risk of allowing the killer to take aimed shots again and again and again. Moreover, if one or more potential victims are firing at an attacker, even if the victims miss, being shot at is, to say the least, very distracting. An attacker who is under fire will have much less freedom to aim his own shots carefully and kill his intended victims. And 143 Rick Armellino, Revisiting the Amish Schoolhouse Massacre, POLICEONE.COM, Aug. 22, 2007, http://www.policeone.com/columnists_internal.asp?view=1271208&vid=1290372 (discussing police tactics). 144 Tom Teepen, Gun Lobby’s Call to Arms Is Way Off Target, COX NEWS SERVICE, Feb. 18, 2008. 145 Good Morning America, supra note 30. 146 BRADY CENTER TO PREVENT GUN VIOLENCE, NO GUN LEFT BEHIND: THE GUN LOBBY’S CAMPAIGN TO PUSH GUNS INTO COLLEGES AND SCHOOLS 10 (2007), available at http://www.bradycampaign.org/xshare/pdf/reports/no-gun-left-behind.pdf (citing Gregory B. Morrison, Deadly Force Programs Among Larger U.S. Police Departments, 9 POLICE Q. 331, 332 (2006) (reporting hit rates of about one in five shots)). 544 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 as the Force Science Institute study explains, active shooters tend to crumble at the first sign of active resistance.147 C. When Have Citizens Stopped Mass Killers at Schools? The first incident was in 1997. A sixteen-year-old Satanist slit his mother’s throat, and then took a deer-hunting rifle to Pearl High School, in Pearl, Mississippi. He murdered his ex-girlfriend and her friend and wounded seven other students at his high school. Joel Myrick was the Assistant Principal of Pearl High School: The moment Myrick heard shots, he ran to his truck. He unlocked the door, removed his gun from its case, removed a round of bullets from another case, loaded the gun and went looking for the killer. “I’ve always kept a gun in the truck just in case something like this ever happened,” said Myrick, who has since become Principal of Corinth High School, Corinth, Miss. [The killer] knew cops would arrive before too long, so he was all business, no play. No talk of Jesus, just shooting and reloading, shooting and reloading. He shot until he heard sirens, and then ran to his car. His plan, authorities subsequently learned, was to drive to nearby Pearl Junior High School and shoot more kids before police could show up. But Myrick foiled that plan. He saw the killer fleeing the campus and positioned himself to point a gun at the windshield. [The killer], seeing the gun pointed at his head, crashed the car. Myrick approached the killer and confronted him. “Here was this monster killing kids in my school, and the minute I put a gun to his head he was a kid again,” Myrick said . . . . In Pearl, federal, state and local laws helped [the killer] shoot nine students. The deer rifle had to be reloaded after every shot. To hit nine students, [the killer] needed time. The moments it took Myrick to reach his gun are what allowed [the killer] to continue shooting and almost escape. Gun laws, and nothing else, gave [the killer] that time.148 Just a few days later in Edinboro, Pennsylvania, a fourteen-year-old went to a Friday night junior high graduation dance, wielding a handgun he 147 148 Ohio Trainer Makes the Case for Single-Officer Entry Against Active Killers, supra note 137. Wayne Laugesen, A Principal and His Gun, BOULDER WKLY., Oct. 15, 1999. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 545 had taken from his father. On the patio of the restaurant where the dance was being held, he fatally shot a science teacher in the head. The killer then entered the building, and fired several shots, wounding two students. The killer fled through a rear exit, pursued by the restaurant’s owner, James Strand, who had grabbed a shotgun. Strand caught up with the killer in a nearby field, and forced him to surrender.149 At Appalachian Law School, in Grundy, Virginia, in 2002, a former student went to the office of two professors, and killed them both at close range with a handgun, and also killed a student. Law student Tracy Bridges, formerly a sheriff’s deputy, ran to his automobile and retrieved his .357 magnum revolver. Another student, Mikael Gross, a police officer from North Carolina, went to his car and got his semi-automatic pistol and body armor.150 Gross and Bridges did not know about each other; they confronted the killer when he had left the building. Bridges shouted an order to the killer to drop his gun. The killer dropped the gun, and was wrestled to the ground by other law students, including Ted Besen and Todd Ross. According to Besen’s version of the story, the killer had already dropped the gun by the time that Bridges shouted his order. Bridges remembers that the killer dropped the gun only after the order. Considering the fast-moving and chaotic situation, it is possible that both Besen and Bridges may be sincere in recounting their version of events. They were, understandably, not focusing their attention on each other, but on the killer.151 It appears that Besen did not claim that the killer had already put down his gun until about two months after the attack.152 Schools are not the only places where citizens with lawfully-owned guns have stopped mass murderers. For example, in Colorado Springs, Colorado, in December 2008, a sociopath entered a large church, and began shooting people. But he was quickly engaged by fire from Jeanne Assam, a church member who was volunteering to provide security at the church, and who was carrying a handgun pursuant to a “Shall Issue” 149 Pennsylvania Students Cope with Shooting Spree, CNN, Apr. 25, 1998, http://www.cnn.com/ US/9804/25/school.shooting.pm/. 150 Rex Bowman, Helping to Stop a Killer: Students Went After Law School Gunman, RICHMOND TIMES DISPATCH, May 5, 2002, at A8; James Eaves-Johnson, Law School, Guns, and a Media Bias, DAILY IOWAN, Jan. 24, 2002; Laurence Hammack et al., Shooting Hits Many Lives, ROANOKE TIMES, Jan. 20, 2002, at A1; Jon Ostendorff, Area Officer Helps Wrestle Law School Gunman to Ground, ASHEVILLE CITIZEN-TIMES, Jan. 19, 2002, at 1B; Diane Suchetka, Ex-Charlottean: I Helped Nab Suspect, CHARLOTTE OBSERVER, Jan. 18, 2002, at 2A. 151 Bowman, supra note 150. 152 John Lott, Missouri Becomes 36th State with Right-to-Carry Law, JOHN LOTT’S WEBSITE, Sept. 11, 2003, http://johnrlott.tripod.com/postsbyday/9-11-03.html. The Brady Center calls Appalachian State “the one example often cited by the NRA and gun lobby groups.” BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 9. This statement is plainly false, since such groups also frequently point to Pearl, Mississippi, and Edinboro, Pennsylvania. Surprisingly, the Brady Center report mentions these latter two incidents in its litany of school shootings, but does not acknowledge how those attacks were stopped. Id. at 32. 546 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 license issued under Colorado law. After a brief exchange of gunfire, the murderer either was killed by the guard’s shots, or had killed himself.153 When the Tennessee state legislature considered a bill to allow faculty licensed campus carry, Carole Borges (a former faculty member at several colleges154) spoke in opposition: “It just escalates. Violence is not the solution to violence.”155 It depends on what one means by “solution.” If one considers saving the lives of many innocent people to be a positive outcome, then swift and violent defense against campus killers has already proven to be an outstanding solution. V. OBJECTIONS TO CAMPUS DEFENSE This section examines various objections to campus carry. The objections can be broken into four major categories, each of which will be addressed in order. The first objection is that campus carry is unnecessary, either because campuses are already safe, or because other approaches to campus security can be taken. A second objection is that campus victims who resist an attack by an active shooter would actually cause more harm than good—either because they are incapable of using firearms competently or because police arriving at the scene would find a gun battle to be more confusing than a scene in which one person is executing victims methodically. The third objection is that even if licensed carry on campus was successful at deterring mass murder attacks, or in stopping such attacks in progress, the overall harm would exceed the good. That is, the reduction in mass murders would be outweighed by the harms caused by faculty or adult students who were licensed to carry guns: the teachers and students, if allowed to use their existing Carrying a Concealed Weapon (“CCW”) permits on a campus, would commit violent gun crimes on the campus. Closely related is a fourth objection: academic freedom would suffer because teachers and students with CCW permits would intimidate people from speaking up about issues being debated in classrooms. A. Campus Carry Is Unnecessary 1. Schools Are So Safe that No Additional Precautions Are Necessary Over twenty percent of college students have been the victim of at 153 Nicholas Riccardi & DeeDee Correll, Guard Saved Untold Lives, Officials Say, L.A. TIMES, Dec. 11, 2007, at A16. 154 Knoxville Writers’ Guild, Profile of Carole Borges, http://www.knoxvillewritersguild.org/ borges.htm (last visited Nov. 16, 2009). 155 Anthony Welsch, Proposal Would Allow Faculty to Carry Guns in Classrooms, WBIR-TV (Knoxville, Tenn.), Feb. 16, 2008, http://www.wbir.com/print.aspx?storyid=54632. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 547 156 least one crime on or near campus. Older teenagers and young adults (persons aged sixteen to twenty-four) are victimized by violent crime at a higher rate than any other age group.157 College students are victimized by violent criminals eighty-one percent as often as non-students in the same age group.158 So even though college students are nineteen percent less likely than people in the same age group to be attacked by violent criminals, they are still far more likely to be attacked than are persons in any age group twenty-five or older.159 Accordingly, it appears that college students have a greater general need to be able to defend themselves than do older people. About nine out of ten victimizations of college students take place offcampus.160 This is good news for campuses, and it indicates that college students have a much greater need to be able to protect themselves from violent crime off-campus than they do on-campus. This fact militates against campus policies that significantly interfere with the ability of adult students to protect themselves off-campus; for example, if a college prohibits adult commuter students from leaving firearms locked in their cars, then the students cannot protect themselves when traveling to or from campus. Some states that have laws restricting guns in higher education institutions have a provision to explicitly protect the right of adult students to have firearms in locked cars. Similarly, most states restrict guns at K– 12 schools, and some have exceptions for guns owned by non-student adults and stored in locked, parked cars.161 A well-written automobile 156 Wesley G. Jennings et al., Are Institutions of Higher Learning Safe? A Descriptive Study of Campus Safety Issues and Self-Reported Campus Victimization Among Male and Female College Students, 18 J. CRIM. JUST. EDUC. 191, 200 (2007). 157 U.S. DEP’T OF JUSTICE, BUREAU OF JUSTICE STATISTICS, TEENS AND YOUNG ADULTS EXPERIENCE THE HIGHEST RATES OF VIOLENT CRIME (2006), available at http://www.ojp.usdoj. gov/bjs/glance/vage.htm (reporting National Crime Victimization Survey data for 1973–2006). 158 KATRINA BAUM & PATSY KLAUS, U.S. DEP’T OF JUSTICE, BUREAU OF JUSTICE STATISTICS, VIOLENT VICTIMIZATION OF COLLEGE STUDENTS, 1995−2002, at 2, tbl.1 (2005), available at http://www.prisonandjail.org/bjs//pub/pdf/vvcs02.pdf (providing National Crime Victimization Survey data for 1995–2002). 159 U.S. DEP’T OF JUSTICE, supra note 157. 160 BAUM & KLAUS, supra note 158, at 5. 161 The following is a list of car-specific exemptions. It does not include statutes which allow carrying (or carrying pursuant to a permit) in general in K–12 schools or in higher education. ALASKA STAT. § 11.61.210 (a)(7) (2008), ARIZ. REV. STAT. ANN. § 13-3102(I)(1) (2001), CAL. PENAL CODE § 626.9(c)(2) (West 1999), COLO. REV. STAT. § 18-12-105.5(3)(a) (2008), FLA. STAT. § 790.115(2)(a) (2007), GA. CODE ANN. § 16-11-127.1(c)(17) (2009), IDAHO CODE ANN. § 18-3302D(4)(e) (2004), IOWA CODE §§ 724.4, 724.4B (2001), LA. REV. STAT. ANN. § 14:95.6B(5) (2004), MICH. COMP. LAWS § 28.425o(1)(a) (2009), MINN. STAT. § 609.66(1d)(e) (2008), MO. REV. STAT. § 571.030(3) (2000), MONT. CODE ANN. § 45-8-361(1) (2007) (school ban applies only to K–12 buildings, not parking lots), NEB. REV. STAT. § 28-1204.04(1)(c) (2008), N.M. STAT. § 30-7-2.1(5) (2004), N.D. CENT. CODE § 62.1-02-05(2) (2003), OHIO REV. CODE ANN. § 2923.126 (West 2006), OR. REV. STAT. § 166.370(3)(f)(B) (2007), VT. STAT. ANN. tit. 13, § 4004 (1998) (school ban applies only to K–12 buildings, not parking lots), VA. CODE ANN. § 18.2-308.1(B) (2009), WASH. REV. CODE § 9.41.280(3)(f) (2008), W. VA. CODE ANN. § 61-7-11A(b)(2) (West 2009), WIS. STAT. § 948.61(3)(e) (2007–08). 548 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 exception, either by statute or by campus regulation, should include all automobiles driven onto campus by an adult, especially by an adult with a concealed carry permit. The exception would take care of much of the problem of school administrators interfering with off-campus lawful selfdefense by college students, as well as by university staff, and by K–12 teachers. However, the automobile exception does not address the problem of on-campus violent crimes against students, of which there are over thirty thousand annually162—hardly a trivial number. Nor does an automobile exception fully address the problem of school mass shootings.163 Some reform opponents point out that, depending on the year, the number of victims of mass murders on American campuses is not too far different from the number of students who are killed from football injuries (seventeen football deaths in 2006, thirteen in 2007).164 Mass homicides are not, however, the sole part of the homicide problem on college campuses. From 1991 through 2003, there were at least ten homicides on American college campuses every year, and sometimes as many as twentyfour.165 Most of these were not mass murders, but more ordinary crimes, such as killing a robbery victim, for example.166 Besides, the fact that the general violent crime rate on campus is lower than in many other locations, or that the total number of murder victims on campus is no more than several dozen per year (and often less) is hardly a reason not to take steps to reduce the victimization rate. After all, nobody says, “The death rate from AIDS in our county is lower than in most other counties. Therefore, we should not consider policies which might further reduce the county’s AIDS rate.” Here, one might draw an analogy to churches. The crime rate in churches, synagogues, mosques, and other religious sites is also low. But most state governments do not enact laws specifically outlawing gun- 162 BAUM & KLAUS, supra note 158, at 5 & tbl.4. See supra Part IV.C. (noting that guns stored in automobiles were used to help stop school shootings in Pearl, Mississippi and at Appalachian Law School). 164 Frederick O. Mueller & Bob Colgate, Annual Survey of Football Injury Research, 1931–2008, at tbl.II (2009), available at http://www.unc.edu/depts/nccsi/FootballAnnual.pdf. An important distinction is that football is a known risky activity in which participants choose to assume the risks. Attending classes for a Master’s Degree program in history, or teaching a tenth grade algebra class, are not supposed to be activities in which a participant knowingly assumes a risk of death or crippling injury. One approach to reduce football deaths would be to vastly expand shooting sports programs in high school and junior high, and aim to entice students to participate in competitive shooting instead of football. The death and injury rates from participation in competitive shooting is zero, making it far safer that almost every other sport, and vastly safer than football. NAT’L SAFETY COUNCIL, INJURY FACTS (2009 ed.). 165 Peter Wood, Homicides in Higher Education: Some Reflections on the Moral Mission of the University, 20 ACAD. QUESTIONS 277, 293 (2007) (compiling data). 166 See generally id. 163 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 549 carrying in churches. They leave the policy up to the church itself.167 There has never been a known case where a person with a CCW permit committed a violent crime in a church. There has been a case, however, where a person with a CCW permit saved many lives.168 Of course if adult students and faculty are too incompetent to use defensive arms safely169 or are dangerous characters who would commit gun crimes if they had a gun,170 then the crime-reductive effects of campus carry might be outweighed by other harms. However, if faculty and adult students are neither incompetent nor dangerous, then the fact that campus crime is relatively low compared to crime elsewhere is not a good reason for failing to adopt measures which would improve campus safety.171 2. Alternative Approaches Obviate Any Benefits to Be Gained from Campus Carry a. More Gun Control Some argue that instead of allowing licensed carry on campuses, there should be greater gun control. This is a false dichotomy. There is no rule that prevents a legislature from passing a bill to protect campus carrying and from also passing another bill which increases restrictions on guns or gun owners, if the legislature believes that both bills can help reduce mass murders at schools. Imagine the following argument: Gallant: “Let’s improve the health of infants. We should repeal the law which prohibits breastfeeding on government 167 Thanks to the First Amendment’s Establishment Clause and its parallel provisions in many state constitutions, and to American public sensibilities, there are no state-supported churches in the United States. If there were (as there are in many European nations), then it would not be improper for the legislature to determine the firearms-carrying policy for the state churches, while leaving the independent churches to set their own policies. 168 In December 2007, parishioner Jeanne Assam, legally carrying a handgun pursuant to a CCW permit, stopped an active shooter’s attack on a church in Colorado Springs. See supra note 153 and accompanying text. 169 See infra Part V.B. 170 See infra Part V.C. 171 It should also be noted that for some opponents of campus carry, the argument about the low rate of campus crime is transparently hypocritical: the Brady Center to Prevent Gun Violence argues against campus carry because crime rates are low on campus, and argues against employees being allowed to store guns in workplace parking lots because crime rates are high at work. See BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at vi (arguing that guns increase the risk of violence at schools); BRADY CENTER TO PREVENT GUN VIOLENCE, FORCED ENTRY: THE NATIONAL RIFLE ASSOCIATION’S CAMPAIGN TO FORCE BUSINESSES TO ACCEPT GUNS AT WORK iii (2005); CENTER TO PREVENT HANDGUN VIOLENCE, GUNS & BUSINESS DON’T MIX: A GUIDE TO KEEPING YOUR BUSINESS GUNFREE i–ii (1997) (arguing again that guns in the workplace increase violence). Thus, low crime rates and high crime rates are both a justification for banning guns. For truth in advertising, the moniker “to Prevent Gun Violence” might accurately be written “to Prevent Gun Ownership.” This is true in regards to workplaces and campuses, where the Brady Campaign (and its legal action arm, the Brady Center) advocate for gun prohibition. 550 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 property.” Goofus: “That’s crazy! You are a pro-breast extremist. We should improve infant health by enacting a law to mandate the use of car seats for children.”172 The obvious fallacy of Goofus’s argument is that his proposal and Gallant’s proposal are not mutually exclusive. Likewise, a legislature could re-legalize campus carry (or override administrative bans on campus carry) and make gun control laws more restrictive, such as by making background checks more extensive, or by registering all guns, or by banning particular models of guns. Assuming arguendo that a particular gun control proposal would impose campus safety, nothing prevents a legislature from enacting that gun control law and at the same time relegalizing campus carry. Whether a particular gun control proposal would help save lives on campus would, of course, be subject to debate. However, there is no reason why the desire to have that debate should preclude the enactment of campus carry legislation. Only two proposed gun controls are incompatible with campus carry. The first is banning all handguns, a proposal which would require repeal of the Second Amendment and of its many state constitution analogues. The other incompatible proposal would be a repeal of a state’s “Shall Issue” law. As long as the law allows some people to own some handguns, then the “Shall Issue” law will ensure that most people who can legally own handguns can obtain a license to carry them, if they are willing to pay a fee, pass a safety class, and submit to fingerprinting. Thus, unless an advocate is proposing an (unconstitutional) ban on all handguns, or an (unpopular) repeal of “Shall Issue,” there is no reason why a legislative body cannot enact campus carry reform and a new gun control bill, presuming that the legislature believes that both laws will improve public safety. b. More Security Guards and Metal Detectors This other proposal is also not incompatible with campus carry. Presumably, if campus carry were re-legalized, then the metal detector personnel would authorize passage of a person with a licensed carry permit—just as schools with metal detectors currently authorize passage of security guards and police, or as airports allow passage of pilots who have authorization to carry firearms in flight. Senators Charles Schumer and Barbara Boxer have introduced legislation to provide federal funding for security at high schools and 172 The names are two characters in a comic strip in the children’s magazine Highlights. Gallant always provides the good example, and Goofus the bad one. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 551 173 colleges. The proposal is not incompatible with campus carry, although it might arguably be inconsistent with federalism.174 If security guards or police were willing to engage aggressively and immediately against an active shooter (rather than just calling for the S.W.A.T. team), then they might well be able to stop a campus shooting in progress. But unless the security level is so dense that there is at least one guard in every building that is in use, and several guards in every multi-story or large building, then there may be considerable carnage and death before any guard has time to respond. After all, at Northern Illinois University in February 2008, campus police arrived within minutes of a shooting outbreak. However, they did not arrive quickly enough to stop five people from being murdered, and many more from being wounded.175 Colorado’s “Shall Issue” law states that a government building may be declared a gun-free zone, and made off-limits to licensed carry, if and only if the government makes it a true gun-free zone, by setting up metal detectors at every entrance.176 The metal detectors should prevent a criminal from bringing a gun into the building. Only then, according to Colorado law, is it fair to tell licensed citizens that they cannot carry their defensive arms. A similar policy would be fair on campus. If a building is genuinely secured with metal detectors, then banning licensed carry within the building is reasonable. As a practical matter, metal detectors have several limitations. First, at K–12 schools, almost all students arrive at the school for the first period within a narrow time window. Processing hundreds of students and teachers so quickly is very difficult, unless the school is willing to pay for staff to monitor multiple lines, as at airports. Second, at airports and at 173 See Press Release, Senator Charles E. Schumer, After Series of Tragic School Shootings and Scares at NYC Area Schools, Schumer Calls for Passage of Key Legislation and Massive Federal Mobilization to Stem Rash of School Violence, Protect the Million [sic] of Kids at NYC Schools (Feb. 16, 2008), available at http://schumer.senate.gov/new_website/record.cfm?id=293534. 174 After all, federal funds are simply funds that are raised from taxpayers in various states (or, in case of a deficit, debt imposed on future generations). Accordingly, if security guards are a costeffective way to improve campus safety, the spending might as well take place at the state and local level, where balanced budget requirements often succeed at ensuring that the current year’s spending desires are matched with the current year’s revenue. 175 Gunman Kills Five, Injures 16 in Attack at University, VIRGINIAN-PILOT, Feb. 15, 2008, at A1. 176 COLO. REV. STAT. § 18-12-214 (2008). The statute states, in relevant part: (4) A permit issued pursuant to this part 2 does not authorize a person to carry a concealed handgun into a public building at which: (a) Security personnel and electronic weapons screening devices are permanently in place at each entrance to the building; (b) Security personnel electronically screen each person who enters the building to determine whether the person is carrying a weapon of any kind; and (c) Security personnel require each person who is carrying a weapon of any kind to leave the weapon in possession of security personnel while the person is in the building. Id. 552 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 secured government office buildings, metal detectors are not simply staffed by a single person who looks at the TV monitor. Every checkpoint is manned or backed up by two or more armed officers. This reduces the risk that an attacker will simply kill the unarmed employee at the metal detector and then proceed inside for further attacks.177 Many American college campuses are sprawling facilities covering hundreds of acres. Preventing public access onto these campuses is impossible—unless one were to surround the campus with high fencing, and allow access only through a few checkpoints.178 Some college campuses do consist of just a few buildings whose entrances could be genuinely secured by metal detectors backed up with armed guards. So for any school, or building within a school, which is genuinely secured, the need for licensed carry is greatly reduced. Accordingly, this Article’s proposal for licensed carry on campus need apply only to campuses and school buildings which are not effectively secured—which is to say, almost all of them. A real “gun-free zone” is fine. A pretend “gun-free zone” is a deadly legal fiction. The pretend zone—that is, a zone which exists by administrative declaration but is not enforced by metal detectors with armed guards—is simply a zone where the people who follow the rules are made into easy victims for mass killers. c. “Alternative Survival Options” The leading lobby against campus carry is the Brady Campaign. The group’s legal research arm is known as the Brady Center. Arguing for gun prohibition on all campuses, the Brady Center writes that “there are numerous survival options for students, faculty, and staff when confronted with an armed attacker that do not involve carrying a gun and firing back at him.”179 This is a rather callous remark. In a footnote in its report, No Gun Left Behind: The Gun Lobby’s Campaign to Push Guns into Colleges and Schools, the Brady Center cites a security expert’s five recommendations: “(1) try to get away, (2) lock the door and barricade it, (3) concealment, (4) play dead and (5) fight back if 177 This is what happened at Red Lake High School in Minnesota in 2005. A neo-Nazi student murdered his grandfather (a police officer) and the grandfather’s girlfriend, then stole the grandfather’s service weapons, and drove his police car to the school. There, the killer murdered an unarmed metal detector operator, and then entered the school to murder six more victims. David Hancock, Tales of School Shooting Bravery: Slain Security Guard, Wounded Student Saved Others from Teen Gunman, CBS NEWS, Mar. 24, 2005, http://www.cbsnews.com/stories/2005/03/24/national/main682915. shtml? source=search_story; Victims, Key People in Story, GRAND FORKS HERALD, Mar. 21, 2006. 178 College campuses in Ethiopia are in fact secured this way, although the motivation is not so much student security as the dictatorship’s intent to exclude outsiders who might criticize the government. Interview with Habtamu Dugo, Senior Fellow in Human Rights, Indep. Inst. (Mar. 2008). Dugo is a former Ethiopian college professor who fled to the United States and was granted political asylum. 179 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 10. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 553 180 you’re sure you’ll be shot.” These are indeed tactics which have helped some people survive some mass shootings. But quite obviously, these “numerous survival options” did not result in survival for the victims at Virginia Tech, Northern Illinois University, Columbine High School, and elsewhere. The best way to increase the survival rate is to have all the survival options available. Since only a small percentage of the adult population has a CCW permit (well under ten percent in most states, and far less in other places),181 then it is good that people be aware of all the survival options. It would be a bad idea to exclude any survival action simply because an organization found it ideologically offensive; for example, a legislature should not make it illegal to “fight back” just because some pacifists are opposed to all forms of violence. Likewise, a legislature should not make it illegal to defend oneself with a firearm, simply because some people abhor gun ownership. The more survival options that are available, the more survival there will be. B. Self-Defense Will Fail Another set of arguments against campus carry contends that campus defenders are incapable of competent defense against active shooters. First, teachers are “overwhelmed” and thus they cannot achieve competence at any additional task. Second, campus defenders will accidentally kill more innocent people than murders would kill intentionally. Third, campus defenders would confuse police arriving at the scene. Finally, citizen defenders do not have as much training as the police. 1. Teachers Are Already “Overwhelmed” As discussed above, the Nevada Board of Regents and Nevada legislature considered proposals to allow campus carry by professors and public school teachers who would undergo the same training as police officers and then be deputized as reserve officers.182 This proposal would eliminate the school safety monopoly currently enjoyed by full-time security officers. Ken Trump, president of a for-profit company, National School Safety and Security Services, which sells consulting services to schools, did not like the idea. He urged that the government instead spend more money on companies such as his own: 180 Id. at 41 n.97 (citing Bill Redeker, Surviving a School Shooting, ABC NEWS, Apr. 17, 2007, http://abcnews.go.com/US/story?id=3050247&page=1). 181 See Blog O’Stuff, supra note 16 (providing state statistics related to adults with licenses to carry). 182 See supra text accompanying notes 67–70. 554 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 “Teachers get into education to teach, not to be cops,” Trump said. “Teachers are already overwhelmed with all of the academic, behavioral and administrative tasks they have to perform. To say you’re going to add a whole other role and mind-set is unrealistic.” Debate about arming teachers surfaces periodically in other states, usually in the wake of a high-profile campus shooting, Trump said. “Rather than off-the-wall proposals, how about our legislators focus on stopping the cuts to funding for school safety and emergency preparedness, mental health services and support programs,” Trump said. “That might actually provide an improved learning environment, instead of trying to make teachers into cops.”183 If we accept Trump’s argument that teachers get into education to teach, not to be cops, then teachers should never be taught how to perform first aid or CPR, since teachers get into education to teach, not to be doctors. As for the argument that “[t]eachers are already overwhelmed,” perhaps not all teachers throughout Nevada are as “overwhelmed” as Trump claims. Significantly, no teacher would be forced against her will to participate in the program. Given that participation would be 100% voluntary, it was fatuous for Trump to object that teachers are too “overwhelmed.”184 2. Selfless Courage Must Be Discouraged Every major world religion lauds people who charitably accept grave risks to themselves in order to protect other innocent citizens. Yet some educational administrators actively attempt to discourage such actions. For example, the University of Colorado tells students that, in case of an attack by a mass killer, “Do not be a hero. Be a good witness.”185 Arguably, the 183 Richmond, supra note 69. A similar point was expressed by Gannett News national columnist DeWayne Wickham: “If school officials in Harrold want to make schoolchildren more secure, they should give that responsibility to trained personnel instead of pushing it onto gun-toting teachers. Those teachers have enough to do as it is.” DeWayne Wickham, Guns in Class? Maybe School Officials Should Start Doing Their Jobs, Gannett News Service, Aug. 26, 2008. For more on Harrold, Texas, see supra note 63. There are many teachers who would not want to carry a firearm; of that group, some would, however, be interested in training with and carrying defensive sprays, or in learning some basic techniques of unarmed combat—particularly, how to disarm someone when his attention is distracted. 185 Kirk Mitchell, Colorado Campuses Respond to Illinois Rampage, DENVER POST, Feb. 15, 2008, http://www.denverpost.com/food/ci_8271956; University of Colorado Denver Emergency Announcement, https://lists.ucdenver.edu/cgi-bin/wa?A3=ind0802&L=EMERGENCY-ANNOUNCE MENTS&E=quoted-printable&P=3693&B=------_%3D_NextPart_001_01C86F63.7E72E361&T=text %2Fhtml;%20charset=US-ASCII (last visited Oct. 6, 2009) (posting emergency notification sent on the day of the attack on Northern Illinois University). 184 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 555 university should not pressure people to act courageously. But why should the university discourage selfless courage? Several school shootings have been stopped by people who acted heroically against an armed killer. Examples include not only the three school shootings that were stopped by armed citizens—Pearl, Mississippi; Edinboro, Pennsylvania; and Appalachian Law School, all discussed supra.186 In 1998, at Thurston High School in Springfield, Oregon, a killer was stopped when he was tackled to the ground by Jake Ryker, with the assistance of his younger brother Robert and three fellow Boy Scouts. “Jake Ryker gave credit to the fact that he had taken a marksmanship and safety training program given by the National Rifle Association.”187 Because of the firearms safety training, the brothers were familiar with firearms; they watched for when the killer paused to change magazines in his gun, and at that point they acted aggressively, and heroically, and stopped the killer.188 Two people had already been fatally wounded, and many more likely would have been if not for the Boy Scouts’ heroism. When Minnesota’s Red Lake High School was attacked in 2005, sophomore Jeffrey May saved several other students by grappling the killer, and attacking him with a pencil.189 May was shot in the right cheek, causing a stroke which partly paralyzed the left side of his body. Thanks to physical therapy, he was eventually able to walk again without a cane, but his left arm remains partially paralyzed. The readers of Reader’s Digest magazine voted May the 2005 Hero of the Year.190 Under the University of Colorado’s mandate, the Ryker brothers and Jeffrey May should have simply paid careful attention while their classmates were slaughtered one after the other; later, the attentive but inactive bystanders could have been given a Good Witness Certificate. But the University of Colorado campuses are home to thousands of studentathletes, as well as a general student body which is highly interested in outdoor sports and fitness—precisely the kind of young men and women who would have a good chance of overpowering the unfit sociopaths (i.e., an unhealthy mind in an unhealthy body) who are typical perpetrators of school shootings. Even after the mass murder at Virginia Tech, the university strove to make sure that no one on its campus acts like the Ryker brothers did. The Virginia Tech campus policy tells employees “What to Do When Violence Occurs.” The rules include: “Avoid challenging body language such as placing your hands on your hips, moving toward the person, or staring 186 See supra Part IV.C. Reed Irvine & Cliff Kincaid, Does Anyone Remember Jake Ryker?, MEDIA MONITOR, June 15, 1999, http://www.aim.org/media_monitor/ does-anyone-remember-jake-ryker/. 188 Id. 189 Hancock, supra note 177. 190 Victims, Key People in Story, supra note 177. 187 556 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 directly at them. If seated, remain in your chair and do not turn your back on the individual.”; and “Never attempt to disarm or accept a weapon from the person in question. Weapon retrieval should only be done by a police officer.” 191 Under the Virginia Tech rules, Assistant Principal Joel Myrick would have been a bad employee when he took the gun which was being surrendered by a killer who had already murdered his mother, shot several students, and was on his way to kill more—until Myrick stopped him.192 One set of values says, “Don’t be a hero; don’t try to stop the gunman; don’t even accept the gun if he tries to give it to you.” A different set of values says, “Choose to save the lives of innocents, even if you risk your own by doing so.” What would we think of a university that told its employees and students, “Don’t be a hero. If you see someone choking to death, or drowning, don’t try to save them. Be a good witness. Just call the police. Never mind whether you are trained in first aid, or whether you are an intercollegiate swimmer with training in water rescue. Don’t be a hero.”? We would call such instructions monstrous. The instructions are no less monstrous in the context of stopping an active shooter. Of course the circumstances can vary. A person who is strong enough to throw an active shooter to the ground might not know how to swim. Plunging into the water, or moving toward an active shooter involves a decision to risk one’s own life—although in the case of an active shooter, one’s life is already in extremely grave peril if one does not use counter-force. On the other hand, accepting a gun from someone who is trying to surrender it takes no skill at all; everyone who has at least one arm with the strength to hold a few pounds can do so. Are Americans “a nation of cowards”? Attorney General Eric Holder recently said that they are because they do not have frank discussions about race.193 He observed that one reason that such discussions do not take place often enough is “that certain subjects are off limits and that to explore them risks, at best embarrassment, and, at worst, the questioning of one’s character.”194 Certainly organizations such as the Foundation for Individual Rights in Education have documented many cases in which administrators have punished students or faculty for violations of political 191 Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University, Environmental, Health and Safety Services, Workplace Violence, http://www.ehss.vt.edu/programs/EPP_workplace.php (last visited October 31, 2009). A web search for the above-quoted words found them in the policies of Northwestern University, George Mason University, the University of Michigan, and John F. Kennedy University. 192 See supra text accompanying note 148. 193 Remarks as Prepared for Delivery by Attorney General Eric Holder at the Department of Justice African American History Month Program, Feb. 18, 2009, available at http://www.usdoj.gov/ ag/speeches/2009/ag-speech-090218.html. 194 Id. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 557 195 correctness, including on issues of race. In a famous 1994 essay in The Public Interest, attorney Jeffrey Snyder also called Americans “A Nation of Cowards.”196 He chose that title for the essay because he argued that too many Americans refuse to take personal responsibility for their own safety. Rather than having a firearm in the home which they know how to use (and he points out that becoming solidly proficient with a firearm is far easier than learning how to play a musical instrument), many people expect the police to protect them in an emergency. This attitude is immoral and selfish, he contends. He argues that it is wrong to expect a police officer to risk his life to save yours, if you are not willing to take responsibility for defending your own life.197 Thus, for the First Amendment rights of freedom of speech and of the press, or the Second Amendment right of self-defense, some universities seem determined to create a nation of cowards. The debate over campus carry exposes a much broader cultural divide: the divide between traditional American attitudes of self-reliance, confidence, and readiness to take personal action, versus a desiccated feeling that individuals are victims of their circumstances, and not capable of changing them, except perhaps by asking the government to change their circumstances for them. One expression of the latter attitude is to assert with certainty—even though the person making the assertion knows virtually nothing about defensive firearms tactics, or about any form of active self-defense—that armed citizen defenders would necessarily make any situation worse. For example, after a campus carry bill passed out of a Louisiana House committee, an editorial in the Shreveport Times warned, “The picture that arises here is of concealed-carry-permitted students and faculty missing the bad guy and shooting each other.”198 Again, this is an argument that has arisen frequently over the past two decades, as “Shall Issue” laws have become the national norm. The experience of armed defenders shows the inaccuracy of the prediction that armed defenders are incompetent. Had the Shreveport Times merely examined the situation in its own state of Louisiana, it would have found that since 1996,199 there have been over 27,000 Louisiana citizens who 195 For examples, see Foundation for Individual Rights in Education, http://www.thefire.org/ (last visited Nov. 16, 2009). 196 See Jeffrey R. Snyder, A Nation of Cowards, PUB. INT., Fall 1993, at 40. 197 Id. at 43–44. 198 Editorial, Concealed-Carry Guns Have No Place on College Campuses, SHREVEPORT TIMES, May 6, 2008, at 1B. 199 See LA. REV. STAT. ANN. § 40:1379.3 (2008) (providing that as of April 1996, the Department of Public Safety and Corrections would be responsible for rules and regulations for issue of handgun permits). 558 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 200 have been issued concealed carry permits. Most of them have never had to use the gun for self-defense, and for those who have, the mere display or brandishing of the firearm has been sufficient to encourage the criminal to stop the attack and leave the scene. According to the 2007–08 Louisiana State Police Annual Legislative Report (the only report which is available online), in the last reporting year, there were no “documented accidents or deaths involving concealed handgun permittees.”201 Nationally, in our “Shall Issue” nation, the story is much the same. There are hundreds of reported instances of CCW licensees actually firing their guns and, in so doing, successfully stopping a violent crime in progress. The reported instances of an innocent bystander being shot are few.202 Again, this Article does not attempt to re-open the general debate on “Shall Issue” in the United States. That debate took place over the last two decades, and it has been resolved against advocates who insist that Americans are a nation of klutzes—that ordinary citizens who have taken a training class will be so incompetent with a gun that their attempts to stop a violent crime in progress will do more harm than good. Writer Clayton Cramer is perhaps best known as the scholar who did the most to expose the hoax of Michael Bellesiles, a temporarily awardwinning author whose book, Arming America, claimed that guns were rare in America until shortly before the Civil War, but whose purported evidence (such as probate records) turned out to have been fabricated.203 Cramer also maintains a “Civilian Gun Self-Defense Blog” which collects media reports of lawful self-defense by persons with firearms.204 The blog does not purport to provide the full picture of armed self-defense, only a fairly thorough collection of the instances which are reported in the media. The blog was created in 2003 and by 2009 had collected 4000 cases. At that point, Cramer tabulated some cumulative data. He found that of the 4000 cases there were six incidents in which a criminal took a gun from the defender. There was one incident of a defender mistakenly shooting at 200 CONCEALED HANDGUN PERMIT UNIT, OFFICE OF STATE POLICE, LA. DEP’T OF PUB. SAFETY, ANNUAL LEGISLATIVE REPORT 2007–2008, at 1 (2008), available at http://www.lsp.org/pdf/ chAnnualReport07-08.pdf. 201 Id. at i. 202 See generally WATERS, supra note 127 (describing stories of people who have saved themselves from harm by use of a firearm); see also Howard Nemerov, Brady Campaign: Biased, Inaccurate Research, AUSTIN EXAMINER, Apr. 12, 2009, http://www.examiner.com/x-2879-AustinGun-Rights-Examiner~y2009m4d12-Brady-Campaign-Biased-inaccurate-research (questioning the credibility of the claims made in BRADY CENTER, supra note 146). 203 See MICHAEL A. BELLESILES, ARMING AMERICA: THE ORIGINS OF A NATIONAL GUN CULTURE (2000); CLAYTON E. CRAMER, ARMED AMERICA: THE REMARKABLE STORY OF HOW AND WHY GUNS BECAME AS AMERICAN AS APPLE PIE xii—xvi (2006). The former book was eventually withdrawn by its publisher Alfred A. Knopf. 204 Civilian Gun Self-Defense Blog, http://www.claytoncramer.com/gundefenseblog/blogger.html (last visited Oct. 8, 2009). 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 559 someone (police who were investigating a burglary at an auto dealership started shooting at an employee, and he returned fire). And, while most self-defense incidents occurred in a place where carry permits are not needed (e.g., one’s home, one’s own business, or, in some states, one’s automobile), there were 212 self-defense cases with licensed carry permit holders.205 We know from experience that the millions of Americans who carry licensed handguns almost everywhere in their states are not a nation of klutzes. Accordingly, one must ask whether the millions of Americans who do not act incompetently when the need for armed self-defense arises will somehow turn into dangerous buffoons if the attack takes place on a college campus. To emphasize again, the question involves only persons who are already licensed by the state to carry almost everywhere within the state. On college campuses, by far the most common type of violent crime is similar to that which occurs off-campus: a young woman is assaulted and raped in a parking lot, a young man is surrounded by some gangsters who rob him and then beat him up for fun.206 The graduate teaching assistant who works late at school, and who wishes to defend herself from an attack in the school parking lot, is no less competent to do so there than she is in the parking lot of the grocery store. If she is capable of responsible selfdefense in the grocery store parking lot (and the state has already determined that she is), she is equally capable in the school parking lot. An active shooter situation at a school is more complicated. Compared to an ordinary violent crime, there are likely to be many more people in the area. Depending on the particular circumstance, the armed defender might be just a few feet away from the attacker—a distance that is typical for ordinary self-defense situations—or on the other side of a large room. But even in the latter situation, the balance of risks favors active selfdefense. Imagine a scenario in which all of the killer’s victims are either lying on the ground (following the Brady Center’s advice to “play dead”)207 or are running in panic. Nobody is trying to stop the killer; all the victims are following the university rules of “Don’t be a hero” and “Never attempt to disarm” a violent attacker. For the people on the ground, the killer can inflict a head shot at close range that will very likely 205 Clayton Cramer, A Milestone: The 4000th Entry on the Civilian Gun Self-Defense Blog, http://www.claytoncramer.com/weblog/2009_04_19_archive.html#6156324322914958524 (Apr. 21, 2009, 08:12 EST). In one notable off-campus incident in College Park, Georgia, two masked men attacked a birthday party in a student apartment, apparently intended to rob, rape, and murder them. One student grabbed a gun from his backpack, and shot one of the attackers. The other attacker fled. “I think all of us are really cognizant of the fact that we could have all been killed,” remarked student Charles Bailey. College Student Shoots, Kills Home Invader, WSBTV, May 7, 2009, http://www.wsbtv.com/news/19365762/detail.html. 206 BAUM & KLAUS, supra note 158, at 2. 207 See discussion supra notes 179–80 and accompanying text. 560 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 be fatal. Hitting a moving target is more difficult. Of course, the killer’s chance of inflicting a fatal or crippling wound on the moving target are much better if he is concentrating on accurate shooting. Now consider a second scenario. This time, someone is shooting back at the killer. It has been said that “when a man knows he is to be hanged in a fortnight, it concentrates his mind wonderfully.”208 So does being shot at. It is much more difficult to shoot accurately if someone is shooting at you. If the net result is that the attacker and the defender both end up firing a lot of inaccurate shots, the result is likely to be a large net savings of lives. The killer will never have the time for an accurate head shot on a close-range victim, and his chances against the mobile victims will diminish greatly. Maybe a stray shot from the killer will hit someone, but that shot is less likely to be an accurate one which would inflict a fatal or crippling injury. There would be a risk that a third party could be injured by a stray shot from the defender. But the defender would have not been aiming at the third party and trying to kill him, so there is some chance that the stray shot would not inflict a critical injury. Massively degrading the lethal accuracy of a shooter who is intent on mass homicide is likely to save many more lives than might be lost because one or two of the intended victims were fighting back. 3. The Police Will Kill People Because of Mistaken Identity Some campus police chiefs worry that police officers coming on the scene will not know if the shooter is a legitimate defender, or is the attacker. Identifying the “kid without a plan” would take up police time while they took him into custody. Or he might be mistakenly shot by police.209 These objections, however, do not just apply to campus defense. They are applicable in any case where police come upon a crime scene in which the victim is resisting successfully. Already in most of the United States, concealed permit holders can carry almost everywhere in public. The risk of police confusion or mistake is no greater on a campus than it is anywhere else in a state. After decades of experience with licensed carry around the nation, opponents of licensed carry cannot point to frequent instances of the police harmfully mistaking an armed victim with a carry 208 JAMES BOSWELL, 2 THE LIFE OF SAMUEL JOHNSON 152 (1791) (attributing the aphorism to Johnson). 209 Michele Linck, No Guns on South Dakota Campuses, For Now, SIOUX CITY J., Feb. 16, 2008, http://www.siouxcityjournal.com/articles/2008/02/16/news/local/660b198e85dff68a862573f10016cba7 .txt; see also Geoff Fox, UCF Student Group Seeks Guns Rights, TAMPA TRIB., Apr. 4, 2008, at 1 (reporting on the University of Central Florida police chief asking, “How are the police supposed to know the good guys from the bad guys?”); Israel Saenz, Students Wearing Holsters Trigger Debate at A&M-CC, CORPUS CHRISTI CALLER TIMES, Apr. 23, 2008, http://www.caller.com/news/2008/apr/23/ students-wearing-holsters-trigger-debate-at-am/ (questioning campus police chief saying that his force of sixteen officers would find it “hard . . . to differentiate between the good guys and the bad guys”). 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 561 license for a perpetrator. Indeed, quite apart from citizens having guns for self-defense, police often face situations where they have to make a quick decision about who is the attacker and who is the victim. Encountering a brawl in a bar, a domestic violence incident, or a robbery in which the victim is fighting back, the police may not know immediately who is the perpetrator and who is the victim. The police are specifically trained to deal with such situations, and this training helps them avoid shooting the victims by mistake. Moreover, in a “Shall Issue” state, the legislature has already decided that in almost all public places, the benefits of armed resistance by victims far outweigh the potential risk of a police mistake. If a would-be mass murderer starts trying to kill people at a shopping mall, or a public park, then the “Shall Issue” law makes it entirely possible that by the time the police arrive, one or more victims will have already started shooting back. But the most important fact is that the police are fairly unlikely to encounter the active shooter. In the large majority of active shooter incidents at schools, when the perpetrator hears that the police are close by, he kills himself.210 Not every single active shooter incident ends this way, but the number of cases in which the imminent arrival of the police leads to suicide by the active shooter far outnumber the cases in which the active shooter fights it out with the police.211 So, by the time the police get there, the shooting will probably be over. This will either be because the killer heard the police coming and killed himself, or it will be because somewhat earlier, a victim was able to fight back and the killer was stopped sooner. In case the police burst in on a gun battle in progress, the killer’s prompt suicide may well end any confusion. 210 See supra text accompanying note 114. For an example of such a response by an active shooter, see supra note 139. MSNBC commentator Clint Van Zandt (formerly the FBI’s Supervisory Special Agent during the Waco siege) writes: I totally agree that a number of armed students, faculty or staff on the Tech campus could have made a difference during [the murderer’s] killing spree, but I’m not sure the difference would have resulted in a better outcome. Would the armed students know who, among those with guns, was the real shooter that needed to be stopped? How should the police officers who flooded the campus looking for the shooter have responded when confronted by one or two or 50 students and others wielding guns as they ran helter skelter across the campus quad? Could the situation, as terrible as it was, have become even more tragic were innocents to have shot other innocents in the haste of a moment, trying to identify the real shooter as they looked down the barrel of their own gun while their heart beat so loud they couldn’t hear themselves think? Clint Van Zandt, Would Students Be Safer if They Carried Guns? MSNBC, Aug. 20, 2007, http://www.msnbc.msn.com/id/20301979//. It takes more than a string of rhetorical questions to seriously imagine a scenario in which the confusion resulting from two (or fifty) students resisting a mass killer would result in more deaths than the thirty-five for which the killer had free rein against defenseless victims. 211 562 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 4. Training Every one of the competence arguments that has been deployed against “Shall Issue” laws in general, or campus carry in particular, can be used against the principle of police officers having guns. After all, police officers do occasionally make mistakes. They shoot the wrong person, or they aim at the right person and hit the wrong person. Or an off-duty or undercover police officer starts firing at a violent criminal, and then when uniformed police arrive, they are confused about who is the bad guy. These situations do happen, albeit not frequently. Society sensibly decides that the net public safety benefit of armed police far outweighs the statistical certainty (over the long run) of occasional police errors. In the forty “Shall Issue” states, the legislatures have made a similar determination about the public safety benefit of armed citizens in general. “But the police are trained!” comes the opposition’s refrain. The answer in most states has been to require that concealed handgun permitees also be trained. The training does not need to be as extensive as that which a police officer receives; to carry a handgun for lawful protection, citizens do not need to know how to conduct vehicle pursuits or how to interrogate a suspect without violating his Miranda rights. The citizens are trained to know the self-defense laws of their state, particularly those involving lethal force, and to know the fundamentals of gun safety and defensive gun use. Experience has shown, nationally, that this level of training is fully sufficient so that the parade of horribles offered by opponents of “Shall Issue” does not come true. One way to test the sincerity of the argument, “But the police have training,” is to meet it. That is precisely what the Nevada Regents did, before they changed their minds. Under the plan that won initial approval in Nevada, the only people who could carry on Nevada public higher education campuses would be professors and other full-time employees who, at their own expense, underwent the training necessary to become reserve police officers, and who were then formally sworn as such officers.212 The furious opposition to this proposal from some persons in Nevada higher education suggests that the opposition to campus carry may sometimes arise from visceral hostility to guns or to self-defense, rather than to the actual harm that campus carry could cause. While this Article argues in favor of campus carry, it recognizes that political realities and cultural norms differ widely. So while the ideal approach might be to follow the Utah policy, a much narrower policy, such as the Nevada plan, would be much better than nothing. 212 See supra notes 67–70 and accompanying text. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 563 5. Killers Will Adopt New Tactics Which Make Resistance Futile According to the Brady Center, armed defense would be futile, because attackers might respond by “wearing flak jackets.”213 This seems unlikely. First of all, the real-world experience is that criminals do run the risk of encountering an armed victim when they break into an occupied home (since about half of the homes in America have guns),214 and likewise the risk of encountering an armed victim outside the home in the forty states with “Shall Issue” laws. The resulting problem of criminals wearing what the Brady Center calls “flak jackets” has not emerged.215 Certainly, criminal use of body armor has not made it futile for police or ordinary citizens to possess firearms for lawful defense. Moreover, body armor (or a “flak jacket”) does not mean that the bullet bounces off harmlessly, as when comic book criminals try to shoot Superman. The body armor will stop the bullet from penetrating, but the force of the bullet can still be enough to break a rib, or knock a person to the ground.216 Either result would impair the killer at least temporarily and thereby provide more opportunity for victims to escape, or to pin the killer to the ground. And a broken rib, or similar injury, stands a very good chance of greatly degrading the killer’s accuracy. The Brady Center also predicts that having armed teachers “would simply make the teacher the likely first victim.”217 This is opposed to the current situation, where the teacher might be the second, third, or fourth victim. If we hypothesize that the Brady Center scenario came true, and an attacker killed a teacher by surprise, the killer would have no element of surprise against the other armed adults who might be in the building. Their prompt actions might well prevent the killer from methodically murdering defenseless schoolchildren. 213 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 10. See David B. Kopel, Lawyers, Guns, and Burglars, 43 ARIZ. L. REV. 345, 349–52 (2001). Presumably, they mean bullet-resistant body armor. Flak jackets are a type of obsolete military gear, although the term is sometimes loosely used for modern body armor. See Apparel Search, Flack Jacket Definition, http://www.apparelsearch.com/Definitions/Clothing/flak_jacket.htm (last visited Nov. 16, 2009). [Flak jackets were] originally developed by the Wilkinson Sword company during World War II to help protect Royal Air Force (RAF) air personnel from the flying debris and shrapnel thrown by German anti-aircraft guns’ flak (Fliegerabwehrkanone), a type of exploding shell. The jacket consisted of titanium plates sewn into a waistcoat made of ballistic nylon (a material engineered by the DuPont company); therefore, flak jackets functioned as an evolved form of plate armour . . . . Ultimately, however, the jackets proved to be tragically ineffective, and are now generally considered to be inferior to body armor. In modern usage, the term flak jacket sometimes refers to contemporary bulletproof vests. Id. 216 See L. Cannon, Behind Armour Blunt Trauma—An Emerging Problem, 147 J. ROYAL ARMY MED. CORPS 87, 87 (2001) (discussing effects of projectile impact on body armor). 217 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 10. 214 215 564 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 C. Faculty and Adult Students Are Incipient Killers Even if licensed campus carry did save lives by deterring or terminating mass homicides, the question remains as to whether the net result would be more deaths on campus, because teachers and/or students would commit so many more crimes because they were legally carrying firearms. Empirical evidence suggests not. 1. People Licensed to Carry Handguns for Lawful Defense Are Very Dangerous If people with concealed carry permits were already known to be a menace to society, we would not want them on campus. Conversely, if permitees had already demonstrated themselves to be highly law-abiding, then we would want to exclude them from campus only if there were some reason why they might become abnormally dangerous on campus. So the first issue is whether CCW permitees are dangerous in general. Several states require a state police agency or the Attorney General to compile an annual report about CCW licenses, as well as revocations of permits, and the behavior of permitees. These state requirements are examined below. a. Minnesota In Minnesota, the Department of Public Safety must produce an annual report detailing concealed carry license issuances, denials, and revocations.218 As of December 31, 2008, there were 56,919 valid permits in the state.219 In 2008, twenty-one permits were revoked; most of the revocations were not for conduct with the firearm, but because the person was discovered to be ineligible by law to possess firearms (e.g., marijuana was found in the person’s home), or because the sheriff, using discretion which exists in the Minnesota “Shall Issue” statute, had made a factual determination that the applicant was a danger to himself or others. There were two revocations for carrying a firearm while intoxicated, and one revocation for a felony conviction for a crime involving use of a firearm.220 Since the Minnesota law went into effect, there have been 454 crimes committed by permit holders. (Because a permit holder may be charged with more than one crime for a particular act, the number of permit holders who were convicted of crimes is lower, although the exact number is not clear from the report.) These crimes range from “Address change—failure 218 MINN. STAT. ANN. § 624.714 (West 2009). BUREAU OF CRIMINAL APPREHENSION, DEP’T OF PUBLIC SAFETY, STATE OF MINN., Permit to Carry Valid Permits Report, in 2008 PERMIT TO CARRY REPORT 1 (2009), available at http://www.dps.state.mn.us/bca/CJIS/Documents/CarryPermit/2008PTSReport.pdf. 220 BUREAU OF CRIMINAL APPREHENSION, DEP’T OF PUBLIC SAFETY, STATE OF MINN., Revocations Explanation Report, in 2008 PERMIT TO CARRY REPORT 1–2 (2009), available at http://www.dps.state.mn.us/bca/CJIS/Documents/CarryPermit/2008PTSReport.pdf. 219 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 565 to notify” to “Traffic—other” (comprising sixty-seven of the crimes). The report also states whether the person was known to have “used [a] pistol” in the crime. There are forty such crimes, although “used” must be interpreted liberally; for example, three of the “used [a] pistol” crimes are for driving while intoxicated.221 Presumably, the intoxicated driver had the handgun in his car (the permit allows a person to possess the gun while in an automobile, but possession while intoxicated is always forbidden), but it seems doubtful that the handgun was actually “used” for the act of driving while intoxicated. Thus, since 2003, we have 56,919 permitees and forty handgun crimes, or about one such crime per 1423 permitees. It would be difficult to find a significant demographic group in the United States with a lower rate of handgun crimes. b. Michigan According to the Michigan State Police report, there were 312 permit revocations in Michigan between July 2007 and June 2008. The report also tracks crimes involving concealed carry permitees. Again, it compiles all cases in which someone was charged, including instances in which the person was acquitted, or the charges were dismissed, or charges are still pending and have not been resolved.222 The Michigan report lists 161 total charges (involving permitees) for “Brandishing or Use of Pistol” during the previous fiscal year.223 Because of overlapping charges, this involves fewer than 161 criminal acts. Out of these 161 charges, the data suggest that the number of convictions would be approximately forty-five.224 Accounting for overlapping charges, the actual number of criminal acts might be between twenty-five and thirtyfive. The report does not specify whether the alleged crime occurred in a 221 BUREAU OF CRIMINAL APPREHENSION, DEP’T OF PUBLIC SAFETY, STATE OF MINN., Section 5b available at Reporting Requirement, in 2008 PERMIT TO CARRY REPORT 11–12 (2009), http://www.dps.state.mn.us/bca/CJIS/Documents/CarryPermit/2008PTSReport.pdf. 222 MICH. STATE POLICE CRIMINAL JUSTICE INFO. CTR., Statewide Totals, in CONCEALED PISTOL LICENSURE: ANNUAL REPORT, JULY 1, 2007 TO JUNE 30, 2008, at 1–22 (2008), available at http://www.michigan.gov/documents/msp/CPL_Annual_Report_2007-2008_269128_7.pdf. 223 Id. at 22. 224 The category “Carrying or possessing firearm when committing or attempting to commit felony” (a sentence enhancer which would presumably involve most of the separately-listed nonregulatory crimes, such as burglary), lists seventy-nine cases of “Total charges.” MICH. STATE POLICE CRIMINAL JUSTICE INFO. CTR., supra note 222, at 15. Of these, forty-six are still pending; twenty-two of the charges were dismissed; two are classified as “Not Guilty/Not Responsible”; and nine are classified as “Conviction/Found Responsible.” Id. Thus, in over half the cases, the charges are unresolved; in the cases that were resolved, a little over a quarter of persons charged (nine out of thirtythree) were convicted. Yet, along the same line, listing the fact that there were only nine convictions, there is a listing of twenty-seven instances of “Brandishing or Use of Pistol” during the crime. Id. Based on the Report’s rate at which charges turn into convictions, we could estimate that slightly over one-fourth of these cases, that is, seven or eight, would result in a determination that a licensee used a pistol in a felony or an attempt to commit a felony in Michigan between July 1, 2007, and June 30, 2008. 566 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 place where the license might have facilitated the crime (e.g., while the gun was being carried on a public sidewalk) or elsewhere (e.g., a crime in the home). Michigan’s “Shall Issue” licensing law went into effect on July 1, 2001. Licenses are valid for five years and may not be renewed before the final year of the licensing period.225 Thus, the total number of valid licenses in Michigan (as of the date of the last report, June 30, 2008) would be somewhere between the number of licenses issued in the previous four years (172,140) and the number issued in the last five years (203,261).226 Even if it was assumed that every “charge” merited a criminal conviction, and that every charge involved a separate person (that is, there were no duplicate charges filed), there were 161 misdeeds in 2007 and 2008 out of an approximate Michigan licensed population of 190,000 people. This is a rate of less than one per one thousand; once the conviction rate is factored in, and duplicate charges eliminated, the rate approaches one in five thousand. As in other states, Michigan licensees are not absolutely perfect. As a group, however, they seem to be overwhelmingly law-abiding, especially with regard to their licensed carry pistols. c. Ohio The annual report of the Ohio Attorney General provides less detailed information. As of December 31, 2008, the state sheriffs had issued 142,732 permanent licenses227 since the Ohio law went into effect in 2004.228 Since then there have been 639 revocations.229 Sheriffs do not 225 MICH. COMP. LAWS ANN. § 28.425l (West 2009). MICH. STATE POLICE CRIMINAL JUSTICE INFO. CTR., supra note 222 (The number of licenses issued was 56,919. The number of licenses revoked was 312.); MICH. STATE POLICE CRIMINAL JUSTICE INFO. CTR., CONCEALED PISTOL LICENSURE: ANNUAL REPORT JULY 1, 2006 TO JUNE 30, 2007 (2007), available at http://www.michigan.gov/documents/msp/CCW_Annual_Report_2006-2007_ 228850_7.pdf (The number of licenses issued was 23,790. The number of licenses revoked was 163.); MICH. STATE POLICE CRIMINAL JUSTICE INFO. CTR., CONCEALED PISTOL LICENSURE: ANNUAL REPORT JULY 1, 2005 TO JUNE 30, 2006 (2006), available at http://www.michigan.gov/documents/msp/ CCWAnnualReport_181416_7.pdf (The number of licenses issued was 36,754. The number of licenses revoked was 108.); MICH. STATE POLICE CRIMINAL JUSTICE INFO. CTR., CONCEALED PISTOL LICENSURE: ANNUAL REPORT JULY 1, 2004 TO JUNE 30, 2005 (2005), available at http://www.michigan.gov/documents/CCWAnnual_Report 2004_2005_143245_7.pdf (The number of licenses issued was 54,677. The number of licenses revoked was 121.); MICH. STATE POLICE CRIMINAL JUSTICE INFO. CTR., CONCEALED PISTOL LICENSURE: ANNUAL REPORT JULY 1, 2003 TO JUNE 30, 2004 (2004), available at http://www.michigan.gov/documents/CCW_Annual_Report_ 108680_7.pdf (The number of licenses issued was 31,121. The number of licenses revoked was 119.). The grand total would be reduced by the number of revocations in each year. 227 RICHARD CORDRAY, OHIO ATTORNEY GEN., OHIO’S CONCEALED HANDGUNS LAW: 2008 ANNUAL REPORT 3 (2009), available at http://www.ohioattorneygeneral.gov/getattachment/ 74fa629f0bb9-48e1-9d81-7c27be9bbc57/Concealed-Carry-Weapons-Annual-Report.aspx. 228 OHIO REV. CODE ANN. § 2923.1213 (West 2006). 229 CORDRAY, supra note 227, at 5. There were 42 revocations in 2004, 75 revocations in 2005, 194 revocations in 2006, 171 revocations in 2007, and 157 revocations in 2008, totaling 639 revocations since the implementation of the Ohio law. Id. 226 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 567 report the reason for a revocation, and among the causes for a revocation are that the license holder moved out of state, died, or no longer desired to have the permit.230 The Ohio report does not specify how many of the 639 involved revocations were for conviction of a crime, or how many involved misuse of a firearm. d. Louisiana In Louisiana, there have been 27,422 permits issued since the Shall Issue law went into effect in 1996.231 Per capita, the figure seems surprisingly low compared to Michigan, Minnesota, and Ohio. The explanation is probably that Louisiana (like most states in the South and the West) does not require a permit in order to carry a firearm in an automobile for protection. Accordingly, people in Louisiana (unlike people in Minnesota, Michigan, or Ohio) who only want to carry a defensive firearm in their automobile do not need to spend the money and time to obtain a CCW permit. Since 1996, there have been 259 permit revocations in Louisiana.232 Prior to July 15, 2004, the state police computer did not record the reason for a revocation. Since then, there have been 137 revocations for which the causes are known. Only one was for the following reason: “[p]ermittee convicted of a crime of violence.”233 There were twenty other revocations where the cause was the permittee being charged with a bill of information for a felony offense (but not necessarily convicted). There was one other case in which the revocation was because the permittee was the subject of a domestic restraining order. The Louisiana report does not specify which, if any, crimes involved the use of a firearm. The rest of the revocations involve situations in which the permittee became ineligible to continue to hold the permit, but the category had nothing even theoretically to do with the misuse of a gun. So twenty-two of the 137 revocations (sixteen percent) described above might have involved gun misuse. If one applies a similar proportion to the 122 unclassified pre-2004 revocations, then one would have about twenty more cases that might have involved gun misuse. This would be forty-two out of 27,422 people over a twelve-year period, or slightly more than one in one thousand permitees. If taken into account that some people who are indicted of a crime are not found guilty, and that the large majority of felony crimes do not involve misuse of a gun, then the number of cases of gun misuse for Louisiana permittees would be much less than one in one 230 Id. See CONCEALED HANDGUN PERMIT UNIT, supra note 200, at 1. 232 Id. at 14. 233 Id. 231 568 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 234 thousand. e. Texas In Texas, the Department of Public Safety produces an annual report which details the total number of Texas convictions for various crimes and the total number of such convictions among Concealed Handgun License (“CHL”) holders. It includes burglary, violent crimes, sex offenses, weapons offenses, and various other serious crimes, but not drug crimes or most white collar crimes. The latest report, for 2006, shows 61,539 total convictions of these crimes in all of Texas, with 144 attributable to CHL holders. Thus, licensees accounted for two-tenths of less than one percent of the Texas convictions.235 The Texas report does not indicate which crimes were perpetrated with guns.236 As of 2006, there were 258,162 active license holders in Texas.237 The estimated Texas population in 2006 was 23,507,783.238 This computes to a Texas crime rate (counting the crimes in the Texas report) of 0.00262 per capita; that is, 262 such crimes per 100,000 Texans. In contrast, the per capita crime rate for CHL holders is 0.00054; that is, about fifty-four such crimes per 100,000 CHL holders. So, a Texan CHL is only about twentyone percent as likely as a non-CHL holder to be convicted of one of these crimes. This is consistent with other research findings that compared to a CHL holder, a male Texan in the general public is 7.9 times more likely to be arrested for a violent crime than a male Texan CHL holder; for females, the figure is 7.5 times more likely.239 Of the CHL holders who were 234 Id. at 10. There were also 417 license suspensions since the Louisiana law went into effect. Of those, 211 were pre-2004, and hence the reasons for the suspensions were not recorded. Of the 216 suspensions with known reasons (that is, after July 15, 2004), none involved gun misuse. The overwhelming reason was failure to comply with the Louisiana statute requiring a permittee to notify the deputy secretary of public safety services if he is arrested for any cause, including for a misdemeanor. Failure to do so results in a ninety day license suspension. See LA. REV. STAT. ANN. § 40:1379.3(R)(1) (2004); LA. ADMIN. CODE tit. 55 § 1313(B)(5) (2009). 235 REGULATORY LICENSING SERV., CONCEALED HANDGUN LICENSING BUREAU, TEX. DEP’T OF PUB. SAFETY, CONVICTION RATES FOR CONCEALED HANDGUN LICENSE HOLDERS 4 (2009), available at http://www.txdps.state.tx.us/administration/crime_records/chl/ConvictionRatesReport2006.pdf. Again, as with the Michigan report, many of these crimes appear to involve multiple charges growing out of a single criminal act. 236 For offense names that include the use of a weapon that might be a firearm, the conviction figures for CHL holders were as follows: Deadly Conduct Discharge Firearm, 1; Unlawful Carrying Weapon, 24; Unlawful Carry Handgun License Holder, 10 (presumably this offense involves carrying the licensed handgun in violation of permit restrictions; the previous offense would involve carrying some other weapon); Aggravated Assault W/Deadly Weapon, 9. Id. at 1–3. 237 Tex. Dep’t of Pub. Safety, Regulatory Licensing Serv., Concealed Handgun Licensing Bureau, Active License Holders and Certified Instructors, available at http://www.txdps.state.tx.us/ administration/crime_records/chl/PDF/ActLicAndInstr/ActiveLicandInstr2006.pdf. 238 Tex. Dep’t of State Health Servs., Estimated Texas Population by Area, 2006 available at http://www.dshs.state.tx.us/chs/popdat/ST2006.shtm (last visited Aug. 31, 2009). 239 WILLIAM E. STURDEVANT, AN ANALYSIS OF THE ARREST RATE OF TEXAS CONCEALED HANDGUN LICENSE HOLDERS AS COMPARED TO THE ARREST RATE OF THE ENTIRE TEXAS 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 569 arrested, 22% were convicted of the crime for which they were arrested, 32% were convicted of a lesser offense, and 46% were not convicted of any offense.240 Of course the vast majority of the general public does not perpetrate serious crimes. Only a tiny minority does so, and among CHL holders, the minority is even smaller. f. Florida In Florida, as of July 31, 2009, there were 607,977 active concealed handgun licensees; since October 1, 1987, there have been 1,565,251 licenses issued. Since 1987, there have been 4927 licenses revoked. Of the revocations, 4209 were for “Crime After Licensure.” Among those, 167 were for a crime with “Firearm Utilized.”241 Thus, the per capita firearms crime rate for licensed Floridians was 0.00027. That is 27 firearms crimes per 100,000 licensed Florida residents. g. The Brady Center’s Claims The Brady Center argues vehemently that people with carry licenses are much too dangerous to be allowed on campus. However, the Brady Center does not cite any government data, such as the data presented above, about crime rates for licensees. Instead, the Brady Center asserts that “thousands of people with CCW licenses have committed atrocious acts of gun violence.”242 The only support for this claim is a citation to the appendix of another one of its monographs, which is said to list “dozens of criminal offenses committed by CCW licenses in Florida alone,”243 plus a Los Angeles Times article, which identifies four violent crimes perpetrated by Texans with licenses.244 The cross-cited Brady monograph lists the criminal offenses behind 105 Florida permit revocations in 1987–97.245 Most of these listings provide no indication that the person whose permit was revoked had committed any crime with a gun, let alone an “atrocious act of gun POPULATION, 1996–1998, REVISED TO INCLUDE 1999 DATA (Sept. 1, 2000), available at http://www.txchia.org/sturdevant.htm. 240 Id. 241 Fla. Dep’t of Agric. and Consumer Servs., Div. of Licensing, Concealed Weapon/Firearm Summary Report: October 1, 1987–July 31, 2009, available at http://licgweb.doacs.state.fl.us/stats/cw_ monthly.html; Fla. Dep’t of Agric. and Consumer Servs., Div. of Licensing, Number of Licensees by Type, available at http://licgweb.doacs.state.fl.us/stats/licensetypecount.html. 242 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at iv. 243 Id. at 34–35. 244 William C. Rempel & Richard A. Serrano, Felons Get Concealed Gun Licenses Under Bush’s ‘Tough’ Law, L.A. TIMES, Oct. 3, 2000, at A1 (noting also that more than 3000 licensees had been arrested, although the article did not provide information about whether the arrests led to a conviction or whether the alleged crimes had anything to do with a gun). Other research has found that forty-six percent of Texas licensees who were arrested were not convicted of any crime. See STURDEVANT, supra note 239. 245 See CENTER TO PREVENT HANDGUN VIOLENCE, supra note 171, at 1C–4C (noting crimes committed by Florida licensees since the passing of Florida’s CCW law in October 1987). 570 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 246 violence.” To the contrary, only thirteen listed offenses include use of a firearm as an element, such as “adjudication withheld on felony assault with a deadly weapon,” “adjudication withheld on felony aggravated assault with a firearm,” or “convicted of felony possession with intent to distribute cocaine, possession of a firearm during drug trafficking offense.” Indeed, for the vast majority of the offenses—such as assault or drug sales—the absence of a firearms count would seem to indicate that a firearm was not used. Likewise, there is no indication that a firearm was used in the many offenses of simple possession of marijuana, passing fraudulent checks, or other non-violent crimes. In short, the Brady Center’s self-cited data, even if extrapolated nationally, do not come remotely close to supporting its allegation that “thousands of people with CCW licenses have committed atrocious acts of gun violence.”247 In the Brady Center policy paper opposing campus carry, Appendix A asserts that a CCW permit “in no way guarantees public safety. In fact, it can often be a license to kill.”248 Of course there are no policies that “guarantee” public safety; the question is whether the policy improves public safety. As for the “license to kill,” the Brady Center provides a litany of twenty-nine cases from around the country,249 presumably the most atrocious ones it could find. Now, if every one of these involved a criminal homicide, these twentynine cases (out of a national CCW licensee population of about five million) would mean that CCW licensees have a criminal homicide rate far below that of the general population. But most of the twenty-nine most atrocious CCW stories that the Brady Center could find do not even involve conduct with a gun that was carried pursuant to a CCW permit.250 Of those that do, not all of them are exactly the stuff of “a license to kill.” For example, United States Representative John Hostettler forgot to take his handgun out of his bag when going through airport security; he pleaded guilty to a misdemeanor.251 A former judge made the same mistake and 246 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at IV. It seems that the only way that the claim that “thousands of people with CCW licenses have committed atrocious acts of gun violence” could literally be true would be if every act of lawful selfdefense by a CCW licensee were counted as “an atrocious act of gun violence.” Regarding self-defense as “atrocious gun violence” would not be inconsistent with Mrs. Brady’s professed view: “To me . . . the only reason for guns in civilian hands is for sporting purposes.” Tom Jackson, Keeping the Battle Alive, TAMPA TRIB., Oct. 21, 1993. Mr. Brady takes the same view; when asked if handgun possession was permissible, he replied, “For target shooting, that’s okay. Get a license and go to the range. For defense of the home, that's why we have police departments.” James Brady, In Step with: James Brady, PARADE, June 26, 1994, at 18. (The author James Brady and the interview subject James Brady have no relation, other than sharing the same name.) 248 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 22. 249 Id. at 22–26. 250 Id. 251 See id. at 24 (citing Jason Riley, Congressman Guilty in Gun Case, LOUISVILLE COURIER-J., Aug. 11, 2004, at 1B). 247 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 571 252 also pleaded guilty to a misdemeanor charge. In Virginia, a school teacher left a handgun locked in a car while the car was parked on school property; he was charged with violating the Virginia law against firearms on school property.253 And in Pennsylvania, the transportation director for a school district was suspended for several months for, among other charges, what the district described as “unintentionally bringing a loaded firearm onto school property” when he left a handgun in a motorcycle saddlebag.254 The Brady Center lists some cases in which a person was arrested after a shooting, but almost never reports dispositions. The Brady Center thus treats a case that was not prosecuted, because an investigation established that the defendant acted in lawful self-defense, as equivalent to a case of criminal homicide. For example, the Brady Center writes: “Fort Lauderdale, Florida, January 1, 2006. Rogelio Monero [sic], 49, allegedly shot and killed Victor Manuel Villanueva, 17, during a New Year’s altercation as Moreno tried to stop a fight between Villanueva and a third party. Moreno was charged with manslaughter.”255 Yet an Austin Examiner phone call to the Fort Lauderdale Police Department revealed that the shooting had been determined to be a justifiable homicide.256 Another Brady Center story: Vancouver, WA, October 3, 2006. Jon W. Loveless, unemployed for ten years, daily marijuana smoker, and father of two children—said that he shot “until my gun was empty” at Kenneth Eichorn [sic, Eichhorn], because Eichorn [sic] had “a weird look” on his face. Loveless also claimed that Eichorn [sic] held a handgun, but the Eichorn [sic] family disputes the claim. Loveless was charged with one count of second-degree murder.257 Missing from the Brady account is the conclusion to the story, which was reported October 5, 2006, in the same newspaper that the Brady Center had cited: Jon W. Loveless was exonerated Thursday on charges of second-degree murder and was to be released from the Clark County Jail. . . . 252 Id. at 25. See id. at 24 (citing Maria Glod, Va. Teacher Accused of Taking Gun to School; Loaded Weapon Found in Locked Car, WASH. POST, Apr. 27, 2005, at B01). 254 Id. at 25. 255 Id. at 23. 256 Nemerov, supra note 202; see also Press Release, City of Fort Lauderdale Police Dep’t, Shooting at New Year’s Eve Party Leaves One Dead (Jan. 1, 2006), available at http://ci.ftlaud.fl.us/ police/pdf/2006/january/06-01%20New%20Year%20shooting.pdf. 257 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 23. 253 572 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 On Wednesday, [Senior Deputy Prosecutor] Fairgrieve indicated he had yet to see evidence that would support a second-degree murder charge. He said the standards police use to arrest a suspect are lower than what prosecutors use to file charges, and by law charges against a person in custody must be filed within 72 hours of the suspect’s first court appearance.258 The Brady Center monograph reports four cases of gun accidents, two of them fatal. As for criminal homicides by people who actually had CCW permits (not people whose permits had earlier been revoked, although the Brady Center lists these), there is only one that was committed in a public place (where the permit would even be relevant), and one more that was committed at home. There are three other cases of misusing a gun against another person (making an improper threat, or carrying it while impersonating a police officer, and a robbery perpetrated by a police officer’s wife).259 Are CCW permittees perfect? No, but they are much more lawabiding than the general population, as the government data indicate. Indeed, “[e]ven off-duty police officers in Florida were convicted of violent crimes at a higher rate than permit-holders.”260 So, should off-duty police be allowed to carry concealed firearms when on school property? If the answer is “No, because they might commit a violent crime against a teacher or student,” then one could, with logical consistency, also oppose campus carry by CCW licensees (although the fear of licensees would have a weaker empirical basis than the fear of off-duty police). On the other hand, if one thinks that the potential anti-crime benefit of allowing off-duty police to carry on campuses outweighs the (miniscule) risk that an off-duty officer might commit a crime, then one would have even less reason to be afraid of a CCW licensee. But what is it about permitees, although generally less dangerous than off-duty police, that makes others fear that they will become much more dangerous in a campus environment? That is the topic of the following sections. 2. Faculty Members Are Very Dangerous As the previous subsection demonstrates, the Brady Center works assiduously to collect information about every possible misdeed by people with concealed handgun licenses. One may be fairly confident that if any 258 Loveless Exonerated in CB Shooting, CLARK COUNTY COLUMBIAN (Vancouver, Wash.), Oct. 5, 2006. 259 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 22–23, 25. John R. Lott, Jr., Gun Control Advocates’ Credibility on Line, http://johnrlott.tripod.com/ credibility.html (last visited Sept. 1, 2009). 260 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 573 instance of misuse was reported in a newspaper, the Brady Center would know about it, and would not be reticent about publicizing it. Yet in a forty-four page paper composed of frantic warnings about what licensed carry permitees might do on campus, the paper conspicuously lacks any report of anything improper that a permittee on campus has done.261 In Utah, a state with a population of over three million, any licensee (not just a teacher or an adult student) has been allowed to carry at kindergartens, grade schools, and universities since 1995.262 In the Brady Center report, there is not one example of the slightest misdeed by any of these people. Nor is there any notation of misdeed by individuals at the large campus of Colorado State University, or the three campuses of Virginia’s Blue Ridge colleges, who are licensed to carry. From the arctic islands of Norway, to the deserts of Israel (a quarter-century of experience), to the jungles of southern Thailand (five years of experience), one can see very diverse real-world experiments with teachers and students being required or strongly encouraged to carry guns. And neither the Brady Center nor any other anti-carry organization has brought forward even one example of gun misuse in those countries. In this and the following two subsections, this Article examines the claims of the Brady Center and like-minded people that licensed carry on campuses would lead to catastrophe. Although the arguments will be addressed in detail, it is important to remember a larger point: these arguments are purely speculative. The advocates who demand a campus ban on licensed carry rely on sheer conjecture, while the advocates of campus carry can point to extensive real-world experience in which not an iota of the malicious conjecture has proven valid. A review of academic-linked homicides over the last twenty years revealed a few cases in which a professor had murdered someone on campus.263 Interestingly, there was only one case (at the University of Arkansas, by a graduate student) in which a killing was perpetrated by somebody with teaching responsibility in the humanities.264 Some people fear that an angry teacher might shoot a student. But if parents believe that their children’s teachers might kill their child if they had a weapon, then why would those parents leave their child in the custody of those teachers for many hours a week? Gallant: “Is your little daughter Brittany going to school now?” 261 See generally BRADY CENTER, supra note 146. See supra text accompanying notes 76–81. 263 See Wood, supra note 165, at 277–82 (discussing the prevalence of student- versus professorcaused murders on college campuses). “[A]ccounts of faculty members resorting to deadly force are relatively rare.” Id. at 281. 264 Id. at 286. 262 574 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 Goofus: “Oh yes, she really likes her classmates, but she seems afraid of her teacher Ms. Springelschnitz.” Gallant: “Do you like Ms. Springelschnitz?” Goofus: “Hmmm. I think that if Ms. Springelschnitz had a gun, she might murder Brittany. Or at least she would threaten Brittany with the gun. But as long as the school district prohibits teachers from having guns, I don’t have a care in the world.” If parents sincerely believe that the most important reason a child’s teacher has not murdered their children yet is that the district policy forbids the teacher to have a gun at school, those parents should immediately transfer their children to a different school. But realistically, although there might be too many mediocre teachers in some schools, American teachers are not borderline killers. Other people worry that a student might steal a teacher’s gun. Putting aside the fact that it is not that difficult for a determined person to get a gun somewhere else (e.g., stealing from someone’s home), the risk could be addressed through policies requiring that the gun always be carried on the teacher’s body or secured in another manner.265 In 2006, the President of the Utah Education Association, Kim Campbell, said, “I would be opposed to guns in school, period. . . . No matter where I would put a gun in a classroom, a class full of little people would find it. And if it were locked up for safety, there would be no chance to get it.”266 Perhaps Ms. Campbell is accurate in her selfassessment of her inability to prevent her students from getting hold of anything she brings into the classroom, even something that she is wearing concealed underneath her clothing. Presumably, she never brings her own medicines into the classroom because her students would make off with her pills and liquids. However, teachers throughout Utah—including, almost certainly, members of Ms. Campbell’s union—have been carrying guns in K–12 classrooms since 1995, and there has never been a known incident of a student taking a teacher’s gun.267 Ms. Campbell’s strong lack 265 For example, guns are often stored in quick-lock safes, which can be opened in several seconds. Some of the safes use a biometric identifier, usually a fingerprint scan. The trade-off is that the gun would not be instantly available if an attack began in that particular room, but the gun could be retrieved if an attack began elsewhere in the building. As for the constitutionality of requiring that a gun be locked up, see infra note 291 and accompanying text. 266 Caitlin A. Johnson, After Shootings, Some Teachers Get Guns, CBS NEWS, Oct. 16, 2006, http://www.cbsnews.com/stories/2006/10/17/earlyshow/main2096721.shtml?source=RSSattr=H OME_2096721. 267 Teachers do sometimes lose keys or cell phones. But unlike classroom keys or cell phones, a concealed firearm is typically worn in a special holster concealed on one’s body. And unlike keys and cell phones, a person does not remove a concealed handgun for ordinary use several times a day. If a teacher puts on a concealed handgun in a concealed holster at 7 a.m., when she is getting ready to go to 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 575 of self-confidence in her own abilities to keep control of the items in her personal possession does provide an example about why the government should not mandate that a teacher be armed. During the Nevada debate over allowing campus carry by K–12 teachers and college professors who completed a background check and training equivalent to that of a reserve police officer, the Las Vegas Sun highlighted the following concern: [W]ould a classroom teacher who is trained as an officer be allowed to use more aggressive tactics in controlling an unruly student? And if a situation arises in another part of the school that requires the attention of a teacher-officer, does that teacher simply leave his class unattended? . . . And in addition to these concerns, there is one very real consequence of having teachers double as officers: Children as young as 5 or 6 could be in classrooms where loaded guns are present.268 To answer these questions, no, a teacher would not be allowed to use unusually forceful tactics on unruly students; the police are taught not to use chokeholds or to draw their weapons unless there is a public safety need to do so. Teachers trained like police officers would be trained to the same standard of conduct. Next, yes, if there is an active shooter in the north part of the school building, the teacher in the south building might leave her classroom, confront the shooter in the north, and thereby leave her students unattended; this result is based on the premise that being unattended while being defended from a homicidal maniac is better than being attended while being murdered. And finally, yes, children as young as five or six would be in classrooms where loaded guns are present. Half of the children in America already live in homes where guns are present. If a gun-phobic parent cannot handle the thought of his child being in a classroom with an armed defender, the parent could be offered the option of transfer to another class. The Brady Center has another fear: “In one recent school year, 2,143 elementary or secondary school students were expelled for bringing or possessing a firearm at school. In how many of those instances would an armed teacher have been tempted to shoot the student because of a perception of danger?”269 Again, one can look to evidence. From the 1996–97 school year through the 2003–04 school year, there were 428 instances in which students in Utah have been expelled for possessing a school, she is not going to misplace the gun when she uses her keys to open the gymnasium at 9 a.m., or when she receives a cell phone call from her husband during lunch. 268 Editorial, Teachers Packing Heat?, LAS VEGAS SUN, Aug. 15, 2007, http://www.lasvegassun. com/news/2007/aug/15/editorial-teachers-packing-heat. 269 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 10. 576 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 270 firearm at public K–12 school. And since 1995, almost every public school teacher in Utah has had the right to obtain a concealed carry permit, and to use that permit on campus. There is no known example of any Utah teacher drawing a gun on, let alone shooting, any of the 428 students who illegally brought a firearm to school. The Brady Center also asks, “And what about fist or knife fights that occur at schools? Should teachers be drawing their guns and trying to intercede?”271 Indeed, we would want a teacher to intercede with a firearm under the same circumstances in which we would want a person with a CCW permit, or police officer, or anyone else lawfully possessing a firearm, to act: according to the state law regarding the use of deadly force. In most states, that would mean that deadly force would be allowed to stop a knife fight or a brawl if the teacher reasonably believes that the victim is in imminent danger of death or serious bodily injury and the teacher also reasonably believes that no lesser force will suffice to save the victim. 3. Adult College and Graduate Students Are Very Dangerous Before even considering the arguments against students possessing arms on campus, let us remember that such arguments are no reason to prohibit middle-aged and older faculty from having guns. The desire to prevent twenty-two-year-olds from being armed is no reason to impose disarmament on fifty-year-olds. Second, in only eight states are concealed carry permits issued to eighteen-year-olds.272 Most states impose an age limit of twenty-one years old or greater. The experience of the six states does not indicate that licensed, trained eighteen-year-olds are incapable of bearing arms responsibly. After all, they bear arms with enormous responsibility if they enlist in the United States armed forces. a. The Brady Center Assertions If all you knew about college students was what the Brady Center told you, you might think that the safest thing to do would be to immediately surround them all with barbed wire and convert them into penal institutions. The Center warns about “introducing guns among bingedrinking, drug-using, suicide-contemplating, hormone-raging college 270 KAREN GRAY-ADAMS, U.S. DEP’T OF EDUC., REPORT ON THE IMPLEMENTATION OF THE GUNFREE SCHOOLS ACT IN THE STATES AND OUTLYING AREAS SCHOOL YEAR 2003–04, at 12, tbl.5 (2007), available at http://www.ed.gov/about/reports/annual/gfsa/gfsa03-04rpt.pdf. In Utah, as in other states, many of the expulsions were modified to a lesser punishment. Id. at 13, tbl.6. 271 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 11. 272 See CAL. PENAL CODE § 12026(a) (West 2009); DEL. CODE ANN. tit. 11 § 1441 (2007); IND. CODE ANN. § 35-47-2-3(g) (West 2007); IOWA CODE ANN. § 724.8 (West 2003); ME. REV. STAT. ANN. tit. 25 § 2003 (2008); MD. CODE ANN., Pub. Safety § 5-306 (West 2003); MONT. CODE ANN. § 45-8321 (2009); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS §§ 23-7-7.1, 23-7-44 (2009). 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 577 273 students.” The Center thus predicts “[g]reater potential for student-onstudent and student-on-faculty violence.”274 According to the Brady Center, colleges face the imminent risk of being forced by “the gun lobby” to accept “students bring[ing] their AK-47 assault rifles with them to show off while guzzling beer at college keggers.”275 The scenario is ludicrous. First of all, the AK-47 is an automatic combat rifle—a type of machine gun. Although the gun is ubiquitous in some nations (e.g., Yemen and Iraq), there are no more than a few hundred in the United States, many of them in museums. To purchase one would cost many thousands of dollars, and require a licensing process (pursuant to the National Firearms Act of 1934) involving signed permission from one’s local police chief or sheriff, plus fingerprinting, a $200 tax, and months of paperwork.276 One can assume that few college students have the means to purchase an AK-47.277 Second, a “concealed carry permit” is a permit to carry a concealed weapon. A rifle of any type is too large to be carried concealed. Third, if we somehow imagine that an extremely wealthy student bought an actual AK-47, and that this super-rich student were also super-sized, so that the rifle could in some ingenious manner be concealed under his clothing, then “showing off” the AK-47 at the kegger would be a violation of the carry permit terms, and the permit could be revoked. Moreover, many states prohibit the possession of any firearm while under the influence of alcohol.278 Yet remember, the Brady Campaign is the most influential anti-gun lobby in the United States. Its absurd and fantastic claims (e.g., that there are thousands of atrocious gun crimes perpetrated by CCW licensees and that students will carry AK-47 rifles to keggers) are the claims made to terrify legislators and administrators against allowing licensed adults to exercise their rights on campus. The Brady Campaign also mistakenly describes the law in Utah, claiming that it provides for unlimited gun possession on public college and university campuses, and authorizes seventeen-year-olds to stockpile rifles in dorm rooms.279 To the contrary, the law applies solely to persons carrying handguns pursuant to a permit 273 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 14. Id. at 5. 275 Id. at V. 276 See 26 U.S.C. §§ 5811(a)–(b), 5812(a)–(b) (2006); see also U.S. Dep’t of Justice, Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco, Firearms and Explosives, Application for Tax Paid Transfer and Registration of Firearm, ATF Form 4 (as revised Mar. 2006) (requiring certification by a “Chief Law Enforcement Officer”). 277 The Brady Campaign works energetically to ban so-called “assault weapons,” some of which look like an AK-47. But none of these guns are machine guns; they just fire one bullet when the trigger is pressed, as does every other standard gun. 278 See, e.g., S.D. CODIFIED LAWS § 22-14-7 (2009) (criminalizing possession of a loaded firearm while intoxicated as a misdemeanor); MO. REV. STAT. § 571.070 (2000) (prohibiting habitually intoxicated persons from possessing firearms). 279 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 4. 274 578 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 issued by the Utah State Police. Utah law requires that such a person be at least twenty-one years old. The Brady Center tells us (on the basis of a citation that does not support the claim) that ages eighteen to twenty-four are the peak years for the commission of “violent gun crimes, including homicides.”280 It is all the more notable then, that in the Brady Center’s Appendix, in this very same report listing the various crimes it can find committed by CCW licensees, the Center cannot list a single violent gun crime committed by anyone in the eighteen to twenty-four age bracket.281 Again, the evidence shows that CCW permitees are a group whose gun misuse is microscopic, and far below the rate of gun misuse in the general population. b. Scholarly Research A study in the Journal of American College Health, by Matthew Miller and two colleagues, collected mail-in surveys from slightly less than 11,000 undergraduates at 119 colleges and found that 4.3% reported at some time having had a working firearm at college.282 The study did not ask about where the gun was possessed—such as in a dormitory, in a campus police storage locker (as many colleges allow and encourage), in an off-campus apartment, or in an automobile. Nor did the study attempt to distinguish between students whose gun possession was legal (e.g., a hunter who checked his rifle with the campus police) from those whose possession was illegal (e.g., a student with an illegal handgun who carried the handgun for confrontations with rival gangs at nightclubs). The study found that, in general, gun owners were more likely to engage in various misdeeds than non-owners.283 However, the study’s findings were 280 Id. at 6 (citing BUREAU OF JUSTICE STATISTICS, U.S. DEP’T OF JUST., SOURCEBOOK OF CRIMINAL JUSTICE STATISTICS ONLINE (2005), available at http://www.albany.edu/sourcebook/pdf/ t472005.pdf). However, the cited table (of arrests in 2005) provides no data for violent gun crime. The only gun-related category is “Weapons; carrying, possessing, etc.” For these regulatory offenses, the peak years are actually 15–21, with persons aged 15, 16, or 17 having much higher numbers of arrests than persons 22, 23, or 24. As for the four major categories of violent crime (for which the cited table does not include any subcategory indicating weapon use), the raw arrest data for homicide is higher for ages 18–24 than for other years. For forcible rape, 17-year-olds were arrested more often than persons aged 23 or 24. For robbery, persons aged 15, 16, or 17 were arrested more often than persons aged 21, 22, 23, or 24. For aggravated assault, the peak years were ages 18–24. The data are raw arrests; the cited table provides no information about arrest rates for particular ages, which would take into account the number of people in the age group in 2005. 281 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 26. There is one crime by an Arizona citizen who reportedly said (a year before the crime) that he had an Arizona CCW permit, but further investigation found no evidence to substantiate this assertion. 282 Matthew Miller et al., Guns and Gun Threats at College, 51 J. AM. C. HEALTH 57, 57–59 (2002). The study is a re-run of a previous similar study: Matthew Miller et al., Guns at College, 48 J. AM. C. HEALTH 7 (1999). For similar studies, see Philip W. Meilman et al., Analysis of Weapon Carrying Among College Students, by Region and Institution Type, 46 J. AM. C. HEALTH 291 (1998); Cheryl A. Presley et al., Weapon Carrying and Substance Abuse Among College Students, 46 J. AM. C. HEALTH 3 (1997). 283 See Miller et al., Guns and Gun Threats at College, supra note 282, at 62–63. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 579 presented in a manner which exaggerated problem behaviors. For example, there are data which purport to show that students who possessed firearms for protection are more likely to “binge and drive” than are other students.284 But this category captures people whose alcohol consumption and driving may have been entirely lawful and responsible, because it defines “binge” as five drinks for a male, or four for a female, regardless of circumstances. Having five shots of tequila on an empty stomach in fifteen minutes, and then going driving, certainly means that one is driving while intoxicated or impaired. Having five light beers while watching a football double-header (about six hours) with some friends, and while eating a pizza and chips, will leave a person well below the legal limits against driving while impaired. For a woman, the supposed “binge” drinking level is set at four drinks—meaning that a woman who attends a four-hour Passover Seder, and drinks the ritual four cups of wine, along with a large festive meal, and then drives home (entirely within the legal limits for blood alcohol content), is labeled by the study as someone who drives after binge drinking. The Miller study makes no distinction. Likewise, the finding that students who own guns for protection may be more likely to have smoked at least one cigarette in the last thirty days285 is not particularly important for a public policy determination. Smoking cigarettes is legal, and unless one is going to argue that defensive gun ownership causes smoking (this would be a “smoking gun theory”), then the finding may allow some public health tut-tutting about the kind of people who own guns, but nothing else. Notably, the study collected no evidence about gun misuse, and the authors acknowledge that their study “contains no data . . . on whether guns at college cause or prevent problems.”286 Most importantly, the study did not inquire whether the gun possessors had a valid CCW permit. Accordingly, it would be dangerous to draw conclusions about college students with CCW permits (who would be over twenty-one years old in most states) based on a study which makes no distinction between lawful and unlawful gun possession, and which, as a random sample of undergraduates, included a large number who were under twenty-one. We know that CCW permit holders are much more law-abiding than the general population.287 c. Does Going to College Make Adult Students More Dangerous? We know that the rate of gun crime perpetrated by CCW licensees is 284 See id. at 60 tbl.1. See id. 286 Miller et al., Guns and Gun Threats at College, supra note 282, at 64. 287 See Lott, supra note 260; see also supra at notes 218–41. 285 580 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 close to zero. Scott Lewis, a board member of SCCC, argues that “under our proposal the same trained, licensed individuals who are not getting drunk and shooting people off of college campuses are the same trained and licensed individuals who are not going to be getting drunk and shooting people on college campuses.”288 The empirical data are indisputable that when twenty-one-year-olds (in most states) or eighteenyear-olds (in a half-dozen states), exercise their right to licensed carry, they do not cause a crime problem. The logical question, then, is whether the circumstances of campus carry make licensed carriers unusually likely to misuse firearms. After all, college campuses, unlike other places, are places where a large number of young adults congregate, and perhaps young adults are more likely to perpetrate crimes when they are in the company of large numbers of persons in their age bracket. The experience of Utah, Colorado, and Virginia, however, provides no evidence to support this hypothesis. Perhaps young adults in the company of other young adults are more likely to drink lots of alcohol, or to engage in promiscuous sex. But they are not more likely to perpetrate gun crimes. If the primary concern is about students drinking, it should be noted that these days, most drinking occurs off-campus, where the college has no power to prevent licensed carry. To the extent that young adults with concealed carry permits do drink, they are required to comply with existing state laws which forbid possession of any firearm while under the influence of alcohol. Some states even forbid carrying a licensed firearm into a restaurant where alcohol is served, even if the person is merely having dinner, and not ordering a drink. On-campus drinking tends to take place in dormitories, not in classrooms. Accordingly, concerns about drinking could be dealt with by adopting the Colorado State University policy: allow licensed carry on campus, but forbid gun possession or carrying in dormitories.289 d. Stolen Guns When CCW permitees are allowed to store their licensed guns in a dormitory room, do the dormitories turn into shopping malls for gun thieves, as the Brady Center warns?290 The experience at Utah’s nine public institutions of higher education provides no support for this hypothesis. However, it would be reasonable for colleges to require that guns not be left in dormitories when vacant, such as during Christmas vacation. A college might also require any gun in a dormitory be stored in 288 Suzanne Smalley, More Guns on Campus, NEWSWEEK, Feb. 15, 2008, http://www.newsweek. com/id/112174 (web exclusive). 289 Telephone interview, supra note 96. 290 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 8–9. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 581 291 a secured locked box, small safe, or similar unit. If these measures are considered insufficient, then the answer would be to prohibit gun possession in dormitories, not to forbid professors from having licensed guns locked in their offices, or adult graduate students from having licensed guns locked in their automobiles. e. Sporting Events It is also argued that if campus carry is legal, students, alumni, and other fans will kill each other at sporting events, especially at important football games.292 Put aside the fact that throughout most of the history of scholastic athletic competition in the United States, there have been no laws against the possession of defensive arms, and no problem of extensive violence perpetrated by the fans. And let us further ignore the argument that America’s culture of responsible individualism, of which responsibility for self-defense is an important component, produces a more mature, self-restrained citizenry than is produced by the nanny-state, gunbanning culture of England, and its attendant soccer hooligans and yobs. The simple solution is to ban guns at sporting events, at least events with large crowds where there are an ample number of armed security guards and police, who could immediately (not several minutes later) take action against a killer. Concerns about the football game on Saturday afternoon can be addressed in a narrowly tailored fashion, without eliminating the self-defense rights of the professor working late on a Tuesday night. D. Academic Freedom The final major argument against campus carry is that it would infringe upon academic freedom. One prong of the argument is that one part of the college’s own communication of ideas is the prohibition of defensive firearms possession by anyone on campus. This argument was discussed 291 Cf. District of Columbia v. Heller, 128 S.Ct. 2783, 2822 (2008) (invalidating gun lock law in District of Columbia). In October 2008, the New York Supreme Court (the general trial court in New York) in Suffolk County ruled that the New York rule requiring that licensed handguns be locked up when not in use was an unconstitutional violation of Heller. See Colaiacovo v. Dormer, No. 08-020230 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Oct. 30, 2008), available at http://www.nysrpa.org/files/colaiacovo_v_dormer.pdf. A district court in Massachusetts came to a similar conclusion. See Commonwealth v. Bolduc, No. 0825 CR 2026 (Mass. Dist. Ct. Feb. 19, 2009), available at http://volokh.com/files/bolduc.pdf. The District Attorney agreed that the district court was correct, and did not appeal. See David E. Frank, It’s (Not) a Lock: Massachusetts Judges Split over Supreme Court Gun Ruling, MASS. LAWYERS WEEKLY, Mar. 16, 2009 (noting that another district court in the state had reached a contrary result). Hypothesizing that Heller eventually leads to a general ban on gun-lock laws, a requirement that guns in dormitories (or teacher guns in classrooms) be locked up might still be constitutional under Heller’s “sensitive places” exception. See supra note 24 and accompanying text. 292 Philip Rawls, Alabama Senate Committee Blocks Campus Gun Bills, BIRMINGHAM NEWS, Mar. 26, 2008, http://blog.al.com/spotnews/2008/03/Alabama_senate_committee_block.html (reporting on Gordon Stone, Executive Director of the Alabama Higher Education Partnership, worrying about potential violence at the Alabama-Auburn game). 582 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 293 in Part II. The more conventional argument about academic freedom is that persons with licensed carry permits will intimidate other people on campus from speaking freely. The Brady Center forecasts that “allowing students to possess and use firearms on college campuses will likely breed fear and paranoia.”294 Given the Brady Center’s frantic and factually inaccurate efforts to promote fear and paranoia about CCW licensees, no one can charge that the organization lacks chutzpah. University of Kentucky engineering professor Kaveh Tagavi worries that licensed carry would destroy trust between faculty and students, and that students might shoot professors after an intense discussion of a controversial topic.295 But if University of Kentucky students and professors are already worried that the only reason that they are not shooting each other is that they are not allowed to have guns, then there is no trust at the present. “No matter how hard you try, someone is going to see that concealed weapon,” claims Jim Spice, campus police chief at the University of Colorado at Colorado Springs. Then, “[t]hey no longer feel free to express whatever thought, whatever topic they happen to be debating at the time.”296 Yet, if one drives just a few hours north on Interstate 25 to Colorado State University, where licensed carry is allowed in classrooms, there has been no evidence of any diminution of academic freedom. Nor are there reports of any impairment of academic freedom at the nine public colleges and universities in Utah, at the three Blue Ridge campuses in Virginia, or in Israel, Thailand, or Norway. The only reported conflicts between campus carry and academic freedom involve people being persecuted for simply expressing support for the idea of campus carry. For example, Hamline University suspended student Troy Scheffler and ordered him to have a mental health evaluation because, after Virginia Tech, he wrote the administration an e-mail criticizing the school’s policy against licensed guns on campus. The freespeech academic group Foundation for Individual Rights in Education (“FIRE”) took up this case.297 Another example: in October 2008, at 293 See discussion supra note 81–90 and accompanying text (discussing University of Utah’s “academic freedom” argument in attempting to ban handguns). 294 BRADY CENTER, supra note 146, at 14. 295 See Art Jester & Ryan Alessi, Campus Gun Bill Stirs Furor, LEXINGTON HERALD-LEADER, Jan. 17, 2008, at A1; see also Van Zandt, supra note 211 (“Students need to fight for their ideas and beliefs, ones honed over the blazing fires of verbal discourse and debate. But their fight should be with words, not bullets.”). 296 Laura Forbes, UCCS Students Want Concealed Carry Permits, KXRM FOX 21 (Colorado Springs, Colo.), Mar. 31, 2008, http://www.coloradoconnection.com/news/news_story.aspx?id= 115314. 297 See Student Advocates Gun Rights, Gets Suspended, WORLDNETDAILY, Oct. 11, 2007, http://www.wm.com/index.php?fa=PAGE.printable&pageId=43961. 2009] PRETEND “GUN-FREE” SCHOOL ZONES 583 Central Connecticut State University, John Wahlberg and two classmates made a presentation in Professor Paula Anderson’s communication class. Assigned to discuss a “relevant issue in the media,” the three students argued that fewer people at Virginia Tech would have died if the victims were armed.298 Professor Anderson reported Wahlberg to the police, who summoned him to the police station that night. After interrogating him about where he keeps his registered firearms (in a safe in his home twenty miles off-campus), the police let him go. Robert Shibley, vice president of FIRE, said, “If you go after students for just discussing an idea, that goes against everything a university is supposed to stand for.”299 After the Columbine murders in 1999, a public school superintendent in Ohio was forced to resign because he had suggested that Columbinestyle massacres might be avoided if teachers were allowed to possess arms. He even had to fight off efforts to strip him of his earned pension because of the claim that his public expression of an idea constituted gross professional misconduct.300 VI. CONCLUSION Sometimes, a campus gun ban may be accompanied by a sign proclaiming the area as a “Weapon-free and Violence-free School Safety Zone.”301 But despite what the sign proclaims, the “weapons-free” part really means “free of weapons carried by law-abiding persons.” And unfortunately, the “violence-free” declaration may be a cruel hoax. A Canadian history professor observes that “[t]he fundamental problem with making a campus legally ‘gun-free’ is that the rule cannot be enforced unless the campus is surrounded by high walls with only a limited number of entrances, all of them guarded and equipped with metal detectors.”302 Gun prohibition on campuses is a deadly policy, and the number of victims of that policy is already far too high. The case against licensed carry on campus is based on conjecture and far-fetched hypotheticals. The case in favor of licensed carry is based on the empirical experience of the places where licensed campus carry has already been implemented, and on the experience of forty states where licensed, trained adults are allowed to carry firearms for lawful protection almost everywhere except on campus. In designing a campus carry policy, legislators and educational administrators are not required to copy the Utah example, under which any 298 Maxim Lott, Professor Takes Heat for Calling Cops on Student Who Discussed Guns in Class, FOX NEWS, Mar. 4, 2009, http://www.foxnews.com/story/0,2933,504524,00.html. 299 Id. 300 See John R. Lott, Jr., Creating Hysteria over Guns, WASH. TIMES, Jan. 30, 2000, at B4 (including Ohio example among other cases of anti-gun hysteria in schools). 301 E.g., GA. CODE ANN. § 16-11-127.1(g) (2008). 302 Kenneth H.W. Hilborn, Packing Heat, 21 ACAD. QUEST. 136, 136 (2008). 584 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:515 person twenty-one years or older may, after being issued a license to carry a concealed handgun, carry that handgun on any public school property, or possess it in a university dormitory. Although that policy has proven harmless in Utah, decision makers in other states could adopt more restrictive policies, such as forbidding guns in dormitories, or allowing only teachers and professors, but not adult students, to carry. Or even, as was proposed in Nevada, allowing licensed carry only by teachers and professors who underwent the same training and background check required for police officers. Any change would be an important step toward greater safety. Campuses should be safe zones for students and teachers—not for predators who are legally guaranteed that their victims will be defenseless. CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW VOLUME 42 DECEMBER 2009 NUMBER 2 Essay Demosprudence, Interactive Federalism, and Twenty Years of Sheff v. O’Neill JUSTIN R. LONG Professor Lani Guinier and others have recently developed a theory called “demosprudence” that explains the democracy-enhancing potential of certain types of U.S. Supreme Court dissents. Separately, state constitutionalists have described state constitutions’ capacity to offer a base of resistance against the U.S. Supreme Court’s narrow conception of individual rights. Applying these two seemingly unrelated theories to school desegregation litigation in Connecticut and to same-sex marriage litigation in Iowa, this Essay suggests that certain state constitutional decisions might function like U.S. Supreme Court dissents to enhance democratic activism. In this way, interactive federalism might usefully serve as a category of demosprudence. 585 ESSAY CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................... 587 II. DEMOSPRUDENCE ............................................................................. 588 III. INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM ........................................................... 592 IV. CAN STATE CONSTITUTIONAL DECISIONS WORK AS FEDERAL DEMOSPRUDENTIAL DISSENTS?.......................... 595 A. CAN STATE CONSTITUTIONAL DECISIONS WORK AS FEDERAL CONSTITUTIONALISM? ................................................ 597 B. CAN STATE CONSTITUTIONAL DECISIONS WORK AS FEDERAL DISSENTS? .................................................................. 599 C. CAN STATE CONSTITUTIONAL DECISIONS MEET THE DEMOSPRUDENCE CRITERIA? ......................................................... 601 V. SHEFF V. O’NEILL AND SCHOOL DESEGREGATION ................... 601 VI. VARNUM AND SAME-SEX MARRIAGE .......................................... 606 VII. CONCLUSION .................................................................................... 608 Demosprudence, Interactive Federalism, and Twenty Years of Sheff v. O’Neill JUSTIN R. LONG* I. INTRODUCTION Twenty years ago, civil rights lawyers sued state officials on behalf of school children in Hartford, Connecticut, complaining that the nearly allwhite suburban schools and nearly all-minority city schools violated the state constitution. The lawyers sued in court because state politicians seemed not to be responding to the de facto segregation. Rather than fight what looked like a futile political campaign, a lawsuit could compel the desegregation Hartford children needed. The lawyers sued under the state constitution because they knew that the U.S. Supreme Court was steadily withdrawing the courts from their historic role in school desegregation. The Connecticut Constitution and courts could avoid this federal retrenchment. In this way, both law and politics were causes of the landmark Sheff v. O’Neill1 case, and both legal and political change were its goals. But constitutional theorists, however, have struggled with how to reconcile law and politics in a principled fashion.2 If our nation is a democracy, what legitimacy can there be for counter-majoritarian law? If we are subject to the rule of law, what room is left for popular will? Lani Guinier’s recently developed idea of “demosprudence” offers a new way of thinking about the law/politics divide. Guinier argues that certain kinds of judicial decisions, and dissents in particular, can inspire popular responses in the form of social and political activism. These political activities can, in turn, affect judges’ understanding of fundamental constitutional norms. In this way, there is an ongoing national debate about the meaning of the most important values embedded in the federal Constitution. U.S. Supreme Court opinions are not merely politics by another means, nor are politics merely parallel to legal interpretation. Instead, both judicial and social activity together comprise a broader conversation about the interpretation of the core constitutional values * Visiting Assistant Professor, University of Connecticut School of Law. A.B., Harvard College; J.D., University of Pennsylvania School of Law. I thank Michael Fischl, Rick Kay, Bob Williams, the participants in the University of Connecticut School of Law faculty workshop series, and Ariana Silverman for helpful comments. 1 678 A.2d 1267, 1289 (Conn. 1996) (declaring unconstitutional state statutes responsible for de facto school segregation). 2 See, e.g., Larry D. Kramer, Professor & Dean of Stanford Law School, “The Interest of the Man”: James Madison, Popular Constitutionalism, and the Theory of Deliberative Democracy, in 41 VAL. U. L. REV. 697, 699–700 (2006) (describing the difficulty and importance of distinguishing between law and politics). 588 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:585 3 underlying our democracy. Meanwhile, Paul Kahn,4 James Gardner,5 Robert Schapiro,6 and other state constitutional scholars7 have persuasively argued that state constitutional jurisprudence can usefully function as a site of resistance to federal constitutional interpretations, a theory known as “interactive federalism.”8 If the U.S. Supreme Court fails to protect such rights as privacy, marriage equality, or public education under the federal Constitution, state high courts may, and often do, provide a competing constitutional vision that does protect those liberties. Although the states’ more expansive protection of civil rights formally derives from the state constitutions, interactive federalism suggests that the true debate underlying these decisions is a dispute about the basic values we share as Americans. State constitutionalism, in this view, can and should function as a legal space for contesting the dominant federal interpretation of national norms. Furthermore, state constitutional jurisprudence can galvanize a popular political response that leads either to changes in federal jurisprudence or to new legislative action.9 This Essay suggests a previously overlooked link between the theories of demosprudence and interactive federalism. Using the example of Sheff v. O’Neill, this Essay asks, “Can state constitutional decisions function as demosprudential dissents?” Preliminary analysis of the Sheff litigation and same-sex marriage litigation suggests that scholars of demosprudence and state constitutionalism have much to learn from each other. Imagining state constitutional decisions as demosprudential dissents offers a new perspective on federal and state constitutional theory, and potentially offers a democracy-enhancing justification for American federalism. II. DEMOSPRUDENCE Professor Guinier’s far-reaching insight is that U.S. Supreme Court dissents can be effective beyond merely persuading some as-yet unseated 3 See Lani Guinier, Foreword: Demosprudence Through Dissent, 122 HARV. L. REV. 4, 15–18, 58–59 (2008) (discussing how dissenting opinions are illustrative of this theory). 4 See Paul Kahn, Interpretation and Authority in State Constitutionalism, 106 HARV. L. REV. 1147, 1148 (1993) (rejecting a separate-spheres approach to federalism). 5 See generally JAMES A. GARDNER, INTERPRETING STATE CONSTITUTIONS: A JURISPRUDENCE OF FUNCTION IN A FEDERAL SYSTEM (Univ. of Chi. Press 2005). 6 See generally ROBERT A. SCHAPIRO, POLYPHONIC FEDERALISM: TOWARD THE PROTECTION OF FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS (Univ. of Chi. Press 2009); Robert A. Schapiro, Toward a Theory of Interactive Federalism, 91 IOWA L. REV. 243 (2005) (providing a useful background and historical evaluation of this philosophy). 7 See, e.g., Lawrence Friedman, The Constitutional Value of Dialogue and the New Judicial Federalism, 28 HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 93, 95 (2000) (describing state constitutional interpretation as legitimately reactive to federal constitutional law). 8 Id. 9 E.g., id. at 298. 2009] DEMOSPRUDENCE, INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM 589 Court majority to overturn the disfavored decision in the misty future.10 Rather, as Robert Williams pointed out in 1984, the Justices’ dissents can, and sometimes do, address contemporary political forces.11 By inspiring, comforting, and teaching common people affected by the Court’s opinion, dissents can reach past legal elites to provoke democratic engagement and change.12 Guinier identifies three defining characteristics of the demosprudential dissent: substantively, the dissent is about a basic issue of democracy; stylistically, the dissent is written with a tone and structure that address a broader audience than the legal in-crowd; and procedurally, the dissent challenges that broader audience to exercise popular sovereignty by counteracting the majority opinion.13 Guinier points out that part of the populism-provoking capacity of the demosprudential dissent comes from its partial-outsider status. The dissent is conducive to popular inspiration in part because it lacks the compelling power of the state behind it; dissents establish no precedent and justify no legal violence. Instead, dissents inherently offer a challenge to the prevailing legal norm and an alternative to the state’s use of force to carry out that norm. Dissents, like the sociopolitical action they hope to provoke, are an act of resistance.14 By describing an imagined alternative to the legal world defined by the majority opinion, and by drawing ordinary people into sharing the dissenter’s vision, dissents protect what Robert Cover called the “jurisgenerative” features of communal life.15 Justices accomplish this, Guinier suggests, by writing directly to the public (or affected segments of it) in language that avoids dry, cold legalisms in favor of emotional appeals to common national values. The best demosprudential dissents attend to “the premises behind the logic, the stories and not just the explanations” underlying the Court’s constitutional hermeneutics.16 In doing so, they welcomeperhaps “authorize”everyday folk to oppose the Court’s 10 See Guinier, Foreword, supra note 3, at 50–51 (“Simply by contesting the view of the Court majority, the dissenter may reveal a more transparent deliberative process of lawmaking.”). 11 See Robert F. Williams, In the Supreme Court’s Shadow: Legitimacy of State Rejection of Supreme Court Reasoning and Result, 35. S.C. L. REV. 353, 375 (1984) (noting the influence of U.S. Supreme Court dissents on Congressand state courts); see also Robert Post, Law Professors and Political Scientists: Observations on the Law/Politics Distinction in the Guinier/Rosenberg Debate, 89 B.U. L. REV. 581, 582 (2009) (describing the significance of Guinier’s theory as its placement of judges within, rather than apart from, democratic deliberation). 12 See Guinier, Foreword, supra note 3, at 15–16 (explaining that dissents sometimes focus on “enhancing . . . democratic potential” rather than reasoning through traditional legal forms). 13 See id. at 49 (describing the elements of a demosprudential dissent). 14 See id. at 48–49 (noting that dissents challenge, rather than exercise, the law’s coercive power). 15 See Lani Guinier, Courting the People: Demosprudence and the Law/Politics Divide, 89 B.U. L. REV. 539, 544–45 (2009) (citing Robert M. Cover, Foreword: Nomos and Narrative, 97 HARV. L. REV. 4 (1983)) (describing demosprudential dissents as a method of cooperation between legal elites and ordinary people). 16 See Guinier, Foreword, supra note 3, at 11, 13 (describing a Justice Breyer dissent). 590 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:585 17 conclusion. In contrast, conventional constitutional thought suggests that U.S. Supreme Court opinions end the debate about the fundamental norms at stake in the decided case; it is for this reason that advocates of judicial minimalism urge the Court to avoid reaching these profound questions.18 For reasons of popular sovereignty, Larry Kramer seems appalled19 by the way that Supreme Court decisions exhibit the “jurispathic” tendenciesthe killing of ongoing popular debate about the meaning(s) of fundamental social values as embodied in lawthat Professor Cover described.20 Demosprudence offers a path toward revival of alternative, non-statist nomoi and narratives because it reminds us that court law and folk law are articulated, just as the leg bone is connected to the hip bone. We the People occasionally find sufficient inspiration in judicial dissents, like Justice Ginsburg’s in Ledbetter21 or Justice Breyer’s in Parents Involved,22 to take up the colors and recapture the legal battlements. As new scholarship from Jason Mazzone confirms,23 the Court speaks, but it lacks the last word. Unfortunately, the orality of dissents from the bench attracts Guinier’s attention as particularly promising for democratic engagement.24 “The idea,” she argues, “is that speech is primary, present, natural, interior, real, authentic, and whole, and writing is secondary, artificial, exterior, a representation of speech, a substitute for speech, removed from reality, a subversion or corruption of the original speech.”25 Even if true, the neartotal unavailability of U.S. Supreme Court dissents from the bench makes 17 See Timothy R. Johnson et al., Hear Me Roar: What Provokes Supreme Court Justices to Dissent from the Bench?, 93 MINN. L. REV. 1560, 1581 (2009) (explaining that oral dissents “signal litigants and other actors . . . that the [Court’s] decision is a bad one and someone must act to change it”). 18 See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Testing Minimalism: A Reply, 104 MICH. L. REV. 123, 128 (2005) (arguing that “the argument for minimalism is strongest in an identifiable class of cases: those in which American society is morally divided, those in which the Court is not confident that it knows the right answer, and those in which the citizenry is likely to profit from more sustained debate and reflection”). 19 See Kramer, supra note 2, at 697 (complaining that lawyers and lay people alike assume without real question that the U.S. Supreme Court has sole interpretative authority over the federal Constitution). 20 See Cover, supra note 15, at 53 (describing state-backed law as tending to destroy all competing legal norms). 21 See Ledbetter v. Goodyear Tire & Rubber Co., 550 U.S. 618, 643 (2007) (Ginsburg, J., dissenting), superseded by statute, 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-5(e) (2009). 22 See Parents Involved in Cmty. Schs. v. Seattle Sch. Dist. No. 1, 127 S.Ct. 2738, 2800 (2007) (Breyer, J., dissenting). At the time of publication, this case had not been published in the U.S. Reporter. 23 See Jason Mazzone, When the Supreme Court Is Not Supreme, 104 NW. U. L. REV. (forthcoming 2010) (describing how the U.S. Supreme Court’s interpretive authority has elided into that of the state courts). 24 See Guinier, Foreword, supra note 3, at 26–27 (emphasizing the special significance of spoken dissents). 25 Id. at 27. 2009] DEMOSPRUDENCE, INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM 591 26 them poor candidates, at present, for democratic engagement. However, Guinier’s distinction between oral and written dissents may be somewhat hyperbolic. A Justice who authored a stirring written dissent but declined to read it aloud might be forgiven for concluding, like the poet, that “Between my finger and my thumb/ The squat pen rests./ I’ll dig with it.”27 Applying Guinier’s concept of demosprudence to written dissents seems to sacrifice little of the theory’s descriptive and normative power. Critics of demosprudence theory notably include the political scientist Gerald Rosenberg. He argues that the theory, although an effort to link the Court with democratic deliberation and with the popular legitimacy such deliberation would provide, hinges on wildly misplaced optimism about how much the public knows or cares about the Supreme Court’s work.28 For Professor Rosenberg, legal elites’ concentrated gaze on the U.S. Supreme Court, even when purporting to study grassroots activism, reveals a blind romanticism. Rosenberg argues that demosprudence imprudently ignores the institutions of popular politics, the majoritarian venues through which democratic deliberation really happens.29 In rebuttal, Robert Post points out that precious few members of the public could identify congressional leaders or the faceless activists who toil on party platforms, either, yet those politicians’ importance to how American popular government works appears beyond cavil. This is because, Post suggests, deliberative democracy operates more through public debate and communal relationships than through the measurable results of superficial shifts in public-opinion polls.30 Indeed, Guinier’s understanding of demosprudence explicitly depends on this subtler (yet more profound) concept of politics.31 Beyond defending Guinier’s development of demosprudential theory, Professor Post, with Reva Siegel, has also recently contributed to the literature on the relationship between the U.S. Supreme Court and democratic action. They explain that political backlash to U.S. Supreme Court opinions, often viewed with dismay by juriscentric legal elites, actually exhibits the mutually influential relationship between grassroots 26 See Frederick C. Harris, Specifying the Mechanism Linking Dissent to Action, 89 B.U. L. REV. 605, 607 (2009) (noting that the possibility of oral dissents provoking grassroots action is hampered by the public’s lack of access to these spoken texts). 27 SEAMUS HEANEY, Digging, reprinted in NEW SELECTED POEMS: 1966–1987, at 2 (1990). 28 See Gerald N. Rosenberg, Romancing the Court, 89 B.U. L. Rev. 563, 564 (2009) (arguing that ordinary people simply do not know about the Court’s opinions and that even elites care only about the holdings, not the Justices’ reasoning or rhetoric). But see Dion Farganis, Does Reasoning Matter? The Impact of Opinion Content on Supreme Court Legitimacy (July 15, 2009) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1434726 (arguing that the reasoning in a Supreme Court opinion does affect how a lay reader perceives the opinion’s legitimacy). 29 Rosenberg, supra note 28, at 564. 30 See Post, supra note 11, at 583–85 (2009) (rejecting Rosenberg’s reliance on observable and quantifiable factors as the sole determinants of political significance). 31 See Guinier, Foreword, supra note 3, at 48 (explaining that the goal of demosprudential dissenters is not necessarily a shift in voting percentages, but a shift in public normative discourse). 592 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:585 32 politics and Court decisions. This connection offers the Supreme Court a measure of democratic legitimacy that helps it escape the charge that its countermajoritarian power undermines popular sovereignty.33 Backlash, though obviously undesirable to the Justices whose interpretations face public rejection, potentially strengthens rather than weakens the Court as a crafter of nomos.34 And how do the Court’s opinions engage the ordinary people who then respond politically? Post argues that the Justices use the “familiar techniques” we recognize in demosprudence theory: a combination of both standard legal reasoning and emotional rhetoric to inspire and persuade.35 III. INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM The new scholarship on demosprudence has focused exclusively on the role of the U.S. Supreme Court in engaging grassroots democracy, to the exclusion of state courts (or, indeed, of states at all). Similarly, the best recent scholarship on state constitutionalism has largely overlooked the relationship between courts and ordinary people in constitutional interpretation, in favor of scrupulous attention to the dialogue between state high courts and the U.S. Supreme Court. The most prominent exception, Douglas Reed’s 1999 article,36 links state constitutions to popular democracy, but treats the interaction between state constitutional interpretation and political forces as internal to each state. Nevertheless, the state constitutionalists’ theory of federalism amply rewards careful study. James Gardner’s path-breaking book, Interpreting State Constitutions,37 proposes an elegant solution to a problem that has vexed state high courts and their academic observers since Justice Brennan’s famous call for state constitutional interpretation independent of federal precedent.38 The difficulty is that many state constitutions include rights provisions worded identically (or close enough) to corresponding provisions in the federal Constitution; what might legitimate a state court 32 See Robert Post & Reva Siegel, Roe Rage: Democratic Constitutionalism and Backlash, 42 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 373, 390–91 (2007) (noting that U.S. Supreme Court decisions can provoke a backlash that consists of ordinary people debating constitutional meaning and acting on their legal understanding). 33 See id. at 383 (arguing that one reason for popular loyalty to the Supreme Court is its potential responsiveness to democratic demands). 34 See id. at 395 (suggesting that backlash might be essential to retaining the democratic legitimacy of judicial opinions). 35 Robert Post, Democracy, Popular Sovereignty, and Judicial Review, 86 CAL. L. REV. 429, 441 (1998). 36 Douglas S. Reed, Popular Constitutionalism: Toward a Theory of State Constitutional Meanings, 30 RUTGERS L.J. 871, 874–75 (1999). 37 See generally GARDNER, supra note 5. 38 See William J. Brennan, Jr., State Constitutions and the Protection of Individual Rights, 90 HARV. L REV. 489, 491 (1977) (calling for state courts to interpret their state constitutions as more rights-protective than federal constitutional jurisprudence). 2009] DEMOSPRUDENCE, INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM 593 in giving such a provision any meaning other than the U.S. Supreme Court’s authoritative interpretation?39 Professor Gardner’s functional approach positions states as competitors to the national government for the People’s trust and affection.40 Like Lawrence Friedman’s earlier work,41 Gardner’s theory suggests that state courts should unabashedly consider such matching clauses as an invitation to check and balance the U.S. The beneficiaries of this Supreme Court’s rights jurisprudence.42 interpretive redundancy are the People themselves, Gardner maintains.43 If either the state or federal high court protects individual liberty insufficiently, the other stands ready to fill the breach.44 Gardner concedes, as he must, that states have frequently been on the wrong side of the state-federal competition to protect individual liberty.45 But state constitutions offer state high courts at least the capacity to consider both intrastate domestic arrangements and the relationship between the state and federal governments. Gardner’s larger challenge lies in explaining what nomos authorizes independent state interpretation. In no uncertain terms, Gardner has steadily rejected the search for an independent state “character” that might provide a normative community sufficient to justify constitutional interpretation.46 Instead, Gardner reminds us that state citizens are national citizens, too, and that state constitutions exist in a legal universe premised on a federalism prescribed 39 See Friedman, supra note 7, at 96–97 (noting that independent interpretation of state constitutional clauses parallel to federal constitutional clauses has attracted criticism as result-oriented judicial activism). 40 See GARDNER, supra note 5, at 125–26 (emphasizing the role of states as a protection for individuals against overreaching national power, and vice versa). 41 See Friedman, supra note 7, at 97 (arguing that autonomous state constitutional interpretation can provide a useful protection against inadequate U.S. Supreme Court rights protection). 42 See GARDNER, supra note 5, at 254–55 (explaining that matching constitutional provisions invite the state high court to react to U.S. Supreme Court doctrine and resist the federal interpretation where appropriate). 43 See id. at 256 (discussing the importance of different levels of government being able to act independently in the best interests of the people). 44 See id. at 254–55 (noting that the same provision in state and federal constitutions can best serve the people as interpreted by the respective state and federal authorities). 45 See id. at 135 (noting that states have historically posed an even greater threat to individual liberty than the federal government); see also Edward A. Purcell, Jr., Evolving Understandings of American Federalism: Some Shifting Parameters, 50 N.Y.L. SCH. L. REV. 635, 666–67 (2005–06) (describing the states’ rabid red-baiting and oppressive speech restrictions, above and beyond the national effort, during World War I and the McCarthy era). 46 See GARDNER, supra note 5, at 231–32 (emphasizing that state citizens derive their political identity from their concurrent status as national citizens); James A. Gardner, Southern Character, Confederate Nationalism, and the Interpretation of State Constitutions: A Case Study in Constitutional Argument, 76 TEX. L. REV. 1219, 1291 (1998) (empirically attacking the argument that state constitutions reflect unique state values or character). For the view that federalism is only justified where the subnational units do express a deep set of norms distinct from national values, see MALCOLM M. FEELEY & EDWARD RUBIN, FEDERALISM: POLITICAL IDENTITY & TRAGIC COMPROMISE 60–61 (2008). 594 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:585 47 by the national Constitution. Therefore, Gardner implies that the national character and national values provide the normative foundation for state constitutional interpretation. Robert Schapiro, like Gardner, accepts the implausibility of founding autonomous state constitutionalism on unique state “character.”48 Rather than looking toward a national nomos, however, Professor Schapiro decouples state constitutions from actual communities of value. Instead, he argues that state constitutions contain, in the texts themselves, all of the normative foundation an interpreter might need. For Schapiro, it is the imagined, aspirational nomos described (or implied) in the constitutional text that ought to drive constitutional interpretation, not any actual or perceived normative community in the real world.49 Schapiro’s concept is especially useful as a justification for counter-majoritarian state constitutional interpretation; the judicial result may not comport with the values of the state’s actual population, but it reflects the fundamental values fixed in the text.50 Implicit in this aspect of Schapiro’s theory lies the central idea that law can influence the ordinary person’s understanding of constitutional values: if the state court’s mediation of the constitutional words into actual law could not move the state polity toward the constitutional aspirations, then the law’s violence would be futile and cruel. Even though autonomous state constitutional interpretation derives justification from each state’s particular constitutional text, Schapiro’s later work emphasizes that states are not stand-alone entities. Rather, state and federal power overlap, like the sounds of woodwinds and strings in a single orchestra: what Schapiro calls “polyphonic” or “interactive” federalism.51 In this view, the state and federal governments each operate simultaneously on the same subject matter as the other, not within separate spheres of substantive jurisdiction. Geography, Schapiro maintains, not regulatory field, distinguishes state from federal power.52 Given states’ overlapping authority with national institutions, Schapiro brilliantly observes that when state law differs from national law (as when state high courts offer independent interpretations of state constitutional provisions textually identical to federal provisions), the result serves as resistance to 47 See GARDNER, supra note 5, at 231–32 (“[S]tate government power is allocated and deployed not only to ensure good internal self-governance on the state level, but also to ensure the success of the larger federal system of which state government is a part.”). 48 See Robert A. Schapiro, Identity and Interpretation in State Constitutional Law, 84 VA. L. REV. 389, 398 (1998) (rejecting existing state norms as a valid basis for independent state constitutional interpretation). 49 See id. at 394 (“Rather than relying on vague generalities about state character, judges can turn their attention to the State Constitution itself . . . .”). 50 See id. 51 See SCHAPIRO, POLYPHONIC FEDERALISM, supra note 6, at 92–95; Schapiro, Interactive Federalism, supra note 6, at 285–86 (2005). 52 See Schapiro, Interactive Federalism, supra note 6, at 285 (“The scope of this political authority is defined by territory, not by subject matter.”). 2009] DEMOSPRUDENCE, INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM 595 53 the U.S. Supreme Court. A state’s divergent view of a constitutional right can illustrate an alternative legal world, thereby demonstrating for officials and citizens alike that the U.S. Supreme Court lacks the final, definitive, jurispathic word.54 Like Gardner and Schapiro, Paul Kahn rejects states as autonomous nomoi.55 Kahn explains state constitutionalism by emphasizing that state constitutions are situated in a federal structure and therefore always exist in a national context.56 The role of state high courts in interpreting their constitutions independently from U.S. Supreme Court jurisprudence “accords with a longstanding justification of federalism,” Professor Kahn says, “under which state governments provide a forum for discussion, disagreement, and opposition to actions of the national government.”57 Reflecting his view that state constitutional interpretation is really about discovering the meaning of a naturalistic “American” constitution, Kahn admires Thomas Cooley’s 1878 treatise on state constitutionalism because it treated the whole field as a single interpretive project across states, rather than as a series of unique state texts.58 For Kahn, the reduction of American constitutional discourse to the holdings of the federal Supreme Court represents a massive social failure; he therefore calls for a renewed interpretive debate over fundamental values in Congress, in law schools, and particularly in the state high courts.59 The consensus of these state constitutional theorists, then, is that state high courts can and do serve as sites of contestation over deep national values. Given their capacity to insulate state constitutional holdings from U.S. Supreme Court review, state high courts enjoy a special power to resist the Supreme Court’s tendency to shrink the national constitutional imagination. IV. CAN STATE CONSTITUTIONAL DECISIONS WORK AS FEDERAL DEMOSPRUDENTIAL DISSENTS? As noted above, adherents to the contemporary demosprudence school of thought focus exclusively on the U.S. Supreme Court as the judicial institution capable of inspiring democratic action (and thereby earning democratic legitimacy). Interestingly, anthropologist Sally Engle Merry 53 See id. at 288–90 (citing Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003), as one such example). See id. at 289 (noting that state law can serve as an inspiring rebuke to federal jurisprudence). 55 See Kahn, supra note 4, at 1148 (“The diversity of state courts is best understood as a diversity of interpretive bodies, not as a multiplicity of representatives of distinct sovereigns.”). 56 See id. at 1166 (arguing that state courts should view their constitutions in light of “American constitutionalism”). 57 Id. 58 See id. at 1162–63; see generally THOMAS M. COOLEY, A TREATISE ON THE CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITATIONS WHICH REST UPON THE LEGISLATIVE POWER OF THE STATES OF THE AMERICAN UNION (4th ed. 1878). 59 See Kahn, supra note 4, at 1155 (arguing that democracy depends on a rich constitutional discourse expressive of more than a single institution’s constitutional view). 54 596 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:585 found trial-level courts and officials to be profoundly influential in inspiring new popular understandings of legally contested values. She noted that trial courtrooms are the scenes of performances, which “allow authoritative judicial and prosecutorial figures to interpret everyday life in new ways.”60 Professor Merry’s research suggests the potential power of courts—other than the U.S. Supreme Court—to foster democratic deliberation. This section asks whether state high court constitutional decisions might share some part of the demosprudential potential of U.S. Supreme Court dissents. By posing this question, I do not intend to consider state constitutional dissents, though those judicial writings might well be concerned with the contestation and negotiation of national values. In part, this Essay adopts this approach because a state high court that gives its state constitution a meaning different from federal jurisprudence already acts as a minority voice; the state court already rejects the federal holding (although possibly not for the same reasons as dissenting federal Justices). State court dissents then fill the role of defending the conception of national values explained by the U.S. Supreme Court’s majority opinion, and so become apologia for the federally-declared law rather than writings of jurisgenerative potential. Nor does this Essay intend to review state high court decisions of federal constitutional law. For one thing, an essay asking whether state court determinations of federal law might plausibly be viewed as about federal law would not likely be interesting, even to legal academics. For another, such decisions fall unambiguously under the authoritative control of the U.S. Supreme Court,61 and although state courts might use the opportunity to critique federal jurisprudence, the U.S. Supreme Court can sap the potency of any judicial back-talk with a binding reversal. Finally, my interest here lies in the capacity of state constitutional decisions to inspire a national political response from ordinary people. State constitutional decisions can, and certainly do, provoke the sort of democratic backlash described by Post and Siegel within the affected state.62 This Essay’s query, which links for the first time the exciting recent developments in demosprudence theory and interactive federalism, asks whether the opinions of state high court majorities interpreting state constitutions might function as federal constitutional demosprudential dissents. This inquiry invites three questions. First, are state high courts really 60 SALLY ENGLE MERRY, COLONIZING HAWAI‘I: THE CULTURAL POWER OF LAW 261 (2000). See Michigan v. Long, 463 U.S. 1032, 1038–41 (1983) (holding that the U.S. Supreme Court may review state court decisions of mixed state and federal law in the absence of a clear statement that the state disposition is independently supported by state law). 62 See, e.g., Strauss v. Horton, 207 P.3d 48, 59 (Cal. 2009) (acknowledging that a popular initiative, Proposition 8, had amended the state constitution to supersede the holding of a state court constitutional decision); see also Reed, supra note 36, at 887–89 (describing the “democratic penetration” into state constitutional interpretation). 61 2009] DEMOSPRUDENCE, INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM 597 talking about the same thing as the U.S. Supreme Court when they interpret state constitutional provisions differently from the matching federal constitutional provisions? In other words, can state constitutional decisions really function as a species of national constitutional law? Second, if state constitutionalism is indeed at least potentially a commentary on federal constitutionalism, can a state constitutional majority opinion function as a dissent, which by definition lacks the force of law? And finally, can state constitutional decisions meet the democracy-enhancing criteria described in demosprudence theory? The remainder of this Essay suggests that the answer to each of these questions might be “yes.” A. Can State Constitutional Constitutionalism? Decisions Work as Federal To start, one must remember that the more common technique of state constitutional interpretation is not divergence from federal precedent, but near-obsequious adherence to it.63 From the practical perspective of state courts, then, and for better or for worse, state constitutionalism is already driven largely by federal doctrine and federal values.64 The work on interactive federalism by Gardner, Schapiro, and Kahn described above further demonstrates that even “independent” state constitutional interpretation is best understood as intimately bound to federal constitutionalism. Because state citizens’ political identity is tied to the national, rather than state, community,65 even state judges who attempt to read the character of their state for purposes of autonomous constitutional interpretation will end up finding a national nomos. As Post and Siegel remind us, open-ended constitutional provisions like those protecting liberty and equality invite courts to express national values.66 These open-ended provisions in state constitutions extend the same invitation. In the political practices of ordinary people, we see “a social consensus that fundamental values in this country will be debated and resolved on a national level.”67 If state constitutional interpreters are really engaged in construing a set 63 See Schapiro, Interactive Federalism, supra note 6, at 290–91 (noting that state high courts usually interpret state constitutional provisions by simply adopting U.S. Supreme Court reasoning and results). 64 See Robert F. Williams, State Courts Adopting Federal Constitutional Doctrine: Case-by-Case Adoptionism or Prospective Lockstepping?, 46 WM. & MARY L. REV. 1499, 1502 (2005) (noting that state courts interpreting state constitutions follow federal jurisprudence in the “clear majority” of cases). 65 See Cover, supra note 15, at 48–49 (observing that “by the mid-twentieth century the states had long since lost their character as political communities”). 66 See Post & Siegel, supra note 32, at 378–79 (relating national nomos to the judicial interpretation of deep constitutional debates). 67 James A. Gardner, The Failed Discourse of State Constitutionalism, 90 MICH. L. REV. 761, 828 (1992). 598 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:585 of national constitutional values, as described here, then an important challenge is why the U.S. Supreme Court should lack the authority to impose its final interpretation on these values.68 Regardless of any “plain statement”69 they might make, why should state courts be permitted to diverge from the U.S. Supreme Court’s interpretation of national constitutional requirements if their state constitutional clauses are merely alternative articulations of those same national values? Robert Williams has argued that the U.S. Supreme Court’s concern for federalism, a concern that seeps into even ordinary individual-rights cases, renders the federal precedents inadequate to teach state high courts what the underlying values ought to be when the filter of federalism is removed.70 Gardner’s functional theory and Schapiro’s interactive federalism, which both argue for a self-consciously federalist approach to state constitutional interpretation, derive their legitimacy from the federal Constitution itself, which carves out from federal oversight the legal space in which state constitutions operate.71 This constitutional space leads to an important consequence. Both the public and legal elites typically believe that the U.S. Supreme Court has the last word on the meaning of constitutional liberty and equality.72 Even the Court itself thinks so.73 But this is false.74 From the perspective of the ordinary person, state constitutional interpretation of liberty and equality often offers the last word. To the cop on the beat concerned with executing a lawful search and seizure, the union organizer wishing to distribute petitions in the shopping mall, or the speeding motorist seeking to contest her ticket before a jury, the U.S. Supreme Court’s determination of these rights under the federal Constitution’s text is the starting point, not the ending point, for analysis.75 The law that actually applies, the word that bears the threat of violence, is the state court’s state constitutional interpretation. If the police officer searches a car without a warrant because federal constitutional doctrine so permits, she will still have done wrong if the state constitutional court has 68 I am grateful to Rick Kay for raising this point. See Michigan v. Long, 463 U.S. 1032, 1041 (1983) (declaring that the U.S. Supreme Court will treat state high courts’ constitutional decisions as presumptively federal unless the state court opinion includes a “plain statement” that the decision rests on state constitutional law). 70 See Williams, supra note 11, at 389–90 (noting how the U.S. Supreme Court seems constrained by federalism concerns inapplicable to the states). 71 See Friedman, supra note 7, at 97. 72 See Tom Donnelly, Note, Popular Constitutionalism, Civic Education, and the Stories We Tell Our Children, 118 YALE L.J. 948, 954–55 (2009). 73 See Brown v. Allen, 344 U.S. 443, 540 (1953) (Jackson, J., concurring) (“We are not final because we are infallible, but we are infallible only because we are final.”). 74 Cf. Mazzone, supra note 23 (noting how the U.S. Supreme Court has, for practical purposes, surrendered much of its interpretive authority over the federal Constitution to state courts). 75 See JEFFREY M. SHAMAN, EQUALITY AND LIBERTY IN THE GOLDEN AGE OF STATE CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 7–8 (Oxford Univ. Press 2008) (cataloging state constitutional protection of equality and liberty above the federal floor). 69 2009] DEMOSPRUDENCE, INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM 599 protected the privacy of citizens’ cars. If the mall manager expels the pamphleteer because the Supreme Court has declined to find free speech protection against private parties, the expulsion will still be unlawful if the state constitution offers a stronger protection of free expression. Of course, perhaps a particular state high court has not protected the liberty or equality claim at question beyond the protection offered by the U.S. Supreme Court. But that conclusion reflects the state high court’s agreement with the Supreme Court majority’s view of the disputed rights, not a lack of power in the state court to disagree. Thus, the final, authoritative judicial declaration of how much rights protection individual citizens actually receive commonly depends on state constitutional interpretation.76 This means that any popular discontent with judicial rights protection“Why, there oughta be a law!”might be targeted at federal institutions and articulated in federal terms,77 but reflects a (perhaps unwitting) response to state constitutionalism. The speeder wishing to contest her ticket before a jury but told she lacks the right to do so might complain about an inadequate Sixth Amendment right to a jury trial, but it is also the state constitution that did not protect her right (although it could have). If the speeder is truly exercised, she might initiate democratic debate leading to a change in the federal understanding of jury-trial rights. But that national result was caused, in part, by the state high court’s interpretation of the state constitution. As Gardner eloquently observes, “My welfare, in other words, depends not only on our shared national Constitution and on my state constitution, but also to some extent on your state constitution as well.”78 State constitutions form a front-line part of the overall American constitutional net protecting liberty and equality. It would seem both fair and accurate, then, to suggest that state constitutional decisions form part of the ongoing federal constitutional interpretive project. B. Can State Constitutional Decisions Work as Federal Dissents? State constitutional majority decisions are law. They mediate, legitimize, and mobilize real violence against human beings.79 Dissents, on the other hand, do not. A dissent is a “story,” an emotional outburst or 76 The state constitution might be interpreted to be less protective than the federal Constitution, but it would then have the same practical effect as if it had the same level of protection, because federal law is supreme. 77 See, e.g., Area Man Passionate Defender of What He Imagines Constitution To Be, ONION, Nov. 14, 2009, http://www.theonion.com/content/news/area_man_passionate_defender_of (satirically illustrating the cultural prominence of the federal Constitution). 78 GARDNER, supra note 5, at 122. 79 See Robert M. Cover, Essay, Violence and the Word, 95 YALE L.J. 1601, 1606 (1986) (identifying the use or threat of violence as essential to the distinction between law and literature). 600 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:585 an attempt to persuade, but powerless to “announce[] . . . new law.”80 How, then, could a decision be a dissent? To begin to resolve that paradox, this Essay first considers why any judge might take the trouble to pen a dissent. Standard explanations for dissenting might envision the dissent as motivated by an attempt to persuade a future Supreme Court to reverse course or an effort to gain political capital for the dissenter against the other Justices for use in future disputes.81 Demosprudence, as seen already, explains some dissents as an attempt to inspire democratic action.82 Additionally, Justice Brennan once suggested that one reason for a federal Justice to dissent lies in the dissent’s potential to persuade a state high court to adopt the dissenter’s rationale as a matter of state constitutional law.83 Could state constitutional decisions, in turn, influence the interpretative strategies of national institutions, including the U.S. Supreme Court? Recent empirical work suggests that “[f]rom due process to equal protection, from the First Amendment to the Fourth and Sixth, the [U.S.] Supreme Court routinelyand explicitlybases constitutional protection on whether a majority of states agree with it.”84 State constitutional decisions, although binding in the state where issued, are merely persuasive everywhere else. They do not impose the state judges’ views on the national polity. In this way, state constitutional decisions are simultaneously law and not-law, depending on one’s territorial vantage point. The generic reasons for dissenting might also help motivate a state high court to adopt an independent state constitutional analysis. For example, just as a Justice might use a dissent to convince her colleagues that future disagreements might provoke future dissents, so a prior independent state constitutional interpretation might serve as a signal to the U.S. Supreme Court that the state high court is willing to reject federal doctrine again in the future.85 To the extent they find federal constitutional jurisprudence unpersuasive—which is frequently the case when a state court construes its state constitution beyond the federal floor—state high courts implicitly or explicitly criticize the U.S. Supreme Court. Doing so might come at some cost to norms of collegiality and respect, just as dissenting from within the 80 Guinier, Foreword, supra note 3, at 48–49. See Johnson et al., supra note 17, at 1568–69 (describing reasons to dissent). 82 See Guinier, Courting the People, supra note 15, at 544–45. 83 See William J. Brennan, Jr., Associate Justice of the U.S. Supreme Court, In Defense of Dissents, Third Annual Matthew O. Tobriner Memorial Lecture at the University of California, Hastings College of Law (Nov. 18, 1985), in 37 HASTINGS L.J. 427, 430 (1986). 84 Corinna Barrett Lain, The Unexceptionalism of “Evolving Standards,” 57 UCLA L. REV. (forthcoming 2009). 85 See, e.g., Commonwealth v. Wasson, 842 S.W.2d 487, 497 (Ky. 1992) (justifying a state constitutional interpretation at odds with federal doctrine by reference to an earlier independent state constitutional interpretation). 81 2009] DEMOSPRUDENCE, INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM 601 86 Court does, so one might not be surprised to find autonomous state constitutionalism practiced only intermittently.87 Nevertheless, the state judges might be motivated to pay that cost by a desire to change future federal doctrine, to gain credibility vis-à-vis the U.S. Supreme Court, and to inspire public political action. The following review of the Connecticut Supreme Court’s decision in Sheff and the Iowa Supreme Court’s decision in Varnum suggests that the functions of a dissent do indeed underlie these state courts’ independent constitutional interpretation. C. Can State Constitutional Decisions Meet the Demosprudence Criteria? Guinier proposes a three-part definition of the demosprudential dissent. First, the dissent must be centrally concerned with an “issue of democracy”; second, the writing must be easily comprehensible to ordinary people outside of the legal elite; and, finally, the dissent must “appear[] to inspire nonjudicial actors to participate in some form of collective problem solving.”88 Notably, on their face, none of these criteria are exclusively limited to U.S. Supreme Court dissents. If an independent state constitutional decision deals with issues of liberty, equality, or basic governmental structure, is written in plain terms, and seems to target ordinary people to deliberate democratically, then the decision would seem to satisfy the core characteristics of a demosprudential dissent. To test whether state constitutional decisions can sometimes meet these criteria, this Essay now turns to actual examples of independent state constitutionalism. V. SHEFF V. O’NEILL AND SCHOOL DESEGREGATION Through the 1970s and 1980s, the U.S. Supreme Court adopted an increasingly hostile view toward desegregation and education rights. In cases like San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez, holding that a Texas school financing system that disadvantaged poor schools did not violate the federal Equal Protection Clause,89 and Milliken v. Bradley, holding that remedial orders for de jure segregation must be confined to the district found to have segregated rather than directed toward a regional solution,90 the U.S. Supreme Court clearly signaled its impatience to end federal court efforts to reverse racial isolation in public schools. The Court’s distaste for ongoing supervision of school desegregation continued 86 See Johnson et al., supra note 17, at 1570 (establishing empirically the significance of collegiality as a motivation to dissent or not). 87 See Justin Long, Intermittent State Constitutionalism, 34 PEPP. L. REV. 41, 42 (2006) (noting the phenomenon of inconsistently independent state constitutional interpretation). 88 See Guinier, Foreword, supra note 3, at 16. 89 San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1, 41, 54–55 (1973). 90 Milliken v. Bradley, 418 U.S. 717, 744–45 (1974). 602 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:585 91 with cases like Allen v. Wright. There, parents of black schoolchildren sued to compel the Internal Revenue Service to enforce anti-discrimination rules against all-white (yet purportedly tax-exempt) private schools, but the U.S. Supreme Court held that the plaintiffs lacked standing.92 These cases certainly gave civil rights lawyers (and the children they represented) good reason to feel discouraged. Early lawsuits in federal court designed to repair the racial isolation in inner-city schools were dropped when Milliken made plain that the federal Constitution could not support inter-district desegregation.93 Yet, rather than accept the Supreme Court’s normative vision of a color-blind Constitution upholding a radically racist education system, civil rights lawyers looked for alternative spaces in which they could contest the federal Court’s proffered nomos. Specifically, they turned to state constitutionalism.94 In April 1989, lawyers from a host of state and national civil rights organizations, including the American Civil Liberties Union (“ACLU”) and the NAACP Legal Defense and Educational Fund (“LDF”), filed a complaint in Connecticut Superior Court seeking a declaration that the isolation of racial minorities in the Hartford Public Schools breached the state’s constitutional obligation to provide equal educational opportunity.95 Unlike conventional school desegregation cases at the time, the plaintiffs did not raise federal constitutional claims because they alleged only de facto segregation, not the de jure segregation the U.S. Supreme Court had come to require before finding a constitutional violation.96 The plaintiffs’ efforts would be vindicated, in 1996, by the Connecticut Supreme Court decision in Sheff v. O’Neill.97 In shifting from federal to state constitutional litigation, lawyers like John Brittain of the Sheff plaintiffs’ team were not expressing an epiphany that Connecticut values, rather than American values, would provide the moral girding necessary for constitutionalized desegregation. To the contrary, these legal elitesthe cream of the national civil rights 91 468 U.S. 737, 757–58 (1984) (holding that the claimed injury of diminished education to children was not fairly traceable to the government conduct alleged to be unlawful). 92 See id. at 739–40. 93 See SUSAN B. EATON, THE CHILDREN IN ROOM E4: AMERICAN EDUCATION ON TRIAL 80–81 (2006) (describing Hartford-area school desegregation cases filed in federal court but rejected upon application of Milliken); George Judson, Civil Rights Lawyers Hope to Use Hartford Schools Case as a Model, N.Y. TIMES, Aug. 15, 1996, at B1 (noting that the U.S. Supreme Court’s anti-integrationist decision in Milliken led to the failure of Hartford school desegregation cases filed in federal court). 94 See Peter D. Enrich, Race and Money, Courts and Schools: Tentative Lessons from Connecticut, 36 IND. L. REV. 523, 524–25 (2003) (noting that education reform advocates turned toward state constitutional litigation to advance public school integration after U.S. Supreme Court retrenchment in the 1970s). 95 See EATON, supra note 93, at 93, 111–12 (describing the story behind the filing of Sheff). 96 See Charlotte Libov, State Readies Court Reply to Desegregation Suit, N.Y. TIMES, Aug. 13, 1989, at 12CN1 (describing the gravamen of the Sheff complaint). 97 678 A.2d 1267, 1270–71 (Conn. 1996). For a previous study of this case, see Justin R. Long, Comment, Enforcing Affirmative State Constitutional Obligations and Sheff v. O’Neill, 151 U. PA. L. REV. 277 (2002). 2009] DEMOSPRUDENCE, INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM 603 barpersisted in their belief that the federal Constitution should have been construed to protect equal educational opportunity; state constitutional litigation was the lawyers’ solution to evade the restrictive federal precedents while still offering school children across the country a constitutional remedy.98 After all, the racial isolation in Hartfordwhere over ninety percent of the students were black or Latino, contrasted with the suburbs, where over ninety percent of the students were white99was a small part of a nationwide pattern that persists today. In American public schools, most black children have been assigned to mostly minority schools; there has never been a single year where our schools were more integrated than that.100 Funding for the Sheff plaintiffs from the ACLU and the LDF would hardly have been forthcoming if those national organizations did not see the case as a role model of national significance. The Sheff complaint thus illustrates the practical role of state constitutionalism as an alternative site to contest American constitutional values and reiterates the potential of state constitutionalism to stand as a counterweight to the U.S. Supreme Court’s perceived role as final arbiter of constitutional values. One might appropriately see the origins of the Sheff complaint as support for the interactive federalism theory: state constitutionalism as commentary on national constitutional values. But does the state high court’s opinion in Sheff satisfy Guinier’s criteria for demosprudence? First, demosprudence requires the case to be about an “issue of democracy.”101 School desegregation, the issue in Sheff, unequivocally fits. As a recent student commentator records, training for the responsibilities of democratic citizenship has always been a prominent purpose of public education in this country.102 Education philosopher Amy Gutmann has written comprehensively on the mutually affirming importance of public education and democratic citizenship.103 And the Sheff court itself acknowledged the close relationship between educational equity and the success of American democracy.104 Issues of race and children are also culturally powerful and controversial, and so likely to strike ordinary Americans as foundational in a way that other issues might not. Second, a demosprudential opinion is written in a rhetorical style that 98 See EATON, supra note 93, at 112. See Libov, supra note 96 (providing racial balance statistics). 100 See PETER IRONS, JIM CROW’S CHILDREN: THE BROKEN PROMISE OF THE BROWN DECISION 338 (Viking 2002) (describing the national failure to integrate public schools). 101 See Guinier, Foreword, supra note 3, at 16. 102 See Donnelly, supra note 72, at 964–65. 103 See AMY GUTMANN, DEMOCRATIC EDUCATION 139–48 (1999) (describing the undemocratic nature of unequal educational opportunity). 104 See Sheff v. O’Neill, 678 A.2d 1267, 1289 (Conn. 1996) (“It is crucial for a democratic society to provide all of its schoolchildren with fair access to an unsegregated education.”). 99 604 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:585 avoids legal jargon and is within the reading comprehension of ordinary people. Parts, but not all, of the Sheff decision satisfy this criterion. “The public elementary and high school students in Hartford suffer daily from the devastating effects that racial and ethnic isolation, as well as poverty, have had on their education,” wrote Chief Justice Ellen Peters for the Sheff court.105 In words surely everyone could understand, the court announced its disposition: “We hold today that the needy schoolchildren of Hartford have waited long enough.”106 Although the court declined to issue an injunction or other remedy beyond its declaratory judgment, it explained the urgency behind its holding, reminding readers that “[f]inding a way to cross the racial and ethnic divide has never been more important than it is today.”107 These phrases are both simple and powerful. They appear in the Connecticut Reports, but they would not be tonally out of place in a newspaper editorial or on a television talk show. The rhetoric appeals to emotions and values as much as to cold legal logic. In this sense, Sheff exhibits the second feature of a demosprudential opinion. Finally, demosprudence requires the judicial writing to target people outside of the legal elite for inspiration toward democratic change. Some features of the decision do seem self-consciously outward-looking in this fashion. In introducing the case, for example, the court noted that the complaint “raises questions that are difficult; the answers that we give are controversial. We are, however, persuaded that a fair reading of the text and history of [the state constitution] . . . [demands a public school system that] provides Connecticut schoolchildren with a substantially equal educational opportunity.”108 These lines seem like an attempt to forestall a backlash; it is as if the court is saying that it knows many people will not like its decision, but that the public should trust the court’s sincerity and wisdom. As Post and Siegel have taught us, backlashes are themselves instances of democratic engagement with constitutionalism,109 and so for the Sheff court to attempt to calm citizens who might otherwise be tempted to engage in popular sovereignty logically implies that the court is speaking to ordinary people outside the legal elite. The remedial portion of Sheff, though, is the most clearly outward-looking component of the opinion. Chief Justice Peters wrote: In staying our hand, we do not wish to be misunderstood. . . . Every passing day shortchanges these children in their ability to learn to contribute to their own well-being and to that of this state and nation. We direct the legislature and the executive branch to put the search for 105 Id. at 1270. Id. 107 Id. at 1290. 108 Id. at 1280. 109 See Post & Siegel, supra note 32, at 390. 106 2009] DEMOSPRUDENCE, INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM 605 appropriate remedial measures at the top of their respective agendas. We are confident that with energy and good will, appropriate remedies can be found and implemented in time to make a difference before another generation of children suffers the consequences of a segregated public school education.110 In this passage, the court is speaking to the public and to public officials quite explicitly, in both tone and substance. In that sense, the opinion seeks to engage ordinary people and inspire them toward political action, and so satisfies the third element of a demosprudential opinion. Indeed, Sheff has inspired much political debate in Connecticut (though disappointingly little action).111 The true test of whether a state constitutional opinion can be a federal constitutional demosprudential dissent, however, presumably cannot rest on inspiring local political action.112 Evidence that Sheff inspired ordinary people or political leaders to reconsider or debate national values would go further toward establishing the demosprudential potential of state constitutional opinions. As it happens, some evidence of that type does exist. For example, one of Connecticut’s U.S. Senators referred to Sheff by name in an address in favor of education reform on the Senate floor.113 An editorial in the Christian Science Monitor, a national newspaper, praised Sheff and situated the case unambiguously in the national struggle for educational equity, arguing that “[c]ourt decisions like that in Connecticut, though they offer no pat solutions, can at least keep us focused on the need to work together toward a more meaningful education for all America’s children.”114 And predictably, civil rights lawyers from other states were eager to learn from the Connecticut experience so as to seek similar progress from their own state courts.115 On balance, the Sheff opinion seems to satisfy Guinier’s concept of a federal constitutional demosprudential dissent. The case was brought to avoid giving the U.S. Supreme Court the final word in an area of law where it had declined to protect liberty and equality, and the state high court did indeed use its power to interpret the state constitution to reject the 110 Sheff, 678 A.2d at 1290. See Vanessa de la Torre, Sheff Backers Worry About State Budget, HARTFORD COURANT, June 16, 2009, at A3 (quoting the co-chairman of the state legislature’s education committee urging support for increased education funding by asking the legislature to meet “‘its [still un-satisfied] legal and moral responsibilities’” under Sheff). 112 But cf. Guinier, Foreword, supra note 3, at 12 (describing a Louisville school official’s use of Justice Breyer’s dissent in Parents Involved to promote local political change). 113 See 147 CONG. REC. S1271-02 (daily ed. Feb. 13, 2001) (statement of Sen. Lieberman) (supporting an amendment to the Elementary & Secondary Education Act of 1965 by praising a Connecticut school’s response to Sheff). 114 Editorial, Desegregation Dilemma, CHRISTIAN SCI. MONITOR, July 30, 1996, at 20. 115 See Judson, supra note 93 (describing contact between Sheff attorneys and civil rights lawyers in other states hoping to emulate Sheff in evading federal court retrenchment). 111 606 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:585 authority of unfavorable federal precedent. The case was about a crucial problem confronting American democracy. In addressing that problem, the court’s opinion speaks in emotional, moral tones to reach and inspire members of the general public. And the opinion urges politicians and ordinary people to respond to its holding with democratic vigor, encouraging a popular debate about national constitutional values and prioritiesthe American nomos. VI. VARNUM AND SAME-SEX MARRIAGE Can the potential of state constitutional decisions to serve as federal constitutional demosprudential dissents find expression in cases other than Sheff? The Iowa Supreme Court’s recent same-sex marriage decision, Varnum v. Brien,116 suggests that Sheff might not be just an outlier. First, although decided strictly on state constitutional grounds, Justice Cady’s decision in Varnum is entirely bereft of any suggestion that the justices would have decided the case differently if they were sitting on the U.S. Supreme Court. The justices applied federal-style equal protection reasoning,117 they cited federal precedents,118 and they expressed a (unanimous) moral confidence that transcended text or jurisdiction.119 The Varnum court sought to effectuate the aspirational values of the state constitution, as Schapiro would encourage, but the values the court identified are national in scope and significance, as the court selfconsciously noted: “The same-sex-marriage debate waged in this case is part of a strong national dialogue centered on a fundamental, deep-seated, traditional institution that has excluded, by state action, a particular class of Iowans.”120 Varnum, to its very core, is about national constitutional values. Furthermore, the decision proudly rejects U.S. Supreme Court jurisprudence on the issue at bar, and in that sense works as a federal dissent, consistent with interactive federalism. Some rejection is explicit, as where the court lists a series of Iowa constitutional decisions extending equality protections in advance of the U.S. Supreme Court’s recognition of 116 763 N.W.2d 862 (Iowa 2009). See id. at 879–80 (describing three tiers of equal protection review: rational basis, intermediate scrutiny, and strict scrutiny). 118 See, e.g., id. at 880 (citing, among others, Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202, 217–18 (1982); United States v. Carolene Prods. Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 (1938); United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515, 532– 33 (1996)); see also Varnum, 763 N.W.2d at 885–86 (“Although neither we nor the United States Supreme Court has decided which level of scrutiny applies to legislative classifications based on sexual orientation, numerous Supreme Court equal protection cases provide a general framework to guide our analysis under the Iowa Constitution.”). 119 See Varnum, 763 N.W.2d at 890 (“Not surprisingly, none of the same-sex marriage decisions from other state courts around the nation have found a person’s sexual orientation to be indicative of the person's general ability to contribute to society.”). 120 Id. at 878. 117 2009] DEMOSPRUDENCE, INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM 607 121 the same rights. Some rejection is stated only indirectly, as where the court uses federal constitutional terms of art but reaches a conclusion contrary to that of the federal government.122 And some rejection is entirely implicit, as where the court describes the same-sex marriage question as open under federal Supreme Court precedent,123 without addressing the U.S. Supreme Court’s decision dismissing a same-sex marriage appeal “for want of [a] substantial federal question” in 1972.124 In acting as a dissent from U.S. Supreme Court constitutional understandings, the Varnum decision fulfills the functionalist role of state constitutions described by Gardner; the court protects its citizens from at least some of the federal government’s intrusions on their right to equality. As Post and Siegel predicted, state constitutional same-sex marriage decisions serve as loci of contestation over national values and constitutional norms.125 Just as Varnum seems to match interactive federalist notions of the role of state constitutionalism in checking the federal government and courts, so too the decision fits well with the criteria for a demosprudential dissent. As a case about marriage, a recognized “fundamental right” under the federal Constitution, the issue can reasonably be described as one concerning “democracy.” With respect to tone and accessibility, few recent constitutional decisions of any American court could match the powerfully inclusive embrace inherent in these plain and gentle lines: This lawsuit is a civil rights action by twelve individuals who reside in six communities across Iowa. Like most Iowans, they are responsible, caring, and productive individuals . . . . Like many Iowans, some have children and others hope to have children. Some are foster parents. Like all Iowans, they prize their liberties and live within the borders of this state with the expectation that their rights will be maintained and protecteda belief embraced by our state motto . . . . Each maintains a hope of getting married one day, an aspiration shared by many throughout Iowa.126 The steady repetition of the plaintiffs’ commonalities with “most Iowans” speaks directly to common folk, reminding them of who they are and what sort of community they hope to maintain. The court’s emotional, moral, and simply-phrased tone accomplishes nothing from a coldly 121 See id. at 877 (noting Iowa’s prescient rejection of the later-overturned federal holdings in Dred Scott v. Sandford, 60 U.S. (19 How.) 393 (1856), Bradwell v. Illinois, 83 U.S. (16 Wall.) 130 (1871), and others). 122 See id. at 906 (“We are firmly convinced the exclusion of gay and lesbian people from the institution of civil marriage does not substantially further any important governmental objective.”). 123 Id. at 878–79 n.6. 124 See Baker v. Nelson, 409 U.S. 810, 810 (1972). 125 See Post & Siegel, supra note 32, at 381–82. 126 Varnum, 763 N.W.2d at 872. 608 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:585 legalistic perspective, but it seems to attempt a reassurance for the ordinary reader that the court’s decision deserves respect. Varnum, along with other same-sex marriage cases on both sides of the issue, appears to have inspired a national debate by activists, politicians, and the public about the constitutional values the decision expresses. Activists and organizers for Lambda Legal, the national LGBTQ-rights organization whose lawyers won the decision in Varnum, also played a central role in the legal and political fights over same-sex marriage in California.127 Newspaper reports suggest that Varnum’s influence falls well beyond the Iowa cornfields; one California minister told a reporter he thought the decision would spark a popular backlash against “‘activist judges’ in general,” but a California gay-rights activist predicted to the same journalist that Iowa’s reputation as “Middle America” and “the heartland” would open more minds to the possibility of following Varnum.128 John Logan, a sociologist, agreed that Varnum’s origin in a rural, Midwest state could make same-sex marriage seem more “related to core American values” than similar decisions in the high courts of Furthermore, state constitutional Massachusetts and California.129 decisions like Varnum might already be increasing the political pressure on President Obama to expand federal rights for same-sex couples (a vivid example, if true, of how Gerald Rosenberg’s focus on quantifiable shifts in polling data might overlook more important aspects of deliberative democracy).130 VII. CONCLUSION State constitutional scholars, working over the last decade, have developed a rich set of theories to explain how state constitutional decisions can serve as a liberty-enhancing counterweight to U.S. Supreme Court decisions. In focusing on the state-federal relationship, however, the scholarship on interactive federalism has paid little attention to the relationship of this judicial dialogue to deliberative democracy. On the other hand, the very recent development of demosprudence theory greatly advances our understanding of the connection between 127 See Lambda Legal, Varnum v. Brien, http://www.lambdalegal.org/in-court/cases/varnum-vbrien.html (last visited Oct. 13, 2009); Lambda Legal, California, http://www.lambdalegal.org/statesregions/california.html (last visited Oct. 13, 2009); see also John Schwartz, Ruling Upholds California’s Ban on Gay Marriage, N.Y. TIMES, May 27, 2009, at A1. 128 Jessica Garrison & Maura Dolan, Iowa’s OK of Gay Marriage Could Bolster Prop. 8 Foes, L.A. TIMES, Apr. 4, 2009, at A1. 129 See Amy Lorentzen, Same-Sex Marriage Upheld in Iowa: State First in Nation’s Heartland to Join Massachusetts, Connecticut, STAR-LEDGER (Newark, N.J.), Apr. 4, 2009, at 3 (explaining that decisions in Massachusetts and California could be viewed as extremism on the coasts, rather than related to core American values). 130 See Michael D. Shear, At White House, Obama Aims to Reassure Gays, WASH. POST, June 30, 2009, at A1 (reporting that President Obama promised to work toward repeal of the federal Defense of Marriage Act that prohibits federal recognition of same-sex marriages). 2009] DEMOSPRUDENCE, INTERACTIVE FEDERALISM 609 judicial and popular constructions of constitutional values. But that scholarship overlooks almost entirely the extraordinary capacity of state constitutional decisions to offer an alternative site for legitimate contestation of U.S. Supreme Court jurisprudence. This Essay has asked whether these two schools of thought might contribute to each other. By studying two state constitutional opinions, it tested the idea that these types of decisions might sometimes work as demosprudential dissents. Both Sheff v. O’Neill, the Connecticut school desegregation case, and Varnum v. Brien, the Iowa same-sex marriage case, appear to function both as examples of interactive federalism and as examples of demosprudential dissents. Perhaps future scholarship will continue to espouse an integrated approach toward state constitutionalism and demosprudence theory. CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW VOLUME 42 DECEMBER 2009 NUMBER 2 Note GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET JEFFREY M. DRESSLER This Note analyzes the intersection of two fundamental components of American sales law under the Uniform Commercial Code: the perfect tender rule and the duty of good faith. It focuses on cases in which buyers of goods use their right to perfect tender to avoid purchasing goods that have become diminished in value. Some commentators, and, indeed, some courts, have argued that such conduct runs afoul of parties’ underlying duty of good faith in the performance of contracts. This Note rejects this position, and, instead, argues that if goods are truly non-conforming—even if only “trivially” non-conforming—buyers should retain their right of rejection irrespective of the hardship this may impose on the seller of goods. In short, this Note suggests that the duty of good faith should never override a party’s otherwise tenable right of rejection and advocates a judicial framework that can allow courts to deal with difficult cases in a way that is consistent with the intent of the parties and conducive to the development of a more predictable body of contract law. 611 NOTE CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................... 613 II. THE ACADEMIC BACKDROP ............................................................ 615 A. THE PERFECT TENDER RULE ............................................................... 615 B. THE DUTY OF GOOD FAITH IN PERFORMANCE .................................... 621 C. GOOD FAITH IN PERFECT TENDER CASES ............................................ 627 III. JUDICIAL APPLICATION .................................................................. 629 IV. A NEW FRAMEWORK ....................................................................... 633 A. CONSIDERATION OF FALLING MARKET CONDITIONS IS NOT HELPFUL IN DECIDING CASES ............................................. 633 B. THE ARGUMENT FOR CATEGORICAL EXCLUSION ................................ 637 C. POTENTIAL FOR ABUSE CAN BE LIMITED BY OTHER LEGAL DOCTRINES AND PERFECT TENDER RULE CONSTRAINTS .... 640 V. CONCLUSION ...................................................................................... 643 GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET JEFFREY M. DRESSLER* I. INTRODUCTION Modern contracts literature is ripe with discussions of the duty of good faith under Article II of the Uniform Commercial Code (“U.C.C.”). Likewise, the rules governing a buyer’s right to reject non-conforming goods under section 2-601—better known as the perfect tender rule—have been vigorously debated. The two issues often intersect. While the perfect tender rule may suggest that a buyer possesses an unwavering right to reject in certain circumstances, the duty of good faith may suggest an obligation to use some degree of equitable restraint in invoking this right so as to not exploit the seller. Nowhere is this dynamic more apparent than in cases where the merits of a particular rejection are challenged against the backdrop of a falling market1 that might lead a reasonable observer to suspect that the buyer’s rejection was actually motivated by a desire to escape from a bad bargain rather than out of legitimate dissatisfaction with any non-conformities in the goods tendered. Exploring this area requires a survey of the contrasting views of the obligation of good faith, however, this Note does not seek to add to the philosophical debate about what good faith should be. Instead, this Note tackles the more pragmatic task of demonstrating why current conceptions of good faith should not be used to restrict the force of the perfect tender rule, especially in the context of sophisticated commercial parties. Ultimately, the goal is to articulate under what circumstances a buyer may reject goods in a falling market, and whether sellers should be permitted to offer evidence of a falling market in order to establish that the buyer rejected in bad faith. This Note argues that buyers should be entitled to reject goods that are truly, even if only trivially, non-conforming regardless of the economic hardship this imposes on a seller. Further, this Note argues that plaintiffsellers should not be permitted to use evidence of a falling market in order to establish that such rejection was made in bad faith. To get there, Part II tackles the sticky issue of defining when goods are non-conforming. It * University of Connecticut, B.A. 2006; University of Connecticut School of Law, J.D. Candidate 2010. I would like to thank Professor Kurt Strasser for his tremendous guidance in writing this Note and for inspiring my interest in contract law. I would also like to thank my colleagues on Connecticut Law Review for their hard work editing this Note. All errors are mine and mine alone. This Note is dedicated to my parents for their unending support. 1 Throughout this Note, the term “falling market” is used as a shorthand to describe a situation in which the fair market value of goods falls significantly between the time the buyer agrees to purchase them from a seller and the time the goods are actually delivered. 614 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 argues that any defect that impinges on the bargain the parties struck should be deemed a non-conformity under the perfect tender rule. As many cases show, this may include “trivial” defects if they do in fact bear such significance to the parties’ bargain. Part II also surveys good faith, ultimately concluding that the most useful model for understanding good faith in this context is an excluder model that repudiates any conduct failing to satisfy the two types of conduct affirmatively required for good faith under the U.C.C.: honesty and commercial reasonableness. Part III then analyzes cases that have dealt with contested rejections and, specifically, cases where sellers relied on arguments that the buyer’s rejection was made in bad faith to escape a bad bargain caused by a falling market for the goods. The cases indicate a divide between courts that factor falling market evidence into their reasoning, and those that either refuse to admit such evidence, or are not persuaded by it. As such, this area of the law is worthy of more study and, hopefully with time, more consistency. With this as a starting point, Part IV argues that courts should resist the urge to use falling market conditions as evidence of a bad faith rejection because this type of evidence does not help determine if a non-conformity in the goods actually exists; only the terms of the contract and the relevant commercial standards help in this regard. Further—assuming a nonconformity does exist—it is not bad faith to act on it in a falling market because doing so is both honest and commercially reasonable. It is honest because, having already established that a non-conformity exists, the honesty prong of good faith should be treated as a nullity in this narrow context. This is so because, even conceding that the falling market was a factor that made the non-conformity intolerable, ultimately the decision to reject was made in light of the fact that a non-conformity actually existed. Further, particularly in the context of sophisticated parties, around which the majority of this discussion revolves, it is commercially reasonable for a party to consider the value for the goods when deciding whether to enforce his right of rejection to the fullest and, indeed, it is generally commercially reasonable for him to insist on the full benefit of his bargain by rejecting under those circumstances. Part IV also argues that, in addition to being unhelpful for the ultimate resolution of contracts cases, permitting evidence of falling markets offers little more than an alternate holding to the main holding in perfect tender cases and, as such, detracts from the development of an efficient and predictable law of contracts. Worse still, this uncertainty encourages litigation by lending support to sellers in future cases who tender nonconforming goods in a falling market, only to cry foul when those goods are rightly rejected. This in turn may have the perverse effect of denying buyers the full benefit of the contracts they bargained for. Finally, Part V concludes by testing the framework advocated in the Note against the facts 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 615 found in previous judicial decisions. II. THE ACADEMIC BACKDROP A. The Perfect Tender Rule U.C.C. section 2-601 provides that in the case of one-shot contracts, buyers may reject the whole “if the goods or the tender of delivery fail in any respect to conform to the contract . . . .”2 The buyer in turn has a corresponding duty “to accept and pay in accordance with the contract.”3 Courts have agreed that section 2-601 reflects a statutory revival of the perfect tender rule.4 The purpose of the perfect tender rule, according to Professor Corbin, is “to secure high performance standards” because without the fear of a buyer’s ability to reject goods, sellers “would be tempted to saddle buyers with unsuitable and defective goods.”5 Professor Miniter provided a popular example of the unfairness that could result if substantial performance were allowed instead of perfect tender: A seller might find that it is significantly cheaper to make the machinery capable of operation within a seven percent deviation than to make it operate within only a five percent deviation as required by the contract. He would be gambling that the buyer could not make out a case for substantial impairment independent of the contract and that any damages that the buyer might prove would be less than his cost savings in producing the inferior machine.6 The possibility of sub-par performance is considered to be more likely to occur in the performance of one-shot contracts, where the absence of a continuous commercial relationship gives the buyer less leverage as to slightly non-conforming goods. For this reason, only one-shot contracts are subject to the perfect tender rule, while installment contracts are subject to a “substantial performance” requirement.7 2 U.C.C. § 2-601 (2002). Proper rejection entails not only a simple refusal to accept the goods, but also notification to the buyer. If goods are not accepted when they should be, the refusal is said to be “wrongful.” See U.C.C. § 2-703 (2002). If goods could have been rejected, but notice was improperly given, then the rejection is said to be ineffective. See 67 AM. JUR. 2D Sales § 592 (2003). 3 U.C.C. § 2-301 (2002). 4 See, e.g., Ramirez v. Autosport, 440 A.2d 1345, 1349 (N.J. 1982) (“To the extent that a buyer can reject goods for any nonconformity, the UCC retains the perfect tender rule.”). 5 8 CATHERINE M.A. MCCAULIFF, CORBIN ON CONTRACTS, CONDITIONS § 33.3 (Joseph M. Perillo ed., 1999). 6 Francis A. Miniter, Buyer’s Right of Rejection, 13 GA. L. REV. 805, 826 (1979). Miniter’s hypothetical is based on the facts of Axion Corp. v. G.D.C. Leasing Corp., 269 N.E.2d 664, 666, 668– 69 (Mass. 1971). 7 Installment contracts are dealt with in U.C.C. § 2-612 (2002). The remainder of this Note discusses only single transaction contracts. For a useful commentary on installment contracts, see 616 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 Almost immediately after the first draft of the U.C.C. was approved, commentators challenged the strength of its conception of the rule. For instance, White and Summers are “skeptical of the real importance of the perfect tender rule,” and argue that the law would be “little changed” if courts required a substantial non-conformity for rejection.8 Then-Professor Ellen Peters called the U.C.C.’s perfect tender rule “a mere shadow of its formerly robust self.”9 Among the many statutory limitations on a buyer’s right to insist on perfection are the fact that goods need not actually be perfect, but rather only need to conform precisely to the terms of the contract (subject to trade usage, course of performance, and course of dealing), the seller’s right to cure, and—perhaps most significantly—the obligation of good faith.10 Courts, however, have not been nearly as eager to declare the perfect tender rule lifeless, and as Professor William Lawrence has argued, “commentators have greatly exaggerated the extent to which the limitations in Article 2 undercut the application of the perfect tender rule.”11 Nevertheless, a brief sketch of the relevant limitations on the buyer’s otherwise formidable right to reject goods is appropriate. 1. Distinguishing Between Conforming and Non-Conforming Goods a. The Perfection Misnomer Professor Williston points out that the perfect tender rule “is somewhat of a misnomer” because the goods do not have to be literally perfect, but must merely conform to the terms of the contract.12 The terms of the contract include both written specifications and supplemental terms that are inferred from trade usage, course of dealing, and course of performance. The more specificity that the parties choose to use in the language of their contract, the less they will have to supplement the understanding of what was to be tendered against more ambiguous concepts such as trade usage. This is a simple point yet it is often overlooked. In essence, parties control their own destiny with respect to the level of perfection required. Parties should be able to bargain for all JAMES J. WHITE & ROBERT S. SUMMERS, UNIFORM COMMERCIAL CODE 302–05 (West Publishing Co., 4th ed. 1995). 8 WHITE & SUMMERS, supra note 7, at 300–01. 9 Ellen A. Peters, Remedies for Breach of Contracts Relating to the Sale of Goods Under the Uniform Commercial Code, 73 YALE L.J. 199, 206 (1963). 10 Other asserted limits on the perfect tender rule include the fact that installment contracts are dealt with in an entirely different section, section 2-504, which provides that an improper shipment contract that causes a late delivery is grounds for rejection only if “material delay or loss ensues.” U.C.C. § 2-504 (2002). Finally, courts may manipulate otherwise acceptable revocations for minor defects under the guise of some other procedural device such as failure to make a proper rejection. See WHITE & SUMMERS, supra note 7, at 301. 11 William H. Lawrence, The Prematurely Reported Demise of the Perfect Tender Rule, 35 U. KAN. L. REV. 557, 558 (1987). 12 14 RICHARD A. LORD, WILLISTON ON CONTRACTS § 40:6 (4th ed. 2000). 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 617 that they want in a transaction. If their negotiations are successful, then courts should have no qualms holding sellers to produce exactly what they promise. Parties that choose to be less descript in the terms they use to reflect that which is to be tendered may find negotiations go smoother; however, this approach leaves more latitude to determine what is and what is not reasonably implied within the definition that the parties did select after the fact. b. Commercial Practices Help Define What Has to Be Tendered Often commercial practices play a significant role in defining the required specifications of a particular good. White and Summers refer to these factors as “[a]dditional restrictions” on the perfect tender rule.13 In fact, it is more helpful to think of them merely as establishing the terms of the contract in cases where the parties did not exercise enough clarity through their own writings. In other words, these concepts do not change the perfect tender rule, they merely shape the requirements of the contract in a way that makes what at first appeared to be a breach actually turn out to be conforming tender.14 An example is when a contract specifies delivery of twelve items, but industry custom is that twelve means anywhere between eleven and thirteen. Under these facts, a delivery of eleven would not invoke the perfect tender rule—not because of an “exception” to the rule, but rather because eleven is a conforming tender in this industry. Prior commercial practices can be disclaimed, but this requires clarity and specificity.15 c. The Debate over “Trivial Defects” Many commentators have suggested that buyers should not be able to reject goods for “insignificant” or “trivial” defects. For example, Professor Robert Summers claims that “a buyer who openly seizes upon trivial defects to justify his rejection . . . admitting all along that he is rejecting the goods because the price has gone down . . . is certainly [acting in] commercial bad faith.”16 Courts, on the other hand, have shown a willingness to enforce the perfect tender rule more vigorously and allow 13 WHITE & SUMMERS, supra note 7, at 300–01. See John A. Sebert, Jr., Rejection, Revocation, and Cure Under Article 2 of the Uniform Commercial Code, 84 NW. U. L. REV. 375, 386–87 (1990). 15 See U.C.C. § 2-202 cmt. 2 (2002) (commercial practices become an element of the meaning of the words used “[u]nless carefully negated”). 16 Robert S. Summers, “Good Faith” in General Contract Law and the Sales Provisions of the Uniform Commercial Code, 54 VA. L. REV. 195, 205–06 (1968); see also Lawrence, supra note 11, at 570 (“Many commentators have praised section 2-508(2) as a desirable provision designed to prevent buyers from rejecting goods with trivial nonconformities in order to escape bargains that become unfavorable because the market for the goods falls.”). But see HOWARD O. HUNTER, MODERN LAW OF CONTRACTS § 11:11 (2008) (“Technically, any failure, however small, is a nonconformity that justifies rejection under § 2-601.”). 14 618 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 buyers to reject even for minor or trivial defects. For instance, in DeJesus v. CAT Auto Tech Corp., a New York court rejected White and Summer’s view that substantial performance should be the standard, stating that “New York has not adopted this view, and continues to subscribe to the perfect tender rule,” which the court described as requiring “exact performance.”17 Likewise, in KCA Electronics, Inc. v. Legacy Electronics, Inc., a California appellate court ruled that “the perfect tender rule imposes ‘a very high level of conformity’ to the contract on sellers, allowing buyers to ‘reject a seller’s tender for any trivial defect, whether it be in the quality of the goods, the timing of the performance, or the manner of delivery.’”18 Some commentators argue these statements are dicta, since the defects in many of the cases containing such language are arguably not insignificant.19 While this may be true in some cases, there remains ample authority in many jurisdictions to support a buyer’s absolute right of rejection as a rule of law. For instance, in DeJesus, the buyer had ordered gift certificates to be distributed to its employees. The court upheld the buyer’s rejection due to the fact that “the paper was different, and the chosen sample contained a decorative border, whereas the finished product did not.”20 And in KCA Electronics, which involved the delivery of canopies designed to allow for the stacking of computer chips, the court held that six percent of the delivered parts lacking uniform features was sufficient to allow the buyer to reject the whole.21 Courts seem particularly likely to allow rejection based on minor nonconformities in cases where the defect goes to a term expressly agreed to by the parties, or where it is clearly important to the buyer. In Texas Imports v. Allday, the parties contracted for the sale of forty-nine cattle.22 The court ruled that ten of the cattle being unsound provided sufficient basis to permit the buyer to reject all of them.23 This was true in spite of the fact that there was no indication in the record that the buyer had been harmed by the tender of ten less sound animals than originally contracted for, as well as circumstantial evidence indicating that the buyer had 17 DeJesus v. CAT Auto Tech Corp., 615 N.Y.S.2d 236, 238 (N.Y. Civ. Ct. 1994); see also Y&N Furniture Inc. v. Nwabuoku, 734 N.Y.S.2d 382, 384 (N.Y. Civ. Ct. 2001) (“The buyer’s right, generally, to reject the goods for any nonconformity, even one that is trivial, is known as the ‘perfect tender rule []’ . . . .”). 18 KCA Elecs., Inc. v. Legacy Elecs., Inc., No. G037285, 2007 WL 2137959, at *1 (Cal. Ct. App. July 26, 2007). 19 WHITE & SUMMERS, supra note 7, at 301–02 n.6; see also Sebert, supra note 14, at 384–85. 20 DeJesus, 615 N.Y.S.2d. at 237. The court also noted that two of the eight certificates had colors immediately outside the borders but that one was “slightly noticeable” and the other “noticeable only upon close inspection.” Id. 21 KCA Elecs., 2007 WL 2137959, at *2. 22 Tex. Imports v. Allday, 649 S.W.2d 730, 732–33 (Tex. App. 1983). 23 Id. at 738. 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 619 24 overbought. In another case, a car buyer was permitted to reject tender of a car that did not have a spare tire.25 In that case, the court noted that the buyer was a traveling salesman who traveled extensively in his trade and the spare tire was important to him for safety reasons.26 Part of the problem fueling the disagreement between courts and commentators may be a matter of mere terminology. Buzz words such as “insignificant” or “trivial” do little to advance the analysis of a defect. A close reading of the case law confirms that a particular defect that is trivial can make goods non-conforming, or may be inadequate to make them nonconforming, depending on a close analysis of what was actually contracted for. A defect may be small (and thus “trivial” under lay usage), yet if it goes to an important component of the good, such as the spare tire to the traveling salesmen, then it should render that good non-conforming. Another small (trivial) defect that does not affect an important component of the tendered good does not make the good non-conforming. This is not because there is some sort of de minimus exception for trivial defects, but rather, because such a defect does not impinge on the bargain the parties struck, and therefore does not make the item legally non-conforming.27 For the duration of this Note, any defect—small, nitpicky, and, yes, even trivial—which goes to the contractually required specifications and thus, if unsatisfied, would permit a buyer to reject will be referred to as “legally significant.” Any non-conformity that is insufficient to trigger a right of rejection—again, not because of the small size of the defect, but because it does not affect what was agreed to be delivered in any meaningful way— will be referred to as “legally insignificant.” 2. Seller’s Right to Cure Section 2-508 of the U.C.C. gives sellers a limited right to cure nonconformities in the goods they tender, thereby maintaining the buyer’s obligation to accept pursuant to the terms of the contract.28 This has been called one of the “most significant new intrusion[s] on the perfect tender rule”; however, there remain “substantial uncertainties” about how to apply it.29 Many commentators talk of the right to cure as though it represents a 24 For example, the buyer did not exercise his right to reject all the cattle, nor did he limit his rejection to the ten non-conforming cattle. Instead, he accepted twenty-seven and rejected twenty-two. See id. at 738; see also Sebert, supra note 14, at 385–86 (discussing the buyer’s probable motive in Texas Imports). 25 Colonial Dodge, Inc. v. Miller, 362 N.W.2d 704, 705 (Mich. 1984). 26 Id. at 706–07. 27 An example of this can be seen in Fanok v. Carver Boat Corp., where the buyer of a yacht tried to reject for scratches on the kitchen table, dirt on the carpet, and master bath shower doors that “rattle a lot when underway.” 576 F. Supp. 2d 404, 418 (E.D.N.Y. 2008). This attempted rejection was made only after the entire yacht had been destroyed by an unexplained fire. Id. Not surprisingly, the court found the alleged defects insufficient under these facts. Id. at 406. 28 See U.C.C. § 2-508 (2002). 29 Sebert, supra note 14, at 389. 620 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 drastic limit on the perfect tender rule. But Professor Lawrence argues that these statements exaggerate the practical effect of the cure provision.30 First, section 2-508(1) only allows a seller to cure defects if it can do so “within the contract time.”31 Therefore, practically speaking, this section is applicable only when the seller tenders goods early. As such, Professor Lawrence argues that it is “not particularly remarkable in light of prior law and business practices.”32 The more significant right to cure is found under section 2-508(2), which provides sellers additional reasonable time to cure if they “had reasonable grounds to believe” that their initial nonconforming tender would be acceptable.33 The comment suggests that the drafters intended for this to be a narrow exception.34 Professor Robert Nordstrom has argued that this subsection was only intended to protect sellers who knew of the defect in their goods, but nonetheless had reason to believe that the goods would still be accepted by the buyer.35 At least one court has rejected this view, and other commentators—including White and Summers—have advocated for broader applicability of section 2508(2).36 However, whatever standard is used to invoke section 2-508(2), once it is successfully invoked, the access to additional time is limited, and as such makes it a difficult provision for sellers to rely on.37 Finally, and perhaps most significantly, under either subsection of 2-508, if a seller is unable (or unwilling) to cure the defect, then the buyer’s rejection stands as valid.38 In other words, the buyer either gets its perfect tender or it gets to reject; in this sense the right to cure is hardly a limit on the effectiveness of 30 See Lawrence, supra note 11, at 568. U.C.C. § 2-508(1). 32 Lawrence, supra note 11, at 563. 33 U.C.C. § 2-508(2). 34 “Such reasonable grounds can lie in prior course of dealing, course of performance or usage of trade as well as in the particular circumstances surrounding the making of the contract.” U.C.C. § 2508 cmt. 2; see also Lawrence, supra note 11, at 564 (arguing that although the comment does not purport to provide an exhaustive list of things that would form the basis for a party to reasonably believe his non-conforming goods would be accepted, it “tends to suggest a narrow range of appropriate criteria”). 35 ROBERT J. NORDSTROM, HANDBOOK OF THE LAW OF SALES 321 (West Publishing Co. 1970). 36 See Joc Oil USA, Inc. v. Consol. Edison Co., 434 N.Y.S.2d 623, 632 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1980). White and Summers think that this remedy should be available if a seller can show (1) that he was ignorant of the defect despite his good faith and prudent business behavior or (2) he had some reason to believe that the goods would be acceptable. WHITE & SUMMERS, supra note 7, at 324. In contrast, Professor Hawkland focuses on the size of the initial defect, reasoning that a seller should be able to invoke section 2-508(2) if “he can do so without subjecting the buyer to any great inconvenience, risk or loss.” William D. Hawkland, Curing an Improper Tender of Title to Chattels, 46 MINN. L. REV. 697, 724 (1962). See generally Michael A. Schmitt & David Frisch, The Perfect Tender Rule—An “Acceptable” Interpretation, 13 U. TOL. L. REV. 1375 (1982) (surveying various attempts to reconcile the perfect tender rule with the cure provisions). 37 See White & Summers, supra note 7, at 322 (stating that cure can only be made within a “reasonable” period of time). 38 See Lawrence, supra note 11, at 567–68 (“The buyer’s right to exact seller performance under the sales contract is not diminished by the right to cure, except for an extension of time [under § 2508(2)].”). 31 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 621 rejection from the buyer’s perspective. 3. Right to Reject Must Be Exercised in Good Faith All aspects of the performance of a contract must be performed in “good faith.”39 Since the rejection of goods is an aspect of performance, rejection—even if otherwise rightful—must be performed in good faith.40 Professor Lawrence believes that of all the so-called “exceptions” to the perfect tender rule, the good faith requirement is the most important (and, from his perspective, the most underutilized).41 Before examining why Professor Lawrence feels this way, it is important to provide some general background on the concept of good faith. B. The Duty of Good Faith in Performance The general obligation of good faith in the performance of contracts is a relatively new concept.42 Section 1-304 of the U.C.C. provides that “[e]very contract or duty within [the Uniform Commercial Code] imposes an obligation of good faith in its performance and enforcement.”43 Under the current Article I, good faith is defined as “honesty in fact and the observance of reasonable commercial standards of fair dealing.”44 The duty of good faith in performance has been hailed as “possibly the single most significant doctrinal development in American contract law over the past fifty years.”45 A full review of the academic literature on the general obligation of good faith in performance under American contract law is beyond the scope of this Note, although ample literature does exist.46 39 U.C.C. § 1-304 (2008). See Lawrence, supra note 11, at 571 (“Invoking the right to reject avoids [a buyer’s] responsibilities and thus can be exercised legitimately only when it is done in good faith.”); see also Linda J. Rusch, Qualifications on Perfect Tender Rule, in 2 WILLIAM D. HAWKLAND, UNIFORM COMMERCIAL CODE SERIES § 2-601:3 (2009) (“[T]here is no doubt that the buyer is under an obligation to act in good faith when he rejects . . . .”). 41 Lawrence, supra note 11, at 571. 42 See Harold Dubroff, The Implied Covenant of Good Faith in Contract Interpretation and GapFilling, 80 ST. JOHN’S L. REV. 559, 571 (2006). 43 U.C.C. § 1-304. 44 Id. § 1-201(20) (2008). Under the U.C.C.’s prior Article I, “good faith” was generally defined to mean only “honesty”; however, Article II has always required merchants to conform with reasonable commercial standards of fair dealing in the trade. See U.C.C. §§ 1-201(19) (2000), 2-103(1)(b) (2002). 45 Sebert, supra note 14, at 383; see also Robert S. Summers, The General Duty of Good Faith— Its Recognition and Conceptualization, 67 CORNELL L. REV. 810, 810 (1982). 46 See generally Eric G. Andersen, Good Faith in the Enforcement of Contracts, 73 IOWA L. REV. 299 (1988); Steven J. Burton, Breach of Contract and the Common Law Duty to Perform in Good Faith, 94 HARV. L. REV. 369 (1980) [hereinafter Burton, Good Faith I]; Steven J. Burton, Good Faith Performance of a Contract Within Article 2 of the Uniform Commercial Code, 67 IOWA L. REV. 1 (1982) [hereinafter Burton, Good Faith II]; Steven J. Burton, More on Good Faith Performance of a Contract: A Reply to Professor Summers, 69 IOWA L. REV. 497 (1984) [hereinafter Burton, Good Faith III]; Steven J. Burton, Good Faith in Articles 1 and 2 of the U.C.C., 35 WM. & MARY L. REV. 1533 (1994) [hereinafter Burton, Good Faith IV]; Thomas A. Diamond & Howard Foss, Proposed Standards for Evaluating When the Covenant of Good Faith and Fair Dealing Has Been Violated, 47 HASTINGS 40 622 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 Instead, this Note provides a brief overview of a few aspects of the debate which are most pertinent to answering the questions posed in Part I. 1. Defining Good Faith The most logical place to begin deciphering the term good faith is to look to the intent of the original U.C.C. drafters. In an early draft of the U.C.C., the drafters defined good faith to include both honesty and the observance of reasonable commercial standards. A proposed comment would have explained the standard as requiring the observance of “commercial decencies.”47 By the time the first version of the U.C.C. was approved, the definition had been pared down to just “honesty” and the reference to commercial decencies had been abandoned.48 Professor Clayton Gillette points out that even without this language, the term “honesty” itself is susceptible to a host of meanings ranging from a very narrow view of honesty in its literal sense, to more liberal conceptions of the term which might themselves include forms of improper commercial behavior deemed dishonest in spirit.49 A contrary version of the original drafting suggests that the commercial standards language was removed at the bequest of practitioners specifically because it was viewed as an “unnecessarily broad, moralistic imperative.”50 Even if the original drafting had produced a clear “intent of the drafters,” the inquiry would still be incomplete. This is true both because (as discussed above) the most recent version of the U.C.C. does restore the element of “reasonable commercial standards” to all parties, and because, regardless of what the U.C.C.’s drafters believed, it was the individual state legislatures that ratified the U.C.C. and therefore their intent that really matters.51 In his seminal piece on good faith, Professor Robert Summers argues that a definition of good faith cannot be verbally conceptualized in any meaningful way, but rather can be understood only as an “excluder” that L.J. 585 (1996); Dubroff, supra note 42; E. Allan Farnsworth, Good Faith Performance and Commercial Reasonableness Under the Uniform Commercial Code, 30 U. CHI. L. REV. 666 (1963); Clayton P. Gillette, Limitations on the Obligation of Good Faith, 1981 DUKE L.J. 619 (1981); Seth William Goren, Looking for Law in All the Wrong Places: Problems in Applying the Implied Covenant of Good Faith Performance, 37 U.S.F. L. REV. 257 (2003); Howard O. Hunter, The Growing Uncertainty About Good Faith in American Contract Law, 20 J. CONT. L. 31 (2004); Christina L. Kunz, Frontispiece on Good Faith: A Functional Approach Within the UCC, 16 WM. MITCHELL L. REV. 1105 (1990); Dennis M. Patterson, A Fable from the Seventh Circuit: Frank Easterbrook on Good Faith, 76 IOWA L. REV. 503 (1991); Summers, Good Faith, supra note 16; Summers, Recognition and Conceptualization, supra note 45; Michael P. Van Alstine, Of Textualism, Party Autonomy, and Good Faith, 40 WM. & MARY L. REV. 1223 (1999). 47 Gillette, supra note 46, at 623 (citing U.C.C. § 1-203 cmt. (May 1949 Draft)). 48 However, as discussed, supra note 44, Article II has always required merchants to conform with reasonable commercial standards of fair dealing in the trade. 49 Gillette, supra note 46, at 621–22. 50 Id. at 624. 51 Id. at 626. 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 623 52 excludes a litany of identifiable instances of bad faith. Professor Summers believes that this is the only conception that can provide the adequate degree of malleability for courts to “do justice.”53 According to Professor Summers, courts should condemn certain types of action as bad faith “even when the objectionable conduct is within the letter of the contract . . . .”54 Professor Summers was concerned that judges were distorting more definite areas of contractual jurisprudence in order to reach the just result in difficult cases. This, he argued, created fictions that undermined legal principles and subverted predictability. Instead, he advocated giving courts a flexible doctrine that they could apply at their own discretion and thus leave other contractual doctrines undisturbed.55 In an influential series of articles, Professor Steven Burton faulted Summers’s conception for being too nebulous.56 Instead, he proposed a more concrete model. Professor Burton believes that whenever a party is entrusted with discretion in contract performance that affects the other party’s benefit, such discretion cannot be exercised to recapture opportunities that were foregone by entering into the contract.57 This, Burton argues, would be bad faith. Any exercise of discretion to recapture opportunities which were not foregone as a result of the contract can be considered good faith.58 This necessarily requires courts to determine the intent a party had when undertaking a given course of action because the same exact type of conduct could be deemed good faith or bad faith, based on the court’s findings as to why the party behaved the way it did.59 Though conceding that there are “well-known difficulties” in determining subjective intent, Burton advocated a subjective inquiry until his most recent article in which he candidly changes course and advocates for an objective inquiry into what caused the buyer’s conduct.60 Not everyone agrees with such sweeping definitions of good faith as Summers, Burton, and others have advocated. Professor Gillette argues that good faith should be little more than an “ancillary exhortative or 52 Summers, Good Faith, supra note 16, at 196. Id. at 198. Id. at 239. 55 See id. at 198. 56 See Burton, Good Faith I, supra note 46, at 369–70 & n.5; Burton, Good Faith II, supra note 45, at 1–3; Burton, Good Faith III, supra note 46, at 497; Burton, Good Faith IV, supra note 46, at 1535–36. Professor Summers in turn has faulted Professor Burton’s conception for providing little substance to the analysis. See Summers, Recognition and Conceptualization, supra note 46, at 810. 57 Burton, Good Faith I, supra note 46, at 372–73. 58 Id. at 373. 59 See Burton, Good Faith III, supra note 46, at 502–03 (stating that an “act” taken by a party can be “legally neutral” when deciding whether there was a breach and that, in order to make such a determination, the court must determine “whether the discretion-exercising party used its discretion for an improper purpose”). 60 See Burton, Good Faith IV, supra note 46, at 1562 n.131. 53 54 624 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 61 precatory function that carries no legal sanctions.” These views mark a significant and—with courts weighing in on both sides—unresolved debate over whether it can ever be bad faith to exercise an option that is provided by the written terms of the contract. This debate can roughly be broken into two camps: the contextualist view and the neoformalist view.62 a. The Contextualist View Proponents of the contextualist view believe that good faith should have independent substantive content.63 This view tries to encourage a cooperative relationship between the parties in which both sides make efforts to protect the reasonable expectations of the others. Professor Summers’s view fits within this group. Summers believes that good faith should prevent parties from declaring technical breaches.64 In other words, even if they technically had the right to declare a breach, parties should forgo that right in certain circumstances out of consideration for the other party. A district court, applying Utah law, articulated an expansive duty that went beyond the express terms of the agreement. Citing a Utah Supreme Court decision, the court stated: An examination of express contract terms alone is insufficient to determine whether there has been a breach of the implied covenant of good faith and fair dealing. To comply with his obligation to perform a contract in good faith, a party’s actions must be consistent with the agreed common purpose and the justified expectations of the other party. The purpose, intentions, and expectations of the parties should be determined by considering the contract language and the course of dealings between and conduct of the parties.65 Although the court found that the duty of good faith had not been breached in this case, its statement that the “express contract terms alone is insufficient”66 demonstrates a contextualist view of striving to honor the spirit of the agreement even if it is contrary to the actual language used to 61 Gillette, supra note 46, at 665. HOWARD O. HUNTER, MODERN LAW OF CONTRACTS § 8:8 (2009). Id. 64 See Summers, Good Faith, supra note 16, at 234–35; see also Gillette, supra note 46, at 619–20 (“[Summers] proposes that good faith be defined to require commercial actors to forbear from declaring technical breaches.”). 65 A.I. Trans. v. Imperial Premium Fin., Inc., 862 F. Supp. 345, 348 (D. Utah 1994) (citing St. Benedict’s Dev. Co. v. St. Benedict’s Hosp., 811 P.2d 194, 200 (Utah 1991)). 66 Id. 62 63 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 625 67 express it. b. The Neoformalist View Proponents of the neoformalist view argue that good faith is meant only to exclude bad faith and fill gaps, and should not impose affirmative requirements beyond the terms of the agreement. As Professor Dubroff posits, “How can a party be said to be performing or enforcing in bad faith when it does no more or less than what was expressly agreed to and understood by the parties?”68 Neoformalists value respecting the allocation of risks which the parties themselves bargained for. Professor Dubroff suggests that expansive good faith conceptions are “unprincipled and may lead to erroneous results in determining rights under the contract.”69 In addition to concerns about respecting the private parties’ bargain, there is another more public goal of encouraging the development of a body of commercial law which is clear and predictable. Professor Gillette argues that judicial usage of good faith language “indicates lack of precision in the court’s reasoning and detracts from the judicial development and comprehension of the [Uniform Commercial] Code.”70 He argues that it has also contributed to uncertainty in commercial contract disputes. Professor Dubroff agrees that these expansive good faith conceptions “create an environment for deciding cases that may be unnecessarily vague and rootless” and their application “can be a confusing and unsatisfying business.”71 The Seventh Circuit issued an opinion that closely expresses a neoformalist viewpoint.72 In that case, which involved a commercial bank enforcing a particularly harsh contract clause at an unexpected and inopportune time for the borrower, Judge Easterbrook wrote: Firms that have negotiated contracts are entitled to enforce them to the letter, even to the great discomfort of their trading partners, without being mulcted for lack of “good faith”. Although courts often refer to the obligation of good faith that exists in every contractual relation, this is not an invitation to the court to decide whether one party ought to 67 Another example of this type of reasoning can be seen in Baker v. Ratzlaff, where the court found a seller to be in breach of the good faith obligation because he declared the buyer in breach “upon a technical pretense.” 564 P.2d 153, 156 (Kan. Ct. App. 1977). Although the terms of their agreement gave the seller the right to declare a breach for the buyer’s non-payment of previous loads, the court was moved by evidence that the market for goods rose sharply and the seller had resold the goods to another party at a higher price. Id. at 156–57. 68 Dubroff, supra note 42, at 602. 69 Id. at 597. 70 Gillette, supra note 46, at 630. 71 Dubroff, supra note 42, at 584, 587. 72 Kham & Nate’s Shoes No. 2, Inc. v. First Bank of Whiting, 908 F.2d 1351, 1357 (7th Cir. 1990). 626 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 have exercised privileges expressly reserved in the document. “Good faith” is a compact reference to an implied undertaking not to take opportunistic advantage in a way that could not have been contemplated at the time of drafting, and which therefore was not resolved explicitly by the parties.73 According to Judge Easterbrook, since the parties had addressed the disputed conduct in their contract (by agreeing that the bank possessed such a right), the issue fell beyond the scope of good faith.74 2. Good Faith as an Excluder In spite of the ongoing debate over whether good faith itself has any independent substance, courts have generally agreed that at the very least, good faith requires the absence of bad faith. This view is based on Professor Summers’s “excluder” definition, and results from that fact that acts performed in bad faith are not allowed under contracts governed by the U.C.C.75 Then-Judge Scalia took this view in a D.C. Court of Appeals case in which he stated: We agree with the observation of Professor Summers that the concept of good faith in the performance of contracts is an “excluder.” It is a phrase without general meaning (or meanings) of its own and serves to exclude a wide range of heterogeneous forms of bad faith. In a particular context the phrase takes on specific meaning, but usually this is only by way of contrast with the specific form of bad faith actually or hypothetically ruled out.76 Judge Scalia added that “even the permissible act performed in bad faith is a breach only because acts in bad faith are not permitted under the contract.”77 The remainder of this Note focuses solely on the excluder issue in the falling market context. In other words, this Note examines whether rejection of goods with a minor defect in a falling market should be considered bad faith, and thus disallowed under either the contextualist or the neoformalist model. To perform this search for bad faith, we will put aside the academic formulations of what good faith should be, and define bad faith more simply as excluding conduct which fails to satisfy the 73 Id. at 1357 (internal citations omitted). Id.; see also Wells Fargo Bank v. Citizens Bank of Tex., 181 S.W.3d 790, 804 (Tex. App. 2005) (“Nor can a bank be said to violate its ‘obligation of good faith’ under [former U.C.C. § 1-203] if it acts in accordance with the requirements of the U.C.C.”). 75 This is true because regardless of what good faith does mean, it certainly does not mean bad faith. 76 Tymshare, Inc. v. Covell, 727 F.2d 1145, 1152 (D.C. Cir. 1984). 77 Id. at 1150 n.3. 74 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 627 U.C.C.’s requirement of “honesty” and conformity with “reasonable commercial standards of fair dealing.”78 The honesty requirement has been interpreted as a subjective standard.79 For instance, in the context of buyers exercising their right to reject goods, they must do so out of actual dissatisfaction with the tender. By contrast, “commercially reasonable standards of fair dealing in trade” is meant to be an objective measure of conformity based on trade usage, course of dealing, and course of performance.80 This inquiry takes into account the reasonable business norms in a given context. For example, in Hubbard v. UTZ Quality Foods, the court held that a commercial buyer of potatoes, which the contract required to be within a certain color range, did not reject in bad faith when he failed to measure the potatoes’ color with a machine before rejecting on the basis of poor color because, even though the machine would have been much more accurate, it was reasonable within the potato industry to use visual inspections.81 C. Good Faith in Perfect Tender Cases Having sketched a brief overview of good faith, one can proceed to examine how it should be applied in perfect tender cases. Professor Lawrence states that good faith “is the most important provision to ensure that the perfect tender rule is applied as a just standard.”82 Although he was generally a strong proponent of perfect tender (as opposed to the substantial performance standard advocated by many scholars), he nonetheless argued that good faith should act as an important restraint on the rule. Specifically, Professor Lawrence argues that “[a] buyer’s insistence upon rejection for a minor contract deviation in order to avoid an unfavorable bargain is an unfair use of buyers’ rejection rights that can be attacked best through utilization of the good faith obligation of the buyer.”83 Lawrence believes that a buyer whose true subjective reason for rejection is to escape a bad bargain is acting in bad faith because their conduct fails the honesty requirement of good faith.84 Other commentators have concurred that good faith should preclude rejection in order to escape from a bad bargain, however, unlike Professor Lawrence they do not believe it would be “dishonest” for a buyer to behave this way. For instance, Summers believes that it should be bad faith for a buyer to reject for a pre-textual reason, however, he argues 78 See U.C.C. § 1-201(20) (2008). Burton, Good Faith IV, supra note 46, at 1539; see also Schmitt & Frisch, supra note 36, at 1397 (“The good faith required of a consumer purchaser is mere honesty in fact—a subjective test.”). 80 Burton, Good Faith IV, supra note 46, at 1539. 81 Hubbard v. UTZ Quality Foods, Inc., 903 F. Supp. 444, 445–51 (W.D.N.Y. 1995). 82 Lawrence, supra note 11, at 558. 83 Id. at 571. 84 Id. 79 628 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 that—at least with a party who conceded his ulterior motive—“[s]ome judges may say that such conduct simply is not in bad faith, for it is not dishonest.”85 Likewise, Professor Sebert concludes: While I have no difficulty concluding that a merchant buyer who rejects because of a clearly insubstantial nonconformity in a falling market has failed to comply with the objective good faith standard . . . I am not sure that that a nonmerchant buyer’s attempt to use the perfect tender rule to escape a bad bargain is, or should be deemed, “dishonest” within the prohibition of the subjective standard of good faith.86 Professor Sebert makes his conclusion based on the fact that failure to satisfy the perfect tender rule does in fact constitute a breach.87 Not all commentators, however, agree that a falling market should be viewed as evidence of a bad faith rejection on the basis of a minor nonconformity. Professor Gillette argues that since the buyer has caused neither the non-conformity nor the falling market he should have no obligation to abstain from enforcing his rights to the fullest extent. Instead, he argues “that initial, trivial breach emerges from materialization of a risk which the seller assumed, presumably because he believed he was in a superior position to control the occurrence of the risk.”88 Professor Gillette believes the effects of this would force contract parties into “forbearance from self-interested action that conflicts with the interests of other parties.”89 In addition, Professor Gillette believes this approach is more faithful to the bargain the parties negotiated and, as such, provides clearer standards of contractual interpretation for future disputes. While critics have contended that buyers assume the risk of a falling market and, thus, their rejection in this circumstance deprives the seller of the expected benefits of the contract, Professor Gillette points out that it is equally true that the seller has assumed the risk of failing to make conforming tender.90 Professor Gillette argues that “[m]aterialization of that risk should not be avoided any more readily than materialization of the risk of market decline.”91 Since there is no way that both parties will still receive the expected value of their bargain in a falling market, it seems unclear why the buyer should be held accountable for the occurrence of a risk he did not control, while the seller is not held accountable for the occurrence of a risk 85 Summers, Good Faith, supra note 16, at 249–50. Sebert, supra note 14, at 387. 87 See id. at 387 & n.77. 88 Gillette, supra note 46, at 641. 89 Id. 90 Id. at 655. 91 Id. 86 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 629 that he and he alone controlled. If the seller had feared his ability to deliver goods of a certain quality or within a certain specified time, he could have struck his bargain differently. Finally, Professor Gillette’s argument should not be taken to excuse a buyer who claims a defect when none exists. This would be a breach of the buyer’s obligation to accept conforming goods.92 Professor Gillette merely points out that it would be “pointless” to also consider the actor’s good or bad faith because “when courts speak of bad faith breaches, they impose remedies based solely on the breach that are not connected to the breacher’s good or bad motives.”93 III. JUDICIAL APPLICATION A current U.C.C. treatise article describes the process of judicial perfect tender analysis as a two part inquiry: “(1) Do the goods conform to the contract? (2) If the answer to (1) is no, did the buyer reject in good faith?”94 As the author points out, “Since the rejection of goods is a matter of performance, there is no doubt that the buyer is under an obligation to act in good faith.”95 In practice, courts tend to agree with this basic model. For example, in GE Packaged Power v. Readiness Management Support,96 Readiness Management Support (“RMS”) was accused of bad faith rejection of power generators built by GE. The court denied summary judgment to GE citing two genuine issues of fact: “(i) whether the generators conformed . . . and (ii) whether RMS believed the generators to be nonconforming.”97 In the court’s view, ascertaining the buyer’s “belief” regarding the conformity of the goods was a necessary precursor to evaluating its’ right of rejection.98 Likewise, another court that had found fabric to be non-conforming nonetheless speculated that if the buyer had rejected for a pre-textual reason “its rejection would certainly not have been in good faith.”99 A number of other cases confirm these results.100 Perhaps unavoidably, courts in these cases are forced to determine whether buyers who reject are truly acting honestly. Since it is inherently 92 See U.C.C. § 2-301 (2002). Gillette, supra note 46, at 638. 94 Rusch, supra note 40. 95 Id. 96 GE Packaged Power v. Readiness Mgmt. Support, 510 F. Supp. 2d 1124 (N.D. Ga. 2007). 97 Id. at 1134. 98 See id. at 1133–34 (stating that “[a] rejection of goods must be made in good faith” and “[t]o reject goods in bad faith, a buyer must have no good-faith belief that the goods are conforming”). 99 Matrix Int’l Textiles, Inc. v. Jolie Intimates Inc., No. 316107/03, 2005 WL 1074774, at *6 (N.Y. Civ. Ct. May 5, 2005). 100 See, e.g., Clark v. Zaid, Inc., 282 A.2d 483, 484–85 n.1 (Md. 1971) (“The buyer’s judgment [as to rejection of goods] would have to be exercised in good faith.”); Y&N Furniture Inc. v. Nwabuoku, 734 N.Y.S.2d 382, 385 (N.Y. Civ. Ct. 2001) (“[T]he buyer’s rejection of the goods must be made in good faith.”). 93 630 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 difficult to know another party’s subjective motivations, courts have relied on circumstantial evidence out of necessity. For instance, in Matrix International Textiles v. Jolie Intimates, the buyer of fabric rejected delivery, claiming it did not conform to the contract specifications.101 The seller suggested that this reason was pre-textual and that the buyer was simply trying to avoid delivery because it was discontinuing the operations of the division that would have used it. The court noted that the buyer had subsequently ordered the item from another supplier at a higher price as circumstantial evidence that rebutted the seller’s claim.102 In another case challenging the rightfulness of a buyer’s rejection, the court ruled for the buyer after finding that the seller “has failed to convince [the court] that [the buyer’s] motivation for rejecting his potatoes was to obtain similar potatoes but at a reduced cost.”103 The court cited a lack of “compelling evidence” that the buyer had purchased from other suppliers at lower market prices after rejecting the seller’s product.104 Several courts have suggested that evidence of falling market conditions prior to the buyer’s rejection may be used as circumstantial evidence that the buyer rejected for a dishonest purpose. One leading case is Joc Oil USA v. Consolidated Edison Co. of New York105 In that case, Joc Oil contracted to sell a large quantity of oil with a specified maximum sulfur content to Con Ed. When the oil arrived it contained too much sulfur. By the time Con Ed rejected delivery the time for performance had passed, and although Joc Oil offered to cure one day later, Con Ed declined this offer. In the subsequent contract suit, Joc Oil alleged that Con Ed had refused to accept the replacement delivery because foreign market forces had caused the value of the oil to decline and that Con Ed was attempting to escape from a bad deal.106 The court seemed to agree, finding that “[t]here can be no doubt that this dispute would not exist if the market had risen at the time.”107 The precise issue on which the court decided the case was not, however, whether the rejection itself was in bad faith, but rather whether Joc Oil had a reasonable basis to believe that their initial delivery would be accepted and therefore, under U.C.C. section 2-508(2), should have been allotted additional time beyond the specified time of performance to make cure. Concluding that “[i]t is difficult to believe that a construction rewarding culpability and penalizing innocence is 101 Matrix Int’l Textiles, 2005 WL 1074774, at *1,*3. Id. at *6. Hubbard v. UTZ Quality Foods, Inc., 903 F. Supp. 444, 450 (W.D.N.Y. 1995). 104 Id. 105 Joc Oil USA, Inc., v. Consol. Edison Co., 434 N.Y.S.2d 623, 630 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1980). 106 See id. at 626 (noting the rise in spot oil purchase prices due to the Arab oil embargo and indicating that the main source of contention between the parties appeared to be the price Con Ed would pay for Joc Oil’s delivery). 107 Id. at 630. 102 103 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 631 preferable, or consistent with the remedial intent of the creators of this remedy,” the court found that Joc Oil did have a reasonable basis to believe the oil would be accepted and therefore should have been given additional time for cure.108 Although the court likely did not mean to suggest that falling market conditions were evidence of bad faith rejection, its disjointed discussion of good faith, culpability, and the underlying falling market make the opinion ambiguous. Even on appeal, the New York Court of Appeals further obscured the issue when it opined that “the premise [for Con Ed’s argument] ignores the policy of the code to prevent buyers from using insubstantial remediable or price adjustable defects to free themselves from unprofitable bargains . . . .”109 At least one plaintiff’s lawyer has cited the case for the proposition that “[t]he Court determined that the buyer used the excuse of the higher sulfur content as a pretext for rejecting the delivery and as an attempt to escape its bad bargain.”110 Other cases do seem to have explicitly endorsed the proposition that a falling market for the goods can be used as evidence of a bad faith motivation for rejection. For instance, in Neumiller Farms v. Cornett,111 Cornett and other small potato farmers in Alabama contracted to sell potatoes suitable for “chipping” at a price of $4.25 per hundred-weight. The buyer, a commercial potato broker, accepted the first several shipments when the market value was $4.25 per hundred-weight, but when the market price fell to $2.00 per hundred-weight, the buyer began rejecting delivery claiming that the potatoes did not chip satisfactorily.112 Upon hearing evidence from the seller’s expert that the potatoes were suitable in all respects, the court ruled that the buyer had breached by rejecting delivery in bad faith. The court stated that “[t]he law requires such a claim of dissatisfaction to be made in good faith, rather than in an effort to escape a bad bargain.”113 Likewise, in Printing Center of Texas v. Supermind Publishing, a court stated that “evidence of rejection of the goods on account of a minor defect in a falling market would in some instances be sufficient to support a finding that the buyer acted in bad faith when he rejected the goods.”114 Finally, in Oil Country Specialists v. Philipp Bros., a buyer rejected pipe that was required to meet specified 108 Id. at 630, 632. T.W. Oil, Inc. v. Consol. Edison Co., 443 N.E.2d 932, 938 n.8, 940 (N.Y. 1982). 110 Trial Brief of Plaintiff Austrian Airlines, Austrian Airlines Oesterreichische Luftverkehrs AG v. UT Fin. Corp., No. 04 Civ. 3854 (LAK) (S.D.N.Y. Feb. 20, 2008), 2008 WL 872782. 111 Neumiller Farms, Inc. v. Cornett, 368 So. 2d 272 (Ala. 1979). 112 Id. at 274. 113 Id. at 275; see also Baker v. Ratzlaff, 564 P.2d 153, 157 (Kan. Ct. App. 1977) (noting that evidence of a buyer’s “hasty resale of the popcorn to another buyer at a price nearly double the contract price, provided the trial court with ample evidence upon which to find an absence of good faith”). 114 Printing Ctr. of Tex., Inc. v. Supermind Publ’g Co., 669 S.W.2d 779, 784 (Tex. App. 1984). 109 632 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 115 industry standards. When the pipe did not conform, the buyer rejected the entire inventory. After hearing evidence that a falling market made the transaction “highly unfavorable” to the buyer, a jury concluded that the buyer had rejected in bad faith.116 A Texas appeals court affirmed the decision, finding that the buyer was entitled to reject “only if it did so in good faith[, t]hat is, if it did so with honesty in fact or in keeping with the observance of reasonable commercial standards of fair dealing in the trade.”117 Unfortunately, the court did not specify which of these two criteria the buyer had failed, instead concluding perfunctorily that the evidence was legally and factually sufficient. Other cases suggest the same result.118 Other courts have not been persuaded by evidence of falling market conditions. One representative case is Austrian Airlines v. UT Finance. In that case, Austrian Airlines agreed to sell a plane to UT Finance (“UTF”) in a contract which required delivery by a specific date and recited that time was of the essence.119 Austrian Airlines could not deliver the plane in perfect condition on time and UTF rejected delivery, effectively denying Austrian Airlines any chance to cure. Part of Austrian Airlines’ subsequent contract suit argued that UTF’s rejection was made in bad faith because they had only done so to escape a bad bargain. Austrian Airlines pointed to two facts in support of this argument. First, UTF had not yet found a suitable secondary purchaser for the plane and thus there was no practical need for UTF to insist on timely performance. Second, Austrian Airlines pointed out that the plane had been ordered prior to the terrorist attacks of September 11, and in the wake of the resulting turmoil on the airline industry, the value of the plane to UTF had been reduced to twothirds of its expected value.120 The court was unmoved by Austrian Airlines’ evidence, and though it stated that “[t]he Court assumes that UTF, quite understandably, was motivated by the decline in market value,” it held that this was not in bad faith.121 The court refused to read Joc Oil USA and similar cases as establishing that subjective motivations could be dispositive of the issue of 115 Oil Country Specialists, Ltd. v. Philipp Bros., 762 S.W.2d 170, 172–73 (Tex. App. 1988). Id. at 178. 117 Id. 118 For example, a New York district court opined that “[a]lthough it [is] true that the Code generally obligates a buyer to act in good faith in rejecting goods, plaintiff has introduced no evidence indicating that the defendants’ motivation in rejecting the fuel oil was a bad faith effort to escape the bargain.” Warren Co. v. Olco Oil Co., No. 86-CV-660, 1988 WL 28940, at *3 (N.D.N.Y. Mar. 15, 1988); see also Matrix Int’l Textiles, Inc. v. Jolie Intimates Inc., No. 316107/03, 2005 WL 1074774, at *6 (N.Y. Civ. Ct. May 5, 2005); Hubbard v. UTZ Quality Foods Inc., 903 F. Supp. 444, 451 (W.D.N.Y. 1995). 119 Austrian Airlines Oesterreichische Luftverkehrs AG v. UT Fin. Corp., 567 F. Supp. 2d 579, 582–83 (S.D.N.Y. 2008), aff’d, No. 08-4176-cv., 2009 WL 1940715 (2d Cir. July 2, 2009). 120 Id. at 581–82, 591–93. 121 Id. at 599–600. 116 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 633 122 bad faith. The court went on to opine that such a rule would not make commercial sense.123 In the court’s view, UTF’s conduct was “entirely reasonable” since the presence of defects was now even more significant to the buyer than in a normal market.124 Noting the sophistication of the parties, the court found “no reason not to give the buyer the benefit of its bargain.”125 The UTF court’s decision was affirmed on appeal by the Second Circuit in a brief opinion that referred to the lower court’s decision as “careful,” “thorough,” and “well-reasoned.”126 Similarly, a California trial court prohibited a plaintiff from offering proof of an “‘ulterior motive’” by the buyer when rejecting the goods.127 In KCA Electronics, the court focused strictly on the non-conformities alleged—namely, that six percent of the small computer components lacked the necessary uniformity—and based its decision to grant summary judgment in favor of the buyer strictly on the defect.128 Not only did this approach produce a rational and well-reasoned decision, but perhaps most significantly, the absence of extraneous discussions regarding why the seller thought the buyer had rejected the goods makes the opinion more precise and helpful to businessmen and lawyers who will have to litigate similar issues in the future. IV. A NEW FRAMEWORK A. Consideration of Falling Market Conditions Is Not Helpful in Deciding Cases 1. A Falling Market Does Not Impact Whether a Defect Actually Exists Nothing within the text or comments of U.C.C. section 2-601 requires any mental state on the part of either the buyer or the seller in order for the perfect tender rule to apply.129 The rule is triggered “if the goods or the tender of the delivery fail in any respect to conform . . . .”130 Hence, any review of whether a good is or is not conforming is necessarily an objective one. It is only the separate good faith obligation that contains the 122 Specifically, the court narrowly read Joc Oil USA to apply only in the context of determining a seller’s reasonable basis to believe his goods would be accepted under the section 2-508(2) standard, and it distinguished Neumiller Farms and Printing Center of Texas. Id. at 600. 123 Id. 124 Id. at 599. 125 Id. at 600. 126 See Austrian Airlines, 2009 WL 1940715, at *1–2. 127 KCA Elecs., Inc. v. Legacy Elecs., Inc., No. G037285, 2007 WL 2137959, at *4 (Cal. Ct. App. July 26, 2007). 128 Id. 129 See U.C.C. § 2-601 (2002). 130 Id. 634 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 requirement that the buyer reject the non-conforming tender with the right state of mind. As such, inquiries into the conformity of the goods and the good or bad faith of the rejection are two separate inquiries.131 A falling market (arguably) is relevant to the latter, but not the former. The initial objective determination of whether a defect is present should not be affected by any external factors including the economy. If such factors are to be taken into account at all, it should be within the context of the actor’s good or bad faith.132 Any analysis of whether a good is objectively non-conforming must begin with the terms of the contract. All descriptions of the good being contracted for should be vigorously enforced. In addition, courts should fill in the gaps by resorting to common trade usage and other established commercial practices for the item purchased.133 In comparing what the contract requires to be tendered and what was actually tendered, courts should avoid falling into the trap of using buzz words such as “trivial,” which does not aid in the analysis. A small defect that goes to the basis of the bargain should be view as legally significant and should permit rejection. By contrast, a defect that does not offend the basis of the bargain should be viewed as legally insignificant and should not permit rejection, even though it could be said to render the good defective under ordinary usage.134 In this sense, this author does not disagree with Professor Lawrence’s argument that buyers should not be able to reject for what he calls “inconsequential deviations” or defects of “no actual importance to the buyer.”135 This Note contends that the so-called “trivial defects” may be consequential depending upon the circumstances and, in such cases, buyers should not be restrained from acting upon those small but consequential defects simply because the market for the goods has fallen. This is consistent with the underlying goal of the perfect tender rule: to “create[ ] an incentive for sellers to produce goods that conform to contract specifications.”136 131 See supra Part III. See, e.g., GE Packaged Power v. Readiness Mgmt. Support, 510 F. Supp. 2d 1124, 1134 (N.D. Ga. 2007) (denying summary judgment based on two genuine issues of fact: (i) whether the generators conformed . . . and (ii) whether [the buyer] believed the generators to be nonconforming”). 133 See U.C.C. § 1-303 (2008). 134 Compare Marlowe v. Argentine Naval Comm’n, 808 F.2d 120, 124 (D.C. Cir. 1986) (noting a six day delay in delivering an airplane was enough to warrant rejection because time was of the essence), and Vitol S.A., Inc. v. Koch Petroleum Group, L.P., No. 01CV2184(GBD), 2005 WL 2105592, at *9 (S.D.N.Y. Aug. 31, 2005) (“Since time was of the essence in the performance of the parties’ contract, defendant’s late delivery violated the perfect tender rule because defendant’s ‘tender of delivery fail[ed] in any respect to conform to the contract.” (alteration in the original)), with Burgess Steel Prods. Corp. v. Modern Telecomms., Inc., 205 A.D.2d 344, 346 (N.Y. App. Div. 1994) (noting that where plaintiff contended that time was not of the essence: “a trial is necessary to determine whether the deadline contained in the contract was so inflexible that the plaintiff’s late performance constituted a breach of a material element of the contract”). 135 See Lawrence, supra note 11, at 572. 136 Id. at 578. 132 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 635 2. If a Defect Does Exist, a Party Cannot Be Said to Be Dishonest in Rejecting Because of It Surely it would be dishonest to claim the right to reject by claiming a defect that does not exist. Neumiller Farms illustrates this point. In that case, Neumiller Farms rejected potatoes, claiming they did not chip satisfactorily, as required by the contract. After hearing expert testimony, the court concluded that the potatoes were suitable for chipping and, thus, Neumiller Farms received exactly what it bargained for and had been dishonest in claiming otherwise.137 Some commentators argue that even if there is a legally significant defect, a buyer must actually be rejecting because of his own subjective dissatisfaction with the defect rather than because of some other factor (such as a falling market). Proponents of this view would suggest that even if the potatoes at issue in Neumiller Farms did not chip satisfactorily, if the court was convinced that Neumiller Farms’ true reason for rejection was the falling price of potatoes, then the farm would be stuck with them because the right to reject (although present) would have been exercised in bad faith. A better approach is to treat the honesty prong of the good faith obligation as a nullity in rejection cases because before the question of good faith even arises in this context, it must first be shown that a legally significant defect does in fact exist. Thus, the honesty of the buyer’s assertion of a rejection should be decided in light of the initial inquiry into the conformity of the goods. Once it is shown that some legally significant defect does in fact exist, it is inevitable that a buyer who claims the right to reject a good because of the presence of a defect is being honest; were it not for the defect, the right to reject would not and could not be claimed. Certainly a falling market for the goods would have influenced the decision that a particular defect was too much for the buyer to tolerate,138 but this should not negate the fact that the defect was ultimately what triggered the rejection; the falling market merely triggered the fact that it was made with a light heart. This very literal approach avoids the complex task of attempting to discern a party’s overriding motivation on some deep philosophical level.139 This approach also avoids a potentially absurd outcome whereby two identically situated buyers both reject nonconforming goods, one claiming, “I am invoking the perfect tender rule 137 See Neumiller Farms, Inc. v. Cornett, 368 So. 2d 272, 274–75 (Ala. 1979). Toleration of defects admittedly becomes much more difficult in a falling market, a point which is explored more in the subsection that follows. 139 It also avoids the flawed assumption that any particular course of action can be explained by one principle motivational factor. This is a questionable assumption even in the context of individual decision making, let alone in the context of commercial business decisions where multiple players (e.g., CEO, in-house counsel, sales manager) with potentially different motivations, each contribute to a decision to reject a particular shipment of goods. 138 636 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 because of defect [X],” and the other claiming, “I am invoking the perfect tender rule because the market for these goods has declined.” If we take seriously the notion of honesty in this setting, then the former buyer has breached his contractual obligations whereas the latter has not. There is no reason to think that the U.C.C. was ever intended to produce such a result and potentially push buyers to claim that they acted for the most insidious reasons imaginable simply to guard against potential liability under the honesty prong of the good faith obligation.140 3. It Is Commercially Reasonable to Expect the Full Benefit of One’s Original Bargain in a Falling Market The second prong of contractual good faith—that the parties abide by “commercially reasonable standards of fair dealing in trade”—is very context- and industry-specific. Nonetheless, there is no reason to think that there cannot be some generalization across industries on some broad points. Particularly with respect to large commercial parties the reasonable commercial standards are likely somewhat homogenous.141 In a falling market, the value of what the buyer is receiving is already, by definition, reduced. Therefore, any defects in the goods are even more significant to a buyer than they ordinarily would be because they necessarily reduce the already deflated value of the goods even further. Having already received the short end of the stick with respect to the market value of the goods, it is all the more reasonable for the buyer to ensure that at the very least the goods are what the contract requires them to be.142 On the whole, the case law shows that buyers are permitted to reject goods with trivial defects so long as they are legally significant. To deny this right because of a falling market would have the perverse effect of denying this otherwise tenable course of action at a time when it is most reasonable for the buyer to want to exercise it. 140 To the extent that parties claimed such an insidious purpose, even while actually believing themselves to be acting for just reasons, this would produce a somewhat paradoxical result of lying in order to be deemed honest. 141 To the extent that this is not true—for there are surely examples where it is not—courts should always elevate the specific industry practices above the more general business norms. 142 The Austrian Airlines court stated: Nor would the rule for which [the seller] argues make much commercial sense. Where a buyer pursuant to a contract calling for future delivery is presented with non-conforming goods, price movements intervening between the agreement and the time for delivery often are taken into consideration in determining whether to reject. It makes sense to consider them because nonconformities often go not to the ultimate utility of the goods, but to their value, especially resale value. Where the parties . . . contract in terms that give the buyer the right to walk away from the deal in the event of a non-conforming tender, there is no reason not to give the buyer the benefit of its bargain. Austrian Airlines Oesterreichische Luftverkehrs AG v. UT Fin. Corp, 567 F. Supp. 2d 579, 600 (S.D.N.Y. 2008), aff’d, No. 08-4176-cv., 2009 WL 1940715 (2d Cir. July 2, 2009). 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 637 B. The Argument for Categorical Exclusion Thus far, this Note has posited that evidence of a falling market is not helpful in the adjudication of disputes over rejection of goods. One could fairly ask why we should categorically exclude such evidence. After all, in some sense it is true that totally removing this circumstantial evidence from the equation could invite some buyers to use their rejection right strategically as a means of avoiding the contract. Conversely, if such evidence is allowed in contract disputes, it is unlikely that sellers would have a similar strategic response; they are unlikely, after all, to intentionally produce goods which fail to conform to the terms of the contract simply because they would be armed with a factually difficult argument that those goods were really rejected on the basis of a falling market. Given this reality, it is fair to ask, “Why not just allow evidence of a falling market to enter these cases for what it is worth?” The response is two-fold. First, to say that a decision to reject in a falling market is “strategic” is not to say that it is wrong or unjustified.143 Second, the inclusion of falling markets evidence in rejection cases hurts the overall body of contract law. When goods that are slightly non-conforming are tendered, a buyer is left with two options. First, he can ask the seller to repair the defect.144 The second option—assuming this is not an instance where the right to cure is present—the buyer can reject the goods outright and risk the dual possibilities of destroying his relationship with this seller and potentially facing litigation. Given the apparent downsides to the second option, buyers are likely to think carefully before taking that course. It is certainly true that the market for the goods is a factor that will play into the analysis. Clearly, if the value of goods had risen rather than fallen, a buyer would be less insistent on enforcing his rights to the fullest degree. He would likely forego his right to rejection and instead permit extra time to make cure or negotiate a cash payment as damages for acceptance of slightly nonconforming goods.145 However, just because the buyer has the ability not to enforce his rights to the fullest extent does not mean that he does not possess those rights in the first place. Parties in voluntary transactions always have the ability to waive their rights against one another, or they have the ability to enforce them exactingly. That market circumstances dictated which course they selected should not detract from the fact that they did actually possess the right to take the action they took under the 143 Likewise, saying that conduct was not entered into strategically by the other party does not mean that that the conduct was rightful under the terms of the contract. 144 Indeed, this is sometimes, but certainly not always, required under the seller’s right to cure. See discussion supra Part II.A.2. 145 U.C.C. section 2-714 (2002) allows buyers to accept non-conforming goods and sue under the warranty for the damage caused by the non-conformity. 638 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 terms of the contract, that the exercise of this right was honest, and that it was commercially reasonable. As Professor Gillette suggests, “That the buyer receives a windfall from the fortuitous breach does not necessarily mean that he is not entitled to it.”146 In addition, while it may be a stretch to believe that a seller will actually go out of his way to strategically saddle a buyer with nonconforming goods, the perfect tender rule is itself an acknowledgement that in the case of one-shot contracts, buyers need a pretty big stick in order to protect themselves from shoddy workmanship. This is particularly true when the defects are small and, therefore, a substantial performance requirement would be inadequate to protect buyers’ rights. It is consistent with this policy to deny the use of falling market evidence, which would tend to undermine the strength of the rule by giving credence to an excuse for lax quality standards (even if those lax quality standards were not undertaken strategically). Finally, there are other consequences of allowing sellers to introduce evidence that rejection was motivated by a falling market which are, on balance, bad for contract law. 1. Detracts from the Development and Clarity of U.C.C. Case Law Judge Learned Hand once opined that words such as “good faith . . . obscure the issue.”147 Indeed, cases such as Joc Oil USA, Neumiller Farms, and TX Printing are difficult to read because the presence of discussions regarding the market for the goods detracts from, and confuses, the discussion of the conformity of the goods. It is difficult to tell if the reason for the court’s holding is the existence of a non-conformity, or the existence of evidence of a falling market. If a future case arises where a buyer notices a non-conformity that has previously been held to be legally insignificant and, thus, insufficient to allow for rejection in a falling market, it is unclear how much weight to give such a holding if the value of the goods in the current case has remained steady.148 This lack of clarity has needlessly impaired the ability of practitioners to advise their clients as to when they can comfortably reject a good that they deem nonconforming. Professor Gillette has summarized the dilemma by saying: It is unclear whether the attorney can advise his client that cancellation of the contract with the defaulting seller is 146 Gillette, supra note 46, at 655. Thompson-Starrett Co. v. La Belle Iron Works, 17 F.2d 536, 541 (2d Cir. 1927). See also Market St. Assocs. v. Frey, 941 F.2d 588, 593 (7th Cir. 1991), a case in which Judge Posner quotes Judge Hand and agrees with his sentiment. 148 Obviously, this type of common law problem is in no way unique to perfect tender rule cases. My point here is only that in perfect tender rule cases, perhaps unlike other cases, there is no need for courts to engage in two parallel lines of reasoning. In this context, one discussion would suffice, and therefore should be deemed preferable. 147 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 639 appropriate under an expansive good faith standard. He must determine whether the client will be affected adversely— beyond the loss of a better bargain—by the nonconformity. Regardless of the difficulty of such a determination, the need to make the inquiry at all introduces into sales law the notion of material breach that is rejected explicitly by the host of provisions concerning perfect tender and cure.149 Professor Sebert argues that the lack of cases using the duty of good faith as a basis for denying buyers a right to rejection may be evidence of the influence the doctrine is having “at the point of decision by a buyer.”150 Such a result may well be tolerable, but it should not be preferable. Courts should be careful to keep discussions of conformity of the goods separate from discussions of the good faith of the actors, and since a falling market has no bearing on either, it should be left out of decisions all together. If there is clear evidence that a good was conforming (as in Neumiller Farms), then rejection should be deemed wrongful irrespective of the motive of the buyer. In such cases, courts need not, and should not, even reach the issue of bad faith. If the good is found non-conforming then an inquiry into good faith is justified, however, since the presence or absence of a falling market should have no impact on this determination, it remains an inappropriate subject matter. KCA Electronics is an example of a case that follows just this model and the holding is made much clearer because of it.151 2. Encourages Litigation at the Expense of Voluntary Settlement For businessmen, even a case that is won in litigation generally represents (at best) an unwanted annoyance. One of the chief goals of the U.C.C. is to provide consistency and predictability in American contract law.152 This predictability is important to help guide parties’ conduct, both in the ordinary course of business, as well as in their decision making after a dispute has arisen (such as when deciding whether to sue or what litigation theories to utilize).153 Ideally, parties should be able to resolve their commercial differences without resorting to judicial intervention; however, realization of this goal requires a predictable outcome if they fail 149 Gillette, supra note 46, at 652–53. Sebert, supra note 14, at 389. 151 KCA Elecs., Inc. v. Legacy Elecs., Inc., No. G037285, 2007 WL 2137959, at *5 (Cal. Ct. App. July 26, 2007). 152 See U.C.C. § 1-103 (2008) (“The [U.C.C.] must be liberally construed and applied to promote its underlying purposes and policies, which are: (1) to simplify, clarify, and modernize the law governing commercial transactions . . . [and] (3) to make uniform the law among the various jurisdictions.”). 153 See Gillette, supra note 46, at 621 (“The Code . . . is a tool for businessmen and their attorneys to predict the legal consequences of voluntary transactions.”). 150 640 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 to agree. This in turn requires “precision of definition and certainty of the effects of performance and nonperformance.”154 Without this certainty of effect, parties may be tempted to abandon the cooperative channels more readily in hopes of imposing a superior result upon their trading partner by judicial decree. Allowing bad faith to void an otherwise tenable right of rejection, encourages litigious behavior by undeserving sellers who have tendered non-conforming goods. As Professor Burton has observed, the imprecise boundaries of good faith have produced “[j]ust enough unorthodox judgments . . . to inspire ever-optimistic plaintiffs’ counsel to keep the lawsuits coming.”155 Ambiguity breeds test cases. Sometimes ambiguity is necessary or even appropriate, but in the commercial contracts context it often leads to inefficiency. For instance, the extraneous discussion of good faith and the falling market in Joc Oil USA turned what could have been a straightforward U.C.C. section 508(2) case into a disjointed discussion that was later cited—erroneously—by a plaintiff in a multi-million dollar contract dispute.156 As has been explained, there is no need for the ambiguity posed by judicial opinions discussing falling markets in cases contesting the rightfulness of rejection, and, therefore, such ambiguity should be readily avoided. C. Potential for Abuse Can Be Limited by Other Legal Doctrines and Perfect Tender Rule Constraints Nothing in this Note should be taken to suggest that cases such as Neumiller Farms (which considered the falling market in determining that the buyer had made a bad faith rejection) reached an incorrect result; indeed the reverse is true. As Professor Gillette opines, “If there were no other safety valve available to prevent the waste inherent in the possibility of rejections for trivial defects, use of the good faith obligation might therefore appear justifiable.”157 The problem that has been posited is that such cases inadvertently and unnecessarily complicate the issues. Several other “safety valves” exist and should be utilized to produce clearer decisions in future falling market rejection cases. First and foremost, courts should recognize that they do not need to address the issue of good faith unless a legally significant non-conformity is found to exist. Neumiller Farms is illustrative. There, Neumiller Farms contracted for the purchase of potatoes suitable for chipping, and that is exactly what the court found it had received.158 Therefore, Neumiller 154 Id. Burton, Good Faith IV, supra note 46, at 1535. See supra note 110 and accompanying text. 157 Gillette, supra note 46, at 653. 158 Neumiller Farms, Inc. v. Cornett, 368 So. 2d 272, 274–75 (Ala. 1979). 155 156 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 641 159 Farms had a contractual obligation to do as it had agreed. This should have ended the analysis. It is irrelevant to inquire why Neumiller Farms performed the way it did or what market factors were to blame. By discussing the falling market conditions and imploring notions of good faith, the court turned an easy case into a hard one. Simply put, if a tendered good conforms to the terms of the parties’ bargain it should always be a breach for the buyer to reject delivery. In addition, courts should enforce the seller’s remedy of cure in appropriate cases. Although, as stated in Part II, sellers often do not have any time allotted to make cure, sometimes they do.160 Buyers who recognize the possibility of a court finding them in breach for not permitting a seller to exercise its right to cure will be more willing to bargain and negotiate acceptable remedies without resorting to legal doctrines, and, more importantly, without using precious judicial resources to get there. As Professor Gillette points out, “A buyer seeking to avoid his bad bargain would be unlikely to invest time or resources in discovering a nonmaterial defect if the known consequence of his rejection is to give the seller an additional opportunity to tender conforming goods.”161 To the extent that time for cure is still available, courts should fully utilize it. Further, although this Note has advocated that, in a general sense, it should not violate any broad standards of commercial dealing for a buyer to reject for small non-conformities when it suits his interests, the argument should not be read to dismiss reasonable commercial standards as an ineffective restraint on the perfect tender rule. Indeed, commercial practices such as trade usage, course of performance, or course of dealing, may be very compelling on a case-by-case basis. For example, a buyer who is contractually entitled to silver widgets but has always accepted bronze widgets from a particular seller should not be able to suddenly insist on silver simply because the price of widgets falls. In that case, the parties would be said to have a clear course of performance establishing that bronze widgets are in fact conforming under the contract—the written terms notwithstanding—and, as such, the buyer would not be entitled to the right of rejection. Finally, the majority of the discussion throughout this Note has assumed a transaction involving two large sophisticated parties. In this context we can, and should, readily expect these parties to take care of themselves. These types of parties should not be able to use good faith as a means of crying foul in a falling market simply because they failed to 159 Id. See, e.g., Joc Oil USA, Inc., v. Consol. Edison Co., 434 N.Y.S.2d 623, 632 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1980) (stating that Joc Oil made “a reasonable and timely offer to cure”). 161 Gillette, supra note 46, at 654. 160 642 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 properly plan their transactions with the necessary specificity in good economic times. Given the resources of sophisticated commercial parties, it is not too much to ask them to safeguard their own interests. It may, however, be too much to ask of a smaller, less sophisticated, buyer. Indeed, one plausible way of reconciling decisions protecting sellers in falling markets and those declining to, are that—as best the records indicated—the sellers in the former category tend to be smaller entities, while those in the latter category tend to be more sophisticated businesses.162 If it is true that the real concern is protecting smaller sellers who lack the bargaining power to protect themselves from being exploited by unfair rejection in a falling market, then courts would be better served by simply saying as much. Instead of accomplishing this aim through the obligation of good faith—which, under the revised U.C.C. section, one applies the same to all parties, whether merchant or non-merchant, sophisticated or unsophisticated—courts could use another doctrine that is more readily understood as a tool to alleviate otherwise harsh results for parties with disparate bargaining power: unconscionability.163 To the extent that a rejection right seems to give a large commercial buyer a patently unjust right of rejection over an individual seller with little bargaining position, it may be appropriate for courts to declare that right of rejection unconscionable under certain facts.164 This will achieve the same goal of protecting weaker parties, without undermining the clear application of the perfect tender rule to more sophisticated sellers who could have protected themselves—but chose not to—by bargaining for a more precise description of goods, or a longer time in which to tender them. 162 Compare Neumiller Farms, 368 So. 2d 272 (involving a dispute between individual potato farmers in DeKalb County, Alabama and a corporate buyer), and Printing Ctr. of Tex., Inc. v. Supermind Publ’g Co., 669 S.W.2d 779 (Tex. App. 1984) (involving a dispute between an independent publisher and a local printing company), with Austrian Airlines Oesterreichische Luftverkehrs AG, v. UT Fin. Corp, 567 F. Supp. 2d 579 (S.D.N.Y. 2008) (involving a dispute between a multi-national airline and a multi-national conglomerate), and KCA Elecs., Inc. v. Legacy Elecs., Inc., No. G037285, 2007 WL 2137959 (Cal. Ct. App. July 26, 2007) (involving a dispute between two high-tech California companies). But see Oil Country Specialists, Ltd. v. Philipp Bros., 762 S.W.2d 170 (Tex. App. 1988) (involving a dispute between two oil companies). 163 See Cont’l Airlines, Inc. v. Goodyear Tire & Rubber Co., 819 F.2d 1519, 1527 (9th Cir. 1987) (“The doctrine of unconscionability cannot be invoked by so sophisticated a party as [the plaintiff] in reference to a contract so laboriously negotiated.”); see also Geldermann & Co. v. Lane Processing, Inc., 527 F.2d 571, 576 (8th Cir. 1975) (noting that unconscionability does not protect a sophisticated investor); AMF Inc. v. Computer Automation, Inc., 573 F. Supp. 924, 930 (S.D. Ohio 1983) (finding unconscionability inapplicable in a contract between “large, sophisticated merchants”). 164 Consider the following example: an adhesion contract between a large company and an individual seller that contained a vague description of the goods, which the large buyer then used to reject goods in a falling market at will, could potentially be deemed unconscionable. 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 643 V. CONCLUSION Despite the fact that the issue of contested rejection of goods against the backdrop of a falling market for the goods is likely a reoccurring issue for many businesses, the issues presented have not been adequately resolved. This is surely—at least in part—a function of businesses’ understandable reluctance to engage in costly litigation, especially when the harm caused by any particular contractual transgression often pales in comparison to the attention necessary to satisfy the business’s other obligations. Hopefully, this Note represents a step in the direction of further examination, debate, and clarification. The framework proposed is meant to be a subtle attempt to refine future judicial opinions to achieve a more focused pool of case law from which future business lawyers can discern precisely where their clients stand. Though the framework suggested may appear to be pro-buyer, nothing argued in Part IV should be seen as particularly radical165 and to illustrate this point, this Note concludes by examining two previously discussed cases, Austrian Airlines (which supports this Note’s position) and Joc Oil USA (which does not) to see what would happen if the alternative rule had been applied to the facts. In Austrian Airlines, the court was unmoved by the seller’s evidence of a severe decline in the value of the plane, which was tendered and subsequently rejected by the buyer. The defects to the plane included the lack of a required FAA Certificate of Airworthiness, without which the plane was useless. If the court had found UTF’s rejection to be a bad faith effort to escape from the bargain, then its rejection of the plane would have been deemed an acceptance and it would have been the not-so-proud owner of a plane, the value of which had been severely deflated not just by uncontrollable market fluxuations, but also by the seller’s own incompetent ability to build it correctly. Some readers may find no trouble with this result—it is, after all, hard to be outraged by the slight unfairness this would impose upon a sophisticated entity such as UTF. However, this result is not contemplated by the contract that two sophisticated parties negotiated and entered into. In the contract they struck, Austrian Airlines assumed the risk of failing to make perfect tender. UTF obviously contemplated the value of the plane in the current market when making its decision to reject delivery, but the court was correct to hold that this was nothing more than a reasonable business decision based on a negotiated contract and that there was “no reason not to give the buyer the benefit of 165 Specifically, I do not wish to suggest any sort of departure from Professor Corbin’s wise admonition that “[t]he law seeks to be neutral between the competing interests of seller and buyer.” Instead, I strive only to promote a framework to accomplish, as Professor Corbin also advocates, the perfect tender rule’s purpose of “protect[ing] the buyers of goods against sellers who would be tempted to saddle buyers with unsuitable and defective goods if buyers could not reject.” ARTHUR L. CORBIN, CORBIN ON CONTRACTS § 33.3 (2009). 644 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:611 166 its bargain.” In Joc Oil USA, the contract required delivery of oil meeting maximum sulfur content requirements with delivery during a specified period. The seller delivered oil with sulfur in excess of this amount and the buyer rejected. Since the stated time for performance had passed, the buyer refused to allow the seller any additional time to cure. In finding that the seller had a reasonable basis to believe his initial tender would be acceptable, the court frequently referenced the sharp decline in the oil market as evidence of the buyer’s unsavory motives.167 Regardless of whether the court meant to suggest a rule of law that rejection for minor defects in a falling market could be grounds for a finding of bad faith, these passing comments did provide fodder for such claims. In reality, the court never needed to go down the path of discussing the falling market for oil because, even without it, there was ample evidence to support the seller’s position. The court noted that the seller had no knowledge that the oil contained too much sulfur and, in fact, had received a report from their supplier indicating that the oil would conform.168 This would seem to satisfy the test advocated by White and Summers that the buyer be unaware of the defect despite his good faith and prudent business behavior.169 In addition, even under the more restrictive approach advocated by Nordstrom,170 the seller likely had reason to believe that his oil would be acceptable with a cash allowance because even the non-conforming shipment had a sulfur content within a range that the seller knew that the buyer was authorized to buy.171 From this evidence alone, the court could have inferred a reasonable basis to believe that the initial delivery would be acceptable.172 Since the buyer failed to provide the seller with the additional time to cure, which the court found he was entitled to, it had breached the contract regardless of its motives. Similarly, had the seller been unable to cure within a reasonable amount of additional time, then the buyer would have been fully within its rights—falling market or not—to reject delivery. To do otherwise would run contrary to the parties’ contract and force the buyer to accept poorer quality oil, when it had already suffered the misfortune of seeing the value of its purchase decline in the world oil market. 166 Austrian Airlines, 567 F. Supp. 2d at 600. See supra notes 105–08 and accompanying text. Joc Oil USA, Inc. v. Consol. Edison Co., 434 N.Y.S.2d. 623, 630 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1980). 169 See WHITE & SUMMERS, supra note 7, at 324. 170 See NORDSTROM, supra note 35, at 321. 171 Joc Oil USA, Inc., 434 N.Y.S.2d. at 626. 172 If anything, the evidence of a falling market for oil, which the court included in this portion of its discussion, actually seems to cut the other way. The seller’s knowledge that the market was falling should have made the possibility of the buyer’s rejection less of a surprise. 167 168 2009] GOOD FAITH REJECTION OF GOODS IN A FALLING MARKET 645 In short, no harm is caused by ignoring the presence of a falling market in a case where the buyer’s rejection has been contested; however, significant confusion, litigation, and unfairness to the contractual rights of buyers may result from its inclusion. As such, courts would be prudent to follow decisions such as Austrian Airlines and KCA Electronics and make their perfect tender rule discussions more about the conformity of the goods and less about market conditions that have only a sentimental impact on the outcome. CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW VOLUME 42 DECEMBER 2009 NUMBER 2 Note CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT: HOW REGULATORY INADEQUACIES IMPAIRED THE FED’S BAILOUT OF BEAR STEARNS BRYAN J. ORTICELLI This Note explores the failure of the investment bank Bear Stearns within the context of the greater financial crisis that began in the summer of 2007, largely as a result of the widespread collapse of the market for subprime mortgage-backed securities. Specifically, this Note discusses in detail the circumstances surrounding the fall of Bear Stearns, the unprecedented measures taken by the Federal Reserve to avoid a disorderly breakup of the firm, and the policy implications of the Fed’s actions for the future of investment bank regulation. By devoting particular attention to the Fed’s response to Bear Stearns’s liquidity crisis, which peaked in March of 2008, this Note seeks to elaborate on the statutory provisions utilized by the Fed in the “unusual and exigent” situation presented by the Bear Stearns predicament. Moreover, drawing on criticisms voiced by members of both the public and private sectors regarding the inadequacies of the Fed’s regulatory resources during the Bear Stearns crash, this Note considers potential reforms to federal supervision of investment banks in the future. With the hope of better understanding the government’s role in the ongoing financial dilemma, this Note uses the Bear Stearns bailout as a template for increasing dialogue on the issue of the government’s proper function during a free market catastrophe. 647 NOTE CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................... 649 II. THE TRAGEDY OF BEAR STEARNS ................................................ 653 A. B. C. D. THE OPENING ACT: JULY 2007–FEBRUARY 2008 ............................... 653 THE PERFECT STORM: MARCH 2008 ................................................... 655 THE TIME OF RECKONING.................................................................... 658 SHOTGUN MARRIAGE MADE IN HEAVEN ............................................ 661 III. AN “UNUSUAL AND EXIGENT” LENDER OF LAST RESORT .... 664 A. TOO BIG TO FAIL ................................................................................. 664 B. SWEETENING THE DEAL ...................................................................... 668 C. THE OFFSPRING OF EMERGENCY ......................................................... 672 IV. INADEQUACIES IMPAIRING INTERVENTION ............................. 675 A. THE CALL FOR REGULATORY REFORM ............................................... 675 B. PRIVATE SKEPTICISM........................................................................... 679 V. GOING FORWARD: THE FUTURE OF INVESTMENT BANK REGULATION ..................................................................................... 682 A. AN ATTEMPT AT RECONCILIATION...................................................... 682 B. THE CURRENT REALITY ...................................................................... 689 VI. CONCLUSION ..................................................................................... 689 CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT: HOW REGULATORY INADEQUACIES IMPAIRED THE FED’S BAILOUT OF BEAR STEARNS BRYAN J. ORTICELLI* As we continue to address current market stress, we must also examine the appropriate policy responses.1 In other words, the regulation that we have didn’t work very well.2 I. INTRODUCTION Long before American taxpayers became the proud owners of up to $700 billion in Wall Street’s “toxic assets,”3 Uncle Sam was already taking novel actions to rescue failing financial giants from their own balance sheets.4 More specifically, in March 2008, nearly seven months prior to “one of the largest-ever government interventions in the nation’s economy,”5 the Federal Reserve (“Fed”) exercised emergency lending authority to prevent an imminent failure of the investment bank, Bear Stearns.6 In so doing, the Fed utilized a “Depression-era law”7 in its role * Nova Southeastern University, Farquhar College of Arts & Sciences, B.S. 2007; University of Connecticut School of Law, J.D. Candidate 2010. I would like to express my sincere gratitude to Professor Patricia McCoy for her guidance and inspiration of this Note. This Note is dedicated to my parents for their unwavering support throughout my life. All errors contained herein are mine and mine alone. 1 Henry M. Paulson, Fmr. Sec’y of the Treasury, Remarks to the National Press Club on Recommendations from the President’s Working Group on Financial Markets (Mar. 13, 2008), available at http://www.ustreas.gov/press/releases/hp872.htm. 2 Tyler Cowen, Too Few Regulations? No, Just Ineffective Ones, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 14, 2008, at B7. 3 See Emergency Economic Stabilization Act of 2008, H.R. 1424, 110th Cong. § 115(a)(3) (2008) (authorizing the Treasury to incur up to $700 billion in purchase costs of troubled mortgage-backed securities and other assets). 4 See Michael Crittenden & Marshall Eckblad, Update: Fed Rescue of Bear Stearns Isn’t Like Bailouts of Old, DOW JONES NEWS SERV., Mar. 14, 2008 (“When the Fed announced . . . it had arranged short-term emergency financing for [Bear Stearns]—an unprecedented event, depending on whom you ask—it sent a signal to the world’s investors that a failure at [Bear Stearns] could put markets around the world at risk.”); see also David Fettig, The History of a Powerful Paragraph, REGION, June 2008, at 33, available at http://www.minneapolisfed.org/pubs/region/08-06/section13.pdf (“When describing the Federal Reserve’s response to the Bear Stearns episode, observers have used words like ‘extraordinary’ and ‘unprecedented.’”). 5 Greg Hitt & Deborah Solomon, Historic Bailout Passes as Economy Slips Further, WALL ST. J., Oct. 4, 2008, at A1. 6 See Timothy F. Geithner, Fmr. President, Fed. Reserve Bank of N.Y., Testimony Before the U.S. Senate Comm. on Banking, Hous. & Urban Affairs (Apr. 3, 2008), available at http://www.newyorkfed.org/newsevents/speeches/2008/gei080403.html (explaining the necessity of Fed intervention in the Bear Stearns financial crisis); Kate Kelly et al., Fed Races to Rescue Bear Stearns in Bid to Steady Financial System—Storied Firm Sees Stock Plunge 47%; JP Morgan Steps In, 650 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 8 as “lender of last resort” to avert the economic catastrophe that a disorderly bankruptcy of Bear Stearns presented.9 Fearful of the systemic risk posed by a sudden failure of an institution as large and interconnected as Bear Stearns, proponents of the bailout justified its imposition given the “unusual and exigent circumstances” involved.10 Moreover, with no private sector solution readily apparent at the time, the Central Bank had few options to choose from to protect the nation’s economy—a process Fed Chairman Ben Bernanke argued was “severely complicated by the lack of a clear statutory framework for dealing with such a situation.”11 The arcane framework criticized by Chairman Bernanke consists of fragmented authority among a variety of agencies including, among others, the Fed, the Securities and Exchange Commission (“SEC”), and the Commodity Futures Trading Commission (“CFTC”), who all play a role in overseeing investment banks.12 Not surprisingly, this consortium of WALL ST. J., Mar. 15, 2008, at A1 (“Credit turmoil spread to the heart of the U.S. financial system as Bear Stearns Cos., an 85-year-old institution that has survived the Depression and two world wars, sought and received emergency funding backed by the federal government.”). For a more detailed discussion of the Fed’s utilization of emergency lending authority during the Bear Stearns crisis, see infra Part III.A.–B. It should be noted at the outset that this Note’s continuous reference to “Bear Stearns” is made with respect to the company as the nation’s fifth-largest investment bank as it existed in March 2008. Benton Ives, Fed Dips into Bag of Liquidity Tricks, CQ WEEKLY, Mar. 17, 2008, at 684. Although The Bear Stearns Companies, Inc. included numerous subsidiary institutions and organizations, this Note is solely concerned with the operations of Bear Stearns as an investment bank. Investment banks (i.e., nonbanks), unlike their commercial depository counterparts, function primarily as financial intermediaries, and are subject to less regulatory oversight and standards than traditional banks. See, e.g., Jose Gabilondo, Leveraged Liquidity: Bear Raids and Junk Loans in the New Credit Market 10 (Fla. Int’l Univ. Legal Studies Research Paper No. 08-01, 2008), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1141955 (“Nonbank lenders need not comply with federal limits on how much the lender can leverage [or assume debt] itself.” (citation omitted)). 7 Greg Ip, Bear on the Brink: Desperate Fed Dusts Off Remedy from the Depression to Save Bear—Opening the Discount Window for a Nonbank Requires Special Votes at Central Bank, WALL ST. J., Mar. 15, 2008, at A9. 8 David Fettig, Lender of More than Last Resort, REGION, Dec. 2002, at 15–19, 44–47, available at http://www.minneapolisfed.org/pubs/region/02-12/lender.pdf. 9 See Ben S. Bernanke, Chairman of the Bd. of Governors of the Fed. Reserve, Remarks at the Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation’s Forum on Mortgage Lending for Low and Moderate Income Households (July 8, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/bernanke 20080708a.htm [hereinafter Bernanke, FDIC] (“[A]llowing Bear Stearns to fail so abruptly at a time when the financial markets were already under considerable stress would likely have had extremely adverse implications for the financial system and for the broader economy.”). 10 See, e.g., Ben S. Bernanke, Chairman of the Bd. of Governors of the Fed. Reserve, Testimony Before the Joint Economics Committee (Apr. 2, 2008), available at http://federalreserve.gov/ newsevents/testimony/bernanke20080402a.htm (“With financial conditions fragile, the sudden failure of Bear Stearns likely would have led to a chaotic unwinding of positions in [critical] markets and could have severely shaken confidence.”); see also Federal Reserve Act, 12 U.S.C. § 343 (2006). 11 Ben S. Bernanke, Chairman of the Bd. of Governors of the Fed. Reserve, Remarks at the Federal Reserve Bank of Kansas City’s Annual Economic Symposium (Aug. 22, 2008), available at http://federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/bernanke20080822a.htm [hereinafter Bernanke, Kansas City]. 12 See Regulatory Checks and Balances, CQ WEEKLY, Mar. 17, 2008, at 681, 681 (“A variety of federal agencies oversee the nation’s financial institutions. In response to the sub-prime mortgage crisis, the President’s Working Group on Financial Markets has proposed that many of those regulators step up their oversight, particularly in regards to trading in mortgage-backed securities.”). 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 651 government entities can result in gray areas of regulation, where seemingly distinct oversight duties can overlap and lead to supervisory inconsistency, or worse.13 For example, although Bear Stearns was primarily regulated by the SEC as a securities firm, the Commission (unlike the Fed) does not “have a checkbook to help inject money into an investment bank or market when it hits trouble.”14 Conversely, during the Bear Stearns emergency, the Fed lacked the extensive regulatory oversight of investment banks that the SEC’s mandate provides15—oversight which may have preemptively thwarted the need for an eventual $29 billion bailout.16 Concerns such as these have prompted intense review by members of both the public and private sectors of existing financial regulation, particularly as coordinated and implemented by the Fed over investment banks.17 With immense changes to government policy already occurring,18 13 See Kara Scannell, The Bear Stearns Fallout: Crisis Highlights SEC’s Limits—Agency’s Lack of Tools to Stem Financial Woes May Rekindle Debate, WALL ST. J., Mar. 18, 2008, at A19 (“These various [agencies] are all doing the same thing even if they’re called different things. It doesn’t allow for the effective measurement of risk, the effective development of national policy. It’s just a patchwork quilt that needs to be revised.” (quoting Harvey Pitt, former SEC Chairman)). 14 Id.; see also Kara Scannell, Credit Crisis: SEC Comes Under Criticism in Light of Bear Woes, WALL ST. J., Mar. 27, 2008, at A6 (discussing the SEC’s limitations in times of financial crisis). 15 See Roger C. Altman, How the Fed Can Fix the World, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 3, 2008, at A25 (“[S]uddenly, the Fed was standing behind both the larger [commercial] banks it regulates and the major investment banks it does not. This cannot continue.”). Despite the SEC’s broad ideological regulatory mission, its efforts in actively overseeing diverse financial operations, including those of hedge funds, have been the subject of ongoing scholarly criticism. See Thomas C. Pearson & Julia Lin Pearson, Protecting Global Financial Market Stability and Integrity: Strengthening SEC Regulation of Hedge Funds, 33 N.C. J. INT’L L. & COM. REG. 1, 48–60 (2007) (evaluating historical limitations on the SEC’s oversight of hedge funds). 16 See Amit R. Paley & David Hilzenrath, SEC Chief Defends His Restraint; Cox Rebuffs Criticism of Leadership During Crisis, WASH. POST, Dec. 24, 2008, at A1 (“The March collapse of Bear Stearns illustrated an array of [SEC] shortcomings, according to a review by the SEC’s inspector general. [The inspector general] concluded that [SEC] officials had been aware of ‘numerous potential red flags’ at Bear Stearns ‘but did not take actions to limit these risk factors.’”); see also Kate Kelly, The Fall of Bear Stearns: Bear Stearns Neared Collapse Twice in Frenzied Last Days—Paulson Pushed Low-Ball Bid, Relented, WALL ST. J., May 29, 2008, at A1 (“To make [Bear’s bailout] palatable to the Fed, J.P. Morgan assumed responsibility for the first $1 billion of any potential losses, reducing the government’s exposure [in the bailout] to $29 billion.”). 17 See, e.g., Stephen Morris & Hyun Song Shin, Financial Regulation in a System Context, BROOKINGS PAPERS ON ECON. ACTIVITY, Fall 2008, at 2, 2–13, available at http://www.brookings.edu/economics/bpea/~/media/Files/Programs/ES/BPEA/2008_fall_bpea_papers/ 2008_fall_bpea_morris_shin.pdf (“The most pressing policy question has been whether broker-dealers, [including investment banks] should fall under banking regulation overseen by the Federal Reserve, and if so how they should be regulated.”); see also Elizabeth F. Browne, The Tyranny of the Multitude Is a Multiplied Tyranny: Is the United States Financial Regulatory Structure Undermining U.S. Competitiveness?, 2 BROOKINGS J. CORP. FIN. & COM. L. 369, 376–410 (2008) (criticizing the American financial regulatory structure as detrimental to global competition and providing empirical analysis of derogatory effects within various financial markets); Ashok Vir Bhatia, New Landscape, New Challenges: Structural Change and Regulation in the U.S. Financial Sector 17–19 (Int’l Monetary Fund, Working Paper No. 07/195, 2007), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm? abstract_id=1007943 (discussing emerging policy considerations in the changing U.S. financial markets). 652 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 questions remain as to the proper scope of the Fed’s administrative authority19—especially now that the financial landscape has altered such that no major independent investment banks exist.20 As the Bear Stearns incident suggests, effective government oversight directives can mean the difference between preventing a crisis and using billions of dollars of public funds to bail out private enterprises.21 However, as former Treasury Secretary Henry Paulson has noted, regulation cannot “go so far as to . . . make our markets less efficient,”22 or less competitive by stemming innovation.23 Using the Bear Stearns case as a template, this Note explores the criticisms regarding the regulatory structure of the American financial industry with the goal of increasing dialogue as to the proper role of government in the free market. By focusing on the unique circumstances precipitating government action in avoiding the collapse of Bear Stearns, this Note analyzes the legal tools relied on by the Fed to rescue Bear, and how these tools may have been inadequate for the task at hand. Finally, this Note draws on existing scholarly work to evaluate models of reform as the economy continues to evolve. Part II chronologically traces the factual developments leading up to and including the Fed’s bailout of Bear Stearns. Discussion centers on the early onset of the subprime mortgage crisis, initial effects of the crisis on Bear Stearns’s ability to do business, and how Bear’s exposure to exotic mortgage products eventually induced its demise. Part II also examines the near bankruptcy of Bear and the Fed’s actions in forestalling this occurrence, including facilitating the acquisition of Bear Stearns by JPMorgan Chase (“JPMorgan”). Part III considers the legal authority (pursuant to the Federal Reserve Act) justifying the Fed’s actions in providing emergency funding to Bear 18 See Stephen Labaton, S.E.C. Concedes Oversight Flaws Fueled Collapse, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 27, 2008, at A1 (“The S.E.C.’s oversight responsibilities will largely shift to the Federal Reserve, though the commission will continue to oversee the brokerage units of investment banks.”). 19 See Bernanke, Kansas City, supra note 11 (“Going forward, a critical question for regulators and supervisors is what their appropriate ‘field of vision’ should be.”). 20 See Jon Hilsenrath et al., Goldman, Morgan Scrap Wall Street Model, Become Banks in Bid to Ride Out Crisis, WALL ST. J., Sept. 22, 2008, at A1 (“It had become increasingly clear to Fed officials . . . that the investment-banking model couldn’t function in these markets.”). 21 See Bernanke, Kansas City, supra note 11 (“The regulation and supervisory oversight of financial institutions is another critical tool for limiting systemic risk. . . . A stronger [regulatory] infrastructure would help to reduce systemic risk.”). 22 Paulson, supra note 1. 23 See Browne, supra note 17, at 376–410 (suggesting that disorganized government policy can negatively affect the United States’ ability to compete for foreign investors in a variety of markets); John T. Lynch, Credit Derivatives: Industry Initiative Supplants Need for Direct Regulatory Intervention—A Model for the Future of U.S. Regulation?, 55 BUFF. L. REV. 1371, 1423 (2008) (“An increasingly heavy regulatory burden and a complex, cumbersome regulatory structure with overlaps at the state and national levels is causing an increasing number of businesses to conduct more and more transactions outside the country.” (citation omitted)). 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 653 Stearns and arranging JPMorgan’s purchase of the company. Additionally, Part III assesses the creation and revision of lending facilities operated by the Fed following the Bear Stearns experience and how these facilities contribute to the growing supervisory authority of the Central Bank. Part IV analyzes criticism as to both the Fed’s apparently inadequate ability to effectively manage the Bear Stearns situation and concerns that have been voiced regarding the increasing omnipresence of government in the free market. To bolster the contextual perspective of these competing positions, comparisons will be drawn from diverse regulatory systems, including those operative in foreign arenas, particularly the United Kingdom. Finally, Part V focuses on the principal issue of systemic risk in evaluating the future of investment bank regulation, and how current research on the topic may contribute to a new regulatory framework better equipped at protecting the American (and global) economy. Part V also reviews the state of the current financial markets in considering the need for added regulation, while reflecting on the causes and implications of the ongoing financial debacle. II. THE TRAGEDY OF BEAR STEARNS A. The Opening Act: July 2007–February 200824 Prior to the summer of 2007, “the world experienced an unusual mix of financial conditions”25 that resulted in a dramatic growth of a variety of consumer and financial markets, most notably the housing market and subprime mortgage loan industry.26 Large investment banks sought to capitalize on the boom in the housing market by not only buying 24 This subpart is intended to provide necessary background leading up to the Fed’s bailout of Bear Stearns in March 2008. As such, brief consideration is paid to the onset of the subprime mortgage crisis and the ensuing credit crisis within the financial markets, and how this phenomenon contributed to Bear Stearns’ operational failure. However, full discussion of the causes and implications of the mortgage and credit crises is beyond the scope of this Note. 25 Timothy F. Geithner, Fmr. President, Fed. Reserve Bank of N.Y., Remarks at the Council on Foreign Relations Corporate Conference 2008: The Current Financial Challenges: Policy and Regulatory Implications (Mar. 6, 2008), available at http://www.newyorkfed.org/newsevents/speeches/ 2008/gei080306.html [hereinafter Geithner, Foreign Relations]. 26 See Raymond H. Brescia, Capital in Chaos: The Subprime Mortgage Crisis and the Social Capital Response, 56 CLEV. ST. L. REV. 271, 282–300 (2008) (providing a detailed account of the growth and eventual collapse of the subprime mortgage market); see also A. Mechele Dickerson, Consumer Over-Indebtedness: A U.S. Perspective, 43 TEX. INT’L L.J. 135, 139–44 (2008) (describing the increase in mortgage lending and consumer debt assumption and noting how such factors contributed to the onset of the mortgage crisis); Paul Mizen, The Credit Crunch of 2007–2008: A Discussion of the Background, Market Reactions, and Policy Responses, FED. RESERVE BANK OF ST. LOUIS REV., Sept./Oct. 2008, at 531, 536, available at http://research.stlouisfed.org/publications/ review/08/09/Mizen.pdf (“The market for subprime mortgages grew very fast.”). 654 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 27 considerable stakes in subprime mortgage loans, but also by “securitizing” and pooling these loans into structured assets that would be attractive to other investors based on anticipated return and risk exposure.28 These assets, known primarily as subprime mortgage-backed securities (“MBS”) and collateralized debt obligations (“CDOs”),29 were particularly popular with two large hedge funds at Bear Stearns: the “High-Grade Structured Credit Strategies Fund” and the “High-Grade Structured Credit Strategies Enhanced Leverage Fund.”30 Despite their initial appeal, subprime MBS and CDOs turned toxic when the housing bubble burst starting in late 2006 and early 2007, and extending into 2008.31 Large losses from these investments quickly resulted in the evaporation of financing for private-label MBS,32 causing loss of investor confidence and the subsequent failure of many subprime lenders.33 As these problems continued to escalate in a vicious cycle 27 See Kenneth C. Johnston et al., The Subprime Morass: Past, Present, and Future, 12 N.C. BANKING INST. 125, 130 (2008) (“[N]ever before had those on Wall Street been invested so heavily in securities backed by subprime loans. . . . [T]hese investment vehicles became highly sought after by . . . investment banks.”); Gretchen Morgenson, Rescue Me: A Fed Bailout Crosses a Line, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 16, 2008, at B1 (“As of . . . Nov. 30, [2007,] Bear Stearns had on its books approximately $46 billion of mortgages [and] mortgaged-backed . . . securities.”). 28 See LUIGI SPAVENTA, CTR. FOR ECON. POL’Y RESEARCH, POLICY INSIGHT NO. 22, AVOIDING DISORDERLY DELEVERAGING 1 (2008), available at http://www.cepr.org/pubs/PolicyInsights/ PolicyInsight22.pdf (“[B]anks would pool and securitize the [products] they originated to distribute them and transfer their risks to a myriad of investors.”). 29 See Johnston et al., supra note 27, at 128–29 (discussing CDOs and MBS as types of investments that derive their value from the repayment of loans by the initial home borrowers). To make these investments marketable, investment firms would splice original loans into “tranches” to reduce the risk of loss presented by a loan’s default. Id. Thus, investors could largely choose the type of risk they were willing to accept based on the yield values of differing tranches. See Steven L. Schwarcz, Protecting Financial Markets: Lessons from the Subprime Mortgage Meltdown, 93 MINN. L. REV. 373, 375–79 (2008) (detailing the distribution of CDOs and MBS through unique schematic processes). 30 These funds held “60% of their net worth . . . in exotic securities.” Matthew Goldstein & David Henry, Bear Bets Wrong, BUS. WK., Oct. 22, 2007, at 50; see also Kate Kelly et al., Two Big Funds at Bear Stearns Face Shutdown—As Rescue Plan Falters amid Subprime Woes, Merrill Asserts Claims, WALL ST. J., June 20, 2007, at A1 (“[T]he two Bear Stearns hedge funds held more than $20 billion of investments, mostly in complex securities made up of bonds backed by subprime mortgages . . . .”). 31 See Joe Nicer & Edmund L. Andrews, Running a Step Behind as a Crisis Raged, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 23, 2008, at A1 (“The subprime mortgage debacle began emerging in the summer of 2007 . . . [b]ut the true depth and extent of the losses did not become clear until [early in 2008] . . . .”); John Tatom, The U.S. Foreclosure Crisis: A Two-Pronged Assault on the U.S. Economy 4–14 (Munich Personal Repel Archive, Paper No. 9787, 2008), available at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/9787/1/MPRA_ paper_9787.pdf (explaining how declines in the demand for housing and slowing in home appreciation contributed to losses in mortgaged related investments). 32 See Ben S. Bernanke, Chairman of the Bd. of the Fed. Reserve, Testimony Before the Joint Econ. Comm. (Sept. 24, 2008), available at http://federalreserve.gov/newsevents/testimony/ bernanke20080924a.htm (“[F]alling home prices and rising mortgage delinquencies have led to major losses at many financial institutions, losses only partially replaced by the raising of new capital.”). 33 See Frederic S. Mishkin, Governor of the Bd. of the Fed. Reserve, Speech to the Money Marketeers of New York University: Outlook and Risks for the U.S. Economy (Sept. 10, 2007), available at http://federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/mishkin20070910a.htm (“The rise in delinquencies in the subprime market has led to the collapse of some large subprime lenders and 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 655 throughout late 2007 and early 2008, consequences soon spread to Wall Street and Bear Stearns, which in the summer of 2007 attempted to save one of its hedge funds by injecting $1.6 billion into its reserves— ultimately to no avail as both funds eventually lost all value.34 “By various accounts, the funds’ meltdown signaled the start of a collapse in the vital element of trust that must exist between a firm like Bear and its many customers.”35 This breakdown in trust would abruptly evolve into a contagion, attacking the heart of Bear Stearns’s business operations and bringing the eighty-five-year-old institution to its knees.36 For the fourth quarter of 2007, Bear reported a $2 billion write down in mortgage securities,37 and posted its “first-ever quarterly loss” of $859 million.38 Unfortunately for the company, such losses would be emblematic of Bear’s remaining existence as a going concern. Throughout the rest of 2007 and into early 2008, Bear saw its stock value plummet, client trust evaporate, and cohesion among its leadership unwind.39 B. The Perfect Storm: March 2008 To understand how Bear Stearns ultimately collapsed, it is first important to explain Bear’s financing structure. As an investment bank,40 Bear relied on short-term (usually overnight) loans called repurchase agreements (“repos”) to finance its daily activities and liquidity demands.41 inflicted substantial losses on holders of subprime [MBS] and of some . . . CDOs. . . . These developments have contributed materially to the drop in demand for housing [in 2007].”). 34 See GARY SHORTER, CONG. RESEARCH SERV., BEAR STEARNS: CRISIS AND “RESCUE” FOR A MAJOR PROVIDER OF MORTGAGE-RELATED PRODUCTS 2, Mar. 19, 2008, available at http://assets.opencrs.com/rpts/RL34420_20080319.pdf (noting that soon after Bear’s loans to these funds, “the funds lost all of their value and were allowed to wind down”). 35 Id.; see also Landon Thomas, Jr., Run on Big Wall St. Bank Spurs U.S.-Backed Rescue, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 15, 2008, at A1 (“The demise of the hedge funds began a slow but persistent loss of market confidence in the bank . . . . Such erosion can be devastating for any investment bank, especially one like Bear Stearns . . . .”). 36 See SHORTER, supra note 34, at 2 (noting that the initial breakdown in trust among Bear’s customers would lead to unprecedented moves by the company to survive). 37 David Smith & Dominic Rushe, The Banking Twister Heading Your Way, SUNDAY TIMES (London), Mar. 16, 2008, at B4 (“A month [after Bear attempted to save one of its hedge funds,] the firm announced that the game was up for the funds, which had effectively lost all their value . . . .”). 38 SHORTER, supra note 34, at 2. 39 See Kate Kelly, The Fall of Bear Stearns: Lost Opportunities Haunt Final Days of Bear Stearns—Executives Bickered Over Raising Cash, Cutting Mortgages, WALL ST. J., May 27, 2008, at A1 (documenting internal developments at Bear Stearns following the failure of its hedge funds in the summer of 2007 through January 2008). 40 Unlike commercial banks, investment banks do not take deposits from traditional individual customers; rather, “[a]n investment bank’s activities” consist of “(1) managing an investment portfolio . . . and (2) operating as a central market maker and counterparty” in financial markets. Dwight Jaffee & Mark Perlow, Investment Banking Regulation After Bear Stearns, ECONOMISTS’ VOICE, Sept. 2008, at 1, 1–2. 41 See Stephen A. Lumpkin, Repurchase and Reverse Repurchase Agreements, in INSTRUMENTS OF THE MONEY MARKETS 59, 60 (Timothy Q. Cook & Robert K. Laroche eds., 1993) (“[Repurchase] agreements usually are arranged with short terms to maturity—overnight or a few days.”); Stephen G. 656 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 Repos are secured by collateral (including MBS) that the borrowing institution promises to buy back at a specified date and at a specified price, “which typically includes interest at an agreed upon rate.”42 In essence, because repos were vital to Bear’s daily operations, they left Bear at the mercy of lender sentiment.43 Thus, when the subprime mortgage crisis unfolded, lenders grew more fearful of entering into collateralized loans with Bear given the firm’s large exposure to mortgage products.44 Instead, lenders hoarded their liquidity, uncertain about the health of their own balance sheets and those of their counterparties.45 “And it was the [eventual] refusal of Bear’s repo lenders to extend overnight loans that confirmed that Bear had a liquidity crisis [in mid-March 2008].”46 However, the growing failure of Bear to secure its vital repos in March 2008 was not the only factor that led to the firm’s “liquidity crisis.”47 While it may be said that Bear’s repo problems kept it from pulling money in, Bear’s exposure to a variety of deteriorating assets led to losses that eroded its already meager capital.48 For example, Bear, like other investment banks, initially appealed to investor concerns of security by selling a type of insurance product along Cecchetti, Crisis and Responses: The Federal Reserve and the Financial Crisis of 2007–2008, at 10 (Nat’l Bureau of Econ. Res., Working Paper No. 14134, 2008), available at, http://www.nber.org/ papers/w14134.pdf (“Large financial institutions that hold various types of assets use repos to finance their short-term liquidity needs—and those needs have grown astronomically.”). Amazingly, Bear Stearns borrowed “more than 30 times the value of its $11 billion equity base,” amounting to a “leverage ratio of over 30 to 1.” Thomas, supra note 35. To make matters more complicated, Bear used large amounts of this borrowed money to invest in the same CDOs it was selling to other investors. See Kelly et al., supra note 30 (“The problems can be exacerbated because many hedge funds invest in CDOs with the help of borrowed money. To buy a triple-A rated CDO note for $1,000, it is common for a hedge fund to put down only $100 of its own money . . . .”). 42 See Lumpkin, supra note 41, at 59, 62. 43 See Gabilondo, supra note 6, at 19 (“It was lender sentiment [in the repo market] that [Bear’s] managers considered when evaluating the severity of the firm’s liquidity crisis.” (internal citation omitted)). 44 See id. (“Anxious about market conditions, these lenders preferred to hoard liquidity rather than to enter into collateralized loans.”). This phenomenon was symptomatic of the larger financial crisis in which banks grew so fearful of lending to one another that access to available credit became very difficult to secure. See Cecchetti, supra note 41, at 12 (“[T]he overriding consideration in the refusal of banks to lend to one another must have become the concern over credit risk—that is, the risk that borrowers would fail to repay.”). 45 See Randall S. Kroszner, Governor of the Bd. of the Fed. Reserve, Remarks at the Risk Management Association Annual Risk Management Conference: Strategic Risk Management in an Interconnected World (Oct. 20, 2008), available at http://federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/ kroszner20081020a.htm (“Uncertainty about the value of assets and other exposures, as well as uncertainty about the ability of institutions to sustain continued access to funding, has caused financial institutions to operate with great caution and hoard funds.”). 46 Gabilondo, supra note 6, at 19. 47 Donald L. Kohn, Vice Chairman of the Bd. of the Fed. Reserve, Speech at the Federal Reserve Bank of New York and Columbia Business School Conference on the Role of Money Markets (May 29, 2008), available at http://federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/kohn20080529a.htm. 48 See Geithner, supra note 6 (“The rumors of Bear’s failing financial health caused its balance of unencumbered liquidity . . . to decline sharply . . . .”). 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 657 49 with the MBS and CDOs Bear promoted. Known as credit default swaps (“CDS”), these insurance contracts were marketed to investors as an effective way to hedge risks associated with the default of underlying mortgage loans.50 Essentially, CDS enabled investors in CDOs or MBS to protect themselves in the event the underlying investment defaulted, by paying a periodic fee in exchange for the promised contingency payment.51 Furthermore, even those investors who had not bought mortgaged-related products could purchase CDS as a type of side bet that loans would default and the investor would be paid the value of the CDS coverage.52 CDS created systemic risk because the same investment banks that were selling these contracts were also buying them from other financial guarantors to secure the CDS they had sold.53 Because the CDS market was largely unregulated,54 the aggregate amounts of these contracts skyrocketed to an estimated total amount of $60 trillion,55 with Bear Stearns alone holding roughly “$14.2 trillion of notional value in derivative contracts [including CDS] outstanding with thousands of counterparties.”56 Ultimately, as mortgage loans defaulted in vast numbers, Bear’s CDS liability was triggered. But there was one problem: “there was no money 49 See SHORTER, supra note 34, at 4. See 60 Minutes: A Look at Wall Street’s Shadow Market (CBS television broadcast Oct. 5, 2008), available at http://www.cbsnews.com/stories/2008/10/05/60minutes/main4502454.shtml (“A [CDS] was available [to investors], marketed to them as a risk-saving device for buying a risky financial instrument.” (quoting Michael Greenberger, Prof. of Law, Univ. of Maryland)); see also Frank Partnoy & David A. Skeel, Jr., The Promise and Perils of Credit Derivatives, 75 U. CIN. L. REV. 1019, 1021 (2007) (“[A] credit default swap is a private contract in which private parties bet on a debt issuer’s bankruptcy, default, or restructuring.”). As credit derivatives, CDS derive their value from an underlying “price, rate, index, or financial instrument,” such as a MBS or CDO. David Mangle, Credit Derivatives: An Overview, ECON. REV., Fourth Quarter 2007, at 1, available at http://www.frbatlanta. org/filelegacydocs/erq407_mengle.pdf. 51 See Franklin Allen & Douglas Gale, Systemic Risk and Regulation 4–5 (Wharton Fin. Inst. Ctr., Working Paper No. 95-24, 2005), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id =787797 (describing CDS arrangements). 52 See Partnoy & Skeel, supra note 50, at 1022 (“Like other derivatives, credit default swaps can be used not only for hedging, but also for speculation or arbitrage.”); 60 Minutes: Financial Weapons of Mass Destruction (CBS Television broadcast Oct. 26, 2008), available at http://www.cbsnews.com/ stories/2008/10/26/60minutes/main4546199.shtml?tag=currentVideoInfo;segmentUtilities (“[CDS] were essentially private insurance contracts that paid off if the investment went bad. But you didn’t have to actually own the investment to collect on the insurance.”). 53 See Geithner, Foreign Relations, supra note 25 (“[O]n the assets they retained, these same institutions purchased insurance from financial guarantors and other firms that were exposed to the same risks.”). 54 See 60 Minutes, supra note 50 (discussing how CDS regulation had been lacking since 2000). Following the stock market crash of 1907, state laws across the country made betting arrangements (such as those embodied by CDS) a felony. Id. However, the Commodity Futures Modernization Act of 2000 effectively removed the restrictions placed on these transactions. Id.; see also Commodity Futures Modernization Act of 2000, 7 U.S.C. § 27f(c) (2006) (preempting state regulation of CDS transactions whose initial manifestation occurred in gambling houses known as “bucket shops”). 55 Jon Hilsenrath et al., Worst Crisis Since ‘30s, with No End Yet in Sight, WALL ST. J., Sept. 18, 2008, at A1. 56 Cecchetti, supra note 41, at 17. This figure is not totally comprised of CDS, as the firm also held other types of derivative products, including futures and options. Id. 50 658 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 57 behind the commitments.” The same institutions that had sold CDS were not legally required to set aside the necessary cash to cover “their potential losses.”58 Together with the defection of its hedge fund customers who could easily withdraw their large deposits,59 the CDS losses suffered by Bear helped set the stage for a classic run on the (investment) bank.60 Amid growing market anxiety, key counterparties began canceling their investment and brokerage accounts with Bear,61 with “[s]ome [investors] pulling their cash . . . for fear it could get locked up if there was a bankruptcy.”62 As clients withdrew their business, Bear watched as its credit dissolved, and it was only a matter of time before Bear’s problems became a public concern.63 C. The Time of Reckoning Bear’s access to and drain of liquidity continued to develop in early 2008. On March 10, “rumors began to circulate in the market that there were significant liquidity problems at Bear Stearns itself.”64 These rumors were then exacerbated by attempts to quell them, as Bear executives and Moody’s Investors Service (“Moody’s”) both issued statements aimed at reassuring investors that Bear was in good health, emphasizing the firm’s large cash holdings of approximately $18 billion.65 Nonetheless, such actions could not stop the intensifying “exit by counterparties” Bear was 57 60 Minutes, supra note 50. More precisely, CDS are traded as over-the-counter (“OTC”) derivatives without strict regulatory oversight, and as such “contracts can be traded—or swapped— from investor to investor without anyone overseeing the trades to ensure the buyer has the resources to cover the losses if the security defaults.” Janet Morrissey, Credit Default Swaps: The Next Crisis?, TIME, Mar. 17, 2008, http://www.time.com/time/business/article/0,8599,1723152,00.html. 58 60 Minutes, supra note 50. 59 See Morris & Shin, supra note 17, at 15. 60 See Bernanke, Kansas City, supra note 11 (“The collapse of Bear Stearns was triggered by a run of its creditors and customers, analogous to the run of depositors on a commercial bank.”). 61 See Kate Kelly, SEC Will Scour Bear Trading Data—Documents Reveal Who Was Exiting Deals in Final Days, WALL ST. J., May 28, 2008, at A1 (describing how several important investment institutions sought to cancel their business connections with Bear in anticipation of the firm’s collapse). The exit by counterparties actually increased market stress, as these parties struggled to find substitute transaction avenues. See Serena Ng, Crisis on Wall Street: Credit-Default Market Freezes as Risk Grows, WALL ST. J., Sept. 19, 2008, at C3 (discussing how this phenomenon negatively affected greater market confidence). 62 Kelly et al., supra note 6. 63 See Kate Kelly et al., In Dealing with Bear Stearns, Wall Street Plays Guardedly, WALL ST. J., Mar. 13, 2008, at C1 (“Bear’s fundamental issue isn’t liquidity or capital as much as the erosion of its business model as a result of the credit crunch.”). 64 JPMorgan Chase & Co., Definitive Proxy Statement (Form DEFM14A), at 27, (Apr. 28, 2008), available at http://files.shareholder.com/downloads/ONE/692396293x0xS1193125-08-92860/777001/ filing.pdf. 65 See id. (“Moody’s clarified that . . . Bear Stearns’ . . . current ratings outlook was stable [and] . . . Bear Stearns issued a press release denying the market rumors regarding its liquidity position.”); Ruddy Boyd & Doris Burke, The Last Days of Bear Stearns, FORTUNE, Apr. 14, 2008, at 86. 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 659 66 experiencing. And “a number of U.S.-based fixed-income and stock traders that had been actively involved with Bear . . . had reportedly decided by March 10 to halt such involvement.”67 On Tuesday, March 11, investors continued to grow anxious over the rumors, and ING Group NV, “a major asset-management company,” stopped doing trades with Bear68—it was clear that “[c]redit was drying up.”69 Again, in an effort to calm market fears, Bear Stearns executives decided that President and CEO Alan Schwartz should address the public live from a media conference in West Palm Beach, Florida.70 Mr. Schwartz did so the next morning, appearing on CNBC and stating that “we don’t see any pressure on our liquidity, let alone a liquidity crisis.”71 Meanwhile, “prime-brokerage clients continued to pull their money” from Bear,72 “causing senior management . . . to become concerned that if these circumstances accelerated Bear Stearns’s liquidity could be negatively affected.”73 When Mr. Schwartz arrived back in New York late Wednesday, March 12, he assembled “senior executives to discuss how to save the firm.”74 But, his efforts would prove fruitless. By Thursday, March 13, “market speculation had swelled” regarding Bear’s access to credit and “[a]round 4:30 p.m., Mr. Schwartz was convinced that Bear was facing a desperate situation.”75 Confronted with the ongoing demands of clients and lenders to withdraw their money from Bear, the firm had seen its liquidity reserves depleted to nearly $2 billion, a loss of approximately $15 billion in four days.76 Frantic to find a solution, Mr. Schwartz contacted Jamie Dimon, CEO of JPMorgan Chase, in a bid to negotiate a deal with the company, which had a long transactional history with Bear Stearns.77 Mr. Dimon agreed to help, dispatching senior 66 See Kelly et al., supra note 6 (explaining the swift departure of customers that had previously been willing to trade with Bear). 67 SHORTER, supra note 34, at 3. 68 Id. 69 Boyd & Burke, supra note 65. 70 See Kelly et al., supra note 6. 71 Interview by David Faber with Alan Schwartz, President & CEO, Bear Stearns, on CNBC: First on CNBC (CNBC television broadcast Mar. 12, 2008), available at http://video.nytimes.com/ video/2008/03/14/business/1194817092072/bear-chief-firm-was-on-solid-ground.html. 72 Kate Kelly, The Fall of Bear Stearns: Fear, Rumors Touched Off Fatal Run on Bear Stearns, WALL ST. J., May, 28, 2008, at A1. 73 JPMorgan Chase & Co., supra note 64, at 27. 74 Kelly, supra note 72. 75 William Sluis et al., Bailout of Wall Street Firm Shocks Markets; Federal Reserve Forced to Save Company Squeezed by Mortgage Securities, CHI. TRIB., Mar. 15, 2008, at C1. 76 See Robin Sidel et al., The Week that Shook Wall Street: Inside the Demise of Bear Stearns, WALL ST. J., Mar. 18, 2008, at A1 (“By [Thursday], Bear Stearns’s cash position had dwindled to just $2 billion.”). 77 See Kelly, supra note 72 (describing how Schwartz contacted Dimon during his birthday party and related to Dimon “[l]et’s do something”); see also Mizen, supra note 26, at 549 (noting that JPMorgan Chase served effectively as Bear Stearns’s “banker”). 660 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 JPMorgan traders to Bear to review the firm’s financial position.78 Upon review, “[Dimon’s] group appeared stunned,”79 and it became apparent later in the evening that Bear would not be able to secure unassisted private financing from JPMorgan or any another institution.80 Bear’s directors approved an emergency bankruptcy filing, and the firm’s corporate counsel, Cadwalader, Wickersham & Taft LLP, began drafting necessary documentation.81 Representatives from the SEC and the New York Fed, which had been closely monitoring the situation, participated in a conference call with members of the Board of Governors of the Fed and the Treasury Department to discuss the implications of a Bear bankruptcy.82 Chaotic discussions continued throughout the evening and into the early morning, but no clear resolution was in sight.83 At 5 a.m. on Friday, March 14, Timothy Geithner (then-President and CEO of the New York Fed) convened a conference call “with top government officials” to rule on the fate of Bear Stearns.84 Recognizing Bear’s highly complex interrelationships with thousands of counterparties, and fearing that a failure of Bear could touch off a domino effect among other institutions in similar market positions,85 “the Federal Reserve, in close consultation with the Treasury Department, agreed to provide funding to Bear Stearns through JPMorgan Chase.”86 Because Bear Stearns was an investment bank, it could not use its collateral to gain a direct loan from the Fed’s “discount window,”87 necessitating the utilization of emergency lending authority.88 Although technically the Fed did not lend directly to Bear, by providing the funds to JPMorgan to then re-issue to the firm, the Fed itself assumed the risk of the 78 See Kelly, supra note 72; see also JPMorgan, supra note 64, at 28 (“Representatives of JPMorgan Chase and officials from the U.S. Treasury Department, the New York Fed and the Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System engaged in discussions regarding how to resolve the liquidity deterioration at Bear Stearns.”). 79 Kelly, supra note 72. 80 See JPMorgan, supra note 64, at 28. 81 Kelly, supra note 72. 82 See Geithner, supra note 6. 83 See Sidel et al., supra note 76 (“‘It was a traumatic experience,’ says one person who participated. Sleep deprivation set in, with some of the hundreds of attorneys and bankers sleeping only a few hours . . . .”). 84 Kelly, supra note 72. 85 For example, “Bear risked defaulting on extensive ‘repo’ loans . . . . If that happened, other securities dealers would see access to repo loans become more restrictive[,]” not to mention the fear that would be set off in the CDS markets. Kelly et al., supra note 6. 86 Ben S. Bernanke, Chairman of the Bd. of the Fed. Reserve, Testimony Before the U.S. Senate Comm. on Banking, Hous. & Urban Affairs (Apr. 3, 2008), available at http://federalreserve.gov/ newsevents/testimony/bernanke20080403a.htm. 87 For purposes of this Note, the discount window is best understood as a lending mechanism which helps the central bank “ensure the basic stability of the payment system . . . by supplying liquidity during times of systemic stress.” The Federal Reserve Discount Window, http://www.frbdiscountwindow.org/discountwindowbook.cfm?hdrID=14&dtlID=43#introduction (last visited Nov. 16, 2009). 88 See Cecchetti, supra note 41, at 17. 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 661 89 loan. “By any measure, this action was extraordinary,” as the New York Fed provided Bear with approximately $12.9 billion, a move not seen since the Great Depression.90 The twenty-eight day government guarantee was greeted with “high-fives” and cheers among Bear executives, who believed that the term of the loan would allow them enough time to find a private buyer for their firm.91 To the contrary, news of the loan was not nearly as welcomed by Bear’s counterparties, or the market as a whole, as Friday saw Bear’s common stock close down forty-seven percent, and the major ratings agencies (Standard & Poor’s, Moody’s, and Fitch) drastically downgraded Bear’s long- and short-term credit ratings.92 Based on these developments, then-Secretary Paulson realized the loan was not a viable solution and contacted Mr. Schwartz that same evening,93 informing the CEO that the Fed-backed liquidity “would not be available on Monday morning.”94 Suddenly, twenty-eight days became two, as Paulson told Schwartz “[he] need[ed] to have a deal by Sunday night.”95 With most of Bear’s customers and clients abandoning ship, there seemed to be only one likely suitor: JPMorgan. D. Shotgun Marriage Made in Heaven Saturday morning, March 15, Mr. Schwartz together with senior management of Bear Stearns met with their counterparts at JPMorgan and J.C. Flowers & Co. (“JCFlowers”) to discuss the potential for mergers or acquisitions.96 Throughout the day and into the evening, Bear’s leadership attempted to negotiate a realistic proposal that could be finalized by late Sunday evening before the open of Asian and European markets.97 At the same time, Bear’s legal team again began to analyze potential bankruptcy and/or liquidation scenarios, mindful of the limited protections available to the firm under the United States Bankruptcy Code, as well as the approaching Sunday deadline.98 Negotiations continued into early Sunday morning, March 16. However, it soon became apparent that a purely private sector solution would not be possible. JPMorgan reported that “it would need some level of financial support from the New York Fed” to undertake a Bear Stearns 89 See Kelly et al., supra note 6. Cecchetti, supra note 41, at 17. See Sluis et al., supra note 75. 92 JPMorgan, supra note 64, at 28. 93 See Kelly, supra note 16. 94 JPMorgan, supra note 64, at 29. 95 Kelly, supra note 16. 96 JPMorgan, supra note 64, at 29. 97 See Kelly, supra note 16 (providing detailed documentation of the negotiations as they unfolded on March 15). 98 See id. (noting that Bear’s status as a broker would present serious limitations and risks in any type of bankruptcy filing). 90 91 662 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 acquisition, and JCFlowers was having difficulty finding institutions to finance any type of transaction with Bear Stearns.99 As such, officials from the New York Fed were advised of the situation and “indicated that [they] would be willing to consider the possibility of an arrangement that would result in the New York Fed assuming some of the risk associated with” a JPMorgan takeover.100 Initially, the Fed agreed to provide $30 billion of “non-recourse funding”101 to JPMorgan secured by collateral consisting mainly of risky MBS and other assets that Bear owned.102 This liquidity infusion would enable JPMorgan to acquire Bear and immediately guarantee its outstanding debts to remaining counterparties and customers—a vital factor in returning trust to the shaken global markets.103 Armed with this taxpayer-based guarantee, JPMorgan approached Bear’s board of directors with a finalized stock merger agreement in which Bear’s common stock would be exchanged for JPMorgan common stock for $2 per share (the “original offer”).104 As a company that had a pershare value of approximately $171 in January 2007,105 the original offer did not sit well with Bear’s board, which voiced its disagreement and worried that acceptance would constitute a breach of their fiduciary duty to stockholders.106 Nevertheless, the fear of imminent bankruptcy coupled with the fact that no other solution was feasible (and increased pressure from the government) led to an endorsement by Bear’s board of the original offer, with the transaction announced in a joint press release Sunday evening.107 Before the original offer could be presented to Bear’s shareholders for 99 JPMorgan, supra note 64, at 30. Id. at 31. A non-recourse loan is one in which the Fed would not be able to raise a legal claim against JPMorgan in the event the loan was not repaid and the Fed lost money. See MARC LABONTE, CONG. RES. SERV., FINANCIAL TURMOIL: FEDERAL RESERVE POLICY RESPONSES 7 (2008), available at http://assets.opencrs.com/rpts/RL34427_20080407.pdf. 102 See JPMorgan, supra note 64, at 31. 103 See id. (“[B]ased on the New York Fed’s willingness to provide the $30 billion special funding facility, JPMorgan Chase thought that it would be able to work towards negotiating a stock-for-stock merger with Bear Stearns . . . with the need to guaranty certain obligations . . . effective immediately.”). 104 Id. 105 See Madlen Read & Joe Bel Bruno, Bear Stearns Shareholders OK Buyout by JPMorgan, USA TODAY, May 29, 2008, http://www.usatoday.com/money/economy/2008-05-29-3197519795_ x.htm. 106 See JPMorgan, supra note 64, at 31–32 (“Bear Stearns registered its objections to [the original offer and] . . . [r]epresentatives of Bear Stearns’ legal advisors reviewed the fiduciary duties of the board of directors, including the duties of directors if a company is insolvent or approaching insolvency.”). Following the eventual endorsement of the merger, numerous “class action lawsuits [were] filed against Bear Stearns, its board of directors and certain of Bear Stearns’ present and former executive officers” alleging, inter alia, breach of fiduciary duty. Id. at 48–49. 107 See id. at 33 (“[T]he Bear Stearns board of directors unanimously approved the agreement . . . . Later that evening, JPMorgan Chase and Bear Stearns issued a joint press release announcing the transaction.”); see also Holman W. Jenkins, Jr., The Short, Happy Death of Bear, WALL ST. J., Mar. 26, 2008, at A14 (“[The Fed] had plenty of legitimate clout, which it apparently used to virtually dictate the original $2 share price.”). 100 101 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 663 approval, “perceived deficiencies” and market reaction concerning the merger’s closure would necessitate amendments.108 With the immediate concern of bankruptcy pacified, Bear Stearns and JPMorgan executives met throughout the week of March 17 to discuss merger revisions that would be more acceptable to Bear’s shareholders and market speculation.109 By week’s end, no revised agreement had been reached, and for a third time Bear’s legal team met to discuss the possibility that the firm would have to file for bankruptcy on Monday, March 24.110 Anxiety increased among Bear’s creditors that the merger would fall through given the low offer proposed, with tense negotiations occurring back and forth between Bear’s and JPMorgan’s legal offices.111 “At one point, J.P. Morgan threatened to pull financing . . . [and Bear’s] directors talked briefly about suing J.P. Morgan[,] . . . [b]ut they quickly realized their position was untenable.”112 Finally, by Monday, March 24, the parties reached a provisional agreement to amend the original offer.113 Most importantly, the new merger agreement appealed to investors and market confidence by increasing the stock transfer rate from $2 to $10, and obligated JPMorgan to assume the first $1 billion in losses as deducted from the $30 billion guarantee to be provided by the New York Fed.114 For many, a crisis had been averted, but at what cost?115 By pledging $29 billion of hard-earned taxpayer money through its discount window to an investment bank foiled by bad decisions,116 the Fed’s actions set a 108 See JPMorgan, supra note 64, at 33 (describing how market reactions to the original offer prompted JPMorgan and Bear executives to enter into revised transaction negotiations). 109 Id. 110 See id. at 34 (“[I]f the New York Fed and JPMorgan Chase were unwilling to maintain their funding of Bear Stearns . . . [Bear] would not be able to open for business on Monday . . . .”). 111 See id. (“[R]epresentatives of Bear Stearns contacted JPMorgan Chase’s counsel . . . to notify JPMorgan Chase that its proposal, as presently formulated, was not acceptable to the Bear Stearns board . . . .”). 112 Kelly, supra note 16. 113 See JPMorgan, supra note 64, at 34–35. 114 See id. at 35–36 (outlining the terms of the new merger agreement). “This means that if the value of the assets [accepted by the Fed] turn out to be less than $29 billion, the [Fed] would suffer a loss.” Cecchetti, supra note 41, at 18. Since the time the Fed accepted these assets as collateral for the loan to October of 2008, taxpayers lost approximately $2.2 billion dollars, based on the ongoing deterioration of mortgage values. Editorial, The Fed Takes a Writedown, WALL ST. J., Oct. 28, 2008, at A16. 115 Given the ongoing corrosion of key markets, the total loss that will be suffered by taxpayers as a result of the Bear Stearns bailout remains to be seen. “[I]n October, six months after taking on $29 billion from investment bank Bear Stearns’ loan portfolio, the Fed decided to write down $2 billion of the holdings.” Jon Hilsenrath, Bernanke’s Fed, Echoing FDR, Pursues Ideas and Action, WALL ST. J., Dec. 15, 2008, at A2. 116 See Jenkins, supra note 107 (“Opening up its loan window to investment banks, and through them to their hedge fund clients, [the Fed] has alleviated the fear of fire sales of mortgage assets.”). For an interesting historical account of the creation and use of the Fed’s discount window, see Anna J. Schwartz, The Misuse of the Fed’s Discount Window (Apr. 9, 1992), in FED. RESERVE BANK OF ST. LOUIS REV., Sept./Oct. 1992, at 60–63, available at http://research.stlouisfed.org/publications/review/ 92/09/Misuse_Sep_Oct1992.pdf. 664 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 precedent that risky investors who were “too big to fail” would be saved from their own self-perpetuated demise.117 Soon after the bailout, critics denigrated the Fed’s actions as uncharacteristic of a capitalist society,118 while others used the event as a catalyst to launch attacks against the broader financial regulatory system.119 Now that the Fed is willing to use its resources to save private investment firms whose bankruptcy could harm the entire economy, what new types of regulation should such businesses be subject to? “As the Bear Stearns episode illustrates, some of the modern-day financial institutions that are too big to fail are not depository institutions that fall under the strict regulatory umbrella that accompanies membership in the Federal Reserve System.”120 The remainder of this Note analyzes the legal authority available to the Fed during the Bear Stearns collapse, why this authority has been criticized as deficient, and how scholarly review of twenty-first century financial threats may lead to the revision and modification of twentieth-century financial regulation. III. AN “UNUSUAL AND EXIGENT” LENDER OF LAST RESORT A. Too Big to Fail “Legally, the Fed can extend virtually unlimited support to our financial system,”121 and since the 1930s the Fed has had the authority to issue direct loans to private businesses through its discount window.122 Nonetheless, before the Bear Stearns predicament, the Fed traditionally reserved discount window loans for those institutions that were subject to the Fed’s strict supervisory protocol, namely, heavily regulated depository 117 Crittenden & Eckblad, supra note 4; see also LABONTE, supra note 101, at 12 (“Institutions that are too big to fail are ones that are deemed to be big enough that their failure could create systemic risk, the risk that the financial system as a whole would cease to function smoothly.”). The problem of encouraging risky behavior by bailing out failing institutions is commonly referred to as “moral hazard.” See id. at 11. 118 See, e.g., Gary S. Becker, We’re Not Headed for a Depression, WALL ST. J., Oct. 7, 2008, at A27 (“The ‘too big to fail’ approach to banks and other companies should be abandoned as new longterm financial policies are developed. Such an approach is inconsistent with a free-market economy.”). 119 See, e.g., Bernanke, Kansas City, supra note 11 (criticizing the regulatory framework of the American financial system as inefficient for being ambiguous in its legal mandates); see also William Neikirk et al., Call Grows for Tough Financial Regulation; Candidates, Congress Consider Intervening in Banking, Markets, CHI. TRIB., Mar. 28, 2008, at C1 (“Political fervor is growing for a broad re-regulation of America’s financial markets after a major credit crunch pummeled Wall Street and Main Street, sent the economy sinking and threatened a market meltdown.”). 120 LABONTE, supra note 101, at 12. 121 Altman, supra note 15. 122 See LABONTE, supra note 101, at 3–4 (discussing the use of the Fed’s discount window in the past). The statutory authority for the Fed’s discount window lending is provided for in section 10(b) of the Federal Reserve Act, which provides that “[a]ny Federal Reserve bank . . . may make advances to any member bank on its time or demand notes having maturities of not more than four months and which are secured to the satisfaction of such Federal Reserve bank.” Federal Reserve Act, 12 U.S.C. § 347b(a) (2006). 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 665 123 institutions. In essence, “[i]n exchange for putting up with regulation from the Fed and requirements over how much capital they can hold, [commercial] banks have access to the ‘discount window,’ at which they can borrow emergency cash in exchange for sound collateral.”124 However, despite its seemingly limitless potential to rescue ailing businesses, the discount window has long been a secondary tool of the Fed in altering market operations,125 and even those firms which could access the Fed’s window in the past have rarely done so for a couple of reasons. First, from the government’s perspective, the Fed has likely been hesitant to issue loans because each time it does so a precedent is established that compounds moral hazard, or the tendency of market participants to engage in risky behavior irrespective of the consequences given the potential for a public rescue.126 Second, when a private enterprise looks to the Fed’s discount window for a loan, it usually means the government is the last resort for the company, which in turn demonstrates weakness to the greater market.127 Thus, as a corollary of both government and private reluctance, rarely would one see the full extent of the Fed’s lending power in action.128 But, what happens when one business’s failure threatens the larger economy the Fed is obligated to protect, as Bear Stearns’s bankruptcy did? Similarly, how can the Fed respond to a systemic threat from an institution not subject to its “regulatory regime?” The answer to these questions lies in a little known provision of the Federal Reserve Act. In such circumstances, the Fed can call on emergency lending authority to protect the larger financial system, and in doing so provide liquidity to any 123 See Greg Ip et al., Stronger Steps: Fed Offers Banks Loans to Ease Credit Crisis, WALL ST. J., Aug. 18, 2007, at A1 (“[T]he discount window’s reach in the current crisis is limited by the fact that only [commercial] banks can use it, and they aren’t the ones facing the greatest stains. Rather the strains are being felt by nonbanks . . . .”). 124 Neil Irwin, Fed Leaders Ponder an Expanded Mission; Wall Street Bailout Could Forever Alter Role of Central Bank, WASH. POST, Mar. 28, 2008, at A01. 125 See LABONTE, supra note 101, at 4 (“The Fed’s main policy tool shifted from the discount window to open market operations several decades ago.”). 126 See Ben S. Bernanke, Chairman of the Bd. of Governors of the Fed. Reserve, Speech at the Federal Reserve Bank of Atlanta Financial Markets Conference: Liquidity Provision by the Federal Reserve (May 13, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/ bernanke20080513.htm [hereinafter Bernanke, Atlanta I]. Chairman Bernanke stated: A central bank that is too quick to act as liquidity provider of last resort risks inducing moral hazard; specifically, if market participants come to believe that the Federal Reserve or other central banks will take such measures whenever financial stress develops, financial institutions and their creditors would have less incentive to pursue suitable strategies for managing liquidity risk and more incentive to take such risks. Id.; see also Cassandra Jones Havard, “Goin’ Round in Circles” . . . and Letting the Bad Loans Win: When Subprime Lending Fails Borrowers: The Need for Uniform Broker Regulation, 86 NEB. L. REV. 737, 752–54 (2008) (explaining moral hazard in the context of the mortgage crisis). 127 See Ip et al., supra note 123 (“[The discount window] is little used because it generally carries a stigma, since it is seen as a struggling bank’s last resort.”). 128 Cf. Nelson D. Schwartz, A History of Public Aid During Crises, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 7, 2008, at A27 (noting government’s past intervention in the private market during periods of financial crisis). 666 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 129 institution, not just those within its regulatory reach. It is this emergency authority that gives credence to the Fed’s characterization as “lender of last resort.”130 And it is precisely this use of the Fed’s emergency authority to rescue Bear Stearns that has incited reconsideration of the Fed’s regulation of investment banks—the argument being that if firms can get public money, they should be subject to heightened public oversight by the agency lending that money.131 The specific legal provision authorizing emergency lending to private enterprises is section 13(3) of the Federal Reserve Act.132 That section provides in pertinent part: 3. Discounts for Individuals, Partnerships, and Corporations. In unusual and exigent circumstances, the Federal Reserve Board, by the affirmative vote of not less than five members, may authorize any Federal reserve bank, during such periods as the said board may determine, . . . to discount for any individual, partnership or corporation, notes, drafts, and bills of exchange when such notes, drafts, and bills of exchange are indorsed or otherwise secured to the satisfaction of the Federal Reserve bank.133 129 See LABONTE, supra note 101, at 1 (“Lending to non-members requires emergency statutory authority that has not been used in more than 70 years.” (citation omitted)). 130 Id. at 2; see also Frederic S. Mishkin, Gov. of the Bd. of the Fed. Reserve, Speech at the Caesarea Forum of the Israel Democracy Institute: Global Financial Turmoil and the World Economy (July 2, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/mishkin20080702a.htm (“[I]t is critical that the Federal Reserve acts as lender of last resort when financial stability is threatened . . . .”). 131 See, e.g., Donald L. Kohn, Vice Chairman of the Bd. of the Fed. Reserve, Speech at the Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond’s Credit Market Symposium (Apr. 17, 2008), available at http://federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/kohn20080417a.htm (“[I]n my view greater regulatory attention will need to be devoted to the liquidity risk-management policies and practices of major investment banks.”). 132 Federal Reserve Act, 12 U.S.C. § 343 (2006). 133 Id. § 343 (emphasis added). Interestingly, in Bear’s case, “[t]he required number of five members of the Board of Governors was not present on the day in question. One of them was out of town and ratified the vote when he returned, but the first loan was already in motion.” Walker F. Todd, The Bear Stearns Rescue and Emergency Credit for Investment Banks, AIER, Aug. 11, 2008, http://www.aier.org/research/commentaries/445-the-bear-stearns-rescue-and-emergency-credit-forinvesmtn-banks. The legal authority allowing for votes of less than five members of the Board of Governors is provided for by section 11(r)(2)(A)(ii)(I)–(IV) of the Federal Reserve Act, which mandates: A. Any action that the Board is otherwise authorized to take under Section 13(3) may be taken upon the unanimous vote of all available members then in office, if: I. unusual and exigent circumstances exist and the borrower is unable to secure adequate credit accommodations from other sources; II. action on the matter is necessary to prevent, correct, or mitigate serious harm to the economy or the stability of the financial system of the United States; III. despite the use of all means available (including all available telephonic, telegraphic, and other electronic means), the other members of the Board 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 667 Originally enacted in 1932, the law was an outgrowth of the bank failures of the early twentieth century and has been used in different contexts over its seventy-seven-year history, albeit never in the same manner as in the Bear Stearns case.134 Aside from the requirement that five governors vote to approve a loan under section 13(3), the provision has few limitations in terms of the amount that can be lent, or the means by which the Fed can do so. The condition that collateral be offered “to the satisfaction of the Federal Reserve bank,” is contingent upon a plethora of extrinsic considerations (including systemic risk) that at times may seem inconsistent.135 For example, some have criticized the Fed for accepting the collateral pledged by Bear Stearns or American International Group (“AIG”) under section 13(3),136 while Lehman Bros. (“Lehman”) was allowed to go into bankruptcy.137 Also, discount window lending is usually secured through collateral possessing a good credit rating, which was certainly not the case in the loans made to Bear Stearns.138 have not been able to be contacted on the matter; and IV. action on the matter is required before the number of Board members otherwise required to vote on the matter can be contacted through any available means (including all available telephonic, telegraphic, and other electronic means) . . . . Federal Reserve Act, 12 U.S.C. § 248(r) (2006); see also Minutes of the Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System 2–3 (Mar. 14, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/ newsevents/press/other/other20080627a1.pdf (documenting the Board’s vote with regard to factors specified by section 11(r)(2)(A)(ii)). 134 See Fettig, supra note 8, at 15–19, 44–47 (describing the historical evolution of section 13(3)); Fettig, supra note 4, at 34 (providing a concise timeline of the development of section 13(3) from 1932 to present). 135 12 U.S.C. § 343 (2006). 136 See Press Release, Fed. Reserve (Sept. 16, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/ newsevents/press/other/20080916a.htm (“The Federal Reserve Board . . . authorized the Federal Reserve bank of New York to lend up to $85 billion to [AIG] under section 13(3) of the Federal Reserve Act.”). 137 See Adam Shell et al., No White Knight Emerges to Rescue Lehman Bros., USA TODAY, Sept. 15, 2008, at 1B (“The failure to get a Lehman deal was due largely to the federal government’s refusal to provide interested buyers such as Barclays with the kind of support that JPMorgan Chase received when it bought troubled investment bank Bear Stearns in March.”); Sale Possible as Lehman Sits on Brink, CHI. TRIB., Sept. 11, 2008, at C1 (“Compounding anxiety is that Lehman, unlike smaller rival Bear Stearns, might not be able to count on a lifeline from the government.”). 138 Technically, Federal Reserve Banks may only provide advances and discounts to individual institutions when such extensions of credit are “secured to the satisfaction of the Federal Reserve bank.” Federal Reserve Act, 12 U.S.C. §§ 343, 347b(a) (2006). For purposes of discount window lending, the collateral being pledged by borrowers must “meet regulatory standards for sound asset quality,” meaning that assets held by solvent, yet illiquid institutions, will generally be adequate to meet the satisfaction standard of the Federal Reserve Act. Federal Reserve Discount Window, Frequently Asked Questions, http://www.frbdiscountwindow.org/cfaq.cfm?hdrID=14&dtlID=89 (last visited Nov. 16, 2009). However, although MBS and SMBS are nominally acceptable as discount window collateral, it is hard to see how the toxicity of Bear’s MBS assets would satisfy Federal Bank officials, especially when one considers the state of Bear’s financial health during the Fed rescue. See Federal Reserve Discount Window General Information, http://www.frbdiscountwindow.org/ discountwindowbook.cfm?hdrID=14&dtlID=43#introduction (last visited Nov. 16, 2009) (noting that “[t]he financial condition of an institution may be considered” when evaluating whether, and to what 668 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 Nonetheless, section 13(3) was used three times by the Fed in March 2008, initially as a means of preventing Bear Stearns’s imminent default and arranging the JPMorgan acquisition, and subsequently to create a new lending facility specifically for the large institutions the Fed conducts daily transactions with.139 Interestingly, it is this last use that demonstrates the Fed’s challenges in responding to emergency situations of a systemic nature. For if the only means by which the Fed can save institutions—by issuing direct loans—is the same mechanism scorned by the market as a sign of weakness, troubled institutions may hesitate to use the discount window during a financial crisis.140 Thus, to counteract the stigma associated with the discount window, the Fed created new lending mechanisms—including the Term Auction Facility, the Term Securities Lending Facility, and the Primary Dealer Credit Facility—in anticipation of the need for heightened borrowing, which has since reached astronomical levels.141 Given this deficiency, “Fed officials believe[] the [current economic] problems require[] more than what a central bank was designed to do—provide emergency loans to healthy institutions in tumultuous times.”142 And yet, stretching the Fed’s loan capacity was not the only uncharacteristic action taken by the Fed in the Bear Stearns case—an even more controversial move was the manner in which the Fed brokered the JPMorgan takeover. B. Sweetening the Deal143 As previously noted, when the Fed issued the $29 billion loan pursuant to section 13(3) of the Federal Reserve Act to arrange for JPMorgan’s acquisition of Bear Stearns, the funds were first filtered to JPMorgan then extent, a Federal Reserve bank will issue extensions of credit through the discount window). Of course, this issue adds to the controversial nature of the Bear Stearns bailout. 139 See Bernanke, Atlanta I, supra note 126 (detailing use of the Fed’s emergency lending authority in each circumstance). 140 See LABONTE, supra note 101, at 4–5 (“Ironically, this means that although the Fed encourages discount window borrowing so that banks can avoid liquidity problems, banks are hesitant to turn to the Fed because of fears that doing so would spark a crisis of confidence.”). 141 See Cecchetti, supra note 41, at 19–20 (noting that as of May 2008, the Fed had nearly $180 billion worth of loans as compared to a total of $190 million only nine months earlier). There is some indication that borrowing and lending from the Fed by both commercial and investment banks has decreased early in 2009—this could be the result of investor pressures seeking bank independence without government support. See Prabha Natarajan & Brian Blackstone, Mortgage-Bond Purchases Start Strong—Fed’s Various Efforts to Bolster Markets Are Ballooning Its Balance Sheet, WALL ST. J., Jan. 9, 2009, at C3 (“Borrowing through the Fed’s discount window by commercial banks . . . fell about $10 billion [in the first week of January, while] [l]ending through the Fed’s [PDCF] . . . fell [$3 billion] . . . .”). 142 Jon Hilsenrath et al., Crisis Mode: Paulson, Bernanke Strained for Consensus in Bailout, WALL ST. J., Nov. 10, 2008, at A1 (emphasis added). 143 This section focuses primarily on the Fed’s use of emergency lending authority and other legal tools to arrange the eventual takeover of Bear Stearns by JPMorgan. As such, the discussion focuses on the legal authority involved in the merger, not other contexts. 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 669 144 used to secure Bear’s debts and take over Bear’s operations. Aside from exercising emergency authority to distribute the loan in the first place, the Fed also had to exempt JPMorgan from another provision of the Federal Reserve Act, which is designed to prohibit the very type of transaction the Bear Stearns deal involved.145 The provision in question is section 23A of the Federal Reserve Act, which provides: Restrictions on Transactions with Affiliates 1. A member bank and its subsidiaries may engage in a covered transaction with an affiliate only if: A. in the case of any affiliate, the aggregate amount of covered transactions of the member bank and its subsidiaries will not exceed 10 per centum of the capital stock and surplus of the member bank; and B. in the case of all affiliates, the aggregate amount of covered transactions of the member bank and its subsidiaries will not exceed 20 per centum of the capital stock and surplus of the member bank.146 Section 23A is designed to limit the extent of covered transactions, including loans, extensions of credit, or the purchase of securities, which member banks,147 such as JPMorgan, enter into with affiliate institutions— in this case a wholly-owned subsidiary formed solely for the purpose of acquiring Bear Stearns.148 Additionally, section 23A “limit[s] the ability of 144 See supra Part II.D. JPMorgan actually formed a wholly-owned subsidiary “solely for the purpose of consummating the merger.” JPMorgan, supra note 64, at 25. 145 See 12 U.S.C. § 371c(a)(1)A–B (2006); Letter from Robert deV. Frierson, Deputy Sec’y of the Bd. of the Fed. Reserve, to Kathryn V. McCulloch, Senior V.P. & Assoc. Gen. Counsel of JPMorgan Chase & Co. (July 1, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/boarddocs/legalint/ federalreserveact/2008/20080701/20080701.pdf (authorizing exemptions from provisions of the Federal Reserve to allow JPMorgan to finalize the acquisition of Bear Stearns); Letter from Robert de V. Frierson, Deputy Sec’y of the Bd. of the Fed. Reserve, to Kathleen A. Juhase, Senior V.P. & Assoc. Gen. Counsel of JPMorgan Chase & Co. (Aug. 20, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/ BOARDDOCS/LegalInt/FederalReserveAct/2007/20070820c/20070820c.pdf (approving initial exemptions from the Federal Reserve Act authorizing JPMorgan to finance Bear’s daily operations). 146 12 U.S.C. § 371c(a)(1)A–B. Near identical restrictions apply pursuant to the Federal Reserve Board’s Regulation W, as codified in 12 C.F.R. § 223.11 (2009) and 12 C.F.R. § 223.12 (2009), which limit the aggregate amounts of transactions between member banks and single or multiple affiliates. 147 The term “member bank” refers to depository firms which are members of the Federal Reserve System. See Transactions Between Member Banks and Their Affiliates, 67 Fed. Reg. 76,560, 76,560 (Dec. 12, 2002). 148 Under section 23A, “covered transactions,” include “loan[s] or extension[s] of credit to . . . affiliate[s] . . . [and the] purchase of assets . . . from [affiliates].” 12 U.S.C. § 371c(b)(7)(A)(C). An “affiliate” includes “any company that controls the member bank and any other company that is controlled by the company that controls the member bank.” Id. § 371c(b)(1)(A). When JPMorgan acquired Bear Stearns, it formed a wholly-owned subsidiary “solely for the purpose of consummating 670 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 a member bank to transfer its Federal subsidy to affiliates,” precluding non-member banks from accessing the Fed’s safety net.149 The intention of the law “is to prevent problems at the affiliate from endangering the [member] bank’s depositors.”150 Exemptions from these restrictions can only be granted by the Federal Reserve Board when found to be in the “public interest and consistent with the purposes of” section 23A.151 As section 23A limits the “aggregate amount of covered transactions” that a member bank and an affiliate may engage in, the statute presented an impediment for Fed officials seeking to arrange the JPMorgan purchase of Bear in late March 2008. Specifically, the statute would expressly prohibit JPMorgan (as a member bank) from taking over Bear, because the $29 billion “extension of credit” that the arrangement involved was a “covered transaction” exceeding “20 per centum of the capital stock and surplus” of JPMorgan.152 Thus, if the purchase of Bear was to be consummated as planned, the transaction would be illegal and void under the Federal Reserve Act.153 This dilemma necessitated the utilization of an authorized exemption from the Federal Reserve Board to ensure that Bear’s bankruptcy could be avoided in a legitimate manner.154 When JPMorgan first agreed to acquire Bear Stearns on March 16, 2008, the Fed granted a temporary (eighteen-month) 23A exemption so that JPMorgan would be able to “finance the operations of Bear Stearns” and guarantee its outstanding debts.155 This initial exemption allowed JPMorgan to enter into transactions with Bear Stearns and its customers in aggregate amounts of up to fifty percent of JPMorgan’s “capital stock and surplus for the second quarter of 2008 (approximately $58 billion).”156 Subsequently, three months after the initial temporary exemption was granted, on July 1, 2008, the Federal Reserve Board again suspended the application of section 23A, allowing JPMorgan to complete the purchase the merger,” which would trigger the application of section 23A of the Federal Reserve Act. JPMorgan, supra note 64, at 25. 149 Transactions Between Member Banks and Their Affiliates, 67 Fed. Reg. at 76,560; see also PATRICIA A. MCCOY, BANKING LAW MANUAL, FEDERAL REGULATION OF FINANCIAL HOLDING COMPANIES § 6.05 (2d ed. 2002) (explaining the scope and purposes of sections 23A and 23B of the Federal Reserve Act). 150 Brian Blackstone, Fed Agrees to Ease Some Rules for J.P. Morgan, WALL ST. J., Apr. 5, 2008, at A2. 151 12 U.S.C. § 371c(f)(2). The purposes of section 23A have been declared by the Board as being two-fold: “(i) to protect against a deposit institution suffering losses in transactions with affiliates and (ii) to limit the ability of a deposit institution to transfer to its affiliates the subsidy arising from the institution’s access to the Federal safety net.” Letter from Robert deV. Frierson to Kathryn McCulloch, supra note 145, at 3 (citation omitted). 152 12 U.S.C. § 371c(a)(1)(B). 153 Id. 154 See Letter from Robert deV. Frierson to Kathleen Juhase, supra note 145, at 1–5 (granting and explaining the exemption from section 23A and setting conditions on the authorized transaction). 155 Letter from Robert deV. Frierson to Kathryn McCulloch, supra note 145, at 6. 156 Id. 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 671 157 of Bear Stearns’s assets for “approximately $44 billion.” In doing so, the Fed reduced the original March 16 aggregate ceiling to $5 billion, and declared the initial exemption void as of October 1, 2008.158 In both instances, the Fed justified its actions in granting 23A exemptions based on past practices,159 and in allowing JPMorgan to complete the purchase of Bear Stearns, the Fed argued that the terms of the acquisition were substantially similar to those that would exist for “comparable transactions with unaffiliated companies,” as otherwise required by federal law.160 While these rationales may be valid, it remains unsettling that the Fed suspended enforcement of section 23A to permit the very type of transaction the law was enacted to prohibit.161 Most importantly, concerns surround the potential losses JPMorgan (and in turn its depositors) were exposed to during the Bear Stearns transactions, a primary issue that the enactors of section 23A meant to protect against.162 “In effect, [these] 23A exemption[s] signaled the Federal Reserve’s willingness to allow troubled investment banks to shift their bad assets to insured commercial banks and thereby expose the Deposit Insurance Fund and U.S. taxpayers to a heightened risk of loss.”163 Additionally, by forwarding a federal subsidy through a member bank to Bear Stearns (a non-member institution) the Fed endorsed a collateralized transaction inconsistent with the underlying policy of “safe and sound banking practices,”164 and specifically restricted by the Federal Reserve Act.165 The highly controversial nature of the Fed’s manipulation of its legal authority in these circumstances has led to internal disputes among 157 Id. at 3. Id. at 6. 159 See id. at 3 (“The Board routinely has approved exemptions . . . for one-time asset transfers that are part of a corporate reorganization and that are structured to ensure the quality of the transferred assets. The Board also has routinely approved exemptions . . . to facilitate the integration of recently merged companies.” (internal citations omitted)). 160 See id. at 5 (“Section 23B [of the Federal Reserve Act] requires that the [JPMorgan acquisition] be on terms that are substantially the same, or at least as favorable to [JPMorgan], as those prevailing at the time for comparable transactions with unaffiliated companies.” (citation omitted)). Restrictions On Transactions with Affiliates. 1. A member bank and its subsidiaries may engage in any of the transactions described in paragraph (2) only— A. on terms and under circumstances, including credit standards, that are substantially the same, or at least as favorable to such bank or its subsidiary, as those prevailing at the time for comparable transactions with or involving other nonaffiliated companies . . . . 12 U.S.C. § 371c-1(a)(1)(A) (2006). 161 See Transaction Between Members Banks and Their Affiliates, 67 Fed. Reg. 76,560, 76,560– 62 (Dec. 12, 2002). 162 See id. at 76,560 (“Sections 23A and 23B of the Federal Reserve Act are important statutory provisions designed to protect against a depository institution suffering losses in transactions with affiliates.”). 163 MCCOY, supra note 149. 164 See 12 U.S.C. § 371c(a)(4). 165 See id. § 371c(c)(3). 158 672 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 government officials as to the extent of the Central Bank’s power to manage financial crises.166 Ideologically, the Fed’s conduct during the Bear Stearns bailout signals a policy shift at the Central Bank that embraces government intervention in preventing the failure of private firms, a strategy unlike the traditional models which allowed for market correction, limited government involvement, and ultimately private failures and bankruptcies. In turn, by becoming more involved in preventing the failure of private firms, the Fed has inherently increased the scope of its marketplace oversight—a result accomplished indirectly through the creation of new facilities and mechanisms implemented to protect ailing institutions. These new facilities, coupled with the modification of existing tools, have become the foundation for a new Central Bank that is progressively intervening more deeply into the market, yet limited by legal authority devised for the twentieth century. C. The Offspring of Emergency Early indications of the Fed’s expanding presence in the financial markets can be traced back to the week leading up to the bailout of Bear Stearns. Mindful of the stigma attached to discount window borrowing, the Fed sought to stimulate lending in mid-March 2008 by relying on a supplementary loan tool initially developed in December 2007, known as the Term Auction Facility (“TAF”).167 Unlike the typical overnight lending done through the discount window, the TAF provides loans with longer maturity terms (such as twenty-eight days),168 and “[t]he TAF allows the Fed to determine the amount of reserves it wishes to lend out, based on market conditions.”169 TAF loans can be collateralized using the same types of assets accepted at the discount window (including MBS),170 but the amounts offered through the TAF “have greatly exceeded discount window lending.”171 For example, on March 7, 2008, the Fed announced it would increase the amounts outstanding in the TAF to $100 billion, and declared that the two auctions to be held in that month would be extended to $50 billion, 166 See Hilsenrath et al., supra note 142 (detailing frequent disagreements between former Treasury Secretary Paulson and Fed Chairman Bernanke over proper scope of Fed authority to respond to systemic threats to the economy). 167 See Charles T. Carlstrom & Sarah Wakefield, The Funds Rate, Liquidity, and the Term Auction Facility, ECON. TRENDS, Dec. 2007, at 5, 6, available at http://www.clevelandfed.org/research/ trends/2007/1207/ET_dec07.pdf (“One of the major changes for the Federal Reserve [in December 2007] . . . was the institution of a ‘term auction facility’ (TAF) to supplement regular discount window borrowing.”). 168 LABONTE, supra note 101, at 5. 169 Id. 170 See id. (“Like discount window lending, TAF loans must be fully collateralized with the same qualifying collateral [accepted at the discount window].”). 171 Id. 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 673 $20 billion more than previously offered in February 2008.172 Additionally, the Fed assumes the risk associated with a decline in the value of the collateral posted by private institutions in return for TAF loans, and questions have arisen as to whether this once temporary program will become permanent following reevaluation, albeit with reduced auction amounts.173 Because the funds distributed by the Fed through the TAF reflect market needs and anticipated demand for assistance, the TAF is a more controlled platform for lending as compared to the traditional discount window.174 In the fourth quarter of 2008, TAF lending and term limits had been extended to as much as $150 billion and eighty-five days respectively175—figures representative of the popularity (or necessity) of the TAF during the current financial crisis. Aside from the growing role of the TAF, “[o]n March 11, 2008, the Fed set up a more expansive securities lending program for the primary dealers called the Term Securities Lending Facility” (the “TSLF”).176 The TSLF allows the Fed to promote financial market operations by providing easy access to liquidity for those institutions the Fed regularly conducts transactions with and whose financial size and strength are directly related to the health of the financial system—the primary dealers.177 Lending through the TSLF can be in amounts of up to $200 billion in Treasury securities, for terms of twenty-eight days, and collateralized through a wide range of assets, including illiquid MBS.178 Initially, MBS collateral had to be AAA-rated; however, the Fed eventually broadened the types of eligible collateral to include “all investment-grade debt securities,” and changed TSLF auctions from biweekly to weekly in September 2008.179 The TSLF allows the largest financial institutions to regularly swap their unmarketable assets for easily marketable Treasury securities, which “is 172 See Press Release, Fed. Reserve (Mar. 7, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/ newsevents/press/monetary/20080307a.htm. 173 See LABONTE, supra note 101, at 5. 174 See id. (“Discount window lending is initiated at the behest of the requesting institution—the Fed has no control over how many requests for loans it receives.”). 175 Press Release, Fed. Reserve (Oct. 6, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/ newsevents/press/monetary/20081006b.htm. 176 LABONTE, supra note 101, at 6. 177 See id. at 6 (explaining TSLF operations and providing technical definition of primary dealers); Press Release, Fed. Reserve (Sept. 14, 2008), available at http://federalreserve.gov/ newsevents/press/monetary/20080914a.htm (explaining how the TSLF stimulates flow of liquidity between largest financial institutions). For a discussion of the role of primary dealers, see Marco Arnone & George Iden, Primary Dealers in Government Securities: Policy Issues and Selected Countries’ Experience 3–10 (IMF Working Paper No. 03/45, 2003), available at http://www.imf.org/external/pubs/ft/wp/2003/wp0345.pdf. 178 See Franklin Allen & Elena Carletti, The Role of Liquidity in Financial Crisis 6 (Sept. 4, 2008) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1268367. Treasury securities include Treasury notes, bonds, and bills, backed by the Federal Government and, as such, are very safe investments. U.S. Secs. & Exch. Comm’n, Treasury Securities, http://www.sec.gov/answers/treasuries.htm (last visited Nov. 16, 2009). 179 Press Release, Sept. 14, 2008, supra note 177. 674 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 intended to promote liquidity in the financing markets for Treasury and other collateral” and improve the overall performance of financial markets.180 Finally, following JPMorgan’s announced acquisition of Bear Stearns on March 16, 2008, the Fed launched yet another new lending tool designated the Primary Dealer Credit Facility (“PDCF”), which was designed to improve access to discount window-type loans to primary dealers.181 The PDCF was created pursuant to the emergency lending provisions of section 13(3) of the Federal Reserve Act, and “provides primary dealers with a liquidity backstop similar to the discount window for deposit institutions in generally sound financial condition.”182 Because many primary dealers, such as Bear Stearns, could not previously pledge their collateral for direct discount window loans from the Fed, the PDCF seems to have been the result of Fed frustration in attempting to work within its legal authority in loaning funds to non-member institutions. As with the TSLF, the PDCF initially required investment-grade securities as collateral for overnight or short-term loans; however, the Fed has subsequently broadened the acceptable PDCF collateral to include assets exchanged in repo markets.183 From its inception, the PDCF seems to have contributed to growing lending confidence among primary dealers and their counterparties, yet the very fact that the PDCF has been extended into 2009 suggests that market conditions remain abnormal.184 The Fed’s use of the TAF, TSLF, PDCF, and other facilities185 raises 180 LABONTE, supra note 101, at 6 (citation omitted). See Fed. Reserve Bank of N.Y., Primary Dealer Credit Facility, http://www.newyorkfed.org/ markets/pdcf.html (last visited Nov. 16, 2009) (“The . . . (PDCF) is an overnight loan facility that will provide funding to primary dealers in exchange for a specified range of eligible collateral that is intended to foster the functioning of financial markets more generally.”). 182 Bernanke, Atlanta I, supra note 126. 183 See Press Release, Sept. 14, 2008, supra note 177 (“The collateral eligible to be pledged at the Primary Dealer Credit Facility (PDCF) has been broadened to closely match the types of collateral that can be pledged in the tri-party repo systems of the two major clearing banks.”). 184 See Bernanke, Atlanta I, supra note 126 (discussing improvement in confidence among primary dealers and their counterparties and noting that despite improvement in confidence, financial markets “are still far from normal”); Press Release, Fed. Reserve (July 30, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/newsevents/press/monetary/20080730a.htm (announcing the Fed’s extension of the PDCF until January 30, 2009). 185 The Fed has developed numerous facilities, other than the ones previously described, in an ongoing effort to stimulate liquidity transfers in financial markets and promote confidence between counterparties. For example, in October 2008, the Fed created the Commercial Paper Funding Facility (“CPFF”), which provides a “liquidity backstop” to domestic providers of commercial paper by allowing the Fed to purchase “three-month unsecured and asset-backed commercial paper directly from eligible issuers.” Press Release, Fed. Reserve (Oct. 7, 2008), available at http://federalreserve.gov/ newsevents/press/monetary/20081007c.htm. Likewise, in late November 2008, the Fed instituted the Term Asset-Backed Securities Loan Facility (“TALF”), which allows the New York Fed to “lend up to $200 billion on a non-recourse basis to holders of certain AAA-rated ABS backed by newly and recently originated consumer and small business loans.” Press Release, Fed. Reserve (Nov. 25, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/monetarypolicy/20081125a.htm. The TALF is designed to 181 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 675 important questions about the expanding intervention of the federal government in our free market economy, as well as the threat to economic independence and innovation that the Fed’s growing presence poses. Similarly, skepticism as to the tools utilized by the Fed to combat ailing market operations emphasizes the concern that the Fed’s policy responses may indirectly promote moral hazard.186 These issues have incited a consensus that regulatory reform is overdue and will be a major undertaking of the Obama administration and the 111th Congress.187 IV. INADEQUACIES IMPAIRING INTERVENTION A. The Call for Regulatory Reform188 Four months after Bear Stearns was saved from bankruptcy, Fed Chairman Ben Bernanke testified before the House Committee on Financial Services to “discuss financial regulation and financial stability.”189 Using Bear Stearns as an example, Bernanke suggested that the current regulatory framework for the financial system was inadequately structured to respond to and remedy problems posed by contemporary investment banks and products.190 In particular, Bernanke explained that limited oversight of investment banking practices and sophisticated investment vehicles had contributed to the creation of a financial system more advanced than the laws that governed it.191 As in Bear Stearns’s case, private institutions (and the market as a whole) had evolved to the extent that a single firm’s failure could bring the entire system to its make it “easier for consumers to borrow money,” thus easing lending markets and stimulating growth. Deborah Solomon, New Facility Targets Consumer Lending, WALL ST. J., Nov. 25, 2008, at C1. 186 See Ben S. Bernanke, Chairman of the Bd. of the Fed. Reserve, Speech at the Greater Austin Chamber of Commerce: Federal Reserve Policies in the Financial Crisis (Dec. 1, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/bernanke20081201a.htm [hereinafter Bernanke, Austin] (“[I]ntervening to prevent the failure of a financial firm is counterproductive, because it leads to erosion of market discipline and creates moral hazard.”). 187 See id. (“In the longer term, the development of a statutory framework for resolving systemically critical nonbank financial institutions in ways that do not destabilize the financial system as a whole must be another key priority.”). 188 This section discusses the impetus for reform of the regulatory structure of the financial system within the narrow realm of the investment banking industry and the expanding role of the Federal Reserve as a central administrator. Therefore, consideration of broader regulatory reform that may be appropriate in other contexts (such as the mortgage industry) is beyond the scope of this Note. 189 Ben S. Bernanke, Chairman of the Bd. of the Fed. Reserve, Testimony Before the House Comm. on Fin. Servs. (July 10, 2008), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/newsevents/ testimony/bernanke20080710a.htm [hereinafter Bernanke, Fin. Servs.]. 190 See id. (“[I]n light of the Bear Stearns episode, Congress may wish to consider whether new tools are needed for ensuring an orderly liquidation of a systemically important securities firm that is on the verge of bankruptcy, together with a more formal process for deciding when to use those tools.”). 191 See id. (“Congress should consider granting the Federal Reserve explicit oversight authority for systemically important payment and settlement systems.”). 676 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW 192 [Vol. 42:647 193 knees. Known as “systemic risk,” the occurrence of this phenomenon necessarily prompts the intervention of the federal government.194 However, the nature of that intervention has come under intense scrutiny in the wake of Bear Stearns.195 Specifically, the scope of the Fed’s authority as lender of last resort during systemic crisis remains obscure in the context of nonbank institutions that traditionally were not subject to Fed oversight.196 “The decision to treat Bear Stearns as if it were a commercial bank appears to have marked a permanent shift in the governance of financial services firms.”197 Likewise, as Professor Steven Schwarcz of Duke University School of Law has noted, de facto bailouts of systemically important institutions facing bankruptcy focus merely on “symptoms of the disease . . . not on the disease’s underlying cause.”198 Thus, the Fed’s capacity to respond to financial distress appears constrained by both the lack of a robust supervisory mandate and a limited number of tools available to protect the nation’s economy.199 For example, although the Fed can issue emergency loans to nonbank financial institutions, “such loans must be backed by collateral sufficient to provide reasonable assurance that they will be repaid; if such collateral is not available, the Fed cannot lend.”200 And while the Fed “serves as the umbrella supervisor of all bank holding companies,” nonbank institutions are generally supervised by other agencies that lack the resources and legal authority of the Fed.201 Discrepancies between the Central Bank’s status as “umbrella 192 See id. (“[T]he stability of the broader financial system requires key payment and settlement systems to operate smoothly under stress to effectively manage counterparty risk.”). 193 See Steven L. Schwarcz, Systemic Risk, 97 GEO. L.J. 193, 198 (2008) (“A common factor in the various definitions of systemic risk is that a trigger event, such as an economic shock or institutional failure, causes a chain of bad economic consequences—sometimes referred to as a domino effect.”); see also Olivier De Bandt & Philipp Hartmann, Systemic Risk: A Survey 10–11 (Eur. Cent. Bank, Working Paper No. 35, 2000), available at http://www.ecb.int/pub/pdf/scpwps/ecbwp035.pdf. Systemic risk as a focus of regulation is discussed infra Part V.A. 194 See Mishkin, supra note 130 (explaining the necessity of the central bank as lender of last resort during systemic financial crises). 195 See Bernanke, Kansas City, supra note 11 (“[I]n the rare circumstances in which the impending or actual failure of an institution imposes substantial systemic risks, the standard procedures for resolving institutions may be inadequate.”). 196 See Bernanke, Fin. Servs., supra note 189 (“[U]nder current arrangements, the SEC’s oversight of the holding companies of the major investment banks is based on a voluntary agreement between the SEC and those firms.”). 197 David A. Skeel, Jr., Governance in the Ruins, 122 HARV. L. REV. 696, 740 (2008) (reviewing Curtis J. Milhaupt & Katharina Pistor, LAW AND CAPITALISM: WHAT CORPORATE CRISES REVEAL ABOUT LEGAL SYSTEMS AND ECONOMIC DEVELOPMENT AROUND THE WORLD (2008)). 198 Steven L. Schwarcz, Markets, Systemic Risk, and the Subprime Mortgage Crisis, 61 SMU L. REV. 209, 214 (2008). 199 See, e.g., Bernanke, FDIC, supra note 9. 200 Bernanke, Austin, supra note 186. 201 Ben S. Bernanke, Chairman, Fed. Reserve, Speech at the Allied Social Science Association Annual Meeting (Jan. 5, 2007), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/ bernanke20070105a.htm. 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 677 supervisor” and its restricted oversight of investment and securities firms is largely the result of the Gramm-Leach-Bliley Act of 1999 (the “GLBA”).202 In passing the GLBA, “Congress was cognizant of the fact that functional regulation for securities [subsidiaries of depository institutions], when combined with the traditional oversight powers of the [Fed], had the potential to create added regulatory burdens for bank and financial holding companies.”203 Therefore, the GLBA directed the Fed “to limit the focus and scope of [its] examinations” into nonbank institutions (i.e., investment banks) subject to alternative regulatory schemes, and “forego examinations [of these firms] in lieu of reviewing examination reports by the [SEC].”204 Unfortunately, this division of responsibility severely curtails the Fed’s ability to anticipate systemic risks posed by investment banks and financial institutions, especially when the SEC does not live up to its obligations. As Professor Patricia McCoy of the University of Connecticut School of Law explains, “[the GLBA] essentially envisions systemic risk as risk that is confined to one sector (for example, the banking sector as opposed to the securities sector). As financial services become more intricate and interdependent, however, that assumption [along with the efficacy of patchwork regulation] must be questioned.”205 Indeed, Bear’s primary regulator, the SEC, “played almost no role” in Bear’s rescue, suggesting that the Fed’s principal regulation of commercial banks may be obsolete and too narrow-minded given today’s reality.206 The regulatory deficiencies that seem to impair the Fed’s ability to effectively respond to systemic threats are even more pronounced considering the fact that “the Fed is the only agency that has the power to serve as a liquidity provider of last resort, a power that has proved critical in financial crises throughout history.”207 Because the Fed has come to assume the risk associated with loans to previously unregulated institutions, officials contend that increased supervision of such firms by the Fed is only reasonable and in keeping with the Fed’s obligation to 202 Gramm-Leach-Bliley Act, 15 U.S.C. §§ 6801–6809, 6821–6827 (1999). PATRICIA A. MCCOY, BANKING LAW MANUAL, BANK AND THRIFT SUPERVISION § 2.04(1)(a)(ii) (2009). 204 Id. 205 Id. 206 See Skeel, supra note 197, at 735–36; see also Kristen French, Wall Street Turf Wars: SEC Versus Fed, July 24, 2008, http://registeredrep.com/regulatory/sec_versus_fed_0724/index.html (“There has been some speculation that the Federal Reserve would begin to regulate investment banks much in the same way that it regulates commercial banks today, requiring them to compute capital requirements and maintain liquidity levels on a consolidated basis, and discouraging certain kinds of financial risk-taking.”). 207 Bernanke, FDIC, supra note 9. 203 678 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 208 promote overall financial stability. Of course, “[w]ith the Fed bearing apex responsibility for U.S. financial stability, it is reasonable to ask whether it enjoys sufficiently broad oversight authorities.”209 Given its “macroeconomic objectives” of “maximum sustainable employment and price stability,”210 Fed leaders have stressed the importance of enhanced oversight authority as a necessity for accomplishing its directives.211 Ideally, providing the Fed with greater supervisory powers would limit the need to issue emergency loans in the future, as the Central Bank could use policy initiatives to deter investment operations that lead to systemic risk. In this way, the financial system as a whole, and the American taxpayer, would be better protected from future instances of market disruption caused by irresponsible trade practices. If the Fed were better able to anticipate failures among individual firms or markets, it would be less likely that gaps in the regulatory structure would afflict the broader economy.212 These issues have led some officials to argue that a unified system of financial regulation under the direction of the Fed would make the most sense in light of the oversight failures of the past year.213 In fact, the heterogeneous makeup of the existing regulatory system has been criticized as unduly redundant, inefficient, and archaic, and a liability to the security of the future financial industry.214 Even before the onset of the current crisis, empirical evidence suggested that those countries that had a 208 See Irwin, supra note 124 (“[Former] Treasury Secretary Henry M. Paulson Jr. said that if investment banks are given permanent access to the Fed’s emergency funds, they should have the same kind of supervision that the Fed requires for conventional banks.”). 209 Vir Bhatia, supra note 17, at 17 (emphasis omitted). 210 Kevin Warsh, Governor of the Bd. of the Fed. Reserve, Remarks at the New York State Economics Association’s 60th Annual Conference: Financial Stability and the Federal Reserve (Oct. 5, 2007), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/warsh20071005a.htm. 211 See Bernanke, FDIC, supra note 9 (“[H]olding the Fed more formally accountable for promoting financial stability makes sense only if the institution’s powers are consistent with its responsibilities.”); Donald L. Kohn, Vice Chairman, Fed. Reserve, Speech at the Exchequer Club Luncheon (Feb. 21, 2007), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/ kohn20070221a.htm (“The Federal Reserve’s activities as a bank supervisor provide us with important and sometimes critical information . . . . Thus, I want to take this opportunity to emphasize and reinforce the case for central bank involvement in bank supervision.”). 212 See Browne, supra note 17, at 385–87 (discussing how gaps in the regulatory structure of the financial industry impair the nation’s global competitiveness). 213 See Scannell, supra note 13 (“‘What makes more sense [than the current approach] is to have a unified system of financial-services regulation.’” (quoting Harvey Pitt, former SEC Chairman)). 214 See Norman D. Slonaker, The Department of the Treasury Blueprint for a Modernized Financial Structure, 1708 PRAC. L. INST. 955, 958 (2008). The current regulatory system of separate agencies across functional lines (banking, insurance, securities and futures) has resulted in: i. No single regulator with all the information and authority to monitor systemic risk and coordinate action throughout the financial system ii. Jurisdictional disputes among the agencies iii. Regulatory redundancies iv. Inefficiency and loss of U.S. competitive advantage Id. 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 679 unified supervisory and monetary program enjoyed fewer bank failures in the 1980s and 1990s than countries that separated such responsibilities among different agencies.215 Together with other statutory reforms designed to streamline government oversight of nonbank institutions and complex securities,216 proponents of enhanced Fed supervision within the financial services industry argue that the Central Bank is the most economic platform from which to shape the future regulatory structure.217 Currently, Fed officials are attempting to clarify the Central Bank’s existing supervisory protocol in an effort to increase awareness as to the Fed’s oversight abilities.218 It remains to be seen whether the results of this internal review will reinforce arguments for the revision of financial regulation. Needless to say, as the market continues to adjust to the barren landscape of the post-housing bubble, commentators have observed that the lack of a clear regulatory structure is hindering economic recovery.219 Still, others doubt whether increased regulation is the answer to recurring economic crises, and even public officials have warned that rushing to regulation is imprudent.220 B. Private Skepticism Amidst the seemingly ubiquitous appeals for tougher regulation, 215 See Joseph G. Haubrich, Combining Bank Supervision and Monetary Policy, FED. RESERVE BANK OF CLEVELAND, Nov. 1996, http://www.clevelandfed.org/Research/Commentary/1996/1196. htm. 216 For example, the Treasury Department has suggested that the SEC and CFTC merge to afford consolidated oversight and regulation of the securities and futures markets. See DEP’T OF THE TREASURY, BLUEPRINT FOR A MODERNIZED FINANCIAL REGULATORY STRUCTURE 11 (2008), available at http://www.treas.gov/press/releases/reports/Blueprint.pdf. Additionally, Chairman Bernanke has suggested that a new regulatory regime be developed specifically for nonbank institutions. See Bernanke, Kansas City, supra note 11 (“A statutory resolution regime for nonbanks, besides reducing uncertainty, would also limit moral hazard by allowing the government to resolve failing firms in a way that is orderly but also wipes out equity holders and haircuts some creditors, analogous to what happens when a commercial bank fails.”). 217 See DEP’T OF THE TREASURY, supra note 216, at 146–56 (detailing how the Fed’s current responsibilities and authority complement the expanded protocol suggested by the Treasury Department). 218 See David L. Kohn, Vice Chairman, Fed. Reserve, Testimony Before the U.S. Senate Comm. on Banking, Hous. & Urban Affairs (June 5, 2008), available at http://federalreserve.gov/newsevents/ testimony/kohn20080605a.htm (“The Federal Reserve is nearing completion of enhancements to its supervisory guidance to clarify [its] role as consolidated supervisor of bank and financial holding companies . . . . The updated guidance is primarily intended to provide greater clarification to [its] own examination staff.”). 219 See Tyler Cowen, Was an Old Bailout a Bad Precedent?, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 28, 2008, at BU5 (“Regulatory uncertainty is stifling the ability of financial markets to engineer at least a partial recovery.”). 220 See Ben S. Bernanke, Chairman, Fed. Reserve, Speech at New York University Law School: Financial Regulation and the Invisible Hand (Apr. 11, 2007), available at http://www.federalreserve. gov/newsevents/speech/bernanke20070411a.htm (“[T]he benefits of regulation come with direct and indirect costs. Direct costs include those arising from compliance with a thicket of complicated rules . . . . Indirect costs include reductions in innovation or competition that can result from overly restrictive regulations.”). 680 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 skeptics have voiced their dissent in an attempt to explain why this most recent economic catastrophe should cause lawmakers to pause before instituting a mass overhaul of the existing regulatory structure. Critics of such a legislative renovation, both in the United States and abroad, argue that more regulation may simply be ineffective in preventing future crises given the incredibly complex nature of today’s financial markets.221 For example, Professor Tyler Cowen of George Mason University has explained that “regulators will never be in a position to accurately evaluate . . . many of the most important market transactions.”222 Because of the intricate web of international finance, which involves highly sophisticated players and trillions of dollars, government regulators lack the resources to use reform as a means to prevent disaster.223 Instead, “the real issue is setting strong regulatory priorities to prevent outright fraud and to encourage market transparency, given that government scrutiny will never be universal or even close to it.”224 Similarly, using government to restrain un-regulated financial sectors after they have wreaked havoc on the system may not be the best guide for controlling future threats.225 As some commentators have pointed out, the debate over the future of regulation has arisen in the smog of disaster, and a complete reconsideration of traditional models of reform may be necessary.226 Additionally, the possibility that reform will create a slippery slope of government abuses and outright favoritism has made headlines in the United Kingdom, where revised banking policies have been criticized as allowing the public sector to “cherry-pick assets and transfer them to a private sector buyer.”227 Interestingly, the United Kingdom delegates the responsibility of bank and financial services supervision to a single agency, the Financial Services Authority (“FSA”).228 As a central hub of financial oversight, the FSA draws on expansive regulatory powers to influence and observe market operations, and functions independently of the Bank of 221 See Cowen, supra note 2, at BU7 (“[I]t’s not obvious that the less regulated financial sector performed any worse than the highly regulated housing and bank mortgage lending sectors, including, of course, the government-sponsored mortgaged agencies.”). 222 Id. 223 See id. 224 Id. 225 See id. 226 See Adrian Blundell-Wignall & Paul Atkinson, The Sub-Prime Crisis: Causal Distortions and Regulatory Reform, in LESSONS FROM THE FINANCIAL TURMOIL OF 2007 AND 2008 55, 66 (Paul Bloxham & Christopher Kent eds., 2008), available at http://www.rba.gov.au/PublicationsAnd Research/Conferences/2008/Blundell-Wignall_Atkinson.pdf (“There needs to be some new thinking about reform of the regulatory and policy-making paradigms for the longer run.”). 227 Philip Aldrick, Banking Reforms Will Jeopardise Financial Industry, Say Lawyers, DAILY TELEGRAPH (London), Sept. 4, 2008, at 3 (quoting Bob Penn, Regulatory Partner, Allen & Overy). 228 See About the FSA, http://www.fsa.gov.uk/Pages/About/What/index.shtml (last visited Nov. 16, 2009) (providing links to details on the scope, objectives, and structure of the FSA). 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 681 229 England. This separation of central banking and banking supervision is emphasized by critics who reject the expanding role of the Fed as a financial administrator over nonbanks.230 Those who endorse the United Kingdom’s regulatory approach contend that increased independence of financial regulators allows flexibility in governance, which in turn promotes efficient use of resources and generally more effective policies.231 By adopting a “principles-based” methodology of supervision that encourages voluntary compliance by private institutions, the FSA has been commended for promoting market discipline.232 Furthermore, by removing supervisory responsibilities from the purview of a central bank, and thereby reducing its oversight authority, some scholars have argued that the risk that a conflict of interest would impede the Fed’s ability to impose monetary restraint out of concern for banks is largely reduced if not eliminated, by the FSA paradigm.233 With countries such as Korea, Japan, India, and South Africa moving toward systems that mirror those of the United Kingdom,234 questions will soon arise as to how the United States should proceed and what the future role of the Fed should be. Finally, even public officials have cautioned that added regulation cannot threaten the ability of market participants to develop innovative business models or investment products.235 Although the existing framework does not seem to promote American competitiveness in key global markets,236 any new regulatory system for the financial industry should not be “counterproductive” by encouraging parties to conduct their 229 Id. See C.A.E. Goodhart, The Organisational Structure of Banking Supervision 8–23 (Fin. Stability Inst. Occasional Papers No. 1, 2000), available at http://www.bis.org/fsi/fsipapers01.pdf (addressing arguments that have been made for the continued separation between central banks and banking supervision). 231 See Harvey L. Pitt, Bringing Financial Services Regulation into the Twenty-First Century, 25 YALE J. ON REG. 315, 321–23 (discussing the benefits of the FSA model of supervision as contrasted with that of the SEC); see also Ben S. Bernanke, Chairman, Fed. Reserve, Speech at the Federal Reserve Bank of Atlanta’s Financial Markets Conference: Regulation and Financial Innovation (May 15, 2007), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/bernanke20070515a.htm [hereinafter Bernanke, Atlanta II] (describing the FSA’s “[p]rinciples-based” supervisory approach as concentrating government resources and attention to those “firms, markets, or instruments in proportion to the perceived risks to the FSA’s regulatory objectives”). 232 See Pitt, supra note 231, at 321–23 (describing how the FSA’s approach is more efficient than traditional models employed by American organizations); John H. Walsh, Institution-Based Financial Regulation: A Third Paradigm, 49 HARV. INT’L L.J. 381, 383–87 (2008) (discussing the mechanics of “principles-based” regulation as adopted by the FSA and some American organizations, and the praise and criticism “principles-based” regulation has garnered). 233 See Goodhart, supra note 230, at 20–23 (discussing how separating supervision from central banking works to reduce the occurrence of conflicts of interest with regard to the creation of monetary policy). 234 See id. at 6–7. 235 See Kohn, supra note 211 (advising that regulations which attempt to anticipate and control all possible systemic threats may unduly restrict market growth). 236 See Browne, supra note 17, at 393–410 (discussing how U.S. firms are losing influence in various markets as a result of current regulatory deficiencies). 230 682 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 237 business overseas. With the major U.S. investment banks now all subsidiaries of bank holding companies, some argue that the Fed no longer needs enhanced supervisory powers over nonbanks to successfully monitor market threats. However, as discussed in Part V, existing oversight restrictions continue to limit the Fed’s capacity to adopt a prophylactic risk management policy.238 Obviously, striking the right balance between laissez-faire and new financial regulation is a complicated issue that remains a key focus of those at the Fed and on Capitol Hill. Therefore, the remainder of this Note draws on existing scholarly work devoted to the challenge of improving banking and financial system oversight with the goal of increasing dialogue as to the proper role of the Fed in such future regulatory schemes. V. GOING FORWARD: THE FUTURE OF INVESTMENT BANK REGULATION A. An Attempt at Reconciliation It goes without saying that the goal of regulators in implementing any new framework of investment banking and financial system oversight should be to focus on the most important threats to economic stability facing our country. While some may argue that those threats range from unbridled greed to government incompetence, the key concern of lawmakers should be the contemporary nature of systemic risk.239 As the current crisis illustrates, systemic risk has developed into a cross-sector cancer, capable of emerging within the securities realm and spreading to the banking and credit sectors. This development stresses the jurisdictional boundaries of federal agencies, reducing the capacity of the Fed or similar regulators to respond to systemic risks in accordance with existing legal authority.240 Because “[f]ederal banking agencies are specifically barred from examining registered investment company subsidiaries,” the Fed must rely on inconsistent piecemeal examinations of these firms, which themselves are subject to “stringent restrictions.”241 For example, as the 237 See Neikirk et al., supra note 119, at C1 (“Those who oppose too many new federal regulations on Wall Street investment banking firms fear such a move could be highly counterproductive and drive more financial transactions overseas to London, Hong Kong, or other spots.”). 238 See MCCOY, supra note 203, § 12.04(1) (describing how the existing scheme of banking regulation is duplicative and inefficient). 239 See Robert W. Hahn & Peter Passell, The Rush to Reregulate, AEI ON THE ISSUES, Aug. 20, 2008, http://www.aei.org/issue/28495 (“The most easily justifiable rationale for [government] intervention is the potential for damage to those not directly involved—for example, people who lose their savings in bank runs when credit markets freeze.”). 240 MCCOY, supra note 203, § 12.04(1)(a)(ii); see also Schwarcz, supra note 193, at 198–204 (discussing how systemic risks faced by individual institutions and markets should not be considered in isolation when defining systemic risk as a focus of regulation). 241 MCCOY, supra note 203, § 12.04(1)(a)(ii). 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 683 GLBA mandates, the Fed may only examine “functionally regulated subsidiaries” (including investment banks) in three instances: (1) where the Fed has “reasonable cause to believe” the activities of the subsidiary “pose a material risk to an affiliated depository institution[;]” (2) where the Fed “reasonably determines” an examination is needed to assess the propriety of the internal monitoring and control systems of the subsidiary; and (3) where the Fed has “reasonable cause to believe” a subsidiary is in violation of federal law within its jurisdiction.242 These provisions effectively preclude the Fed from undertaking routine examinations of investment banks, thereby increasing the potential for risks to go unnoticed. Additionally, the GLBA specifically prohibits federal banking agencies from inspecting or examining any “registered investment company that is not a bank holding company or a savings and loan company.”243 And, although “the FDIC has full authority to examine any affiliate of a depository institution[,]” it can only do so when “necessary to disclose fully the relationship between the two companies and the effect of that relationship on the depository institution’s condition.”244 Loopholes such as these inhibit the effective management of risks within the investment banking and financial sectors, impairing the Fed’s ability to protect the commercial banking industry. Given the potential for systemic threats to devastate various markets and the real economy, enhancing the Fed’s capabilities at anticipating and reacting to systemic risks within the financial and investment contexts is a necessity. This argument is supported by the fact that major domestic investment banks have now become subsidiaries of bank holding companies, thereby augmenting the importance of a consistent and unified structure of supervision.245 With the protection of individual depositors now directly intertwined with the stability of investment companies previously operating in relative isolation, systemic risk is no longer an abstract anomaly confined to the plush offices of Wall Street executives and investors—it is now a concern of all American taxpayers. Therefore, as the primary guardian of banking stability, the Fed ought to be given greater powers to supervise investment banks and other financial companies whose fate can now affect the lives of millions of Americans. As Professor McCoy suggests, “where an investment company is located in a subsidiary of a bank or thrift, consolidating safety and soundness examinations in the deposit institution’s primary federal 242 Id. Gramm-Leach-Bliley Act, 12 U.S.C. § 1820a(a) (2006). 244 MCCOY, supra note 203, § 12.04(1)(a)(ii) (emphasis added) (internal citations omitted). 245 See Bernanke, Atlanta II, supra note 231 (“Rather than addressing specific institutions or instruments in isolation, regulators should begin by identifying their objectives and then address the implications of the broad range of financial innovations for those objectives. By returning to the basics, we can increase the coherence, consistency, and effectives of the regulatory framework.”). 243 684 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 banking supervisor would make for better informed examinations.”246 Of course, this is not to say that systemic risk should become a scapegoat for irresponsible reform measures which do more harm to the country’s economic prowess than protect it. Because future systemic risks may be considered unavoidable occurrences of free market ideology and even human behavior, regulation alone will be insufficient in preventing all future occurrences of systemic threats.247 Instead, a “private initiative that will complement official oversight in encouraging [responsible] industrywide practices” is an essential feature of any future regulatory agenda.248 Nonetheless, “market discipline often needs to be buttressed by government oversight,”249 and the Fed should be granted greater powers over investment banks with respect to reporting, regulation, examinations, capital requirements, and enforcement. 1. Reporting to the Fed Imposing tougher reporting and disclosure requirements on investment banks and their managers has the additional benefit of improving a firm’s internal culture of risk appreciation and understanding. In other words, if investment banks are required to disclose quarterly or semi-annual reviews of balance-sheet status or investment outlooks, irresponsible risk taking will become less of a clandestine affliction.250 Utilizing existing reporting models for commercial banks would prove useful in this regard,251 as would repealing provisions of the GLBA which inhibit the Fed’s examination of “functionally regulated subsidiaries.”252 No longer should the Fed be responsible for supervising the risks posed by investment banks “with one hand tied behind its back,” and investment banks and their managers should be held responsible for filing accurate “quarterly reports of condition” directly with the Federal Reserve, instead of the SEC, CFTC, 246 MCCOY, supra note 203, § 12.04(1)(a)(ii). See Alan L. Beller, Containing Systemic Risk: The Road to Reform—The Report of the CRMPG III, Aug. 6, 2008—Excerpts, 1704 PRAC. L. INST. 19, 39 (2008) (“The fact that financial excess fundamentally grows out of human behavior is a sobering reality . . . . However, official oversight is not a substitute for the effective management of financial institutions, which is, and should remain, a private-sector function.”). 248 Id. 249 Bernanke, Atlanta II, supra note 231. 250 See id. (discussing how effective disclosures can limit the occurrence of reckless trade practices); see also MCCOY, supra note 203, § 12.03(2) (“Periodic reports of condition by individual institutions to regulators are the lifeblood of banking supervision and an important diagnostic tool for monitoring the financial health of banks and thrifts.”). 251 See MCCOY, supra note 203, § 12.03(2)–(3) (describing the types of reports and data that insured institutions must file with federal regulators). 252 Id. § 12.03(1)–(2) (“Because of its enormous exposure to losses . . . the federal government requires every insured depository institution . . . to file detailed financial reports on a regular basis.” (emphasis added)). Professor McCoy describes how the GLBA sought to streamline reporting requirements for companies subject to oversight by multiple regulators, but may have “swayed too far” in doing so—a concern made all the more apparent given the well publicized lapses of the SEC as of late. Id. § 12.03(2). 247 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 685 253 or other functional regulators. Additionally, legislation aimed at creating new reporting standards may want to consider the value of independent auditing, public disclosures, and mandatory penalties for “false reports or late filings.”254 Finally, Chief Risk Officers or comparable executives within investment banks should develop a working relationship with Fed examiners that fosters enhanced transparency and promotes greater market discipline.255 2. Regulation Granting the Fed greater regulatory powers over investment banks will necessarily conflict with the jurisdictional authority of the SEC. However, given the critical role played by the lender of last resort during systemic crisis, the Fed should be granted “the authority to set expectations and require corrective actions as warranted in cases in which firms’ actions have potential implications for financial stability.”256 The Central Bank should also have the ability to establish prospective regulations designed to limit the need for emergency discount window loans. For example, by instituting a clear process by which the Fed can manage the anticipated insolvency of an investment bank, the likelihood that a disorderly failure will instill fear in the markets is reduced, as is the potential for banks runs and contagion.257 Additionally, as Chairman Bernanke has argued, the Fed’s oversight of “systemically important payment and settlement systems” must be explicitly delineated so that the Fed can ensure that these systems remain fluid in crisis situations.258 As a benefit to the firms, greater regulation should, in turn, allow investment banks greater access to the Fed’s “discount . . . window under nonemergency circumstances.”259 But, such access must not be seen as an excuse to ignore market discipline.260 The SEC should develop policies intended to assist the Fed in overseeing the operations of investment banks, yet “consolidated supervision” of these firms is more efficient than the process currently in 253 See id. (“The Federal Reserve Board and its fellow agencies should not be dependent . . . on the SEC . . . for reports on interaffiliate transactions and other ‘subtle hazards’ that could endanger a bank or thrift’s safety and soundness.”). 254 Id. § 12.03(2)–12.03(4). 255 See FIN. STABILITY FORUM, REPORT OF THE FINANCIAL STABILITY FORUM ON ENHANCING MARKET & INSTITUTIONAL RESILIENCE 22–26 (2008), available at http://www.financialstabilityboard. org/publications/r_0804.pdf (recommending that “[r]isk disclosures by market participants” be increased to improve transparency within the financial markets). 256 Bernanke, FDIC, supra note 9. 257 See Bernanke, Austin, supra note 186 (discussing the benefits of the FDIC’s ability to manage the insolvency of commercial banks and how a similar system for securities firms may be needed). 258 Bernanke, Fin. Servs., supra note 189. 259 Kim Dixon & Karey Wutkowski, Financial Regulation Reform—But Not Paulson’s—Likely in 2009, INS. J., Aug. 25, 2008, http://www.insurancejournal.com/news/national/2008/08/25/93050.htm. 260 See Bernanke, FDIC, supra note 9 (“[A]ttention should be paid to the risk that market participants might incorrectly view the Fed as a source of unconditional support for financial institutions and markets, which could lead to an unacceptable reduction in market discipline.”). 686 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 261 place. Therefore, the Fed’s supervisory role should be extended to include oversight of investment banking and financial services firms, which are now subsidiaries of depository institutions. New regulations necessary to protect economic stability should be adopted with the understanding that flexibility and some risk taking are vital to fostering growth and innovation.262 3. Examinations Creating a detailed examination process for the Fed to use in overseeing financial services firms is critical. In keeping with its new role as consolidated supervisor of investment banks, the Fed’s examination authority should be enhanced to mirror that which exists for traditional For example, “[s]afety and soundness depository institutions.263 examinations” which generally assess a commercial bank’s infrastructure in key areas such as “solvency,” “management,” and “information technology,” ought to be implemented with new standards for investment banks.264 Additionally, “compliance examinations” which focus on a firm’s compliance with applicable “consumer and investor protection laws” should be instituted to ensure that investment banks maintain legitimate market operations.265 A rating system that appraises vital elements of a firm’s operations may be beneficial, and examinations should be conducted regularly so as to identify potential threats or risks within single or multiple institutions.266 To accommodate the concerns of the private sector, an “appeals process” similar to that used for depository institutions would be useful in checking government discretion and improving the accuracy of examinations.267 “To fulfill its responsibilities, the Fed would also need to have the ability to look at financial firms as a whole, much as the [Fed does] today when [it] exercise[s] [its] umbrella 261 Id. See id. (“[R]eforms in the oversight of these firms must recognize the distinctive features of investment banking and take care neither to unduly inhibit efficiency and innovation nor to induce a migration of risk-taking activities to institutions that are less regulated or beyond our borders.”). 263 See MCCOY, supra note 203, § 12.04(1)(b)–(4) (discussing in detail the examination process of “Federal bank examiners” over depository institutions). 264 Id. § 12.04(1)(b). Safety and soundness examinations monitor the solvency of insured institutions, evaluate management and follow up on areas of needed improvement. Safety and soundness examinations include full-scope examinations, specialty examinations in areas such as information technology and trust operations, and special examinations that focus on specific issues of concern at an institution. Id. (internal citations omitted). 265 Id. 266 See id. (describing how depository institutions are examined in accordance with specific guidelines under the “Uniform Financial Institutions Rating System”). 267 See id. § 12.04(2) (explaining how banking examinations may be subject to an independent review process). 262 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 687 268 authority over financial holding companies . . . .” Increased examinations of investment banks will provide Fed officials with information necessary to enhance the efficacy of the government’s containment of systemic risk, reducing threats to other sectors of the economy and protecting individual consumers. When appropriate, the results of examinations should be published to allow the interested public the opportunity to review the state of an individual firm’s business model.269 Of course, such disclosures must be mindful of the threat of bank runs that co-exists with the public’s interpretation of a company’s financial health.270 4. Capital Requirements Another crucial factor in improving the Fed’s ability to contain systemic risk is ensuring that investment banks have the necessary capital resources to prevent the liquidity crisis Bear Stearns and other institutions have recently faced. Leverage ratios must be controlled to guard against the possibility of future government bailouts and reduce the occurrence of moral hazard.271 Fortunately, proposals such as those announced in Pillar 1 of the Basel II Capital Accord provide detailed and practical frameworks that the Fed can utilize in determining the best method for setting capital reserve minimums for investment banks.272 Because depositors now have an interest in the solvency of securities firms, leverage ratios must remain conservative enough to protect against bankruptcy and illiquidity quagmires. For those depository institutions that have now become the parent company of investment bank subsidiaries, the Fed must make certain that the vast resources of a depository institution do not become indirect incentives for investment banks to assume more debt than the subsidiary can afford. Thus, to provide the most protection for depositors, reserve standards for investment bank subsidiaries should remain independent of those of the parent holding company. Also, sections 23A and 23B of the Federal Reserve Act must remain key safeguards in restricting the types and extent of transactions that depository institutions can engage in with their affiliates and counterparties.273 At no time should 268 Bernanke, FDIC, supra note 9. See MCCOY, supra note 203, § 12.04(4) (describing how public disclosure of past examination reports may improve the “accountability and consistency” of bank examinations). 270 See id. (“In sum, across-the-board disclosure of examination reports could provide valuable information to some market participants, albeit at the potentially high cost of occasional bank runs.”). 271 See Morris & Shin, supra note 17, at 21–26 (using case analysis to describe why future financial regulation must consider the possibility of leverage restraints on individual firms). 272 See BASEL COMM. ON BANKING SUPERVISION, INTERNATIONAL CONVERGENCE OF CAPITAL MEASUREMENT & CAPITAL STANDARDS 12–14 (2005), available at http://www.bis.org/publ/bcbs107b. pdf (outlining the process for determining minimum capital requirements as a basis for improving banking regulation). 273 See Federal Reserve Act, 12 U.S.C. §§ 371c(a), 371c-1(b) (2006) (prescribing restrictions on transactions with affiliates). 269 688 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 a “covered transaction” imperil the security and liquidity of any depositor’s account,274 and regularly conducted examinations should stress the consistency of an investment bank’s capitalization to confirm that the subsidiaries’ leverage does not affect the health of the depository institution. 5. Enforcement How the Fed goes about enforcing its oversight authority over investment banks is open to vast commentary. Nonetheless, the existing structure of formal and informal275 enforcement mechanisms for commercial institutions may again provide useful guidance in this respect. For example, aside from the “examination process[es],” “board resolutions and commitment letters,” and “supervisory directives,” which comprise the bulk of informal bank supervision, the Fed should also be allowed to impose “cease-and-desist orders,” officer and director suspension (and removal or prohibition), and civil monetary penalties against securities firms when federal regulatory compliance is lacking, or the investment bank’s practices deviate from “generally accepted standards of prudent operation.”276 Additionally, lawmakers may want to consider the potential benefits afforded by “agency adjudication”277 and public disclosure278 in insuring that investment banks maintain acceptable investment and risk portfolios. However, it is vital that a proper balance between regulatory enforcement and market independence be maintained. In this regard, enforcement mechanisms may in some circumstances be subject to judicial review,279 with top Fed officials periodically assessing enforcement standards to confirm that regulation is not stifling market progression and economic growth. At the risk of oversimplifying the problems inherent in creating a new regulatory framework for investment banks, the preceding discussion has offered several suggestions for improvement of the Fed’s oversight authority in the financial services industry. Clearly, the topics focused on do not exist exclusively from one another or in isolation of other considerations which are relevant to this issue. For instance, complications will soon arise when one factors in the important issues of private sector reluctance, global central bank policy coordination,280 and securities274 See id. § 371c(b)(7)A–E (defining covered transactions). See MCCOY, supra note 203, §§ 13.02, 13.03(4)–(10). Id. §§ 13.02, 13.03(3), 13.03(5), 13.03(6). 277 Id. §13.03(9). 278 Id. § 13.03(10). 279 See id. § 13.03(1) (discussing the potential avenues of judicial review for formal enforcement mechanisms in the commercial banking context). 280 See Ben S. Bernanke, Chairman, Fed. Reserve, Speech at the Fifth European Central Bank Conference (Nov. 14, 2008), available at http://federalreserve.gov/newsevents/speech/bernanke 275 276 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 689 281 specific regulation. Nevertheless, each contribution to this topic encourages the reform that is essential to economic recovery. B. The Current Reality The global economic crisis that continues to wreak havoc in the United States and other countries is as far-reaching as it is complex. For nearly two years, the world has witnessed the destruction of financial powerhouses, the deterioration of the stock and credit markets, and repeated attempts by political leaders to rejuvenate the economy through unprecedented government programs. Unfortunately, the crisis demonstrates how regulatory inadequacies have allowed irresponsible and reckless trade practices to create a worldwide catastrophe not seen since the 1930s. “For years, too many Wall Street executives made imprudent and dangerous decisions, seeking profits with too little regard for risk, too little regulatory scrutiny, and too little accountability.”282 The excesses of greed and carelessness have been seen by all Americans who have suffered from the exploitation of investment products by financial firms and their managers. Moreover, vast sums of public money have been taken from the coffers of taxpayers in an effort to rescue the financial system from those who have profited from its unrestrained manipulation. As this disaster best illustrates, a robust and dynamic twenty-first century economy cannot survive in the midst of such abuses. Because of the diversity of problems posed by the current recession, investment banking and financial services regulatory reform is likely to be a drawn-out process that may take years to complete. However, the existing regulatory structure is incapable of providing the type of oversight and supervision that is required of modern financial markets and the enterprises involved therein. Consequently, new policies are an inevitable and indispensable feature of stable financial growth, new investor confidence, and economic recovery in general. VI. CONCLUSION The story of Bear Stearns is in many ways a microcosm for the larger economic calamity that began in late 2007 and continues to this day. As Wall Street’s fifth largest investment bank, Bear used aggressive tactics 20081214a.htm (discussing the importance and challenges of ongoing policy coordination between central banks across the globe). 281 For example, any new regulations imposed on investment banks must be implemented in a way that will complement the controls adopted for CDS, ABS, and other complex securities and derivative products. 282 Pres. Barack Obama, Speech at George Mason University: American Recovery and Reinvestment (Jan. 8, 2009), available at http://www.marketwatch.com/news/story/text-obama-speecheconomy/story.aspx?guid=%7B4C5C66C9-2BD5-4870-8FE2-02BC6B75F3E7%7D&dist=msr_1 (emphasis added). 690 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:647 rooted in unchecked speculation to acquire and sell exotic financial products whose value was uncertain and largely dependent on the continued success of the housing market. In the absence of strict oversight, Bear sold complex derivative investments that pushed the firm’s debt beyond the point backed by readily available liquid assets. Then, when the housing bubble burst, Bear’s infrastructure collapsed under the weight of its irresponsible balance sheet, bringing the securities firm to the brink of bankruptcy. Constrained by antiquated laws providing only a limited number of options to choose from, the Central Bank intervened to prevent Bear Stearns’s disorderly failure, fearing that the firm’s downfall would touch off an uncontrollable domino effect among similar institutions. In doing so, the Fed committed billions of dollars of taxpayer money in an effort to prevent a larger disaster, the implications of which could not be fully predicted. Such actions raised important questions regarding the legality of the Fed’s brokerage of the sale of Bear Stearns to JPMorgan, especially the risk posed to commercial depositors that had been a focus of federal laws aimed at precluding similar transactions. And despite the bailout, investment banks continued to fail, while others drastically changed their business structures to survive the loss of investor confidence that continues to shake the foundation of Wall Street itself. Now, in the aftermath of the devastation of America’s investment banking industry, the call for regulatory reform has been widespread and intense. As the past two years demonstrate, the federal government must be granted broader authority within the financial services industry to effectively manage systemic risks in a way that reduces the likelihood of future bailouts and reckless market practices. Still, this reform must also preserve the competitiveness of key sectors of the United States economy. Given the Fed’s assumed role as steward over much of the existing investment banking landscape, it should be given the supervisory powers needed to fulfill its newfound responsibilities. If one considers the development of the current economic crisis from a macro level, the comparisons to be drawn from the Bear Stearns incident are apparent. First, the demise of the housing market and the onset of the mortgage crisis precipitated the failure (or near failure) of some of Wall Street’s largest institutions. In turn, these events threatened the vitality of the entire economy. Second, the federal government took unprecedented actions to bail out the financial system, injecting up to $700 billion of public money into the ailing credit and securities markets. But the economy continued its recessionary fall, with investors fleeing, unemployment rising, and growth stagnating. Finally, in the wake of this catastrophe, the Obama administration and Congress have promised sweeping regulatory programs designed to combat the failings of existing frameworks, while also strengthening economic resilience and progression. 2009] CRISIS COMPOUNDED BY CONSTRAINT 691 In this way, both Bear and the larger crisis have followed the course from failure, to bailout, to calls for reform. CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW VOLUME 42 DECEMBER 2009 NUMBER 2 Note THE ROLE OF PARENTS INVOLVED IN THE COLLEGE ADMISSIONS PROCESS MICHAEL P. POHORYLO After the U.S. Supreme Court decided the 2003 University of Michigan affirmative action cases, the law concerning the use of race-based affirmative action programs in the college admissions process seemed to be settled for the next few decades. However, in 2007, the Supreme Court once again revisited the use of race-based affirmative action, this time at the K–12 level, and subtly, yet significantly, altered how the law will treat challenges to affirmative action programs in higher education. The purpose of this Note is to examine the likely impact the holding of this 2007 U.S. Supreme Court case, Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School District No. 1, will have on both the current case law surrounding the use of race-based affirmative action policies in the college admissions process and the development and implementation of future institutional affirmative action policies. In addition, this Note explores the public policy effect resulting from restrictions on the freedom of institutions to create their own admissions policies. 693 NOTE CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................... 695 II. AFFIRMATIVE ACTION IN AMERICAN SOCIETY ........................ 698 III. AFFIRMATIVE ACTION IN THE COURTS...................................... 702 A. B. C. D. PRETEXT TO BAKKE ............................................................................. 702 BAKKE.................................................................................................. 703 HOPWOOD ........................................................................................... 705 THE UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN AFFIRMATIVE ACTION CASES ........... 707 IV. THE LEGACY OF PARENTS INVOLVED IN HIGHER EDUCATION ....................................................................................... 711 A. PARENTS INVOLVED .............................................................................. 711 B. IMPACT ON HIGHER EDUCATION ......................................................... 715 V. THE BENEFITS OF DIVERSITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION FOR STUDENTS AND SOCIETY ...................................................... 723 A. SPECIFIC BENEFITS TO SOCIETY AND INDIVIDUALS ............................. 724 B. ALTERNATIVES TO RACE-BASED AFFIRMATIVE ACTION ARE NOT A SUITABLE REPLACEMENT ............................................. 726 VI. CONCLUSION ..................................................................................... 731 THE ROLE OF PARENTS INVOLVED IN THE COLLEGE ADMISSIONS PROCESS MICHAEL P. POHORYLO* I. INTRODUCTION After the United States Supreme Court decided the 2003 University of Michigan affirmative action cases,1 college administrators rejoiced in what many saw as a victory over the opponents of race-based affirmative action policies in the college admissions process.2 While these decisions did not go so far as to ensure that the use of race-based affirmative action policies would be a valid practice forever,3 administrators knew that for the foreseeable future they could consider the race of an applicant during the admissions process. Specifically, in affirming the precedent set in Regents of the University of California v. Bakke,4 the Supreme Court held that achieving a diverse student body within the realm of higher education was a compelling government interest, and, as a result, race-based affirmative action policies could withstand strict scrutiny if they were narrowly tailored.5 Although these policies had to be narrowly tailored to survive judicial review, colleges and universities were still provided with sufficient autonomy to adopt admissions standards that were consistent with their educational mission and the needs of their communities. By 2006, however, this period of celebration had already come to an abrupt end when the U.S. Supreme Court decided that it would address the issue of whether race could be used as a factor in assigning K–12 students * Amherst College, B.A. 2004; Boston College, M.A. 2007; University of Connecticut School of Law, J.D. Candidate 2010. I would like to thank Dean and Professor Darcy Kirk for her suggestions and comments throughout the writing process. I would also like to thank my parents, Michael and Diane Pohorylo, for their years of guidance, without which this Note would not be possible. Finally, this Note is dedicated to my wife, Morgan, for her endless encouragement and support. All errors contained herein are mine and mine alone. 1 These cases were published as Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 306 (2003) and Gratz v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 244 (2003). 2 See, e.g., Narrow Use of Affirmative Action Preserved in College Admissions, CNN, Dec. 25, 2003, http://www.cnn.com/2003/LAW/06/23/scotus.affirmative.action (“[T]his is a wonderful, wonderful day—a victory for all of higher education, because what it means at its core is that affirmative action may still be used and the court’s given us a road map to get there . . . .” (quoting University of Michigan President Mary Sue Coleman)). 3 See Grutter, 539 U.S. at 343 (“We expect that 25 years from now, the use of racial preferences will no longer be necessary to further the interest approved today.”). 4 See 438 U.S. 265, 311–12, 315–17 (1978) (holding that achieving a diverse student body was a constitutionally permissible goal for colleges and universities but that race could not be the deciding factor in determining whether an applicant was admitted). 5 See infra notes 111–13 and accompanying text. 696 CONNECTICUT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 42:693 6 to public schools. Although the Court would be addressing this issue within the K–12 education system alone, many experts debated whether the University of Michigan affirmative action cases would still be good law after a decision was rendered.7 While some experts in higher education law believed that the holding would have no effect on the Michigan rulings, others believed that the Court would suggest that it was “open” to revisiting the 2003 holdings and possibly revising the precedent set at that time.8 Many of the fears among the supporters of race-based affirmative action were later alleviated when the Court decided Parents Inv