Pluralism Revisited
Transcription
Pluralism Revisited
Pluralism Revisited Robert A. Dahl The struggle of individuals and groups to gain autonomy in relation to the controlof othersis, like the effortsto acquirecontrolover others, a fundamental tendency of political life. Struggles for autonomy result from conflicts and cleavages; when these strugglesare successful, as they often are, they resultin turn in tendencies toward pluralism. Because conflicts and cleavages are ubiquitous, so too are tendencies towardpluralism. By suppressingautonomy and preventingthe public manifestationof conflicts and cleavages, a hegemonic regime can prevent the developmentof a pluralisticsocial andpoliticalorder.Wheneverthe barriersto organizedoppositions arelowered, however, the thrusttowardautonomyandpluralismbecomes evident in political and social life. In polyarchies, where by definition these barriersare lowest, comparativelyspeaking, subsystemautonomyand organizationalpluralismare always markedfeaturesof the social and political order. However, even if a considerabledegree of pluralismis a necessarycondition, an essential characteristic, and a consequence of a democratic regime, pluralismalso creates problemsfor which no altogethersatisfactorysolution seems yet to have been found. You will have noticedthatI have alreadyused the word "pluralism" several times, andin severalsenses. "Pluralism''is often used simplyas a synonymfor "diversity." Thus "culturalpluralism" seems to mean essentially the same thing as "cultural" or "social diversity," except that "pluralism" may be intendedto carrya more favorable, "diversity" a more neutral,connotation.I see no profit in this usage, and prefer to use the term "diversity" instead. I want to use the term here in two different but related ways. First, by 'conflictive pluralism''I intendto referto the numberandpatternof relatively 191 Comparative Politics January 1978 enduringcleavages that must be taken into account in order to characterize conflicts among a given collection of persons. I wish to distinguishconflictive pluralismfrom strict bipolaritywhich, I shall argue, is a comparativelyrare cleavage pattern,if we considerany numberof public, politicalconflicts within the variouscountriesof the world, or at any rateamongthose wherethe barriers to the public expression of conflict are relatively low. Second, by "organizationalpluralism"I intendto referto the numberandautonomyof organizations thatmustbe takeninto accountin orderto characterizeconflicts among a given collection of persons. Organizationalpluralismis greater, other things being equal, the greaterthe numberof organizationsand the greatertheir autonomy. Systems that permit a significant measureof autonomyto importantunits or subsystemsare, in fact, frequentlycalled pluralistic,or at leastpluralisticin that respect. ThuscontemporaryYugoslav writerssometimesdescribetheirsystem of decentralizedsocialism as pluralistic,in contrastto strictlyhegemonic rule with a commandeconomy, as in the Soviet Union, or Yugoslavia itself before 1951. In Italy, and until the military coup also in Chile, Communist party leaders spoke of their commitmentto pluralismin orderto signify their intention of maintaininga regime that would permit opposition parties. Thus, the termis no longer limitedto Westernbourgeoisthought,nor is it necessarilyan epithet among Marxistsor other socialists. I will now very briefly, and necessarily thereforesomewhat superficially, examine the causes of organizationalpluralism, some of the problems or pathologies it gives rise to, and some of the remediesthat are often proposed. AlthoughI can hardlydo more thanhint at the main lines of the argument,my considerations will lead me to the conclusion that none of the commonly proposed solutions would accomplish much. What is more, with some the remedy seems to me ratherworse than the disease. Causes of Organizational Pluralism The extent of organizationalpluralism within a political system, and more concretely within a country, is mainly to be explained, I think, by: (1) the amount of latent conflictive pluralism;(2) the nature of the socioeconomic order;(3) the natureof the political regime; (4) the concrete structureof the political institutions. These four factors are not wholly independentof one another;their relationshipsare complex and by no means well understood. Conflictive pluralism As Joseph LaPalombara'srecent analysis of the evidence indicates, and as othershave also found,1 in most countriesthereexist a numberof different lines of cleavage, and the intersectionof these cleavage lines has produceda patternof conflictive pluralism,not bipolarity.Bipolarity along a cleavage line formed by social class tends to exist only in highly homogeneouscountrieslike New Zealandor Finlandwhere otherdifferences, 192 Robert A. Dahl as of language, religion, race, or ethnic group, are not sufficiently salient to disturbthe effects of differences in social class. Ironicallyfor orthodoxclass theory, however, it is precisely because of their high homogeneity that such countries manageto deal rathereasily with conflicts arisingfrom class cleavages. In these countriesthe patternthat tends to emerge, then, is not extreme polarizationaccompaniedby acute antagonismsbut rathera moderatebipolarity within a ratherconsensual political environment. It is possible to interpretcleavages otherthanthose formedby social class as crumblingobstaclesto class consciousness, left behindby the slow recessionof traditionalsociety and early capitalism, destined neverthelessto rapiderosion by the push of new economic relationships. Historically, however, this interpretationhas led to a persistentunderestimationof the continuingstrengthof identificationsformedby subculturescenteredaroundreligion, region, ethnic group, race, and language, and failure to foresee the emergence of new identificationscenteredarounda varietyof economicdifferencesthatdo not fall nicely along a single prominentcleavage line but rathergenerate several or many cleavages, as among skilled and unskilledworkers,organizedand unorganized, blue collar and white collar, service workers, professionals, executives, and so on. Finally, in reducingideology to an epiphenomenonof class (a position, it should be added, that many neo-Marxistshave long since abandoned), orthodoxclass interpretationshave tendedvastly to underestimatethe extent to which ideological diversityamongelites leads to fragmentationrather than solidarity. Nowhere is this last tendency more visible, incidentally, than among the intellectualpartisansof the working classes. To accountsatisfactorilyfor the powerfulthrusttowardconflictive pluralism exhibited in practically all countries in the present world, and certainly in countriesin the latersequencesof economic change, wouldcall for a deeperand more extensive explanationthanthe accountI have given here. It would start,I think, with the conjecturethat concrete humanexperiences provide a narrow base for creating strong identifications and attachmentsthat extend much outside the small, specific, and idiosyncraticcluster of human beings with whom each of us is most intimatelyassociatedduringthe importantoccasions of our lives. Whateverthe explanationmay be, the importantpoint is not that "class" is unimportantbut ratherthat, however it may be measured, in practically all countrieswhere oppositions are relatively free to organize and express themselves, "class" in its variousmanifestationsis only an element, albeit nearly always a significantone, in a fragmentedpatternof cleavages andconflicts that is persistentlypluralisticand not bipolar, much less consensual. So far I have emphasized the prevalence of conflictive pluralism. But it would be wrong to suppose that the amount of latent conflict available for expression when the barriersto oppositions are lowered is approximatelythe same in every country. Whatis known from studiesof particularcountriesand 193 Comparative Politics January 1978 from such cross-nationaldataas now exist stronglysupportsthe hypothesisthat thereexist significantvariationsin the amountof conflictive pluralismamong countrieswith similarregimes, particularlyamong polyarchies,and withinthe same countryover long periods. The socioeconomic order It is reasonableto ask whether a high degree of organizationalpluralismis, at least in moderntimes, so exclusively a productof capitalismthatit would necessarilydisappearin an economic orderthatboth in theoryandpracticetook for grantedthe fact thatgiantfirmsarenecessarilyboth public enterprisesand political systems. In particular,would a high degree of organizationalpluralism necessarily vanish in an order where the principal meansof productionwere socially ratherthanprivatelyowned-in, then, what would ordinarilybe called a socialist economic order? Although such a view is widely held, it seems to me unambiguouslyfalse, and rests upon a theoretical confusion that makes ownership equivalent to control. Advocatesof capitalism,like theirsocialistcritics, have often assumed thatprivateownershipis both a necessaryand a sufficientconditionfor control of the enterpriseby the owners; conversely, ownershipby the governmentof the state is thoughtto be botha necessaryand a sufficientconditionfor control by the government of the state. If an enterprise is privately owned, it is assumed, then of course the owners make the key decisions, either directlyor throughmanagerswho are no more than agents. If enterprisesare owned by society, the government,the people, or the workers,then it mustfollow thatthe decisions of enterpriseswill be made by society, the government,the people, the workers. This is an egregious error, simple-mindedin its concepts and tragic in its consequences. For experience in this century has conclusively demonstrated that ownershipis definitely not a sufficient condition for control. One cannot even be certainthat a particularform of control requiresa particularform of ownership.Publiclyor socially ownedenterprisesrangeall the way fromhighly hierarchicalsystems of managerialdominance,whereeven tradeunions areof negligible importance-as in the Soviet Union-to the system of selfmanagementor workers' control practicedin Yugoslavia. If we accept the axiom thatin general a specific form of ownershipis not a sufficient condition for a specific control relationship (and may not be a necessarycondition), then the question of control is theoreticallypriorto the question of ownership. (Unfortunately,this has rarely been appreciatedin controversiesover capitalism vs. socialism.) Seen in this perspective, what capitalismdid in theory, and in substantialmeasurein practice,was to inauguratea system of decentralizedcontrolover economic organizationsthatwere to a relativelyhigh degree autonomousvis-a-vis the centralgovernmentand one another.If socialism by definitionentails social ownershipof economic enterprises, andunless by definitionit mustbe centralized,then a socialisteconomy 194 Robert A. Dahl can be highly decentralizedand thereforepluralistic. A socialist government might well elect to grantextensive autonomyto enterprisesin orderto permit internal controls far more democratic than have ever existed either under capitalismor in centralizedsocialist systems like the U.S.S.R. Obviously no socialist government-probably no government-would eliminate all external controls, whetherby markets,the governmentof the state, or both. A decentralizedsocialist ordermight nonethelessgeneratejust as much organizational pluralismas exists in any nonsocialistorder, and perhapsa good deal more. Nor is organizationalpluralismin a socialist ordernecessarily at odds with Marxism.On this as on so manyotherquestionsthe corpusof Marx's work is, taken as a whole, ambiguous. For half a century, Marxistswho looked to the Soviet Union as the very embodiment of Marxist verities assumed that a socialist order must necessarily operate as a centralizedcommandeconomy. Yet there are passages in Marx that lend eloquent support to the idea that socialism would be highly decentralized. Again, the experienceof Yugoslaviaafterturningaway from Stalinismin the 1950s lends supportto a perspectiveon Marxismthatcannotbe lightly dismissed as simply hereticalor cryptocapitalistapologetics. Unless one is preparedto argue that by definition the Yugoslav economy is capitalist (or anyway nonsocialist) andthatby definitionYugoslav Marxistsare not real Marxists,one is compelledto concludethatMarxismas interpretedby some Marxistsis compatible with a high degree of organizationalpluralism, and socialism with a comparativelyhigh degree of organizationalautonomy. To understandthe really crucial alternatives,for both the political and the economic order, one must focus on control, not ownership. In sorting out economic alternatives,the key question is not whetheran orderis socialist or nonsocialist (though that may be an importantsecondaryquestion) but how much autonomyis permittedto economic enterprisesand the natureof internal and externalcontrols. A nonsocialist, privately-ownedeconomy can be dominated by a hegemonic political order that closely regulates the activities of economic enterprises, as in Nazi Germanyduring war time. Conversely the experience of Yugoslavia, even if it is unique up to now, demonstratesthat a socialist economic order can be highly decentralized and organizationally pluralistic. A shift from capitalismto socialism, then, need not necessarily reduce the amountof organizationalpluralismin a country.It is altogetherpossible thatin some countries(the United States mightbe one) where importantdecisions are strongly influenced by giant corporationshierarchicallydominated by their managers,the inaugurationof a decentralizedsocialisteconomy-in which, for example, the decisions of an economic enterprisewere made accordingto the principles of full proceduraldemocracy, where all persons employed by the firm (and only those) enjoyed rights of citizenship in the governmentof the 195 ComparativePolitics January 1978 firm-would result in an increase, not a decrease, in the number and autonomy of economic organizations. To sum up: The amountof organizationalpluralismin a countrydoes not dependon whether the economic order is capitalist, in the sense that the enterprisesare privately ratherthan publicly or socially owned. It does depend on the extent to which decisions are decentralized, that is, on the amount of autonomy permittedto enterprises.And the amountof autonomypermittedto enterprisesappearsto be theoreticallyindependentof forms of ownership, hence of capitalism and socialism as such. A capitalistordermay be, but need not be, highly decentralized. A socialist order may be, but need not be, highly centralized. Regime Suppose there were a country with a remarkable degree of diversity among its people on a very considerable number of characteristics: language, religion, ideology, region, ethnic group, national identification, race, etc. To prevent the manifestation of these cleavages in political life would doubtless require a regime in which a small set of unified rulers is in a position to mobilize an overwhelming preponderance of political resources for their own use and for the maintenance of a severely hierarchical bureaucracy, and to deny to everyone else practically all access to political resources. Given a highly hegemonic regime of this kind, no public conflict would appear and the underlying predisposition toward conflictive pluralism would remain unmanifest. Suppose now that the barriers to oppositions were gradually reduced. It would be reasonable to expect that as the barriers went down, relatively autonomous organizations would spring up, and that some of these organizations would seek to advance the claims of the hitherto politically latent groups and subcultures. Up to some point, the more the barriers to organization and participation were reduced, the greater would be the proliferation of relatively autonomous organization. In time, no doubt, a limit would be reached and more stable patterns would emerge. Fortunately, historical experience provides us with a nice laboratory for exploring these conjectures. For the fact is that something very much like this did occur in Italy, Austria, Germany, and Japan after the displacement of hegemonic regimes in those countries as World War II came to a close. De-Stalinization in Yugoslavia after 1950 also led to a great multiplicity of interest groups. To take another example, a rich organizational life began to proliferate in Czechoslovakia during the famous Prague Spring of 1968. Finally, Portugal offers a current, if still unfinished, experiment. And the reverse development often occurs when leaders establish hegemonic control over the government, destroy all autonomous organizations, prevent the manifestation 196 RobertA. Dahl of publicconflict, and build a hierarchicalstructureof orderand cohesion over the remains of the silenced opposition. It is importantto keep in mind that whether the movement is toward organizationalpluralismor away from it, the process need not come to rest either in a highly hegemonic regime at the one extreme or in a comparatively open polyarchy at the other. It may simply stop somewhere along the way. Consequently a regime may be rather "pluralistic" without being highly "democratic.'"Not only do polyarchiesvary in the amountof conflictive and organizationalpluralism they exhibit but, as Juan Linz has shown, so do hegemonies .2 Yet it would be an egregious mistaketo supposethatthe extent of organizational pluralism has nothing to do with the nature of the regime. As our illustrationsare intendedto show, in the same countryin a period of time too shortfor significantchanges to occur in the latentpatternof social cleavages, changesin regimehave resultedin enormouschangesin the amountof manifest organizationalpluralism.Indeed, one of the most strikingdifferences among regimesin the modernworldis to be foundpreciselyin theextentto which those who oppose the conduct of the government of the state are permitted to organize, expressthemselves, andparticipatein political life. Let me continue to use the term"polyarchy"to referto a regimein which the rightto participate is broadly extended and the institutionalguaranteesto oppositions are, by historicalstandards,comparativelystrongand the-barriersto oppositionscomparatively low. Let me continue to use the term "hegemonic" for regimes where the institutional guarantees are weak or absent and the barriersto oppositions high.3 The propositionI now wish to advance is that: Organizationalpluralismis ordinarilya concomitant,bothas cause andeffect, of the liberalizationand democratizationof hegemonic regimes. In particular,the comparativelyhigh level of institutionalguaranteescombined with the broad inclusiveness that (by definition) together characterize polyarchy are inevitably associated with extensive organizationalpluralism. The guaranteesof the rightto form andjoin organizations,freedomof expression, the right to vote, the right of political leaders to compete publicly for support, particularly in elections; the existence of alternative sources of information-all these are importantconditions for the growth of organizations, particularlypoliticalorganizations,for they both heightenthe incentives for forming political organizationsand reduce the costs of doing so. Hence: Given essentiallythe same latentpatternof cleavages in a country,if its regime is polyarchalit will exhibitmoreconflictive andorganizationalpluralismthanif it is hegemonic. 197 Comparative Politics January 1978 Concrete political institutions Althoughthe concretepolitical institutionsof a countryare of course partlydeterminedby the natureof the regime and the extent of conflictive pluralism,they can also makean independentcontribution to the numberandautonomyof organizationsin a country.These consequences are perhapsmost visible in polyarchies, among which there are markedvariations in political institutions.Threekinds of variationsseem to be particularly significantfor their effects on organizationalpluralism.First, multipartysystems of course increase the number,if not the autonomy, of political parties. Second, in some polyarchies, such as Switzerland and the United States, constitutionalnormsand political practicesprovide for an extensive partitioning of governmentalauthorityby means of both federalismand separationof powers;the resultis to increasethe numberand autonomyof governmentaland other political organizations.In other polyarchies, such as New Zealand and Britain, there is much less constitutionalpartitioning;a unitaryratherthan a federal system, combined with parliamentarygovernmentratherthan a strict separationof powers betweenexecutive and legislative, makefor considerably greaterconcentrationof governmentalauthorityand correspondinglyless organizationalpluralismamonggovernmentaland otherpolitical organizations. Finally, the numberor the relative autonomy of organizationsis also increased by the institutionsand practices of "consociational democracy," as practicedin the Netherlands(even if the degree of conflictive pluralismthat originally stimulated the growth of these institutions has waned), and by systems of "corporate pluralism" or "democratic corporatism" that have developed, and may be increasing in strength, in Norway, Sweden, and elsewhere. Because each of these threesourcesof variationin concretepolitical institutions seems to be capable of varying independentlyof the others over a wide range, and becausethe concreteinstitutionsof a particularcountryalso change fromtime to time, even amongcountrieswith essentially similarregimes, such as polyarchies, differences in concrete political institutionshelp to create a staggeringvarietyin the specific patternsof organizationalpluralismexisting in differentcountries. Problems Any specific constellationof organizationalpluralismis, then, a highly complex phenomenon.The particularconstellationsvary in importantways from one country to another. A good deal of evidence appears to support the hypothesis that: In different countries, the constellation of organizationalpluralism varies in amount, in inclusiveness, and in the patternof cleavages and conflicts in which organizationsparticipate.Countrieswith similar regimes, e.g., polyarchies or hegemonies, may have significantly different constellations of organizational 198 Robert A. Dahl pluralism. Moreover, although some degree of organizationalpluralism is a necessary condition for polyarchy and a fairly high degree of organizational pluralismappearsto be a consequenceof the institutionalguaranteesand exclusiveness of polyarchy, the particularconstellation of organizationalpluralism presentin a given countrywith a polyarchalregime is not necessarilyessentialto maintainpolyarchy, and may be undesirableon other grounds. Inequality In particular,it is prettywidely held that in its effects on decisionmakinginstitutions,organizationalpluralismin polyarchiesoften fails to meet reasonablecriteriafor equality and, partly but not wholly as a result, for a broader"public" or general interest. It is hardlyopen to doubtthat organizational pluralismand the institutionalguaranteesof polyarchyare not sufficient conditions for a high degree of equality in the distributionof control over the governmentof the state or other organizations,or the distributionof political resources, or, more broadly, status, income, wealth, and other key values. Stasis This conclusion would be less consequential, no doubt, if it could be shown that organizationalpluralism is a dynamic force with a more or less steady thrust toward the reduction of inequalities. I am not aware of any theoreticalreasoningthathas been advancedon behalfof the existence of such a dynamicforce. Over againstthis possibility, therearegroundsfor thinkingthat despite markedinequalities in control over the governmentof the state in a polyarchy, organizationalpluralismmay sometimes develop a self-sustaining patternover fairly lengthy periods. A stable system can develop in which the most disadvantagedare unorganizedor poorly organized and thereforecomparatively powerless to remedy their condition; in which, more broadly, a stable patternof inequalityin the distributionof majorvalues is preserved,at least in part, by the resultsof organizationalpluralism;in which majorpublic problems go unsolved because every solution that does not have substantial agreementamong all the organizedforces is, in effect, vetoed; in which public policies in every sector are prettyclearly not determinedby considerationof what mightserve the best interestsof the greaternumberbut resultinsteadfrom the play of organizedgroups,each concernedexclusively with its own interests; in which, finally, some such perceptionas this of the way the system operates becomes widely diffusedandleads to disillusionanddiscontentnot merelywith the particularsystem of organizedpluralismthat creates stasis and its consequences but with the constitutionalstructureof the polyarchy, and more, to polyarchy in general or even to the desirabilityand feasibility of democracy itself. So: A particularconstellationof organizationalpluralismcan producea stablesystem in which mutualvetoes preventthe reductionof inequalitiesand, moregenerally, structuralchanges in the status quo. 199 ComparativePolitics January 1978 For most polyarchies, no doubt, my portraitis overdrawn. But there is enough resemblanceto conditionsin many, includingmy own, to cause one to wonder how a stable equilibriumof inequalitiesmight be overcome. Solutions and Their Difficulties Quite possibly thereis no generalsolution. That is, desirablesolutions may be specific to a particularsituation or country. However, some of the most commonly offered solutions run into serious difficulties of their own. Substance: Common interests versus particular interests One common genre of solutions looks to the discovery of a broad, overarching public, national, collective or general interest (or good) that, if it were properly understood,would clearly specify the properdecision to be made in cases of conflicting andparticularisticclaims. The properdecision mightspecify which claim is to be given priority, or an outcome transcendingall the particular claims. If everyonewere to know the generalgood, andgive priorityto it, then presumablythe autonomousorganizationswould no longer oppose changes aimed at the common good. Inequalitiesthatremainedwould be the resultless of the relativestrengthsof the variousorganizationsinvolved in a conflict than of some broaderprincipleof justice or generalgood deliberatelyadoptedby all the membersof the polity, and concurredon by the variousorganizedforces. In this view, a greatdeal of conflict comes aboutbecause of disagreements thatare, at base, irrational.These conflicts arise because the social consciousness of some or all of the political actors is, so to speak, deformed. Irrationalities occur because some people simply misunderstandthe nature, causes, and consequencesof mattersin dispute;or they neglect their long run interestsin favor of their immediateinterests;or they unwittinglysacrifice the interestsof theirbroader,more social selves to the claims of a narrowerself identifiedwith the primaryindividualego, or the family, the kin group,or some other narrowsocial fragment. If all thepartiesto a conflict alwaysunderstoodtheirtrueor realinterests,it is argued, many conflicts would vanish. At the very least, betterunderstanding would facilitatea searchfor and the discovery of mutuallybeneficial solutions to conflicts. Fromthis perspective,then, properlyconductedinquirywill lead to betterknowledge of the true natureof self and society, and this knowledge will in turn help to foster harmonyratherthan conflict. Unhappily,this proposalis less a solution than it is a prescriptionto search for a solution. All assertionsas to the specific natureof a general, collective, public, or national interest are, unless they are merely vacuous, themselves likely to become mattersof publiccontroversy.I don't meanto say thatthe idea of the generalgood is meaninglessbutonly thatit inherentlyinvolves debatable philosophicalassumptions,togetherwith judgmentsof fact andvalue that will 200 Robert A. Dahl ordinarilytransforminto a controversialpolitical question any claim publicly advancedon behalfof a specific policy said to be in the public interestor for the generalgood. I have yet to runacross a propositionaboutthe generalgood that is concrete enough to specify outcomes and not highly controversial. More specifically, argumentsattemptingto demonstrateto membersof an advantagedmajoritythattheirbest interestsrequirethem to make sacrifices in favor of a relativelydisadvantagedminority,convincing as they seem to their advocates, are not necessarily convincing to the majority. Nor do advocates fare betterwho seek to demonstratethat a relativelyprivileged minorityought in its own interests to yield some of its benefits in favor of a relatively disadvantagedgroup, whether another minority or a majority. Anyone who puts forthargumentsof this kindis eitherignoredor soon embroiledin political controversy.What seem to be crystalline, self-evident truthsto advocates are falsehoods to their opponents. In a concrete sense, then, advocates and opponents of particularchanges are partisans. If they organize to further their respective demands, they simply foster organizationalpluralism. Thus what sets out to be a way of ending conflicts among organizedgroups may only deepen an existing cleavage or create a new one. In the absence of general agreementon the substantivecontent of a transcendentpublic good, each group strives to impose its policies on the rest. This is why I statedearlierthat solutionsof the kindI have been considering seem reduciblemerelyto recommendationsthatin all cases of conflict a search ought to be made for mutuallybeneficial and mutuallyacceptableoutcomes. These proposalsdon't and evidently can't guaranteethat mutuallybeneficial and acceptable outcomes will actually be discovered. To search for such outcomes seems to me desirable,butunless we aretold whatpoliticalprocesses and structureswill increase the likelihood of discovering and bringing about such outcomes, if andwhenthey exist, an exhortationto searchfor the common good does not take one very far. Structures: Centralization versus decentralization Anotherkind of solution fills the void of the firstby specifyingchangesin politicalstructuresthat, it is thought, would lead to the reductionof inequalities. Typically, structural solutions require either greater centralizationand hierarchic controls over subsystems or greaterdecentralizationand democratizationof subsystems. Let me briefly clarify what I mean by centralizationand decentralization.If organizationsare subsystemsin some largersystem of controls, then thatmore inclusive system is decentralizedto the extent that its subsystemsare autonomous. By definition,A is autonomousin relationto B, with respectto some set of actions x, to the extent that B does not control A with respect to x. (To simplify, I am going to omit the phrase "with respect to x." However, referenceto a scope,x, is always implied.) Also by definition, if A's autonomy increases in relation to B, then B 's control over A decreases. Sometimes one subsystem controls all the rest, but not necessarily com201 Comparative Politics January 1978 pletely. Let me call a special subsystem of this kind the "Center." Then startingfrom any given situation, to decentralize means to increase the autonomyof othersubsystemsin relationto the Center.By definition, decentralization also means a decrease in the Center's control of the subsystems. To centralize means exactly the reverse. Now it is sometimes arguedthat because organizationalpluralismleads to unacceptableinequalities and prevents the adoption of policies designed to reduceinequalities,the solutionis to reducethe autonomyof organizationsand to increase the control of a Center. In relation to private organizationsthe Center is ordinarilythe governmentof the state. In relation to governmental organizations,the Centeris usuallythe leadershipof the governmentalbureaucratichierarchies.Advocatesof this solutiontypicallyproposegreatercentralization of control in the government and a correspondingreduction in the autonomyof business firms and certainother organizations.Within the government,they advocategreatercentralizationof control in the chief executive and a correspondingreductionin the autonomyof governmentbureaucracies. Some advocates of the centralizingstrategyrecommendthe abandonmentof polyarchy itself, arguing that polyarchy is inherently too pluralistic; they recommendthe adoptioninsteadof a highly centralizedhegemonic regimeand a commandeconomy. Only so, they argue, is it possible to reduceunacceptable inequalities in both the opportunitiesand rewardsthat are generatedby any modern industrialor "post industrial"society. Whether the solution of centralizationis intended to preserve and even strengthenpolyarchy, or to transformpolyarchy into a hegemonic regime, it faces one grave difficulty. As we have seen, centralizationmeans that the autonomy of certain subsystems is reduced and the control of the Center is increased. To increase the control of the Center requires that the political resourcesof the Centerbe increasedrelativeto the resourcesof the subsystems. If the Center is the central leadershipin the governmentof the state, as this solution usually prescribes,these political resourceswill ordinarilyinclude an increasein the access to the means of coercion availableto the centralleaders. The more the subsystemsmustbe deprivedof theirautonomyin orderto bring about the reallocations necessary if greater equality is to be achieved, the greatermust be the resourcesof control, including coercion, available to the leaders at the Center. At the limit, subsystemswill have no autonomyand no resources for resisting the control of the central leaders. To say thatothersubsystemshave little autonomyand little controlover the Centeris to say that the political system is based on a high degree of political inequality. Since reciprocalcontrols by others are weak or absent, the incentives of the centralleadersto reduceinequalitiesaregeneratedonly by theirown consciences and ideology. Historically, over the long run these have been weak, particularlyas new generationsof leaders succeed to top positions in a centralized system. The leaders at the Center are free to redirect privileges 202 Robert A. Dahl toward themselves, or more generally to their own political stratum,ruling class, or elite group. Given the weakeningclaims of conscience and ideology, they generally do. They may further intensify the system of privilege by recruitingtheirsuccessorsmainlyfromtheirown stratum,including,of course, their own children. Thus a strat egy of centralizationthatis initiallyjustifiedas a way of reducing inequalitiesrunsa seriousriskof establishinga systemthatnot only is basedon a high degreeof political inequalitybut in due time facilitatesthe development of socially and economically privileged ruling elite as well. Faced by this prospect,or perhapseven the reality, one may recommendan alternativestrategyof decentralization,together with the democratizationof relatively autonomoussubsystems, whethergovernmental,partisan-political, economic, or other. Muchas I preferthis approachto the other, I am compelled to confess that it also has difficulties. Except under highly unusual circumstances,the resourcesof the varioussubsystemsare likely to vary. Differences in resourcesarise from variationsin skills, energies, culturalqualities, previousaccumulationsand investments,scarcities, markets,readilyavailable naturalresources, and many other factors. Thus each subsystem might be internallydemocratic,and the principlesof distributionand allocation within each subsystemmightbe acceptedas perfectlyjust by all the membersof each organization, yet if there were no central controls over distributionsand allocations, social and economic inequalities would surely arise among the membersof differentorganizations. To reduceinequalitieseven amonghighly democraticsubsystemsandtherefore among the membersof differentsubsystemsrequirescentralizedcontrols over allocations, limits of some sort on organizationalautonomy. How much and what kinds? Are there trade-offs among different forms of inequalitypolitical, economic, social, and other? If so, what principles of distributive justice should guide decisions and what do these principlesrequire?In short, which trade-offsare acceptable, which unacceptable? I doubtwhetheranswerscan be foundthatareappropriatefor manydifferent situations and many different countries. Wherever people are free to raise questionssuchas these, the answersarelikely to become, implicitlyat least, the subject of political controversy. NOTES 1. JosephLaPalombara,Politics WithinNations (EnglewoodCliffs, 1974), pp. 440 ff. Robert A. Dahl, ed. Political Oppositionsin WesternDemocracies (New Haven, 1966), pp. 380 ff. Dahl, ed. Regimes and Oppositions (New Haven, 1973), pp. 14 ff. MorrisJanowitz and John Segal, "Social CleavageandPartyAffiliation:Germany,GreatBritain,andthe UnitedStates," American Journal of Sociology, LXXII (May 1967), 601-18. S M. Lipset and Stein Rokkan, eds. Party Systemsand VoterAlignments(New York, 1967). 2. JuanJ. Linz, "TotalitarianandAuthoritarianRegimes," in FredI. GreensteinandNelson W. Polsby, eds. Handbookof Political Science, vol. 3, MacropoliticalTheory (Reading, [Mass.], 1975), pp. 175-411, particularlypp. 277 ff. 3. Dahl, Polyarchy, Participationand Opposition (New Haven, 1971), pp. 1-13. 203