angelaki
Transcription
angelaki
ANGELAKI journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:53 21 November 2015 T his special issue of Angelaki – the second of three on the theme of “philosophical ethology” – is devoted to the work of Vinciane Despret. It comes between an earlier issue of Angelaki 19.3 (2014) dedicated to the writings of Dominique Lestel, and a forthcoming issue devoted to the writings of Roberto Marchesini. Despret is a Belgian philosopher who has been writing for over twenty years on human– animal relations. She is maître de conf érence in the Department of Philosophy at the Université de Liège, and maître de conf érence in the Department of Social Sciences and Labour Sciences at the Université Libre de Bruxelles. She studied philosophy and psychology at the Université de Liège, has undertaken field studies in Belgium, France, Israel, England, and Portugal, and has been a visiting speaker around the world. Despret is the author of numerous books and essays in French on the history and philosophy of psychology and ethology, human–animal relations, and feminism. Over the course of her career she has collaborated with many humans (academic and non-academic, experts and amateurs) and non-humans (in the field, in laboratories, on farms) on a variety of projects associated with her interest in animal behaviour. They include well-known theorists and artists (e. g., Isabelle Stengers, Jocelyne Porcher, filmmaker Didier Demorcy, choreographer Luc Petton), as well as unknown, though no less important, farmers, breeders, scientists, and conservationists. Animal collaborators have included birds, sheep, apes, elephants, rats, horses, and many, many more. However, despite her popularity at home – she is widely read, has a EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION brett buchanan matthew chrulew jeffrey bussolini VINCIANE DESPRET weekly radio show in Belgium, and has recently been named Wallonne Person of the Year – her writings on animals remain relatively unknown to English-speaking audiences.1 This issue thus aims to provide a broad introduction to her work. Most of this issue comprises translated excerpts from each of Despret’s major books on ethology: Naissance d’une théorie éthologique (1996), Quand le loup habitera avec l’agneau (2002), Hans, le cheval qui savait compter (2004), Être bête (with Jocelyne Porcher, 2007), Bêtes et hommes (2007), Penser comme un rat (2009), and Que diraient les animaux, si … on leur posait les bonnes questions (2012).2 We also ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020001-3 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039819 1 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:53 21 November 2015 editorial introduction include a new piece by Despret written for her public radio programme; a new prefatory essay by Donna Haraway, “A Curious Practice,” written specifically for this issue; an interview with Despret; and an expository essay introducing some of the central tenets of her philosophical ethology. We are pleased to include art images by many friends and collaborators of Despret, including Edmond Baudoin, Luc Petton, Michel Meuret and Gilles Lacombe. Each of these artists has collaborated with Despret, and she with them, on projects involving dance, painting, drawings, photography, film, mixed-media, and artefacts. Together, these artists and theorists, humans and animals, explore human–animal relations in situations that are at times staged, choreographed and/or improvised, at other times in the field, museums, and/or laboratories, and that reside in our imaginations just as much as in our actions. The cover image is Light Bird 19, choreographed by Luc Petton and photographed by Virginie Pontisso. Cover image: Light Bird 19 © Choreography: Luc Petton, Photography: Virginie Pontisso 2015. notes Page 15: Light Bird 4 © Choreography: Luc Petton, Photography; Virginie Pontisso 2015. Despret, Vinciane. Our Emotional Makeup: Ethnopsychology and Selfhood. Trans. Marjolijn de Jager. New York: Other, 2004. Print. Despret, Vinciane. Penser comme un rat. Versailles: Quæ, 2009. Print. Despret, Vinciane. Quand le loup habitera avec l’agneau. Paris: Le Seuil, 2002. Print. Despret, Vinciane. Que diraient les animaux, si … on leur posait les bonnes questions? Paris: La Découverte, 2012. Print. Despret, Vinciane, and Jocelyne Porcher. Être bête. Arles: Actes Sud, 2007. Print. Stengers, Isabelle, and Vinciane Despret. Women Who Make a Fuss: The Unfaithful Daughters of Virginia Woolf. Trans. April Knutson. Minneapolis: Univocal, 2014. Print. list of figures in this issue 1 A number of essays have been translated into English, and a translation of Que diraient les animaux, si … is forthcoming from University of Minnesota Press. Page 33: Meuret 1 © Michel Meuret 2013. 2 Not included in this issue are excerpts from Despret’s two other books, both of which have already been translated into English and neither of which treat philosophical ethology specifically. See Our Emotional Makeup and Women Who Make a Fuss. Page 55: Meuret 14 © Michel Meuret 2013. Page 35: Meuret 2 © Michel Meuret 2013. Page 53: Meuret 4 © Michel Meuret 2013. Page 73: Meuret 10 © Michel Meuret 2013. Page 75: Meuret 6 © Michel Meuret 2013. Page 87: Meuret 3 © Michel Meuret 2013. Page 89: Meuret 5 © Michel Meuret 2013. Page 101: Meuret 8 © Michel Meuret 2013. bibliography Page 103: Meuret 9 © Michel Meuret 2013. Despret, Vinciane. Bêtes et hommes. Paris: Gallimard, 2007. Print. Page 111: Charlottenberg © Gilles Lacombe 2007. Despret, Vinciane. Hans, le cheval qui savait compter. Paris: Le Seuil, 2004. Print. Page 113: Défense danoise © Gilles Lacombe 2007. Despret, Vinciane. Naissance d’une théorie éthologique: La Danse du cratérope écaillé. Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond, 1996. Print. Page 119: Edmond Baudoin’s La Loutre et le pisciculteur © Christophe Raynaud de Lage 2007. 2 buchanan, chrulew & bussolini Page 135: Meuret 13 © Michel Meuret 2013. Page 149: Meuret 7 © Michel Meuret 2013. Page 151: Meuret 12 © Michel Meuret 2013. Page 163: Swan 1 © Choreography: Luc Petton, Photography: Laurent Philippe 2012. Page 179: Swan 4 © Choreography: Luc Petton, Photography: Laurent Philippe 2012. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:53 21 November 2015 Page 181: Swan 5 © Choreography: Luc Petton, Photography: Laurent Philippe 2012. Brett Buchanan Department of Philosophy School of the Environment Laurentian University 935 Ramsey Lake Road Sudbury Ontario P3E 2C6 Canada E-mail: [email protected] Matthew Chrulew Centre for Culture and Technology Research and Graduate Studies Faculty of Humanities Curtin University GPO Box U1987 Perth, WA 6845 Australia E-mail: [email protected] Jeffrey Bussolini Sociology – Anthropology Department City University of New York 2800 Victory Boulevard Staten Island, NY 10314 USA E-mail: [email protected] ANGELAKI journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:57 21 November 2015 Interesting research is research conducted under conditions that make beings interesting. Vinciane Despret, personal communication To think with an enlarged mentality means that one trains one’s imagination to go visiting. Hannah Arendt, Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy 43 V inciane Despret thinks-with other beings, human and not. That is a rare and precious vocation. Vocation: calling, calling with, called by, calling as if the world mattered, calling out, going too far, going visiting. Despret listened to a singing blackbird one morning – a living blackbird outside her particular window – and that way learned what importance sounds like. She thinks in attunement with those she thinks with – recursively, inventively, relentlessly – with joy and verve. She studies how beings render each other capable in actual encounters, and she theorizes – makes cogently available – that kind of theory and method. Despret is not interested in thinking by discovering the stupidities of others, or by reducing the field of attention to prove a point. Her kind of thinking enlarges, even invents, the competencies of all the players, including herself, such that the domain of ways of being and knowing dilates, expands, adds both ontological and epistemological possibilities, proposes and enacts what was not there before. That is her worlding practice. She is a philosopher and a scientist who is allergic to denunciation and hungry for discovery, needy for what must be known and built together, with and for earthly beings, living, dead, and yet to come. Referring both to her own practice for observing scientists and also to the practices of PREFACE donna haraway A CURIOUS PRACTICE ethologist Thelma Rowell observing her Soay sheep, Despret affirmed “a particular epistemological position to which I am committed, one that I call a virtue: the virtue of politeness” (“‘Sheep Do Have Opinions’” 360). In every sense, Despret’s cultivation of politeness is a curious practice. She trains her whole being, not just her imagination, “to go visiting.” Visiting is not an easy practice; it demands the ability to find others actively interesting, even or especially others most people already claim to know all too completely, to ask questions that one’s interlocutors truly find interesting, to cultivate the wild virtue of curiosity, to retune one’s ability to sense and respond – and to do all this politely! What is this sort of politeness? It sounds more than a little risky. Curiosity ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020005-10 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039817 5 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:57 21 November 2015 preface always leads its practitioners a bit too far off the path, and that way lie stories. The first and most important thing at risk in Despret’s practice is an approach that assumes that beings have pre-established natures and abilities that are simply put into play in an encounter. Rather, Despret’s sort of politeness does the energetic work of holding open the possibility that surprises are in store, that something interesting is about to happen, but only if one cultivates the virtue of letting those one visits intra-actively shape what occurs. They are not who/what we expected to visit, and we are not who/what were anticipated either. Visiting is a subject-and-object making dance, and the choreographer is a trickster. Asking questions comes to mean both asking what another finds intriguing and also how learning to engage that changes everybody in unforeseeable ways. Good questions come only to a polite inquirer, especially a polite inquirer provoked by a singing blackbird. With good questions, even or especially mistakes and misunderstandings can become interesting. This is not so much a question of manners but of epistemology and ontology, and of method alert to off-thebeaten-path practices. At the least, this sort of politeness is not what Miss Manners purveys in her advice column. There are so many examples of Despret learning and teaching polite inquiry. Perhaps the most famous is her visit to the Negev desert field site of the Israeli ornithologist Amotz Zahavi, where she encountered Arabian babblers who defied orthodox accounts of what birds should be doing, even as the scientists also acted off-script scientifically. Specifically, Zahavi asked in excruciating detail, what matters to babblers? He could not do good science otherwise. The babblers’ practices of altruism were off the charts, and they seemed to do it, according to Zahavi, for reasons of competitive prestige not well accounted for by theories like kin selection. Zahavi let the babblers be interesting; he asked them interesting questions; he saw them dance: Not only were these birds described as dancing together in the morning sunrise, not only were they eager to offer presents to one another, not only would they take pride in caring for each other’s nestlings or in defending an endangered comrade, but also, according to Zahavi’s depiction, their relations relied on trust. (Despret, “Domesticating Practices” 24) What Despret tells us she came to know is that the specific practices of observation, narration, and the liveliness of the birds were far from independent of each other. This was not just a question of worldviews and related theories shaping research design and interpretations, or of any other purely discursive effect. What scientists actually do in the field affects the ways “animals see their scientists seeing them” and therefore how the animals respond (34). In a strong sense, observers and birds rendered each other capable in ways not written into pre-existing scripts, but invented or provoked, more than simply shown, in practical research. Birds and scientists were in dynamic, moving relations of attunement. The behavior of birds and their observers was made, but not made up. Stories are essential, but are never “mere” stories. Zahavi seemed intent on making experiments with rather than on babblers. He was trying to look at the world with the babblers rather than at them, a very demanding practice. And the same demands were made of Despret, who came to watch scientists but ended up in a much more complex tangle of practices. Birds and scientists do something, and they do it together. They become-with each other. The world in the southern Israeli desert was composed by adding competencies to engage competencies, adding perspectives to engage perspectives, adding subjectivities to engage subjectivities, adding versions to understand versions. In short, this science worked by addition, not subtraction. Worlds enlarged; the babblers and the scientists – Despret included – inhabited a world of propositions not available before. “Both humans and babblers create narratives, rather than just telling them. They create/disclose new scripts” (31). Good questions were posed; surprising answers made the world richer. Visiting might be risky, but it is definitely not boring. 6 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:57 21 November 2015 haraway Despret’s work is full of literal collaborations, with people and with animals, not simply metaphors of thinking with each other. I admit I am drawn most by the collaborations that entangle people, critters, and apparatuses. No wonder that Despret’s work with sociologist Jocelyne Porcher and the farmers, pigs, and cows in their care, sustains me. Despret and Porcher visited cow and pig breeders on nonindustrial French farms, where the humans and animals lived in daily interaction that led sober, non-romantic, working breeders to say such things as “We don’t stop talking with our animals” (Despret, “Becoming of Subjectivity” 124).1 The question that led Despret and Porcher to the farmers circled around their efforts to think through what it means to claim that these domestic food-producing animals are working, and working with their people. The first difficulty, not surprisingly, was to figure out how to ask questions that interested the breeders, that engaged them in their conversations and labors with their animals. It was decidedly not interesting to the breeders to ask how animals and people are the same or different in general. These are people who make particular animals live and die and who live, and die, by them. The task was to engage these breeders in constructing the questions that mattered to them. The breeders incessantly “uprooted” the researchers’ questions to address the queries that concerned them in their work. The story has many turns, but what interested me most was the insistence of the breeders that their animals “know what we want, but we, we don’t know what they want” (133). Figuring out what their animals want, so that people and cows could together accomplish successful breeding, was the fundamental conjoined work of the farm. Farmers bad at listening to their animals, bad at talking to them and bad at responding were not good farmers in their peers’ estimation. The animals paid attention to their farmers; paying equally effective attention to the cows and pigs was the job of good breeders. This is an extension of subjectivities for both people and critters, “becoming what the other suggests to you, accepting a proposal 7 of subjectivity, acting in the manner in which the other addresses you, actualizing and verifying this proposal, in the sense of rendering it true” (135). The result is bringing into being animals that nourish humans, and humans that nourish animals. Living and dying are both in play. “Working together” in this kind of daily interaction of labor, conversation, and attention seems to me to be the right idiom. Continually hungry for more of Despret’s visiting with critters, their people, and their apparatuses – hungry for more of her elucidations of “anthropo-zoo-genesis” (“Body We Care For”) – I have a hard time feeling satisfied with only human people on the menu. That prejudice took a tumble when I read Women Who Make a Fuss: The Unfaithful Daughters of Virginia Woolf, which Isabelle Stengers and Vinciane Despret wrote together with an extraordinary collective of bumptious women. “Think we must!” cries this book, in concert with the famous line from Virginia Woolf’s Three Guineas. In Western worlds, and elsewhere too, women have hardly been included in the patrilines of thinking, most certainly including the patrilines making decisions for (yet another) war. Why should Virginia Woolf, or any other woman, or men for that matter, be faithful to such patrilines and their demands for sacrifice? Infidelity seems the least we should demand of ourselves! This all matters, but the question in this book is not precisely that, but rather what thinking can possibly mean in the civilization in which we find ourselves: But how do we take back up a collective adventure that is multiple and ceaselessly reinvented, not on an individual basis, but in a way that passes the baton, that is to say, affirms new givens and new unknowns? (Women Who Make a Fuss 46) We must somehow make the relay, inherit the trouble, and reinvent the conditions for multispecies flourishing, not just in a time of ceaseless human wars and genocides but also in a time of human-propelled mass extinctions and multispecies genocides that sweep people and critters into the vortex. We must preface Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:57 21 November 2015 dare “to make” the relay; that is to create, to fabulate, in order not to despair. In order to induce a transformation, perhaps, but without the artificial loyalty that would resemble “in the name of a cause,” no matter how noble it might be. (47) Hannah Arendt and Virginia Woolf both understood the high stakes of training the mind and imagination to go visiting, to venture off the beaten path to meet unexpected, non-natal kin, and to strike up conversations, to pose and respond to interesting questions, to propose together something unanticipated, to take up the unasked-for obligations of having met. This is what I have called cultivating response-ability. Visiting is not a heroic practice; making a fuss is not the Revolution; thinking with each other is not Thought. Opening up versions so stories can be ongoing is so mundane, so earth-bound. That is precisely the point. The blackbird sings its importance; the babblers dance their shining prestige; the storytellers crack the established disorder. That is what “going too far” means, and this curious practice is not safe. Like Arendt and Woolf, Despret and her collaborators understand that we are dealing with “the idea of a world that could be habitable” (Women Who Make a Fuss 159). The very strength of women who make a fuss is not to represent the True, rather to be witnesses for the possibility of other ways of doing what would perhaps be “better.” The fuss is not the heroic statement of a grand cause [ … ] it instead affirms the need to resist the stifling impotence created by the “no possibility to do otherwise, whether we want it or not,” which now reigns everywhere. (162–63) It is past time to make such a fuss. Despret’s curious practice has no truck with loyalty to a cause or doctrine; but it draws deeply from another virtue that is sometimes confused with loyalty, namely, “thinking from” a heritage. She is tuned to the obligations that inhere in starting from situated histories, situated stories. She retells the parable of the twelve camels in order to tease out what it means to “start from,” i.e., to “remain obligated with respect to that from which we speak, think, or act. It means to let ourselves learn from the event and to create from it.” In a sort of cat’s cradle with powerful fables, Despret received the parable from Isabelle Stengers, and then she relayed it to me in early 2013. I relay it back to her in this preface. To inherit is an act “that demands thought and commitment, an act that calls for our transformation by the very gift of inheriting” (Despret, “Why ‘I had not read Derrida’” 94). In his will, the father in this story left his three quarrelsome sons a seemingly impossible inheritance: eleven camels to be divided in a precise way, half to the eldest son, a quarter to the second son, and a sixth to the third. The perverse requirements of the legacy provoked the confused sons, who were on the verge of failing to fulfill the terms of the will, to visit an old man living in the village. His savvy kindness in giving the sons a twelfth camel allowed the heirs to create a solution to their difficult heritage; they could make their inheritance active, alive, generative. With twelve camels, the fractions worked, leaving over one camel to give back to the old man. Despret notes that the tale she read left actual camels out of the enlargement and creativity of finding what it means to “start from.” Those storied camels were conventional, discursive, figural beasts, whose only function was to give occasion for the problematic sons to grow in patriarchal understanding, recapitulating more than a little the history of philosophy that Despret – and I – inherited. But by listening, telling, and activating that particular story her way she makes something that was absent present. She made an interesting, curious fuss without denouncing anybody. Therefore, another heritage emerges and makes claims on anyone listening, anyone attuned. It isn’t just philosophy that has to change; the mortal world shifts. Long-legged, big-lipped, humped camels shake the dust from their hot, hardworked hides and nuzzle the storyteller for a scratch behind the ears. Despret, and because of her, we, inherit camels now, camels with their people, in their markets and places of 8 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:57 21 November 2015 haraway travel and labor, in their living and dying in worlds-at-stake, like the contemporary Gobi desert.2 We start from what is henceforth a dilated story that makes unexpected demands to cultivate response-ability. If we are to remain faithful to starting from the transformed story, we can no longer not know or not care that camels and people are at stake to each other – across regions, genders, races, species, practices. From now on call that philosophy, a game of cat’s cradle, not a lineage. We are obligated to speak from situated worlds, but we no longer need start from a humanist patriline and its breathtaking erasures and high-wire acts. The risk of listening to a story is that it can obligate us in ramifying webs that cannot be known in advance of venturing among their myriad threads. In a world of anthropozoogenesis, the figural is more likely than not to grow teeth and bite us in the bum. Despret’s philosophical ethology starts from the dead and missing as well as from the living and visible. She has studied situated human beings’ mourning practices for their dead in ways strongly akin to her practice of philosophical ethology; in both domains, she attends to how – in practice – people can and do solicit the absent into vivid co-presence, in many kinds of temporality and materiality. She attends to how practices – activated storytelling – can be on the side of what I call “ongoingness”; i.e., nurturing, or inventing, or discovering, or somehow cobbling together ways for living and dying well with each other in the tissues of an earth whose very habitability is threatened. Many kinds of failure of ongoingness crumble lifeways in our times of onrushing extinctions, exterminations, wars, extractions, and genocides. Many kinds of absence, or threatened absence, must be brought into ongoing response-ability, not in the abstract but in homely storied cultivated practice. To my initial surprise, this matter brought Despret and me together with racing pigeons, also called carrier pigeons – in French “voyageurs” – and with their avid fanciers – in French “colombophiles,” lovers of pigeons.3 I wrote an essay for Despret after an extraordinary week with her and her colleagues in the 9 chateau at Cerisy in July 2010, in which I proposed playing string figure games with companion species for cultivating multispecies response-ability (Haraway, “Jeux de ficelles”). I sent Despret a draft containing my discussion of the wonderful art-technology-environmentalactivist project by Beatriz da Costa called PigeonBlog, as well as a discussion of the communities of racing pigeons and their fanciers in southern California. Pigeon racing is a working-class men’s sport around the world, one made immensely difficult in conditions of urban war (Baghdad, Damascus), racial and economic injustice (New York, Berlin), and displaced labor and play of many kinds across regions (France, Iran, California). I care about art-design-activist practices that join diverse people and varied critters in shared, often vexed public spaces. “Starting from” this caring, not from some delusional caring in general, landed me in innovative pigeon lofts, where, it turned out, Despret, attuned to practices of commemoration, had already begun to roost. In particular, by leading me to Matali Crasset’s “Capsule” built in 2003 in the leisure park of Caudry, she shared her understanding of the power of holding open actual space for ongoing living and working in the face of threatened absence as a potent practice of commemoration.4 The Beauvois association of carrier pigeon fanciers asked Crasset, an artist and industrial designer, to build a prototype pigeon loft that would combine beauty, functionality for people and birds, and a pedagogic lure to draw future practitioners into learning demanding skills. Actual pigeons had to thrive inhabiting this loft; actual colombophiles had to experience the loft working; and actual visitors to the ecological park, which was rehabilitating exhausted farm land into a variegated nature reserve for recuperating critters and people, had to be infected with the desire for a life transformed with avian voyageurs. Despret understood that the prototype, the memorial, had to be for both the carrier pigeons and their people – past, present and yet-to-come. Neither could have existed or could endure without each other in ongoing, curious practices. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:57 21 November 2015 preface But without lovers of pigeons, without the knowledge and the know-how of men and of birds, without breeding, without mentoring, without the transmission of practices, while certainly pigeons would remain, none would be a voyageur. What it is to commemorate, then, is not to recall the animal alone, nor a practice alone, but to activate two becomings-with, an activation inscribed from the very beginning of the project. Otherwise put, what is at stake is to bring into existence those relations by which pigeons transform people into talented colombophiles, who reciprocally transform pigeons into trust-worthy voyageurs. It is that which the work commemorates. The project is charged to make a memorial in the sense of actively prolonging, actively bringing forward in time and space. (Despret, “Ceux qui insistent”)5 ••• And then Camille came into our lives, rendering present the non-linear generations of the not-yetborn and not-yet-hatched of vulnerable, co-evolving species. Proposing a relay into uncertain futures, I end this preface with a story, a speculative fabulation, which starts from a writing workshop at Cerisy in summer 2013, part of Isabelle Stengers’s colloquium on “gestes spéculatifs.” This ending of a preface will be another sort of commemoration, like all commemorations prolonging actively the stories and practices of those at stake to each other, but this time inherited from those yet to come. Gestated in SF writing practices, Camille is the keeper of memories in the flesh of a world that may become habitable again. Despret must become Vinciane for me to tell this story that makes Camille real. Companion species, we start from Camille together. Camille is one of the Children of Compost who ripen in the earth to say no to the posthuman of every time. I signed up for the afternoon workshop at Cerisy, called “narration spéculative.” The first day the organizers broke us down into writing groups of two or three participants and gave us a task. We were asked to fabulate a baby, and somehow bring the baby through five human generations. In our times of surplus death of both individuals and of kinds, a mere five generations can seem impossibly long to imagine flourishing with and for our multispecies world. Over the week, the groups wrote many kinds of possible futures in a rambunctious play of literary forms, all different, all vital. Versions abounded. Besides me, the members of my group were the filmmaker Fabrizio Terranova and Vinciane. The version I tell here is itself a speculative gesture, both a memory and a lure for a “we” that came into being by fabulating a story together one summer in Normandy. But I cannot tell exactly the same story that my cowriters would propose or remember. My story here is an ongoing speculative fabulation, not a conference report for the archives. We started writing together, and we have since written Camille stories individually, sometimes passing them back to the original writers for elaboration, sometimes not; and we have encountered Camille and the Children of Compost in other writing collaborations too. All the versions are necessary to Camille. My memoire for that workshop is an active casting of threads from and for ongoing, shared stories. Camille, Donna, Vinciane, and Fabrizio brought each other into co-presence; we render each other capable. Vinciane, Fabrizio, and I felt a vital pressure to provide our baby a name and a pathway into what was not-yet but might-be. We also felt a vital pressure to ask our baby to be part of learning, over five generations, to radically reduce the pressure of human numbers, currently set on a course to climb to ten to eleven billion by the end of the twenty-first century CE . We could hardly approach the five generations through a story of heteronormative reproduction (to use the ugly but apt American feminist idiom)! More than a year later, I realized that Camille taught me how to say “Make Kin Not Babies.”6 Immediately, however, as soon as we proposed the name of Camille to each other, we understood that we were now holding a squirming child who had no truck with conventional genders or with human exceptionalism. This was a child born for symbiosis and sympoiesis – for becomingwith and making-with. Luckily, Camille came into being at a moment of an unexpected but powerful, interlaced, planet-wide eruption of numerous communities of a few hundred people each, who felt moved to migrate to 10 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:57 21 November 2015 haraway ruined places and work with human and nonhuman partners to heal these places, building networks, pathways, nodes, and webs of and for a newly habitable world. Camille’s people moved to West Virginia on a site that had been devastated by mountain-top removal coal mining. They allied themselves with struggling multispecies communities in the rugged mountains and valleys, both the local people and the other critters.7 Coming from every economic class, color, religion, secularism, and region, members of the emerging diverse settlements around the earth lived by a few simple but transformative practices, which in turn lured – became vitally infectious – for many other peoples and communities. Some of the practices: every new child must have at least three parents, who may or may not practice new or old genders. Corporeal differences, along with their often fraught histories, are cherished. New children must be rare and precious, and they must have the robust company of other young and old ones of many kinds. Kin relations can be formed at any time in life, and so parents and other sorts of relatives can be added or invented at many significant points. Such relationships enact strong life-long commitments and obligations of diverse kinds. Kin making as a means of reducing human numbers and demands on the earth, while simultaneously increasing human and other critters’ flourishing, engaged the most intense energies and passions in the emerging worlds. Thus, the work of these communities is an intentional kin-making practice across deep damage and significant difference. Historical social action and cultural and scientific change – much of it activated by anti-colonial, antiracist, pro-queer feminist movement – had seriously unraveled the once-imagined natural bonds of sex and gender and race and nation, but undoing the widespread destructive commitment to the still-imagined natural necessity of the tie between kin making and a tree-like biogenetic reproductive genealogy became a key task for the Children of Compost. The decision to bring a new human infant into being is a collective one for the emerging communities, and no one can be coerced to 11 bear a child. Although not in the form of individual decision making to conceive a new baby, individual reproductive freedom is cherished. This freedom’s most treasured power is the right and obligation of the person, of whatever gender, who is carrying a pregnancy to choose an animal symbiont for the new child. All new human members of the group come into being as symbionts with critters of a specific threatened species, and therefore with the whole patterned fabric of living and dying of those particular beings and all their associates, for whom the possibility of a future is very fragile. The symbionts must also be members of migratory species, which critically shapes the lines of visiting, working, and playing for all the partners. The core of each new child’s education is learning how to live in symbiosis so as to nurture the symbiont, and all the other beings the symbiont requires, into ongoingness for at least five human generations. The symbionts keep the relays of life going, both inheriting and inventing practices of recuperation, survival, and flourishing. Because the animal partners in the symbiosis are migratory, each human child learns and lives in nodes and pathways, with other people and their symbionts, in the alliances and collaborations needed to make ongoingness possible. Literally and figurally, training the mind to go visiting is a life-long pedagogical practice in these communities. Together and separately, the sciences and arts are passionately practiced and enlarged as means to attune rapidly evolving ecological naturalcultural communities, including people, through the dangerous centuries of irreversible climate change and continuing high rates of extinction and other troubles. A treasured power of individual freedom for the new child is to choose a gender – or not – when and if the patterns of living and dying evoke that desire. Bodily modifications are normal among Camille’s people; and at birth a few genes and a few microorganisms from the symbiont are added to the child’s bodily heritage, so that sensitivity and response to the world as experienced by the animal symbiont can be more vivid and precise for the human member of the team. The animal partners are Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:57 21 November 2015 preface not modified in these ways, although the ongoing relationships with lands, waters, people and peoples, critters, and apparatuses render them newly capable in surprising ways too, including ongoing EcoEvoDevo biological changes.8 Throughout life, the human person, in our case, Camille, may adopt further bodily modifications for pleasure and aesthetics or for work, as long as the modifications tend to both symbionts’ well-being. Monarch butterflies frequent land near Camille’s West Virginia community in the summers, and they undertake a many-thousandmile migration south to overwinter in a few specific forests of pine and oyamel fir in central Mexico, along the border of the states of Michoacán and Mexico.9 Along the way, the Monarchs must eat and breed in cities, farms, forests, and fields of a vast and damaged landscape. In particular, the young of the leapfrogging Monarch migrations face the consequences of genetic and chemical technologies of mass industrial agriculture that make the indispensable food plant for larvae – native, local milkweeds – unavailable along most of the routes. Not just the presence of any milkweed but also the timing of flowering of local milkweed varieties is syncopated in the inherited flesh of Monarchs. Unhinged in time and stripped of food, larvae starve. Migrations fail. The trees in central Mexico mourn the loss of their winter shimmying clusters, and the fields of North America are desolate without the flitting shimmer of orange and black in summer. Camille’s birthing parent chose Monarch butterflies as Camille’s symbionts. That meant that Camille of the first generation, and further Camilles for four more human generations at least, would grow in knowledge and know-how committed to the ongoingness of these gorgeous and threatened insects all along the pathways and nodes of their migrations and residencies. Camille grew rich in worldly communities throughout life, as work and play with and for the butterflies made for intense residencies and active migrations with a host of people and other critters. As one Camille approached death, a new Camille would be born to the community in time so that the elder could teach the younger to be ready. At initiation, as a coming-of-age gift, the second Camille decided to ask for chin implants of butterfly feelers, a kind of tentacular beard, so that tasting the worlds of the flying insects could become the heritage of the human partner too, helping in the work and adding to the corporeal pleasures of becoming-with. All the Camilles knew the work could fail at any time. The dangers remained intense. A legacy of centuries of mostly capitalist exploitation of both people and other beings, excess extinctions and exterminations continued to stalk the earth. Still, successfully holding open space for other critters and their committed people also flourished, and multispecies partnerships of many kinds contributed to building a habitable earth in sustained troubled times. Nonetheless, after decades of heartening progress, new fungal diseases afflicting several species in the subfamily Danainae emerged too quickly for response; and near the end of life, the third Camille witnessed the loss of the Monarchs and the active patterns of living and dying they sustained. The fourth Camille thus inherited another task from the mentor, to become the Speaker for the Dead, to bring into ongoing presence, through active memory, the lost lifeways, so that other symbiotic and sympoietic commitments did not lose heart. The fourth and fifth Camilles traveled widely, drawing from their heritage of Monarch symbioses, to teach and learn how to practice healing and ongoingness in the cyclones of continuing damage. Through the practice of vital memory, the work of the Speakers for the Dead was to strengthen the healing that was gaining momentum across the earth. The Children of Compost would not cease the layered curious practice of becomingwith others for a habitable world. With Vinciane and her companions, it is time to make a fuss, time to go visiting, time to think with each other. notes 1 With courage and precision, Porcher has also studied horrific industrial pig facilities that can never be called farms. 12 haraway 2 For example, see the film The Story of the Weeping Camel (2004), directed and written by Byambasuren and Luigi Falorni. 3 Pigeons and doves constitute the bird clade Columbidae, with about 310 species. 4 For an exposition of the project and a photograph of Matali Crasset’s pigeon loft, see <http://www.artconnexion.org/espace-public-pub lic-realm/37-matali-crasset–capsule>. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:57 21 November 2015 5 Quoted in Haraway, “Jeux de ficelles” 52 (my translation). Original: Mais sans colombophile, sans savoir et savoir-faire des hommes et des oiseaux, sans sélection, sans apprentissage, sans transmission des usages, quand bien même resterait-il des pigeons, plus aucun ne sera voyageur. Ce qu’il s’agit de commémorer n’est donc pas un animal seul, ni une pratique seule, mais bien un agencement de deux “devenirs avec” qui s’inscrit, explicitement, à l’origine du projet. Autant dire, ce qu’il s’agit de faire exister, ce sont des relations par lesquelles des pigeons transforment des hommes en colombophiles talentueux et par lesquelles ces derniers transforment des pigeons en voyageurs fiables. C’est cela que l’œuvre commémore. Elle se charge de faire mémoire au sens de prolonger activement. 6 This slogan joins a litter of symbiogenetic and sympoietic provocations that lure my writing. In the 1980s, Elizabeth Bird gave me “Cyborgs for Earthly Survival.” Later, Rusten Hogness gave me “Not Posthuman but Compost!” as well as humusities rather than humanities. Camille gives us “Make Kin Not Babies.” Breaking the “necessity” of the tie between kin and reproduction is the task for feminists now. It is past time to make a fuss. Disloyal to patriarchal genealogy, we have helped disable the sense of natural necessity of the ties of race and nation, although that work is never done; and we have unraveled the bonds of sex and gender, although we are not finished there either. Feminists have been powerful players disabling the pretensions of human exceptionalism too. No wonder that there is much more collaborative work to do strengthening webs, cutting some ties and knotting others, to live and die well in a habitable world. 13 7 <http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Mountaintop_rem oval_mining>. See the film Goodbye to Gauley Mountain: An Ecosexual Love Story (http:// goodbyegauleymountain.org/). 8 Ecological Evolutionary Developmental biology, or EcoEvoDevo, was one of the most important knowledge practices to reshape the sciences in the late twentieth and early twenty-first centuries CE . 9 See <http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Monarch_ Butterfly_Biosphere_Reserve>, <http://www.nets tate.com/states/symb/butterflies/wv_monarch_but terfly.htm> and <http://www.wvdnr.gov/Wildlife/ Butterflies.shtm>; for a good map of the migrations, see <http://www.flightofthebutterflies. com/epic-migrations/> and <http://www.fws.gov/ international/animals/monarch-butterfly.html>. See also Kingsolver. Western Monarch butterflies overwinter in California, including Santa Cruz, where we avidly seek them out each year in eucalyptus and Monterey cypress groves at Natural Bridges State Park. Monarchs in Santa Cruz numbered about 120,000 in 1997 but had plummeted to 1,300 by 2009, a few dozen in 2014, and maybe a couple hundred in winter 2015 (http:// www.xerces.org/wp-content/uploads/2011/03/we stern-monarchs-factsheet.pdf). Camille’s community has ties here too. bibliography Arendt, Hannah. Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy. Brighton: Harvester, 1982. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “The Becoming of Subjectivity in Animal Worlds.” Subjectivity 23 (2008): 123–39. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “The Body We Care For: Figures of Anthropo-zoo-genesis.” Body and Society 10.2–3 (2004): 111–34. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “Ceux qui insistent.” Faire Art comme on fait societé. Ed. Didier Debaise et al. Paris: Réel, 2013. I.7. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “Domesticating Practices: The Case of Arabian Babblers.” Routledge Handbook of Human–Animal Studies. Ed. Garry Marvin and Susan McHugh. New York and London: Routledge, 2014. 23–38. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “‘Sheep Do Have Opinions.’” Trans. Liz Carey-Libbrecht. Making Things Public. preface Ed. Bruno Latour and Peter Weibel. Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 2005. 360–68. Print. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:57 21 November 2015 Despret, Vinciane. “Why ‘I had not read Derrida’: Often Too Close, Always Too Far Away.” Trans. Greta D’Amico and Stephanie Posthumus. French Thinking about Animals. Ed. Louisa Mackenzie and Stephanie Posthumus. Ann Arbor: Michigan State UP, 2015. 91–104. Print. Haraway, Donna. “Jeux de ficelles avec les espèces compagnes: rester avec le trouble.” Trans. Vinciane Despret and Raphael Larrière. Les Animaux: Deux ou trois choses que nous savons d’eux. Ed. Vinciane Despret and Raphael Larrière. Paris: Hermann, 2014. 23–59. Print. Kingsolver, Barbara. Flight Behavior. New York: Harper, 2012. Print. Stengers, Isabelle, and Vinciane Despret, and collective. Women Who Make a Fuss: The Unfaithful Daughters of Virginia Woolf. Trans. April Knutson. Minneapolis: Univocal, 2014. Print. Donna Haraway History of Consciousness Department University of California at Santa Cruz 1156 High Street Santa Cruz, CA 95064 USA E-mail: [email protected] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:58 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:58 21 November 2015 ANGELAKI Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 The best drama is written by animals, I think, and I think that it was a good choice for ethology to choose stories, not only because it’s pedagogical but because it always obliges and requests from us to remember that we are dealing with a living being, a subject with their own experience. Vinciane Despret1 I hope to feel differently. To have new percepts […] To change. Vinciane Despret2 F or over twenty years Belgian philosopher Vinciane Despret has been carving a unique path in the study of human knowledge about animals: its forms, history, limits, questions, future. And though it has led her to be a leading figure in the interdisciplinary field of animal studies, her writings are still relatively unknown to English audiences. Equally at home in philosophical discussions on Leibniz or Deleuze, ethological observations of birds or orangutans, and historical or current practices of scientific investigations and methodologies, Despret has approached the lives of animals with a refreshing and open-minded curiosity. Rather than starting out from a prescribed theoretical position and methodological base, Despret waits, like the ethologists she works with and studies, for animals to show their ways to her. She takes her lead from animals, and those who work with them: she thinks with, from, and like them, follows them, observes and learns from them, and in the process she continuously becomes transformed by them. What do they have to say? How do they behave? What questions do they ask? How are their behaviours affected by the presence of observers? Why have humans approached the study of animals in the ways brett buchanan THE METAMORPHOSES OF VINCIANE DESPRET they have? The result is a rich and diverse body of writings, with over eight books and eighty articles and counting, full of stories that demonstrate just how much more surprising, inventive, and intelligent animals are than we credit. A veritable bestiary of animals and interesting stories are found throughout Despret’s writings, and her sources are as varied as the animals themselves: she draws from field research (Arabian babblers, sheep, wolves), YouTube videos (cats, crows, lions), scientific laboratories (capuchins, rats), zoos (orangutans, baboons), rescue centres (elephants, chimpanzees), farms (pigs, goats, cows), film (parrots), literature (horses, tigers), philosophy and history (octopuses, ticks, jackdaws), and more. Despite the ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020017-16 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039818 17 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 the metamorphoses of vinciane despret slightly classificatory feel to this list, none of these stories are just about one species either. Every story is multispecied. Perhaps it’s no surprise, then, that one of her latest books is an abecedary; from A to Z, from artist to zoophilia, from ants to zebras, animals utterly permeate our languages, our thoughts and behaviours, our accounts of ourselves, our everyday lives. But Despret does not generalize or universalize. There’s no attempt at systematicity or completeness. Like Isabelle Stengers (one of Despret’s mentors), she actively resists an all-purpose explanation or theory (Que diraient; Stengers, Cosmopolitics I). And like Jacques Derrida, Despret claims that not a single animal can speak for its species, just as no species is representative of animals as such (Quand le loup 28; Buchanan, Chrulew, and Bussolini; Derrida). There is no as such. No two stories are alike, then, in the same way that no animal is just like another. Instead, one discovers a plurality of singular animals and meanings that reawaken our understandings of animal lives. Despret’s methodological approach is similarly idiosyncratic, always changing, and resists easy explanation. Like a curious investigative reporter, she has a knack for discovering, analysing, and articulating good stories. Early in her career, Despret’s work established her as both a philosopher and ethologist, albeit with a twist: as a philosopher, she’s out “in the field,” creating concepts with birds just as much as with ideas, and as an ethologist, she’s more an “ethologist of ethologists,” studying the behaviours and practices of the ethologists as much as the birds that they themselves are observing. This ability to look at particular situations in new and inventive ways, from multiple perspectives, defines Despret’s work over the ensuing decades. In one project she’ll wear the hat of a literary detective and lawyer, poring back over the infamous case of Clever Hans to unravel the testimonies of the expert witnesses (Hans); in another she’ll enter the world of rat experimentations to cast a light on the questions being asked of the rats, and the rats’ responses to this misplaced attention (Penser); in yet another she’ll work with filmmakers, installation artists, and curators to create a large exhibition in Paris on the extraordinariness of animal lives (Bêtes et hommes). Finally, it’s not just the animals that teach and inform Despret’s thoughts, even if she herself would be the first to claim that she’s learned the most from the animals themselves. Her human sources are just as wide-ranging. These include writings from the history of Western philosophy (from the Ancient Greeks to Gilles Deleuze), the practices and philosophies of contemporary science studies and animal studies (Donna Haraway, Bruno Latour, and Stengers), the science of ethologists and primatologists (Amotz Zahavi, Shirley Strum, Barbara Smuts, Marc Bekoff), historical biologists (Edward Thompson, Charles Darwin, Jakob von Uexküll), and political theorists (Karl Marx, Peter Kropotkin) as well as the oral reports and anecdotes of farmers, conservationists, caretakers, trainers, and breeders. The point is not to supply an exhaustive list of all of Despret’s influences but rather to exhibit their great diversity. It is for all of these reasons, and more, that her writings will be of interest to those working in animal studies, science studies, contemporary philosophy, cultural anthropology, social geography, political theory, religious studies, and artistic practices. Her training and experience have drawn from the academic disciplines of psychology and philosophy, and ethological fieldwork in parks, farms, laboratories, and cities throughout Europe. Throughout it all, Despret seeks something relatively simple. Simple to say, but far more difficult to achieve. She seeks transformations and metamorphoses: to transform and be transformed, to change ideas, behaviours, and habits, both her own and those of others. To view the world differently – and to take joy in its plurality – will be the sign of such an achievement. She wants, in short, no more than to let animals be interesting, and no less than to change the world, and this begins with “learning to transform our habits” and acquiring “new ways of living together” (Quand le loup 255). origins Despret admits that it is somewhat of a cliché for an author to appeal to an “origins” story 18 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 buchanan for how she or he came to have an appreciation or love for animals. Perhaps it was a family companion animal while one was young, perhaps a discovery of one’s own eating habits, or perhaps a black bear encountered along a forest trail. But this doesn’t mean there isn’t some truth in these stories, and this is no less the case with Despret herself. She has her own versions of an origins story, but there are a few caveats: on the one hand, there isn’t a single “origin” to Despret’s passion for animals, but rather many continuously unfolding origins, and on the other, these stories are not so much about her own self-awakening (as such stories tend to emphasize), but rather they are just as much about the animals themselves. In one of her most autobiographical works, Despret explains that it is a matter of performing through narration the pressing obligation that is now mine: to always attempt, by all means possible, not only not to erase the presence of the animal, but above all to avoid relegating the animal to the status of a passive object. This is a moral, political, and epistemological obligation. (“Why ‘I Had Not’” 98) This story could therefore begin with an account of Despret listening to a blackbird early one spring morning in her Liège backyard garden. Overtaken by the experience of the blackbird’s song, Despret has said that the bird sang as if the importance of the world was in its song, that this blackbird knew what importance meant, and that it was teaching Despret something about importance.3 Like many of her colleagues in ethology, she dismisses any suggestion that a sentiment such as this bears a negative mark of anthropomorphism. Human attributes are not being attributed to animals, as it may in fact be just as much a case of theriomorphism, with humans adopting the capacities and influences of the animals.4 In the present scenario, the blackbird taught Despret about the notion of importance, of being open and available to the world around her, of hearing the song, and of becoming transformed through an event as seemingly simple and routine as this. 19 This story, however, could just as easily begin when Despret showed up on the doorstep of the Israeli ornithologist Amotz Zahavi, eager to observe Arabian babblers with him in the Negev desert. Through this process she discovers that Zahavi is just as interesting as the birds themselves, so much so that her project takes off in a different direction. One of these insights is that no one is “neutral” in the study of others: neither the scientists nor the animals. Each contributes to the production of existence that brings them together, and each constructs the stories that are told (Naissance 14–22; Stengers, Invention 146). Then again, this story may begin when she first met Isabelle Stengers, and discovered that her theoretical approach to the sciences was exactly what she herself was intuitively thinking about, but had not yet been able to formulate with respect to her work with animals. Or it may start with her work with the dance choreographer Luc Petton (whose images appear in this issue), with whom she re-imagines the notion of choreography and collaborative work as they place in motion a dance involving humans and Manchurian cranes or humans with swans. In every case, Despret transforms her thinking and actions through all of her engagements. By her own admission, she gets bored by the status quo, by the same overarching generalizations, by the erasure of individual idiosyncrasies, anecdotes, and knowledges (Buchanan, Chrulew, and Bussolini). There isn’t a single “origin,” then, but multiple origins that arise as a result of the “agencement” of various agencies coming together (Despret, “From Secret Agents” 38); each origin isn’t self-produced, as though autonomously willed by Despret alone. Instead, each origin is both the commencement and consequence of a new entanglement of which she forms a part, as she becomes together with her interlocutors, both human and non-human. She listens to animals, and her writings are responses in kind. More on this below. That there isn’t just one story to be told here is likely clear, but there is one particular fable that runs its course throughout her writings. Beginning with her doctoral thesis on emotions Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 the metamorphoses of vinciane despret (Our Emotional Makeup) and continuing through to her most recent writings (Les Faiseuses; “Why ‘I Had Not’”), Despret has evoked a fable – “The Twelfth Camel” – about an old man who, anticipating his coming death, needs to leave his eleven camels to his three sons. With no easy way to divide them, the father bequeaths half to his first son, a quarter to his second son, and a sixth to his third son. Upon their father’s death, the sons are unsure how to divide up this legacy, so approach an old sage in town. The sage’s solution is to give them his own old camel, out of which the sons divide the camels into groups of six, three, and two respectively, whereupon they, having resolved their problem, return the old camel back to the sage. For Despret, this fable of the twelfth camel provides a means for thinking about how one responds to problems that stem from influences, legacies, and inheritances. The twelfth camel wasn’t a solution in and of itself to the sons’ problem but it did provide a creative means of changing the problem by constructing a new one. As explained in Our Emotional Makeup, the sons responded with an affirmative “yes” to their problem, seeking and finding solutions to a problem that in fact has no clear or identifiable solution. Instead of fighting over their inheritance, resorting to negative hostilities due to their situation, or escaping from the problem altogether, the sons sought a creative solution, one that involved the receiving and returning of a gift.5 It’s clear that this fable resonates with Despret, and it does so for at least three reasons. The principal one is that, as she puts it, I am interested in the problem: how to pinpoint what we know, how to state our practices in a way that I know will make them exist, make them change, in a way that offers them a possibility likely to be of interest to us. (Our Emotional Makeup 21) From a broadly theoretical point of view, the fable is oddly pragmatic: the sons are compelled to find the best solution possible within an otherwise unresolvable scenario. For Despret, this becomes an epistemological, ontological, and ethical challenge of discovering one’s role in a particular problem, how one contributes to the “production of existence” of knowledge and things (Naissance 22), and how changing the conditions of a problem leads it to become much more interesting. For example, what is a scientist’s interest in an experiment? What is the interest of the animals in question? How might the investigator be creating the conditions of the apparatus that he or she believes to be objective? How are the animals responding, and to what are they responding? The pragmatic practice of thought actually leads to more questions, considerable uncertainty, and greater flexibility, but it also makes the experiment, both of thought and practice, much more interesting. More specifically, the fable speaks to the ability to adapt creatively to the inheritance one receives. Despret was educated in both psychology and philosophy – and for a time worked as a therapist and clinician – but it was her curiosity with the boundless untold stories of animals that led her towards ethology. To be frank, animals became more interesting. At this juncture in her early career, however, the question of her own indebtedness to and inheritance of two or three rather distinct traditions (philosophy, psychology, ethology) placed her in a concrete quandary. As both a methodological and material dilemma, what does she actually study, and how? Does she think from her philosophical tradition, one rooted in the erudite traditions of logic, exegeses, and critical analyses, or does she think on behalf of the animals, from a tradition seen as rooted in anecdotes, subjective biases, and questionable scientific validity? The fable resonates because it pulls her out of this forced and false alternative between “pure” philosophy and “pure” ethology – with their internal mechanisms of isolating, differentiating, and separating problems – and instead presents her with the freedom to reinvent what will become, through her writings, a new practice of philosophical ethology. The fable, in other words, “put an end to the compromise I had made between two contradictory obligations: that of thinking from philosophy, and that of thinking from animals” 20 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 buchanan (“Why ‘I Had Not’” 94). It’s a false alternative – though one still very much embedded within our Western academic practices – and the fable provided a lesson that an inheritance is “an act that calls for our transformation by the very gift of inheriting” (ibid.). To understand Despret’s practices it’s also important to appreciate the subtle humour and laughter that flows through the majority of her writings. Her usage of the fable reinforces this trademark of hers, as she reads the twelfth camel to be positively affirmative, optimistic, and even comical in tone. Rather than being burdened by their inheritance, the sons find a creative solution, and in doing so proclaim a joyous “yes” to their situation. There is more than a hint of Nietzschean inspiration throughout Despret’s writings, and this fable underscores it. “I would like to attempt, then, to produce this same ‘yes,’” Despret writes, to create the conditions by which we can produce it, conditions by which we can invent a new relationship to our heritage, a new way of being worthy of it and gain trust, a new way of being in harmony with it. (Our Emotional Makeup 18–19) Like Nietzsche’s amor fati, accepting one’s lot and creating one’s future demands an inventive “yes” in place of a resigned or resentful “no”; and like Zarathustra’s three metamorphoses, which move from the burdened camel, through the defiant and critical lion, to the playful and creative child, Despret reads the fable as “child-like” in that she builds relations, starts new beginnings, and laughs along with her animals.6 These three aspects of the fable – addressing a problem with no real solution, receiving an inheritance that requires inventive shuffling, and an appreciation for surprise and humour – find their way into much of Despret’s philosophical ethology. In fact, they become the methodological foundation for her writings. versions The fable of the twelfth camel is just as significant for what it lacks as for what it gives. 21 For all of its strengths, the camel in this fable is an allegorical one, a representative symbol, and a “passive animal” at that; it’s missing, in other words, a real camel, and for this reason it remains a theoretical construct and pale version to the otherwise more fascinating, and always more interesting, worlds of real animals. This proves to be a decisive point in Despret’s thought, and it occurs quite early in her career. In point of fact, it is precisely what instigates her career in philosophical ethology. Returning to the account of the blackbird, Despret realized it was not enough to write and think about the representations of animals; it’s far more productive, and interesting, to write and think with real animals. Writing about her earliest publications, Despret notes that “[i]t goes without saying that I did not have any intention of speaking about real animals. Rather, my aim was to follow the path of representations, the symbolic” (“Why ‘I Had Not’” 98). Her own self-criticism is that she “produced many of my own monologues” and that “in ethology, and more generally in animal sciences, monologues make terrible narratives” (ibid.).7 This is a lesson that Despret learned very early on, and one she took to heart, unlike certain other theorists and philosophers who have written about literary, conceptual and otherwise imagined animals, and who would go on to become examples of rather strong indictments. Donna Haraway’s critique of Derrida and Deleuze on this point comes foremost to mind.8 Always clever, insightful, and rigorous in their thinking, Haraway contends that their animals are nonetheless fictitious animals. They are not real animals, interacting with other real animals, entangled in complex social–historical–material relations. They are not embodied animals who have the capacity to “bite back.”9 Heading out into the field was the most immediate and direct way for Despret to overcome this problem. During the summer of 1994, Despret, with only a few ethology courses behind her (one can sense her spirit of adventure and humour!), headed out to the Negev desert to study with Zahavi, the Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 the metamorphoses of vinciane despret celebrated ornithologist. Zahavi was famous for his Handicap principle, a theory that countered the common sociobiological explanation for altruism among Arabian babblers (Turdoides squamiceps), his most commonly studied bird.10 The Handicap principle provides a hypothesis for the seemingly paradoxical cases of animal nature and behaviour (e.g., the peacock’s bright tail feathers, the altruism of babblers) that is potentially “costly” and “extravagant,” and that should put the animals at risk, but actually favours them for sexual selection. As Zahavi explains, animal signals are reliable and honest in that they show what they mean to show (Despret, “Domesticating Practices”; Zahavi and Zahavi). In the case of the babblers, their social and gregarious behaviours, such as their dances and their care for nestlings that are not their own, do not emphasize cooperative family modelling, as an altruistic interpretation would have it, but individual status and strength. Zahavi suggests that the babblers’ extravagant behaviours show that an animal is actually well suited for mating since it is able to take such costly and apparently unnecessary measures. Despret’s interest was in how these birds seemed to defy common biological norms, and thus set out to study the “hybrid” formation between what Zahavi and his team of observers were “saying” about the babblers and what the babblers were “doing” (Naissance 31). In short, she wondered whether it was the birds who were eccentric, or if it was Zahavi’s own eccentricity that depicted them as such. Despret’s experience in the Negev desert has had a lasting impact on her thought, and has been raised in many of her subsequent writings.11 She has recently written that “the field ‘happened to me’” (“Domesticating Practices” 25), and in the process it transformed her and her questions. She entered the desert with the simple objective “to do in the field what philosophers did with respect to texts” (“Why ‘I Had Not’” 98), but came away from the experience with an entirely different perspective. Perhaps more than anything else her methodological approach to the study of animals changed, not only from a switch from symbolic animals to real animals but just as importantly in the kinds of questions she learned to ask. To “ask the right questions” becomes a central motif of Despret’s thought, for asking the right questions does more than attribute a different approach to the animals, it just as importantly highlights a different response from animals.12 Animals, in other words, are not “texts” awaiting hermeneutic interpretation any more than they are “objects” that can be explained through scientific experiments; both are suggestive of a detached objectivity ill-placed with respect to subjective agents. Rather, asking the right questions demonstrates a form of “politeness” towards other beings, not only giving animals the benefit of the doubt of being able to respond but doing so in a way that allows them to respond on their own terms and to answer questions that are of interest to them.13 In Thinking Like a Rat, for instance, Despret demonstrates how research with animals too often has them conforming to the preconceived expectations of the researchers – as formulated through the hypotheses guiding the research – rather than to what the animals themselves might be interested in (Penser 8; Que diraient 235–37). This can extend from the assumed gullibility of the research subjects (e.g., that rats will naively abide by the fixed parameters of the research apparatus) to an active violation of the animals themselves (e.g., removing the whiskers from a rat, or removing a dominant baboon from his troop). Politeness is a form of methodological courtesy as well as an ethical obligation. It not only allows animals to perform to their capabilities, as opposed to mechanically react according to the research apparatus, it also allows them to “collaborate” as active and curious participants in the process of discovery and learning (Penser 15). Similarly, it provides and encourages every opportunity for such collaboration to unfold (Chrulew 33; Lestel, Les Amis 34–35). This form of politeness is found through all of Despret’s writing. In her work with the sociologist Jocelyne Porcher, with whom she cowrote Être bête, Despret found that asking the right questions applies equally to those who work with animals. To ask the philosophical 22 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 buchanan question “what is the difference between humans and animals?,” as they originally did with farmers throughout parts of Europe, had very little applicability or relevance to those who work, play, train, and live with animals on a daily basis (11). The question simply made no sense. Much of their book, therefore, is about the reformulation of questions such that they can matter to both “amateurs” and animals.14 In lieu of a “difference” between humans and animals, for example, the questions became shaped by how animals and humans live “together” (12); similarly, rather than considering what separates human capacities from animal capacities, the farmers thought in terms of similarities. On the farms visited, the sheep, cattle, pigs, and dogs are all individuals, with their own personalities, friends, intentions, likes, and fears. The status quo, therefore, is that animals are similar and not dissimilar to us, and the question is instead that of wondering “what are animals capable of?” instead of what they are incapable of (30). As a methodological framework, then, “the right question” does not imply that there is the right question to ask. This isn’t a prescriptive or normative injunction, and Despret never tells her readers how to ask the right questions. The right questions are those that lead towards more questions, that leave open the possibility for others to respond on their own terms. It is not to jump ahead and anticipate how an orangutan will respond to a bunch of string and thread (Que diraient 243), just as it isn’t to assume how ravens will respond to carrion left in a forest (Quand le loup 207). The assumption of a false pretence will either result in precisely what one expects (no surprise) or disappointment in the unexpected result. By contrast, the politeness Despret extends is one of remaining “hesitant” – in limbo, as it were – towards how any animal may respond within a particular scenario. The hesitation is strategic, and draws from the thought of William James in a few ways. To begin with, Despret likens the question of “what is an animal capable of?” with “what can a body do?” Both find roots stretching back through Latour, Deleuze, James, and Spinoza, 23 but it’s specifically James’s emphasis on slowing down and holding open a question that particularly interests Despret. With his thought she finds an affable spirit with which to hesitate and slow down, and to appreciate the perplexity and ambiguity of human and animal bodies coming together to create something new and unexpected. “If we want to explore how these experiences with rats or horses are constructed,” she writes, if we want to gain an access that gives the chance for many more entities to be active, we need a theory that prevents us from deciding too quickly what is cause and what is effect, what affects and what is affected. James’s theory of emotions provides a good means to build this undetermined site. (“The Body” 125) Drawing from James, Despret notes that “[a]n emotion is not what is felt but what makes us feel” (127), such that this indeterminacy allows animals the opportunity to, as James puts it, participate in “the creative process of their own verification” (Quand le loup 26), which is to say, to play an active role in the shaping of the ideas we have of them. The hesitation – waiting, watching, learning, playing, etc. – allows animals to affect us just as much as we affect them. “Leaving it undetermined or hesitant allows many more entities to be active” (“The Body” 123). In a parallel fashion, Despret develops the concept of “version” in and around this sense of hesitation. A version, for Despret, is a particular story, account, perspective, or explanation that coexists, simultaneously and peacefully, with other multiple versions of the same event (Our Emotional Makeup 30). Properly speaking, versions exist only in the plural, as there are always multiple versions that coexist. Ontologically, versions exist in a mode similar to how James (and Latour) speaks of the pluriverse (and Latour also of the “multiverse”).15 Just as the pluriverse refers to the coexistence of multiple overlapping universes, and does so to counter the position that there is a singular universe and universal truth, versions construct multiple stories that transform Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 the metamorphoses of vinciane despret our knowledge about how animal lives are observed and represented. For Despret, the connection to Uexküll’s Umwelt theory is especially strong here, as Uexküll provides a theory that depicts the existence of multiple animal worlds, and does so in such a way that any suggestion of a so-called objective “real” world is robbed of its familiarity.16 By the same token, however, Despret finds the Umwelt theory to overemphasize a vision of subjective worlds that doesn’t adequately capture the entangled becomings of various versions that together form new agents. Epistemologically, versions are Despret’s way of holding open different narratives that are each capable of constructing our understanding of a particular event. This notion of version is contrasted with what she calls a “vision”: James gives us tools to help cultivate a site where different versions can coexist. This is the very definition of what I call a version, instead of vision. A version is when multiple stories can coexist; where they are compossible, Leibniz would say. With vision, if you say “Oh, this is your vision of the world,” it means that it’s a subjective experience and it cannot coexist really with mine, because this is your vision of the world, and I can say that you don’t have the truth. You just have an opinion. (Buchanan, Chrulew, and Bussolini 169) More recently, Despret has juxtaposed version with “theme” as a means to demonstrate the capability, or not, of maintaining multiple positions (Que diraient 231–42). Drawing from translation theory, a theme occurs when a particular meaning of a term in one context (e.g., human “mourning”) is directly transposable to another (e.g., chimpanzee “mourning”). If they don’t have the exact same meaning, they don’t share the same theme. Throughout her analyses of scientific practices Despret finds that animals are all too often diminished if it’s “found” that the attribute or capacity in question isn’t “thematically” exact. The question as to whether chimpanzees “mourn” suggests, then, that there must be an exact equivalency – a theme – between humans and chimps. Versions, by contrast, allow the same term to “open up many meanings and different senses” (233). They operate on equivocations and homonymies, not exactitude and synonyms. When writing a version of how chimpanzees relate to the death of a loved one, it is entirely appropriate to say that they “mourn,” knowing full well that this version maintains this as an open possibility. Compared with both “vision” and “theme,” therefore, Despret proposes “versions” so as to emphasize the plurality and mutual transformability of animal worlds. All of this theoretical discussion about Despret’s methodological approach to philosophical ethology leads towards the kinds of stories she tells about animals. And stories they are. In addition to formulating the right questions in human–animal research, it is just as important to tell the right kind of story. Her time spent with Zahavi first accentuated this penchant for storytelling, and since then it has been reinforced time and again through her collaborative projects with academics, scientists, farmers, “amateurs,” and artists, not to mention the babblers, wolves, chimps, orangutans, elephants … Indeed, Despret’s affinity for telling a good story extends to her ventures in film, dance, fiction, and even the art of writing her own fables (“The Otter and the Fish Farmer”). “Ethology is a story of stories,” she explains, and it reinforces the idea that as a field of study, with its own histories, characters, and concepts, it fundamentally deals with living beings and their own experiences (Buchanan, Chrulew, and Bussolini 165). With respect to Zahavi’s scientific articles, she notes that there is a “rupture with the traditional style” of scientific reporting in so far as he replaces statistics and tables with “stories” recounting the individual lives of each bird: he describes what this bird does during the day, why this bird eats what it does, how it interacts with others, etc.17 In other words, the “science” is much closer to the domain of “non-scientific” writing, such as that of “amateurs,” naturalists, or journalists. And yet Despret notes that even Charles Darwin, the grandfather of biology himself, wrote in such a style (“From Secret Agents” 24 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 buchanan 32). While some may write off such storytelling as romanticized, unprofessional, or, as with the case of Darwin, a product of his period, Despret finds the collaboration of perspectives between the arts and sciences not only entirely appropriate but entirely necessary. The creation of stories is not akin to the fictionalization of animal worlds but more a matter of restoring some of the unfamiliarity that lies within subjective lives that will always surprise us. Despret describes this as the “re-enchantment” of our shared worlds, worlds – or one could say “pluriversions” – that have been increasingly reduced over the last two centuries to informational data and animal machines. This is what attracts Despret to the writings of the nineteenthcentury naturalist Edward Thompson: In effect, Thompson happily mixes together in his writings what would gradually be separated in the course of history that follows him: God, scientific knowledge, prophecies, propositions of transformation, anecdotes, testimonials of dog owners and zoo keepers, rigorous experimentations, and a political project for the composition of a world where peace reigns between humans and nonhumans. (Quand le loup 256)18 Where science and critical analyses separate and divide, Despret takes pleasure in the combination and entangling of diverse objects and views. She appreciates that a crow might enjoy surfing down a snowy roof or that a horse may be demonstrating a form of knowledge not otherwise discerned by an emerging psychological apparatus. She seeks “richer narratives” that allow for the coexistence of nature and culture, God and science, peace between humans and non-humans, as well as penguin LGBTQ communities, painting elephants, and macaques who like to drink a little too much. In the case of Thompson, Darwin, Zahavi, and others, she appreciates scientists who don’t “de-animate” the worlds they observe.19 What is needed is a two-fold practice: both to ensure that the world isn’t de-animated in the first place, and that it becomes re-enchanted where and when it has been robbed of its possibility to enchant. 25 When Despret calls herself a “methodological animist,” therefore, she does so for precisely these reasons (“On Asking” passim). She is an empirical fabulist and non-fiction storyteller, piecing together bits and pieces of observations to tell a story that gives life and allows versions to coexist. To return to her earliest book for a moment, she explains that ethological theory “bears the mark of the hybridization of methods” (Naissance 143) between an a priori and an a posteriori approach to animals. The former is akin to the traditional scientific method: formulate a hypothesis based on what is expected, and proceed with a “trial.” The latter, on the other hand, consists in an “investigation” of the empirical evidence: amassing observations and anecdotes and making sense of them by connecting the dots. While both approaches are “versions” in their own right, Despret’s preference clearly falls towards the empirical fabulation which she also likens to a “police investigation” or detective procedural (145). It’s no surprise, then, that one of her books – Hans, le cheval qui savait compter – is constructed in precisely the manner of a detective novel. Taking her cue from a book by Pierre Bayard that sets out to reopen and re-examine the case of Agatha Christie’s The Murder of Roger Ackroyd (because Bayard does not accept that Poirot found the “right” killer in the novel!), Despret similarly sets out to reopen and re-examine the case of Clever Hans, the famous Berlin horse believed to be capable of counting and other feats of independent intelligence at the turn of the twentieth century.20 Under the watchful eyes of celebrated psychologists, Hans was first believed to have the remarkable skill of answering mathematical questions by counting out numbers by tapping his hoof, only later to be charged with the more mundane capacity to read involuntary clues from his human handlers. At one moment an animal savant, the next moment a boring counterfeit. For Despret, however, this “trial” too quickly indicts Hans and his handlers, taking away his modes of intelligence just as quickly as they were attributed. In the excitement of rushing to conclusions, the Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 the metamorphoses of vinciane despret investigators were led astray, or worse, selfblinded from the more interesting hypothesis at work: that Hans the horse was doing something even more interesting than counting: “not only could he read bodies, but he could make human bodies be moved and be affected, and move and affect other beings and perform things without their owners’ knowledge” (“The Body” 113).21 Though far from the end of the story, Despret finds new clues suggesting that it is in fact Hans who is leading the humans, just as much as they’re leading him. The story takes on a new version here, and provides a much more interesting and provocative reading of human–animal agencies, reciprocal adjustments, and transformations (Hans 126). All of these methodological approaches – asking the right questions, humour, politeness, versions, storytelling, animation and re-enchantment, and more – suggest a common thread: that of finding and creating connections among human and non-human animals. The creation of links is what leads Despret to see herself as a “constructivist,” namely as someone who consciously chooses to find and build relations, links, and connections between otherwise disparate propositions, rather than engaging in negative forms of critique, division, reduction, destruction, and other discriminating practices. Through her writings, Despret erects bridges so as to accentuate the often untold “successes” and “achievements” of animals, be they in laboratory settings or out in the field (Quand le loup 95–129). The reasons why she does so might be as simple as saying no more than that it is polite to do so, or that it provides a more generous, and optimistic, account of our worlds. That it generates stories of happiness and goodwill, rather than despondency and bad faith. Another way to put this is to say that it demonstrates “passion,” which for Despret “refers neither to some parasitic supplement nor to some sweet story of love: it means to make an effort to become interested, to immerse oneself […] It means to care” (“The Body” 131). For the same reason, constructing links shows an interest – a genuine, curious interest – in animal lives. “Interesting research,” Despret writes, is research on the conditions that make something interesting. As soon as one focuses on the conditions, the question of knowing “who” becomes interesting is superfluous. Of interest is he or she who makes someone or something else capable of becoming interesting.22 Of course, if animals, and our relations with them, become more interesting, we ourselves will become more interested in them. No longer the animal machine or mechanical automaton or supermarket shrink-wrapped protein, animals affect us. And the risk is that we ourselves will be transformed as a result.23 transformations Despret willingly submits herself to change. Even embraces transformation. And she does so with respect to both human–animal relations and the kinds of world we wish to inhabit together. “If we make an effort,” she writes in Quand le loup habitera avec l’agneau, “to follow the stories of transformation for each of these animals, then quite quickly this contrast between ‘for them’ and ‘for us’ proves to be, over the course of our journey, not only difficult but impractical” (24). In the same vein as both Stengers and Latour, albeit with a particular emphasis in philosophical ethology, Despret is interested in how new bodies are articulated. At a conference on “Theorizing the Body,” at which both Despret and Latour presented, Latour states that an inarticulate subject is someone who whatever the other says or acts always feels, acts and says the same thing […] In contrast, an articulate subject is someone who learns to be affected by others – not by itself. There is nothing especially interesting, deep, profound, worthwhile in a subject “by itself,” this is the limit of the common definition – a subject only becomes interesting, deep, profound, worthwhile when it resonates with others, is effected, moved, put into motion by new entities whose differences are registered in new and unexpected ways.24 An inarticulate subject is one who speaks in “themes,” who conducts “trials,” who is 26 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 buchanan impolite and disenchants the world. An articulate subject, by contrast, is one who engages in an “‘anthropo-zoo-genetic practice’, a practice that constructs animal and human” (Despret, “The Body” 122). In her own paper from this same conference, Despret develops this practice of articulation through an example provided by the French ethologist Jean-Claude Barrey. Horses and their riders, we know, develop very close relations with each other, so much so that they’re able to “read” one another’s movements, both intentional and unintentional. As summarized by Despret, talented riders behave and move like horses. They have learned to act in a horse-like fashion […] Human bodies have been transformed by and into a horse’s body. Who influences and who is influenced, in this story, are questions that no longer receive a clear answer. Both, human and horse, are cause and effect of each other’s movements. Both induce and are induced, affect and are affected. (115) This practice of becoming articulated between animal and human is replicated over and over again, whether it’s Zahavi and his babblers, Konrad Lorenz and his jackdaw, Hans and the psychologist Oskar Pfungst, rats and their experimenters, Heinrich and his ravens, or any other of our own everyday experiences with non-human others. This relational sense of agency is not simply one wherein animals passively influence our human understanding and sense of being, but whereby all animal bodies – human, nonhuman, more-than-human – actively co-constitute each other, both ontologically and epistemologically. The claim made by primatologists and ethologists – “The animals have changed, but we have also changed” – can receive another translation (if we wish to be faithful to the way that they themselves describe their work): “Animals have also changed because they have changed us.” (Quand le loup 30–31) The function of this change is an admittedly novel twist in Despret’s thought, for she reappropriates the French word “agencement,” as 27 used specifically by Deleuze and Guattari, in order to recover an ontologically foundational sense of pre-existing agency.25 Unlike “assemblage,” as it is often translated into English, Despret refers back to agencement to delineate a rapport of forces that makes some beings capable of making other beings capable, in a plurivocal manner, in such a way that the agencement resists being dismembered, resists clear-cut distribution […] Agency is the product of this agencement; there is no agency without agencement. In other words, a being’s agency testifies to the existence of an agencement. There is, in each agencement, co-animation. (“From Secret Agents” 38) In some of her most recent engagements with the dance choreographer Luc Petton, Despret seeks to explore such agencements in how classically trained ballet dancers “agence” with swans in one scenario, and with Manchurian cranes in another. Though the dances are not choreographed per se, to say that they are “instinctive” is clearly not the correct term either for the coordinated and harmonizing movements of the dancers and birds. Through their reciprocated movements, it’s not clear who is choreographing whom. Their bodies transform together, creating new understandings and new propositions, as suggested by some of the photographic work in this issue.26 Despret searches for these transformations and metamorphoses in ethological practices, just as much as she encourages them within her self. As a sign of her commitment on this front, she isn’t afraid to go too far at times, to force herself out of her comfortable limits, to say and do things that may encounter resistance. At times, as discussed above, such risks are necessary in order to “emancipate” our selves, both animals and humans, from pre-existing prejudices or constraints, and from ties that are too binding, so as to give new relations a chance. The reasoning is not only so as to change ourselves but it’s also to change the world. “We need more work,” Despret writes, “more good constraints, and more relations to give animals a chance to actualize their forces, Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 the metamorphoses of vinciane despret their intelligences, their competencies, and their social talents. We need more knowledge and more practices so as to create a common world” (Quand le loup 94). The title and epigraph from which this quote is taken, Quand le loup habitera avec l’agneau [When the Wolf Shall Dwell with the Lamb], draws inspiration from the Book of Isaiah (11.6) which reads (in the King James version): “The wolf also shall dwell with the lamb, and the leopard shall lie down with the kid; and the calf and the young lion and the fatling together; and a little child shall lead them.” To transform the world such that lambs may lie with wolves is a commendable if unpromising goal, but it’s one that Despret eagerly advances, albeit with some reservations. Like any good fantasy, Despret’s versions of a “common world” have their utopic elements; however, for the very same reasons, they’re nevertheless somehow believable. I don’t dream of a perfect world where beings are no longer exploited by others, which would not be a perfect world but a world without life, for there are no lives that are independent of other lives – it’s Haraway again who reminds us of this. Nevertheless, I continue to cultivate the idea of a world that helps us to be a little less evil, a world where people are responsible for what they ask of other beings, and act on this responsibility, with neither the pretence of innocence nor that the impossibility of innocence allows us to do whatever we want. (Penser 78) Her account is strangely but appropriately Kantian in tone: even if we rationally know that a perfect world is unattainable, we are nevertheless obliged to attempt to realize it.27 This obligation – a kind of multispecied, pluriverse imperative – underlies all of her writing, even if it’s not always apparent. For me, this is the key to her interest in philosophical ethology, and the stories she tells. Her thought is underscored by hope which finds its articulation through a secular notion of “belief”: belief, not in terms of “what is” (and thus the underlying assumption that some beliefs are right or wrong), but rather in a pragmatic sense of what beliefs make possible. A “belief is what makes entities ‘available’ to events” (“The Body” 122). It is the belief that our animal and human worlds are compossible; that, as she writes in her most recent, unpublished writings, we need to believe in (and thus remain attentive to) the present and future demands wrought by extinction events, and what they signal in terms of the loss of unique ways of experiencing the world that are individually and species specific.28 Despret’s belief is what holds her open and endlessly available to the curious stories of animals. Understood in this way, Despret offers us an opportunity to believe, to believe in what is possible, as well as impossible, in what may be articulated differently, in what new propositions are still to come. And, in her own way, she does it full of grace and humour. disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author. notes I would like to thank Matt Chrulew and Jeff Bussolini – my co-editors, colleagues, and friends – for their support, assistance, guidance, patience, and above all friendship through the preparation of this issue. I would similarly like to thank Donna Haraway for her enthusiastic acceptance to write the prefatory essay for this issue; Hollis Taylor and Stephen Muecke for their translations; Luc Petton, Michel Meuret, Gilles Lacombe, and Edmond Baudoin for the use of their images; and Vinciane Despret for her warm hospitality, gracious responses to questions, and for the gift of her writings in the first place. This work was supported in part by a Laurentian University SSHRC Research Support Fund. 1 Buchanan, Chrulew, and Bussolini 165–66. 2 Ibid. 175. 3 See Penser 3–5; Buchanan, Chrulew, and Bussolini; Despret, “Why ‘I Had Not’” 97. 4 I recommend here the writings of Dominique Lestel, Jocelyne Porcher, and Roberto Marchesini 28 buchanan in particular. See Lestel, Les Origines animales and L’Animalité; Porcher, Éleveurs et animaux and Vivre avec les animaux; Chrulew; Marchesini; Marchesini and Andersen. “expert” in the field in every way but for a “professional” accreditation or degree. Amateurs include farmers, trainers, breeders, caretakers, naturalists, hobbyists, etc. 5 In addition to Our Emotional Makeup, see also Les Faiseuses 63–71. 15 Latour writes: “To name such a world, I will employ the term multiverse, put to such good use by James: the multiverse designates the universe freed from its premature unification” (“How to Talk” 213). Latour also uses “pluriverse” (Politics 40). See also James; Latour, Inquiry. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 6 I don’t have the time and space to fully develop this comparison, but please see Nietzsche, The Gay Science 223 and Thus Spoke Zarathustra 137–39. 7 See Despret, “Ethique et Ethologie” and “Ecology and Ideology.” This early phase didn’t last very long, for already by 1995–96 Despret was engaged in ethological fieldwork for her Master’s thesis. 8 Haraway famously called out Derrida in her book When Species Meet for both his lack of attention to real animals (despite his claims to be affected by the gaze of his cat) and his seeming blindness to the work and writings of ethologists, biologists, primatologists, and the like (19–23). See Despret’s own humorous take on Derrida’s lack of humour: “his worries about his shame of being naked in front of his cat seems to lack something I found in Mowat: humour. Derrida doesn’t laugh at his own worries – neither does he scream ‘peeping Tom!’” (“Responding Bodies” 64). 9 See Oliver 2; Buchanan, “Most Beautiful Companion.” 10 See Zahavi; Zahavi and Zahavi. 11 See Naissance, “L’Éthologie comme pratique” 64, and Quand le loup 160–61. 12 See Quand le loup 70, Être bête 88, and Que diraient passim. 16 See Despret, Que diraient 221–30, “From Secret Agents” 31, and Penser 31–37; Uexküll; Buchanan, Onto-Ethologies. 17 Naissance 14. This methodological procedure is in the same spirit as Dominique Lestel’s descriptions of etho-ethnology, in short, the transposition of anthropological and ethnographical methods to animal lives. See Lestel, “Ethology and Ethnology”; Bussolini. 18 In much the same spirit as Thompson’s list, Despret quotes the fantastical and constructive list from Borges’ “The Analytical Language of John Wilkins” as the epigraph to Bêtes et hommes (11). 19 See “From Secret Agents” 36. Despret here draws on the recent work of Hustak and Myers on plant becomings, and appreciates in them what she elsewhere accentuates through the writings of thinkers such as Eduardo Viveiros de Castro and Philippe Descola. 20 See Despret, Hans 115; Bayard. 21 On the notion of being affected, particularly the idea of “affected perspective,” Despret writes: “in choosing the term ‘affected perspective’, I aim to emphasize how the scientist risks being touched/ affected by what matters for the animal he/she observes” (“Responding Bodies” 57). 13 By asking which of the hypotheses and questions are more interesting, Despret consciously opposes herself to classical theories of science, including those of ethology and psychology, which argue that, all else being equal, a simpler explanation is always preferable over one that is more complex. In this respect, Morgan’s Canon, itself an iteration of Occam’s razor, stipulates that when it comes to animal intelligence, lower psychological processes ought to always overrule higher psychological functionality (Morgan; Despret, Que diraient 17, 137). 22 See “Sheep Do Have Opinions” 363 and Quand le loup 257; Haraway, “Preface.” On the note of “interest,” Despret writes elsewhere that it is “the expectations of someone who cares, of someone who was interested, of someone who trusts, moreover, of someone who was interested, someone it interests (inter-esse, to make a link)” (“The Body” 124). 14 Despret borrows the term “amateur” from Latour to refer to “non-scientists” who have a particular taste or nose for a certain field; they are an 23 On this notion of “risk,” as well as seven other “conditions” that Bruno Latour outlines as part of the “Stengers–Despret Falsification Principle” 29 the metamorphoses of vinciane despret (or “Stengers–Despret Shibboleth”), I highly recommend “How to Talk About the Body?” 214–23. 24 Ibid. 210. 25 See Deleuze and Guattari 260, 321. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 26 “Propositions” is a term that runs throughout all of Despret’s writings. And though it is readily apparent that it is an important term, it can be easily overlooked due to its colloquial usage. For a theoretical position on “proposition,” and one that Despret is quite familiar with, consider this description by Latour: Working in the vicinity of Isabelle Stengers’s Whitehead, I have acquired the habit of using the word propositions to describe what is articulated. The word “proposition” conjugates three crucial elements: (a) it denotes obstinacy (position), that (b) has no definitive authority (it is a pro-position only) and (c) it may accept negotiating itself into a com-position without losing its solidity. (“How to Talk” 212) See also Politics of Nature 247 and “Well-Articulated Primatology.” 27 See Kant’s “Idea for a Universal History” and “Perpetual Peace.” 28 Personal correspondence on species extinctions (e.g., passenger pigeons). See Buchanan, Chrulew, and Bussolini. bibliography Bayard, Pierre. Who Killed Roger Ackroyd? The Mystery behind the Agatha Christie Mystery. Trans. Carol Cosman. New York: New, 2000. Print. Borges, Jorge. “The Analytical Language of John Wilkins.” Other Inquisitions, 1937–1952. Trans. Ruth L.C. Simms. Austin: U of Texas P, 1975. 101–05. Print. Buchanan, Brett. “Most Beautiful Companion.” Environmental Philosophy IX.II (2012): 173–87. Print. Buchanan, Brett. Onto-Ethologies: The Animal Environments of Uexküll, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Deleuze. Albany: State U of New York P, 2008. Print. Buchanan, Brett, Matthew Chrulew, and Jeffrey Bussolini. “On Asking the Right Questions: An Interview with Vinciane Despret.” Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities 20.2 (2015): 165–78. Print. Bussolini, Jeffrey. “Recent French, Belgian and Italian Work in the Cognitive Science of Animals: Dominique Lestel, Vinciane Despret, Roberto Marchesini and Giorgio Celli.” Social Science Information 52.2 (2013): 187–209. Print. Chrulew, Matthew. “The Philosophical Ethology of Dominique Lestel.” Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities 19.3 (2014): 17–44. Print. Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Trans. Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1987. Print. Derrida, Jacques. The Animal That Therefore I Am. Ed. Marie-Louise Mallet. Trans. David Wills. New York: Fordham UP, 2008. Print. Descola, Philippe. Beyond Nature and Culture. Trans. Janet Lloyd. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2013. Print. Despret, Vinciane. Bêtes et hommes. Paris: Gallimard, 2007. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “The Body We Care For: Figures of Anthropo-zoo-genesis.” Body and Society 10.2–3 (2004): 111–34. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “Domesticating Practices: The Case of Arabian Babblers.” Routledge Handbook of Human–Animal Studies. Ed. Garry Marvin and Susan McHugh. Abingdon: Routledge, 2014. 23–38. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “Ecology and Ideology: The Case of Ethology.” International Problems 63.3–4 (1994): 45–61. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “Ethique et ethologie: Une histoire naturelle de l’altruisme.” Cahiers d’éthologie 11.2 (1991): 141–266. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “L’Éthologie comme pratique des habitudes.” Vers des civilisations mondialisées. De l’éthologie à la prospective. Ed. Jean-Éric Aubert and Josée Landrieu. La Tour d’Aigues: L’Aube, 2014. 59–71. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “From Secret Agents to Interagency.” History and Theory 52.4 (2013): 29– 44. Print. Despret, Vinciane. Hans, le cheval qui savait compter. Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond/Le Seuil, 2004. Print. 30 buchanan Despret, Vinciane. Naissance d’une théorie éthologique: La Danse du cratérope écaillé. Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond/Le Seuil, 1996. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “The Otter and the Fish Farmer.” Trans. Matthew Chrulew. Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities 20.2 (2015): 115–18. Print. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 Despret, Vinciane. Our Emotional Makeup: Ethnopsychology and Selfhood. Trans. Marjolijn de Jager. New York: Other, 2004. Print. of Plant/Insect Encounters.” Différences 23.3 (2012): 74–118. Print. James, William. A Pluralistic Universe. Lincoln: U of Nebraska P, 1996. Print. Kant, from Lewis Beck. Print. Immanuel. “Idea for a Universal History a Cosmopolitan Point of View.” Trans. White Beck. On History. Ed. Lewis White Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice, 2001. Despret, Vinciane. Penser comme un rat. Versailles: Quæ, 2009. Print. Kant, Immanuel. “Perpetual Peace.” Trans. Lewis White Beck. On History. Ed. Lewis White Beck. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice, 2001. Print. Despret, Vinciane. Quand le loup habitera avec l’agneau. Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond/Le Seuil, 2002. Print. Latour, Bruno. “How to Talk About the Body? The Normative Dimension of Science Studies.” Body and Society 10.2–3 (2004): 205–29. Print. Despret, Vinciane. Que diraient les animaux, si … on leur posait les bonnes questions? Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond/La Découverte, 2012. Print. Latour, Bruno. An Inquiry into Modes of Existence: An Anthropology of the Moderns. Trans. Catherine Porter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 2013. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “Responding Bodies and Partial Affinities in Human–Animal Worlds.” Theory, Culture and Society 30.7–8 (2013): 51–76. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “‘Sheep Do Have Opinions.’” Trans. Liz Carey-Libbrecht. Making Things Public: Atmospheres of Democracy. Ed. Bruno Latour and Peter Weibel. Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 2005. 360–68. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “Why ‘I Had Not Read Derrida’: Often Too Close, Always Too Far Away.” Trans. Greta D’Amico and Stephanie Posthumus. French Thinking About Animals. Ed. Louisa Mackenzie and Stephanie Posthumus. East Lansing: Michigan State UP, 2015. 91–104. Print. Despret, Vinciane, and Jocelyne Porcher. Être bête. Arles: Actes Sud, 2007. Print. Latour, Bruno. Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into Democracy. Trans. Catherine Porter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 2004. Print. Latour, Bruno. “A Well-Articulated Primatology: Reflections of a Fellow Traveler.” Primate Encounters: Models of Science, Gender, and Society. Ed. Shirley Strum and Linda Fedigan. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2000. 358–82. Print. Lestel, Dominique. Les Amis de mes amis. Paris: Le Seuil, 2007. Print. Lestel, Dominique. L’Animalité. Paris: L’Herne, 2007. Print. Lestel, Dominique. “Ethology and Ethnology: The Coming Synthesis. A General Introduction.” Trans. Nora Scott. Social Science Information 45.2 (2006): 147–53. Print. Lestel, Dominique. Les Origines animales de la culture. Paris: Flammarion, 2003. Print. Despret, Vinciane, and Isabelle Stengers. Les Faiseuses d’histoires: Que font les femmes à la pensée? Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond/La Découverte, 2011. Print. Marchesini, Roberto. Posthuman: Verso nuovi modelli di esistenza. Turin: Bollati, 2001. Print. Haraway, Donna. “Preface: A Curious Practice.” Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities 20.2 (2015): 5–14. Print. Marchesini, Roberto, and Karin Andersen. Animal Appeal: Uno studio sul teriomorfismo. Bologna: Alberto Perdisa, 2003. Print. Haraway, Donna. When Species Meet. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2008. Print. Morgan, C. Lloyd. An Introduction to Comparative Psychology. London: Scott, 1903. Print. Hustak, Carla, and Natasha Myers. “Involuntary Momentum: Affective Ecologies and the Sciences Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Gay Science. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage, 1974. Print. 31 the metamorphoses of vinciane despret Nietzsche, Friedrich. Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. The Portable Nietzsche. Ed. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Penguin, 1982. Print. Oliver, Kelly. Animal Lessons: How They Teach Us to Be Human. New York: Columbia UP, 2009. Print. Porcher, Jocelyne. Éleveurs et animaux, réinventer le lien. Paris: PUF, 2002. Print. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 11:59 21 November 2015 Porcher, Jocelyne. Vivre avec les animaux, une utopie pour le 21ème siècle. Paris: La Découverte, 2011. Print. Stengers, Isabelle. Cosmopolitics I. Trans. Robert Bononno. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2010. Print. Stengers, Isabelle. The Invention of Modern Science. Trans. Daniel W. Smith. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2000. Print. Stengers, Isabelle. Thinking with Whitehead: A Free and Wild Creation of Concepts. Trans. Michael Chase. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 2011. Print. Uexküll, Jakob von. A Foray into the Worlds of Animals and Humans, with A Theory of Meaning. Trans. Joseph D. O’Neil. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2010. Print. Viveiros de Castro, Eduardo. “Perspectival Anthropology and the Method of Controlled Equivocation.” Tipiti: Journal of the Society for the Anthropology of Lowland South America 2.1 (2004): 3–22. Print. Zahavi, Amotz. “Mate Selection – A Selection for a Handicap.” Journal of Theoretical Biology 53.1 (1975): 205–14. Print. Zahavi, Amotz, and Avishag Zahavi. The Handicap Principle: A Missing Piece of Darwin’s Puzzle. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1997. Print. Brett Buchanan Department of Philosophy School of the Environment Laurentian University 935 Ramsey Lake Road Sudbury Ontario P3E 2C6 Canada E-mail: [email protected] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:07 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:07 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:08 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:08 21 November 2015 ANGELAKI journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 translator’s foreword The case of the Arabian babblers is a controversial and significant one in ethology. Their dancing, their gifting, their care for nestlings that are not their own, are singular enough to trouble standard sociobiological theories of the evolution of behaviour. The theory of Israeli ornithologist Amotz Zahavi is that the dance is a contest for status that ensures the reliability of communication and that tests and performs their social bonds (Zahavi and Zahavi). Zahavi’s handicap principle has been heavily criticized by sociobiologists, only to later find support in the mathematical modelling of others. But is the real difference of Zahavi’s approach only theoretical, or does it lie elsewhere, in his anthropomorphic descriptions or habituating field methods? And what is so special about the babblers? Vinciane Despret set off to the Israel desert to find out. Already well versed in the literature on bird altruism (“É thique et éthologie”), she sought to complement and challenge her reading via fieldwork among scientists and their subjects. She set out to watch the birds, and to watch their watchers, to ask the latter questions about the questions they asked the birds, about the ways they saw them differently. If she initially suspected that it was Zahavi’s own eccentricities that shaped his distinctive portrayal of the babblers, she soon came to find that what went into the construction of a scientific theory was here much more complex and interesting. The result of this encounter in which, as she says, “[t]he field ‘happened to me’” (“Domesticating Practices” 25), was her first book, Birth of an Ethological Theory, written in a joyful rush of creative energy and promise. In it, she vinciane despret translated by matthew chrulew MODELS AND METHODS sketch of a field study tells of the encounter with the curious theory that led to her visit, and sets up the theoretical context of the controversy: evolutionary explanations for altruism in terms of group selection or reciprocity, debates over sexual selection and the “arms race” models of natural competition. She situates among them the idea of “ritual,” introduced into ethology by Julian Huxley, which bears on Zahavi’s theory. She then delineates in detail the case of the babblers, combining discussion of the published literature with her own ethnographic observations in a sophisticated exercise in reflexive and empirical field philosophy. This was a site, she explains, of divergent models and methods, narratives and metaphors, epistemologies and ontologies, that are only truly visible and understandable ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020037-16 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039841 37 models and methods Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 if one takes into account the respective scientists’ particular ways of comporting themselves with the birds they are studying, and the babblers’ active role in writing their own scripts. In so far as it resembles the immersive participation and individual biographing of anthropological and primatological methods, and pays skilful attention to the reasons for their actions, Zahavi’s way of relating to and questioning the babblers gives them the opportunity to respond, and to bring us to understand and affirm why it is that they help and dance. F rom the reading of one of Zahavi’s articles devoted to the babblers (“Arabian Babblers”) has emerged the question of whether the babblers were such extraordinary birds, with their dances, their games, their disputes, and their competitions for the privilege of being altruistic, or if it was the particular gaze that Zahavi brought which conferred on them this originality. Upon reading this article, my questions had to change (Despret, “Ecology and Ideology”; “L’Idée de société en éthologie”; L’Homme en société). In fact, the literature that I inventoried at the time generally consisted of articles describing, relatively soberly, types of uncreative automatons, exhibiting behaviours that in this context are rather conventional. In order to answer my new questions, I was then left with the solution of going there myself, to ask questions, to read and to watch. I will not maintain the suspense, and all that precedes suggests my answer. Probably disappointingly, at any rate obvious to my readers, it appeared to me marvellously complex, because it preserved the two poles of my questioning, not reducing one to the other nor exhausting any of the meanings. The babblers are no ordinary birds, and Zahavi’s theories emerge in no ordinary contexts of justification. equilibrium and the great divide An ironist will say that the birds appeared extraordinary to me, because I saw them through the eyes of Zahavi. I was myself this ironist on arriving at the Centre. They are right, I was right, but we must go beyond this one-sided constructivism of the pole of “nature”: not all birds dance, and not all have this elaborate social structure. Firstly, because not all birds live for fifteen years. Also rare are birds which let themselves be approached so closely. Let us stop here, just a moment, and look at what just happened: we have, without realizing it, slipped from the bird to the observer, and situated ourselves right in the space between them. It is in this space, geographical and relational, that the double question can arise. The essential and pressing duplicity of this question transforms all research into ethical, aesthetic and ethological research: “who am I, how does my gaze work so that you appear to me as you are?” at the same time as “who are you so that I see you thus?” The first without the second pulls us back to a sterile constructivism; the second without the first to a dogmatic realism. Together, they form the moment of equilibrium, the best point for thinking about things in dynamic, relational and complex terms. These moments of equilibrium in the space that unites natural objects and the questions that interrogate them are moments that, no doubt, contribute to erasing the great modern divide between nature and culture. And with this erasure the great divide between the human and the animal is itself seriously put into question: Isabelle Stengers sees in the heresies of the new primatologists (like those of Shirley Strum) the signs of this challenge (Invention of Modern Science 62–63). By letting the baboons respond to other questions than those traditionally posed to non-humans, by granting them, for example, social skills that are no longer merely the product of obedience to species-specific rules, but rather of their creativity in the construction of social links, these primatologists seem to sketch the structures of a space of equilibrium. What happened there for one to come to abandon the old questions in order to formulate the new? The answer that Stengers suggests brings us back to our anchor point, to the crux of our problem, to what we have said about ritual and dance: the primatologist was 38 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 despret able to give up the search for invariants which individuals obey, in the same way that ritual and dance led Zahavi to question, beyond species similarities, individual singularity. If one lingers a while at the waning of Strum’s research – with what Stengers calls her “quest for pertinence” (Invention of Modern Science 63) – as it is recounted both in her book Almost Human and in the article written in collaboration with Latour (“Redefining the Social Link”), one makes out a parallelism of questions with those that arise here for the babblers: when confronted with surprising discrepancies between what she sees among her baboons and what the data of her colleagues and the literature in general had prepared her to see, Strum concludes that each baboon troop deviates from the norm. But this conclusion, one suspects, is not without its problems. In her attempt to find a “way out of this dilemma of intraspecies variability,” Strum considers two possibilities: she could, in the first, “reject data and the views of the observers. A common position was this: other baboons did not behave differently, they were just inaccurately studied” (“Redefining the Social Link” 787). Another way out of the dilemma would be – and this is the position that she proposes to adopt – to call into question both the epistemology and the ontology that underpins the research, to place herself in a position that takes into account at the same time the subject, its modes of knowledge and of definition of the object (the paradigm), and the object itself, become subject in turn: “the traditional, ostensive definition of baboon society has been unable to accommodate the variety of data on baboon social life. As a result, some information has been treated as ‘data’ and other information as discrepancies to be ignored [ … ]” (789). To regard, with the performative paradigm, “[b]aboons [as] ‘performing’ society might also allow a more consistent interpretation of the cross-populational data and data from other species of monkeys and apes” (790). Thus it is not only a matter of admitting, as in many controversies in ethology, that the abilities of the observer can, by themselves, explain the deviations from the norm, but of broadening the 39 paradigms in order to render them more flexible, more open in the face of difference, variety or even contradictions. Substituting the performative paradigm for the ostensive paradigm at the epistemological level leads to interesting upheavals at the level of the ontology resulting from the research: other “beings” acquire the right to existence, objects become subjects. It is here also that there opens up, among primatologists, what we identified as a space of equilibrium between the poles of subjectivity and objectivity, of nature and culture, of the gaze and the object gazed upon. In the same way that the baboons were able to make the primatologists change their questions, the babblers gave Zahavi the opportunity to pose questions otherwise. We locate here, somewhat artificially, our response as regards the babbler, active subject of the relationship that unites the researcher and his object of study. The space of equilibrium lies more in the very relationship between an active subject and a likewise active observer, within the play of questions and answers that characterizes the link created between them. This space of equilibrium can, I think, be partially described in the methodologies: indeed, it is these which give a framework and some tools for the questions as well as for the answers. a priori and a posteriori methodologies When analysing the relation between the conceptions underlying the search for species similarities and the methodologies used to observe them, a term appears that is common to the object and its categorization, and to the way of doing fieldwork: the term a priori. Behavioural invariants are, in a way, the a priori of the programmes and their innate releasing mechanisms: does not Lorenz declare himself Kant’s heir when he deems the organization of behaviour to be a priori? To this a priori may correspond certain methodologies which may also merit the name of a priorist in so far as they are neither the result, nor the condition. The general characteristics Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 models and methods of the method may, however, make it easier to perceive invariants. The researcher equipped with an a priorist methodology goes into the field with a hypothesis to which he intends to submit the facts (the term submission merits all its ambiguity here). This methodology is based on previous research, and organizes the work around the hypotheses developed on the basis of these theories. For Jon [Jonathan Wright], the Oxford researcher, for example, it is inconceivable that one could go into the field without wanting to test a hypothesis. The a priorist thus searches for answers to “how” questions. His advantage will be, in this case, the regularity of reality: the invariants can make up this ideal regularity. This is how, in a way, the approach and the focus of interest will be found in a system of resonances, a mirror system. The a priorist will more readily make use of the experimental approach: the manipulation of variables – to understand reality by resisting it (in the words of Bachelard)1 – will be for him the suitable methodology for measuring and understanding the invariants. Thus, the decoy method illustrates perfectly what we have been saying. For the bird’s egg, one can substitute an egg that is bigger, smaller, redder, or whatnot, which enables the varying of these invariants, that is to say of the instinctive or pre-programmed response of the bird faced with the stimulus signal that represents certain characteristics of the egg. The a priorist, faced with variety, will attempt to create variation by deviating from the ordinary conditions of observation. The a priorist, in a way, imposes on reality his question and the limits of the answer, as the programme imposes on the organism its questions (the stimuli signals acting as keys in a lock) and the behaviours that respond to them (the innate responses). In this sense also, the methodologies and objects begin to resonate, create an isomorphism and form a mirror effect. If we consider the approaches on a continuum, we find opposite the a priorist procedure that of the a posteriorist.2 Zahavi’s approach illustrates this well. The term’s reference to “what is known from experience” refers here not to the experience of the experimenter but to the most common experience. No hypothesis is explicitly formulated before going into the field. It is a matter of going there with the sole intention of seeing what will take place, first, and subsequently of putting forward, a posteriori, hypotheses and interpretations regarding what one saw. Of course, hypotheses are not entirely absent, but they are generally implicit, and go beyond the scope of the first hypothesis stipulating that there is something to see. With Zahavi, one can, for example, think that the influence of the theory of individual selection is accompanied by some expectant utterances. This approach resembles, from numerous methodological and theoretical points of view, the anthropological approach. The a posteriorist collects anecdotal facts and tries to make sense of them by creating links between these facts. Rather than to variation, it is to variety that he becomes attached, and on it that he bases his experience in the sense of common experience. For example, Zahavi critiques evolutionary game theory because it does not account for the fact that the animals in the field “react in a highly variable way,” with reactions that seem “determined by information gathered rather than by a pre-set program activated by simple arbitrary signals” (“Some Comments on Sociobiology” 414) Of course, this continuum is an artifice and one practically never encounters a totally pure approach. The most illuminating illustration of these two approaches is found in Lorenz who can pass, within the same study, from one extreme of the continuum to the other. Although driven by a theory in terms of a priori – the behavioural invariants of the innate programme – Lorenz may adopt in the field a dual approach: the anthropological approach and the a priorist and experimental approach of searching for invariants. His research on imprinting during the following reaction in geese is a striking example of this hybridization of approaches and of objects. To recall, the theory recounts the fact that a young goose, within hours after birth, undergoes a critical period during which it will follow any moving object found nearby. 40 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 despret The theory itself bears the mark of the hybridization of methods, since it interprets imprinting as resulting from the combination of an innate invariant programme with respect to its form, and the open mechanisms of learning with respect to its object. The hybridization of the theory thus faithfully reflects that of the objects: the experiment of manipulating the variables in play takes place on both fronts. As an experimental approach, it verifies its hypothesis, and emphasizes the innate, a priori response of the gosling; as an anthropological approach, it emphasizes what is acquired by the gosling “through experience,” what goes beyond the scope of the invariants, what might then be called the a posteriori of behaviour. This approach is all the more anthropological as Lorenz, himself, plays the role of decoy, thus utilizing, in a quasi-anthropological manner, the special relationship established with the subject of his experiment, the young goose who takes him for its mother. The two linked poles of the objects and the methodologies are thus reflected in this particular operation: the experimental approach highlights the a priori of the programme (the immediate innate response), while the a posteriorist or anthropological approach reveals, for its part, the variety that this programme has not anticipated. It allows a space for surprise and creativity to be created. the investigation and the trial Other differences may appear from either side of our continuum, which give to each of the approaches their own characteristics. They appear in what may be called the procedures of research and of the construction of theories. The a priorist, of whom we are told that he fixes to reality the strict frameworks of its response, does not trust what reality tells him: the duplicity of causes, the certainties of opinion constitute so many opportunities for poor thinking. He will impose on reality to repeat the story again and again. He will expect of it that it does not betray itself, that its versions are reliable, that the regularity of the deviations from the original response (that 41 obtained without the decoy) confirms his hypothesis. It is not only reality that is put on trial, it is he himself in his relationship with the objects (witnesses) and the hypotheses describing a system of causes and effects. Testing reality renews the etymology which designates the procedure: it is truly a matter of putting his testimony to the test, as in a judicial trial. Altruism, studied by the a posteriorist, must for its part be the object of a thorough investigation: it must gather clues that belie the innocence of behaviours, seeking, beyond appearances, the meaning, the linking of seemingly unrelated facts. To the trial of the experimenter corresponds, then, the investigation of the a posteriorist. This investigation, which focuses on variety rather than variation, is not, however, without creating some difficulties. In fact, how can any ordinary explanatory interpretation be put forward on its basis? If the trial of variation boils down to the confrontation of fictions in order to oust them, the investigation of variety uncovers neither meanings nor criteria which enable it to decide between these fictions. The hypothesis results from putting together heterogeneous observations that make sense once assembled, but it can only win over opinion on the assumption of support for a fiction. I have called this manner of proceeding “investigation,” not only because it is situated as the previous and different moment of the trial but also because it is present in the traits and characteristics of the police investigation of the masters of suspense: the researcher not only joins together disparate facts but, above all, brings in contact “facts that don’t fit” with some of the testimony, or else that “don’t fit” between them. Remember how the theory’s chronology unfolds and how I have presented it: the question of how such an altruistic bird has not convinced Zahavi of the pertinence of the theory of group selection is in a way answered in that Zahavi does not believe in the “innocence” of the babblers. And with good reason; too many troubling elements, too many facts that “don’t fit” and which, once put together, begin to make sense and to Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 models and methods indicate what is truly going on (assuming Zahavi is right, of course): helping at the nest is more harmful than beneficial; to a gentle taking by the hand corresponds an aggressive behaviour, and vice versa; the reprimands of the dominants take the strange forms of gifts and grooming, with some gifts, but not all, leading to conflicts; not everyone can make offerings within the group; the dancing always occurs “when it should not be, where it should not be.” Is it not thus, through a meticulous collection of small things that should not be found there, or that say something other than what they seem to say, that the police investigation is carried out? So, to the trial of the experiment, confrontation of all the fictions, responds here the investigation, a fiction itself, a fictional and hypothetical construction which can have no greater power than that of convincing, by the simple fact of what it proposes. This was for a long time one of the reasons for the indifference or the suspicion of the scientific community towards Zahavi’s theory. The trial in the mode of variation offers, for its part, the dispositive of the confrontation of these fictions, that is to say the experimental apparatus that, as Stengers defines it, puts them to the test and enables it to decide between them (Invention of Modern Science). A fiction that ousts the others can carry with it the support of the other researchers. Perhaps it will be more tangible for us to visit, at the time of a trial, the scene of the testing of the ethological fictions. This description will allow us to grasp the entire difference between the two approaches. experimentation as the locus of the trial The manipulation of reality is a way of verifying the “how” of what is observed: “what is at stake here, what is the cause of what I observe?” The manipulatory procedure will consist of a modification of reality to speed it up, to vary it, to insert into it a series of constraints so that it is at once in laboratory conditions all while respecting the conditions of nature.3 But, in the procedure itself, there is no indication which will serve as a guarantee that we are talking about the right “how,” a guarantee that what is at stake is the effect of the right cause, that the fiction is the true fiction. That it is not a simple matter of opinion – of which it is known since Plato, and no pun intended, that it has bad press. It is the way in which the test is organized that will serve as guarantee, because this organization will, progressively, put each of the fictions to the test of the other fictions, as in the trial. Look at how an experiment is organized: Jon participated in the research of a group of Oxford zoologists led by John Krebs which, in collaboration with a group from Toronto led by David Sherry and Sarah Shettleworth, tried to explain how certain birds (American blackcapped chickadees and European marsh tits) memorized the hundred or so food caches that they used.4 The question here is clear, and simply expressed in terms of “how”: how do they find the caches again? The initial hypothesis – we are within an a priorist approach – is that the birds use their memory, and not olfactory cues or other non-mnesic processes of the association of signs. From there, the approach will unfold in a discursive mode. The progressive elimination of alternative fictions itself takes the narrative shape of a fiction or an imaginary trial. In the field, the researcher is alone – or with his assistants, close collaborators, or students – but he will gather around himself the imaginary characters of a trial. Each of the imaginary characters seems to call upon the researcher to put to it an objection in the form of another fiction. The imaginary trial will then proceed until the elimination of each of the fictions proposed by these characters. Let us follow the steps: in an artificial forest, one of the researchers drilled, into each of the trees, a hole closed off with Velcro. We know, the author tells us, that the bird can open it because it resembles some of the natural conditions of the closure of orifices. As you see, the experiment has not yet begun without imaginary objections already intervening. The Velcro is itself used to fend off 42 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 despret another objection: the bird would not need to demonstrate its memory if the food were visually accessible. During the first stage of the trial the birds hide the seeds, and then are removed from the forest to be released there twenty-four hours later. They find the caches again and the seeds that they contain, and thus allow the researcher to attribute the success of the performance to memory. Another objection, however, seems to have been created, since our researcher begins his experiment again, but with the addition of a variation: the birds could find the seeds due to their odour. They could also rely on the fact that the Velcro does not close up the visited caches again in exactly the same manner. The researcher will remove the seeds after the first visit, in the absence of the birds, reclose the Velcro, note where the seeds were cached, then, after twenty-four hours, observe the return of the birds. They head straight for the used caches. Another imaginary objection crops up again: “The birds do not memorize the used caches but use certain indications or certain criteria, always the same, to hide the seeds. Finding the caches again is thus not an exercise of the memory, but a combination of habits similar to those we typically use to park and return to our car.” The researcher therefore hid the seeds himself, and showed the caches to the birds. This had no impact on the performances. After having thus eliminated all the imaginary objections, the rival fictions in short, there remains for the researcher the opportunity to show that not only is his hypothesis correct but that it is perhaps even better than what the fictions have testified to. A two-stage experiment puts the tits back in the presence of the caches to let them eat half the seeds. In the second stage, twenty-four hours after this first phase of consumption, forty-eight hours after they had hidden the seeds, they are released once more into the artificial forest. The tits will show that they have not only stored the caches in memory but that they have, furthermore, memorized the caches already visited in the preceding visit. They thus memorize not only the filled caches but also the emptied ones. 43 This examination in an imaginary court seems to constitute here the guarantee against subjectivity, against the opinion of just one. The experiment becomes the locus of an imaginary public space, a fictional way to open the doors of the natural laboratory. In a way, this examination plays the role of the initial trial, with publication allowing, for its part, the appeal proceedings for wrongfully ousted fictions or for sanctioning fictions with inflated claims. During this stage the imaginary jury ceases to perform the role of a real jury, who will, in principle, not miss any of the failed objections or any of the procedural flaws that occurred in its absence. the babblers on trial If we turn now to the trial in which Jon will stage the babblers, we still do not find all the characteristics of the procedure. In fact, this trial is still in its first phase, in which possible alternatives are considered. The trial itself will only begin next spring. Yet we can already point out a few of the permanent features of the confrontation of fictions in the courtroom of the experiment. The alternative fictions are here the hypotheses that seek to explain “helping at the nest”: first, the initial hypothesis – issuing from the theory of kin selection – is that the birds assist those they are related to; the second fiction considers helping at the nest as a system of exchanges founded on reciprocity. Jon’s final fiction is the Zahavian hypothesis: the birds are “helpers at the nest” because this represents a good way for them to enhance or to demonstrate their status. How to decide between these fictions? An element of variation must be found for each by which the situation opens itself up to experimentation. The form of the assistance appears to meet all the requirements, and can be varied by introducing decoys. How the young are fed seems to reflect the way in which interests conflict within the group: for example, kinship theory predicts that the helping will be positively correlated with the degree of kinship but negatively correlated with the size of the group of helpers. This negative correlation is logical enough. The more Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 models and methods helpers there are, the less it is necessary to work for the brood. Contrariwise, within the framework of the Zahavian theory, the size of the group should not affect the helping since it is not useful to the recipient, but to the giver. The fiction of reciprocity must be evaluated on the basis of observation: do the current helping relationships reflect former relationships? And do they predict future relationships? It would seem that the observations carried out so far provide no evidence in support of this fiction. A first stage of the work consists in observing, for a certain period, how natural variations affect the relationships of helping at the nest. In the second stage, Jon will attempt to produce variations that should enable him to decide between the fictions: if the effort of a member of the group significantly increases, one can predict, according to each hypothesis, different consequences produced by this variation. Thus, if the fiction of kin selection is the “true” fiction, in response to the increased efforts of an individual, the other helpers will decrease their efforts. It is not necessary to force-feed the young; if they are fed, each of the helpers can attend to something else. Contrariwise, if Zahavi’s fiction is true, and if the act of feeding the young constitutes an exhibition, then even if an individual increases his provisioning the other helpers will maintain their level of effort, or will even enter into competition and increase it. For this stage, Jon will carry out a simple manipulation: he will provide some helpers with artificial feeders that will allow them to easily increase their apparent investment in alloparental care. In another stage of the trial, Jon also plans to decrease the capacity of some helpers. Three solutions were considered: to attach a weight to the tail of some babblers; to reduce the mobility of the beak of some – by a system of small ties; or else, to produce a decoy: the cries of chicks will be recorded and played next to the nest, when selected individuals pass by, in order to induce in them the belief of a very intense demand on the part of the brood. If they increase their efforts, one can measure the decrease, stabilization or increase of the efforts of other members of the group. This possibility should, in principle, be the only one used – for clear ethical reasons. If the imaginary tribunal of the experiment guarantees the a priorist approach, the question must now turn towards the a posteriorist to ask what guarantees his own. the a posteriorist approach In contrast to the experimental procedure which creates an identity between what grounds the hypothesis and what ensures its validity by means of the decisive experiment (which by showing “how it works” at the same time proves that “this is how it works”), Zahavi’s approach separates the two moments of the procedure. Zahavi himself separates them so well that he never occupied himself with the testing5 and left the care of this step to others. In fact, the tests to which the theory has given rise were carried out elsewhere, and mostly in order to contradict the theory: Slotow, Alcock, and Rothstein, for example, changed the colour of the feathers of dominated sparrows to “disguise” them as dominants. According to them, if the theory of the social control of status is correct and “cheating” is impossible, the dominated usurpers should be subjected to a change in the intensity of aggression, that is to say be much more frequently attacked. This was not the case. Since the usurpers were not revealed, the authors were able to conclude that the principle of reliability, which is at the heart of the handicap principle, was a false fiction. Some laboratories of fiction also tested the theory. After having refuted it, the procedures showed that the fiction was realistic. The process of collecting singular and anecdotal clues, which constitutes the groundwork for the investigation, tries to find, beyond and despite invariants and a priori, what is distinctive about the response of each individual. We mentioned the heresy of the primatologists; we find it again, here also, in the daily confrontation between the researcher and his babblers. The heretical approaches of one (the primatologists) like the other (Zahavi) are, in fact, the approaches used by anthropologists. The great 44 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 despret divide challenged by the new questions of the primatologists knows, especially here, to my mind, the signs of its erasure. This erasure can be explained as much by the methodology and the approaches used as by the particular personality of the bird. Zahavi is not only accepted close by the group, but he fits in with it and always moves to the middle of the birds, and not like an external observer would, from the outside, in front or behind. Most of the birds observed are tame – the others are called the barbarians. Each receives a name that allows it to be identified: the birds, like all living beings who are distant from us, appear too similar to each other to hope to recognize them without fail; thus each bird will be identified and named through the four colours of its bands. The name of each is thus formed from four initials of these colours in Hebrew: so when a researcher says he saw MMCT or AMMT, everyone knows exactly who he means, and to which group the bird belongs. new ethological time and space Like an anthropologist, Zahavi has learned to recognize each of the individuals and to know, over the years, the development of its alliances and its status. Thus one can know, by consulting the records and the archives of the large chart permanently displayed in the laboratory (and some of the articles that adopt this narrative form), that AMMT was born in 1975, that he lived with his father and a brother of the same brood. His mother was replaced by another female in 1977, and he became “breeding helper.”6 His dominant brother was driven from the territory and AMMT was thus able, on the death of his father, to become the dominant male. In 1975, he thus had five nestlings, six between 1980 and 1981. In 1982, there was once again a change of female and he could mate with her. The two sons that he had with the missing female who disappeared became breeding helpers. He drove one away and remained with the other until his death, in 1987. AMMT thus remained in the same territory all his life, waited to become dominant, 45 lived twelve years and had twenty-nine children as dominant. So, one can also find the more tumultuous story of SMTA, who had to conquer a new territory and lose his collaborators, or else that of MTMC, who was driven from his territory by his brother. He lived as a refugee, before being rejoined by two of his sons. After a few years occupying marginal territories he was able to replace a male who had just died, and form a new group. The bird’s time is thus structured like human historical time, and the stories become life stories. Ethological time is thus replaced by anthropological time. Space is also structured in a particular manner, since Zahavi observes from in the middle of the birds. The ritual of approach and of encounter initiates – and doubtless defines – the relationship: Zahavi whistles by imitating the babbler’s call and throws them bread. The babblers respond, hop up to him, eat the bread, then return to their activities without seeming to be concerned about his presence any longer. The distinctive structuring of space is made possible by the familiarity of the birds. It is possible, yet it is not necessary, and each researcher integrates the relationship into a substantially different space: Jon, the Oxford zoologist, experimenter constantly putting the fictions on trial, establishes with the birds a relationship of distant spectator. He is either in front or behind, never in the middle, never too close. Roni [Osztreiher], the doctoral assistant, is always in front of them, but so close that the other researchers reproach him for disturbing the birds (we saw him, one day, block with his head the entrance to a bush where the nest was found, in order to observe more closely). The spatial structuring of the encounter between Zahavi and the birds shapes as a space without borders between the observer and the observed. To this space without borders corresponds, in an analogous manner, a common mental space, the space of anthropomorphic identification: “When we do not understand why an animal does this or that, we try to understand what use this behaviour could serve in humans, then we try to see if the hypothesis Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 models and methods can be confirmed by these observations” (Zahavi, pers. comm.). It is this procedure that Zahavi calls the anthropomorphic model. This model should not be understood here as a model in the technical sense of the term, but rather as a psychological model, the referent of identification. A controversial heuristic strategy, it was nevertheless the tried and tested method of many hunters: Bushmen, for example, so identify with the animal they are hunting that they can answer questions like “what should I do now if I were this animal?” with amazing accuracy (Kennedy 94–95). Zahavi’s approach, however, diverges on one key point: interpretation is substituted for prediction. The question is not so much “what will it do?” – a question whose answer can confirm or refute the fiction – but “why does it do it?” – whose response does not have the power to oust alternative fictions. Interpretations will always suffer from the impossibility of consensus about them. In other words, as I commented regarding the investigation, the sharing of fictions can only be based on common opinion; disagreement expresses the inability of the interpretive statement to be anything other than a mere fiction dependent on the intentions and convictions of its author.7 This inability is all the more marked as the anthropomorphism proceeds from an identification of causes with intentions, thus bringing about a confusion between intentionality and causality. In sum, as will have been well understood from the beginning, the “how” is far more of a “why.” The fictions encounter and confront each other, without allowing them to be decided between. This work will be done elsewhere. Anthropomorphism and the anthropological method complement each other in a process of fictionalization of a very particular kind: not only everything that the animal does or demonstrates receives a meaning, but each of the behavioural sequences must be understood as the best possible compromise by which the animal does what it can. This process of the saturation of meanings and of the elaboration of positive and rewarding fictions is not only linked to the attributive or projective mechanisms of anthropomorphism nor to the anthropological approaches characterized by spatial proximity and personal relationships, even though it is largely dependent on them. It is based on an evolutionary epistemology coupled with an ontology of nature: “the Oxford people,” says Zahavi, “argue the stupidity of the cuckoo. For me, if the cuckoo is stupid, it is because it is good to be stupid, because some errors are less costly. I do not think that there is in nature much room for these kinds of problems like the arms race. It is thought, in this framework, that one is stupid and the other intelligent. The strategy of deceit is only good if you think that the others are fools.” To the ontology with Panglossian resonances (everything that is in nature is the best possible) will correspond what I would call a genuine epistemological ethic – that probably also allows the opportunity of going beyond the perception and study of invariants: “if I go into nature and I see a peculiar behaviour that I can not understand, I have two options: either I do like at Oxford, and I say this animal is stupid, or I say to myself that it is me who is stupid, and I remain in the field until I understand” (pers. comm.). It seems that this is the message that Richard Dawkins understood, and which seems to create difficulties, when he wrote, in the second edition of The Selfish Gene, the amendment correcting the criticisms levelled at Zahavi in the first edition: if Zahavi’s hypothesis is correct, which now seems to him to be the case, the prospect is worrying “because it means that theories of almost limitless craziness can no longer be ruled out on commonsense grounds. If we observe an animal doing something really silly, like standing on its head instead of running away from a lion, it may be doing it in order to show off to a female. It may even be showing off to the lion: ‘I am such a highquality animal you would be wasting your time trying to catch me’. But, no matter how crazy I think something is, natural selection may have other ideas” (313). The saturation of meanings brought about by the anthropomorphic, anthropological, adaptationist and fictional approach is not unlike this 46 despret characteristic of mythic rationalities, such as they are described by Lévi-Strauss: before a reality to be understood and its lack of meaning, its non-testable objects and its experiences without objects, myth will furnish “a plethora of meaning” (181) and overload reality. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 mythic scene and experimental scene We have seen that to our description of Zahavi’s method as a mythical and attributive approach taking place between two characters – human and bird – we have opposed the experimental approach by describing it as one that triangulates the roles, since it always involves three characters: a bird-witness, an observer-manipulator and an imaginary jury. Can it be maintained that the latter protects itself in this way against any attributive temptation? In other words, can it be thought, according to these descriptions, that one of the two approaches is totally attributive and that the other protects the triangular system thus formed from the intrusion of subjectivity and from the processes at work in mythic rationalities? I will recall here two interpretive events: the hypothesis concerning the “modesty” of the babblers, first, and later that of the “false signal.” Recall that with the social control hypothesis Zahavi states that the “modest” male who keeps the other males away from the scene of coupling proves to the female his capacity to defend future interferences around the nest. We will later analyse the “mirror” phenomenon between Zahavi’s methods and the way the males perform the expulsion of other suitors. We can now consider Jon’s alternative proposal: according to him, the Zahavian interpretation of the demand for privacy forgets an important character in the scene: the female. The females, although in a different way, also exercise a form of social control. They can accordingly be in conflict with the males, even if this conflict does not take the appearance of an open conflict. According to Jon, the female can achieve this control by hiding from the males who is the father of the eggs. If the female can hide the coupling, and 47 if she isolates herself with each of the males of the group, none of them can be certain that he is not the father of the brood. On the contrary, if the coupling is truly discreet, each of them will be able to have good presumptions concerning the paternity of the eggs. Consequently, each of the males has a vested interest in taking care of offspring that could be his own. Before anything else, I pause to underline that Jon has well demonstrated one of the most important lacunas of the Zahavian system: a peculiar enough “androcentrism.” The male controls the totality of relations, and what could be interpreted as a demand of the females becomes an exhibition of the male. Furthermore, it will be noted that the influence of the theoretical framework of the arms race is evident here: conflicting interests, evolving strategies, a parasite – the female – who exploits a host – the male invests his efforts in a brood that could just as well be that of another. The interpretive grid marks its signature very clearly at the bottom of the interpretations: rather than the interpretive grid, it seems to us to become, in this particular context of the emergence of interpretations in “the field,” a genuine fiction-producing grid. Alongside the influence of the theoretical corpus, the practices themselves seem to colour the interpretations and the construction of fictions, as if the observer attributed his own practice to those he observed. The female in fact uses the means of the experimenter. Beyond the grid of the arms race, what is described of the female is curiously similar to the experimental procedures: setting up of decoys – however, in a vaguer sense of the term than the usual one in ethology – in the form of creation of beliefs, manipulation of subjects. This analogy will seem much clearer – and even more pertinent – in our second example: the false signal hypothesis. The “false signal” hypothesis of food contribution has been interpreted by Jon as an “anti-bluff” manoeuvre. I have already connected this hypothesis to the general theoretical model that constitutes the interpretive framework of his hypotheses, and have shown that this statement could be largely dependent on Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 models and methods this framework. We can try to go further in the hypotheses and show that here, too, the attributive approach is present in this type of reading of behaviours and colours the hypotheses, albeit in a more implicit way. What does the bird do, in Jon’s hypothesis? It verifies the actual hunger of the brood by creating a “test” experiment. It acts on a variable to measure the deviation from the norm, it creates a decoy that allows it to decide between the duplicity of causes, it does not rely on what seems obvious and makes the brood the locus of experimentation. Thus, according to our hypothesis, in his interpretation of the behaviour of the bird, by attributing to it an identical approach to that which he uses, Jon created a “mirror effect.” He attributed to the bird his own approach, his frame of thought, his procedure. The methodology thus also becomes the source and model of the fictions. my own. But let those who are laughing, by making of me the object of the same analysis as that of the previous level, know that they, too, have just created an almost infinite play of mirrors, a regression of reflected attributions, as in the famous painting of the mirror that reflects a mirror, etc. And let them accept, henceforth, to laugh with me, and no longer at me. Here, no doubt, also resides the lesson of laughter inflicted on the ironists by Isabelle Stengers when she invites us to find together this “capacity to recognize oneself as a product of the history whose construction one is trying to follow” (Invention of Modern Science 66). We have thus just caught up with one of our very first aporias: the outcome of the analysis we made of the anthropologist sent to Rosenthal, which showed the impossible exteriority of the researcher, his total inclusion and the inaccessibility of the fundamental hypothesis. the tables turned and the laughter of passers-by methodologies and loyalties It will not escape the reader that we are not ourselves sheltered from mythic rationality when we consider what I call here the mirror processes. Mirror processes are those that cause the content of the analysis to reflect the form or the procedure used – for example, when an a priori approach preferentially analyses the a priori of behaviour – or else, when the researcher seems to regard the animal as doing, at the same time as him, the same thing as him: when Zahavi reads behaviour in terms of information he attributes to the animal the same role and the same work as that taken or done by the observer (reading the behaviour of his fellows as so many sources of information); likewise, when Jon sees the helper at the nest as testing the fledglings he attributes to the bird a genuine work of experimentation in the nest. This will be the occasion to pause here a minute to share a laugh with those who haven’t missed the following fact: I apply the same mythic rationality, and I attribute to each of the researchers the same approach as If one was to take up again the idea of a continuum of methodologies observed in the field, ranging from the more anthropo-morphological (Zahavi) to the more experimental (Jon), a third character appears whose ambivalence sheds another light on the practices of each. Rather than a real mediator, Roni, Zahavi’s doctoral assistant, strikes me as the bearer of two difficult-to-reconcile projects, of two loyalties to divergent orders of practice. His practice itself seems indicative of these tensions: if, on the one hand, he clearly adopts the position of outside spectator, if he neither whistles at nor feeds the birds, on the other hand, he adopts so intimate an approach that he cannot be without influence on their behaviour. Conscious of the demands and necessities of the domain in which he works – that is to say, constructing spaces for the confrontation of fictions – and of the need to subscribe to it in order to be published, he remains, however, close to Zahavi’s methodologies: the management of space can thus be seen as a compromise between the “uninvolved” distance of the 48 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 despret objective spectator and the crowding of the anthropologist. I will also analyse his practice as an attempt at conciliation between the demands of putting fictions to the test of the experimental approach and the demands of a descriptive and interpretive practice of the anthropological approach. If we return, for a moment, to the disagreement over the babblers’ dance, it is to recall first that his interpretation remained fully Zahavian. Then, one will be able to suggest that the dance offers him something other than the locus of a disagreement: it brings him above all the evidence of the influence of the observer on the subjects observed. And through this evidence, by giving him something to work on, the dance provides him with the opportunity to reconcile the demands of the two approaches. What he learned is perhaps also no stranger to his intrusive manner of intervening in the groups. Moreover, this style is all the more intrusive as he is accompanied, in his work, by rather cumbersome video equipment. Visits to the birds are regularly in the morning, at sunrise, and in the afternoon, from around 3 o’clock until the sun sets and the birds sleep. The dances can be observed on certain days, just after rising and just before sleeping. Remember the two hypotheses in play: according to Zahavi, the dance, like a ritual, is a test imposed on partners; according to Roni, it is the means of affirming his superiority, particularly for the sharing of resources. Roni’s research begins with a simple enough observation: the frequency of the dances varies in the course of the year. And yet, if Zahavi’s hypothesis is correct, if the dance’s function is to test the strength of the group’s links, the dance should have a higher frequency at the moment when the group needs to be the most supportive, that is to say when the adults must perform the most tasks in common. This solidarity is particularly crucial in the period that follows the hatching of the eggs. And yet, Roni notes, this is not the case. Just after the hatching the frequency of the dances decreases sharply. 49 Roni then sets about comparing two types of groups: on the one hand, groups that have successfully carried out the reproductive stage; on the other, groups that were unsuccessful in this phase. Once the first group’s eggs have hatched he finds that the level of competition is greatly reduced, while at the same time this phenomenon does not occur in the groups which have no eggs: the competition remains at the same level. Among the latter, the frequency of dances remains high as long as possibilities to reproduce exist. Only at the end of the reproductive season does one witness the gradual disappearance of the dances. A final point lends support to the thesis of the importance of “status” in the function of the ritual: the adults dance at the time of sexual competition, with a view to reproduction; the young will do it most frequently in autumn, at the time of competition over food resources. Access to these resources, during the most difficult period of winter, will be determined by the outcome of these competitions. We can already glimpse that Roni’s methodologies seem distinct from Zahavi’s: that which, in the master, proceeds from an intuitive development becomes, in the student, the object of a procedure for the verification of fiction. It is not yet a matter of a real confrontation of fictions in a courtroom designed to decide between them – Roni does not yet interfere here in the natural course of things – but of the substitution of one mode of questioning for another: to Zahavi’s “why,” Roni opposes a “how.” With the answer to this “how,” he thus hopes to supplant the fictions of “why.” Zahavi makes claims on the basis of a series of clues, and answers the question of why the birds dance – like a good investigator, he seeks the motive. Roni, for his part, carries out the reconstruction: “it can’t be about this because of that.” Roni seeks proof. If we were to continue our metaphor linking the investigation and the trial, I would situate Roni in the intermediary phase: the investigation is concluded, it is now the stage of preparing the case. One builds up the stock of witnesses, studies the plausibility of the facts and motives. In relation to laboratory work, one can suggest that the work has Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 models and methods received, with Roni, a first “purification”: from a qualitative analysis, one slides towards a quantitative analysis of these qualities. It is, strictly speaking, not yet a matter of a genuine work of experimentation or of putting fictions to the test, since it is always about “watching and doing nothing.” However, another part of Roni’s research – which is the consequence of his work observing the dances – seems to me to attest to a certain will to do science.8 Roni noted, as his research went along, that the frequency of the dances not only varied in the course of the events in the life of the group but that it seemed to be affected by the manner and timing of the observers’ visits. He thus elaborated the plan for a comparative experimental study, modifying the hours of visits and how they are carried out (the distance, the presence or absence of equipment … ). He thereby discovered that night time visits reduced the chance of the morning dance, while morning visits increased it. He then organized quite a job of analysing the influence of the observer on the behaviour of the observed. One might at first think that, with this experiment, Roni questions Zahavi on the subject of his habituation practices. But this does not account for the way in which he himself practises the approach. If this research reveals that Roni has, in a certain way, internalized the reproaches of his colleagues, or else has realized that “something” was going on, it seems to me to indicate a more important factor regarding this type of approach. This research seems to respond to a twofold imperative. The first, just evoked, is that employed by Zahavi, which consists of observing and doing nothing (not modifying the environment more than is done by the presence of the observer); the second responds to the criteria of the experimental approaches: to better observe, study the variation that the experimenter produces in the natural course of things. Here, however, it is not the bird who is called as witness in the trial of fictions but the particular relationship between the researcher and his subject-object. In this context, the variables are nothing other than the researcher himself, time, and space; the laboratory, to him, will be the space of their singular relationship. Here, it is not the fictions that are put on trial but the researcher himself who is put on the stand. Here, the bird will not be the passive subject of the manipulation of its environment but will be called into a relation that asks for its participation. This is where the dance appeared to me to offer him something other than the locus of a disagreement: through it, he could actively create the conditions for the reconciliation of two contradictory demands with which he found himself confronted. This experiment then would be, for Roni, a way to demonstrate his loyalty to the field practices of his teacher. He adopts in it the anthropological approach of Zahavi, but to take it even further, to its conclusion: with it, in fact, and this is the culmination of an anthropological approach in ethology, he takes into account the fact that those whom he questions will integrate the dispositive that questions them and give it meaning. disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author. notes Translated from Vinciane Despret, Naissance d’une théorie éthologique: La Danse du cratérope écaillé © Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond, 1996, 135–70. 1 Bachelard writes: “we understand nature by resisting it” (33). [Translator’s note.] 2 I must thank Ezio Tirelli for having, during a discussion on the subject, emphasized this distinction. 3 A number of controversies in animal psychology will also bear on this argument (Collins and Pinch). This procedure seems rather old since it can already be found at the beginning of the century in Kropotkin. He in fact rebels against the claim that marmots are aggressive: it is only in conditions of captivity that this phenomenon may take place; 50 despret the marmots he encountered in the field were, for their part, entirely peaceful. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 4 A detailed record can also be found in Marian Dawkins’ book Through Our Eyes Only?, which utilizes not the procedure but rather the data obtained from the experiment to discuss the problem of the attribution of cognitive faculties among birds. 5 Except in an article, prior to 1973, devoted to the hybridization of certain birds, and in some articles written in collaboration with some a priorists about the behaviour of the cuckoo, for example, the results of research conducted in Japan in collaboration with a Japanese zoologist (Lotem, Hitoshi, and Zahavi). 6 In English in the original. [Translator’s note.] 7 “The ‘authority’ of experimental science, its claim to objectivity, thus has no other source than the negative: a statement has conquered – at a given epoch, of course, and not in the absolute – the means to demonstrate that it is not a simple fiction, relative to the intentions and convictions of its author” (Stengers, Invention of Modern Science 90). 8 One will recognize here the borrowing of a title from Isabelle Stengers: La Volonté de faire science. bibliography Bachelard, Gaston. The Formation of the Scientific Mind: A Contribution to a Psychoanalysis of Objective Knowledge. Trans. Mary McAllester Jones. Manchester: Clinamen, 2002. Print. Collins, Harry, and Trevor Pinch. The Golem: What Everyone Should Know about Science. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1993. Print. Dawkins, Marian Stamp. Through Our Eyes Only? The Search for Animal Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1998. Print. Dawkins, Richard. The Selfish Gene. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1989. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “Domesticating Practices: The Case of Arabian Babblers.” Routledge Handbook of Human–Animal Studies. Ed. Garry Marvin and Susan McHugh. Abingdon: Routledge, 2014. 23– 38. Print. 51 Despret, Vinciane. “Ecology and Ideology: The Case of Ethology.” International Problems 63.3–4 (1994): 45–61. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “Éthique et éthologie: Une histoire naturelle de l’altruisme.” Cahiers d’éthologie 11.2 (1991): 141–266. Print. Despret, Vinciane, et al. L’Homme en société. Paris: PUF, 1995. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “L’Idée de société en éthologie.” Cahiers d’éthologie 13.4 (1995): 435– 68. Print. Kennedy, John S. The New Anthropomorphism. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1992. Print. Lévi-Strauss, Claude. Structural Anthropology. Trans. Claire Jacobsen and Brooke Grundfest Schoepf. New York: Basic, 1963. Print. Lorenz, Konrad. Behind the Mirror: A Search for a Natural History of Human Knowledge. Trans. Ronald Taylor. London: Methuen, 1977. Print. Lotem, Arnon, Nakamura Hitoshi, and Amotz Zahavi. “Rejection of Cuckoo Eggs in Relation to Host Age: A Possible Evolutionary Equilibrium.” Behavioral Ecology 3.2 (1992): 128– 32. Print. Slotow, Robert, Joe Alcock, and Stephen I. Rothstein. “Social Status Signalling in WhiteCrowned Sparrows: An Experimental Test of the Social Control Hypothesis.” Animal Behavior 46.5 (1993): 977–89. Print. Stengers, Isabelle. The Invention of Modern Science. Trans. Daniel W. Smith. Minneapolis and London: U of Minnesota P, 2000. Print. Stengers, Isabelle. La Volonté de faire science. Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond, 1990. Print. Strum, Shirley. Almost Human. New York: Norton, 1990. Print. Strum, Shirley, and Bruno Latour. “Redefining the Social Link: From Baboons to Humans.” Social Science Information 26.4 (1987): 783–802. Print. Zahavi, Amotz. “Arabian Babblers: The Quest for Social Status in a Cooperative Breeder.” Cooperative Breeding in Birds: Long-Term Studies of Ecology and Behavior. Ed. Peter B. Stacey and Walter D. Koenig. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1990. 103–30. Print. models and methods Zahavi, Amotz. “Some Comments on Sociobiology.” Auk 98.2 (1981): 412–15. Print. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 Zahavi, Amotz, and Avishag Zahavi. The Handicap Principle: A Missing Piece of Darwin’s Puzzle. New York and Oxford: Oxford UP, 1997. Print. Vinciane Despret Philosophie et Lettres Université de Liège 4000 Liège Belgium E-mail: [email protected] Matthew Chrulew Centre for Culture and Technology Research and Graduate Studies Faculty of Humanities Curtin University GPO Box U1987 Perth, WA 6845 Australia E-mail: [email protected] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:09 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:10 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:10 21 November 2015 ANGELAKI journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 translator’s foreword Vinciane Despret describes her 2002 book Quand le loup habitera avec l’agneau [When the Wolf Will Live with the Lamb] as “the major scientific statement of my research.” The book continues along avenues she had started previously, such as the ethology of ethologists, the importance of asking the right questions in research, and the characterization of some ethological inquiries as sleuthing akin to a detective novel. Building on her book about Zahavi and the Arabian babblers, Despret furthers her inquiry into both important historical episodes in the development of ethology and contemporary research that continues to build the discipline. She structures the book in part as a series of letter-essays dedicated to persons who have influenced her thinking and being, with several chapters drawing on concepts or ideas from those to whom they are addressed (the chapter here on ravens is to Bruno Latour, and it draws on his concepts of interest and the Greek middle voice as a formulation that allows for thinking the intertwining of agency in productive contexts of interaction and research). The title of the book, of course, refers to the famous verse in the Book of Isaiah 11.6 that prophesies a time when, “The wolf will live with the lamb, the leopard will lie down with the goat, the calf and the lion and the yearling together; and a little child will lead them.” Isaiah provides a vivid imaginary of multispecies bonds and flourishing. The first chapter of the book, on “Transformations,” dedicated to Despret’s son JulesVincent Lemaire, concerns changes that animals and animal cultures can undergo over time, and makes the case that non- vinciane despret translated by jeffrey bussolini THE ENIGMA OF THE RAVEN human animals are equally as much subjects of history as humans are. The second chapter, “The Primate at the Origin of our History,” to Jean-Marc Gay, looks at how conditions of confinement and observation in early research on primates, notably by Solly Zuckerman, introduced longstanding misconceptions about primate behavior that continued to reproduce themselves in the literature for decades. The third chapter, “Apes and Savages in an Anarchist World,” to Didier Demorcy, addresses the work of Kropotkin and Russian naturalists who saw cooperation rather than competition defining animal interactions; the chapter also looks at how different figurings of the relationship between apes and so-called primitive humans, for instance in Darwin and Freud, ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020057-16 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039842 57 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 the enigma of the raven have led to widely differing cultural and political ideals. Chapter 4, on “How to Have Trust in Prophets,” to Thelma Rowell, analyzes how, despite numerous reports of striking cognitive, technical, and emotional capabilities among primates and other animals in early naturalist literature, quasi-theological and anthropocentric notions such as that of the great chain of being caused a subsequent ignoring or disavowal of them; she points to the importance of changing ourselves as humans to change animals (in our observations and interactions with them). Chapter 5 evaluates “Successes and Achievements” as they might be construed for different animals; the importance of taking into account an animal’s own point of view and interests leads to a better sense of interesting achievements. Chapter 6 addresses “The Habits of Researchers and their Animals” and extends the argument about how changing human habits also gives other animals a chance to change theirs, and looks at ethology as a practice of habits involving distance, knowing activity, politeness, milieu, and alliance. Chapter 7, dedicated to Isabelle Stengers, is “Becoming Woman,” and it looks at how the practice and activity of women ethologists such as Thelma Rowell, Shirley Strum, and Barbara Smuts refigure ethology (not because of their gender but because of their practice and the questions they pursue); it is no accident that Jane Goodall, Dian Fossey, and Birute Galdikas have transformed the field of primatology. Chapter 8, to Bruno Latour, is translated here. Chapter 9 looks into “What Parrots Talk About” and considers talking birds and primates as subjective interlocutors who can become persons in the exchanges allowed by language; setting, milieu, and influence (cohabitation) are central aspects of the interactions and research with these animals. Chapter 10, to Jocelyne Porcher and Dominique Lestel, concerns “Bringing Animals into Politics” and recalls the intriguing story that Edward Thompson (who has come up earlier in the book) was motivated in naturalism and primatology by his hopes to help instantiate Isaiah’s prophecy in terms of multispecies interaction. It looks at the tremendous suffering and domination visited upon animals by human society, and at ideas of composing with and “living well together” as some avenues fraught with possibility yet also vigilance. to bruno latour “ S ome years ago, the American Skinnerians, who had heard tell somewhere that there existed other birds than the eternal pigeon, tried to replace it with the great raven. Without success. The raven, who found the situation in a Skinner Box profoundly absurd, did not at all wish to push on the levers at the command of the little lights that illuminated or for any other signal. Instead, it successfully used its enormous beak to completely dismantle the apparatus. This behavior was judged to be unamerican and everyone went back to pigeons” (Chauvin 138). Certainly, in resisting the propositions of the behaviorist researchers with admirable vigor, the raven no doubt escaped years of monotonous labor in dispositives that were probably none too thrilling for beings of such remarkable curiosity.1 It was this quality that seemed to cause so much consternation for the American researchers: evidently, they never posed the question of knowing what a raven could, through this somewhat maniacal behavior, teach them about what interested it. “Recalcitrance” to the impoliteness of the behaviorists, in demonstrating such strong incivility, was not the only crime that the ravens were guilty of, according to the researchers. We might recall that before becoming their specialist, Bernd Heinrich classified them at the very bottom of the ladder of choices considered sensible by ornithologists. The list of their annoying habits does not stop there: when Heinrich submitted to his mentor a thesis proposal to study ravens, he strongly dissuaded him. Little work had been done on ravens, but the testimony of those who knew them or spent time with them converged: they are of remarkable intelligence. It would be better to avoid studying an animal that is smarter than you, he told him, in sagely 58 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 despret recommending the study of protozoans the simplicity of which, the author reassures us, nonetheless presents interesting problems. If you want to study ravens, it will take you years before knowing them. Their timidity – that Heinrich attributes to the fact that they had been, in our regions, victims of accusations of the most diverse abuses and persecuted for it – makes them altogether unapproachable. And then count on still more years before any of the information that you would be able to gather with difficulty can make even the least sense. Beyond that, if you try to elaborate any model to make sense of their behaviors they will take a malign pleasure in contradicting it in the course of subsequent observations. Ravens, evidently, do not want to obey any of the rules that make research possible: the incivility that excommunicated them from the laboratories of the behaviorists having already been stigmatized from the time of the Flood – the ravens were in fact the only ones to have disobeyed the rule that stipulated that there be no mating on Noah’s Ark. Unruly, unpredictable, calling into question even the intelligence of their researchers, the pertinence of their models, and the solidity of their dispositives, they are by all accounts unreliable; in any case, they were not so to a sufficient degree to succeed in recruiting an army of biographers, as primates had been able to do. However, after some years spent in caring for the peaceable world of protozoa and no doubt forgetting the sage advice of his advisors, Bernd Heinrich will decide to resubmit his candidacy to the ravens. A sabbatical year offered by the University of Vermont, where he taught, and the possession of a country house in the Maine forests where the ravens Corvus corax live, will provide the opportunity for it. This year will be followed by another, by another still, and will end up extending beyond a decade. The ravens will literally recruit their researcher into what will become a passionate inquiry; they will reveal to him the resolution of an enigma the difficulty and the interest of which would be in accord with what makes them impossible to study. This inquiry will come to resemble, gradually with 59 its unfolding, more and more those tales to which the master writers of suspense invite us. And this inquiry, full of suspense and sudden turns, from season to season, from enigma to findings, from hypotheses to tests, will transform all that we know about ravens. However, if we can fairly compare this adventure that will link Heinrich and his ravens to a police investigation it is necessary also to observe that, to the contrary of many of them, the “guilty” of the story are given from the beginning: it is the ravens. That which we could consider to be the “crime,” the act that transgresses the rules and expectations, is also known: the ravens present a behavior that has no sense from the point of view of evolution. This “crime” that will kick off the whole affair appeared to Heinrich by accident in the course of an observation even before the inquiry commenced: fifteen ravens were feeding around a carcass. Nothing could be more banal, we might think. Unless this were an assembly of wrongdoers, and these wrongdoers could be deemed guilty of the transformation of an animal into a carcass – which is not the case since ravens generally do not attack living creatures unless they are of very small size – there is really no cause here to open an investigation. Now, in the eyes of someone who knows Maine ravens a bit, this behavior is justifiably suspect. In principle, these ravens have no business being there all together. In Maine, they are not only rare but most often solitary, with the exception of some couples and whilst raising young. If certain ravens can come together at night to share a communal nest, during the day they generally avoid one another and go about their business in places that are at a distance from one another. The presence of many ravens at the same site can therefore not be due to simple habit or coincidence. Of course, the carcass is a sufficient motive for coming together; but how would they have been made aware of it, from many kilometers away? The response is simple, Heinrich explains: they could not all have come unless the raven who found this carcass had called them, explicitly. If that one had wanted to maintain the privilege of dining on the Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 the enigma of the raven carcass, the other ones would never have known: ravens are capable of being silent when they don’t care to be noticed. This “recruitment” behavior of others around a carcass, Heinrich concludes, goes against all logic. Given the rarity of resources, a raven who finds food has no interest in being joined by others; and it has all the means of avoiding it in remaining discreet. Why then had a raven called the others, why had it invited the others to share in the party? If food is difficult to find, why take the risk of needing to share it, when ravens are true experts in hiding food items? Heinrich therefore had the “crime”: an absurd behavior from the point of view of traditional models of evolution; he also had the guilty parties. On the other hand, that which would make up the crux of the enigma and which could not be elucidated except at the end of a long and patient inquiry, the most important element in the eyes of an ethologist, would be the motive. Why do ravens do that which the logic of evolution should prohibit them from doing? It is this motive that it will be not only a matter of discovering but also of inscribing in the regime of proof. As far as suppositions are concerned, there are many that we could make of this situation. We could gamble on the generosity of ravens, in an anthropomorphic version that ethologists prefer to avoid since the hypothesis is difficult to test. We could, in a more plausible and verifiable manner, advance the hypothesis of a moment of distraction or stupidity: the behavior would not be repeated in other circumstances. We could also take up, to give credit to the ravens, the hypothesis that Zahavi developed to understand the babblers: the fact of sharing food affirms the prestige of the one who offers it to others and permits him to climb, with a great economy of conflicts, the hierarchical ladder. Ravens, even if generally timid, are not sparing with moments of bravery. Some of these could be interpreted as a desire to cause a sensation. Many observations describe very audacious aerial acrobatics – steep nosedives toward the ground with a swerve at the last minute – generally followed by an attempt at one-upmanship by one or other congener; simulations of attacks on wolves, eagles, or dogs, or even the theft of their food from right under their noses. Some observations have even shown that, following simulated attacks, a raven will prevent its companions from coming to its assistance, as if it wanted to conserve the privilege of showing its bravery. Ravens also accomplish a series of acts that appear to be useless, that pertain at once to both the game and to the affirmation of skill: transporting objects in their feet, wrapping up these objects, especially in the presence of a female, it would seem, rolling on their backs, doing superb slides in the snow or pushing snow onto their companions. This hypothesis of “exhibition” therefore would merit being tested. One could also just as well think that ravens practice a system of reciprocity of exchanges of good conduct, as has been observed among certain vampire bats in Costa Rica. A raven who shares a find can count on the fact that its companions will return the favor, when the occasion presents itself. Yet another version can be evoked, with the theory of sociobiology. In this case the ravens would constitute an umpteenth example of the “all purpose” model and, dominating in this area, of the theory of the “selfish gene.”2 According to this theory, any animal presenting behaviors that are said to be “altruistic,” whether it be a bee “sacrificing” itself for its hive sisters, a bird renouncing reproduction to feed the young of another, or a primate aiding a congener in difficulty, is guided by a single motivation; this would be to transmit the greatest possible number of its genes to the population. Applied to ravens, this theory would stipulate that, certainly, the “altruistic” recruiters diminish their chances of survival in sharing a rare resource, but that the “sacrifice,” costly from the individual point of view, can reap benefits in regard to evolution. In effect, still according to this theory, if the raven shares the find with an individual who carries a similar genetic baggage as its own, a close relative for instance, it augments the probabilities of transmitting its genes to the next generation, in promoting the survival of those whom it 60 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 despret helps. According to the sociobiologists, this model permits the resolution, once and for all, of the mysteries of apparently paradoxical behaviors such as “altruistic” behaviors, whether they concern ants, Florida blue jays, or hamadryas baboons. The animal simply obeys a relatively inflexible rule: help your relatives, ignore others, and you will multiply the copies of yourself. Ravens, however, do not seem to want to yield to this rule: their sense of the family does not extend beyond the migration of young. One could incidentally think that if they had done so the investigator would have quickly reached his conclusions: when animals are similar and all do the same thing, he says, they very quickly become boring as subjects of study. If the underlying principles become simple enough, they lose all interest once you have grasped them. In other words, no investigator worthy of the name could be fascinated by a crime committed by an idiot without imagination. Now, everything led Heinrich to believe that this situation had nothing to do with such a person, and that those in whom he was interested would require, on the contrary, resources of imagination, curiosity, and patience to be able to understand the enigma. For of all the available models to take account of the reasons for cooperation among the birds, none seemed able to accommodate the observations. When a model finally seems to connect all the elements and give them meaning, a new version of recruitment appears that places the whole model into question. How does the motive make the “crime” an achievement for the raven? How to accord this achievement with that which translates, for a raven, the fact of succeeding in its everyday survival? Clearly everything depends upon the criteria that you use to qualify this as an achievement. If you opt for the sociobiological theory, you must evaluate the reproductive success, and try to link together in the same schema the carcass, the recruitments, the relatives, the descendants, long-term strategic choices and DNA. Your animal will be above all similar to others, and all the variations will 61 be nothing but details of the same motive. On the other hand, if you are interested in the differences, in unexpected strategies, if you take into account the fact that the animal does not cease to transgress the rules and models and that it is unpredictable in its choices, you must adopt other criteria of achievement. It is this that the ravens seem to demand. The criterion of achievement chosen by Heinrich has nothing of an ambitious program about it: on the contrary, it leaves the program totally open in regards to its realization. The primary achievement of a raven, the author explains, is first and foremost that it “can procure resources from the environment and convert them to more of itself” (Heinrich, Ravens in Winter 36). Based on this simple premise, all organizations remain possible. “Converting the environment into a little more of itself” offers huge scope for invention – and incidentally responds well to the raven’s extraordinary opportunism. It remained then to understand how the recruitment of others around resources constitutes, paradoxically, a way of realizing this achievement, of accomplishing this conversion. The search for a motive will demand of the author that he explore all the paths, consider all the conditions, imagine all the tricks and stratagems. The politeness of “getting to know”3 here takes on a surprising form: the relationship is no longer inscribed in the register on which I insisted in the previous chapters, a register of negotiations of interests and stakes. Certainly, the question remains the same: it does concern “getting to know” by posing the question, in terms of achievement, what it is that interests the raven. But observation alone does not suffice. It is not only a matter of understanding what the raven does and how it does it; it is necessary to elucidate why it does it. Of course one could, in ideal conditions, observe the scene every day, verify whether the raven recruits each time, in what circumstances it does so and in what other ones it does not. But these conditions are not exactly those of ravens. Carcasses do not rain down in the forests of Maine, the activity on the highways notwithstanding. If you want to distinguish from the tangle of all the possible explanations, Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 the enigma of the raven in the skein of motives, that which can truly permit you to understand the stakes of the “crime,” you have to help things along; you have to create situations that permit the ravens to help you decide, among all the contesting fictions, the right fiction. You have to do so all the more so since the ravens will not show you, straightforwardly, what counts for them. If you see a raven in front of a carcass, hopping about in a “dance of hesitation,” not hazarding too close but seeming to wait for one of its comrades to begin the process of cutting into it, you can take up several possible interpretations, each of which modifies the reason for recruitment. The raven may have some fears, in view of past experiences, that the cadaver is in fact a predator who is feigning sleep and waiting for an imprudent raven in order to reverse the situation and convert the bird into a little more of itself: we might recall the trick thought up by Thompson’s monkey.4 You could also imagine that it is a question of precedence in the hierarchy, and that the subordinate ravens wait for the green light from the dominant; or that you are dealing with an inexperienced raven, who does not know how to open a carcass, and who does not know the vulnerable places on it. With the first hypothesis, the motive for recruitment would then be that of salutary egoism: it would be better to be with many others in the case of this type of error. On the second hypothesis, you find yourself with a model of social organization, with, for example, for the dominated, the obligation to share. In the third, you would have still another type of cooperation and the exchange of good conducts to make sense of the motive of recruitment: “I find, you open.” All the work of the researcher consists, then, in leading the ravens to take a position in relation to his fictions and hypotheses: resisting those that do not explain them; clarifying, in those that seem to be able to, that which counted for them. The scientist must, in other words, create a dispositive that confers on the ravens “the power not to submit to his interpretations.”5 It is in this way that the politeness of “getting to know” presents itself. It does so all the more, and it is here that I can develop this story as that of an investigation around a crime, in that it unfolds all along as a test of the intelligence and cunning of each of the partners. Heinrich’s research addresses the achievements of the ravens; it is interested in that which renders them enigmatic and fascinating; it interrogates them where they are competent and where we have to become more so, theoretically to the degree that we understand nothing about what they are doing, and practically to the degree that we have to learn their tricks to be able to approach them. And it addresses them above all where they actively resist the models to which they could have been subsumed. It is not only a matter of explaining or understanding but also a matter of finding the procedures that attest to the pertinence of these explanations. The enigma, like good detective stories, inscribes the protagonists in a relation of rivalry: if I want to understand them, Heinrich says in some way, I must try to be as smart and cunning, or more so, than they are. Not letting oneself be taken in easily, not letting oneself be duped by appearances, not according credence too swiftly; subjecting things to a strong standard of proof, enticing the ravens, cobbling together situations that oblige them to take a position. The politeness of “getting to know” does not necessarily turn on an attentive benevolence but on the art of finding the forces, and exchanging them, in an exercise of rivalry – constituted by a clever mixture of complicity and opposition – and of putting to the test. This politesse can sometimes even take the form of suspicion: “respect,” the etymology reminds us, demands of us to look twice (respectare). Confidence without verification offers little guarantee as to its robustness. A competence that is too easily accorded attests to nothing, if not to the great flexibility of our interpretations. If we want to witness in a reliable manner, if that which we learn from the ravens is to be treated with confidence, if we want to define ourselves as authorized by them to speak in their name, we are required to offer them the opportunity to show what they can do. If they are able to take a position in relation to the different versions that could 62 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 despret take account of what they do, the version that passes the test will emerge as the most robust. In this way, if numerous anecdotes on the subject of ravens report their intelligence, it does not honor them to accept this interpretation too quickly. Each anecdote, Heinrich explains, could be susceptible to an alternative explanation that is just as plausible: at times one recollection will suffice, at times the simple vigilance to things that we do not perceive, at other times still happenstance or chance. For example, when one observes a raven throw objects and detritus onto those who approach the nest, we consider right away that it must be an intentional and dissuasive strategy. But, Heinrich says, the behavior closely resembles that of a maniacal disturbed person who takes out their rage on objects. On the other hand, when we see a raven succeed in threading many pieces of meat on its beak before going to hide them, we could think that it anticipates the fact that others will come and steal the pieces he leaves on the ground during the journey. One could always respond that the simple desire not to tire itself out and to economize on comings and goings amply justifies this behavior, and that it gives no proof of the capacity of ravens to anticipate the intentions of others. Heinrich will propose to the ravens that he welcomed in an aviary to demonstrate their competences: they must prove that they are capable not only of anticipating the intentions of others but of acting accordingly. We have already made reference to this experiment, so we will briefly recall it here. Heinrich gives Orange a number of pieces of meat in front of his fellow creatures White and Red. Orange, anticipating what will become of this unexpected gift, immediately starts hiding the pieces. Each of his movements is, needless to say, watched by the two others, who do not then hesitate to dislodge the pieces of meat from their hiding places. Orange tries to follow them but must soon renounce the effort. Then he changes strategy: he simulates the act of hiding food, and when the others are busy digging to find them, he hides them 63 elsewhere, out of their view. The raven has become a reliable witness for his researcher’s proposition; he not only became worthy of the proposition, but he became, by the very form of it, autonomous in relation to the interpretations of his author. He helped the researcher to construct a “fact.” And the scientist, in giving the raven a chance to take a position in relation to his proposition, became worthy of witnessing in the raven’s name. Returning to our enigma, to the motive of apparently inexplicable behavior: how to ask the ravens, with the same politeness, to take a position in relation to all the possible conjectures of the investigation? How to ask them to teach us the good explanation, the right motive? How, in other words, to unmask the criminal? The researcher will have to learn the art of the trap and the net: the art of the lure and the trick; the art of learning, from those whose enigma you are trying to solve – and have no intention of helping you – how that which counts can count for them. It is, in sum, the art of the mētis (μῆτις) (Detienne and Vernant, Cunning Intelligence 11, 12; Les Ruses de l’intelligence 10), that particular form of intelligence that the Greeks cultivated, and that they learned from hunters and fishers, that intelligence that combines intuition, cunning, perspicacity, dissimulation, improvisation, vigilant attention and the sense of timeliness. It is the only way of getting to know (making knowledge) that can hope to address “intelligent, highly flexible” (Heinrich, Ravens in Winter 259) beings, like ravens, who require of those who want to know them the same flexibility and the same intelligence. And it is not by chance that it is this type of “getting to know,” long eclipsed by the choices made in philosophy, that is now returning in some ethological research. For this type of “getting to know” was constituted exactly “to be found in a domain where human intelligence is constantly at grips with the land or sea animals” (Detienne and Vernant, Cunning Intelligence 317; Les Ruses de l’intelligence 305) in an area where humans saw their intelligence and techniques transform in learning from animals. Heinrich, we will see, will Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 the enigma of the raven attest to the possibility of prolonging this transformation. Strange politeness, some might say, that goes by way of the art of cunning, lures, and manipulation: enticing ravens; seeing without being seen; tracking the least indications that would betray their motives; obliging them to choose; luring them to actualize the choices; creating situations as if they were natural so as to let the birds do the talking. But it is not a matter, in this research, of searching out the faults to weaken the ravens, quite the contrary: it is a matter rather of rendering them more robust in comparison to the researchers, of giving them the occasion to resist, of giving them the power to send the researcher to work. While Harlow’s laboratory bet on passivity, the “reactivity” of its subject, Heinrich’s dispositive will take form as an invitation to activity to those to whom the questions are addressed. By these strategies and dispositives, the researcher commits to more activities in order to encourage them in return among those that he observes. In other words, and more concretely, the investigator will invite the guilty to take action. Heinrich’s first activity will thus be to create an occasion for the ravens to busy themselves around his problem. To make the crime possible, it would be necessary first of all to find an enticement that interests them, a carcass if possible. To begin with, it would be better to trust the ravens and to act like them. Heinrich will let himself be recruited by them: he will report to the rendezvous made apparent by the cries announcing the discovery of a meal. The cadaver of an elk, left there by a poacher, becomes the object of a noisy feast. The birds take flight at the approach of the researcher. Without shame, he takes the carcass and will place it close to his observation post. The next day at dawn, two ravens arrive, followed by a third. All three remain silent. Ten minutes later, they are joined by two others. Some “quorks” are exchanged very quietly. These are no doubt salutations, not publicity. The ravens eat silently. When one of them is full, it flies up to a branch and lets out noisy cries. Others arrive. A falcon joins them, rapidly chased off by two ravens. Did they wait until they were full to recruit their fellows? Maybe, Heinrich comments. But does it really amount to recruitment? There is no way to be sure that the later arrivals came because they heard the cry. They were perhaps just passing by. It is necessary therefore to verify the power of attraction in these cries. Heinrich procures a tape recorder to capture them and loudspeakers to be able to disseminate them later. He would also need another cadaver. One of his friends had just killed a pig and offered him the entrails. Eighty kilos should be sufficient to motivate the generosity of the one who would find them. Heinrich places the meat near to his observation post and waits. Two ravens arrive, followed by a third. They eat silently, then they leave discreetly. After hours of waiting the author, discouraged, returns to his lodging. It is at that moment that he hears the cries. He reverses course and succeeds in recording some cries. The next day, the ravens come and go, but none of them appears to touch the meat. The one closest to it executes a small dance of hesitation and finally decides. It takes some little pieces and sets to work going to hide them. None of the birds makes the least noise. Others come in the afternoon but content themselves with flying over the meat, as if they simply wanted to verify its presence. They remain silent. Why are they not recruiting now? The next day, the afternoon scene repeats itself. No one eats or calls. A new hypothesis must therefore be considered: the reason for their abstention is perhaps linked to the type of food that is offered to them. Perhaps it is not their congeners that they are interpellating, but simply the other scavengers, coyotes or bears, endowed with sufficient strength to open carcasses? The pig entrails being directly accessible to them, they may not have needed to call for aid. It would thus be necessary to recommence the experiment, this time with a cadaver that was impossible to open. A goat bought on a visit to Vermont would fit the bill. The next day Heinrich waits with the goat cadaver placed prominently nearby. A raven arrives, approaches it, then takes off again. Others 64 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 despret come, no more interested than the first one. They neither call nor do they eat. Could it be that the goat is, in their eyes, an inferior substitute for what they usually eat? Heinrich goes to test his lure on other ravens, kilometers from there. Those ravens accept his gift with much goodwill. Nothing, however, says that if the recruitment does not seem to be addressed to other species it would then be a signal of invitation addressed to fellow ravens. The lure could be used to respond to this question: the ravens fall for the trick. The call seems very well indeed to recruit them. There will be, within fifteen minutes, thirty birds around the new feast organized by Heinrich … but none of them eats! From squirrel cadavers to rabbit remains from the side of the highway, from cow kidneys to pieces of giblets, the ravens demonstrate the most erratic behaviors: eating without being called, calling without eating, eating and calling, eating in the morning and not in the afternoon, or the contrary. There is only one logic: that of the most complete unpredictability. Things become singularly and decidedly more complicated: not only do the ravens not respond to questions but they pose new ones. It is no longer about understanding why they call, but on the one hand understanding why they do it in some situations and not others; and on the other why they feed at certain times and seem not to want to do so at other times. For the first question, Heinrich considers that the response could be linked to the quantity of food available: lately, they have been content with small game found here and there. If there is not enough of it, the ravens would perhaps have the advantage of remaining silent. The hypothesis is simple to test; the game warden would help by bringing all that he would be able to find by way of large cadavers in the forest. Heinrich organizes an enormous banquet. Against all expectations, the ravens seem to respond to the first hypothesis: they recruit, no doubt because the food is abundant. But they require the author to pose the second question: they do not, however, touch the food. They execute the dance of hesitation. 65 These two hypotheses combined – they recruit but seem to be scared to approach – can become the object of a new formulation: are they perhaps scared of having to do with a fake cadaver and do they wait until they are sufficiently numerous to diminish the risk? But the logic of the following observations does not allow the support of this hypothesis: the ravens, if that were the case, should have stopped calling their congeners once they started to eat and thus verified that it was not a trap. Perhaps the danger does not come from the prey, and their hesitation is simply due to the fact that they are scared of a predator who prowls around? This hypothesis can be tested by simply leaving the choice to the ravens. Heinrich places the meat on the ground and in a tree. The ravens, if the predictions are correct, will go without hesitation into the tree, where they have nothing to fear. However, they will not be so obliging, the author says: against all expectations, they feed on the ground, after a hesitation dance. On the other hand, how to understand the fact that the ravens can seem so fearful when at other times they are capable of so much bravery? Isn’t this the crux of the problem? Wouldn’t there be some ravens who are braver than others, which would justify the fact that some can eat while others hesitate for a long time before doing so? Wouldn’t this be dependent on age or experience: bravery, in raven societies, being precisely “what separates the ‘men’ from the ‘boys’” (Heinrich, Mind of the Raven 272)? But how could we ask them to verify this hypothesis? The author recounts a shocking coincidence that flows from the comparison of all his observations: sometimes the recruitment is done, sometimes it is not; but, in the second case, it frequently happens that only two ravens eat. Heinrich decides to verify this coincidence: he places two piles of food in nearby places and observes. Two birds come to feed from one of them; a recruitment of many ravens takes place at the other one. Is this then a couple and a group? Later observations support the thought that ravens form very stable couples, that can last a lifetime. We think, moreover, Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 the enigma of the raven that when the young leave the nest they associate in bunches until the age of three or four years. However, if the first affirmation concerning couples seems to be correct, Heinrich comments, nothing is less sure for the second one: it is not necessarily the case that since we frequently see groups of ravens around refuse that they live together in a bunch. We can only affirm that they frequently share communal nests for the night. Observations also show that couples defend their territory against all intrusion. This defense can take highly variable forms: they can sometimes attack any congener who approaches, sometimes they settle only for escorting it to the boundary of the territory. Do the first to arrive form a couple, and the second a group of juveniles? Do they all belong to the same group? We can’t be sure, since we cannot know whether, on the one hand, birds arriving in a pair form a couple, and whether, on the other hand, these are the same ones who mutually recruit one another, a condition of being able to affirm that this would be a true group. After all these months of research, Heinrich confesses that he has no answers. Quite the contrary: he now has nine hypotheses and not enough life left to be able to test them all. He had to transport tons of meat, purchased goats, donated pigs, gifts from the game warden, deer abandoned by poachers; he had to scour the highways for road-kill cadavers; and on top of that he had to spend hundreds of hours immobile in his observation post, race through the woods and the snow, climb up into trees, endure extended waits, raise false hopes, use lures in the form of recordings … and the mystery is deeper now than at the start. Biological detective stories, he comments, are visibly more complicated than the classical investigations: the more you find out the more you know that there are things that you do not know (Heinrich, Ravens in Winter 301). More cunning, more imagination, more activities to oblige the ravens to choose between hypotheses. It would be necessary to organize more feasts, simulate invitations, call again and again by means of recordings, propositions, and situations capable of interesting the ravens. It would be necessary to find the right way to recruit the ravens for the resolution of his problem. Now, if Heinrich learns with difficulty the means of recruiting the ravens, it is in fact the inverse that is in the course of declaring itself. It is the ravens who will recruit the author. The indices of this transformation take shape gradually with the research. “It is still dark, and I’m already being awakened by raven calls! Several birds are flying over Kaflunk making short, high-pitched calls that are unlike the usual quorks. These calls convey excitement. The birds are flying to a kill! I feel it. Even I can understand, and I too am recruited” (Heinrich, Ravens in Winter 81). We cannot ourselves understand it otherwise: if this recruitment by non-humans was able to acquire such an efficacy, it is because the human was transformed by those whose enigma he was trying to understand. The story conveys nothing so much as that of a becoming. Heinrich’s long investigation connected him to the ravens in an unexpected manner. In learning to recruit them, he learned to be recruited by them. That which constitutes achievement for a raven now constitutes, in another way, achievement for himself; feeding on their emotions, letting himself be pervaded by their joy, letting himself be drawn into their enigma: converting the environment into a little more of himself. He learned to become sensitive to what makes the ravens sensitive. “The majority of bird sounds have no emotional content for us. It surprises me, therefore, that many of the raven’s calls sometimes display emotions that I, as a mammal for whom they are not intended, can feel [ … ] I also feel I can detect a raven’s surprise, happiness, bravado, and self-aggrandizement from its voice and body language. I cannot identify such a range of emotions in a sparrow or in a hawk” (Heinrich, Ravens in Winter 250). For the author, the joy of a feast around a carcass takes on the same force of recruitment that it can have for a raven. When the raven dances the dance of hesitation the researcher holds his breath: there he is, also hesitating, before that which he wants to understand. 66 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 despret This becoming “with the raven” that builds up and transforms that to which the human is sensitive will in turn submit him to new demands. These will radically reorient the course of the research. How to take account of what counts for a raven, without going through the ways that the ravens themselves negotiate it together? The position of control and exteriority reached its limits. The ravens cannot respond to questions in the manner that they were posed to them. If some are brave and others are not; if some have good reasons to be afraid and others have none; if the models do not hold water since they cannot take account of the “eccentrics”; if there are small differences we cannot perceive that guide the behaviors; if recognizing one another is important, then it is necessary to go by way of what the ravens demand. “Progress often depends more on how well one follows the situation than on how well one controls it. Especially when control is difficult” (Heinrich, Ravens in Winter 196). One must learn to recognize them. One must also learn to ask them to give evidence differently and to try to understand how a raven ponders a question. The first evidence will arrive in the form of a weakened raven that has to be saved. The author brings him to his house and feeds him. The surprise is overwhelming: while it will sometimes take a raven three days to approach a carcass, and the least provocation can provoke its flight, the pensive raven seems to find the situation “altogether normal,” and comes, after two hours of taming, to eat from his hand. “And now, when everything is suddenly new, this bird acts as if nothing is out of the ordinary! I do not know how they perceive the world. I can only guess that they see it not as an absolute but as departures from the accepted. When everything is different, then comparisons cease, and almost anything can be accepted. And come to think of it, isn’t that how humans perceive the world as well?” (Heinrich, Ravens in Winter 133). Heinrich will tag him and release him, after his recovery. The new program is launched: it is necessary to recognize the ravens. It is also necessary to feed some of them who can respond to questions that the 67 other ones do not allow to be asked. Tame and be tamed to better find out what matters from a raven’s point of view; gain the trust to respond to the demands of the politeness of “getting to know.” Make of this taming a distinctive occasion to convey other things, and to respond to other questions. This occasion, Heinrich explains, “occurs when the individual close to the bird is trusted, has earned a trust that is not offered lightly. Given that trust, much is revealed that could otherwise never be seen” (Heinrich, Mind of the Raven 32).6 A huge aviary will be built in the garden, and young ravens will be released there. Theo, Thor, Ralph, Ro and Rave will teach the author that ravens develop their personality in the course of the first months: Ralph will be the most adventurous and the most curious; he will also be the one who will be the most attached to the researcher. He will soon become the dominant and show that the hierarchy takes shape as a function of bravery. Those who are the first to eat while the others hesitate win a sort of tacit right of precedence, without there being any conflict around this point. The experiment will be an achievement. “My observations were possible only because I was so closely in their midst. My rearing them from nestlings, and daily association with them for ten months, had won me their trust, which made the expression of their fine-grained unfiltered and hence complex behavior possible in my presence. The aviary also compensated for my inability to fly. I could follow them here, while at the same time provide an experimentally crowded situation that elicited flexible and innovative behaviors that otherwise might occur only rarely in the field where the birds can more easily avoid each other if they choose” (Heinrich, Mind of the Raven 259). The dispositive of taming, then, proves to be a privileged access of “getting to know”: it actualizes competences that have less chance of occurring in usual conditions: those of the birds and those of the researcher. It transforms habits: once again, those of the birds and those of the one who investigates them. In a parallel fashion, Heinrich will tag each of the ravens that he can catch. He makes each an Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 the enigma of the raven identity file, puts a ring on the leg, and then a small piece on the left wing, in different colors for each one. The colors determine the age and the name of each one of the ravens. The stories change from this moment on: the investigator has become biographer. W20 and Ro try to court R26, but being rejected each time, they finally give up. The juvenile Ro is amazing: in the absence of adults he behaves like a dominant. But as soon as adults arrive, he reverts to all the attitudes of submission. Some birds are very regular, others are often absent. They have habits that individualize them. Ro and R26 both arrived at the same time today, but each one from a different side: they are probably not in a real relationship; or else they have broken up. The marking spreads, in the stories, even to those who are not banded: the one who has only one leg did not come yesterday; the one who has a white spot on the back seems more timid, the one who does not have a tail was there today. Not being there today comes across in another manner: when he tried hard to establish a statistic on their dispersion by attaching a signal beacon to some of the youngest ravens, Heinrich discovers that many among them were killed: “The statistics that I knew so well were taking on new meaning. These were “my” raven friends and neighbors being killed” (Heinrich, Mind of the Raven 81). If the terms that guide the “getting to know” were transformed, this does not mean that the investigation is abandoned. On the contrary: it will finally, and thanks to these transformations, come to its conclusion. The questions addressed to each one, Ro, R26, W20, white back, one leg, Thor, Theo, and all the others, will bear fruit. One simply has to listen to them tell, at certain times, and to offer them propositions, at other times. First of all, the fact that the birds can mix in many places with resources seems to indicate that the recruitment is not oriented toward the protection of a stable group. Certainly, information can be transmitted among the group that finds itself together during the night: if one keeps some birds in captivity and releases them in the evening after several days, but only letting some of them join a communal nest, the next day the ones who do will be present with their night companions around a carcass that the members of the nest had discovered some time before. Those who could not join the nest will not be. Next, only the dominant juveniles recruit in the presence of adults, the others do not do it except in their absence or at a distance. If one compares this behavior with those that take place in the aviary, one could then consider that the fact of recruiting must be linked to demonstrations of bravery. The best proof of the value of a bird is its capacity to procure food. As among the ravens, the fact of eating often depends on bravery, and since bravery is often gained by experience, the fact of calling others around a food find, would it not constitute a reliable gauge of the quality of the recruiter? The ravens fully demonstrate this: bravery counts for them, it is a good measure of the value of partners, and a good opportunity to show one’s own. Those of a very fearful nature will not take so many risks in many situations, unless it is for something that really counts. It is truly that which, among the ravens, separates the men from the boys. The first motive for the crime is therefore elucidated. But it is necessary also to understand that this motive was not the only one: it links together many of the events, but not all of them. It cannot explain, for one thing, the fact that in certain cases the recruitment seems to have taken place elsewhere: and, for another thing, that sometimes the ravens who come in pairs sometimes eat and others don’t. It is in engaging this detail that the second motive can be brought to light. To elucidate it, it is necessary to link two pieces of information. The first of these requires proof by means of an experiment. This will be set up to determine the link between position in the hierarchy and the manner of recruiting. If the raucous recruitment can be, at some times and in some circumstances, an opportunity to show one’s bravery, what would the reasons be for a more discreet recruitment, at a distance? Would it be the fact of less brave or subordinate ravens? Heinrich kept twenty birds for a month and observed 68 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 despret how the hierarchy was organized. When this proves to be clear and stable, the birds are relaxed. The researcher leaves a carcass in a place, and leads a subordinate female there. She does not eat, and stays close to the meat, dancing a little dance of hesitation. That evening, she joins the nest. The next day, they are all there … and she eats with them. A first explanation can be confirmed: the carcass, like any new object, could be dangerous; the fact of eating, since vigilance for predators is diminished, adds to the danger. The presence of fellow ravens can constitute excellent protection. But the danger of a carcass that would miraculously revive is not the only cause; if not, then how to explain that sometimes a more raucous recruitment continues after the corpse has been shown clearly to be dead? Possible predators no longer constitute a sufficient reason: there are circumstances showing that it is not the only possible motive. The difference in behavior between the ravens who move in pairs and those who are in a group adds another version to the motive. For once they are identified; these ravens who eat as a pair and who keep others at a distance are shown not only to form a couple but the proprietary couple of the territory where the food is found. The reason for recruitment becomes clear, in this last situation, and permits understanding why ravens present such indecisive behaviors around food: when a territory is occupied by a couple, they will chase off all those who approach. Except if they are too numerous. If some juvenile vagabonds find a carcass and the territorial couple is far away, they will eat silently so as not to attract attention. If, on the contrary, the couple is close, they will call, and wait to be part of a sufficiently large number to eat in safety. And if they do not come, they will not eat. The achievement that recruitment represents for the ravens now conveys an achievement for Heinrich: he succeeded in recruiting the ravens around his problem, which he could not elucidate without their help; he succeeded in being sufficiently recruited himself to invent pertinent ways of addressing them. The ravens taught him the taste for differences: the 69 models are now commensurate with their unpredictability. He learned flexible habits from the ravens that would permit him to celebrate and to take account of the flexibility and the achievement of their habits. Heinrich became their expert and their reliable spokesperson: he gained the status of being authorized by them to speak in their name. He became the competent expert through whom they acquired their competences. He could now convince and interest his colleagues, in terms that count for them: he could test each hypothesis. He can speak in the name of the ravens, enroll other researchers to pose other questions, offer them new occasions. He could also bear witness for them. When in Germany, in the mid-1990s, fifty ravens invaded the idyllic Swabian Alps region, near the town of Balinger, the worst accusations were made against them. Farmers suspected them of attacking their livestock. A shepherd described them as a troop of disciplined soldiers who would launch at their victims, at the signal of their commander, to kill them. The newspapers immediately seized on the affair. “Nature turned to horror,” ran one headline. The accounts recorded seemed to come straight out of a Hitchcock film. Hunters joined in to support both the poor farmers and the threatened animals. All the observations aligned: the ravens were very often near or in the fields where the cows and sheep gave birth to their young. And these newborn lambs and calves were found with mutilated eyes or tongues. All the groups present testified against the ravens: their killing would be necessary. Heinrich came to the defense of their cause. A new investigation commenced, with a real crime and real guilty parties this time. The motives are, on the other hand, much more heterogeneous, most of them not being those of the ravens: the farmers claimed compensation from the government; the hunters demanded that the law that had protected the ravens since their quasi-extinction be lifted with the goal of preserving other species of birds; politicians, anticipating heavy payments, did not hesitate to jump on the bandwagon, and the Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 the enigma of the raven press saw, with each “crime,” a substantial increase in sales. To begin with, Heinrich argued, he’d never heard of ravens attacking livestock: they don’t approach cadavers that are still moving. At a pinch ravens can eat dead lambs just after birth. But in New England, cows and sheep give birth to their young in stables, such that the ravens cannot be blamed for all the animals that die during farrowing. Now, in this region of Germany, the livestock are left outside all year, including during the birthing periods. Heinrich obtained the support of ecologists, who exerted pressure on the government in favor of requiring autopsies before paying compensation. The results of these autopsies will be definitive: all the animals attacked by the ravens were already dead, for other identifiable causes, before the birds stepped in. These deaths were also, beyond that, much more numerous among negligent landowners. In the light of proof, the number of crimes suddenly plummeted in a dramatic manner; the compensation, which had become pointless, was suspended and the livestock were better kept. The ravens had been exonerated; the truce could once again be respected. The German ravens had in their turn succeeded in recruiting the representative of the American ravens; and he was able to recruit ecologists, who in their turn mobilized experts and politicians, who themselves modified the habits of the owners of the cows and sheep. The recruitment does not stop there. Heinrich will continue to enroll other humans around his ravens, in drawing this time on particular talents of these birds: in certain circumstances and in certain regions, they can achieve amazing interspecific recruitments. And inasmuch as it is a prophecy that serves as a guiding thread for my story, it is the wolf that I will ask to bear witness to a last version of this achievement. Isaiah’s bet would certainly have been less risky if in the place of proposing it to the sheep he had instead addressed it to the ravens to put the wolf to the test in terms of peaceful cohabitation.7 Wolf observers, Heinrich remarks, take the presence of ravens so much for granted that none of them has posed the question of understanding the nature of the bond that ties them to the wolves. Heinrich will seek out those of his colleagues who study wolves in Yellowstone National Park. What is the motive for this surprising association between ravens and wolves? How does this so-called peaceful cohabitation between them play a role in their achievement? Are the ravens of Yellowstone different from the Maine ravens owing to the fact that they live with wolves? The researchers accept the recruitment and the programs of research are launched. The information collected is astonishing: the Yellowstone ravens conform to the hypotheses that had to be abandoned for the Maine ravens! The rules that guided the behaviors and the motives for recruitment in Maine do not apply in Yellowstone. The presence of the wolves transformed the ravens. While in Maine, except in particular circumstances or exceptional bravery, ravens are always hesitant around a carcass and take many precautions; those in Yellowstone, when they are in the presence of wolves, do not demonstrate any timidity and do not hesitate a second before eating. Not only do they not fear the wolves – who are of an exemplary patience with the most mischievous ravens who, with bravery, come to bite them on the tail – but when the wolves are there they are no longer afraid of anything! The wolves allow the ravens to conquer their fear in the presence of large items of food, such as the carcasses of large animals; they changed the constraints that hold sway over the habits of the ravens. Better still, it seems that the ravens rely on the wolves and seek their company in order to eat. Dan Stahler, the Yellowstone colleague recruited for these observations, put this hypothesis to the test: he left deer carcasses out in the open in places where he had previously seen ravens join wolves just at the end of a hunt. When the wolves did not find the carcass, then either the ravens did not come, or they came, but did not touch it and left straight away. Besides, when a raven finds a carcass that is not open, and therefore inaccessible for it, it calls: in a few minutes the one who was recruited – the wolf – generally appears and 70 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 despret opens the prey for it, from which it immediately takes its share of the benefits. But that is not the only benefit of this exchange of good conduct for the wolves. It seems that the ravens are much more alert and vigilant than the wolves. One can relatively easily approach a wolf without it responding, something which is never the case for the raven: they sound the alarm at the slightest noise. Ravens assume with wolves the role that the Viking gods accorded to them; they spy and surveil to the ends of the earth and report everything to those who sent them. One can hide nothing from them, “the birds serve the wolves as extra eyes and ears” (Heinrich, Mind of the Raven 238). The prophecy, translated in terms of recruitment, takes an amazing turn: of course wolves live with ravens and even eat with them. And, certainly, the scientists who specialize in wolves now work with those who specialize in ravens: the recruitment of wolves by the ravens extends to the recruitment of their spokespeople. But who could have thought, if not no doubt a descendant of La Fontaine, that it is the ravens who protect the wolves and permit them to eat with their eyes closed? disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author. notes Translated from Vinciane Despret, Quand le loup habitera avec l’agneau © Editions du Seuil/Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond, 2002, 207–34. 1 The French term dispositif has an important specificity that has caused difficulties in prior translation and in capturing the range of meanings that it covers (including technical, military, legal, and ontological/arrangement dimensions). The term is at once an everyday, general term for referring to machines and devices of all kinds (such as cameras and pencil sharpeners but also airplanes) and it is a philosophical concept that has been drawn upon by Gilles Deleuze, Michel Foucault, 71 Louis Althusser, Giorgio Agamben and many others. Owing to the technical connotations of the term, it has often been rendered as “apparatus” in English, but this presents a major problem since the French term appareil, much more closely related to “apparatus,” is used as distinct from dispositif by the thinkers mentioned. Owing to the specificity of the concepts, there is an increasing use of the English term “dispositive” to capture dispositif and the distinctions from appareil. Timothy Armstrong’s earlier translation of Deleuze’s famous essay on Foucault’s use of the concept uses “social apparatus” to distinguish it from “apparatus” and to emphasize the social and assembling dimensions. These social and assembling dimensions are particularly important to Despret’s use of the concept in the philosophy of science and ethology. See Gilles Deleuze, “Qu’est-ce qu’un dispositif?” in Michel Foucault philosophe (Paris: Seuil, 1989), Giorgio Agamben, Che cos’è un dispositivo? (Rome: Nottetempo, 2006), and Jeffrey Bussolini, “What is a Dispositive?,” Foucault Studies 10 (2010): 85–107. [Translator’s note.] 2 Despret refers here to the canonical work in gene-centered evolutionary theory, namely Richard Dawkins’ The Selfish Gene. [Translator’s note.] 3 Vinciane Despret uses the French expression “faire connaissance” that has a range of meanings that are difficult to capture in English. “Faire connaissance” denotes getting acquainted in the sense of “meeting” or “making someone’s acquaintance,” and “getting to know someone,” but it also literally means “making knowledge,” and Despret is drawing on each of these elements here. It is rendered here as “getting to know” which has resonances of meeting, acquaintance, and friendship, but it should also be read with an emphasis on making and producing, as in “getting to” something via a process of inquiry and labor. “Faire connaissance” is closely related to her concept of politeness as an integral part of the type of research that she is describing here, exemplified by Bernd Heinrich’s involvement with the ravens. [Translator’s note.] 4 This story was told by the naturalist Edward Pett Thompson in 1851, in Passions of Animals. A monkey in Thalassery, from whom some crows were regularly stealing food from its plate on the ground while the monkey was on the top of a climbing pole, once feigned to be sick and laid on the ground. When the crows, deceived by its apparent state of agony, went to take the food the enigma of the raven the monkey suddenly jumped, took one of them, trapped it, and plucked it vigorously. 5 I borrow this definition “of the work of a scientist worthy of the name” from Isabelle Stengers, Introduction to Nathan, Nous ne sommes pas seuls au monde. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:11 21 November 2015 6 For each of these passages, the emphasis is the author’s. 7 The Book of Isaiah 11.6 emphasizes interspecific relationships in its “The wolf will live with the lamb, and the leopard will lie down with the goat. The calf, the young lion, and the fatling will be together, and a child will lead them.” Holman Christian Standard Bible (http://biblehub.com/isaiah/11-6.htm). [Translator’s note.] bibliography Chauvin, Rémy, and Bernadette Chauvin. Le Modèle Animal. Paris: Hachette, 1982. Print. Dawkins, Richard. The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1976. Print. Detienne, Marcel, and Jean-Pierre Vernant. Cunning Intelligence in Greek Culture and Society. Trans. Janet Lloyd. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1991. Print. Detienne, Marcel, and Jean-Pierre Vernant. Les Ruses de l’intelligence. La Mètis des Grecs. Paris: Flammarion, 1974. Print. Heinrich, Bernd. Mind of the Raven. New York: HarperCollins, 2000. Print. Heinrich, Bernd. Ravens in Winter. New York: Vintage, 1991. Print. Nathan, Tobie. Nous ne sommes pas seuls au monde. Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond, 2001. Print. Thompson, Edward Pett. Passions of Animals. London: Chapman, 1891. Web. Vinciane Despret Philosophie et Lettres Université de Liège 4000 Liège Belgium E-mail: [email protected] Jeffrey Bussolini Sociology – Anthropology Department City University of New York 2800 Victory Boulevard Staten Island, NY 10314 USA E-mail: [email protected] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:12 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:12 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:13 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:13 21 November 2015 ANGELAKI journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:13 21 November 2015 translator’s foreword The case of Clever Hans is one of the most notorious episodes in the history of animal psychology. Among numerous “clever animals” of the time, this horse’s apparently human-like displays of mathematical, linguistic and musical understanding caused a stir in Germany just after the turn of the century; the effects of his encounters with the scientific delegations sent to investigate him are still felt today. The case is full of intriguing elements: claims to supernatural influence and other extraordinary phenomena, accusations of deception, questions of anthropomorphism and mechanomorphism. It attracts romantics and sceptics in equal measure, from Maurice Maeterlinck to J.B. Watson. Today there is hardly a serious thinker of animal mind who has not turned their attention to these infamous events in order to elaborate their own theories. The “Clever Hans effect” has become the name of a cardinal scientific sin, the experimenter effect by which researchers inadvertently give their subjects the answers to their questions. Yet this discrediting accusation is often overstated, and in need of a careful differentiation: there are multiple, and multi-directional, forms of “influence” between observers and observed, some indeed problematic but others in fact salutary and revelatory. What goes on between scientists and animal subjects so that such effects are possible at all? What, indeed, was going on between Clever Hans and the committees of venerables sent to solve his case, particularly the eminent psychologist Stumpf and his student, the now-infamous Pfungst? It is here that Vinciane Despret comes in with her usual literary and investigative flair, vinciane despret translated by matthew chrulew WHO MADE CLEVER HANS STUPID? casting herself in the role of a cold-case detective, a meddling Bayard to Pfungst’s manipulative Poirot, exhuming buried evidence and retracing concealed errors and blindnesses. Was it really just a matter of reacting to inadvertent stimuli? Hans was influenced, sure – but by whom, and to become what? If he was stupid, then what made him so, if it was not a subhuman animality? Could it be the psychologist’s regime of questioning itself? If he was clever, then in what did his cleverness consist, if it was not a quasi-human rationality? Must the spectre of Hans’s cleverness remain an ironic epithet – an accusation of falsity and bête stupidity – or can we recast it as an alternative intelligence, a remarkably attentive capacity to be affected? This is ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020077-9 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039843 77 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:13 21 November 2015 who made clever hans stupid? where Despret excels, in the careful elaboration of distinctive performative modes of scientific questioning, interaction, awareness, and responsibility, in light of which the opposition of exceptional humans to mechanical animals melts away. In her book, then – of which the final, revelatory act of the epilogue is translated here – Despret digs through the files to reconsider Hans and his psychologists, and thereby, also, provokes us to rethink the legacy of this meaningful scandal in the subsequent history of scientific research on animal intelligence. D id Hans possess this independent intelligence? Has the Clever Hans error, as Pfungst claims, and as psychologists have generally agreed, indeed been totally resolved? Pfungst’s solution, despite its coherence and all the accumulated experimental evidence, leaves here and there unexplained residues, peculiarities, details that do not settle well with the whole and which suggest that there might be another explanation. We find ourselves confronting this case in the same position as the mischievous author who, at the end of a novel by Agatha Christie, calls for the reopening of the investigation (Bayard). Hercule Poirot has not conducted this one well, he declares, and the culprit is not at all the one whom Agatha Christie has nominated. The author of The Murder of Roger Ackroyd has been misled by her cocky detective, far too many mysteries remain, matters are too quickly resolved. The confessions of the designated culprits are themselves suspect. Certainly, Hans’s confrontation with the tests “without knowledge” proposed by the investigator Pfungst was decisive. Hans’s silence or stray responses to the blind questions marked him as guilty of having tricked the humans. Nonetheless, how is one to understand the success of these blind tests during the work of the commission? Pfungst will, of course, give some explanations a posteriori. These are somewhat confused: clearly our psychologist is not quite at ease. He could probably have done without giving them, since they still risk leading to the undesirable conclusion that the members of the commission have done their work poorly. Recall that the blind test had consisted in dividing the roles: the questioner and the one who receives the response were not the same person, the second did not know what the first had proposed. Mr Schillings had given Hans a number, had left, Mr von Osten had then gone in and asked Hans to carry out an arithmetical operation starting from this number. The horse was in fact wrong. But the commission had clearly decided to give Hans credit for his answers: there would have been a misunderstanding since Schillings had not understood the instructions and reportedly asked Hans to repeat the number. And it is this number that Hans has given, in any case enough times to convince. How has Hans succeeded in divining the answer? According to Pfungst, only one solution proves to be possible. Hans would have relied on someone else in the gathering who knew the number to generate, since he had heard it pronounced by Mr Schillings. It should first be accepted that this other person has not corrected the misunderstanding. Granted. This hypothesis, however, belies the way Hans goes about things. It was observed that the latter relies first and foremost on the people who are closest to him. He can count neither on Mr Schillings, who is out at this moment, nor on Mr von Osten, who does not know the answer. Would Hans have changed his habits? The horse has thus had to show great shrewdness: first he had to perceive that Mr von Osten could not guide him, which is not as obvious as it seems. According to Pfungst’s theory, Hans cannot “know” that his questioner does not know the answer only because the latter does not make the recoil movement. He would have therefore had to tap quite some time before realizing it. That will be in any case what he will do in the blind tests proposed by Pfungst: he starts and does not stop. So he had to perceive, before it was too late, that he could not count on von Osten. How did he manage? It is a mystery. Hans then had to understand that he had to look elsewhere and locate, among those present, someone more reliable who could help him. 78 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:13 21 November 2015 despret Has Pfungst followed the same path as those I critique? He seems in any case not really to believe in this solution, he does not go on and on about it. His innermost thoughts are almost readable, though never explicit: Hans has managed to lead the members of the commission to hasty conclusions. However, Pfungst concedes, one can understand their mistake: certain events that preceded the meeting of the 11th and 12th of September must have led to these overly generous findings. Recall that Hans corrects his questioner a few times during the preliminary stage of this work. A few days before the meeting started, some members of the commission had begun the work with him, in order to do some tests and to establish a good connection with the horse. From this preparatory work, the Count zu Castell has returned quite surprised: on the 8th of September he had asked Hans the date. Hans had responded with eight taps of his hoof. Yet zu Castell was convinced that it was the 7th. He was about to correct Hans when somebody pointed out to him that the date was indeed the 8th, and not the 7th. On another visit, still in the course of this week, zu Castell presented to Hans a slate bearing the numbers 8, 5 and 3, and asked him to add them. In his excitement, zu Castell thought that the total was 10. Hans went up to 16. Other events of this kind happened. Pfungst inventoried them: there were some seven. Others will later come to confirm the fact that these events had no reason to be rare: Pfungst will correct himself on two occasions, notably in a miscalculation. Seven occurrences during the work of the commission, says Pfungst, is certainly not such a high frequency, but these cases were impressive enough that their importance was overstated. He still had to find them a plausible explanation. Pfungst will consider two hypotheses. The first proves to be consistent both with that to which his technique makes him attentive, and with his hypothesis of the procedure without knowledge. One can imagine, in these latter situations of errors corrected by the horse, that in fact the questioner might possess the correct response at another level of 79 consciousness, or more precisely at the edge of it. This would be the part of consciousness that would have brought him to act, still without knowledge. The splitting would have operated in favour of the correct answer. The second, much simpler hypothesis refers for its part to luck: Hans himself would have made a mistake that, by chance, each time would precisely compensate for that of his interrogator. In the case of the answer “8” instead of the 7 imagined by zu Castell, he would simply have stopped too late. The same for the 16 in place of the 10. As luck would have it … It saved, at least partially, the honour of the commission. One can therefore explain the difference between the September report and that of December by relating the first situation back to error … and thus the second to the clarification of truth. There would, however, be another way of translating the contrast. I have, for my part, at the start of this investigation, considered the difference between the situation which saw Hans pass the tests without knowledge, and that which led him to fail, by invoking what had happened between the two moments: Hans had entered into psychology. Two interpretations were possible: the one I followed proposed to understand the contrast by considering the objectives of each of the dispositives. The first, that of the commission, had observed conditions in which the test produced successes; the second, that of psychology, had put in place conditions in which Hans could not pass this test. Another, more radical interpretation was also thinkable: the Hans before Pfungst’s experiment and the Hans after it were not the same. The horse would have been transformed by the way Pfungst worked with him, by the suspicion, by the manner of addressing him. This hypothesis is not actually mine, it is suggested to me by the criticisms that were directed to Pfungst: he would have transformed the horse. In some ways, one might think that this solution is even engraved in his own work: mistrust affects the performances of the horse, trust grants success. This would be to overlook the peculiar and deeply ambivalent status that Pfungst accords to trust. When it comes to the Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:13 21 November 2015 who made clever hans stupid? possibility of a conceptual intelligence in the horse, there is only a short step from trust to gullibility: here is Hans who understands French. Pfungst has a point: it is not that one attributes too much to the horse, it is that one attributes to him badly. The question of conceptual intelligence is a poor question for Hans (posed in terms of independent intelligence it is, moreover, a bad question for everyone): it reflects what interests us, reading, counting, not what makes for an interesting horse. Trust is misplaced. It is other capabilities that it must support. The hypothesis of transformation has nevertheless not eluded Pfungst, evidenced by what he writes in conclusion: some may assert that it was through our experimentation that the horse became mechanized and incapacitated as regards conceptual thinking; that formerly he really could solve arithmetical problems, and only later developed the very bad habit of depending upon the signs which I gave him. (211) Leaving aside this troublesome issue of conceptual intelligence, one realizes that Pfungst actually hits on an essential aspect of what the experimental dispositives are: they are apparatuses of transformation; they can never claim to have revealed that which pre-existed the examination. Yes, Pfungst is right to consider it, but wrong to translate a branch of the alternative in terms of conceptual intelligence – the dispositive has transformed the horse. The processes of this transformation are readable all over. We are here faced with the most problematic aspect of the psychologist’s work: he has well and truly mechanized the horse. Some of the anecdotes reported by Pfungst describe nothing else; they are not rare. Thus, to make it even more visible that it is indeed the head movements that make the horse act, Pfungst shows, for example, that he manages to obtain from Hans, by moving slightly and shaking his head, that he taps alternately and rhythmically the right hoof, the left hoof, the right, the left, etc. (61). Hans, he will repeat on several occasions, responds altogether mechanically (199). He was, he says again a few pages later, “like a machine that must be started and kept going by a certain amount of fuel (in the form of bread and carrots)” (202). It was possible, he finally claims, to make Hans respond to the most outrageous questions by means of signals. One could successively obtain “yes” and “no” to the same question, or else get him to show the direction of the ground when asked where his head was, and that of the sky when he should indicate his hooves. In what the psychologist describes, one is ultimately not far from the technique of dressage, with the results that it produces. Hans became a circus horse, a clown horse (see Crist 17). Recall that during one of those lengthy notes in which Pfungst indulges his work dissolving paranormal phenomena, he compares [spiritualist] table-turning and the horse. Certainly, he admits, the second is a living being. This difference is immediately brushed aside with the back of the hand: the cases are in the end similar. We touch here on the crux of the problem. Pfungst’s research takes place at a critical moment of the bifurcation of psychology: the transformations of Hans herald the transformation of subjects. One can read, engraved in this history, the first signs of the advent of behaviourism. The “all this was nothing but that” that punctuates every moment of clarification is the expression, in its own way, of what happened with Hans: he was subjected to a series of reductive operations. With the first, Pfungst reduces the conduct of the horse to simple mechanisms, he makes Hans pass from the animal who responds into the “animal that reacts.” Reaction is at the heart of this whole affair, it is the real transformation that announces that living beings, as the objects of these sciences that make psychologists dream, will finally submit to the laws that govern the universe. Only the conversion of response into reaction can enable this passage, as identified rather well by Eileen Crist when she says that “the distinction between action and behavior – sometimes rendered in terms of ‘conscious’ versus ‘unconscious’ behavior – is not a distinction between ‘natural kinds’ of conduct” (1). Pfungst, she continues, has created a distinction between “action” and “behaviour” (or response 80 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:13 21 November 2015 despret and reaction) by displacing Hans to the other side of the border that separates “intelligent actors” and “mindless reactors.” This operation will constitute the very essence of behaviourist dispositives. In the systems of conditioning that will come some years later, the animal will generally be submitted to training during which it must learn to react to certain stimuli: a light that turns on, a bell sound, a picture. When it perceives the stimulus it is asked to recognize or discriminate, it must present the reaction that the experimenter has taught it. It will be, at best, rewarded with a bit of food, at worst, punished with an electric shock or another unpleasant experience. By dint of repeating the stimulus, the experimenter gets what he was looking for: the rat, the pigeon, the monkey or the dog is conditioned, it now behaves like a mechanical spring toy. By observing how dogs, in this type of experiment, are subjected to constraints that transform in the mode of stupefaction, the sociologists Arnold Arluke and Clinton Sanders (81) have taken up again for themselves this irrevocable conclusion of Vicki Hearne (58): To the extent that the behaviorist manages to deny any belief in the dog’s potential for believing, intending, meaning, etc., there will be no flow of intention, meaning, believing, hoping going on. The dog may try to respond to the behaviorist, but the behaviorist won’t respond to the dog’s response. … The behaviorist’s dog will not only seem stupid, she will be stupid. Hans never showed himself to be spontaneous, says Pfungst, he never on his own initiative did something similar to what was generally asked of him (202). Granted, but Pfungst does not ask the obvious question: what would have been the point? If the horse was indeed able to take an interest in what fascinated humans, if he was able to give meaning to what for him was normally meaningless, such interest could only make sense within a relationship. The verdict of the lack of spontaneity only reinforces the implementation of the operation: it will be reserved solely for those reactions that prove unable to demand an active, autonomous, 81 spontaneous position … without the question arising of the dispositive that created this inability. This is where the notion of reaction becomes like a poison: the search for causes similar to those of sciences like physics renders unthinkable and impossible all those events through which living beings get on together, transform themselves, build mutual capabilities. For if there is indeed a question to which the problem of influence should have led, it is that of the influence of the dispositive itself, the effect of ways of addressing the horse on what it is in the process of becoming. The issue of trust might have led Pfungst there, but trust, as we have seen, is defined under poor conditions: trust is too close to credulity when it is aimed at “irrelevant” capabilities. Pfungst’s hypothesis, taken to its limits, could in turn have opened the question: if, as he repeatedly maintains, Hans does not have in his head what the questioner has in his own head, the dispositive’s suggestions should not have been separated from the question of influence; intelligent horse facing relevant questions, sensitive horse facing sensitivity, mechanical horse facing one who sees as the only hypothesis that of an associative chain of actions and reactions. This will to transform action into reaction, which is subordinate to the ambition to find simple causes and generalizable laws, can then account for certain details too quickly swept away like dust under the carpet, for certain unresolved questions, for certain skirted impasses that punctuate the work of Pfungst. At first, this question of influence was raised unilaterally, as we saw. The humans influence the horse; natural expressive movements stand in the way of any other hypothesis. This could, however, be opened up when it is discovered that the form of the signals that indicate “zero” and “no” was taught to the humans by the horse, without their realizing it. We could not show any better the possibility of reciprocal influence. Pfungst, however, throughout his affair of verifying whether this transformation of signals is experimentally possible, does not explore the consequences of what he discovers. He could hardly have done so, in any case, in Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:13 21 November 2015 who made clever hans stupid? the system elaborated: from the moment when Hans’s behaviours are defined in the sole register of reaction, that is to say in the register of passivity, it becomes difficult to give him such a share of the responsibility. It becomes above all very difficult to think of influence as a process of reciprocal adjustments, of agencements or agreements by which affecting and being affected are distributed in an indeterminate manner. The way in which influence can play on the rhythms of the accord rather than on those of mere transmission could have, however, appeared to Pfungst when analysing the results of tests taken with a stopwatch. These, as I recall, were introduced to have the most complete certainty that it was indeed the human who gave the signal for the end of the count. If the head movement had come after the last tap of the hoof, this would have meant, at best, that this was not the movement involved, at worst, that Hans knew all by himself when he should stop. Recall that von Osten, Schillings and Pfungst played the role of questioner. Stumpf, two of his colleagues, and Pfungst himself, when he was not involved in the role of questioner, were successively the observers. Pfungst declared, at the end of two sets of tests, that the results confirmed his hypothesis. Yet when one looks more closely, these results are full of anomalies. On one hand, the first set proves to be very contradictory. The horse follows the movement of the human very clearly with Pfungst (Hans gives his last hoof tap when the psychologist straightens up); a little more randomly for Schillings (in 83 per cent of cases, the head comes first, in 17 per cent, it follows); however, in the case of von Osten, the horse seems to anticipate his master in a majority of cases! A second set of tests is then attempted. Everything returns to normal on the side of Schillings; the results of von Osten, in contrast, do their utmost to muddy the waters. The explanations that Pfungst summons to take account of the difference between the two sets are not very convincing. Practice might have made the second test more reliable. One can rightfully ask how practice could change things. In any event, if Hans’s response is indeed a mere reaction, things ought to be clearer. They are even less so if one takes the trouble, as Crist did, to take up again the results that Pfungst has not recorded. He has in fact excluded from his tables every case where the two movements were simultaneous, by declaring them “undecidables.” Yet the statistics that result from these “undecidables” are astounding: if with Pfungst, records of simultaneity account for only 8 per cent of all the tests, with Schillings, however, one passes to 21 per cent and with von Osten, depending on the observers, between 20 and 30 per cent! That’s a lot. All these elements begin to put in doubt the fact that one is dealing with a simple “reaction” to influence. It is not a matter of putting back on the table the hypothesis of conceptual intelligence, but of drawing out the lesson of these cases, too quickly stowed away under the terminology of “undecidable”: influence does not fit well in the schemas of reaction and causality. What do these “undecidable” cases of simultaneity in fact signify? Do they not bear witness to the fact that the Hans affair is far more complicated than Pfungst wants to think? Hans can, in certain cases, anticipate the movements, and he more than likely does it based on other clues that have escaped Pfungst, whether because they do not exhibit the same regularity, or else because they are beyond our sensory channels, or finally because they are difficult to interrogate within the dispositives. For if Hans can anticipate with some and not with others, this means that there is, between the questioners, some variability of movements; that there would be, in some way, subsidiary movements that would supplement the information that Hans selects and takes. Which should then lead us to think that Pfungst’s solution is in fact only a very small part of the solution: literally, the most visible. It is here that the second operation of reduction carried out by the psychologist is formed. As we have seen, the method “by elimination” leads him to favour a purely visual hypothesis. Certainly, this makes of Hans an exceptional horse, since he has relocated a capability – the isopraxic ability that enables him to read in his muscular sensations those of his rider – into 82 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:13 21 November 2015 despret another register, where the horse does not normally excel: the visual register. Is this elimination method so convincing? This is doubtful. The horse normally uses several sensorial channels, each of its senses is involved in what it perceives – it is, in the words of ethologists, a polysensorial being. And yet, if the senses complement each other, the suppression of one does not automatically lead to its relay by the others. On the contrary, this suppression can render them ineffective, at least for a while. If the blinded horse does not perceive any sign, this does not mean that only vision is involved: it may simply mean either that he is too disoriented to refer to his other senses, or even that in the absence of vision his other senses “no longer speak to him.” Certainly, the horse uses his vision, but, in the lovely expression of Jean-Claude Barrey, “he will never believe his eyes,” he always has to confirm it with his nose. At the same time, muscular sensations are not perceived by the body alone; at the slightest movement of the rider, the ears of the horse lie down: he listens to the effect of his sensation-movements in his body, he uses his ears “as the eyes of the body.” Merely to say in the same breath that muscular sensations are heard by the “eyes” or that scent confirms vision gives us an idea of the difficulty of determining both how the horse perceives and what can produce the neutralization of just one of his senses. In a certain manner, Pfungst reduced the horse to the measure of what he was capable of interrogating: visual movements. But nothing permits saying that the mystery is solved and that Hans does not use a variety of means to read human bodies. Finally, if we interpret all the “undecidable” cases that tipped us off as possible instances of simultaneity, it becomes clear that Pfungst imposed a third reduction: he wanted to translate into the Procrustean bed of causality that which largely overflows it. Indeed, how to account for this simultaneity if not in terms of “attunement”?1 It is precisely these terms that seem best able to translate the capacity of the horse and the human to attune, to connect in so supple a manner; this capacity for attention to the other so strong that it makes it impossible 83 to distinguish differences in the rhythm of the accord. We no longer know which, horse or human, induced his movements in the other; we do not know, in these agencements, how the anticipations of one actualize the anticipations of the other. Independent intelligence makes a decidedly poor figure relative to the capabilities that are deployed: a dual intelligence, involving bodies, attentions to the other, desires and wills, consciousnesses capable of splitting, of being relocated, edges of consciousness that bring about more effective actions. Let us not, however, be totally unfair to Pfungst. He is capable of using these terms, particularly when he abandons the constraints of the psychologist to adopt a posture closer to the ethologist. Let us recall what he reports to us at the end of his investigation among the horses. It is with an excerpt from Tolstoy that he gives us at the same time the exceptional talent of Hans and its similarity to that which his domesticated counterparts develop: a capacity for attention to human desires so strong that they are capable of anticipating this desire from a simple muscle movement (Pfungst 183–84).2 What makes Hans an exceptional horse is that he was able to divert this talent to other senses. The fact that one can find at times such contradictory characteristics in Pfungst reflects the context in which he works. His laboratory is situated at a critical juncture in the history of psychology. In the same motion, he can celebrate the talent of Hans, focus on his singularities, raise the question of the proper ethos and of the relevant problems, and a few lines later mechanize him to dismiss his abilities as mere reactions. He announces the behaviourist turn at the same time as he is heir to the choices of psychology since its inception; those taking physics as a model, and those making of its own objects, objects obeying laws: reactions. Furthermore, another contrast, his subjects are talented subjects, sought-after as such, and some of them still benefit from the interchangeability of roles. But the procedure without knowledge indicates that asymmetry, as the mode of organization according to the recognition of expertise, is already installed. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:13 21 November 2015 who made clever hans stupid? His practice as experimenter, however, still connects him to the old tradition. The splitting of consciousness, the ability to adopt “naı̈ve” positions, the active practice of self-ignorance, all testify to that which constituted the identity of the experimenter: if psychology becomes discipline, it is still defined, for the experimenter, as discipline of the self. To be a psychologist, one is committed: the experimenter is the reliable witness of events that he makes himself capable of eliciting. The technique is not yet an “all-purpose” technique but a way of forming oneself as a talented scientist. Pfungst has made the horse talented because he cultivates the same qualities that he attributes to him: an extraordinary capacity for attention and for attention to the other. Hence his achievement. The experiment in which he shows that one can modify natural expressive movements is exemplary in this regard. By moving his arms he manages to lead his subjects, without their being aware, to change the movements of their eyes. Imagine the concentration, the discipline, the willpower it took to conduct an experiment the success of which depends on whether the experimenter leaves his eyes “out of things” and prevents them from following the movement. This culture that required experimenters to submit themselves to the risks and demands of their technique will die out: psychologists will become predominantly “anyone”; protocols will supersede these distinctive forms of selfcommitment and will make of psychology a technology of control “over others” – in this case, subjects. These subjects – interchangeable, but between themselves this time – will by cohorts come progressively to replace the talented observers. We shall now close this case and yield Pfungst and Hans to history. Having seen how this story turned out for psychology, I would be remiss not to conclude with the way it ended for Hans. When Mr von Osten got him back after the experiments, things did not go very well. In short, von Osten, of whom Pfungst tells us that he was somewhat quicktempered and moody, oscillated for several months between two positions: at times he resented Pfungst and accused him of having completely mechanized his horse; at times he resented Hans and reproached him for having fooled him. It is probably on this latter version that his story with Hans came to an end. He sold him to Karl Krall, a jeweller from Elberfeld. The public success of Hans had in the meantime subdued. But Mr Krall had not been convinced by Pfungst’s arguments. He resumed his education, organized exhibitions on the progress of his pupil, and very rapidly Hans revived his fame. He did not remain alone. Krall, encouraged by the success of his illustrious horse, bought two others, Mohammed and Zarif, who received an education very similar to that of their companion. One specialized in arithmetic, the other in spelling. New techniques improved their performances: two hooves would be used, one for units, the other for tens; the instruments were modernized and made more practical. The horses were given a spring-board on which it was easier for them to tap. The three of them became the “famous Elberfeld horses.” Certainly, there were still some controversies, but without the intensity of the first. Mr Krall strove to prove that Pfungst was wrong. So, the horses were called to answer in the dark: this did not seem to affect their performances.3 Perhaps they did not ultimately (or exclusively) rely on the signals detected by Pfungst? None of the scientists, however, took the trouble to reopen the case. This is probably a good thing, at least for Hans: in the end, it was no doubt better for him to remain one about whom we were mistaken. disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author. notes Translated from Vinciane Despret, Hans, le cheval qui savait compter © Editions du Seuil/Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond, 2004, 115–34. 84 despret 1 These are also the terms (attunement) that infant specialist Daniel Stern favours to account for the symbiosis of rhythm, perceptions and affects that attune, and through which are attuned, the mother and her newborn. 2 The reference is to the horse race in Anna Karenina. [Translator’s note.] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:13 21 November 2015 3 This information comes from Fernald and is confirmed by Candland, except on the occupation of Mr Krall. bibliography Arluke, Arnold, and Clinton R. Sanders. Regarding Animals. Philadelphia: Temple UP, 1996. Print. Bayard, Pierre. Who Killed Roger Ackroyd? The Mystery behind the Agatha Christie Mystery. Trans. Carol Cosman. New York: New, 2000. Print. Candland, Douglas Keith. Feral Children and Clever Animals: Reflections on Human Nature. New York and Oxford: Oxford UP, 1993. Print. Crist, Eileen. “From Questions to Stimuli, from Answers to Reactions: The Case of Clever Hans.” Semiotica 113.1/2 (1997): 1–42. Print. Fernald, Dodge. The Hans Legacy: A Story of Science. Hillsdale, NJ and London: Erlbaum, 1984. Print. Hearne, Vicki. Adam’s Task. New York: Knopf, 1987. Print. Pfungst, Oskar. Clever Hans (The Horse of Mr. von Osten): A Contribution to Experimental Animal and Human Psychology. Trans. Carl L. Rahn. New York: Holt, 1911. Print. Stern, Daniel N. The Interpersonal World of the Infant: A View from Psychoanalysis and Developmental Psychology. New York: Basic, 1985. Print. Vinciane Despret Philosophie et Lettres Université de Liège 4000 Liège Belgium E-mail: [email protected] Matthew Chrulew Centre for Culture and Technology Research and Graduate Studies Faculty of Humanities Curtin University GPO Box U1987 Perth, WA 6845 Australia E-mail: [email protected] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:14 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:14 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:15 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:15 21 November 2015 ANGELAKI journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:16 21 November 2015 translator’s foreword “But, what’s this?” asks the writer Paul Marty, quoted in the book, “I saw cows with tears in their eyes?” Between this perception, and the reality of the tears, we find the play of the short book from which we have translated one of the chapters: Être bête, the title itself a pun playing between “being stupid” and “being a beast.” Knowledge is the issue in this ethological essay on research into agricultural animals, neglected “ordinary” farmyard animals like cows, pigs and goats, set in France of course. The knowledge trips across three levels and back again: what the philosophers/sociologists (Despret and Porcher) think they know with their theories and methods, what farmers know and narrate about their livestock, and what the animals themselves might know, what competences they might have and even what they feel. And the book poses the question at its simplest: “What is the difference between humans and animals?” then elaborates the question, not by staying at a philosophical level but by asking farmers what they think, and reflexively, what they think about the kinds of questions being asked. That is the focus of the chapter here translated, as it explains the model – which is how I have rendered the notorious word dispositif, on this occasion – for a pragmatic (interspecies) sociology for doing research with farmers and their animals, not about them. Thus we hear the farmers, throughout the book, elaborate their knowledges via interviews, especially on questions of work, and animals’ competences: “Recognizing Competences” is chapter 1, followed by 2, “Offers of vinciane despret jocelyne porcher translated by stephen muecke THE PRAGMATICS OF EXPERTISE Subjectivity,” then 3, “Exchanges of Properties and Sharing of Worlds,” then this chapter, the methodological one, and finally the Conclusion, which reiterates that the book is about the “co-evolution” of humans forged as “beings for animals” and animals as “beings for humans,” a co-evolution which “farming extends and makes perceptible” (124). When experience is accompanied by the awareness of what it “does” and what it “transforms” (or what it “creates,” as in art), new conditions are thus produced that themselves become objects of interest, and which can eventually lead to new, specific, problematic situations, on the basis that they henceforth become part of the contextual conditions in relation to which the ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020091-9 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039845 91 the pragmatics of expertise researcher develops his or her aptitudes, desires, knowledges or science. Zask, “La Politique comme experimentation” 18 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:16 21 November 2015 W ould we have obtained the same answers, followed the same path, or bifurcated in the same manner if we had asked the question the way they traditionally do in research projects: “In your opinion, what is the difference between humans and animals?” We have touched on the first reason for the choice of this particular procedure that consisted in searching for the “right questions” and in delegating, to those we were addressing, the task of constructing them. We were not certain at any moment if our question had a meaning, nor if it represented an interest, nor even if it were relevant. We had even more reasons to adopt this procedure since the other question guiding our inquiry – the one interrogating the possibility that animals could take an active part in work – turned out to be even more problematic. Besides, it was in explaining the difficulties linked to this question, exactly as they were put at the end of the preceding inquiries, that we decided to take it on board: “During the research I undertook with farmers I (Jocelyne Porcher) often heard anecdotes, stories, even ways of talking which suggested that animals, in some way, collaborated in work. Now, when I tried to pursue this question with the farmers, head on, I was met with resistance or incomprehension. Clearly it’s not a good question to ask. But first-hand evidence kept coming up; this encouraged me to persevere. So, in your opinion, as a farmer, how do you think I should be framing my question so that it has a chance of being understood and being interesting?”1 These two questions, put like this, show how we have tried to reconstruct and modify the way traditional research is done. We have asked people to think with us. We have asked them to help us construct a problem and not to reveal situations or hand over information. Instead of the position of informant, conventionally applied in most inquiries, we have substituted a position that implies sharing, a redistribution of expertise.2 We know that problems are not interesting unless they interest. So we should ask farmers raising stock to themselves construct the interest they might have in our own interrogations, even to the point (and this is the gamble we take) that we might hear it said that our problems are not interesting, relevant or subject to sharing. Or, to the point of hearing a response, like with André Louvigny: “Let me say, your question sounds a little weird,” or like Claude Baijot: “Strange questions you are asking.” In the end, and on the surface quite paradoxically, we ask for the maximum amount of indulgence for our research while at the same time creating the conditions for maximum “recalcitrance”:3 “Your question is not relevant.” The fact that a number of farmers, for example, might relocate the question of difference, by looking for other sites where it might seem more relevant, is receipt acknowledged, as far as we are concerned, for this offer of “recalcitrance.” This will to construct a space of “recalcitrance” and to maximize occasions likely to call for it comes in response to a difficulty in social scientific practice, a difficulty to which our earlier work has sensitized us.4 For the most part, these practices assume that the procedure for coming to know consists in gathering information, facts, opinions – even in the case of psychology studying reactions or behaviour. Now, this type of procedure keeps coming back to, keeps in existence, a radical asymmetry of expertise. There is, on the one hand, the “author-researcher” who creates the questions, interprets the hypotheses, constructs the problem; on the other hand there are those acting as social witnesses, informants, holders of opinions, beliefs and representations which the researcher will have the job of analysing. The fact that scientists, for example, refer to their colleagues by citing their names, while witnesses are all interrogated anonymously, is just one of the many ways of noting this asymmetry of expertise and of the possibility of being authorized to think and to be recognized as putting one’s thought to the test.5 The authors of theories, endowed with names, are cited; opinionholders are interchangeable and listed. 92 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:16 21 November 2015 despret & porcher But the fact of having a name or not, being the creator of thought or of theories, or the simple representative of an opinion, is but the symptom of a more general situation characterizing certain habitual practices. They are based on a procedure which demands the submission of those it interrogates – submission to questions; submission to the inevitable play of interpretations that will come along to judge their depositions, their beliefs, even their unconscious motivations; submission to the theories guiding the research; submission to the problem being imposed on them and the way the researcher constructs and defines it. The subject is called upon by a problem that he or she often has nothing to do with, or at least nothing to do with the way it is defined, just as the researcher is most often not concerned with the way the problem can, or not, be a problem for the person called upon. And, for the most part, subjects thus mobilized will agree to respond to the questions without challenging their grounds, their relevance, or even their politeness,6 since it seems obvious enough that the scientist “knows better.” So our model [dispositif] had the aim of breaking with the habitual practices that banked on submission. We research the places where those we interrogate would be in a better position to “object”; we address ourselves to them in places where they would be “fully involved” and therefore where they would be interested and interesting. This is why, to each of our demands, we insist on using the phrase “you, as farmers.” Because this is where the real stakes of our proposition lie. It became a matter of addressing ourselves to those to whom we were submitting our questions at the sites where they were competent experts and where we were able to be confident in them. Our question, both formulated as a demand for “good questions” and addressed at what makes a person skilled in “objecting,” seemed to us able to keep the bet. And in fact it elicited in its very form the possibility for the farmers to actively contest our questions, even to doubt the relevance of the hypothesis that underpinned them: “Your question makes no sense,” or “That’s not the 93 way to put it,” even “That is not the main issue.” Yet none of our interlocutors left us empty-handed after having responded to our implicit request for contestation. They really helped us. They proposed a lot of questions that should allow us to explore the difference between human and animal. Of course, some of our interlocutors refused the suggestion to respond to a question with other questions, and took a short-cut: “I don’t know what has to be asked of farmers, but as for me, this is what I think of the difference between humans and animals.” But the large majority accepted the exercise. We had implicit help from Philippe Betton, who even encouraged us when we were investigating together how to formulate our question: “Exactly, by not presenting yourselves as coming from the milieu, from that milieu at all. You are tackling the subject from the outside. Since you know nothing and since the [industrial] farmers are in any case used to being asked questions that are, in inverted commas, ‘naı̈ve’, ‘ordinary’. If you ask them questions like that, naı̈ve ones … ” In this framework, one fact leaps out at us – the model creates work. The search for the right question ends up with lots of suggestions and hypotheses and leads the farmers to a genuine sociological exercise. They analyse the contrasts of different systems of farming and the different ways people have of organizing themselves with their animals, each of these different systems demanding, according to them, a different question. For instance, concerning the possibility of asking about animals’ work, Jean Rabat, on the pretext of getting the words right, starts work on a cartography of habits: “I have a little idea on this point. It all depends on the type of farmer you are dealing with. You have two categories. If you look at the organic people, there are in general a lot of peasants (in inverted commas) who have just started, people who did something else before, who came there and who therefore have completely different approaches. The usual peasant, coming from father to son, trained in agricultural school – where you aren’t trained but untrained, in such a way as you always do things the same way, reproduce Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:16 21 November 2015 the pragmatics of expertise the same system. If you speak to them about behaviour, the word behaviour, it’s not a word they usually use.” He continues: “Go ahead, ask them: ‘When you are working with animals, do you have the feeling that they want to collaborate with what you want to make them do, or not?’ Because otherwise everyone of my age thinks about work back then when we put them in harness. That no longer happens; it’s all over.” Philippe Betton brings our semantic education to its conclusion by suggesting we avoid using the term competence because “it’s a word that is used for meanings other than the industrial, productivist raising of stock. I don’t think this term would be well received by the farmers. Perhaps you could use the word behaviour.” If you talk like that, you are not going to be understood. This is the posture of the expert in a country of diverse customs who teaches us the rules of “savoir-parler” and who, in the same movement, touches up in fine detail the map of social relations and conflicts. Patrick André, after having taken into consideration that our question on work, in fact, touches on what farmers expect of their animals in the relations that they have with them, suggests differentiating the latter as a function of our preferred approach. Would we like to compare what “cuts across all modes of production” or, on the contrary, do we want to “differentiate all the modes of production in order to make the fine distinction among all the approaches that might exist?” The expectations, he said, are certainly a transversal problem, but the forms they take can be different: “I’m not sure that a farmer who is in industrial agriculture expects the same thing of animals as a peasant who has a different approach in that he thinks he has to be in harmony with nature, while the former must rather adapt nature to himself.” We cannot fail to notice the way in which the farmer makes the question of expectations move around, creating an amazing similitude between our relationship to research and the relation of the farmers with their animals. You must specify what you expect from your question, and know that it must vary in function with what the farmers expect of their animals. With them we learn about the practice of the “erotetic,” this felicitous term forged on the basis of the Greek eros which means love as well as lack, and which defines the art of questioning. A good question, according to some of our interlocutors, is not only one that is well addressed, in terms that can be shared, it is also an occasion which should lead the person being questioned to put themselves in question. It should elicit reflexivity, or at least make values explicit. A good question puts things to the test. “What I think,” says Jean Rabat, “is that you have to ask them if they think the animal is there to serve humans, to help humans get what they want done. So if you say to them, ‘get what you want done’ you are putting the question in terms of what they want for themselves. And that the animal is there to help them do it. And if the response is yes, they are going to say, ‘I use animals to make money,’ and that can take the question a bit deeper, asking themselves, ‘But how far would I go in making money out of animals?’ That might be one way of approaching the problem.” Patrick André takes up again his reflections he had at the beginning of our interview about work when he advised us to go via the problem of farmers’ expectations: “I think that one angle to approach [the question of difference] is exactly in asking the question, ‘what do we expect of animals?’ But is the door open enough to try to get a feel for the difference between humans and animals? With a crude question like that, I don’t think you’ll get much out of them.” Philippe Roucan takes another tack, to end up with a similar statement on the difficulty of the question: “How can you ask the farmer this question? Asking it is not rude. He finds it upsetting to be asked this question. At least, it is not that it’s upsetting, it irks him a little bit. Because for my part, let me tell you, there are not that many differences.” Eliciting recalcitrance also allows one to make things explicit, and therefore arguable, which is what we are after. In most human 94 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:16 21 November 2015 despret & porcher science research a good part of the aims of the project remains hidden from the subjects, or those being researched. Scientists, in fact, have learned to fear the problem constituted by their expectations. If the sociologist or the psychologist reveals too clearly what they are looking for, the theory guiding their work, you can always suspect the subject to have replied by way of being “obliging” and thus to conform to the expectations of the interrogator. This is what leads us to think that if researchers in experimental psychology could for one moment imagine, as do farmers, that animals might have the intelligence to want to please, or to practise a preference for harmony, this would give them serious methodological problems.7 With humans, researchers have taken this possibility fully into account. Incidentally, to counter this difficulty, psychology has invented a technique of the lie and the trap, designed to hide what the researcher is really looking for, so as to avoid subjects being tempted to confirm the research hypothesis.8 More generally, to the extent that the research depends on people’s submission to what the researcher proposes, the problem of the influence of the latter’s expectations cannot be avoided. In asking farmers to both judge the relevance of our research and help us find the most “practicable”9 modes of access we have endowed expectations with a new status, which has made us much freer and much less worried about them. The fact of explaining them by opening wide the door onto any objection can benefit clear and active positioning on them. “What are you interested in?,” “How can I help you?” we have often been asked. Sometimes in the form of a quite recalcitrant hypothesis, as does Claude Baijot when he tells us: “I’m so sorry I am not able to reply to you,” and a little later specifies this by concluding: “You would have liked to have heard something else … ”; often helping us in the process. As when André Louvigny makes the suggestion: “I think that the word work is not well adapted to what you want to understand,” and later: “You need to perceive this human–animal relation in order to grasp what?” This leads us 95 to this paradox: our model is just as good at maximizing recalcitrance as indulgence. The prime effect of this model, if we were to sum it up, is a kind of translation in the form of what we might call a “call for expertise.” The “naivety” that Philippe Betton encouraged us to own up to – we don’t know how to ask the right questions – redistributes expertise and alters the asymmetry of positions. Above all, it has the effect of making (people) interested and interesting. A corollary consequence came up during the interviews, and everything above attests to it. Once the farmers made the question interesting, they wanted to answer it. And they do so. The answers nevertheless keep a certain emphasis as we formulate them; we addressed our questions to them “as farmers.” This emphasis, as we said, created a way of situating our interlocutors in a position in which they seemed to us to have the greater capacity to object. And other effects were also present. Our interlocutors have taken this invitation in two ways. First, “as a farmer” has been translated as “situated point of view” – I think as a farmer. Secondly, it has been able to indicate a privileged epistemic stance: “As a member of a collective who knows its mysteries, its functioning, its conflicts and issues … ” These two meanings are confirmed when farmers arrange for us to think about the difference (or the possibility of saying that animals work), in its relation to, for example, systems of production, to various limits and to everything that, from their point of view, can determine one conception or another. “There are,” Philippe Betton notes, “people who are very attuned to the well-being of animals and respect them, to the point of being vegetarians. The difference for me, as a farmer, that one must not lose sight of, in relation to whatever people who are very protective of animals might think, is that, well, they will be eaten [ … ] One must not lose sight of this, as a farmer. I think that all farmers are aware that this is about feeding people. So already, there’s your answer to what’s the difference between you and an animal. They will tell you that we are the ones eating them. That is the crudest response that Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:16 21 November 2015 the pragmatics of expertise a farmer could give, the difference is that we are the ones raising them for food.” André Louvigny, on the other hand, contests the generality of this “as a farmer”: “Even at the heart of the community, there are farmers who are gentle and competent in their relations with animals and others who are brutal, idiots. So, there’s already a world. There are those who have no feelings for their animals. There are those who treat them well, and there are others who don’t get it. The opposite also goes, there are people who live for their animals and are crazy about them. Yes, who live more for their animals than their family, who neglect their family and their home.” Philippe Roucan comes to a similar conclusion. “What I call a farmer, you know what I mean, for us you’re a farmer, with the kind of farming you do, I mean a type of farming that you can call family, which is done on a small scale like us, with a limited number of animals, I mean I think that a farmer is not the same if he has a hundred head, or if he has ten thousand, because, as far as I’m concerned, he wouldn’t have the same perception of the animal.” Most of the statements that farmers make present a common characteristic; they are reflexive and contextualized. Each suggested we take their remarks as a function of their particular situation, their type of practice, the conditions, the animals, the quality of their relations, the fact that death was the fatal outcome for the life trajectory of both farmer and animal. And likewise, each could set up contrasts, saying, “Here you ought to ask this type of question, over there you have to speak differently.” It is in general the sociological researcher who fills in the gaps of the research in relating positions, beliefs or affirmations of those being interrogated to determinisms, contexts or situations. The fact of delegating this part of the work to the farmers provides a not insignificant advantage; it short-circuits any analysis in terms of unknown causes for the actors.10 The advantages of a so-called pragmatic sociology, which asks actors themselves to put into operation the analysis of why they are thinking the way they do, are considerable. Researchers are required to have better manners, because they can no longer develop knowledge behind the back of those they are interrogating. The interrogated, for their part, can construct their analysis in all confidence.11 They will be invited to share all the more intelligence in that they have to take responsibility for the more interesting part of the work. It rests on them to make the link between what they think and what determines their particular way of thinking. We are tipping more in this direction, like Antoine Hennion, who analysed the manner in which amateurs defined their relation to taste, from “the analysis of critique to pragmatics” (Hennion) – one doesn’t do things, or think things “because of” social determinisms, one works “with.” Farmers, those whom we met because we knew that they had the capacity to do it, were not there to “say” or to witness a problem, they were with us to “do” and to construct the problem, and to do so actively and explicitly on the basis of what gives them a particular, localized, knowledge of the problem. “In our culture,” as Portuguese farmers Acácio and Antonio Moura say with respect to the question of work, “we link work with physical work. Women at home don’t work. Our mentality is set up as such, if we go to see someone and if we ask him if the cow is working or if it is not, he will reply, if she is in harness she is working, otherwise she isn’t working. This mode of thought which has been around for several years is also attached to the fact that a cow that works physically had a better market value.” In Claude Baijot’s case, his answers go back to the economic conditions of his system: “I think that as far as my stock goes, I was [previously] more sensitive to that side of things also, while now I am in the midst of it all, I have to manage to meet the needs of the family, and pay my investments as well. It’s maybe the economic aspect that … It’s definitely the economic aspect also, and I have to manage as best I can; last week we bought a house and we have to keep up. We are young, I am twenty-eight and this is maybe why … which sums up the way I think.” In two or three sentences the farmer has explicitly brought together several 96 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:16 21 November 2015 despret & porcher explanatory registers which allow him to come to terms with the contrast between how he sees things today and how he saw them previously – “I was more sensitive”: to economic and psychic investments, causalities linked to status, or to the stages of life and family organization. The fact that a question addressed to a farmer “as a farmer” can boost confidence became even clearer to us when we realized, in the course of the research, that there was an interesting similarity between our proposition and the choice of system that most of them had adopted. Thus, the organic farmers often say to us that their specific practice is to lead animals to “do the work themselves,” graze rather than being fed; move to water sources; calve on their own; bring up their calves, even adopt another. The very act of reproduction is left up to them, most of such farmers giving up techniques of artificial insemination or even “hand breeding” [monte en mains]. Philippe Betton, not without humour, tells us that he resists the attempts of his boars to get him involved in copulation: “A farmer might have the reflex, especially with a sow in heat, when the boar tries to mount her, the farmer – sorry, I’d better not mix up the farmer and the boar – can have the immediate reflex to help the boar penetrate the sow, whereas in my case, I say, ‘No, that’s a mistake! That’s a mistake!’ If you have the reflex to help the boar penetrate the sow, the boar – he’s a bit lazy – he’s going to get lazy and later, he will get into the habit of waiting for the farmer so he can penetrate the sow.” We have taken the same path, in a way, by delegating our work in asking our interlocutors to take some of it on board, on trust. It is exactly by linking it to this term that the farmers describe the possibility of sharing work with their animals. And, no doubt also, the fact that the same Philippe Betton ends his anecdote about lazy boars by asserting that “the participation of the farmer has in some respect made the animal incompetent” should lead us to interrogate the way that research projects can sometimes leave few opportunities for competences. 97 A last consequence for our programme came up as we reread the transcripts of our interviews. Our interlocutors have often said things such as “I never thought about it, but now that I do … ,” “As I speak I realize … ,” or also, hesitating, changing their minds, telling us they are changing their minds, revealing contradictions themselves, announcing that they have suddenly found themselves “in a deadend, but I’ll get out of it,” saying, “it’s hard, I try to get it right. We do things so mechanically that we don’t even ask the question.” Or then Claude Baijot, who announces, at the end of the interview, that he had begun by describing himself as close to organic farmers, and who wonders, at the end of the discussion, if he isn’t an industrial farmer: “Now you have made me unsure.” What they have done with our proposal is grasp it as an occasion to put thought to work. Thinking with us or for us, to be perplexed, to slow down. They have helped us to turn this inquiry into a real experiment, an experience which, one way or another, transforms questions, modifies attitudes, displaces points of view and brings new ones into existence. So it is not so much of an accident if, in researching the differences between humans and animals, we have been greatly surprised to find ourselves exploring the inverse of our question, the one that concerns similarities and competences. disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the authors. notes Translated from Vinciane Despret and Jocelyne Porcher, Être bête © Editions Actes Sud, 2007, 87–107. 1 We have each taken on the responsibility for the questions that interest us respectively. Questions of work and the fact of power rest on earlier interviews and were therefore formulated by Jocelyne the pragmatics of expertise Porcher; questions of difference and reference refer to the academic work of Vinciane Despret. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:16 21 November 2015 2 Our experience is not unique in this genre. Other researchers have, for their part, also tried redistributing expertise in other ways, without, however (as far as we know), using this particular protocol. Note, for example, that in the work of sociologists linked to agriculture and agronomy the processes by which knowledge is co-produced by sociologists and agronomists and by farmers have been widely studied. Darré, Le Sens des pratiques and La Production de connaissances pour l’action. 3 The notion of “recalcitrance” was Isabelle Stengers’, later put to use by Bruno Latour. It is explained at length in Stengers’ Invention of Modern Science and Cosmopolitics I and II. 4 The fact that Jocelyne Porcher worked as a farmer and therefore felt close to those she was investigating makes for a certain kind of practice. The choice to write on piggery work in collaboration with a former employee of the pig farming industry, Christine Tribondeau, translates and prolongs this political choice (Porcher and Tribondeau). For Vinciane Despret, it became necessary to modify her practice during research in refugee camps in the former Yugoslavia where the effects of the research ran the risk of stigmatization and therefore of worsening the condition of the people investigated. Addressing these people as refugees, for example, an identity they didn’t recognize themselves as having, only repeated the process of exclusion. On this topic, see Chauvenet, Despret, and Lemaire. 5 On this question of the methodological choices embarked upon in the refugee camps, see Despret, “L’Effet sans nom.” 6 In an earlier work we analysed the politeness of questioning by designating under this name the capacity for a question to make the one being addressed interesting. An impolite question makes people less interesting, less reflexive and, in a related manner, less interested. See Despret, Quand le loup habitera avec l’agneau. 7 Apart from the problem of expectations, other difficulties come crowding in the moment one takes into consideration the fact that the one being interrogated cannot help but be affected by the manner of interrogation. See Porcher, “L’Occultation de l’affectivité.” 8 Most experiments in psychology are constructed on the ignorance of subjects as to what is really driving the research. Stanley Milgram, for example, in his famous experiment, makes out he is conducting research on the effects of electric shocks in training. In fact, the true object of the experiment is the capacity of the subjects to be obedient – without realizing to what point the apparatus is only measuring the subjects’ submission to the researchers. The so-called ignorance of the subjects is incidentally often cast as “silent consent,” but they have, for the most part, understood what is going on, and have at the same time perfectly adapted to the idea that what is expected of them is simulated naivety. 9 In this, our work links in at least two aspects, to Jean-Marie Lemaire’s proposed clinical work in consultation clinics. One is the active search for expertise as resource, especially by insisting on the fact that the social workers, in situations of multiple difficulties, are brought in by the users. Secondly, it is all about looking, to the best of one’s ability, for the sites where conflicts, dissent, and disagreements are practicable. See Lemaire, “Liens soignées, liens soignants.” 10 Here we are inheriting a whole tradition in pragmatic sociology, going from John Dewey to Bruno Latour and passing through Luc Boltanski and plenty of others. However, this position is often only made possible after critical work has been done. So, what can one do when strategies to mitigate suffering are at the same time those that paralyse thought? 11 The fact that interpretation always comes afterwards must on no account make one think that the stance of the inquiry is not affected. The very fact of replying to questions concerning biography, infant traumas, “life stories,” as is the case with numerous projects, and the fact that those interrogated, in general, don’t allow themselves to make remarks such as “But what’s that got to do with my project?,” shows that from the very start they submit themselves to the researcher’s interpretation. bibliography Boltanski, Luc, and Laurent Thévenot. On Justification: Economies of Worth. Trans. Catherine Porter. Princeton: Princeton UP, 2006. Print. 98 despret & porcher Chauvenet, Antoinette, Vinciane Despret, and Jean-Marie Lemaire. Clinique de la reconstruction. Paris: L’Harmattan, 1996. Print. Darré, Jean-Pierre. La Production de connaissances pour l’action. Arguments contre le racisme de l’intelligence. Paris: INRA/Fondation Maisons des sciences de l’homme, 1999. Print. Zask, Joëlle. “La Politique comme expérimentation.” By John Dewey. Le Public et ses problèmes. Trans. Joëlle Zask. Pau and Paris: PUP/ Farrago/Léo Scheer, 2003. Print. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:16 21 November 2015 Darré, Jean-Pierre. Le Sens des pratiques. Conceptions d’agriculteurs et modèles d’agronomes. Paris: INRA, 2004. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “L’Effet sans nom. L’Anonymat dans les pratiques de la psychologie.” Web. <http:// www.vincianedespret.be/2010/04/leffet-sans-nom/>. Despret, Vinciane. Quand le loup habitera avec l’agneau. Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond, 2002. Print. Dewey, John. The Public and its Problems. Carbondale: Southern Illinois UP, 1984. Print. Hennion, Antoine. “Affaires de goût. Se rendre sensible aux choses.” Sensibiliser. La Sociologie dans le vif du monde. Ed. Michel Peroni and Jacques Roux. La Tour d’Aigues: L’Aube, 2006. 161–74. Print. Latour, Bruno. Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network Theory. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2005. Print. Lemaire, Jean-Marie. “Liens soignées, liens soignants, cliniques de concertation et violences de quartier.” Cahiers de psychologie clinique 28.1 (2007): 99–120. Print. Porcher, Jocelyne. “L’Occultation de l’affectivité dans l’expérimentation animale. Le Paradoxe des protocoles.” Nature, Sciences, Société I (2002): 33– 36. Print. Porcher, Jocelyne, and Christine Tribondeau. Une vie de cochon. Paris: La Découverte, 2008. Print. Stengers, Isabelle. Cosmopolitics I. Trans. Robert Bononno. Minneapolis and London: U of Minnesota P, 2010. Print. Stengers, Isabelle. Cosmopolitics II. Trans. Robert Bononno. Minneapolis and London: U of Minnesota P, 2011. Print. Stengers, Isabelle. The Invention of Modern Science. Trans. Daniel W. Smith. Minneapolis and London: U of Minnesota P, 2000. Print. Vinciane Despret Philosophie et Lettres Université de Liège 4000 Liège Belgium E-mail: [email protected] Jocelyne Porcher 143 rue Marc Rigal, C322 34070 Montpellier France E-mail: [email protected] Stephen Muecke School of Humanities and Languages University of New South Wales Sydney, NSW 2052 Australia E-mail: [email protected] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:17 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:17 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:18 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:18 21 November 2015 ANGELAKI journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:19 21 November 2015 translator’s foreword For four months in 2007–08, Paris’s Parc de la Villette housed a multimedia art exhibition entitled Beasts and Humans. Located in Paris’s 19th arrondissement, the park is historically and culturally important: today it is a sprawling park system of concert venues, museums, green space, pavilions, cinemas, and more, but a century and a half ago the area, then on the outskirts of the city, was an abattoir district. Beasts and Humans was housed in the newly renovated “Grand Hall,” formerly a slaughterhouse, and the first image that visitors would see as they entered the hall was that of a long shot of a cow ruminating in a moving image by the experimental filmmaker Georges Rey. As then-President of the Park Jacques Martial puts it in his Foreword to the book, “this cow ties together the history, heritage, and present” of the area, and does so by staring them in the eyes, “awakening their humanity” (5). The exhibit featured moving images, photography, installation art, drawings, cultural and scientific artefacts, and more, all showing a diverse representation of animals and their varied lives. Vinciane Despret was one of four experts on the commission of this exhibition, and acted as scientific and cultural advisor, as well as author of the exhibits’ descriptions and eventual book, the eponymous Beasts and Humans. In the final page of her book, Despret writes that one of the requirements they hoped to achieve was to bear witness to the “joyous transformation” of both humans and animals, both historically and in the present, and to show how we have all, humans and animals, transformed and changed together. What began as an epistemological enterprise vinciane despret translated by brett buchanan BEASTS AND HUMANS ended with an open political question: with whom do we wish to live, and how? The book has five parts: (i) Introduction, (ii) Animals transform humans, (iii) The animal is a stranger to humans, (iv) Animals have jobs, and (v) Animals impose choices. The selections translated here are taken from the second and fifth parts, as well as a previously untranslated fable. With the first, Despret draws from the ancient Greek concept mētis to highlight a form of cunning intelligence that is shared and learned between humans and animals. It is an overlooked and often neglected form of intelligence, especially in comparison to phronesis or sophia, but, as Despret notes, humans have been transformed by what they’ve learned, ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020105-5 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039846 105 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:19 21 November 2015 beasts and humans habitually and bodily, by their proximity to and with animals. The second selection showcases how animals continue to surprise and confound humans’ expectations. Drawing on two different cases where vultures have been reintroduced into extirpated areas, we read how the success and achievement in one area is not necessarily duplicated elsewhere, and how different forms of knowledge (lay and expert, human and animal) converge, overlap, and diverge. In the book Bêtes et hommes this flows into the discussion of an incident between a fish farmer and some otters that, in the exhibition itself, Despret related in the alternative form of a poetic fable (in the spirit of la Fontaine), and accompanied by Edmond Baudoin’s painting (reproduced in this issue). Translated by Matthew Chrulew, the fable mimics the push and pull between the otters and the fish farmer as each attempts to outwit the other and lay claim to the fish, with much amusement and consternation along the way. mētis I s the difficulty of creating stories with animals related to the reasons that led to the disappearance of mētis?1 For the people of ancient Greece, this term meant a form of thought and mode of knowing acquired through contact with animals. In particular, mētis stands out as the art of laying and avoiding traps. To use the definition given by Marcel Detienne and Jean-Paul Vernant, it translates as “a type of intelligence and of thought, a way of knowing; it implies a complex but very coherent body of mental attitudes and intellectual behavior which combine flair, wisdom, forethought, subtlety of mind, deception, resourcefulness, vigilance, opportunism, various skills, and experience acquired over the years” (Detienne and Vernant 3). Under the same term, mētis united the intelligence of gods, heroes, fishers and hunters, frogs, octopi, foxes, and many other animals. Its close connection to these various figures might explain its progressive abandonment from our language and philosophy. It testified a little too eloquently to the surprising complicity by which humans learned a certain art of invention and thought from animals. Aristotle, to mention only him, never hid his distrust for mētis, for in his Nicomachean Ethics he critiqued the fact that some of his contemporaries didn’t hesitate to attribute phronesis, the practical wisdom of prudence that rationally guides behaviour, to some species of animals. For the Greeks, among the countless animals with mētis, two deserve mentioning. The octopus and the fox have the value of being true models, and besides, the fox is comparable to the octopus due to its ability to play dead when approached by a flock of prey. “Like the fox, the octopus defines a type of human behavior: ‘Present a different aspect of yourself (epı́strephe poikı́lon ēthos) to each of your friends’” (Detienne and Vernant 39). Odysseus is the hero of mētis, as he puts on a different face to everyone, and the Greeks observed that the octopus brought the art of camouflage and transformation to the limits of what was imaginable – it is capable of taking on the appearance of the most diverse things, like stones, and can blend into the environment to the point that it becomes invisible. Mētis deploys itself as an intelligence of traps and cunning; in the animal world, like in the human world, power relations are constantly distorted by its intervention. In order to defend themselves, those who have neither power nor weapons received another resource from the gods, an intelligence rich in cunning and strategies. It’s thus in the very experience of the animal world that mētis finds itself strengthened, and packed with all the necessary resources. In his treatise on animals, Plutarch insists that hunting octopi develops practical skills and intelligence. All of the descriptions show this similarity. The hunter and fisher must have the very same qualities as those they’re trapping: vigilance (the animals they lie in wait for never give up their vigilance), cunning, speed, trickery, and camouflage (the art of seeing without being seen). These terms are common to both human and animal, especially the term polútropos that refers to both the octopus and 106 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:19 21 November 2015 despret human with mētis, the “man of twists and turns,” thus accentuating their kinship.2 This kinship unfolds both metaphorically as well as through action and practices; for the human who confronts the animal, it consists of learning from the animal’s intelligence and imitating him so as to triumph over him. However, mētis is not simply an appropriation of technique, as is the case in the examples above. It is towards a real transformation that humans are called. When Odysseus is compared to an octopus because of his cunning forms we realize that this analogy implies a metamorphosis, and active identification, of his entire being. Because he learned this cunning from a long tradition of relations between the Greeks and marine animals, Odysseus had become like “some octopus.”3 The epic of Odysseus, in the hands of Homer, inscribes itself therefore within another story, a story through which humans, in a relation that has both complicity and rivalry, have learned a thing or two from animals who transform their being. It is a story of “becoming with.” A story of the active construction of resemblances. This active construction of resemblances – and it is in this that it clears itself of an anthropomorphism that would only bring the other into oneself – subjects itself to a demand: that of entering the world of the other, to think as he or she thinks, to allow oneself to experience their desires and affects. In short, to extend one’s being to the being of the other. Some two thousand years later, albeit in an entirely different manner, a theory will propose to follow through with this project: the theory of the Umwelt. Except for one small difference, which inverts the perspective. It isn’t the possibility of resemblances and identifications with animals that guides this project; rather, it’s an intuition of their profound strangeness. […] achievements and their excesses Of all the situations that we’ve encountered, a common thread can be drawn: over the course of centuries, we have placed our trust in 107 nature because it has seemed to be a reserve of stability and immutability, a bastion of strength in the face of an unstable human world that is always in the midst of controversies and negotiations. Animals have switched over to the side of humans, and we cannot trust them except on this one point: no matter what you propose to them, they will surprise you. It is always risky to bet the future on what they will offer to a proposition. What counts as an achievement here might over there, a hundred kilometres away, be met with the worst difficulties. Here and there; but what changes? Here or there, it is nevertheless the same desire: we want to live again with vultures. Necrophagous, or scavenger, species are not only vulnerable; they also do extremely useful work. Here we find the Jonte gorges in Grand Causses Regional Natural Park, in central south France. Some ecologists asked some naturalists from the Pyrenees region for help; the latter accepted, and brought along a few vultures. But how does one convince the local farmers of the merits of the vultures’ return, especially in so far as vultures were over centuries eradicated by these farmers’ ancestors? An old shepherd will play the role of mediator. He is passionate about these birds and will slowly convince the local population of their benefit. The support of the farmers will be decisive because they are participating in the project by stocking the feeding areas with animal cadavers. Things have proceeded rather well so far. The farmers’ waste is recycled by the vultures, which is interesting economically speaking. Here, therefore, is an achievement in breaking from old and impolite habits by finding new interests that, this time around, converge. There, by contrast, the alliance will encounter the worst difficulties. There is the Pyrenees. In order to invite the vultures, they were similarly offered sites for feeding. The animals responded with enthusiasm; with a little too much enthusiasm really, for after a while the vultures proved to be too numerous for the ecosystem. “What has changed from one situation to the other?,” we asked ourselves. It is precisely the achievement: these situations are always at risk of unpredictable successes. The opposite of an Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:19 21 November 2015 beasts and humans achievement, in other words, is an excess of achievement. The feeding sites had to be closed down, and in response to this, the vultures began to behave in frankly uncivil ways: they renounced their comfortable and peaceful necrophagous positions, it would seem, in order to adopt predatory practices on livestock. And so now one finds these inconsistent birds (volatiles) proposing a category change: after centuries of good and loyal service in the cleaning of carcasses, they purport to reach the dignity of predator. The conflict between the vultures and farmers now moves over to one between farmers and naturalists: for the former, the vultures have well and truly changed categories. This could modify the conditions of their protection agreement: this in fact happened in Germany, where the agreement was challenged in the mid-1990s when fifty or so ravens invaded the idyllic region of the Swabian Alps, close to the town of Balingen, and, according to witness accounts, proceeded to attack livestock (cf. Despret, “Enigma of the Raven”). The farmers affiliated themselves with hunters in order to demand that the law, which has protected ravens since their nearextinction, be lifted. Should this not also apply to the vultures? The ecologists, one may suspect, will not be prepared to consider a change of categories. This lends itself to the thought that, beyond the rather concrete stakes of this story, lay knowledge and scholarly knowledge may not have the same confidence with respect to the reliability of categories or, according to some, the same flexibility. The fact remains that, according to the ecologists, the vulture would still be unfairly accused: a vulture cannot attack a living animal because he doesn’t have the means to kill it. All of these incidents occurred on the basis of a tragic misunderstanding: the animals who were attacked were all sick, but because of their immobility, they were seen by the vultures to be dead. This is also the argument that, in Balingen, ended up saving the ravens from condemnation. Ravens, as related by an old Inuit legend, received an assignment, at the origin of the world, to make it a little less perfect – the gods had quickly understood that a perfect world would be profoundly boring. Ravens were thus specially tasked with complicating the lives of humans, who were themselves, it must be said, created as a menagerie for the amusement of the gods. They put such an effort in playing the trickster – e.g., reversing the flow of rivers, replacing the leaves off trees with fat – that the gods had to put the brakes on their enthusiasm: humans no longer had the upper hand. complications And this is exactly what characterizes the new adventures of cohabitation: they complicate our lives. They force inventiveness. In this respect, otters have nothing to envy in crows, for they could just as well have been mandated by who knows what mischievous gods to annoy humans. When recounted after the fact, the situation is almost funny: we must wonder whether otters acquired a sense of humour during their contact with humans, unless it is a taste for provocation. Hasn’t this been considered with respect to wolves who, as some farmers claim, taunt them right under their noses and in the light of day when they attack livestock? Making peace with animals who are quite clearly not ready to make any concessions requires a bit of courage and imagination; and this is all the more so when dealing with beings who are quite resourceful, like otters.4 disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author. notes Translated from Vinciane Despret, Bêtes et hommes © Editions Gallimard, Paris, 2007, 38–41, 128–30. 1 The timidity of anthropologists and philosophers, nevertheless, has a few exceptions. One 108 despret can find an hypothesis on these exchanges of properties in Robert Maggiori’s wonderful book Un animal, un philosophe, which shows, through many philosophical tales, the profound diversity of our ways of entering into relations with animals. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:19 21 November 2015 2 The “man of twists and turns” is a reference to Odysseus, and is drawn from the opening lines of Homer’s The Odyssey: “Sing to me of the man, Muse, the man of twists and turns […]” (Prologue, line 1). [Translator’s note.] 3 Homer, The Odyssey, Book V, lines 476–78: “Like pebbles stuck in the suckers of some octopus / dragged from its lair – so strips of skin torn / from his clawing hands stuck to the rock face.” [Translator’s note.] 4 Two French researchers, the ethnologist Patricia Pellegrini and the sociologist Elisabeth Remy, carried out a nice study on the various arrangements to which the otters invited us: the one we are recounting here, on the one hand, and on the other hand, that of the creation of “otterducts,” namely aquatic tunnels designed to facilitate the passage of otters under highways. They show that these arrangements have largely contributed to feeding the knowledge of naturalists, who, due to the discretion of these animals, are often not well known. bibliography Despret, Vinciane. Bêtes et hommes. Paris: Gallimard, 2007. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “The Enigma of the Raven.” Trans. Jeffrey Bussolini. Angelaki 20.2 (2015): 57–72. Print. Detienne, Marcel, and Jean-Paul Vernant. Cunning Intelligence in Greek Culture and Society. Trans. Janet Lloyd. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1991. Print. Homer. The Odyssey. Trans. Robert Fagles. New York: Penguin, 1996. Print. Maggiori, Robert. Un animal, un philosophe. Paris: Julliard, 2005. Print. Remy, Elisabeth, and Patricia Pellegrini. “Changer nos habitudes de prédation: L’Exemple de la loutre et du pisciculteur.” Éducation relative à l’environnement 5 (2006): 51–64. Print. Vinciane Despret Philosophie et Lettres Université de Liège 4000 Liège Belgium E-mail: [email protected] Brett Buchanan Department of Philosophy School of the Environment Laurentian University 935 Ramsey Lake Road Sudbury Ontario P3E 2C6 Canada E-mail: [email protected] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:20 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:20 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:20 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:20 21 November 2015 ANGELAKI Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:21 21 November 2015 journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 vinciane despret translated by matthew chrulew THE OTTER AND THE FISH FARMER ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020115-4 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039848 115 the otter and the fish farmer A young man with a comely face and ambitious plans Chose to earn his living breeding fishes. From its old owner he bought up a beautiful expanse To host them and achieve his wishes: Wooded fields, meadows, ponds and a river; Of singing waters though harsher winters. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:21 21 November 2015 How he got a fright At the dawn of a promising future To discover, at the fall of night How many strange visitors Were guests at the christening of the site To shamelessly feast around his labour. Nothing seemed to rein in the romp, nothing curbed their appetites All: young fishes, plump mothers, breeders, and even, our man was nonplussed, Ten kilo fishes, The finest and the biggest Prematurely finished their lives In gluttons’ guts. The young man was conciliatory, He did not want hostility There certainly must be Arbitration channels With the voracious mammals. What had been done by his predecessors Faced with this war? “You’d rather not know” – they avoided the issue For the scamp, I remind you Has the protection Of many conventions. Some methods talk of welfare A silent smile sometimes says a lot Like a rifle shot. Our man is gallant, as I have told He doesn’t want harsh methods, just a little resolve He appeals to the authorities, Seeks a compromise with the environmental ministry The response, he notes, disappoints somewhat: “If the otters are there; “They were already there.” In a nutshell They washed their hands well And left the waters To the otters. Our pisciculturist is undeterred The centre for otter preservation is called in turn 116 despret Observing overnight, there are clues, evidence of plunder Discovering especially the rascals’ wily plots The weak armour of the fences they easily sunder Thinking: so little work for such a jackpot. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:21 21 November 2015 If this fencing cannot stop them Maybe a little shock, just one blow Will discourage the mammalian deviants Who will learn from their woe. The punishment can be lenient Electrical wire will do fine The parry is prepared; he’s drawn the line. The wire, however, should be kept from the ground And not touched by the snow that in winter abounds. This is where the villains From this wise precaution Will derive the real lesson: Within a few days, the trick is unravelled And beneath the wire, the otters still travel. The solution might come from light – why had he not thought of it? That should scare them, on each of their visits A good fright: lamps that light up will make them scuttle And take away their mettle. Except that otters are creatures of habit And habits are formed and modified – As they have already well testified Faced with danger when formerly diurnal They escaped the hunt by becoming nocturnal – Showing that the harshest adversities Are often founts of creativity. If the light bothers them momentarily They get used to it very quickly And even seem to enjoy diverting the lure To taunt the fish farmer. All that remained was an appeal to the dogs Who would guard the ponds They are left in the garden at night They do their work, they chase, bark and bite Then each can rest, trouts and humans. This should be the right solution. The affair, however, met still more wrinkles, And like the sprinkler sprinkled, 117 the otter and the fish farmer One discovers in the morning, a dog’s bloody shoulder, Bitten by a frightened otter. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:21 21 November 2015 Perhaps geese might prevail? But what could they do where dogs have failed? It all happened there, and after every try, He had to begin again: Enclosures, electricity, dogs, lights, odours, fences low and high They jump, crawl, bypass, ignore; nothing frightens them. But the otters have allies Since it comes to preventing war Choosing peace will get its reward And the Ministry, this time Will care for the ponds, the fish, the otters and the farmer. And that is why, around ponds now with protection By the miracle of an agreement Humans, otters, trout, farming and conservation Engage together in an experiment Around the best solutions. note Translated from Vinciane Despret, “La Loutre et le pisciculteur,” exhibited at Bêtes et hommes, Parc de la Villette, Paris, 2007–08. Vinciane Despret Philosophie et Lettres Université de Liège 4000 Liège Belgium E-mail: [email protected] Matthew Chrulew Centre for Culture and Technology Research and Graduate Studies Faculty of Humanities Curtin University GPO Box U1987 Perth, WA 6845 Australia E-mail: [email protected] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:22 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:22 21 November 2015 ANGELAKI journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 translator’s foreword Vinciane Despret’s short 2009 book Thinking Like a Rat is a continuation of her concept of asking good questions in animal research and use of the tools of biosemiotics and cognitive ethology to address how animals perceive, interpret, and act upon research situations. She asks, prominently, what does the maze mean for the rat? In doing so she points out that behaviorist research using rats and mazes failed to inquire how the rats perceived the mazes and what the rats found interesting. It also overlooked the ways in which the maze itself was fashioned as a tool that intersected heavily with the everyday habits and navigation of rats living within the walls of a human built environment. Departing from that research and drawing on the critiques of the experimenter effect and the perception of expectation in research, she opens up the field of research involving animals and humans to include more understanding of how animals perceive contexts of research and form intersubjective ties with human scientists as well as other animals that affect the outcome of the research. She points out that animals, like human research subjects, are canny observers of the process who often have a good idea of what the research is designed to reveal, regardless of the lures, dissimulation, and other tools used to mask the true questions at hand. She proposes developing interesting questions that give animals a chance to demonstrate their interests and be interesting in lieu of reductive and standardizing set-ups that seek to hide the true questions at hand or treat all individuals as the same. Interesting research asks animals about their interests and ways of doing things rather than attempting to force vinciane despret translated by jeffrey bussolini THINKING LIKE A RAT an answer to a question that may or may not be of importance to them. The book is divided into six chapters and an interview discussion. The first chapter is devoted to “Lures and Artefacts” as important concepts and practices in research with animals. The second chapter asks what happens “if researchers are nice with their animals,” opening up the considerations about how good questions and genuine interest in the life and mind of an animal can produce much more fascinating results than stultifying repetition. Chapter 3 asks “what a maze can mean” to a rat who experiences it, and how it is that rats recognize and navigate different parts of it. The fourth chapter looks at the perception that animals have of human expectations and how this can ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020121-14 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039849 121 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 thinking like a rat be a major factor in results, as the animals ask themselves “what does it (the human) want of me?” Chapter 5 investigates the idea of response and says “the question of response is a question whose answer changes everything.” The final chapter says that “joy is demanding” and takes account of how recent research in judgment and emotions opens a fertile field for considering how animals judge the questions of research and what they feel about the activities and situations involved. The interview and discussion gives an elucidation of some of the themes and concepts Despret introduces in the book. lures and artefacts I n the mid-1960s experimental psychology received severe critiques on the subject of the validity of its experiments: experimental subjects conform most often to the expectations of their experimenters. This is to say, as the American psychologists Martin Orne and Robert Rosenthal will each argue in their own way, that every experiment relies in large part on an artefact: the scientists think that the subjects respond to the question that is posed to them, but the subjects, in fact, respond to another question. If I propose to take an interest in this and to make this detour it is because these critiques touch very close to the subject that I would like to explore. They interrogate the way in which the subjects of the experiments and their responses are affected by the way in which they live and actively take into account that which is expected of them. In sum, we will see, these two critiques pose the problem of the “point of view” of those whom the science investigates, the “point of view” on the question that is addressed to them, or on the protocol to which they are submitted, and how they respond to what they interpreted the question of the experimenter to be. Now, it is exactly this that seems to constitute, even if later and in forms surpassing that of critique, a remarkable slide in research on animals: beginning to take into consideration the point of view that animals have on the way in which they can take a position in relation to what is proposed to them in scientific research. The critiques of Orne and Rosenthal emerged at the same time, during the 1960s; both of them emanate from the very interior of psychology since they were both trained by practitioners of experimentation. Their critiques are founded on relatively close empirical premises and are presented in a very similar form: many of the convergences will nonetheless paradoxically lead to very different, even antagonistic, responses and propositions. We should specify that their critique was not, in and of itself, an absolute novelty. Psychologists were well aware that their subjects could be influenced by what the scientist was looking for. This was incidentally the reason why, in the research, the experimenters tried most often to camouflage the real questions guiding their research, which would permit them to eradicate the hypothesis according to which the subjects would do what was demanded of them because the researchers asked them to do so. From the fact that they do not know what is expected of them, because it is hidden from them, the subjects do not do what they do because the experimenter asked them to do so, but for more abstract and more general reasons. This, according to the psychologists, would therefore guarantee the “ecological validity” of the experiment. This describes or demonstrates something that would apply outside the laboratory, which would not be the case if the subjects had done what they did because the scientist had asked them to do so: that which they did by means of this strategy, they would do in other circumstances. When the psychologist Stanley Milgram, to take up a famous experiment dating from the same period, undertakes to study the capacity for obedience in humans, he does not ask his subjects: “are you capable of electrocuting someone because I ask you to do it?” He pretends, on the contrary, that they are taking part in an experiment on the effects of punishment in the learning setting, and that they must give electric shocks to a “student” when he does not respond correctly to questions that they must pose to him (the experimenter 122 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 despret convinces them that he is also a volunteer in the experiment). Since the subjects do not know that they are taking part in research on obedience, Milgram feels well justified in claiming that the true stakes of the experiment will not guide their responses. The problem of expectations, it was thought, had found its solution. Orne and Rosenthal will, however, take up, each in his own way, this critique of the influence of the experimenter and take it further. On the one hand, this matter of the effect of the question was until then confined almost exclusively to experiments with humans, since it was believed that they were the only ones sensitive to expectations.1 Rosenthal extends it to animals: they too would be affected by what is expected of them by the experimenters, and this would modify their performances.2 On the other hand, if human psychology had thought to find a solution to this problem of expectations in hiding from its subject the real stakes of each experiment (as I just indicated in the case of Milgram), Orne shows that this solution raises still more difficulties than it resolves. The subjects, most of the time, not only predict what the experimenter expects of them but they conform to it with such good will that the care taken to hide these expectations cannot but underscore their extreme importance (Orne; Orne and Holland). Starting with the work of Orne, we’ll approach that of Rosenthal in the next chapter.3 In the beginning, this experimental psychologist, a specialist in hypnosis, did not have a critical dismantling of the way in which experiments were conducted in mind; he simply wanted to find the experimental dispositive that would allow him to discover a reliable marker of difference between the subjects who had been hypnotized and those who had not.4 In fact, nothing up to that point in the experimental procedure guaranteed that one was dealing with a subject really under hypnosis, and not with a subject that was simulating it. Every procedure indicating hypnosis was consequently always suspect, since one could never prove that the phenomenon the effects of which one was trying to elucidate was indeed what one claimed to have set up. Orne therefore 123 considers a situation that can “make a difference”: according to him, the capacity to tolerate an annoying task and to do it well over a long period of time and simply because the experimenter had asked for it would clearly create the contrast. Hypnotized people should, in principle, show a very different deference from that of normal subjects. Orne starts with the test group, composed of non-hypnotized subjects. He asks them to conduct an absolutely absurd, repetitive, and tedious task. This was to resolve some two hundred additions on a sheet of paper and, at the end of this, to fish for a card that would invariably give a directive to tear the completed paper into thirty-two pieces, then to take another calculation paper, resolve the two hundred additions there, take another card that would invariably have a directive to … It would be the experimenter who, after more than five hours of observation, blinked first. And when the subjects were asked why they did all this work without objecting and without posing other questions, they responded that they had thought that it was a test of endurance. And they obeyed because a scientist asked them to. That is to say that they did not respond to the question that the scientist thought he was asking but to the way in which they interpreted that which was expected of them, in the very particular context of the laboratory. Now, Orne remarks, if I had asked my secretary to do a fortieth of this task, she would have refused. He continues, if you ask some people in your entourage whether they agree to do you a favor, and on their affirmative response you tell them to do five push-ups, they will respond “why?” If you ask a group of people if they want to take part in a scientific experiment and, after their agreement, you tell them that you expect them to do five pushups, they will ask “where?” Deference, Orne concludes, evidently cannot constitute the acceptable criterion of difference between hypnotized subjects and “normal” experimental subjects.5 In light of what his subjects responded to him, Orne goes further in concluding that the lure utilized to mask the expectations, in Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 thinking like a rat psychology, far from resolving the problem, only complicates it. A simple dispositive suffices to show this: Orne brings the subjects together and tells them what will be asked of them and what they will have to do in the course of the experiment. He carefully describes the protocol and the tasks to execute without telling them more about it than if they were really participating in the experiment, therefore hiding, as is done in these types of situations, the real stakes. He asks them at the beginning of these explanations what, in their view, the psychologist is really looking for: the subjects then formulate very precise and pertinent hypotheses. This has since been nicely shown by an investigation of that famous experiment of Milgram’s that I referenced above. The scientific journalist Ian Parker went to re-interview the subjects who had taken part in the experiment, forty years later. Most of them told him that, if they had played the game, it was precisely because they had understood that the experiment must necessarily have been rigged, since it is clear, according to them, that electrocuting people is not allowed in universities. Certainly, one can always suspect that persons retroactively revisit the story and seek to give themselves a clear conscience by always pretending to have known that it was, as the children say, “only make believe.” The fact remains that the arguments make good sense: it would be difficult to imagine sending – with the blessing of a scientist, and under his responsibility – lethal charges to another human in a respected university – to an animal, we should note, it would be a different matter. The people interviewed, on the other hand, proposed explanations that seem convincing to me: some said, for example, that at the moment when the supposed victim screamed in pain they turned worried toward the desk of Milgram and his assistant watching the operations, behind glass, and saw them laughing – or undisturbed. They concluded from this what they should conclude. When Ian Parker asked them why they then continued, and why they said nothing, since they had taken account of the fact that all of this was nothing but a farce, they responded that it was “for the sake of science.”6 Since they were asked to … The allure of a paradox in this type of research should not be ignored. When psychology inquires into this problematic deference on the part of the subjects, what it covers over or deliberately ignores is that this deference is not an inherent characteristic of humans, it is due to the organization of the research itself. Everything points to the necessity of this: the rigid and constraining protocol, the fact that the scientist distributes expertise in a very asymmetrical manner, a situation close to that of the examination, the supposed or induced ignorance of the subjects, etc. Now, psychology treats deference not as an effect of what it imposes but as an essential characteristic that it acts to counter. Which leads to a paradox: psychologists construct dispositives that give rise to deference and must do everything possible to neutralize it. And, as in every situation with a lure, they are then obliged to keep asking: “but did my subjects really believe me? Did they not nonetheless understand what I was looking for and respond to that very question, without my knowledge?” They also use posttest questionnaires to verify that the subjects have indeed been taken for a ride. Now, and it is Orne who emphasizes this, the subjects, in this case, knowing that the fact of having understood the hypothesis will invalidate their research, prefer to say nothing and to continue pretending to have responded in all naivety – it is what is called the pact of double ignorance, since neither of the two, neither the experimenter, nor the subject, really has the desire to say or to know what is really at play: on either side, this would ruin the experiment. It would thus be much better, concludes Orne, in the experiments, to count on the collaboration of the subjects rather than on their socalled gullibility. what a maze can mean In proposing to translate what happens to rats in terms of meanings, I draw here on the very important work of the naturalist Jakob von Uexkü ll, and his theory, especially that of the 124 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 despret Umwelt. And since we are with the rats here, it is with them that I propose to consider the ways in which this theory could open up for the animal, at least partially, the question of point of view. Some biographical elements are in order. Jakob von Uexküll was an Estonian naturalist (1864–1944). After studies in biology, he took part in a comparative study of invertebrate physiology. This research led him, contrary to what the practices of the time encouraged doing, to want to enlarge his perspective and to consider the totality of the organism in relation to its environment (milieu), an environment that he will define as a concrete or lived one: the Umwelt. The intuition from which this theory departs is to all appearances quite simple: the animal, endowed with sensory organs different from our own, cannot perceive the same world as we do. Bees don’t have the same perception of color as we do, we do not perceive scents in the same way that butterflies do, and we are not at all able to sense, as a tick can, the odor of the butyric acid released by the sebaceous follicles of mammals. It is there that the theory will take a courageously original turn, for perception will be defined not as a form of “reception” but as an act of creation: the animal does not perceive passively, it “fills its environment with perceptual objects,” it constructs its environment by peopling it with perceptual objects that, from then on, become perceived. In other words, perceptions are not passive, they are the object of an activity by which the animal will perceive them. The activity of perception is above all an activity that confers meaning. Only that which has a meaning is perceived, just as only that which can be perceived, and which is important for the organism, is accorded a meaning. The Umwelt, or lived world of the animal, is above all a world where things are only perceived, on the one hand, because they are captured by particular sensory equipment – the butterfly lives in a world of luminous intensities and of odors, for example – and, on the other hand, to the degree in which they have taken on a meaning. And it is with these meanings 125 that the animal constructs its perceptual universe. Time, space, place, path, way, house, odor, enemy, each event in the perceived world is an event that “signifies,” which is not perceived except in that it signifies – and by that which it signifies – an event that makes of the animal a “lender” of meaning, that is to say a subject. For each perception of meaning, according to Uexkü ll, implies a subject, just as each subject is defined as that which accords meaning. How do things acquire a meaning? Quite simply, Uexkü ll responds, through action. The animal never enters into a relation with an object as such. The object is constituted in action; its meaning does not emerge except in relation to action that can be practiced. Objects are not alone in having meanings accorded to them. Inspiring the work of Konrad Lorenz, in fact, Uexküll will hold that the Umwelt is at the same time an environment of relations, that is to say an environment in which beings will take on various meanings for one another. Consequently, if it is perceived, no animal can be neutral in the environment of another; that is to say if it can be accorded a meaning, or if it can be seen to be accorded one. What does a jackdaw mean in the life of a jackdaw, or rather, what does this jackdaw mean in the life of this other jackdaw? This is the question that Lorenz will pose to Tchock, the jackdaw he adopted. It is a strange lure that made this type of research possible: Lorenz himself became the alluring producer of sociality, an enticement for meanings (since lures are frequently required in order to convey the meanings of an animal). By adopting a young jackdaw, Lorenz shows that a human can take on the meaning of “socius” and subsequently learn what “socius” means in the life of a jackdaw. The jackdaws who live in society have the habit of associating, for their whole lives, with a companion (socius) with whom they carry out various activities together. Tchock, who was raised by Lorenz, thus took him for a maternal socius. He followed him everywhere and asked him to give him food. He later tried to teach him to fly; but after the failure of his repeated attempts the jackdaw finally gave up and considered Lorenz as an Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 thinking like a rat activity companion, acceptable, certainly, but limited. This original adventure shows us that meanings are not fixed once and for all, flowing from elementary needs of the organism: they are flexible, can apply to other beings, extend to unforeseen situations, change, and even invent and create new relational uses. It is time now to return to the rats, with the goal of asking them, in accordance with a tradition that I am, however, interrogating, to help me to test a hypothesis: when observing rats, what can produce the activity of translating their behaviors in terms of meanings? “Thousands of experimental series have been made in the past decades by numerous American scientists,” Uexküll writes, “who tried to determine how soon an animal was able to learn a certain pathway, through requiring widely varied animals to orient themselves in a maze … They have neither investigated the visual, tactile or scent cues, nor given thought to the application of the coordinate system by the animal – that right and left is a problem in itself has never struck them. Nor have they ever debated the question of the number of paces, because they did not see that in animals, too, the pace may serve as the measure of distance” (“Stroll” 51). The critique is certainly merited, but its accuracy requires some clarification. The behaviorists, and John Watson in particular, did in fact very much consider the influence of optical, tactile, and olfactory perceptual characteristics. I would not, however, go so far as to say that they examined them. Unless one confuses the term “examine” with that of “neutralize.” For that is indeed what Watson did, in a procedure that, if one were to think of it as resembling an examination, would guide the patient toward a sadistic torturer rather than to their doctor: he removed the rat’s eyes, olfactory bulb, and whiskers, which are essential to the sense of touch in rats, before throwing it into the exploration of the maze. And since the rat no longer wished to run in the maze or go in search of the food payment, he starved him: “he began at once to learn the maze and finally became the usual automaton.”7 Of course. All that he proves is that, if we remove the conscience from a psychologist, he continues to write.8 Who has become the automaton in this story? This falls far short. And it is certainly very far from the universe of meanings. For that matter, this is even further from it since the being issuing from this systematic practice of destruction is no longer, for the psychologist, a rat. If the world had probably lost all meaning for this de-sensed rat, the rat itself had lost all meaning for its experimenter – that is, if it ever had one for him. It is a new organism, reduced to a minimum of its sensations, and who, from this fact, counts for all the others. This is the goal of the procedure: search out the lowest common denominator, the “leftover,” the automaton, the behavior that, from one species to another, will render all organisms commensurable (Burt). And this commensurability, it can be underlined in passing, bears on the criterion par excellence for a society haunted by the idea of production and efficiency (Haraway 43ff.): the time required to run a maze. All of this, one can see, has nothing to do with the meanings that the maze can take on for the rat. We haven’t learned much of value; it is on this point that Uexkü ll will resume his critique, in his essay on the theory of meaning: “In this way, American researchers have attempted tirelessly, in thousands of experiments, beginning with white rats, to study the most different kinds of animals in their relations to a maze. The unsatisfying results of these labors, which were conducted with the most precise methods of measurement and the greatest skill in calculation, could have been predicted by anybody who had come to the realization that the tacit assumption that an animal could ever enter into a relationship with an object is false” (Uexküll, Foray 139; Despret cites Uexkü ll, Mondes animaux 94). One can note in passing that this critique finds an echo today in the research on wellbeing. When we ask chickens about their preferences, Robert Dantzer explains, we generally ask them what effort they are ready to agree to for a particular environment. The bird has use of two keys that it can work with its beak to narrow (with one key) or augment (with the 126 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 despret other) the size of the cage. One can note, he continues, not without a point of irony, that the space the chickens grant themselves differs little from commercial conditions. One could conclude from this therefore that it is the optimum space for chickens. “But this would be a bit hasty and neglect a major epistemological problem, namely that it is not straightforward to enter into the subjective universe of an animal in interrogating it through an experimental dispositive thought up by a human. It is possible that the animal responds in the experimental dispositive on the basis of very different elements, for example the proximity of a congener, but not the representation of the space in itself as such” (Dantzer 99).9 To return to the rat: on the basis of what elements does it respond when it is submitted to the demand to traverse the maze? Posing this question goes back to asking what this particular experimental dispositive can mean for a rat. How can this traversing come to be, from the point of view of the rat, that which Uexkü ll calls a “familiar path”? How do the rats, in pretending to respond to the questions of the behaviorists (in this case, the question is: what is the abstract relation of a being, whatever it may be, that which the behaviorists call an organism, to a neutral object?), respond in fact to another question? For it is indeed this that it concerns: the artefact par excellence. The rats respond to another question than the one the experimenter poses to them. And the experimenter can never suspect this would be the case, simply because he never took into consideration the point of view that the rat could have of the situation. The problem can be posed differently, on the basis of another supposition, that will allow us to affirm Uexkü ll’s hypothesis by adding some clarifications to it: why do rats always touch the walls as they go along them? It is this that all those who have been able to observe rats, notably when they invade our houses, have been able to affirm. Responding to this question will give us some indices as to what a “familiar path” can be for a rat. We must, however, reformulate the question, exiting the why of causes and entering into the regime of meanings: 127 from this perspective, what does a wall (something to run along) mean for a rat? The American biologists who observed them invented a term to characterize rats: they are “haptophiles,” they like to touch. The wall therefore has the meaning of “thing to touch.” But a slightly more complicated hypothesis could make sense of this characteristic (Sullivan 12). Rats developed a particular kinesthetic memory, since the rat must resolve this problem in its everyday activities. And its haptophilia is a response to this problem. In its daily peregrinations that lead it from the nest to different places of exploration that will permit it to feed itself, how can it find the return path? How to memorize the indications, and all the more so since the majority of these are indications that have meaning only for humans – objects, name and number of the street, right, left, or indeed even maps or designs? The rat resolved this problem by mapping its route in another manner. It inscribes the course of its route in its body in the form of lines, curves, and turns, or even roughnesses, textures, sensations of cold or humidity – what do we know about what the body of a rat can sense? The rat draws, marks, soaks up, in its muscles and on its skin, the map of a lateral landscape. And it is the agreement of this map with the sensations that it will check on the return route that will tell it that it is indeed going the right way, and that the nest will be there, at the precise place where all the sensations will have finished unfolding. The relation to the trace is inverted: it is no longer only a matter of “marking” the places one passes, like rats and many animals do, extending their bodies to the limits of their territory with many doses of odiferous substance, it is also a matter of letting itself be marked by the space, itself organized by the trajectory, and of incorporating the organization. All this is to say: the maze was built by actively integrating a characteristic of the rat; one could say it is “rattish,” in slightly mimicking Uexkü ll. But it integrated this characteristic by retranslating it as an abstract characteristic – the dispositive will for that matter apply to a Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 thinking like a rat considerable number of animals, inasmuch as it is the object on which is built an infinite series of comparisons between what will become organisms. Doing this, by effacing the link, the singular accord that can be woven between the rat and the structure that is presented to it, by rendering unthinkable the event of what a maze could constitute for the rat, the experimental dispositive pulls the rug out from any questioning on the subject of the rat, on all that which it could bear witness to regarding what is interesting for it. Since the rat does not respond to the question of learning, he responds to the question of an architecture that constitutes the world for him. Which is altogether different. And which cannot, from the manner in which the things are organized, be predicted. Of course, we are here in the territory of meaning and points of view. I remain, however, with my question: how does the rat interpret this particular dimension of the experiment that sets her within a question from a human, how does she translate what is expected of her? How does she interpret what is wanted of her, when she is made to run, when she is rewarded, or when she is blinded and each of her sense organs is removed before she is starved? To this question, which is perhaps a contemporary question, at least in the domain of the sciences, Uexkü ll makes no response. These are the limits of his field of inquiry. For if Uexküll can attribute a subjectivity to the animal, and if the Umwelt is also a social environment, it seems to me that his interest is particularly focused on the physical environment and its objects. The “animal’s own world” can, with difficulty, include the human observer as an observer. The “own world” does not appear as a world subject to the double hybridization that requires the interspecific encounter and the crossing of an experimental universe with that of an experience of life. In other words still, even if the “own world” of Uexküll can aspire to “thinking as” another animal, only with difficulty can it envisage a “thinking with” this other animal.10 Besides, the animals that Uexküll, as a biologist, focused on (ticks, flies, sea urchins), are relatively simple organisms, of whom it could not be said, to put it somewhat simply, that it is easy to interest them in our problems. The fact remains that the contrast set up regarding the ways of thinking what a maze can represent maintains its full pertinence, and gives a measure of the cost, in terms of knowledge, of failing to take the animal’s point of view into account. The maze can authorize neither the question of the “familiar path” nor that of the meaning of the wall, still less its meaning as event in the world of a rat. It forbids doing so all the more surely since it is constructed in such a way that this question cannot be opened, since the rat cannot do other than follow along the walls. And when an animal cannot do other than what he is constrained to do, when he does so only because he does not have other possibilities or other choices, then there is a certitude: this has to do with an artefact. At the very least with one artefact. what does it expect of me? I closed the preceding section in a somewhat elliptical manner, by affirming that the situation in the maze presents at least one artefact, leaving one to think that there would then be others. One will recall that, regarding the experiments of human psychology, I defined as artefactual the situations where the being who is interrogated responds to a different question than the one the scientist poses to her. But there are many ways of responding to another question: there are therefore as many possibilities of artefacts. If I broached this problem at the beginning of the book it is for a simple reason: when the question of the artefact is posed – I learned in the course of this research – there is frequently something interesting that opens up as possible. It appeared to me that, most of the time, the hypothesis of the existence of an artefact accompanies the possibility of taking into account the fact that the animal would have a point of view on the situation. Certainly, this possibility can be ignored, can lead to, as Rosenthal pointed out, the will to a larger epistemological sanitization, where the researcher does not take full 128 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 despret measure of what his anxiety prompts in the course of research. When this anxiety, in lieu of expanding the imagination, paralyzes it. I also equally learned to recognize, under the form of the injunction of “more control,” the little red light that announces this paralysis. And I admit to being a bit sad each time that a good opportunity was missed: what I thought to be a promise will not be kept. For there is something promissory each time the anxiety of the artefact is profiled in the sciences that mobilize the beings that respond to it. Consider, then, how the promises weaken and what favors the fact that they can receive, as a response, that which they take on. In an article evaluating the research on relations between humans and livestock animals, the authors note that the animals can react to the observers. However, they continue, these are not the only elements taken into account by the animal: “Researchers must also consider the animals’ expectations during a test. For example, choice tests measuring animals’ preferences for or aversion to different handling procedures indicated that they could predict which procedure was likely […] from environmental or human cues.”11 That is to say, and I follow here the authors’ conclusion, that generalization becomes problematic. Each experiment indicates not only the manner in which the animals generally experience the procedures but the way in which each of the animals lives them as a function of the perception that it has of them, as a function of what it expects. One can see that the problem of expectations is here attributed to the subject of the experiment and that it conveys the way in which the animal actively integrates what is expected of it. Certainly, generalization is in that case compromised. In fact I will go further in affirming that there is no artefact unless there is generalization. If one knows to what specific question this animal here, with perceptible or deducible expectations, in this particular context, responds, then there is no artefact. This clearly does not resolve the problem of generalization.12 That which, one senses, can just as well open either onto a need for more control 129 (even if somewhat vain), in virtue of which the researchers get it into their heads to neutralize everything that could permit the animal to interpret what is expected of it; or, in a more fecund manner, onto the fact of becoming interested in how the animal interprets the situation. In the first case, one does not eradicate the artefact – since animals always expect something, therefore always respond to another question; in the second, we subordinate the results to the question: “To what did it respond?” The way in which the expectations of the animal affect the experiments was well noted by some animal professionals, and some scientists, in research designed to evaluate certain foods for farm animals.13 It would seem, when we observe the ways they behave, that animals interpret these dispositives for what they are: exceptional dispositives. But for some of them the term “exceptional” would seem to take on a double meaning: “this is not usual” and “this will not last.” Things become more complicated. In fact, everything about them indicates exceptionality: the time of the experimental dispositive is not the same since it is set within a provisional and short time (five days of testing, corresponding to the work week) while the time of the farm is a time of accumulated memories and experiences. That which is given to the animal as food also falls under the exceptional, since new types of feed will be tested. Now, if animals eat these types of fodder with less appetite, it is for a very simple reason: because it is not the same thing that they are used to receiving. “From the point of view of the animal, the memory of the food eaten before plays a role, and thus it eats less than in usual circumstances: the results, then, say nothing about the situation but instead about the manner in which the animal interprets the transition. It expects something else, thus what one gives it is not the sole cause involved. This has to do with the effects of the transition because the animals, and it is the animal experts like farmers and shepherds who tell us this, know that this situation will not last. In the same way, when one tries a new dry fodder with a group of cows, and they see that the Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 thinking like a rat group next to them receives fresh grass, they stop eating and think: ‘we too are going to have some of that’. And thus the results of the experiment are dependent on what takes place in the experiment next to it, but no one takes account of the fact that the researches are compartmentalized.”14 One could not give a better definition of the artefact: animals certainly respond to a question, but it is not the one we pose to them. The humor of the situation is too nice not to be underlined: the researchers compartmentalize the research; the animals do not stop prompting them to decompartmentalize it.15 At this point in my exposition you could respond to me that all these critiques go against my hypothesis, that things haven’t really changed since what they are directed at is the fact that researchers do not take into account the point of view of the animal. I am going to try to respond. First of all, I approached the problem from the point of view of the artefact. I recall here that it was in this manner that it was possible to get bearings on the moments when the researchers pose the question from the point of view that the animal can have on the experimental situation. Now, the artefact always constitutes the object of a critique: a critical worry when the researcher ponders her own work; an accusation when another researcher says of the work of a colleague: “you didn’t think of” or, to take back up the terms that Dantzer used, regarding the cages and the chickens, “you have been a bit hasty.” In a certain manner, when Waiblinger affirms that the animal can predict what will be offered to it, or when Meuret suggests that that animals think “we are also going to have some of that,” we are very much within this perspective: animals do not judge an abstract situation, but a situation offered to them as it is offered to them. Following this, I can confirm that some researchers have crossed the divide that consists in taking into consideration the animals’ points of view on the situations presented to them – but not all researchers. And the critiques are evidence of those, and for those, who have crossed the divide. Finally, the critique can just as much take the form of anxiety. In this frame, it would mean that the researchers actively and explicitly started to take into account the fact that the animal poses, to her researcher, the question: what do they want of me? When, for example, Meuret describes his own research, his approach seems to me particularly exemplary of this possibility of considering, actively, the manner in which the animal itself actively takes the questions and the presence of the researcher into consideration. Meuret observes sheep and goats and a part of his research consists in evaluating what they eat when we put them in unfamiliar situations such as zones of underbrush clearing (to avoid forest fires). After a first stage of reciprocal habituation between the animals observed and their observers, each researcher on the team follows, each day, an animal and observes what they eat all day. Each detail is carefully noted, each species of plant inventoried, each bite recorded. The proximity is complete, the interest for the observed is unflagging. The scientific method requires that the animals be chosen randomly, in order to constitute a random sample. But this random choice can turn out to be disastrous, for many reasons. The procedure therefore requires going through a series of steps. As such, the second step is designed “to identify animals within the group that can be monitored uninterruptedly from a very close distance. While alternating movement within the group and close monitoring, the observers look for individuals which seem indifferent to their permanent presence. The full-time presence of an observer automatically changes the social status of an individual. This is why, at the beginning of this step, the individuals to be sought should neither be a leader nor an aspirant leader. Here again, it is important to listen to the herder’s advice if he knows well the social hierarchy within his flock. At the end of this step, about 15–20% of the individuals are considered to meet the prerequisites for full-time close monitoring” (Agreil and Meuret 101–02). In this manner, for certain goats, Meuret explains, the fact of being the object of an intense interest 130 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 despret on the part of the human gives rise among them to forms of conduct such as that of wanting to supplant the others, to take their food, even of seeking fights. For others, being the object of a researcher’s attention will provoke the aggression of their companions, as if the observer’s interest conveyed a desire on the part of the goat to change its place in the hierarchy. And this introduces a famous disorder into the group. On the other hand, Meuret continues, we no longer really know what we are seeing: what a goat eats in natural conditions, or on the contrary, what a goat eats when it wants to show to others its superiority since, suddenly, it thinks that its status has changed. Of course, one could always translate the preceding into the shoddiest and most conventional version of the artefact: we influence that which we observe! But if this version seems shoddy to me, and if I oppose this somewhat lazy conclusion with which the systematic theories have pestered our ears, it is only because it reduces the problem to its simplest expression. Because it supposes, once again, that there would be an active, influencing observer, and a passive observed, whose sole activity would be to be influenced. Now, there are many signs that say otherwise, that say that this has to do with beings who negotiate the conditions of research, who mutually affect one another, who exchange judgments and opinions, who reciprocally modify one another and who know that they do it. Michel Meuret does not speculate on the fact that he influences the goats or the sheep that he observes, he actively asks them to take a position in relation to his proposals and he is in harmony with theirs.16 He expects, and he expects of the sheep and goats, that they respond to him, contest, and protest. And this implies something other than a simple reflexivity on the question of influence: it demands attention.17 The concern could be exclusively epistemological, and in fact it is epistemological, but not exclusively. Yes, it is a matter of not disturbing, of not creating an artefact, but there is also a quality of the relation, a concern for the comfort of the animal, a rightness of the relations that transpire as much in 131 the writings as in what he relates to me. Meuret explains, for example, that at the third step (we had remained a bit with the second) the candidates observed are abandoned if their attitude testifies to “the interest, the anxiety of a discomfort due to the close and constant presence of the observer.”18 Why is interest a bad motive, in this frame? Because the animal must be interested in other things besides the human being, it must continue to live its life as a goat or a sheep. The choice of the “good” animal is founded on a very simple conviction: the animal responds to her observer; and it is what her response indicates that will constitute the criteria permitting the continuation, or not, of the observation. A last remark from a researcher illustrates this in an even clearer manner: “ … a good sign to start an observation is when an animal pushes you because you are in the way of what it covets: this says that it is capable of demonstrating that you are bothering it.”19 You want to practice habituation and be certain not to disturb the animals? The solution, as simple as it is, took time to emerge: all you have to do is ask them. disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author. notes Translated from Vinciane Despret, Penser comme un rat © Editions Quae, Versailles, 2009, 8–15, 28–45. 1 Certainly, the investigation conducted in Berlin in 1904 about the case of the famous clever Hans, the horse who knew how to count, could be considered as the start of the critical elucidation of the effect of human expectations on an animal. However, the point of focus of the research, oriented toward the human factor and heavily laden with the mechanism typical of the emerging behaviorism, minimized the point of view that the horse could have on the situation. To put it in terms that will emphasize my process, the horse, thinking like a rat in the perspective adopted, did not “respond” to the expectations but “reacted” to them. On this subject see Despret, Hans. 2 One finds an account of his research in Rosenthal, Experimenter Effects. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 3 The analysis of Rosenthal’s research is contained in the following chapter of Despret’s book, but is not included in this excerpt. [Translator’s note.] 4 The French term dispositif has an important specificity that has caused difficulties in prior translation and in capturing the range of meanings that it covers (including technical, military, legal, and ontological/arrangement dimensions). The term is at once an everyday, general term for referring to machines and devices of all kinds (such as cameras and pencil sharpeners but also airplanes) and it is a philosophical concept that has been drawn upon by Gilles Deleuze, Michel Foucault, Louis Althusser, Giorgio Agamben and many others. Owing to the technical connotations of the term, it has often been rendered as “apparatus” in English, but this presents a major problem since the French term appareil, much more closely related to “apparatus,” is used as distinct from dispositif by the thinkers mentioned. Owing to the specificity of the concepts, there is an increasing use of the English term “dispositive” to capture dispositif and the distinctions from appareil. Timothy Armstrong’s earlier translation of Deleuze’s famous essay on Foucault’s use of the concept uses “social apparatus” to distinguish it from “apparatus” and to emphasize the social and assembling dimensions. These social and assembling dimensions are particularly important to Despret’s use of the concept in the philosophy of science and ethology. See Gilles Deleuze, “Qu’est-ce qu’un dispositif?” in Michel Foucault philosophe (Paris: Seuil, 1989), Giorgio Agamben, Che cos’è un dispositivo? (Rome: Nottetempo, 2006), and Jeffrey Bussolini, “What is a Dispositive?,” Foucault Studies 10 (2010): 85–107. [Translator’s note.] 5 Since then, the possibility of discriminating between subjects really under hypnosis and subjects simulating it has been able to be staged experimentally. Thus, for example, a hypnotized subject can be convinced that he no longer knows how to read. “Not being able to read” seems impossible to simulate: when we know how to read, in normal conditions, the letters make sense in a fashion that cannot be ignored; we can no longer “not know how to read.” If one presents subjects with an image representing the word “blue” written in yellow, the non-hypnotized subjects will show a latency time when one asks them the color of the letters, the meaning “blue” interfering with the answer “yellow”; the subjects under hypnosis, for their part, do not demonstrate this latent delay. 6 Parker, “Obedience.” For an analysis of the question of the authority of the scientist, and the way in which subjects actively take account of what is asked of them, to which the present text remains, across the years, profoundly indebted, I refer to Isabelle Stengers, Invention of Modern Science. 7 Watson, “Kinaesthetic and Organic Sensations” 2–3; cited in the wonderful little book by the English historian Jonathan Burt, Rat (103). 8 For a more extended analysis of what this type of experiment does to the experimenter, see Vinciane Despret, Quand le loup habitera avec l’agneau. 9 We find elsewhere, in an article by Isabelle Veissier and Bjorn Forkman, a very clear critique on the ties between different types of defining well-being (and therefore of testing it experimentally) and the different philosophical conceptions that preside over each of these definitions. 10 I would like to thank my philosophy colleagues at the University of Liège, and particularly Julien Piéron and Stéphane Galetic, whose attentive interest, commentaries, and discussions helped me greatly in analyzing the work of von Uexküll. 11 I have referred to this article before in terms of the illumination of the little red light (the models should permit more control): I try here to continue along the lines of interest opened up. Waiblinger 197 for what follows. 12 François Calatayud asks whether it really makes sense to present “to different individuals conditions that one imagines to be equivalent in order to test a hypothesis regarding an average individual.” The notion of meaning, he explains, is incompatible with an average individual, and this is the case, the author continues, even if one is able to bring forward two beings who have “the same usage of the world.” Text from the conference “From natural behavior to the discourse of ethology: Reflections on the place of subjectivity in ethology,” presented at the colloquium organized by Florence Burgat, Comment penser le comportement animal (How to Think Animal Behavior), 132 despret EHESS, Paris, 21–22 Jan. 2008. Burgat, Comment penser le comportement animal. 13 In this regard, see the work of Michel Meuret. In addition, Meuret agreed to take part in a long interview with me in June 2008 in which we were able to raise many of the questions that gave rise to this research. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 14 In the same interview with Michel Meuret. 15 This humor of the situation appeared to me most clearly in following the work of the consultant clinicians already mentioned (Hellal). Far be it for me to compare animals and humans, but the institutional structures and the type of intelligence that they can give rise to are important. These clinicians based their work on the fact that the teams of social workers confronted with multiple cases of distress, and who frequently work with the same family, but in ignorance of what their colleagues are doing, must learn to follow the decompartmentalizations that the families who call them present to them. 16 One recognizes, under this formulation in terms of “propositions,” the mark of the work of Bruno Latour, notably in The Politics of Nature. 17 The animal professionals of the Theix Center emphasize that the term “attention” largely overflows the dimension of “well-being.” “Paying attention” is to take care of, but it is also “to mind,” that is to say to pay attention to someone and not to ignore possible disagreement. For example, “paying attention, they say, is to put limits on what one does but also on what the animal does (‘a just environment’ they also say).” This dimension of attention insists on the fact that all research is intrinsically founded on collaboration, whether or not one ignores it, but they do not ignore it and say that they are not able to forget it. 18 Meuret interview with Despret, 2008. Burgat, Florence, ed. Comment penser le comportement animal. Contribution à une critique du réductionisme. Paris: EHESS/Quae, 2010. Print. Burt, Jonathan. Rat. London: Reaktion, 2006. Print. Dantzer, Robert. “Comment les recherches sur la biologie du bien-être animal sont-elles construites?” Les Animaux d’élevage ont-ils droit au bien-être? Ed. Florence Burgat and Robert Dantzer. Paris: INRA, 2006. 85–103. Print. Despret, Vinciane. Hans, le cheval qui savait compter. Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond, 2004. Print. Despret, Vinciane. Quand le loup habitera avec l’agneau. Paris: Les Empêcheurs de penser en rond, 2002. Print. Haraway, Donna. Simians, Cyborgs, and Women. New York: Routledge, 1991. Print. Hellal, Selma. De proche en proche. Proximité et travail de réseau en Algérie. Algiers: Barzakh, 2008. Print. Latour, Bruno. The Politics of Nature. Trans. Catherine Porter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 2004. Print. Latour, Bruno. Politique de la nature. Paris: La Découverte, 1999. Print. Orne, M.T. “On the Social Psychology of the Psychological Experiment: With Particular Reference to Demand Characteristics and their Implications.” American Psychiatrist 17.11 (1962): 776–83. Print. Orne, M.T., and C.H. Holland. “On the Ecological Validity of Laboratory Deception.” International Journal of Psychiatry 6.4 (1968): 282–93. Print. Parker, Ian. “Obedience.” Granta 71.70 (2000): 101–25. Print. Rosenthal, Robert. Experimenter Effects in Behavioral Research. New York: Appleton, 1966. Print. 19 Meuret interview. Stengers, Isabelle. The Invention of Modern Science. Trans. Daniel W. Smith. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2000. Print. bibliography Agreil, Cyril, and Michel Meuret. “An Improved Method for Quantifying Intake Rate and Digestive Behaviour of Ruminants in Diverse and Variable Habitats Using Direct Observation.” Small Ruminant Research 54.1 (2004): 99–113. Print. 133 Stengers, Isabelle. L’Invention des sciences modernes. Paris: La Découverte, 2000. Print. Sullivan, Robert. Rats: A Year with New York’s Most Unwanted Inhabitants. London: Granta, 2005. Print. thinking like a rat Uexküll, Jakob von. A Foray into the Worlds of Animals and Humans. Trans. Joseph D. O’Neill. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2010. Print. Uexküll, Jakob von. Mondes animaux et monde humain. Trans. P. Muller. Paris: Denoël, 1965. Print. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:23 21 November 2015 Uexküll, Jakob von. “A Stroll through the Worlds of Animals and Men: A Picture Book of Invisible Worlds.” Instinctive Behavior: The Development of a Modern Concept. Ed. Claire H. Schiller. New York: International UP, 1957. 5–80. Print. Veissier, Isabelle, and Bjorn Forkman. “The Nature of Animal Welfare Science.” Annual Review of Biomedical Sciences 10 (2008): T15–26. Print. Waiblinger, Susan, et al. “Assessing the Human– Animal Relationship in Farmed Species: A Critical Review.” Applied Animal Behaviour Science 101.3–4 (2006): 185–242. Print. Watson, John B. “Kinaesthetic and Organic Sensations: Their Role in the Reactions of the White Rat to the Maze.” Psychological Review: Monograph Supplements 8.2 (1907): i–101. Web. Vinciane Despret Philosophie et Lettres Université de Liège 4000 Liège Belgium E-mail: [email protected] Jeffrey Bussolini Sociology – Anthropology Department City University of New York 2800 Victory Boulevard Staten Island, NY 10314 USA E-mail: [email protected] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:49 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:49 21 November 2015 ANGELAKI journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:52 21 November 2015 translator’s foreword In many ways, Despret’s publication of Que diraient les animaux, si … on leur posait les bonnes questions? (2012) represents the epitome of her style and approach to philosophical ethology. Witty, irreverent, and always surprising, the twenty-six chapters of this abecedary playfully question many of our popular and scientific understandings of animal behaviour. Whether it is “D for Delinquency,” “G for Genius,” or “Y for YouTube,” these chapters open with seemingly innocent anecdotes of animal behaviour – in the field, in laboratories, on television, and so on – and proceed to show that so many of our implicit understandings about animals, their habits, and cultures are subject to re-questioning. Despret covers such stories as how elephants learn to paint in Thai sanctuaries, how vervet monkeys enjoy an alcoholic beverage or two, and what might happen when one urinates in front of baboons. Many of these stories have been internet or newspaper fodder (“Animals Have Sex in Public!”), not to mention the subject of countless scientific studies; but with Despret, these stories lose any sense of familiarity as she recasts the players as intentional agents who, despite our attempts, show just how unfamiliar and wonderfully surprising the world actually is. And yet, within the midst of this re-enchantment of our multispecies worlds, animals are familiar, have individuality, personality, intelligence. As an abecedary, every letter from A to Z, like each and every animal and species, makes a case for the importance of the seemingly insignificant. Not unlike a mosaic, every story throughout the book’s chapters depicts a world in miniature, where humans vinciane despret translated by brett buchanan ANIMAL ABECEDARY “o for œuvres” and “q for queer” and animals co-exist, at times knowingly and innocently, at others ignorantly and questionably, but always, without a doubt, meaningfully. In these two selections – “O for Œuvres” and “Q for Queer” – Despret takes two different bird species (the bowerbird and the king penguin) as her muses in order to look more closely at the notions of art and sexual identity. In the case of the bowerbird, how and why do their spectacular mating arches count as “art,” or not? What is it that “art” does, and how might the bowerbirds’ “art” produce a new agency, not only in their prospective mate but in us, the observers? In the case of the penguins, why should it be surprising that the natural/cultural worlds of animals are ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020137-11 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039852 137 animal abecedary full of rich, complex, and shifting sexual identities? How might we reconsider the all-toooften implicit political agendas involved in biological observations, classifications, and ontological constructions? The worlds of animals are far more instructive and interesting than we tend to admit. o for œuvres1 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:52 21 November 2015 do birds make art? C an animals create works of art? The question is not far off from the one that asks whether animals can be artists. To test this, at least speculatively, raises again the question of intention, which in principle should preside over any work. Must there be an “intention” in order to make a work, and, if there must, is it the intention of the artist that determines, or not, whether she is the author of the work? Introducing animals into the posing of this problem has the merit of making us hesitate and slow down. Bruno Latour has made us sensitive to these hesitations by proposing a reconsideration of the distribution of action in terms of “making” [ faire-faire].2 It is worth considering the splendid arches of the pink-naped bowerbirds, which are much more interesting than they at first seem for the fact that these birds have re-appropriated, for the sake of their own works, some of our artefacts and put them to use in their compositions. If one pays attention to the work accomplished – one merely has to enter the name of the bowerbird in any search engine – one can see, thanks to the camera work of biologists, that there is nothing accidental about the composition; it is all organized to create an illusion of perspective. According to the biologists, it is all staged to make the bowerbird dancing in his arch appear larger than he actually is. We are therefore dealing with a scene, a staging [une mise en scène], and a truly multimodal artistic composition: a sophisticated architecture, an aesthetic balance, a creation of illusions designed to produce effects, and a choreography that concludes the work. In short, what the philosopher É tienne Souriau would likely have recognized as a poetry of movement. This skilfully orchestrated illusion of perspective refers us to how he proposed to make sense of simulacra. They are, he writes, “sites of speculation on meaning” that indicate that one can no longer clearly have in nature the capacity for making being out of nothing, in the desire of the other. Making being out of nothing in the desire of the other: is this a work in the sense that we understand the bird to be the true artist and author? I am temporarily leaving to the side the sterile and boring debates that attempt to reduce the animal to instinct, and that, in order to provide an account of the work accomplished, provide us with explanations of the causally deterministic and biological kind. It is also worth noting, just in passing, that in terms of these kinds of explanations, sociobiologists have similarly tried to apply them to humans: every action and every accomplishment describes nothing more than a program to which one is genetically bound and whose goal is to better perpetuate one’s genes. I leave it up to the reader to describe this in more carefully chosen terms. The fact that these explanations are in such bad taste and so impoverishing ought to prevent us from using them with non-humans who have already been so abused by theory!3 On the other hand, I could take up the way that the question is posed by Alfred Gell, the anthropologist of art, when he asked it not about animals but about artistic productions in cultures that do not consider their productions artistic (Art and Agency). Gell’s problem is the following, albeit summarized a bit quickly: if one considers art to be what is received and acknowledged as such by the institutionalized world of art, then how should one consider productions from other societies that we consider as artistic whereas these societies do not themselves accord the same value to the objects? To not do so, as has been the practice for so long, would return the others to a status of primitives expressing their primary needs in spontaneous and childlike ways. To do it anyways, as Gell explains, obliges the anthropologist who is studying the creation of objects in other cultures to impose on these 138 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:52 21 November 2015 despret cultures a completely ethnocentric frame of reference. Indeed, if one considers that some of the objects do not have any aesthetic value either for the ones who produce them or for whom they are made, then the solution that consists in placing each production in the cultural framework of the one designating the rules and criteria of aesthetic taste does not solve the problem. Put more simply, a shield, for example, is not art for “them” but for “us.” How to escape this impasse? Gell proposes that the problem be redefined. Anthropology is the study of social relations; one must also therefore consider studying the production of objects within these relations. In order to avoid falling back into the impasses that I have just recounted, however, the objects themselves ought to be considered as social agents endowed with the characteristics that we give to them. Gell, therefore, attempts to take the question of intentionality out of the narrow framework in which our concept has confined it, and instead open up the notion of the agent – as a “being endowed with intentionality” – to others besides human beings. A decorated shield, to take up again the problem of carried objects, has for us an aesthetic value, but it doesn’t have this value in the context of a battle in which it is used. It elicits fear, or fascinates, or captivates the enemy. It signifies nothing, and symbolizes nothing; it acts and reacts, it affects and transforms. It is, therefore, an agent, a mediator of other agencies [agentivités]. The concept of agency (which the French translator of Gell’s Art and Agency translates as “intentionality” [intentionnalité]) is therefore no longer posed as a way of classifying beings (those who would be ontological agents, endowed with intentionality, and those who would be ontological patients, devoid of intentionality). Agency (or intentionality) is relational, variable, and always inscribed within a context. The work not only fascinates, captivates, enchants, and traps the recipient; rather, it is the agency contained within the very material of the work to be made that controls the artist, who thus takes the position of patient. If I understand Gell in Latour’s terms, the work makes 139 happen [ fait-faire]; the shield makes the artist make (the artist is made-to-make by the shield), it makes the one using it (for example, it can make one more daring in battle), and it makes the enemy warrior (for example, be fascinated, scared, captivated by it).4 In our relations to works, Gell says, we are quite similar to how the anthropologist Edward Burnett Tylor described the indigenous peoples of the Antilles: they claimed that it was the trees that called to the sorcerers and gave to them an order to sculpt their trunks in the form of an idol. By distributing intentionality in this manner, Gell agrees in a certain way with what Souriau proposed, albeit with much more speculative prudence. According to the latter, the work imposes itself on the artist, or if I were to use Gell’s terminology, “it is the work that is the agent,” it is the work’s intentions that are insisted on, and it is the artist who is the patient. Nevertheless, if I now want to ask about the possibility of art among animals, and to do so seriously, I must abandon Gell and align myself with Souriau. For even if Gell clearly redistributes intentionality and agency, he reduces the redistribution, despite a few worthy attempts, to a relation between the work and its recipient. He writes, “Anthropologists have long recognized that social relationships, to endure over time, have to be founded on ‘unfinished business’. The essence of exchange, as a binding social force, is the delay, or lag, between transactions which, if the exchange relation is to endure, should never result in perfect reciprocation, but always in some renewed, residual, imbalance.” He continues, “So it is with [decorative] patterns; they slow perception down, or even halt it, so that the decorated object is never fully possessed at all, but is always in the process of becoming possessed. This, I argue, sets up a biographical relation – an unfinished exchange – between the decorated index [which means the “work” object as carrier of intentions] and the recipient” (Gell 80–81). In short, the speculative leap that distributes the intentions between the work and artist is not carried through to its end, for Gell clearly hesitates to make Antilleans of Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:52 21 November 2015 animal abecedary us, a sorcerer of the artist, and a summoning agent of the work. This question is posed entirely differently by Souriau when he evokes, in his 1956 paper “From Modes of Existence to the Work to be Made,” and in terms that appear to be similar, the existential incompleteness of everything.5 But the incompleteness of the work, for Souriau, is not found between the work and its recipient, but rather between the work to be made [l’œuvre à faire] and the one who will devote him or herself to the work, the one who “must respond to it,” the one held responsible. Works to be made are real beings, but whose existences demand promotion on other planes. They are deficient in existence, if only because they only benefit from a physical existence. A work, in other words, calls for its fulfilment on another mode of existence. Can we return to the problem of animal artists with what has been proposed here? Souriau anticipated this question with his book The Artistic Sense of Animals.6 From the very first pages he evokes the sense that his response will take: “Is it really blasphemous to think that art has cosmic foundations and that one can find in nature the same great instaurating [instaurateurs] powers?” The term “instaurating” is not chosen by accident. Souriau did not use “creator” or “constructor” (even if he at times considers these terms as equivalent, we are still well before the arrival of constructivism, so “construct” is not yet a loaded term). Instaurating means something else.7 The work, as we’ve just seen, calls for its accomplishment on another mode of existence. This accomplishment requires an instaurating act. In this sense, if one can say that the creator carries out [opère] the creation, the being of the work nevertheless exists before the artist has made it. However, this being could not have made itself by itself. “To instaurate is to follow a path. We determine the being to come by following its path,” he writes. “The being in bloom,” he continues, “reclaims its proper existence. In all of this, the agent has to bend to the work’s own will, to divine its will, to abdicate himself for the sake of this autonomous being that he is seeking to promote according to its own right to existence.” To say that the work of art is instaurated, then, is neither to attribute causality somewhere else nor to deny it. It is to insist on the fact that the artist is not the cause of the work, and that the work alone is not its own cause; the artist carries responsibility, the responsibility of one who hosts, who collects, who prepares, who explores the form of the work. In other words, the artist is responsible in the sense that he must learn to respond to the work, and to respond to his accomplishment or his failure to accomplish such work. If we return, then, to our question, can we imagine speaking about natural beings as masters of a work? To be sure, when Souriau engages with this question in his book on the artistic sense of animals, he seems to hide at times behind a form of vitalism that is particularly noticeable in the commentaries that accompany the images: “Life is the artist, the peacock is the work.” For that matter, however, in returning to the birds one discovers this surprising proposition beside a photo showing a zebra finch in the process of making its nest: “The call of the work.” Here, quite clearly, it is no longer a matter of an abstract nature but rather of an instaurating being, responding (as the one responsible) to the challenging demand of accomplishing a work. Beneath this title, Souriau explains that “often the nest is made by two of them, and its preparation is essential to sexual courtship. But occasionally a celibate male will begin this work alone.” A female could join him and help, he says, and it is in this sense that the nest is a work of love, or rather, as he corrects himself, “a creator of love: the work mediates.” Invoking love the way he does makes me want to prolong it. The work really has the power to captivate those who carry out its accomplishment. It is thus a completely different theory of instinct that we are invited to consider. It is a theory of instinct that, far from mechanizing the animal and returning it to biological 140 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:52 21 November 2015 despret determinism, instead offers, in a speculative mode, much more fruitful analogies. Let us return for a moment to the nests of the bowerbirds that I raised earlier and take up again the question where it was left off, somewhat entangled between instinct and intentionality. I am not responding to the question of knowing whether or not these birds are artists, for it is no longer here that the problem interests me. If I were to go back over one of Gell’s examples, namely that of the shield, then by following the analogy one could maintain that these nests are objects that captivate, transform, and produce beings that fall in love, or that they enamour, fascinate, and have an effect on them. But if I follow the path opened by Souriau, and interest myself not in the relation with the recipient but instead with what deploys the instaurating act of the nest, then I could also suggest that the pink-naped bowerbirds are well and truly captivated by the work to be made, and that it is really this that dictates the work’s need to exist. “This must be.” Of course, our preferences tend to instead favour the idea that a work can only be made by someone, that the work is less dispersed, for this is how we consider art, in a kind of exceptional status. It is without doubt this lack of exceptionality that justifies the cumbersome recourse to the argument: if everyone can do it, it must be instinct. It’s true that for these birds the making of this work is tied to vital questions, since the making-of-the-work [le faire-œuvre] is for each bird the condition of its preservation. Without the work there will be no descendants who themselves will make future works. But do not confuse a condition of preservation with a condition of existence, and do not confuse what the work makes possible with its motive. Or, at any rate, abandon the concept of instinct, but guard preciously what it makes us feel, what feels like a force in the face of which being must bend – like we sometimes do in the face of love. No matter what utilitarian aim we might impart to these works, we know that birds do not have this utilitarian aim in mind (the motives are always identifiable a posteriori, a convenient rationalization that, from a biological point of 141 view wherein everything is pertinent, is not what one might say matters). What instinct both affirms and masks is the call of the thing to be made. That some things are beyond us. The captivation known to some artists. That this must be made. Period. q for queer are penguins coming out of the closet? Queer: strange; odd. Slightly ill. Usage: the word queer was first used to mean “homosexual” in the early 20th century … In recent years, however, many gay people have taken the word queer and deliberately used it in place of gay or homosexual, in an attempt, by using the word positively, to deprive it of its negative power. New Oxford American Dictionary 1387 Between 1915 and 1930 a group of penguins lived at Edinburgh Zoo. Over the course of these years a troop of zoologists meticulously and patiently observed them, beginning by naming each and every one of them. But first, before receiving their names, each of the penguins was placed within sexual categories: on the basis of a couple, some were called Andrew, Charles, Eric, and so on, while others were christened Bertha, Ann, Caroline, etc. As the years passed, however, and the observations accumulated, more and more troubling facts seemed likely to sow disorder within this beautiful story. To begin with, one had to face the facts, as the categorizations were based on a rather simplistic assumption: certain couples were not formed by a male penguin and a female “penguine,” but from among all penguins. The permutations of identity – on the part of the human observers, not the birds – had a Shakespearean complexity to them. In addition to this, the penguins themselves decided to put their own stamp on things and make things even more complicated by changing their couplings. After seven years of peaceful observations, it was therefore realized that all but one of the attributions were wrong! A complete overhaul of the names was thus carried out: Andrew was re-christened as Ann, Bertha Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:52 21 November 2015 animal abecedary turned into Bertrand, Caroline became Charles, Eric metamorphosed into Erica, and Dora remained Dora. Eric and Dora, who spent their days peacefully together, were now called Erica and Dora, while Bertha and Caroline, who were known for some time to be homosexual, were from now on known as Bertrand and Charles. These observations, however, were not going to damage the image of nature. Homosexuality remained a rare phenomenon in the animal world and these penguins were probably just a few pathological cases observed here and there on farms and in zoos, and thus assumed to be due to conditions of captivity – which fell into perfect agreement with human psychopathological theories that equated homosexuality with mental sickness. Homosexuality was definitely unnatural, as nature could testify. But it seems that, in the 1980s, nature had a change of heart. Homosexual behaviours were now everywhere. One was probably supposed to imagine, during these same years, disastrous consequences from the queer revolution and the American gay movements that would contaminate innocent creatures. But the question should no doubt be posed differently: why hadn’t homosexuality been seen in nature until this point? In the book Biological Exuberance, Bruce Bagemihl considers a number of hypotheses following his long investigation in reporting on species that had recently come out of the closet.8 To begin with, he says, homosexuality wasn’t seen because nobody expected to see it. There wasn’t a single theory available to meet the facts. Homosexual behaviour appeared to be a paradox of evolution since, in principle, homosexual animals did not transmit their genetic heritage. This stems in fact from a very narrow conception of sexuality, on the one hand, and of homosexuality, on the other. For the former, animals only mate due to the goal of reproduction. The strictest god would have succeeded in obtaining from animals a virtue that he had not been able to with any of his faithful humans. Animals don’t do a thing except if it is useful for their survival and reproduction. For the latter, homosexual animals would be exclusively oriented towards partners of the same sex and, in this respect, would be proof of a strict orthodoxy. Next, for those who observed behaviours oriented towards a partner of the same sex, a functionalist explanation could justify them perfectly well, and it had the merit of removing this behaviour from the sphere of sexuality. When I was a student, we learned in an ethology course that when an ape presents his or her genitalia to another and allows him- or herself to be “mounted” – I also heard this said of cows – it has nothing sexual about it; it is just a way of affirming dominance or submission, depending on the position adopted. Lastly, another reason that has had considerable influence is the fact that researchers have only observed but a few homosexual behaviours in nature because they are so rarely seen. Not that they are rare, but that we don’t see them. Just like we rarely observe heterosexual behaviour, because animals, who are very vulnerable in these moments, generally do it in hiding so as not to be seen, and especially so from humans who are seen as potential predators. And since we see newborns emerge every year, nobody has ever doubted that animals have a sexuality, even if it is only seen on rare occasions. But rare does not mean “not at all,” and this concerns homosexual behaviour as well. How is it that this has remained unmentioned for so long in research studies? The primatologist Linda Wolfe queried her colleagues on this subject at the end of the 1980s (Wolfe cited in Bagemihl). On the condition of remaining anonymous, many of them admitted that they had seen such behaviour, with males just as much as with females, but they were afraid of homophobic reactions and of being seen as homosexuals themselves. In light of these reasons, therefore, one can legitimately think that the queer revolution changed things. It opened the idea that forms of conduct that were not strictly speaking heterosexual could exist, and it encouraged researchers to look for them and speak about them. Hundreds of species now participate in this revolution, from dolphins to baboons, as well as macaques, Tasmanian geese, Mexican 142 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:52 21 November 2015 despret jays, gulls, insects and, of course, the famous bonobos. At the same time, animal sexuality benefited from what I would call their “cultural revolution.” After having been excluded, animals can now claim to be within the order of culture. They have artisanal traditions (for tools or weapons); fashionable songs (with whales, for instance); practices of hunting, eating, medications, and dialects that are specific to groups from now on christened as “cultural”; and practices that are acquired, transmitted, abandoned, or undergo waves of inventions and reinventions. As such, sexuality is now a candidate, and this includes its homosexual dimensions. It also carries the mark of cultural acquisition. The ways that acts are performed – for example, among female Japanese macaques – demonstrate these differences: some practices appear to be more popular within some troops, and they evolve over time, with some inventions tending to supplant other ways of doing things. Some “traditions,” or models of sexual activity, can be invented and transmitted across a network of social interactions, moving between and within groups and populations, geographies and generations. According to Bagemihl, sexual innovations in a non-reproductive context have contributed to the development of other significant events from the point of view of cultural evolution, most notably in the development of communication and language, as well as in the creation of taboos and social rituals. Among bonobos, twenty-five sign-language signs have been found to indicate an invitation, a desired position, etc. These signs can be transparent and their meaning immediately decipherable, but some of them are more codified and require that the partner already knows them in order to understand them. The gesture of inviting a partner to return, for example, is in one group executed by making one’s hand turn in towards itself. Their opacity and stylization invite one to think that there are abstract symbols here. The order of the gestures, which is equally important, leads to the hypothesis that animals may be able to use syntax. In terms of the organization of relationships, they seem to be marked by complex codes. 143 According to Bagemihl, rules guiding how to avoid others are, with certain species, relatively different if it consists of hetero- vs. homosexual relations; what seems to be not permitted with one sort of partner might be permitted with another. To focus on the diversity of these practices, as Bagemihl does, is an explicitly political issue, and one with many positions. On the one hand, this diversity takes sexuality out of the natural domain so as to situate it within a cultural one. It’s an important issue, and one that constitutes a choice. It is not just a case of removing homosexuality from the sphere of mental pathologies or from legal domains – in some US states it still continues, as we will see. Bagemihl will refuse the hand stretched out to him, the allies who could have strategically helped to depathologize and decriminalize homosexuality. In the outstretched hand there is this simple proposition: if homosexuality is natural, it is therefore neither pathological nor criminal. The argument for its unnaturalness has also been used during a trial by a judge from Georgia – in the Bowers v. Hardwick case. Caught in the act of homosexual relations, Hardwick was sentenced, and the unnaturalness of the act was used among the arguments justifying the accusation. Naturalizing homosexuality could take care of a lot of things. For Bagemihl, even if homosexuality is natural, it cannot be figured into the equation “What is natural is right.” Nature does not tell us what ought to be from what is. It can feed our imaginations, but not compel our actions. It is worth noting, in passing, the irony of this story. Despite this refusal, Bagemihl’s book will be invoked, in 2003, during a trial that featured the Texas court system vs. two homosexuals, Lawrence and his partner, who were caught in bed together by the police following a report of night-time disturbance of the peace. On the grounds of the previously mentioned judgment, that of the Bowers v. Hardwick case, they were prosecuted for homosexuality. The Texas judges, however, refused to follow the case law set by the precedent judgment, and refuted, on the basis of Bagemihl’s book, among other reasons, the Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:52 21 November 2015 animal abecedary argument of naturalness.9 At the end of the trial, the anti-sodomy law was considered to be anti-constitutional.10 The author of Biological Exuberance had another, less theoretical, reason for refusing to record homosexuality as a fact of nature. Bagemihl is not only homosexual. He is queer. To quote him, what interests him is “the world as ‘incorrigibly plural’ … It suffers difference, honoring the ‘anomalous’ and the ‘irregular’ without reducing them to something familiar or ‘manageable’” (Bagemihl 262).11 The meaning of being queer cannot be better defined. It is a political will. And this political will does not only concern humans. It concerns the world around us. It concerns our ways of entering into relations with this world and, among these relations, of knowing and practising this knowledge. Bagemihl measures the risks of accepting whether or not homosexuality is natural. It seems to be the object of biologists to try and resolve this paradox, and he knows very well which biologists are already on the case: it’s the sociobiologists. They have, in effect, buckled down with an insatiable appetite for this new problem: it’s another case that will come to illustrate and expand their theory. It will be even more “all-encompassing” [toutterrain]; the world will be sociobiologized.12 For the theory of kinship has a solution entirely found in homosexuality, though it rests on a strict conception of an orthodox homosexuality. Of course, homosexuals do not transmit their genes to their descendants, so normally they ought to disappear due to a lack of descendants carrying this gene – it goes without saying, homosexuality is genetic. Homosexuals, however, direct their attentions and their abundant leisure time (because they don’t have any dependants) towards their nephews, who are carriers of an identical part of the genetic heritage. It is therefore through these latter descendants that the gene continues to assure its propagation. This type of biology is political, not only in the sense for which we usually reproach it – these theories can easily be retranslated into misogynistic, racist, eugenic, capitalistic, etc. theories – but in the sense that, to put it simply, these theories animalize, insult, and impoverish those for whom they pretend to take account. In other words, sociobiological theory – to recall the words of the psychologist Françoise Sironi – is an abusive theory. Every behaviour is reduced to a genetic purée; beings become blind imbeciles determined by laws that escape them – and that prove to be disturbingly simple. No more inventions, no more diversity, no more imagination – and yet, if they still persist, it’s because they have been selected in order to allow us to spread our genes. One cannot be both queer and a sociobiologist. But can we really say that animals are “truly” homosexual, in the same sense as we can be? Bagemihl responds: but can we say this even of ourselves? Can we name, under the same term, the same realities, from the amorous youth of ancient Greece to the most diverse modes of being today? And can we say that, among animals, the entire range of forms of relations that organize between the same sex are “truly” the same? It’s here that I find the coherence of Bagemihl’s project. Biology must respond to the diversity and exuberance of nature and beings; it must rise to the level of what is required of it. This reflects the bias of what he says about the scientific task: multiply the facts in order to allow a chance at multiplying interpretations. This is far from the “allencompassing” theories; the diversity of things will fertilize the diversity of interpretations. This is what he elsewhere calls “doing justice to the facts.” Nature is invited to a political project. A queer project. It teaches us nothing about who we are or on what we ought to do. But it can feed our imagination and open our appetites for the plurality of usages and modes of being and existing. It never stops recombining categories and re-creating, from the multidimensionality of each and every one of them, new modes of identity. What is meant by being male or female, for example, can be found among many animals according to inventive modes that are similar to a multiplicity of ways of inhabiting a gender. One can find among certain birds – and sometimes even 144 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:52 21 November 2015 despret among members of the same species – two characteristic situations: on the one hand, one can find females living an entire life as a couple, making a nest together each year, incubating eggs that one of the females has fertilized in mating with a male, manifesting regular courtship behaviour towards one another, and yet never showing any mating behaviour. On the other hand, one can find a male mating all his life with the same female, with whom he mates regularly and raises the young, but who, on the occasion, mates with a male (and never does so again). How do you categorize this? Are these relations homosexual? Bisexual? Are these birds consistently female or male? Are these even good categories to take account of what they’re doing and of who they are? I recognize here a project that I was able to find in the writings of Sironi, based on her work with transsexual and transgendered people. The queer project that she supports roots itself within questions of sexual and gender identity, but its political aim is first of all tied to a practice that obliges us to think and that calls for thought. These two approaches, however, aim to transform habits, transform relations to norms, to oneself and others, and to open possibilities. So if this clinician’s will is to learn, along with those who address themselves to her, how to help them fight against the “abusive theory” that her colleagues exercise against them, to “free gender from its normative shackles,” and to support “its amazing creative vitality,” she relies just as much on them – those who are the experts of metamorphosis – to help us to think and imagine different “contemporary identity constructions” (Sironi 14–15). “Transidentitary and transgender subjects have a function, currently, in the modern world … Their function is to enable becomings, to show diverse expressions of multiplicity in itself and in the world” (229–30). To deterritorialize, to open up to new agencements of desire, to cultivate an appetite for metamorphoses, and to forge multiple affiliations. 145 disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author. notes Translated from Vinciane Despret, Que diraient les animaux, si … on leur posait les bonnes questions? (Paris: La Découverte 2012) 160–68, 180–90. An English translation of this book is forthcoming with University of Minnesota Press, and we gratefully acknowledge their permission to publish these pages in this issue of Angelaki. Copyright by the Regents of the University of Minnesota. 1 The word “œuvre” is sufficiently well known in English to remain untranslated in this chapter heading, but throughout this chapter I have translated it as “work” (e.g., a work of art), but it also carries the slightly different connotation of “accomplishment” (e.g., accomplishing a task). In some contexts, then, I have translated œuvre in the latter sense. [Translator’s note.] 2 Latour, Reassembling the Social 58. Latour’s notion of “faire faire” is part of a longer expression, “making someone do something” (“faire faire quelque chose à quelqu’un”). Like the French word “faire,” “make” has a number of connotations that include creating and producing as well as forcing and causing. “Fait-faire,” as Despret employs it, shares in all of these subtleties. [Translator’s note.] 3 The notion of “theoretical mistreatment” is drawn from Françoise Sironi’s work on transgender clinics. Drawing an analogy between what happens to humans and what happens to beasts is always perilous, however, in so far as what she describes deals with situations and shrinks who “theorize” those who come to them (and must also aid the individuals looking to undergo their transformation), and discredit them with their suspicious and insulting theories, and thus contribute to their suffering, the analogy can still hold without being insulting. These bewildering theories (théories abêtissantes) have concrete effects on animals, whether they are direct (e.g., in laboratories) or indirect, by legitimating thoughtless treatment (e.g., that they are, after all, only beasts, and not geniuses). The adventure of this Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:52 21 November 2015 animal abecedary political clinic that “makes one think” is a highly interesting read. Sironi, Psychologie(s) des transsexuels et des transgenres. virulent homophobes, Luiz Solimeo, refers to it, which leaves me with little doubt of its existence. See <www.tfp.org>. 4 The various usages of “fait-faire” in this sentence all play upon the notion of the shield’s “agency,” as in making something happen, making others do something, putting something into action. [Translator’s note.] 10 The arguments that led to the decriminalization of homosexuality following the Lawrence affair can be found at <www.bulk.resourece.org>. 5 The 1956 presentation that I refer to, as well as the introductory theories, can be found in the recently republished Souriau, Les Différents Modes d’existence. The co-authored preface by Bruno Latour and Isabelle Stengers is important – even essential. Their preface guides the reading, which is at times difficult, and it raises the speculative air that accompanies the adventure of its discovery; it is what first drew me to the issues raised by Souriau. 6 This little marvel of a book remains perfectly current, and it is from this book that the different examples of animals are drawn. It has been a profound inspiration in the writing of this chapter. 11 The idea of the world as “incorrigibly plural” is cited by Bagemihl from Louis MacNeice’s poem “Snow.” [Translator’s note.] 12 “Tout-terrain” is a term that Despret borrows from the writings of Isabelle Stengers to mean an idea (or concept, theory, dispositif, etc.) that attempts to conquer and handle every field. It is translated here as either “allpurpose” or “all-encompassing,” though it might be better thought of as the “philosophical equivalent of a military all-terrain Jeep,” as Bruno Latour puts it in his essay “What is Given in Experience?” (http://www.bruno-latour.fr/sites/ default/files/93-STENGERS-GB.pdf). [Translator’s note.] 7 In the encyclopedic reference Aesthetic Vocabulary, edited by Étienne Souriau with Anne Souriau, “instauration” is defined in part as “Establishment, foundation (of an institution, a temple). A formal definition, which underlies the notions of duration and stability. However, the Latin sense of instaurare and instauratio implies the idea of a new beginning, in order to bring to reality what had not been able to previously. Indeed, the idea of instauration implies a dynamic, active experience that finds its completion in an existence. Instauration tends toward a work” (Souriau with Souriau, Vocabulaire d’esthétique). [Translator’s note.] bibliography 8 The example of the Edinburgh Zoo penguins is drawn from this book. Latour, Bruno. “What is Given in Experience? A Review of Isabelle Stengers’ Penser avec Whitehead.” Boundary 2 32.1 (2005): 222–37. Print. 9 This notwithstanding, there is no mention of any reference to Bagemihl’s book; it is, however, confirmed by other sources: at the request of the court, the American Psychiatric Association (APA) was called upon during the trial to act as an amici curiae (“friend of the court”), a form of general council of experts for a given problem. Reference to Bagemihl’s book is included in the legal notice as potentially putting into doubt the unnaturalness of homosexuality. I have not had access to this amici curiae, but one of the most Bagemihl, Bruce. Biological Exuberance: Animal Homosexuality and Natural Diversity. London: Profile, 1999. Print. Despret, Vinciane. Que diraient les animaux, si … on leur posait les bonnes questions? Paris: La Découverte, 2012. Print. Gell, Alfred. Art and Agency: An Anthropological Theory. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1989. Print. Latour, Bruno. Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network Theory. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2005. Print. MacNeice, Louis. “Snow.” Collected Poems. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1966. 30. Print. McKean, Erin, ed. New Oxford American Dictionary. 2nd ed. New York: Oxford UP, 2005. Print. Sironi, Françoise. Psychologie(s) des transsexuels et des transgenres. Paris: Jacob, 2011. Print. Souriau, Étienne. Le Sens artistique des animaux. Paris: Hachette, 1965. Print. 146 despret Souriau, Étienne. Les Différents Modes d’existence. Paris: PUF, 2009. Print. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:52 21 November 2015 Souriau, Étienne, with Anne Souriau, eds. Vocabulaire d’esthétique. Paris: PUF, 1990. Print. Vinciane Despret Philosophie et Lettres Université de Liège 4000 Liège Belgium E-mail: [email protected] Brett Buchanan Department of Philosophy School of the Environment Laurentian University 935 Ramsey Lake Road Sudbury Ontario P3E 2C6 Canada E-mail: [email protected] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:53 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:53 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:54 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:54 21 November 2015 ANGELAKI journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:55 21 November 2015 translator’s foreword Vinciane Despret is a psychologist and philosopher at the University of Liège, but, as she herself might insist, “let us not go too fast” (“The Body We Care For” 128). Always circling back, swift to question and complicate, Despret can be counted on to meticulously sift through whatever is deemed true, neutral, or objective, particularly in the field of ethology. Products of habit and power are not safe in her hands. Her terrain is how we create, cocreate, and re-create our lives, identities, and bodies, as seen through the wide viewfinder of our tales and texts about nature, culture, animals, and science. In this, she seems to don a third hat, that of a literary critic – and here she credits the profound influence of novelist Michel Tournier (on whom she wrote her thesis).1 Despret is fascinated by how we report on relationships – on the different narratives that are told and might be told about the seemingly same event. This burden infuses all of her work: “to judge among all the versions not which is the most true (that is indeterminable) but, in line with James’ pragmatism, which is the most interesting, the most fecund – the one that adds to the world, opens more deliberations, and makes us think and imagine.”2 She often refuses to take sides, claiming of her disparate sources: “They need one another.”3 No respecter of disciplinary limits, species borders, nodes of prestige, impact factor, preexisting truths and facts, or Western science’s exclusive authority, she instead seeks out unanticipated communicatory modes and dialogic mixes – highlow, inout, natureculture. Despret’s reach and popularity as a Belgian vinciane despret translated by hollis taylor WE ARE NOT SO STUPID … ANIMALS NEITHER and French intellectual thus extend well beyond her formal citation index. For instance, Saturday and Sunday mornings, we can tune in to her radio show on Bon week-end, which is aired on Radio Télévision Belge Francophone.4 Her five-minute segment is entitled “We are not so stupid … Animals neither,” which is appended with: “One finds plenty of evidence of it and sometimes even contradictory evidence.”5 The Saturday programme finds Despret presenting half-page vignettes sent to her by listeners – true stories involving a pet or perhaps an animal someone randomly encountered. She reads these to us as she might a bedtime story, vocalizing animal sounds as required and presenting them without comment. They ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020153-9 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039855 153 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:55 21 November 2015 we are not so stupid … are memorable readings of memorable accounts. On Sundays, she shifts to a more scientific perspective, although without leaving behind her penchant for narrativity and wonder. Focusing both on ethologists who study animal behaviour in natural environments and cognitive psychologists who question animals in laboratories, Despret mulls over their discoveries and probes their methodologies. Do animals have a face – or better still, do animals give us a face? Could mice be having fun during experiments? Who is the star of Darwin’s selection theory? These and many other questions intrigue her and, through her skill as a presenter, captivate us. She excels in delivering quick, rapid summaries of complicated issues, which she describes as “an exercise in style that I like.”6 The compilation below of recent Sunday programmes finds her sleuthing theory construction, legal status, taxonomic classification, research conditions, and capacities vis-à-vis dogs, horses, humans, cassowary, dinosaurs, sheep, and tortoises. Does this culminate in radio listeners who are progressing in their understanding of animals (including humans)? “Maybe yes, a little,” she responded, “but it’s hard to say things are changing. We cannot know whether we are ‘with’ change or ‘in’ change … All that can be said is that we accompany transformations.”7 chronicle of sunday, december 22, 2013 L ast October, the Sunday Times headlined an article: “Dogs Are People, Too.”8 By the way, I thank my student at ULB, Thibault De Meyer, who regularly sends me references to fascinating articles, sometimes accompanied with a comment that pinpoints exactly where it is “good to think.” Let’s go back to our dogs, who supposedly are people like any other. The article was written by American neuroscientist Gregory Berns. He reports how for two years he and his colleagues trained dogs to agree to go in an MRI scanner without the need to anaesthetize or restrain them. “Our goal has been to determine how dogs’ brains work, and even more important,” he writes, “what they think of us humans.” Now, he concludes, after training and scanning a dozen dogs, he has arrived at an inescapable conclusion: dogs are people. However, it is the manner in which dogs have become people that interests me most. You’ll see. “Because dogs can’t speak,” says Gregory Berns, “scientists have relied on behavioural observations to infer what dogs are thinking. It is a tricky business. You can’t ask a dog why he does something. And you certainly can’t ask him how he feels.” Besides, speaking of emotions in animals frightens many scientists, and most have preferred to put this question aside as scientifically unanswerable. “Until now,” says Gregory Berns. “By looking directly at their brains and bypassing the constraints of behaviourism, MRIs can tell us about dogs’ internal states.” However, magnetic resonance image-taking procedures are cumbersome: they make noise, it’s a bit frightening, and you must remain absolutely still. Animals had to be anaesthetized so they could get through it. But you can’t study the feelings of an anaesthetized animal. And so, from the beginning, these scientists treated dogs as people. First, they did as is done when people are asked to participate in an experiment: they are asked to sign a consent form (sometimes called an Informed Consent Form). They thus adopted a consent form typically used for children, not because dogs are children but because, as with children, the form must be signed by the person responsible – in this case, the dog’s owner. The form stipulates that participation is entirely voluntary and that a dog has the right to leave the experiment whenever their owner wishes. Then, scientists used “only positive training methods. No sedation. No restraints. If the dogs didn’t want to be in the MRI scanner, they could leave. Same as any human volunteer.” “My dog Callie,” says Gregory Berns again, “was the first. Rescued from a shelter, Callie was a skinny black terrier mix, what is called a 154 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:55 21 November 2015 despret feist in the southern Appalachians, from where she came.” I looked feist up in the dictionary; it has no translation, but feisty means spirited, so I think we can work out the character of this little dog. And in fact, true to her roots, this little dog “preferred hunting squirrels and rabbits in the backyard to curling up in my lap. She had a natural inquisitiveness, which probably landed her in the shelter in the first place, but also made training a breeze.” With the help of a dog trainer, Mark Spivak, “we started teaching Callie to go into an MRI simulator that I built in my living room.” She learned to go in, place her head on a pillow, and stay still for periods of up to thirty seconds. She also learned to wear earmuffs to protect her sensitive hearing from the frightening noise the scanner makes. “After months of training … we were rewarded with the first maps of brain activity: [her] brain response to two hand signals [as well as] which parts of her brain distinguished the scents of familiar and unfamiliar dogs and humans.” Once they published their results, Berns explains, “the local dog community learned of our quest to determine what dogs are thinking. Within a year, we had assembled a team of a dozen dogs who were all ‘MRI-certified.’” For now, Berns says, “[a]lthough we are just beginning to answer basic questions about the canine brain, we cannot ignore the striking similarity between dogs and humans in both the structure and function of a key brain region: the caudate nucleus.” In humans, the caudate, rich in dopamine, “plays a key role in the anticipation of things we enjoy, like food, love and money.” Of course, in light of the incredible complexity of relations among interconnected brain regions, cognitive or emotional function cannot be assigned to a single region. However, the caudate nucleus is quite consistent: one sees it noticeably activated each time we are involved in an activity that we enjoy, indicating quite clearly “our preferences for food, music and even beauty.” When will we have dogs review our shows and exhibitions? And why not? I like the idea of stretching the limits of how we define beauty and broadening our wealth of diverse opinions 155 by adding to them those of our non-human companions! We will return next week. chronicle of sunday, december 29, 2013 We saw last week that scientists have succeeded in teaching dogs to surrender voluntarily to an MRI scan so that the electrical activity of their brain may be measured, and these scientists have begun to contemplate reading “what they think” with the assistance of magnetic resonance imaging. I highlighted an important finding: that of the similar role and function of the central caudate nucleus, which seems to play the same role in humans and dogs. With us, one sees this centre activated when we are confronted with pleasurable situations: a piece of music that we appreciate, a painting, food, and love. In dogs, we noted that this centre is activated when we make a hand signal to indicate food. It is also activated when the dog smells the scent of a familiar human. In the first tests, we saw it activated when their master, who was out of the room, reappeared. Do these results prove that dogs love us? We cannot confirm that in this way. However, we can nonetheless say that many things that activate the caudate nucleus in humans, which indicate positive emotions, also do so in dogs. This is what is called in neuroscience a “functional homology,” which says something about dogs’ emotions. The ability to experience positive emotions like love and attachment shows that dogs possess a level of sensitivity similar to that of human children. And, says Gregory Berns, the author of this research, this should lead us to rethink the way we treat dogs. They have long been considered as property, as things. I will note in passing that some European states have changed their laws and now consider animals as non-things, which is already progress. “But now,” says Berns, “by using the MRI to push away the limitations of behaviourism, we can no longer hide from the evidence. Dogs, Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:55 21 November 2015 we are not so stupid … and probably many other animals (especially our closest primate relatives), seem to have emotions just like us. And this means we must reconsider their treatment as property. One alternative is a sort of limited personhood for animals that show neurobiological evidence of positive emotions. Many rescue groups already use the label of ‘guardian’ to describe human caregivers, binding the human to his ward with an implicit responsibility to care for her. Failure to act as a good guardian runs the risk of having the dog placed elsewhere.” Given that the law provides no legal basis for this guardianship, it is difficult to intervene based on this concept in order to protect an animal. For Berns, we must go a step further and give dogs the rights of personhood. But, he says, “I suspect that society is many years away from considering dogs as persons.” Dogs are not people. However, he suggests, even if they have nothing to do with dogs, two recent rulings by the United States Supreme Court “have included neuroscientific findings that open the door to such a possibility.” In both cases, “the court ruled that juvenile offenders could not be sentenced to life imprisonment without the possibility of parole. As part of the rulings, the court cited brain-imaging evidence that the human brain was not mature in adolescence.” And so, says Berns, “[a]lthough this case has nothing to do with dog sentience, the justices opened the door for neuroscience in the courtroom.” And we can therefore hope that one day someone will defend a dog’s right based on its brain images! chronicle of sunday, january 12, 2014 Two weeks ago, therefore last year, I presented a chronicle about dogs and thanked my student at ULB, Thibault De Meyer, who regularly sends me references to fascinating articles, sometimes accompanied with a comment that pinpoints exactly where it is “good to think.” Not only does this mention allow me to publicly express my gratitude but it enables me to underline what we have already discussed in a previous chronicle about bees, the fact that science is a collaborative practice (in the case of bees, there were children in a primary school who had led an experiment to understand how bees locate flowers from which to gather nectar) and that this collaboration can extend far beyond the laboratory proper. The work I am going to talk about today is again brought to my attention by him, but more importantly it is accompanied by a reflection that I will read at the end: his remarks are fascinating and expand our perspective. Today, we will talk about horses and riders, from a recent article by three researchers – three ethnographers – Anita Maurstad, Dona Davis, and Sarah Cowles, who interviewed sixty riders in Norway and the US Midwest. In the abstract preceding the article, the three researchers write that the stories the riders told them described how the horses, like the riders, were changed in the course of their relationship. To account for these changes, the authors employ the term proposed by American physicist Karen Barad: that of “intra-action” (323). Intra-acting refers to the fact that in a relationship each partner is changed in the encounter, or even comes to exist in a different mode than before the meeting: in this perspective, partners – those that are and those that could be – do not pre-date the relationship. They become what they are in an encounter. One becomes a rider in a tangible engagement with a horse, in a tangible commitment to this meeting, and one becomes a horse with a rider during the same encounter. We sense this from the first lines of the article: not only do the riders talk about their horses as subjects – as beings with their own will – and not as objects with which they would engage in activities, but, more importantly, they show that training together constitutes part of a practice where beings “become comprehensible to each other” (325). Thus, “horse–human communication crosses the species divide” (326). When a rider tells the researchers that she must reassure the horse about the fact that birds and moose do not eat 156 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:55 21 November 2015 despret horses, she is in the process of perceiving the world as a horse perceives it, and things and beings no longer have the same meaning. Similarly, many riders explain how it is essential to modify their body movements because they know that certain movements are difficult for a horse to interpret, and that they must constantly pay attention not only to what each gesture may mean to the horse but also to what a gesture may signify that could prompt the horse to consider, “hey, there, my rider is talking to me and telling me something”: “sitting straight, head resting on the body, being balanced” (326), ensuring that every movement will be received by the horse, etc. “Every muscle twitch of the rider will be like a loud symphony to the horse” (326, citing Hearne 108). Humans learn to play softer and softer symphonies as they progress in developing their riding talent, learning to make sense via their own body movements, and to attune to and understand the feel of a horse’s body (326). And the horse does the same, adjusting and coordinating what it transmits and what it perceives. The horse speaks differently with humans than it does with its conspecific companions. And the riders say their body acquires a different language, which they say is evident even in their relationship with other humans, with whom they become more attentive to body language on account of what they have learned with their horse. In other words, these riders are, with their horse, constantly trying to develop a shared language, a bodily language. They call this a “third language,” one that is co-created by horse and human (326). It is around this third language that Thibault De Meyer made a most interesting remark to me, which accompanied the article: “Implicitly,” he writes, “one can read here at what point to anthropomorphize a horse is to zoomorphize a rider (as in isopraxism). One finds this feature, in particular, in the concept that the riders themselves mobilize: the ‘third language,’ the invention of a new language which is neither the rider’s nor the horse’s, but an undefined meeting point. The language is the result of a relationship; it is only with 157 the construction of modern national languages that language became a prerequisite to relationships. What if animals were simply teaching us to resist nationalism and other empires?” chronicle of sunday, january 19, 2014 I would suggest that today we do a bit of anthropology and talk about an amazing animal, the cassowary. In fact, listeners who regularly follow this programme must be aware that I have become increasingly interested in nonscientific knowledge, or even the fact that nonscientific aspects are increasingly invoked in science: primary school children publish their scientific experiments; a researcher conducts fascinating research on his own dog; to know about horses, we question their riders, etc. This means that the sacrosanct separation between scientific knowledge, academic knowledge, and that of amateur experts is less and less clear-cut – and the fact that we invite our listeners to tell stories is part of this movement: what can we learn about animals from those who live with them? However, this separation between scientific knowledge and pre-scientific knowledge has long (since the nineteenth century) been the rule. This separation between objective knowledge (conducted under very specific rules) and a more empirical knowledge (said to be stained by subjectivity) falls under the rubric of what sociologist Bruno Latour calls the “Great Divide.” Latour borrowed that term from anthropologist Jack Goody, who was referring to “anthropologists’ persistent (if not congenital) tendency to divide up human societies, types of knowledge, and, more importantly, systems of thought into two classes, each separate and distinct one from the other. He [Goody] lists as an example some of the classifications drawn since the nineteenth century: primitive/ civilized, traditional/modern, pre-logical/ logical, scientific/pre-scientific” (Journet 40). This approach resulted in our considering Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:55 21 November 2015 we are not so stupid … other cultures’ knowledge in an entirely different way from how we view our own. Latour takes up the work of the anthropologist Bulmer, who notes and wonders why for the Karam the cassowary is not a bird. First of all, this question is based on an unexamined conviction, since it supposes that to think that the cassowary, a large feathered biped that does not fly, is not a bird would be a deviation from the normal and natural trajectory that would make the cassowary a bird. And one notes that this position is so unambiguous to Bulmer that he only inquires about the contingency of Karam classifications when they differ from ours: those that are the same as ours require no explanation. Taxa are only subject to investigation when, and it is Bulmer who stresses this, “objective biological facts no longer dominate the scene” (“Why is the Cassowary Not a Bird?” 6). Since the reasons behind the confusion of the cassowary must be unravelled, Bulmer analyses how the Karam invoke a complicated story of cross-cousins that justifies how the cassowary, “a bird by nature,” finds itself in the taxon of “kobtiy,” of which it is the sole representative (5). “Happy Englishmen!” exclaims Latour. “No one ever arrived on their shores to investigate by what quirk they placed cassowaries in the taxon of birds” (“Comment redistribuer” 211). No cultural explanation is necessary to account for “objective facts.” But the cassowary – is it a bird? Well, it all depends on how the classifications are constructed. And if one follows closely how such taxa are formulated, one comes to realize that even the category “birds” could be problematic. I propose, given the complexity of the problem, to take this up again next week. chronicle of sunday, january 26, 2014 Last week, we saw on the question of animal classifications in the example of the cassowary (a large feathered biped that does not fly) that these classifications could depend, even in our world run by scientific knowledge, on the culture and selections of those who categorize. Reality does not impose itself by waving a magic wand, but instead each of these classifications is the subject of discussions, debates, hesitations, and stories. Adrian Desmond, in his book on warm-blooded dinosaurs, provides exemplary material for understanding how classifications can be constructed in such a way. In one of the book’s chapters Desmond asks why, for some palaeontologists, Archaeopteryx is a bird and not a dinosaur. Obviously, for Desmond Archaeopteryx is not a bird. In fact, while Archaeopteryx indeed has feathers, it is quite incapable of flying (and so the cassowary would not have, after all, much reason to be a bird either) – all the more so since Archaeopteryx closely resembles a dinosaur and would probably be considered one beyond doubt if we had not found fossil feathers. However, for those palaeontologists who hold to the idea that dinosaurs are cold-blooded, the presence of feathers excludes Archaeopteryx from the class of dinosaurs. There are nonetheless proponents of the idea that there have been warmblooded dinosaurs. And if that is the case, Archaeopteryx can very well be one of those. It does not fly; its feathers do not make it a bird. But what purpose do they serve, then? In fact, Archaeopteryx solved the problem of warm-blooded dinosaurs, that is to say, the problem of maintaining a constant body temperature – of how to ensure thermoregulation. Either one becomes very large, increasing in volume and thus reducing heat loss, or natural selection favours another means, allowing the dinosaur to stay small and occupy a distinctive ecological niche: it lies in growing feathers on the forelimbs. With these feathered forelimbs, Archaeopteryx could not only ensure its thermoregulation by having a protective layer but also by waving its limbs; this enabled it to snare flying insects, its feathered arms serving as a net. And in the long run, by dint of beating its wings, Archaeopteryx (therefore no longer Archaeopteryx) became a flying animal. The problem of pre-adaptation is solved: we wondered how birds got wings if they could not help them fly when they first emerged; this 158 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:55 21 November 2015 despret issue is resolved: the wings are a response to the problem of thermoregulation; wings only became a flying device later. However, if Archaeopteryx is a warm-blooded dinosaur, then it means that the divisions no longer hold between mammals and birds but between mammals and dinosaurs, of which birds would be the living representatives. Isn’t this in the end an interesting perspective? Not only did dinosaurs not go extinct (they merely underwent a crisis at the end of the Cretaceous 65 million years ago), but, what is more, some have become very good musicians. So, let’s take good care of them, and if you would, put small balls of fat and seeds in your gardens so that dinosaurs remain a while longer among us. But if you go to your seed merchant, and you order food or shelters and tell them that it is for the preservation of dinosaurs, do not be surprised if he looks at you strangely and asks if you listen to a radio show called Bon weekend on Radio Cro-Magnon. chronicle of sunday, february 2, 2014 We spoke last week about dinosaurs and the change of status that was imposed on certain animals. Today, we are again going to speak about change of status and descendants of dinosaurs.9 So, let’s talk about reptiles. For listeners who have followed us since the beginning of this chronicle, one could say that reptiles are undergoing a revolution similar to that of sheep when primatologist Thelma Rowell observed them. Once we thought to ask questions that allowed them to show of what they are capable, sheep demonstrated much more complex and intelligent behaviours than scientists had previously believed. Note in passing that this revolution continues with the work of Michel Meuret, who had the good idea to query shepherds, who show us the extent to which sheep are inventive and socially sophisticated creatures. But let’s go back to our sheep of today, reptiles. For a long time, reptiles have been, in comparative intelligence studies, ranked last. Few 159 scientists were keen to see what was going on in their heads, and those who tried came back with results confirming that there was nothing to expect from them; they were relatively stupid, primitive, some kind of instinctive machines without hearts, and, above all – more scientifically – without a hippocampus: in short, cold-blooded animals are rough drafts of what was to come after them in the triumphal march of evolution. We diverged from them 280 million years ago, with good reason. But in recent years, other researchers have decided to give reptiles a chance. It was discovered that lizards are capable of solving complex puzzles, that they adapt to novel situations, and that they can teach us about the evolution of cognitive abilities, including the fact that some skills are much older than previously thought, or – an alternative hypothesis – that these emerged on several occasions during the course of evolution. I’m going to focus on the research of an English researcher in cognitive psychology, Anna Wilkinson, and her red-footed tortoise, named Moses (MuellerPaul et al.). She asked her tortoise to navigate in an eight-armed radial maze around a central area, which formed a kind of cartwheel. At the end of each arm was a strawberry. The tortoise only got one chance in each arm to retrieve the strawberry; the tortoise couldn’t return to where it had previously been. He had to memorize each of the arms that he had already passed. In the first experiment, the walls of each arm were lined with a curtain with different cut-out shapes pinned to it. One notes that the tortoise relied on these cues (which he memorized) to remember where he had already passed. If the curtains were removed, he would find himself in difficulty. Indeed. Except that the tortoise came up with another strategy: in this case, he understood that he had to follow, in order, the arm adjacent to the one he had just visited. And he succeeded. The tortoise thus demonstrated what is called behavioural flexibility, reflecting the fact that he was capable of adapting to new environments and inventing new strategies to deal with different events. Hence, reptiles are capable of innovation. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:55 21 November 2015 we are not so stupid … Why had this not been seen before? For the simple reason that researchers had hitherto used the equipment employed for mammals and birds, which is not at all suited to reptiles. And furthermore, to shorten the learning curve, they had used a method also employed with rodents: bright lights or strident sounds associated with events to mark the memory of experimental subjects. But with reptiles these sounds and lights are totally counter-productive; they paralyse them and put them in a kind of cataleptic state. Moreover, they were asked to accomplish impossible tasks: reptiles never use their paws to manipulate objects, unlike rodents and other mammals that can be asked to open boxes or unpack things. So, reptiles were constantly confronted with impossible tasks. And finally, being cold-blooded animals, reptiles are very sensitive to temperature; they need warmth. If rats can feel comfortable with a laboratory’s twenty degrees, reptiles need higher temperatures; they learn considerably less well in lower temperatures. Either researchers imposed their norms on reptiles and obtained poor results, or they had to adapt to the norms of their subjects, which was very uncomfortable and discouraged many. With these new studies, one can conclude (along with one of the researchers) that intelligence is probably much better distributed than we imagined. By taking some of the tests devised for animals known to be intelligent, and adapting them to other species, we discover that so-called “intelligent” animals are ultimately not that unique! disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author. notes 1 E-mail to author, 16 Jan. 2015. 2 Ibid. 3 Ibid. 4 “On n’est pas si bêtes … Les Animaux non plus” is a feature La Première on RTBF, the public broadcasting organization of French-speaking Belgium. See <http://www.rtbf.be/lapremiere/emissions_ bon-week-end?programId=312> (accessed 5 Jan. 2015). This translation fails to take into account the title’s double entendre, since bêtes can refer not just to stupidity but also to beasts. “Not as beastly as you may think” and “Far from stupid” are just two alternative translations of something best read in the original French, where we are left to confront the supposed synonyms animal and stupid. 5 “Ethology is a fabulous story,” begins the programme’s Facebook page, acting as a sort of mission statement (https://www.facebook.com/pa ges/On-nest-pas-si-bêtes/858670957485128). The most recent programmes are available for podcast, and the website is replete with compelling images of animals. 6 E-mail to author, 9 Jan. 2015. 7 Ibid. 8 All quotes from Berns below are from this unpaginated article. 9 And I wish to again thank the tireless and generous researcher Thibault De Meyer, who sent me the article I’m going to talk about today and who fully understands its significance. bibliography Berns, Gregory. “Dogs Are People, Too.” The New York Times 5 Oct. 2013. Web. 6 Jan. 2015. <http://www.nytimes.com/2013/10/06/opinion/sun day/dogs-are-people-too.html>. Bulmer, Ralph. “Why is the Cassowary Not a Bird? A Problem of Zoological Taxonomy among the Karam of the New Guinea Highlands.” Man 2.1 (1967): 5–25. Print. Desmond, Adrian J. The Hot-Blooded Dinosaurs: A Revolution in Palaeontology. New York: Dial/James Wade, 1976. Print. Despret, Vinciane. “The Body We Care For: Figures of Anthropo-zoo-genesis.” Body and Society 10.2–3 (2004): 111–34. Print. Hearne, Vicki. Adam’s Task: Calling Animals by Name. New York: Skyhorse, 1986. Print. 160 despret Journet, Nicolas. “De l’oral à l’écrit: Rencontre avec Jack Goody.” Sciences humaines 83 (1998): 38–41. Print. Latour, Bruno. “Comment redistribuer le grand partage?” Revue de Synthèse 3.110 (1983): 203– 36. Print. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:55 21 November 2015 Maurstad, Anita, Dona Davis, and Sarah Cowles. “Co-being and Intra-Action in Horse–Human Relationships: A Multi-Species Ethnography of Be(com)ing Human and Be(com)ing Horse.” Social Anthropology 21.3 (2013): 322–35. Print. Mueller-Paul, Julia, Anna Wilkinson, Geoffrey Hall, and Ludwig Huber. “Radial-Arm-Maze Behavior of the Red-Footed Tortoise (Geochelone carbonaria).” Journal of Comparative Psychology 126.3 (2012): 305–17. Print. Vinciane Despret Philosophie et Lettres Université de Liège 4000 Liège Belgium E-mail: [email protected] Hollis Taylor University of Technology, Sydney CB10.05.113 PO Box 123 Broadway, NSW 2007 Australia E-mail: [email protected] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 ANGELAKI journal of the theoretical humanities volume 20 number 2 june 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 Brett Buchanan: As a philosopher, what drew you to ethology and the study of animal behaviour? Vinciane Despret: I was trained in philosophy, but I studied psychology because I wanted to be a clinician; with a philosophical diploma it was very hard to find a job in Belgium, as they don’t teach philosophy in high school. And so I began to study psychology and the most interesting courses I had were not the clinical courses but the courses in ethology and animal psychology. Back at that time, the reason I really liked ethology was that it was always surprising. I wouldn’t say that ethologists tried to surprise us but they shared their own surprise. They were always surprised by the animals they were discovering, which is maybe an important word because “discovering” was exactly what was happening. Psychology was just keeping on the same track with the same ideas, but in ethology everything was new, even if it was not a new science. It was a new science compared to others and ethologists were discovering so many things; they were always surprised by these things because they did not expect the animals to do what they did. Or we didn’t understand why they seemed so strange. Why we expected one thing but they were doing something else. And they might look idiotic but if you understand correctly they’re not idiotic at all. They have good reasons for what they do, and they see the world differently. That’s the first thing: you know, remember the beginning of philosophy, “thaumazein,” to be surprised, to be curious. And I think that being a philosopher maybe influenced me so that I could be so sensitive to that question. The question of surprise. The question of risk. The question of translation. The question of not being in a brett buchanan matthew chrulew jeffrey bussolini ON ASKING THE RIGHT QUESTIONS an interview with vinciane despret 1 routine. Because that’s exactly the game philosophers should – or do – play when they are good. Not playing the game. What does Deleuze say about philosophy? He says it’s “a throw of the dice.” So maybe I was prepared for that because I was a philosopher. The second reason is more anecdotal. Ethologists tell wonderful stories. Ethology is a story of stories. Even a history of stories. Because you have living animals, who have lives, who do things. They risk their life, they reproduce, they have babies. They take care of their babies. They meet someone, they have friends (and another being becomes “someone”), sometimes they enjoy living … And these are all stories – beautiful stories. The best drama is written by animals, I think, and I think that it ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/15/020165-14 © 2015 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2015.1039821 165 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 on asking the right questions was a good choice for ethology to choose stories, not only because it’s pedagogical but because it always obliges and requests from us to remember that we are dealing with a living being, a subject with their own experience. And the third reason was a question of translation. I loved the problem translation raised. Ethologists were, I think, really keen, intelligent and imaginative translators because they were confronting not just another language but totally, radically, different types of languages. So there was an opening up of worlds and discovering that scientists can be surprised and that surprise constitutes, maybe … their mode of being. I am thinking here about the ethology of ethologists, in the sense Deleuze gives to the word ethology, as that of a practical study of modes of being, that is to say, the practical study of what humans or animals can do; not of what they are, of their essence, but of what they’re capable, of what they’re doing, of the powers that are theirs, of the tests that they undergo. That is what makes an ethologist a good ethologist. I would say that if an ethologist is not able to be surprised, he’s not a real ethologist. There are multiple talents: to be a good observer, to be imaginative, but I think that first one is not only to be able to be surprised but even to seek to be surprised. BB: Was it the element of real surprise, then, and a love of good stories, that drew you into fieldwork in the beginning? VD: I am happy I did fieldwork because you learn that – you know, it’s very easy to dream about what fieldwork is. A lot of people dream about fieldwork. “Ah, it’s observing animals!” But most of the time they don’t do anything. Thelma Rowell says that with baboons there’s always something happening, but with sheep, for example, you can stay there and wait for hours before they decide to begin a conversation. It was important for me to learn that fieldwork is spending a long time doing nothing except observing, taking notes, and hoping that something happens and, after a few hours, hoping that they just go back home and that you can yourself go back home because it’s winter and you’re freezing to death. I think my ethology professor was right to make me do fieldwork, even if it might have nothing to do with what I was doing, because he also wanted me to learn how to observe and to learn to be modest. Otherwise, you have big dreams about what fieldwork is and you don’t understand what people really do. I think it’s important to see what they really do. Like Bruno Latour, whom I will discover later, says, you don’t learn something by just reading the papers, you learn by seeing what they do and doing it with them. Matthew Chrulew: What was it that you learned from Zahavi and the babblers? VD: I began with a theme of research for my Master’s degree by reading all this literature about altruistic birds. Mostly, if not almost totally, subtropical birds. I don’t know about now but at that time most thought that only subtropical birds were altruistic. Maybe there’s some ecological condition that favours the altruistic behaviour. But I also think that some ecological conditions favour why ethologists want to study some birds as opposed to others. I mean, my fieldwork would never be in the Arctic or something like that! [Laughter.] So I read all this literature and it’s then, the fact of knowing profoundly one little field of ethology, that I can say I became an amateur in Latour’s sense of the word, which means somebody who knows, who likes, but can have good taste about things. An amateur is the one who says – when you present him or her something or you read a text – says, [sniffs] “No, it’s not a good taste here. There’s no style here.” And studying these birds that were behaving altruistically really gave me an amateur taste for the practice of ethology. Because after the thesis I could discriminate more finely the criteria that make an ethologist interesting compared to another one who goes about business as usual, for example those for whom this bird could have been another bird and it wouldn’t change anything. I finally noticed that helpers of the nest were the most studied. Mobbing was also well documented. And I thought: why are these behaviours so privileged for researchers in altruism? I think that if we make this 166 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 buchanan, chrulew & bussolini hypothesis it’s because they are the most easily observed, because the nest is easy to observe. Mobbing is also easy to see because it’s spectacular. Thelma Rowell says something very interesting: if we have seen so much competition it’s because we were observing things that were easily observable, which means the way animals eat and act together, or where the food is concentrated or rare. But she says that most primatologists, for example, didn’t see cooperation in cases of predator attack because predators don’t attack where the observer is observing, if he practises habituation for example. So I think that altruism was mostly helping at the nest because that’s the way that’s easy to observe. I think the second reason it was so well studied was because of the dominance of sociobiology, which for all these reasons, if you observe certain comportement, it’s easier for this kind of theory to find proof. Anyway, in reading all this literature on altruism I noticed that after the surprise of the first five or six birds – Blue Jay, Florida Scrub Jay, Mexican Jay, and so on – they all were the same. They were all doing the same thing, for the same reason, in the same ways, with the same motive. And I noticed that finally after ten birds I was getting bored. And I was getting bored because it was always the same big story – there were no individuals, you know? It’s what we call in French the quiconque, anyone. But there were only two exceptions that I found: one was the dunnock in Great Britain, which were observed by two British sociobiologists, and the other was the Arabian babblers, studied by a certain Zahavi. The babblers were really different birds, and Zahavi was really contesting the main sociobiological theory. First, they have stories. They were all identified, and he gave a story of some of the birds in order to explain them. Zahavi never stopped saying “in principle,” but it was interesting because the “in principles” became, you know, “they are more flexible than that.” “Okay, we can say that in general, but they won’t follow you everywhere,” which means that he was attentive to the details and to the individuality of these birds, and I thought this was surprising for birds, because back to that time this was only 167 the story for primates. Having a name, having a biography, having a personal story, having experiences, building society, as Latour and Strum would say. So I was really interested in understanding why these babblers were so different from other birds, and I came up with two hypotheses. The first one would be that these birds are very different because they live in some ecological condition that is different – this is a surprise of nature. But the second hypothesis that I believed at that time was the hypothesis that was inspired by philosophies of science – mostly French – that were dealing with natural history in trying to find what was natural and what was political in each theory. And they were, for example, dealing with Spencer, Darwin, Kropotkin, and others. I was inspired by what I was reading in philosophy of science and I thought that maybe these babblers are so original because they’re observed by an ethologist who does not respect the rules. As a matter of fact, Zahavi was heavily anthropomorphic with the babblers, giving them motives, intentions, projects, strategic plans, and so on. So I thought we might have babblers that ultimately are the subject of over-interpretation. And that’s exactly why I wanted to go to the field, to see if babblers really were so different from other birds. MC: So you weren’t just observing the babblers, you were observing the scientists observing the babblers and Zahavi observing the babblers. VD: That’s what I wanted to do. But after five minutes you can’t do that anymore … It was nonsense to think that I was going to look at Zahavi while he’s observing babblers. [Laughter.] Remember what Latour said, with the proverb “when the sage points at the moon, the idiot looks at the fingers.” Observing Zahavi, I would have been exactly this kind of idiot. And it would not be polite because you don’t look at people like that all day long because it’s profoundly disturbing. [Laughter.] Zahavi thought that the only thing that was interesting in the field was the behaviour of the babblers, not him. And, of course, he was not interesting because he stays still. There’s nothing to observe. He wouldn’t have Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 on asking the right questions understood why I took so much of his time and asked for his help, only to observe him and not what was interesting to observe, the babblers. The babblers really were interesting, but they were all the more interesting because I was observing them with Zahavi. I don’t think that I would have been interested to stay hours and hours. I don’t have the patience of an ethologist. Nor the knowledge or expertise. You don’t see much while observing animals because you need stories to see things, you need stories that help you to collect things. I am not a real ethologist because I wouldn’t have the patience and I could not understand most of the things that happen. A little, sometimes, but not much. But it’s so interesting to hear somebody telling you: “I see this, and this will happen next, I can tell you already because did you notice that this happened, just before he did that?” These details all connect together and make a story. And this story helps you to predict what will happen and to be attentive to what will happen. Otherwise, you’ll miss it. Finally, I had the good fortune that other people were also in the field and were not seeing the same thing as Zahavi. They also asked lots of questions, and you begin to understand how, upon observation, a theory can be built – what counts as observation, what counts as details, what counts as a good interpretation. BB: How did this book come to be written? VD: I will tell you the truth about the babblers book. I came back from the field in Israel and decided to write an article. I had so much to say, I thought, I can’t write this article. So I wrote fifteen pages and sent it to a friend, and he says: “This is too boring. Nobody would read that.” I said, “Oh, good grief, what should I do?” And then I heard Isabelle Stengers on the radio. And when I heard her … good grief. This woman is really something. I didn’t know her personally, you know, just her name because she was already famous due to the Nobel Prize of Prigogine. So I bought her book, The Invention of Modern Science, and read it and thought: I’ve got it. The babblers. She is writing for the babblers – that’s exactly what I felt. Everything she says may apply to the babblers, so I have my stuff, my material. I know what I should do with all the data I collected. And now Robert Rosenthal makes sense. I had already read Rosenthal but I didn’t know what to do with it, but all of a sudden, after reading Stengers, I understood that of course Rosenthal is wrong and the babblers are right. They have the right to dance and to rightly do it. Then I read Bruno Latour’s Laboratory Life. So that’s the part of the babblers. And Hans was written in 2003. It was written very, very fast. But the main idea was about my surprise in discovering that all these stories that were trying to explain the “Hans” case were so different, as though several investigators had conducted an inquiry on this subject, but arrived at unbelievably different stories. That is what gave me the idea to deal with this book like a roman policiers, like a detective novel. At that time I had just read a very interesting book by Pierre Bayard, Qui a tué Roger Ackroyd? It’s such a funny story. He read Agatha Christie’s The Murder of Roger Ackroyd, and he claims she didn’t find the murderer at the end. That’s not him, that’s not possible. And he says: “No, no, no, no, no. She has been the dupe of Hercule Poirot. He was completely wrong and she believed him. I’m going to do a new inquiry. [Laughter.] Yes, I am going to do it all over again so that we read Christie’s book thinking this doesn’t work, this doesn’t work, this doesn’t work, and he found another murderer in that book. [Laughter.] I found the one who did it.” And it’s such an amusing and funny book. It’s really great because his analysis is premised on the idea that Christie breaks very important rules in that book. And so the idea behind my Hans book is exactly what Bayard was doing with Christie. I don’t accept Pfungst’s results. He’s wrong. I’m going to do it again. That was the idea, and everybody has noticed – I mean, good readers – noticed that the architecture of the book was the same architecture as the police novel. BB: A significant part of your writings is about asking the right kinds of questions about the 168 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 buchanan, chrulew & bussolini multispecies world around us. To me you don’t seem bound by existing theories or paradigms, you rather allow your curiosity and wonder to lead you. of events, signs to read, connections to make, and so on. Connectivity. VD: Maybe I had something that helped me a lot. I’ll refer back to my love of stories. I’ve always loved to read stories, to read novels, and to tell stories and to be told stories, and my mother told me stories, and my father loved to tell real stories that happened to him or to his friends. What I like in stories is how they make links between events that are not normally linked. If you tell a story, but you know how it ends from the very beginning, it might be a good story but you have to hope it takes an unpredictable path to arrive at the end if you already know the end. Otherwise there is no interest at all. So, I like to make links. One is always trying to reconnect all the elements of the world because they are totally disconnected. Like what Philippe Descola calls analogism. If you read Gombrowicz’s Cosmos, that’s exactly what he is doing. He’s trying to find connections between all the elements. Because for the narrator of Cosmos the world is in such chaos that he has to make all the connections and create links that make a little bit of order in that world. What is the relationship with a bird that has been hanged by someone? And a little piece of wood they discovered three days after that? Maybe there’s a connection between them. And what does it mean? And who did that? And so on. And it’s a completely different world. I loved this work of the imagination. Creating links is a thing that I can do. I don’t say that my links are good but I love to create stories and to create links between things. That’s why Leibniz interests me so much now, because it’s totally weird – a totally different way of creating links between events that he proposed with his “Monadology.” You can accept cause and effect, but it’s too simple for Leibniz because effects are only one part of the explanation. It’s the clearest part of the explanation. That’s also why I like Michel Tournier’s novel The Erl-King; that’s exactly the way he functions in it. Conspiracy, complicity VD: I don’t remember. I know that he came during my thesis because I read philosophers about emotion and I was really dissatisfied by what they were doing with emotion. This thesis was complicated because I was searching for different theories of emotion and new frames of analysis. The exception to the traditional psychological theories was anthropology – that was my discovery during my thesis because anthropology, and ethno-psychology of emotions, was a really flourishing, interesting, and new field. That was a great moment. And it was James that I focused on, because James was really critical about the way the sciences dealt with psychology and because his theory of emotions was really fascinating. James was, I think, the first one to give me the tools to begin to think the notion of “version,” and the notion, which is so important to me, of indetermination. The double fact. Don’t try to separate subjective experience and objective world. Don’t try to think that maybe dancing Arabian babblers are a subjective projection. If you say that, it’s because you made a choice and nothing can guarantee that your choice is right. So, it is just a choice to separate subjective experience and objective world. And James helps – he gives us tools to think this through. Not to bifurcate nature, like with, say, Whitehead. James gives us tools to help cultivate a site where different versions can coexist. This is the very definition of what I call a version, instead of vision. A version is when multiple stories can coexist; where they are compossible, Leibniz would say. With vision, if you say “Oh, this is your vision of the world,” it means that it’s a subjective experience and it cannot coexist really with mine, because this is your vision of the world, and I can say that you don’t have the truth. You just have an opinion. So, vision, for me, means the exclusion of other possible stories, whereas version, for me, is the word that defines the possibility of multiple hypotheses 169 MC: At what point did you begin reading William James? Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 on asking the right questions that can coexist. In Women Who Make a Fuss, my book co-written with Stengers, you will find a definition of “version” in English; it’s also in the Abécédaire under “Version.”2 Perhaps you saw on YouTube the crow that slips on an icy roof with a little disk of some sort, like a Frisbee? She takes it in her beak, puts it on the top of the roof, and slides on the snowy roof with the Frisbee, then takes it back and goes back on the top of the roof and does it again and again. It’s really funny to see. If you see that, you can think she’s playing. But an anthropologist who studies animals might reproach the animalist and say: “these fantasists, connectivists, they say that this crow is playing, but no, she’s just trying to know if it’s eatable.” I was thinking about that and I think that we have a good story for the version. If it’s the case that the sceptic is right, you exclude the hypothesis that she’s playing. Okay? So, eating is the only hypothesis that can be kept, and you can’t say anything else. Animals are animals. They are only a stomach with fur. You know, they just think about eating, that’s the only important thing animals do in their lives. Reproducing and eating. But if you say that she’s playing, you don’t exclude the fact that maybe at first she believed that it was food, she tries to eat it, she slips, and discovers that you can do something else with food or non-food than eating, and she just enjoys it – a beautiful article by Nathan Emery and Nicola Clayton has recently commented on this video and claimed that birds like to have fun (“Do Birds Have the Capacity for Fun?”). This is the same with conditioning. If you say that you learn by association and you say association is enough and it’s not higher competencies, you exclude everything. If you say higher competencies, you don’t exclude association because association may take part in the learning of higher competencies. You see what I mean? And for me James gives really good tools not only to help make versions coexist but to prevent us from excluding too prematurely a hypothesis that could get its chance to discover something else. And that asks for further questions. BB: It seems that all of your writings have an underlying notion of metamorphosis, and even hope. The playfulness and openness you have towards different versions of stories show not only what animals are capable of but how they and their stories can transform our understandings and relationships with them. VD: I’m an optimistic person, but this is only a personal characteristic. I prefer to walk on the bright side of the street. I could refer to my parents and so on – there are a lot of things, you know? Because I’m the daughter of a history. I’m the daughter of a history – people having lost their parent during the war, having known the war, and having tried to teach their children that their life was beautiful as well as they could. I wasn’t born just after the war, it was fifteen years later, but I hear it and inherit a history and my parents were two marvellous people. They lost their fathers during the war. I think that really they probably believed that the world would be better if we trust the world. I’m probably not the only one of my generation having benefited because of this sort of joyful optimism. The second reason is that I went against this philosophical tradition that was my first path, which is critical philosophy. For example, trier les bonnes graines de l’ivraie, if you wanted an Evangelical sentence, which means separate the good seeds from the bad, the wheat from the chaff. And that’s what normally I was supposed to do. Ideology or Science? Kropotkin – ideology. Darwin – science. Malthus? Ideology but one that is science, at least when it becomes Darwin and if it doesn’t end up as Spencer, for example. So you just make a constant operation of separating and separating and separating, which is kind of philosophical. “I’m critical.” Critical philosophy. And denounce. Oh, that’s so much fun to denounce. [Laughter.] Because you are so intelligent when you denounce. [Laughter.] Yes, because not only are you more intelligent than the one you denunciate because you caught them, but you are more intelligent than all these people who still believe them. And so you build your own 170 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 buchanan, chrulew & bussolini intelligence on the stupidity of others. And I think that this feeling, to be ironic, sarcastic, is a sort of bad joy, joie mauvaise in the Spinozist sense, passion triste, sad passion. You know? To be so intelligent at the expense of others and convert them to your truth and cure the blind. [Laughter.] In French we say dessiller les yeux. Open the eyes – that were closed. I didn’t feel at ease with that because I felt that there was something profoundly dishonest in it. Because you always write against someone else and you always create a kind of easy intelligence that is only built upon the stupidity of others. That was why I could not go along with this for very long. Thankfully, my own eye opening happened in the field because otherwise it probably would have taken me years before transforming an uneasiness, inquietude or malaise into something that can be thought, that can be used to make things, to make thought, to make stories … I think that the best fortune I had was that it happened in the field. I cannot separate. My uneasiness with doing that might have lasted a long time before I would finally have revolted against this kind of ethos – this ethos as a feeling, as a way of habit. That’s why I like James. He has humour but he never built on stupidity in order to be intelligent. The only thing I could do, then – instead of denouncing stupidity, malpractice, bad sciences, especially uninteresting sciences, I could do something that was comfortable for the way I like to work, for what I can do, because I’m not very good at denouncing [laughter] – was to celebrate achievements and just keep silent about the rest, which is not an easy position in the sense that it sometimes asks you to say nothing, just to keep silent. With Quand le loup habitera avec l’agneau I made a concession to that position and I criticized Harlow. I did it because I didn’t want everyone to believe that everything is a romantic and wonderful world where all the scientists are wonderful people. Everybody still thought that Harlow was such a great scientist because he taught us love … [Laughter.] BB: In some ways your approach highlights a difference between yourself and particular 171 streams of contemporary French philosophy that work through deconstruction, genealogical analyses, critical readings, and so on. How do you see your animal projects in relation to the various other “questions of the animal” in Derrida, Deleuze, or even in relation to the rise of “animal studies” in general? VD: I came late to these discussions – first because I wanted to study with scientists, and they are rare, I mean in this literature, rare are the people who really take this seriously, who study scientists doing things with animals. We have some people now but they were very rare before – I didn’t know anyone who was really studying scientists in their real relationship with the animals. They were talking about what they were writing and the political context of the writing, and the political ideas that were in the writing. But in the French tradition I could not find anyone who could help me, except Latour and Stengers, who are not dealing with animals but with practices; that’s why I have been reading them and follow them, because they are interested in practices and they are very helpful to think about practice. Not only do they think and write about practice, but they write about their love of the practices – of the good practices, of course, especially for Stengers (Latour is less normative). This is the first point. I didn’t read Derrida for a long time, and if I did read Derrida it’s because of Donna Haraway, which is funny because I had to read Haraway the American to come back to a French philosopher. I didn’t want to read him because I was so suspicious, suspicious of philosophers because they were talking about animals but without knowing, and believing in the human exception has been for me so disturbing since the beginning. Derrida, you know, I saw him in Liège, and he said something that was very important for me. He gave a talk – not about animals – it was a sort of roundtable, and one of the participants asked him what he thought – since he had been writing a bit about animals – about Bergson who says this and that, quotes a lot of philosophers, and Derrida was really mad and said, “why are you Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 on asking the right questions philosophers always quoting old philosophers who didn’t know what we know today and why don’t you read scientists?” To say that, given the reproach Haraway made later on … Well, I thought maybe this man is not all that bad. [Laughter.] Because it is exactly what I was thinking, that when my colleagues in philosophy say to me, “If you read about animals you will find that … and so on,” I thought, I don’t want to read these people, because they were right to think what they thought, probably not all of them but Bergson, for instance, was right to write what he thought because scientists were thinking the same at the same time and he was interested in sciences. If Bergson helps you to speculate, then yes, great, for the gesture of speculation, for what he did with fake or faux problems. This is important. But not necessarily the content. So take the gesture, take the problems, but don’t take the content with it. So I didn’t really want to read philosophy. Then I read Derrida but with Haraway’s reproach in mind – I think that she’s right. She’s quite right because the cat appeared on the scene, complicated it, but very soon, you know … The animal is again just a pretext. What Derrida is right about – but I didn’t need Derrida to point this out – is that “animal” is a concept, a really badly founded one. That’s what bothers me in animal studies; that it rests on that really ill-founded concept. Because it seems that it’s again animal on one side and human on the other. And I would rather prefer different frameworks – maybe the field is too young for that, but that it contains a future possible splitting. We know, for example, that with anthropology today, if you know a little bit, and you ask someone “What are you doing?,” they’ll respond, “I am an anthropologist.” The next question will be “which cultures are you studying?” If you don’t raise this question, you don’t know anything about anthropology; because anthropology doesn’t exist, as Dominique Lestel says that ethology doesn’t exist. It exists in peerreviewed journals, but it’s a big word for very different realities. Are we able to consider that animal science or studies is a big word for very different realities? I’m not sure. That’s the first point. The second point is that I didn’t read until lately all the writing of people like Deborah Rose, Thom van Dooren, Cary Wolfe, all these people. You know that there is a profound difference between the way the French tradition and the English-language tradition deal with the problem of animality. It’s very, very different. In France you generally have a very apolitical way of dealing with it; the question of biopower, and so on, has only begun to emerge. The French tradition has been more of an érudite tradition, dealing with old phenomenology, or like É lisabeth de Fontenay’s history and so on. I didn’t like this tradition – this kind of erudition that doesn’t pay attention to what’s happening here and now, even if all these people are very sensitive to animals. The third important point is that people like Thom, Deborah, Donna, all these people writing about animals have been not only very politically engaged and involved but morally and ethically they were saying we have to protect and denounce what’s happened, the iniquity of treatments and so on. I could not take this risk. Had I done this I would have been completely stigmatized as a militant and not as a philosopher. What was possible in the United States, for example, to write about the injustice, the way we treat animals and so on, here would have looked like a militant discourse. Scientists would have suspected me to be a type of liberationist, and philosophers wouldn’t have accepted it all the more because I am a woman and I would have been, I think, designated as “the sensitive woman” who takes care of protecting animals and denounces their suffering. So I strategically tried not to be involved; I didn’t read this literature because it could not help me. And it’s only lately that I decided that not only have they a lot of things to teach me but in some of their work there is a way of thinking that is really interesting. Like when I was talking about the gesture of Bergson, I’m talking about the gesture of Thom, the gesture of Deborah, and they each have their own philosophical gesture. This gesture, their way of apprehending animals, of talking about animals, of creating a new sensitivity because they are really creating sensitivity, they are 172 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 buchanan, chrulew & bussolini good technicians of narrative, especially Donna, she’s an expert in creating narratives that modify your sensitivity. Thom, I would say, has a particular skill to make you hesitate with the “but.” You say okay, well, Lorenz did that – but, and he has even criticized me for this in his book Flight Ways, and he’s right to do it. “Despret says that what Lorenz did was – but she forgets that … ” and he’s right because after that you have to hesitate. You cannot be innocent any more. So, I would say that Thom’s skill is to make you hesitate. Donna’s skill is to transform your sensitivity and to transform culpability into responsibility, indifference on the one side and culpability on the other, which are counter-productive. She transforms people with narratives that have poetic metamorphoses. Nobody’s indifferent to Donna Haraway, because when people are transformed they cannot be indifferent, they can resist metamorphosis but they cannot be indifferent. I think that what prevents me from reading some authors, either in France or in the United States, is they are not talking about real animals. They are still talking about rules, principles, discourse and so on. And I have had enough of that. Philosophy should take … well, Michel Tournier explains it well. What is it to write a philosophical novel? It is to give a philosophical architecture to reality. To go back to reality and be the most concrete you can be. And that’s what I reproach, the lack of concreteness. Jeffrey Bussolini: As a science, ethology has largely focused on animal behaviour that is restricted to a particular species, population, family, or individual. But what is the role of the human here? How do you see ethology asking the right questions about humans? VD: An ethology of human beings has never been something that excites me or interests me because I think that, since we have language, language should be a part of the picture. Language is important for every being that communicates, but to deprive humans of what is so important for them seems to me rather uninteresting. Secondly, I don’t like the 173 idea because I’m sure this will lead to human exceptionalism again. If an ethology of humans makes sense, it will be an ethology of humans and animals together. That makes sense. This would be a form of sociology – not as generally practised – but a new kind of sociology, as one can see with some sociologists who are beginning to open anthropology to the relationship between all animals – human and non-human. But ethology, I think, does not have the right tools to look only at humans because it cannot consider language and a lot of other things. And because it separates; it always raises the question of whether something is cultural or natural, and for me this is not the right question. If ethology opens up to humans and animals, I think the question of culture/ nature can’t be raised because not only is it very hard to see if a cultural behaviour is from nature or from culture, but because culture doesn’t mean a human product anymore. Dominique Lestel says, I think, that ethology doesn’t exist anymore. I don’t know if he still thinks that but he used to think that. Perhaps a kind of anthropozoology is needed, but even this isn’t a good term because if you say anthropozoology you still consider that man is unique and it’s probably too big a category as well. So, I rather prefer what Jeffrey does; a kind of sociology of relationships. Doing yoga with cats for example – it’s a sociological act of observation participante. But I don’t think that the observer is the human one. [Laughter.] In these situations, the question is raised: who is the observer? The question may be raised but you don’t have any answer. That’s the interesting question; you can see, and you can observe how your cat observes you observing him, and it’s very interesting. I think that, for example, the ethology of dogs or cats is really helpful too because the question of nature and culture cannot really be raised, because even if all dogs behave in a certain way, it might be culture, but … it’s not a culture of the dogs. It’s rather a culture of the history of dogs with humans that transformed both dogs and humans, and created an artefact. A dog is an artefact. A wonderful artefact. A non-Cartesian on asking the right questions one. Which means also some things you don’t expect. “Artefacts” has multiple meanings here. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 MC: You’ve worked a fair bit with other people; you’ve co-written with Jocelyne Porcher and with Isabelle Stengers, worked with artists through art galleries, on documentary films, with farmers, scientists, and so on. How do these collaborations come about, and how would you characterize their importance for your own practices? VD: This is a definition of my own subjectivity that I am giving here. A part of my subjectivity may be at rest because somebody I trust is taking charge of this part of my subjectivity, which means we arrive at a project of collaboration, which means that they are part of my subjectivity that I don’t cultivate, because some other people will do it better than I can and allow me to do exactly the stuff I’m at ease with. So we arrive at the collaborative aspect of the work. I would have loved to be an artist. I have a lot of friends who are artists and I like to discuss things with them. But I cannot be an artist in the strict sense of the term. It’s funny – making a movie is a medium and it asks you to think like a filmmaker, but I don’t think like a filmmaker. I tried to write a theatre play with a friend of mine, with a real playwright. I began the dialogue, and he says, “you cannot make her say that.” I said, “Why? We have to say that to the audience.” “You don’t have to say that, you have to show it.” I’m not a playwright because I’m not able to translate something from one language to another kind of language, that is, into silence where you show or evoke things. But I tried to learn because I think it’s important to change, to push the border as far as you can, and still be a philosopher while intruding in another field, and considering not that I am annexing the other field because the border is still there but rather re-creating the border. Working with artists, for me, has been really great because it makes me explore all these borders and sometimes jump to the other side, and it means that the border of philosophy is not at the same place anymore because you cannot forget you are a philosopher. For example, the exhibition at la Villette was, of course, a great experience, but it was not a true collaborative experience with artists because the artistic creator was the one really in charge (Despret, Bêtes et hommes). I could say a word here and there, I could give advice, but I never worked with the artists, you know? I didn’t choose the placement of the works … I was still at ease in narrative, and in this exhibition I created narratively. Any time we were working on the exhibition I was telling a story. The last movie, the film I made with Didier Demorcy, is “Non Sheepish Sheep.” I have been more involved in the scenario because I had the scenario in my mind already when we began. As I had read a lot of Thelma Rowell before, I knew what I wanted and when I asked the question the scenario took place. Didier let me be really free about that. But it’s not really an artistic film. It is made by an artist and me, but it’s more an exploring, sharing movie. I’m also working with Luc Petton, a dancer who dances with birds, and he has been working lately with starlings, blackbirds, jays, and it’s fantastic to see. You see the dancer dancing and the birds coming and flying around the body, responding to each other. It’s really beautiful. After that he made another show, a more classical one, with a black and white swan, called “Swan,” and it takes all the conventions of classical ballet but puts a real swan in it. Now he’s preparing a ballet with the Manchurian Crane. They are beautiful birds. Very big, tall, black and white, and they dance. In nature they dance and, you know, one of Luc’s dancers says that they probably invented the entrechat, a typical figure of dance with the legs. Luc asked me to come and work with him, so I went to see the rehearsal with the crane and I didn’t know what to contribute; I think that it’s perfect that way. Because we will figure it out together somehow. Yes it’s an expérience de pensée, a thought experiment, but it’s an experiment that calls for change, not in the relationship because I don’t like the word, but to change la mise à rapport. The way to relate to the world, the way to connect to the world … I can try this with Luc because what I noticed right 174 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 buchanan, chrulew & bussolini away when I saw the dancers dancing with the crane, I thought, “Oh this is interesting because we don’t know who the choreographer is here.” We don’t know who the choreographer is because the cranes are so strong, they have their own will, and strongly mark it. They know how to dance – sometimes they will take the initiative and sometimes respond to the initiative of the dancer. With this idea of how the crane perceives the world in that particular situation, I think that we will learn with them because each time they answer to a gesture and come or follow or begin to fly … they are saying something. You don’t improvise your own gestures, you just hope that making a gesture will provoke one of the responses you expect, and if not, it will be a response that will make the dancer respond. For example, when I saw this particular dancer proposing a lot of gestures to the crane, I thought this was fantastic because Whitehead wrote about a lure for feelings, a lure for thoughts (Process and Reality). What philosophy makes – what a good proposition makes – is a lure for feelings and a lure for thoughts. Lure is appât in French; something that attracts. But in French we have also the word appeau and an appeau, for example, is a fake whistle that you use to trick birds, a fake whistle that ethologists and hunters use to call birds. In French it’s appeau, which has the same roots as appât, like lure, but this is a specific name to designate the object that can lure animals. Anyway, I proposed that we think of dancing as creating appeaux. Which means that I’m considering that the dancing, for example, is creating for the dancers, either for the humans or for the cranes, a new way of perceiving the world. Interspecific ways of perceiving the world, which are neither the same nor symmetrical because both are transformed, and we can see the transformation. What I’m expecting of collaborations, then, is to change. That I change. And this is very egotistical. Because this is a concern of mine, that I think that I might work better if I change because I think that I’m stuck in a routine. If something has been working pretty well and I have no reason to abandon it because it works 175 well, then that’s just a good reason to abandon it. It works too well. BB: It’s a really interesting notion of egotistical though. You’re saying that you’re doing it for yourself but the self that you’re doing it for is the self that you want to change, to transform, to test. VD: Collaborations force me against my, I wouldn’t say “laziness,” but my tendency to inertia. If something works, why change? Yes, change. If you think that, change. It’s risky, but I don’t have anything to risk any more except that I still have ten years of work at the university in front of me, and I hope more after that. But yes, I hope to feel differently. To have new percepts. That’s it exactly. Working with artists gives one new ways of perceiving, new ways of thinking, and maybe more courage to go a little too far sometimes. Yes, to go too far. I have gone too far sometimes but I didn’t do it on purpose. I only noticed it because some reactions were bizarre. [Laughter.] But I would like to go too far on purpose – a little too far. Not to offend anyone, but just to cross a border and see whether maybe I’m home. Or maybe not. Maybe somebody will say to me: “What are you doing here?!” [laughter] and it will be nice. Just a visit. JB: Can you give an example of when or where you’ve gone too far? VD: One way of going too far is what I’m trying to figure out now, and it will probably be a direction I take with Luc Petton, is how I take into account the problem of extinction and equality, there being enough room for everyone, conservation problems, and so on. I don’t want to deal with these kinds of problems – extinction, for example – ethically. I don’t want to say this is an ethical problem – even the term “ethical problem” for me, I get bored as soon as I say that. [Laughter.] The way I’ve been thinking about extinction, for example with passenger pigeons, is to consider that if one species disappears, what disappears is an ontological part of reality. Following Gustav Fechner, and James, the matter of the world is the way the world is enduring into its existence. And one Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 on asking the right questions of its modes of enduring into existence is to think itself. The world is thinking itself. And this makes it also exist. Leibniz has helped me to clarify this as well. If I say, for example, that if we lose little penguins, this is a part of reality that disappears; not only the reality made by the body of the existence of penguins but the way the world is perceiving itself, by the way, or through the way, penguins perceive the world. What is lost is the particular noise of the waves that only penguins can hear, and the light that only these penguins can see. I’m not holistic, in a Gaia hypothesis sense, but I am trying to speculate about the fact that each species that disappears impoverishes the way the world is perceived. So I am not talking only about the way the world is inhabited but the way the world is thinking itself. And saying that, if I say that to a scientist, I know I am going too far. So, how can I go too far without being completely misunderstood? It doesn’t help if everybody believes you are a fool. So you have to learn how to go too far, which makes things change – I mean ways of thinking change – but not too, too far. You know? In this case, for example, I can say to a scientist, and in a way they will understand when I say it, “I am a methodological animist.” So I am not an animist – maybe I am, but that’s my concern – but I am a methodological animist, which means that if I speculate that way, how does it help us to change the way we perceive the world, the way we perceive animals, and the way we enter into relations with them? And this is to go too far, which means that I have to go outside of my normal field, which was describing scientists, understanding a dispositive, and so on. When I speculate that when a species disappears the world is losing a way of perceiving itself – if it’s true, what does it change? But if you ask the question “if it’s true what does it change?” you also have to raise the question “but which kind of truthfulness are you talking about?” And I’m referring here to Bruno Latour’s modes of existence. In which mode of existence does this truthfulness belong? It’s not a scientific truth. I am not describing a word chain of references of translation that comes from a piece of Earth to the laboratory in Los Angeles, all these little chains of translation that make the science work and the truth become truth. The real becoming – or the becoming real – of a true statement. The truthfulness of my statement is not a scientific one; that is why I specify that I am a methodological animist, which means I don’t say that I believe that each being has a soul and that the world is the soul of every being like Fechner did. It’s only methodological. Let’s try to imagine the world: we don’t know how the world is composed. Yes, we know scientifically how the world is composed, but we don’t know for other modes of existence how the world is composed. We don’t know outside causality how things connect together, and yet at the same time we do know, but the term “to know” has changed meaning. I mean, yes we know a little bit, but we have a lot to learn and we are not well equipped for that. So, if I say it’s a methodological animism it’s to specify that it is just a gesture, a position I take, and an experimental trial. If we think that seriously, what does it change and what should we change? BB: Are there any particular moments or events that stand out to you in your own metamorphoses? VD: Two personal experiences. One of the greatest experiences I have had in my life is one morning hearing a blackbird – I’ve written about this – and all of a sudden I had the feeling that this blackbird knew what importance means. On that morning I really thought that the blackbird invented the concept of importance. I really did think this … this is going too far, I know, but I’m crossing a border here, that if we know what importance means, it’s because a blackbird taught us. Because if you hear a blackbird singing in the morning you will know what importance means. And plus the blackbird has this characteristic – I don’t know if it has been studied but when they sing – I don’t know if you have the same feeling as me but, with the tympani of the ears, sometimes you feel that it’s not the same place where the music arrives and 176 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 buchanan, chrulew & bussolini where the words arrive – like if it was geographically distributed in your ears. I feel it that way – I’m not sure that it’s not scientific – but I feel that words don’t arrive at the same place in my ears as music. When the blackbirds sing it arrives where the words arrive in the form of music. It was the most fantastic experience of hybridization. And a second experience that is funny – well, it was a fun experience – I went to visit a friend in Normandy. She raises horses. In the afternoon they proposed that we travel on a carriage, an open one, you know, a very old, open one. And I was with the driver in the front seat. There are a lot of horses there, you know, it’s a part of Normandy where it’s only prairies with horses, sheep, goats, dogs, a lot of animals, I couldn’t believe it. I’d never seen so many before; these horses, all of these animals, it was sort of like heaven. We were crossing a little path and all the animals came running to the fence to see the two horses pulling our carriage, and they were talking together. I’ve never noticed that before, because they don’t do that for us. But they did that for the horse. And I was like a poor person, welcomed in a chateau with all these animals. And all these animals were welcoming these horses because they knew each other – I asked, and this man rides very often so the horses know every animal where they go – and the animals know the horse and all these animals were running, just saying hello. It was so fantastic. I was in another world. BB: Like a fairy tale. VD: Yes, it was. We always live under the sort of obvious thought that the world belongs to us. We act like that, we feel like that, we have been living like that, we have been raised like that. And when you see all these animals ignore you, or they pretend they do, and have so much conversation together, and they live two metres from us and we ignore them, then all of a sudden the world doesn’t belong to us. I know that this was not for me, but I was involved in it, and it was like a gift, you know? All these animals were making me a gift. 177 disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the authors. notes 1 The majority of this interview was conducted in person (in English) outside of Nîmes, France, in May 2014. It has since been edited, expanded, and revised via e-mail. Responses in French have been translated by the interviewers. 2 Despret and Stengers, Les Faiseuses d’histoires and Women Who Make a Fuss; Despret, Que diraient les animaux and What Would Animals Say? bibliography Despret, Vinciane. Bêtes et hommes. Paris: Gallimard, 2007. Print. Despret, Vinciane. Que diraient les animaux, si … on leur posait les bonnes questions? Paris: La Découverte, 2012. Print. Despret, Vinciane. What Would Animals Say? Trans. Brett Buchanan. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, forthcoming. Print. Despret, Vinciane, and Isabelle Stengers. Les Faiseuses d’histoires: Que font les femmes à la pensée. Paris: La Découverte, 2011. Print. Despret, Vinciane, and Isabelle Stengers. Women Who Make a Fuss. Trans. April Knutson. Minneapolis: Univocal, 2014. Print. Emery, Nathan J., and Nicola S. Clayton. “Do Birds Have the Capacity for Fun?” Current Biology 25.1 (2015): R16–R20. Print. Gombrowicz, Witold. Cosmos. Trans. Danuta Borchardt. New York: Grove, 2005. Print. Leibniz, G.W. “Monadology.” Discourse on Metaphysics and Other Essays. Trans. Daniel Garber and Roger Ariew. New York: Hackett, 1991. Print. Tournier, Michel. The Erl-King. Trans. Barbara Bray. London: Atlantic, 2013. Print. Whitehead, Alfred North. Process and Reality. New York: Free, 1978. Print. Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:56 21 November 2015 on asking the right questions Vinciane Despret Philosophie et Lettres Université de Liège 4000 Liège Belgium E-mail: [email protected] Brett Buchanan Department of Philosophy School of the Environment Laurentian University 935 Ramsey Lake Road Sudbury Ontario P3E 2C6 Canada E-mail: [email protected] Matthew Chrulew Centre for Culture and Technology Research and Graduate Studies Faculty of Humanities Curtin University GPO Box U1987 Perth, WA 6845 Australia E-mail: [email protected] Jeffrey Bussolini Sociology – Anthropology Department City University of New York 2800 Victory Boulevard Staten Island, NY 10314 USA E-mail: [email protected] Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:58 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:58 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:59 21 November 2015 Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:59 21 November 2015 notes on the contributors Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:59 21 November 2015 brett buchanan is Director of the School of the Environment and Associate Professor and Chair of the Department of Philosophy at Laurentian University (Canada). His work is situated at the intersections of contemporary Continental philosophy, environmental thought, and animal studies, and in addition to a number of articles and book chapters he is the author of OntoEthologies: The Animal Environments of Uexküll, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Deleuze (State U of New York P, 2008). He sits on a number of scholarly boards and committees, including Wilfrid Laurier University Press’s “Environmental Humanities” book series, Environmental Humanities journal, and is currently translating Vinciane Despret’s book Que diraient les animaux, si … on leur posait les bonnes questions? for the University of Minnesota Press’s “Posthumanities” series. Together with Matthew Chrulew and Jeffrey Bussolini, he edited issue 19.3 of Angelaki on the philosophical ethology of Dominique Lestel. 183 jeffrey bussolini is Associate Professor of Sociology-Anthropology at City University of New York; and CoDirector, with Ananya Mukherjea, of the Center for Feline Studies, which has conducted etho-ethnographic study of feline–human interactions since 1995. He is affiliated with the Scuola di Interazione Uomo–Animale (School of Human–Animal Interactions) in Bologna, Italy. He translated Dominique Lestel’s book on animal friendship, The Friends of My Friends, forthcoming from Columbia University Press. Jeffrey wrote the articles “Toward Cat Phenomenology” in Found Object 8 (Spring 2000) and “Recent French, Belgian, and Italian Approaches to the Cognitive Science of Animals: Dominique Lestel, Vinciane Despret, Roberto Marchesini, and Giorgio Celli” in Social Science Information 52.2 (2013), and appeared as “Feline Sociologist” in the VICE Media film Lil Bub and Friendz (2013). He has been Visiting Scholar at Macquarie University (CRSI), UNSW (Environmental Humanities), and the University of Copenhagen (CMSTS). Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:59 21 November 2015 matthew chrulew is a Research Fellow in the Centre for Culture and Technology at Curtin University in Perth, Western Australia. He was previously a Research Fellow at the Centre for Research on Social Inclusion at Macquarie University in Sydney, under the supervision of Deborah Bird Rose, where he convened two international collaborative workshops on “The History, Philosophy and Future of Ethology.” His essays have appeared in Angelaki, SubStance, New Formations, Foucault Studies, Australian Humanities Review, Humanimalia, Antennae, The Bible and Critical Theory, and the collections Animal Death and Metamorphoses of the Zoo. With Chris Danta he edited issue 43.2 of SubStance on Jacques Derrida’s The Beast & the Sovereign lectures, and with Jeffrey Bussolini and Brett Buchanan he edited issue 19.3 of Angelaki on the philosophical ethology of Dominique Lestel. He is an associate editor of the journal Environmental Humanities. vinciane despret is maître de conférences at the University of Liège and at the Free University of Brussels. She is philosopher of sciences. Her first fieldwork was in the Negev desert, in Israel, where she explored the possibility of making an “ethology of the ethologists.” Since then she has worked with animals and with the humans who observe them, live with them, or simply know them. She has been scientific curator of the “Bêtes et hommes” exhibition held at the Grande halle de la Villette, Parc de la Villette, Paris, 11 September 2007 to 20 January 2008. She is the sole or co-author of eight books, and her latest book, Que diraient les animaux, si … on leur posait les bonnes questions?, will be translated into English in 2015. For more information see <http:// reflexions.ulg.ac.be/cms/c_12740/en/despretvinciane> and <http://www.vincianedespret. be/papers/>. donna haraway is Distinguished Professor Emerita in the History of Consciousness Department at the University of California at Santa Cruz. She earned her Ph.D. in Biology at Yale University in 1972 and has taught the history of science, science and technology studies, feminist theory, and multispecies studies at the University of Hawaii, Johns Hopkins University, and since 1980 the University of California at Santa Cruz. She has been the principal adviser for over sixty doctoral students and served as committee member for many more in North America, Europe, and Australia. In 2000, she was awarded the JD Bernal Prize, the Society for Social Studies of Science’s highest honour, for distinguished lifetime contributions to the field. With particular attention to the intersection of biological sciences with culture and politics, Haraway’s work explores the string figures composed by science fact, science fiction, speculative feminism, speculative fabulation, science and technology studies, and multispecies worlding. Her books include When Species Meet (U of Minnesota P, 2008); The Companion Species Manifesto: Dogs, People, and Significant Otherness (Prickly Paradigm, 2003); The Haraway Reader (Routledge, 2004); Modest_Witness@Second_Millennium.FemaleMan© Meets OncoMouse™ (Routledge, 1997); Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature (Routledge, 1991); Primate Visions: Gender, Race and Nature in the World of Modern Science (Routledge, 1989); and Crystals, Fabrics, and Fields: Metaphors that Shape Embryos (Yale UP, 1976; North Atlantic, 2004). She is completing a new book titled Staying with the Trouble: Anthropocene, Capitalocene, Chthulucene, as well as a collection of short pieces titled Elderberries, focusing on surprising tangles for human and non-human critters accompanying each other growing older together. Manifestly Haraway, a reissue of the “A Cyborg Manifesto” and “The Companion Species Manifesto,” with an extended conversation with Cary Wolfe, is forthcoming with the University of Minnesota Press in autumn 2015. 184 stephen muecke Downloaded by [Laurentian University] at 12:59 21 November 2015 is Professor of Ethnography in the Environmental Humanities Program at the University of New South Wales, Sydney. He works with Indigenous groups in Broome (a recent book is Butcher Joe, for Documenta 13 (Hatje Cantz, 2011)) and on the Indian Ocean; Contingency in Madagascar, with photographer Max Pam, appeared in 2012 in Intellect Books’ Critical Photography Series. jocelyne porcher is Director of Research in Sociology at INRA (National Institute for Agronomic Research), France. Her main field is the human–animal relationship at work. She has worked on different topics related to human and animal intersubjectivity at work: attachment, love, suffering, communication, and sharing of skills, especially in animal farming and in factory animal production. Her aim, in the framework of French and EU collective programmes, is to conceptualize animal work (in situated forms of production: animal farming, zoo, circus, cinema, care, army, etc.) and to propose a third path between “animal exploitation” and “animal liberation” (e.g., in taking into account animal labour). She is the author of numerous book chapters in English, including, most recently, “Are Organic Animal Farmers Able to do Animal Husbandry?” in Organic Farming, Prototype for Agriculture? (Springer, 2014) and “Animal work” in The Oxford Handbook of Animal Studies (Oxford UP, 2015). She is also the author of eight books (three co-authored) that highlight the relationships between humans and animals today and those that may exist – or not – tomorrow. Her book Living with Animals: A Utopia for the 21st Century will be published in English by Brill in 2015. 185 hollis taylor is a Research Fellow at Macquarie University, Sydney, in the Department of Media, Music, Communication and Cultural Studies. Previously, she was a Chancellor’s Postdoctoral Research Fellow at the University of Technology, Sydney, a Postdoctoral Research Fellow at the Laboratoire d’Eco-anthropologie et Ethnobiologie in the Muséum National d’Histoire Naturelle, Paris, and a Fellow at the Institute for Advanced Study in Berlin. Her research focuses on three Australian avian species – pied butcherbirds, lyrebirds, and bowerbirds – as she reflects on animal aesthetics, human exceptionalism in the arts, and the nature– culture continuum. She performs her awardwinning (re)compositions of pied butcherbird songs on violin and is the author of Post Impressions: A Travel Book for Tragic Intellectuals, which documents (in text, audio, and video) Jon Rose and her bowing fences throughout Australia. Her monograph Is Birdsong Music? Outback Encounters with an Australian Songbird is forthcoming. She is webmaster for <www.zoömusicology.com>.