Touching Art: Intimacy, Embodiment, and the
Transcription
Touching Art: Intimacy, Embodiment, and the
m l . I ouchln g art Intimacy,embodiment,and the somatosensory system EllenJ.Esrock L ) e p a r t n r c n to f L a n g u a g e ,L i t e r a t u r e , a n d C o r n r n u n i c a t i o n , R e n s s e l a e r PolytechnicInstitutc Viewersl-rave a way of using thcir somatoscnsorysystemto creatctcrnporary boundary changesthat bring thern into intirnate relationshipswith art objects.Spcctatorsexperiencethis irnaginaryfusion whcn simultaneor"rsly atter-rding to tl-reirown somatoscnsoryscnsations,wl-ricl-r occur insiclethc body, and to qualitiesof the artwork, wlrich exist in the exterr.ral world. At such nromcntsviewersreinterprettheir sornJt()scnsory scns.rtionsas a quali ty of the artwork. When ir-rside and outsideare reintcrpretcd,vicwcrscross the conventionalbounclarybctwecnselfand object.This eftectcan trc illustrated in first pcrson reportsand supporteclby currcnt rcsc:rrchin the r-reu rclsciertces and the hun-rar-rities. Keywords:somatic r-narkers, somatoscnsorysystcnl,emboclirnent,projcction, enrpathy Imagine you are standing in an art museum, mesmerized by an enormous canvas of turbulent blue paint. Though you find no recognizable images, you are fascinated by the swirling movements of rich azures and cobalt blues. Yclur eyes follow the artist's long, energetic brush strclkesacross the work, and you feel a powerful rush of motion inside your body. Sr-rdclenly,your attention is caught by a small area of densely patterned paint flecked with hints of scarlet. You linger. The thick color glows. As your awareness of the surroundings dim, the bright spot on the canvas expands, and the sensuoLrscolor flclws into you. Yclu are immersed. Instants later, the bond breaks, as your lttentitln shifts to the murmurs of a nearby cclnversatior.r. ( - ' t r t s c i o r r - s r r& c s I- ss t t o t i L t t t : : z ( z o o r ) , 4 3 2 5 4 . r s s N 1 5 6 6 5 l J - 1 6 ( ) : o o r J o l r n I l e t r j r t m i n sP u b l i s h i n g ( i r n r p a n v 23'4 Ellenl. Flsrock What ir viewer is experiencingin such rlorlents of imr.nersionis a shifi in the orclinary senseof one's boclily boundaries. For an instant, r'iewer and artwork seem to merge. Other art forms create sirnilar ellects, whicl-r irre Phraseslike lteing.fille expressed in common lingr.ristic expressions. d with nrtrsic and absorbedin a storyspeakto a shift in the orclinaryextensionof the body. Such boclily changeshave been central to markedly different theories of aesthetics.Cor.rceptsllke sublintity,empathy,altsttrption,.flrtw-allcurrent at one t i r n eo r a n o t h e rs i n c ea n t i q u i t y- c o n c e r ns o m ek i n c lo f e x p e r i e n c teh a t a l t e r s o u r o r d i n i r r ys e n s eo f b o d i l y c o r r t a i n r n e n t I. n ' . l c c . l ,s u c h e h a n g c si n o u r rnany facetsof life of the bodily perin-reter occur in though r.rot experience necessarily with the kind clf motivation or volitional control thirt occursin the arts.Eroticism,spiritualancihealingpractices,aswell aspathologicaiconclitions can all involvethe body as a siteof fusion with objectsanclothers in tl-reworld. My toprichereis the spectator'srelationshipto visual art. I hypothesizethat viewerscan usetheir bodies,specifically, tl-reirsclmatosensory system,to create temporary boundary changesthat bring thern into intimate relationshipswith responsestc) trrt objects.They achievethis effectby using their son.ratosensory standfor aspectsof objectsin the world. I characterizethis as a reinterpretation a sttntaticreinterpretatiorr. lt coulcl be of one's somatosensoryexperienct clescribedas a kind of tacitly held, performanceknowledgethat evolvesover our lifetimes,dependingon our bodily constitutions,aptitudes,and expsliqnces, which servesthe positive function of er-rhancingour experienceof the artwork. Somaticreinterpretationis a powerful phenomenonbecansethe bcldy is so intimately linked with our senseof iclentity erndego boundary tl-rat altering our senseof the body, although irnaginativeancltenrporary,involves c h a n g i n gs o m e t h i n gb a s i ct o w l ' r a t u, n d e r s o m et h e o r i e s i,s c o n s t i t u t i v eo f o u r s e n s eo f s e l f . In exploring this hypothesis,I undertaketwo relatedtasks.The first ar-rd most basicis to rnakethis little recogniz-ed bodily phenomenon rnore familiar to reaclers. As the production of theseboundary changesmight be considerecl a non-verbal skill or practice,my challengeis tcl bring these char-rges to the attention of tl-rosewho unknowingly experiencethese shifts and to prrclvicle sclmeguidancein their procluctionfor others.For thosewho clo not appearto experiencevisual art in this way, even with instruction, my goal is simply tcr render the experienceplausible.As the most compelling testirnony to tl"re phenomenaarethe responses I havereceivedby realviewersin lectureaucliences,I draw on thesefor cliscussion. Touchingart 45 The second and more challengingtask is to develop an argument that fleshesout my hypothesisabout how theseboundary changesoccur.Although t h e p r t l p o s e dn o t i o n o f s o r n a t i cr e i n t e r p r e t a t i o inn v i t e st u r t h e re l a b o r a t i o ni,t s coreicleasare supportedby a convergence of scientificresearchand humanistic Thesearepromisingtimes to considersuchicleas,fbr scientistsand scholarship. humanists are united in posing the kind of cluestionsthat were not even conceivablein prior decades.This particular study,engageclwith interclisciplinary issuesof embodiment and artistic experience,is oft-erecl in the spirit of newly emergingresearchinto consciousness and emotion. The paperbeginswith an overviewof the major argumentand fbllowswith a sectionon guided experiencesof viewing. A full treatment of the argument follows. The final sectiondraws connectionsbetrveenthe key ideasproposed here and cltherrelatedtheoriesand oractices. r. Overview of the argument Takethe viewer'sexperiencein the museum describedabove.I strggestthat we undergosuchan experienceby an interpretiveoperaticlnwe perform, Llnaware, on our somatosensorysensations.In the exampleabove,we might experience the sensationof our own lungs expandingand contractins in slow, rhythmic surgesjuxtaposedto the sensationof our own bodily heat.The juxtapositionof however,might appearto Lrsas a quality of the artwork. Were thesesensations, this to happen,we would be reinterpretingour bodily sensationsas a featllreof the art object. We would be temporarily renaming, or reinterpreting, our somatosensory sensationsas the pulsatingluminescenceof color on canvas.In short, we would identifl,what is insidethe boundariesof the body with what is outsidethe body. To help explicatethis phenomenon, I draw on the sornaticmarker hypothesis of A.R. Damasio,which suggeststhat we can mark certain somatosensory sensationsas positive or negative,depending on the context in which they occur. Extending Damasio'shypothesis,I areue that in certain moments of viewing,we mark, or reinterpret,thesesensations aspropertiesof the clbjectswe gazeupon. Thus marked,thesesomatosensory sensations function in two ways: they referto somethingexternalto the body - whateverthey come to n-rarkand, given their neuroanatomy,they ref-erto somethingthat is ir-rternal to us. To advancethis hypothesis,I offer a central argllment concerning the polaritiesof differentsensorysystems.Thesepolaritiesref-erto the origin of the 46 Ellenl. Esrock infbrmation that is conveyedby the senses- whether the information referstcr the subjectivepole of the selfor the objectivepole of the externalworld. Vision is not usuaily considereda bipolar sense.Oriented to the polarity of the external world, vision givesus information about objectsoutsidethe body. Conversely, touch is bipolar. By touching, one can acquireinformation about an external object - the feel of the thing in the world that is touched. But touch is alsir oriented to the subjectivepolarity, for one can receiveinfbrmation about an internal object - the subjectivefeelingof being touched. Visceralfunctions ancl other somaticstates,which are not bipoiar,give us infbrmation only about the inner world. When looking at art works,vision and touch finction together.Oriented to the objectiveworld, touch assumesthe externalobjectprovided for it by vision and thus mentally touches the visually apprehendedobject. But touch also orientsto the subjectivepole and, thus,conveysthe sensationof being touched. In this casethe thing that doesthe (mental) touching is the externalobject of vision. One'sbody feelstouchedby vision'sobject.Thus, in its bipolar capircities,touch refersboth to the self that is touched,as well as the touched object outsidethe body. The combination of thesetwo polaritiesbridgesthe physical distancebetween the visually perceivedobject and the viewer, bringing the palpability of the object seen into the subjective,bodily boundaries of the subject.Thus, in both casesinner and outer realitiesmergedeepinsidethe body - not merely at the top layersof skin, where surfacetouch operates.One finds the objectwithin one'sselfor one finds that one is within the object. These changesin boundaries can be effectedthrough use of the entire somatosensorysystem, not just its touch component. The somatosensory systemcan becomebipolar in an uncharacteristicway.When visuallyengaged with the object,the feel of the somatosensorysystemcan be interpretedas the feel of certain qualitiesof the object viewed. h-rdeed,thesesensationscan be interpretedto feellike the very substanceof the object- its weight, density,or movement>in which caseour somatosensory systemis being projectedonto the systemcan alsobe interpretedasbeing objectin the world. Our somatosensory touched by the object viewed - in which casethe object is being introjected into one'sbody. Whateverthe location, subjectiveor objective,the experience retainsboth components. When the somatosensory systemis projectedoutward into the object,there is still the sensethat what is projectedis one'sinner body, ancl,likewise,when the somatosensorysystemreceivesthe externalobject, there is the sensethat what is introjected into the body is a thing that inhabits the external world. Touchingart 2J7 The participation of the entire somatosensorysystemin this engagementwith vision substantiallyreinforcesthe narrow link between vision and touch by themselves. During theseexperiencesone feelsthat externalobjectsare not engaging system- but somethingcentral just a part of one'sbody - the somatosensory to some kind of personalself, as dehned by specificconceptsof self identity. Thus, through thesechangesof boundaries,one finds the object within one's personalselfor one linds that one is within the object. To strengthen this argument, I discuss converging concepts that are formulated within different areasof scientific and humanistic research.I draw on key conceptsin psychoanalysis,attribution theory in cognitive psychology, image schemamodels in linguistics,sensorimotortheory of percepticln,and simulationsof a phantom Iimb type of displacement. 2. Guided viewing and audience produced somatic reinterpretations When speakingto audienceson this topic, I begin by intrtlducing the ntltion of bodily intimacy with art objects,which primes the audienceto the issuesof bodily feelings.Severalslidesare then projectedon a large screen.With each slide I instruct the audienceto perform a different task. Readersmight try to recreatesome of theseeffectswith their own artwork. When attemptingthis at home, one should usevisual imagesthat are larger than book-size,so that the eyeshavea fairly largedistanceto scan.The imagesusedwith lectureaudiences are Paul Strand's, Leaves,1929, Edward Weston's Shell, 1927, and Edvard 'the Cry,1895. Munch's In viewing Leaves,a close-upphotographof long, blade-like'striped leaves oriented vertically,I instruct the audienceto let their eyesslide up and down the Ieaves.After a few seconds,I ask them to feel a corresPondingline moving through their bodies.Somereportedthat they lirst thought the instructi()llwas impossibleto perform but tried and found, to their surprise,that they produced the line. Were these not lecturesbut workshops, orienteclto closely guided introspection,the participantsmight havediscoveredother dimensionsof their viewing experience.In theseremarks I shall explorethis broader spectrum of possibleviewing experlences. two imaginedtouchesare happenilg. Tlie first is our With Strand'sLeaves, eye touching the artwork and the secondis the senseclf a correspondingline touching our body. That the eyemight foster a senseof imagined touch is not 238 Ellenl. Esrock a new insight. What I call to attention, however,is the role of the sclmatosensory systemin definingthe characterof this imaginary touch and its extensiondeep inside the bocly. Were the viewer's experiencesftrrther developed,the line within the viewer'sbody might be f-eltto havea thicknessto it, a palpability. This palpability would consistof the backgroundfeelingof the sornatosensory system.The backgror.rndfeeling would lirnction in two ways. On the one hand, when orientedto its subjectivepole, it would possess associations of the selfto which it belongs.On the other hand, in its ob.iectiveorientation, the background feelingwould acquirethe objectof the eyescan.As an imaginedtouch directecl towardsan externalobject,it would becomethe palpablef-eelingof that object. Perceptiblequalities of the object its texture, weight, balance,emotional tone, anclcolor saturation,could becomeidentiliedwith the palpablequality of tl-reline echoing within the body. In this superimposition of objective ancl subjectivepoles,this internally felt line createsa senseof the object f-eltwithin us.'fhe object is within us, or, under a paralleldescription,we are within the object,becausethe samepalpability,which is the object, is also the palpability that is our own body. Note, the echoingf-eeling of the objectwithin neeclnot be experiencedonly in terms of linear movement. There might be a focal point on a canvasor sculpturethat can serveas a conduit from the eyeto the inner body. One miglit, fbr example, gazeat a fairly circumscribed part of an artwork - a srnall areaof lines along the contours of a well proportioned vase- anclf-eel cross-hatched a senseof internal balance that seemssituated within the palpability of a reinterpretedsomatosensory system.Or, one might gazeintently at a coior in a painting anclf'eelthe color enter the body anclbecomeinfirsedthroughout the blood stream. This is precisely how the poet Rilke experiencescolor in Cezanne'sPortrait of Madarne Cezanne: Ir-rnry fecling,the consciousness of theirpresence hasbecomea heightcning which l can feelevenin n.rysleep;r.nyblood describesit within r.ne,but thc namingof it passcs try somcwhcre outsideand is r-rotcalleclin. Did I write about it? - A rccl,upholstcrcci low arrnchtrirhasbecr.rplaccdir.rfl'or.rtol-ar.r p.lttern(a crosswith tl.recenterleft earthyereenwall in whicha cobalt-trluc o u t ) i s v e r ys p a r i n g lrye p e a t c(d1 9 8 5p, . 7 9 ) . A seconcldemonstrationinvolvestl-reuse clf Westcln'sSlrcll,a clclse-upphotograph of a nautilus shell againsta dark backgrouncl.In this caseI instruct the audienceto placetl-reireyesat the bottom lefi of the large fan shapeanclmove Touchingart 239 the eyeslowly around the curved top edgeofthe shelland then over the center to wherethey began.I askthem to feelthe fragileedgeof the shellas they rnove and then to let the eyetravelback and forth over a largecentralportion ofthe shell.While they are doing this, I instruct them to feellinesbeing drawn insicle t h e i rb o d i e s . After a presentationat the Orange County Museum, Califclrnia,an cllder "It participant said to me about this particular experience, was so arclusingl" 'l'hough her tone and manner did not suggestthat she was awareof reporting sexualarousal,it seemeclto me, given the phallic connotations of Weston's image,that the feelingof moving her eyesrhythmicallyover the shellwas highly erotic.Others commentedon this particular image,though none as directly. Arousal,whether or not keyedspecificallytcl the sexualsystem,is an aspect of somatosensoryawareness that can also be reinterpreted.We might experiencearousalrelatedto the subjectmatter of the representedobject,whether the arousalis generatedthrough musculartensioncreatec'l in respclnse to the youth in Chardin's YoungMan Blowing Bultblesor whetl-rerit is more cliffusely experiencedas excitement in responseto the backstagef'lurry clf action in Degas'Balletat ParisOpera.Arousalmight alsobe generatedin our responseto the formal qualitiesof the object,suchas the agitationof paint or the precision of a delicatecutout. There is alsothe arousalgeneratedin the subject'spursuit of meaningor curiosity about the constructionof the artwork. Howeverit is generated,arousalmight be reinterpretedas somethingit is not. In the museum situation describedabove, the viewer's description of arousalpertainedto her internalexperienceof imaginativetcluch- a reference to the subjectivepole. I did not questionher as to whether the arousalbecame reinterpretedas an object within. Others viewers might have describeclthis same kind of experienceas an energeticheightening of the external a referenceto the objectivepole. With the Chardin painting, fcrr exantple,the spectator'sarousalmight be reinterpretedas tl-reboy's concentration or the expansionof the bubble as he blows it. The final slidein my lecture-demonstrationis EdvarclMunch's lithograph The Cry, a slightly different black and white version of the coloreclimaee that decoratesgift shop windows. I instruct the audienceto let their eyes slide rhythmically around on the lines and to become conscious of their own breathing.Next, I ask them to find a way of using their breathing to interact with the work. For instance,I suggestwhen inhaling they pretend they are taking in the image with their breath and when exhaling pretend they are propelling themselvesalong the long, fluid lines. Standing before the same z4o EllenJ. Esnrck Iithographin a Munch exhibition at BostonCollege,I brought this cluestionttr a viewer willing to sharehis responses: Q: Can you rnakethis work connectto yor"rrown breathing? A: Oh sure.. . . breathingout takesthosefiguresin the backgroundaway from me anclbreathingin bringsthem towardsme. (Persclnal Intcrvicw, February7, 200I ). The spectator'sbreathcan serveboth as a meansof changingone'spsychological distanceto the externalobject,by inhalingand exhaling,and ofchanging the nature of the selfand the object.The use of breath is somewhatdifferent from the other somatic reinterpretationsbecauseof the strong emotional and cognitive associationsthat it often carries. Breathing is a function of the somatosensorysystemthat is regardedin many culturesas an activity of high emotional and spiritual significance.In such contextsthe intake and releaseof air is thought to havea transfcrrmative quality. The ancient Hebrewsused the sameword for both spirit and wind, the Navajoslinked the notions of awarenessand air, and the Buddhistsconceivedof the Chi as an interior, spiritual breath(Abram, 1996).Furthermore,psychodynamictheorieslike Bioenergetics and the Feldenkraismethod all conceiveof one's breathine as a conduit fcrr emotion and consciousness. One'slungsexpandingand contracting,one'sheart beating,and one'spulse throbbing might all be experiencedin the dual capacity as subjective,as belonging to the self, or objective,when ascribedto the external. Munch's figures on the page might be drawn into one's own body might say suckecli n, or they might exercisetheir will on the observer,drawing him into their immensity.Such feelingswould be in keepingwith Munch's own experiencesof being forcefullyand palpabilitygripped by his own paintings. 3. Model of reinterpretation: The somatosensory system The effectsof the somatosensorysystemhave been central to long-standing discussionsof emotion and imagination.When we say we have a certain gut feeling we are referring to the visceralfunctions of the autonomic nervous system,those involving the regulationof musclesin the heart and lungs, the intestines,the blood vessels, the stomach,and the skin. My considerationof the somaticsystemalso includesour tactile sensatior.rs on the body's surface,and, from deeperinside, our prclprioceptivesensations,those detectingvibration Touchingart and spatialposition, as well as the kinestheticsensesof boclilymovement and baiance.Although the somaticsensationof temperatureis alsopertinentto this study, pain sensationsare less scl.If this vast network of systemswere not enough to consider,I augment it by addressingthe brain's own re-creationof such bodily states,as in the phantom limb experience.By consideringthese brain simulations, I can explore imaginary representationsas well as ftrlly embodiedphenomena. According to Damasio (1994) we have an ongoing awarenessof the somatosensorysystem.Noting that the brain continually receivesfeedback signalsfrom the body's autonomic processes, Darnasioarguesthat this feedback provides us with a constantbackground awarenessof our body's solrratosensory systems.This low levelof awareness,he claims, is akin to a mocld that colors our "The ordinary consciousness: backgroundbody senseis continuous,although one may hardly noticeit, sinceit represents not a specificpart of anythingin the body but rather an overallstateof most everythingin it" (p. 152). Even were this overall awarenessof the somatosensorysystemnot within our backgroundconsciousness, it would be reasonableto supposethat it can come into consciousness upon our inspectionof the artwork. As we look at the work we can attend to differentkinds of things - formal elements,like colors and lines, and subject matter, like balletsand lilacs. While engageclin such reflections,the body can become aroused- whether through curiosity with novel stimuli, through pleasure,or through associatedf'eelingsevokedby the subjectsof the artwork. This changein the body'smetabolismproducesa shift from the statusquo, which helps draw attention to the body. In short, whether through speci{icarousalgeneratedin responseto the artwork or thror-rghthe body's own continuous presenceto consciousness, we can becorneaware of somatosensorysensations. To explain how we reinterpret these bodily sensationsI build upon a processcharacterizedby Damasio as the sorrlrrf ic marker hypttthesis. Damasi<t arguesthat when we experiencesituationsthat affectus as positivelyor negatively, the particular somatosensorystateof our body becomesmarked with thesepositive or negativeevaluations.Thesemarked, or evaluated,bodily states alsobecomeassociated in memory with images(in any sensorymoclality)of the stimuli that triggeredthem. When we subsequentlyreexperiencetheseimages and their correspondingbodily states,we also reexperiencethe positive or negativeassociations that mark thesebodily states.For example,supposeyoll oncehad a negativeexperiencein the stockrnarketand are now thinking about making a risky investment.This past negativeexperienceis stored as irnages z4r z4z Ellcn I. Esrock with a specific,negativelyfelt body state.When posedwith that are associated this new financial opportunity, your body might produce an unpleasant internal feeling,which causesyou to p -eedwith caution. This so-calledgut feeling would actually be a negativell ,rlarked bodily state, associatedwith i m a g e so f r i s k yi n v e s l m e n l . l Basedon his work with brain-damagedpatients,Damasiohypothesizes that we Llsethesesomaticmarkersin the reasonir-rg As we can producethese p:rocess. boclily statesquickly, they might help us in sorting various possibilitiesand callingto attention options that havepotentialbenefitsor drawbacks.What we call intuition might be a reasoningprocessthat usesthesesomaticmarkers. My hypothesistakesDamasio'snotion of somatic markers a step further. WhereasDamasio claims that our somatic experiencesmight be rnarked as positiveor negative,I suggestthat they might alsobe marked,or reinterpreted, with specilic content. This content would be deriveclfi-onr the things we gaze upon. It might include such things as the fbrrnal elementsof the artwork - a chair,a flower,a chilcl,or blue dabs,repeatedlines,the objectsrepresented the emotionsand associations that the artwork evokes.(,az-ingintently at these works, we might have a bodily sensethat we do r-roteven recognize as bodily becauseit is reinterpretedas it arisesinto awareness. In fbrmulating his somatic marker theory, Damasio also points out that firll bodily circuits, body loops,need not be involved in our use of thesemarkers. The brain has the capacityto respond to a stimulus by creatingthe kind of brain statethat would be configuredwere a messageto havebeen receiveclfrom the full body. Called an as-if loop,this brain statepermits quicker changesin our registration of different somatic markers than would be possiblethrough use of the full body. I suggestthat the production of as-if loops might be particularly valuablein the arts experience,for it would permit rapid transitionsbetween bodily states,which might thereby keep up in tempo with the spectator's m o m e n t t o m o m e n t e x p e r i e n co ef t h e w o r k . ' What is central to my reinterpretationhypothesisis that these somatic markersfunction in two ways:They are markersof contentexternalto the bcldy and, more basically,they are markersof what is ir-rternal to us.'lb advancetl-ris hypothesisfurther, I suggestthat when we experiencethese somatosensory markers as internal, they convey something that, uncler certain definitions, would be a calleda senseof the se1f. Touchingart 24J 4. Model of reinterpretation: Concepts of the self Scientistsand humar-rists haveproposeddiversetheoriesof the self,ranginu in emphasisfrom neurobiology to cultural construction, and severalof these moclelsposit a connectionbetweentheir definitionsof selfanc'lthe somatosensory system.In respectof this connection,thesemodelsreinfbrcethe folk belief that the self,at leastthe so-calledemotionnlsefi is constitutedbywhat is deep insideof us, relatedto our somatosensorysystem.(lonventionalphraseslike ir takesnty ltreathaway or yoive stolenrny hecrr expressthe power of wl-ratis notselfto affectthe coreof the selfby its capacityto appropri.rteou r v isceralorgans. Although l do not intend to endorseany particular theory of selfhood, plausibleconnectionsbetweennotions of selfand the somaticsystemshcluldbe notecl,asthey might further explainthe viewer'ssenseof intimacy when gazing on objects.For example,when reinterpretingthe body I might feelnot just that my inner body is out in the world inside the object, but that 1 am out in the world insidethe object.This is not to suggestthat the processof bodily reinterpretationalwaysinvolvesa profoundmergerof selfwith object,as this seemstcr vary from encollnterto encounter.The impact of the link betweenthe somatic body and the self might simply be to prime the viewer to feel self-involved. It has been arguedfrom an evolutionaryperspectivethat certain som.rtosensoryrepresentations, as linked tcl the motor systern.constitute the oldest "Proprioception representations of the self.M. Sheets-fohnstone writes that in generaland kinesthesiain particularadvertto a knowing subject,a subjectthat, at minimum, knows when it is moving and knows when it is not" (1998, p.291). Proposingthe concept of a prirnitive self (SELF) linked to sensorymotor activity,JaakPankseppwrites: I advocate the positionthat the rootsofthc selfgobackto specificmesencepl-ralic anddiencephalic sensory-motor actioncircuitswithin tl-remarnmalian (an auton'ratizcd brain which can gcnt'ratca prinritivcsort of inter-rtionality (globalafltctive actionrcadiness) and primitiveformsof psychiccohcrcncc states of thc brain)by interactionwith variouscr.notionarl attcntionalcircuits tl.rater.rcode basicbiological valucs.( l99lt,p. 566-7) Whereas the subjectivedimension of self is illumir-ratedby Panksepp ancl Sheets-Johnstone's conceptsof the primitive self,the objectiveorientation of the selfto the externalworld is made clearerthrough Damasio'snotion clf Cclre which is one mode in a tripartite rnodel. Core CclnscioLlsness Consciousness, bestdescribesthe objectively-oriented self,assomaticallymodified by an object whose existencehas been located in time and space.In this rnode the self is 244 Ellenl. Esrock aware of itself as the subjectwhose awarenessis directed to an object in the world. Damasio'sdescriptionof the self'sengagementwith the object might characterizewhat, in the processof somaticreinterpretation,correspondsto a kind of absorptionof the self within the object. Certainly the allusion to T. S. Eliot'snotion of incarnationcarriesthis association.Describingthe experience of Core Consciousness, Damasiowrites: Ycruknow itis yousecing because thestorydepictsa character you- doing Youhardlynoticcthc storytelling theseeing.... because theirnages thatdon.rir-rate thementaldisplayarcthoscof tl"re thingsof whichyou arenow conscious - theobjectsyou sceor hear.. .. 1'.S.Eliotmightaswellhavebeenthinkingof theprocess ... whenhesaid'youarethemusicwhilethemusiclasts.' He wasat leastthinkingof thefleetingmomcntin whicha deepknowledge canemergc a unior.r, or incarnation, 1999,p.172) ashe calledit. (Damasio, In summary, our experienceof the somatosensorysystemcan be oriented in two polar directions.The {rrstand most basicis an orientation to the subjective world of the self.Our senseof blood pulsing,heart beating,heat changing,and so on are all associatedwith one'sown subfective,internal states.The second orientationis objective.It operatesthough a reinterpretingofone's background somatic experienceto stand for things in the externalworld. Together,these t w o o r i e n t a t i o ncso n s t i t u t e s o m a t i cr e i n t e r o r e t a t i o n . 5. Model of reinterpretation: Sensory polarities The polaritiesof subjectiveand objectivewithin the somatosensorysystemare reinforced by a more commonly recognizedbipolarity both within a single component of this system- the senseof touch - and within a different system not generallyascribedwith bipolar properties- the visual system.The visual system might be understood to have a bipolar orientation, although it is generallycharacterizedas providing us with knowledgeonly of the object world. In David Katz'sanalysisof colors,for example,he writes: Colorphcnomena arealwayscharacterized by objcctification; theyarcalways projected into cxternalspace.... Experiencing a colorpl-renontenon assubjectivc alwaysoccurson the basisof certainsecondary cucs.No matterhow d c c p l yo u r a t t c n t i o np c n e t r r t ei\n t o a s u b j e c t i vpch c n o m c n o lni k c i n t r i n s i c visualgrayor darklight,it nevergivesevena glimmerof whatwe readilyknow to be a stateof our own bodilysclf( 1989,p.aI ). Toucl-ring art 245 Although Katz explainsthat vision is oriented to the externalworld, there is a sensein which vision might alsobe understoodto havea subjectivedimension' As Damasiopoints out, a signalfrom the outside(like our visualperceptionof a tree) is recognizedboth as a signalindicating somethingof the outsideworld and a signal conveyingsomethingof the inner, bodily world, speci{ically,the placein the skin where the specialsignalentered the eye.He writes: you seeor hearexcitcsthc specialscnseof sightor soundas a Sornething "body"signalhailingfrom the placein "nonbody"signal,but it alsoexcites a siglalcntered.... Whenyou sce'you do not justsee: theskinwherethespecial (Damasio, 1994,p'232)' with youre1'cs something youfeelyouare seeing To this I would add that what is carriedby this signalis a connotationof the self with the bodily siteof the signal:the eye.Thus, we havesignals that is associated both of the objectiveworld and of the organ belongingto the self-asperceiving it. This personalsenseof the eyeasbodily givesvision a subjectiveconnectiotl, if only, I suggest,to prime it for subjectivity provoked by other senses.What givesthe visualsensea greatercapacityfor communicatingsubjectivemessages is its coordinationwith the senseof touch - real or imaginedtouch. Unlike vision, touch is regardedas a wholly bipolar sense.When experiencing touch as a conduit to the objectiveworld, we can pressa fingertip to our foreheadand feel the touchof an object- our forehead.Moreover,we can alscr - the feeling of a become awareof the subjectiveaspectof this same touch warm, internalsensationin our fingertip or foreheadwhen the contactis made: linkedto a componentthat refersto thebodyseemsinescapably A subjective secondcomponcntthat refersto the propcrtiesof objects'We therefore asbipolar.... At lny nlolncrlt'eitherthesubjcc tactualphenomenon describe perceptionmaybe dominant,but thisbipolarity tactual side of objective tiveor (Katz' p.4l ). 1989' persists ncverthcless The phenomenologyof Maurice Merleau-Pontyis relevanthere,although he is narrowerin the rangeof what he considersto be bodily than what I propose.f 4] Focusingon the arts, Merleau-Pontyarguesthat the bipolar nature of touch and vision permits spectatorsto lend their bodiesto the art objector the thing they gazeupon. For Merleau-Ponty,the eyecan seeits own body as an object in the "My body is a thing among things" ( 1964,p' 163)' For world, like other objects: such purposesvision exemplifiesthe objectivepolarity. It identifies objects,and one of theseidentilied objectsis the body. On the other hand, one has a sense of cloing the seeing- a senseof one's eye movements,the sensationsof a bodily self doing the seeing.This exemplifiesvision's subjective pole. By 246 EllcnJ. Esrock interchangingthe subjectiveand objective- as both are aspectsof the same sense'one'ssubjective,seeingselfbecomesan objectivething that existsin the with the subjecexternalworid as an object.The object world, now associated tive sell comesto existas part of the subjectiveworld of the self.'' A reversalaiso occursin the senseoftouch - the act oftouching and the "l feelof being touched. can feel myselftouched aswell and at the sametime as "There is touching" ( 1968,p. 142).Tbuch and vision blend together,such that evenan inscription of the touching in the visible,of the seeingin the tangible" (p. 143).In viewingpaintings,then, the senseof selfassociated with the eyethat touchesthe painting becomespart of the painting as an object,and qualitiesof the painting become incorporated into the self - self as constituted by a seeing/touchingeye. The hypothesisof somaticreinterpretationhas thus far been supportedby sketchingout its variouscomponents,someoperational,somenelrroanatomical. Although this constitutesthe major support for the hypothesis,the clarity of the hypothesismight be enhancedby illuminating it againstthe backdropof similar, more well-known theories, which contain concepts analogous to varitlus componentsof the reinterpretationhypothesis.Although the plausiblity and power of theseanalogousconceptscannot be transferrecldirectlyto the reinterpretationhypothesis,they can havean inc'lirectimpact, temperedby the extent to which one regardsthe comparisionsassubstantial.Theseindividual analogies In effect,the assemblage becomeevenmore persuasivein their convergence. of these analogousconceptsstrengthensthe credibility of the reinterpretation hypothesisand suggests other avenuesfor its clevelopment. 6. Converging concepts: Cognitive psychology Within the disciplineof cognitivepsychologythe theory that containsthe most closely related concept of reinterpretingsomatosensorystatesis attribution theory, which emerged during the 1960swith the experiments of Stanley Schachterand ]erome E. Singer (1962). Schachterand Singerinjecteclpeople with Epinephrineto raisetheir heart rate and bring about other physiological changes.Some of the subjectswere made awareof the effectsthat this would produce and others were not. Each of the groups was then piaced in social situationsthat were designedto evokeeither positive or negativefeelings.Those who were injected with the drug and not told of the physiologicaleffects describedtheir emotional responseto these situations as more emotionally Touching art positiveor negativethan did the other subjectsin the samecontexts.Schachter and Singerarguethat thosesubjectswho experiencedarousalbut did not know it was drug-induced attributed this physiological effect to the particular emotion that was most likely to be experiencedin that situation. In other words,thosewho did not know their arousalwas drug-inducedinterpretedthis arousalaspart of eithera positiveor a negativeemotion. By contrast,thosewho were aware of the side effectsof the drug reported havir-rgmllch less of an emotional responseto the samesituations. Although their findings have been challengedon various grounds, their conclusionthat emoticlnis producedby one'sinterpretationof what is happening in ar-ryspecific,socialsituation - one'sattribution, along with a general stateof bodily arousal,remainsa dominant explanatoryrnodel within psycholoey. What attribution theory has in common witl-rsomatic reinterpretationis that both involve an interpretive operation that we impose upon our own bodily sensations. With attribution theory,however,what one imposesis uot a quality of an external object but a feeling state, an emotion, and thus the interpretationdoesnot servethe function of changingour bodily boundaries. 7. Converging concepts: Psychoanalysis Freudiantheory containsa number of conceptsthat bear a closerelationshipto the proposednotion of bodily reinterpretation.Notably,there is the condition known as hysteria,a situation in which a person suffersa bodily allliction, such asblindness,paralysis,or memory lossthat doesnot appearto havean clrganic cause.In treating such patients, Freud concluded that the disabilitieswere producedby conflictswithin the mind involving the unconsciousand that the bodily alfliction was a symptom of an underlying problem that was psychological. Thus, with hysteriathe somatic body becomesmarked as a sign of a conflict existingin anotherdomain. In the caseof somaticreinterpretation,the body is also marked as a sign of somethingoutside of itself. However,in this casethe marked body is feh to becomethe specificthing that is represented,not only to mark it indexically,as with hysteria. Also relatedto the reinterpretationhypothesisare the key psychoanalytic notions of projectionand interjection.Accordingto psychoanalysis, projection occurswhen one'sown wishesand feelingsare ascribedto another person or object.Analogously,introjection occurswhen qualitiesof externalobjectsare ascribedto the self. Whereas the psychoanalyticnotion of projection and 247 248 Ellenf. Esrock introjection concernf-eelings and wishes,in the reinterpretationhypothesisthe spectatorengagesin theseboundary-alteringstrategieswith regardto a different range of object and self properties and with different motivations. As the psychoanalyticalconceptsof introjection and projection pertain to f-eelingsand wishes,there is not any transferof somethingspecificto a bodily system,as in the caseof the reinterpretationhypothesis.Furthermore, the reinterpreting spectatorexercisesmore volitional control over the transfersthan in cases where projection and introjection are psychoanalyticallyapplied. In both theories,however,the subjectascribesaspectsofthe selfor the non-selfto the other entity, thus shifting the boundaries of the self. 8. Converging concepts: Linguistics and the sensorimotor theory of perception Various linguistic theoriesutilize the notion of projection, and in thesecases what is projectedis relatedexplicitlyto bodily systems.Language,which offers numerousmetaphorsof boundary change,is saidto contain the framework frrr a deepand systematicuseof the body. Mark fohnson and GeorgeLakoff(19U7) arguethat this frameworkis build upon imageschemasof the body, a founding set of bodilymetaphors that orient us in time and space,with objects,ancl in social interactions(Johnson, 1987,p.29). In contrast to the caseof somatic reinterpretation,Johnsonand others do not describetheseprojectionsas online, moment-to-moment eventsthat a person experiencesbodily. Nonetheless, their conceptof image schemessupports the reinterpretation hypothesisinsof-ar as these schemasare based upon a belief in the importance of our bodily awarenessand the projection of this awarenessinto all domains of human experience,non-linguisticaswell as linguistic (Newton, 1996,p.22). Argumentsframed from a linguisticperspectiveabout the projection ofbodily imageryonto non-physicalactivitiesand conceptsmight be understoodwithin the broader context of a sensorimotor theory of perception, which readily accommodatesthe somaticreinterpretationhypothesis.Such a theory positsa "Perception deepconnectionbetweenmovement and perception: is simulated (Berthoz, action" 2000, p. l0). Differing in terms of where the origin of the motor intention is located- whether in a centrai or a peripheral source,all versionsof sensorimotortheory hold that the notion of live, independentsenses is misleading.Sensoryperception does not occur without the use of motor images,which are schemasof motor activity stored in memory and deployed in Touclring arr 249 connection with the various sensesto achievespecificgoals.Such motor images c a n b e c o m e c o n s c i o u s u n d e r c i r c u m s t a n c e sw h e r e o n e ' s u n c o n s c i o u s preparationsto perform a motor actionare frustrated(leannerod,1994,p. 190), as,I suggest,in casesof viewing art. Generallyplacedin situationswhere one is expectednot to touch the artwork, a spectatormight nonethelessengagein a kind of imaginative play with an object that consitutes a form of motor preparation,though it never resultsin action. The very lack of action would bring this motor preparationto awarenessas a motor image,which might be reinterpreted. Although the somatic reinterpretation hypothesis is not incompatiblewith other theoriesof perception,it is supported at a fbundational levelby the sensorimotortheory of perception. 9, Converging concepts: Phantom limbs The linal analogyis perhapsthe most interestingin its power to advancethe theory of somatic reinterpretation,though the researchis speculativein its original context. Exploring the phenonemon of phantom limbs, in which a subjectfeelssensationsin a body part that is no longer attachedto the body, V. S. Ramachandranand William Hirstein induce phantom limb type experiencein thosewith intact bodies.For instance,they report creatingcontextsin which a subjectfeelsas if his nose has been displacedto a different location. This illusion is createdby an experimenter taking the left index finger of the subject and tapping it on the faceof another person, who is sitting next to the subject,looking in the samedirection.The experimenterthen tapsthe subject's nose in exactlythe samepattern as that being usedwith the subject'sleft finger. They note that 12 out of l8 subjectsreportedthat their nose felt dislocated. Their explanation for this senseof displacementis that we take the similarityof patternedtapping on the nose and on the finger not to be coincidental. Thus, we unif, the two taps under one category, in accord with what they describe as Bayesianlogic (Ramachandran & Hirstein, 1997, pp.452 3). Concerning a relateddemonstrationhaving to do with a subject gazing in a mirror at a dummy's face, the experimenterswrite: "The subfect comes to experiencethe dummy's head as being his own to such an extent that it is now hooked up to his own limbic systemand autonomic output" (p.a53). The most striking demonstrationof this occursin an experimentin which Ramachandran and Hirstein had subjects rhythmically stroke chairs and tabletopswhile they were having their own hand strokedin the samerhythm. z5o Ellcn J. Esrock Although the subjectis stroking inanimate objects,she feelsthat the sensation explain: of his or her hand emanatesfrom theseobjects.The researchers Youwill startcxpcricncing tapsanclstrokes asemerging from thetablesurface though your consciousrnind krrowspcrfcctlywcll that this is logically ever.r improbabilityof thc two scqucnccs of taps absurd.Again,the sheerstatistical your hand leacl and strokcs onc sccnon the tablesurfaceanclone felt on (Ramachandran., thebrainto conclucie thatthetableis nowpartof yourbody 1998,p.60). & Blakeslee, "can From the evidencethat you actuallyproject your sensationsto external and Blakeslee objects"(Ramachandran& Hirstein, 1997,p.60), Ramachanclran "your concludethat body image, despiteall its appearanceof durabilty, is an entirely transitory internal construct that can be profoundly modihed with a f e w s i m p l et r i c k s " ( p . 6 2 ) . The claim that the boundariesof our body imageare malleableis consistent with viewsarticulatedby PaulSchilder(1950)and others.Although the reinterpretationhypothesisdoesnot seemto describesomethingas strikingly illusory as the feeling that one's nose has been displaced,it does involve manipr,rlating one'ssenseof bodily boundariesso asto givethe sensethat one inhabits things in the world. In this respect,Ramachandranand Hirstein's demonstrations support the hypothesisabout reinterpretingthe somatosensorysystem. Their demonstration, however, need not be used only to reinforce the generalclaim that body images are malleable.Concluding this section on a speculativenote, I raisethe possibilitythat the analysisof dual touchesin the demonstrationmight be applicablealso to the perceptionof visual art. fust as Ramachandranand Hirstein's subjectsmove their hands back and forth over a table top, so too, with the photo of Strand'sLeaves,the spectatorsmove their eyesback and forth over the leaves.In place of having an experimenter stroke the subject'shand in a pattern that correspondsto what the subjectis actually doing to the table, spectatorsof the artwork stroke themselves- imaginatively. They produce an imaginative,bodily stroking,which correspondsto what the spectator'seyes are doing with the photograph. Perhaps the coordination between a spectator'srhythmic eye scanning and rhythmic internal stroking changesthe spectator'sbodily relationshipto the art object." This sectionhas describeda number of theoriesfrom different disciplines t h a t b e a r s t r o n g a n a l o g i e st o c o m p o n e n t so f t h e s o m a t i c r e i n t e r p r e t a t i o n hypothesis.Theseinclude our use of the somatosensorysystemto represent somethingother than the body, the capacityof projection and introjection to Touching art 25r changethe boundariesof selfand object,the use of motor imagesin the act of visualperception,the projectionof one'smotor imagesinto the thing perceived and, finally,the malleabilityof the boundariesof body image and its displacements, through rhythmic movement, into tl-reobject world' Although these they both points are situatedwithin independenttheories,in their convergence clarify and strenghtenthe reinterpretationhypothesis' To exploremore fully the issuesraisedin this paper it would be helpful to expandthe Iimited and sometimesmisleadingdescriptionsof internal experiencethat are availablein our language- a problem noted by William Iames ( l g 1 g , p . 1 9 4 - 5 ) a n d r e i t e r a t e db y o t h e r s( J e a n n e r o dp, . 1 8 7 ) . T h i s i s a c c o m plishednot only by sharpeningour introspectivetechniquesand our analytical descriptionsbut also by broadeningthe questionsposed for experimentation and humanistic study. How might we better describethis senseof changing bodily boundaries and our production of motor images?Do traditional' scholarlydescriptionsof the imagination sufliceto describetheseexperiences? What kind of belief statesare are generated? Without losing the senseof the art object as directive,I suggestthat we might further exploreindividual differencesin bodily viewing experiences,in background skills, aptitudes,and personality types for trained viewers and makersof art, aswell as for collegestudentswho volunteer for psychologytests'; The study of empathy, originating in lgth century aesthetics,might be productively reexaminedin light of current cognitive neuroscienceresearchand humanistic scholarship. Similarly, the distinction between emotion and rationality - a dominant cultural construct that informs much art theory, might alsobe reappraised.In short, the possibilitiesare rich for exploring the subtle ways that we move our embodied selvesthrough the object world that envelopsus. Notes r. Theideaofprojectingone'sselfintoanobject-ernpathy-wasexploreclincicpthb of the lgth century.The traditions numberof writerswhoseworkis tiedto theintellectual ( l e r m a n R o m a n t i c p o e t s p r o v i d e d g e n e r a l n o t i o n s o f n ' r c r g e rw i t h n a t u r e , a n d a e s t h e t i c i a n s under thc l i k c R o b e r t V i s c l - r e r( l t t 7 2 ) a n c l T h e o d o r L i p p s ( 1 8 9 7 ) f u r t h e r d e v e l o p e d t h e i c l t - ; r name of errpat hy (EinJ'i.thlung).Though the bodily component becone more specific in tl-resc aesthetictheorics, their concepts rcflect the dominirnt philosophical ir-rfluencesof their culture. z. peter Munz examines the rclationship betwecr-rersomatic markcr ancl a verbal description o f i t i n C r i t i 4 u t o l l n p u r c R t ' a s o r (r i 9 9 9 ) . 252 Ellen J. Esrock the valueof as-ifbody loopswitl-rDonaldHoftman lPersonalconvers.ition, 3. In discussing February2 l, 2001], he pointedout that full-body circuitsmight alsobe valuablebecausethey might createa rich, complexlayeringof somatoscnsorl, experiences, much like William James'notion of consciousness. 4. Speakingto the narrownessof Merleau-Ponty'sbodily model, Drew Leder notes in Tfte "The AbsentBody, livedbody he IMerleau-Ponty] describes is nevercompletc.Thcreis little discussion of n-retabolism, visceralprocesses, birth, and death"(l.eder,1990,p.6). Whereas Ledergoeson to investigatethe way in which visceralprocesses arepowerful but nllsentfron-r "My awareness, corporeal depths disappearnot only from perception but relativeto my structureofwill and action" (p.a5),I explorehow theybecomepresentto consciousness. 5. Becausctheeyeoftheselfseesobjectsandthebodilyselfisanobject,sotoo,objcctssee "things thc self.This explainswhy, Merleau-Pontynotes, painterssay that look at them" (Visibleand the Invisible,p. 167). 0. If the changesin bodilv boundariesare effectedthrough some kind of internalized, rhythmicmotions,it would be interesting to exploremusicalrhythmsof viewingasa means of creatingout-of-body states.I refer to the intriguing work of William H. McNeill, Keeping Togetherin Tinre:Dnnceand Drill in Huntan History,and to Ellen Dissanayakc's provocative Art ontl Intitnocy:How the ArtsBegnn. 7. I intervieweda spectatorbeforea painting that I thought would readilyevokethe senseof a bodily line. Though thoroughly engagedwith the image,the viewer confessedthat he felt nothing somatically.Followinga hunch, I then askedhim to form a motor imageof himself taking somekind of action while playinga sport he liked - swinginga bat, kicking a ball. He repliedthat he wasn'tsurehe wasableto do it. He could seehimselfhitting a ball but could not feel himself performing the action. lt seemsto me that this was an individual who wirs producing visual imagery,a third personviewing of himself,and not motor imagery,a first personperspectivein which he is the performer.His seeminginability to form a motor image ofa sport he thoroughlyenjoyedreinforcesmy suspicionthat the somatosensory experiences ofthe sort I havedescribedarecloselyconnectedto a person'sskill in the creationofmotor images,the habitual choiceabout when to producethem, and the ability to recognizethem. lf this is the case,then,asI suggest, somaticreinterpretation would not be equallycommon to all viewers. References Abram, D. ( 1996).Thespellof thesensuous. New York: VintageBooks. Berthoz,Alain. (2000).Thebrain'ssenseof movetnent.Cambridge:Harvard UniversityPress. Damasio,A. R. ( 1994).Descartes error:Emotion,reason,ond thehurnonbraln.New York: G.P Putnam'sSons. (1999).Thefeelingof what happens: Bodyand emotionin tht:mokingof consciouyress. New York: Harcourt Brace& Co. Dissanayake, E. (2000).Art arul intimacy.Seattleand London:Universityof WirshingtonPress. Hoffman,D.D. (2001).PersonalInterview,February16. Touchingart 25J of psychology. V.l, New Yrrrk:DoverPublications. Jamcs,William. ( l9l8). Theprinciples "The Marc (1994). Representing Brain:Neural(lorrelates of Motor Intentionand Jeannerod, Imagcry." Behovioraland llrain Sciences, 17,p. 187-245. Johnson,M. (1987).The bodyin the tnind: The ltodilybnis o.fnrcnning,inngination,and reason.Ohicago:Universityof ChicagoPress. Katz, D. (1989).Tfte v,orldof lorrcfi(Krueger,LesterE., Trans.).Hillsdale,Nf: l.awrence Erlbaum Associates. l.akoff,G. (1987). Wornen,.fire, and dongerousthings:I{hot categories revr:nlobout the ntind. Chicago:Universityof ChicagoPress. Leder,D. (1990). The nbsentltody.Chicago:Universityof(lhicago Press. Lipps, T. (1897).Raumasthet ik und Geonetrisch-olttische Touschungen. Lcipz.ig]. A. Barth. McNeill, W.H. (1995). Keepingtogethcrin tirne: l)ance ond drill in hurnan history.Cam bridge,MA: HarvardUniversityPress. Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964).Theprimacyof perception: And Ltthercrr.i/i orrphenonrcnological psychology,the philosophyof art, history and politics. Northwestern: Northwestern UniversityPress. Merleau-Ponty, M. ( I 968). Thevisibleand thc inyisible(AlphonsoLingis,Trans.). Evanston: NorthwesternUniversity Press. Munz, P. (1999). Critirlue of impure reason:An essoyott neurotls,s<trtttrticrnarkers,ond const'.iousness. Westport,CN: Praeger. Newton,Natika.( I 996). Foundations of understandirig. lohn BenjaminsPublishingCompa ny. Amsterdam,The Netherlands. "The Panksepp,J. ( l99B). Periconscious Substrates ofConsciousness: AffectiveStatesand the " Evcrluticrnary Origins of thc Self. lournal oJ Consciousncss Sllr/lc-s,5(5-6), 566-5U2. Ramachandran,V.S.,& Blakeslee, S. ( l99B). Phanlomsin tlrc ltroin: Probingtlte ntysteries oJ. thehunranmind. Ramachandran, V.S.,& Hirstein,W. (1997)."ThreeLawsof Qualia:What NcurologyTells Us About the BiologicalFunctionsofConsciousness." Studles, JournalofConsciousness ,l (No.5-6),429-457. (Agee,f oel,Trans.). New York: Fromm International Rilke,R.M. ( I 985).Letterson Cezanne PublishingCorporation. "Cognitive, Schachter, S.,& Singer,]., E. (1962). Social,and Physiological Determinantsof EmotionalState."Pq,chological Review, 69 (5),379-399. Schilder,P. (1950). The imageand appearance o.fthe human ltody: Studiesin the ronstructit,t: energies of thepsyche.New York: InternationalUniversitiesPress. "Consciousness: Sheets-Jcrhnsone, M. (1998). A NaturalHistory."lounnl of Conscrousness Sru/ics,5(J). 260-2e4. Vischer,R. (1927).Drei Schriften zum Asthetischen Formproltle rn. Halle:Saale,M. Niemeyer. Author's address F,llenl. Esrock Departmentof [.anguage, Literature,and Communicatitrn, Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute,Troy,NYl2ltt0, U.S.A Guidelines for Contributors to Consciousnessand Emotion t Contributionsshouldnotexceed6000words.TheyshouldbeinEnglishfollowingtheAPAstyle.Ifnotwritten by a native speakerofEnglish it is advisableto have the paper checkedby a native speaker.Pleaseavoid excessive use offield-specihc terms, or add a short glossary. z. Manuscripts:Pleasesubmit 4 copiesof your paper, double spaced,with margins of 3 cm all round. The first page of a manuscript should contain the title of the article, the name, alfliation and addressof each author, followed by a self-containedabstractin English (max. I50 words), a short list ofkey words, and a biosketchofthe author(s). 3, Upon acceptancethe author will be requestedto send the final version on disk in any standard format, but preferablyin WordPerfect;or as an attachment,preferablyin MIME, UU, or Binhex encoding, and send a paper copy by mail. 4, Authors are responsiblefor observingth e laws of copyrighr when quoting or reproducing rnaterialfrom other sources.Thecopyright to articlespublished in Consciousness nnd Emotion rsheld by the Publisher.Permissionsfor the author to use the article elsewherewill not be withheld unreasonablyupon written request. 5. Papersshould be reasonablydivided into sectionsand, ifnecessary,subsections. 6. Spe//lngshould be American English consistentlythroughout the paper. 7. Line drawings (Frgures)and photographs (P/ates)should be submitted as reproducible originals or as TIF or EPS files accompanied by the creation file and a hard copy. They should be nurnbered consecutively and appropriate captions should be provided. Referenceto any Figuresor Plates(including captions to Figuresand Plates) should be made in the main text and an indication should be given where they should appear approximately. 8. Visual information and data that are not suitable for printing in the journal may be placed on C&E's accompanyingwebsite.Pleaseconsult with the Editors as to the necessityof such additional information. 9. Tn&lesshould be numbered consecutivelyand should be referred to in the main text. ro. Noresshould be kept to an absoluteminimum. They should be numbered consecutivelythroughout the paper. 'Notes' Notes should be listed in a section following the main text. rr. References: Referencesin the text should follow the style: (Brown, 1989,pp. 224-256). The References section shoulcl follow the notesand should list all referencescited in the main text. References should be listed ( 1) alphabeticallyand (2) chronologically.Authors' names and journal titles should be given in full with pagereferences.Examples: Books and unpublished manuscripts/theses Lightbrun, L.T. (1995). The relation of critical fusion frequency ro agc. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, U n i v e r : i t yo f N e w l e r . e y . Niemeier, S. & R. Dirven (Eds.) (1997). Tlrc Languageof ernotions.Amsterdam & Philadelphia:.lohn Benjamins. Sperber,D. & D. Wilson (1986/1995).Relevance: Communicotionand cognition.Oxford: Blackwell. Article in book/journal Ziv, O. (1,996).Writing to work: How using e-mail can reflect technological and organizational change. In S. Herring (Ed.), Computer-mediatedcommunication: Linguistic, sociol ond cross-culturalperspectives Qp. 2a3-26\. Arnsterdam & Philadelphia:.[ohn Benjamins. A t k i n s o n ,R . C . , & R . M . S h i f f r i n ,( 1 9 7 1 ) .T h e c o n t r o l eo f s h o r t t e r m m e m o r y . S c i e n t i J iAcm e r i c a n , 2 2 5 , 8 2 - 9 0 . Pleaseconsult the PublicatiotrManual of the Americnn Psychological Association4th ed. for details. rz. Authors are kindly requestedto check their manuscripts very carefully before submission in order to avoid delays and extra costs at the proof stage.Once a paper is acceptedfor publication, it will be allocated to a forthcoming issue and the author will receive two copies of page proofs of his/her contribution for hnal correction. These must be returned to the Editor with corrections by the dates determined by the publication schedule.Any author's alterationsother than typographical correctionsin the pageproofs rnay be chargedto the author. r3. Authors (first named) of articleswill receivea complimentary copy and 30 olfurints of the issuein which their paper appears. r4. Manuscripts and all editorial correspondenceshould be sent to The Editor, Ralph D. Ellis, P.O.Box 81, Clark Atlanta University,Atlanta, GA 30314,U.S.A.E-mail: [email protected]