Stomach Punch: Boxing with Archimedes 1 It`s a knockout
Transcription
Stomach Punch: Boxing with Archimedes 1 It`s a knockout
Stomach Punch: Boxing with Archimedes ABC 1 It’s a knockout Dissection Problems The above paradoxes naturally suggest the consideration of dissection problems. An excellent typical example is to cut a square into 20 equal triangles, and conversely to construct a square of 20 such triangles. There is an interesting historical example of such a problem. Two late Latin writers, Victorinus and Fortunatianus, describe an Archimedean toy composed of 14 ivory polygons which fitted exactly into a square box, and they suggest that the puzzle was to fit the pieces into the box. A recent discovery [1899 in [33]] has shown that its association with the name of Archimedes is due to the fact that he gave a construction for dividing a square into 14 such pieces (namely, 11 triangles, 2 scalene quadrilaterals, and one pentagon) so that the area of each piece is a rational fraction of the area of the square. His construction is as follows: let ABCD be the square, and E, F , G, H, the midpoints of the sides AB, BC, CD, DA. Draw HB, HF , HC, and let J, K, L be the mid-points of these lines; draw AKC cutting HB in M , and let N be the mid-point of AM , and P the mid-point of BF . Draw BN . Draw AP cutting HB in Q. Draw P J. Draw BL, and produce it to cut DC in R. Draw F L cutting AC in S. Draw LG. Rub out AQ and BL. The remaining lines will give a division as required [see Figure 1(i)], each figure being an integral multiple of 1/48th of the square. Why Archimedes propounded so peculiar a division it is impossible to guess, but no doubt the problem has a history of which we are ignorant. W. W. Rouse Ball [3, p. 54] A mathematical formula is eternal. But a winning formula, in order to stay a commercial proposition, remains forever new and improved, changing with changing tastes. Mathematical books also have their market share. So the book we know today as Mathematical Recreations and Essays [3], by Walter William Rouse Ball (1850–1925), has enjoyed continuing popularity for over a century, making the grade as a landmark [31] of early modern mathematics. But Ball himself reworked it considerably through frequent editions, and a more abrupt and thorough-going change occurred when Harold Scott MacDonald Coxeter (1907–2003) took it over for the 1 11th edition in 1939. Indeed, a retrospective review [4, (b)] of the 12th (1974) edition, now presented as the joint work of Ball and Coxeter [4, (a)], cautioned “changes have been so great, one should not discard earlier editions”, although being of the view that later editions contained “much more material of real mathematical interest”. F C P B S Q G L K J E R M N D H A (i) After Suter (ii) Ausonian elephant ? Figure 1: Stomachion The changes over this comparatively short time frame may increase our appreciation, not only for what remains to us of the works of Archimedes (?287–212), but also that the acknowledged difficulty of these works makes it likely that they have been less altered at the hands of transcribers and editors than the Elements of Euclid (?325–?265). The historical irony here is that presumably Ball’s account of the Stomachion — Ostomachion or loculus of Archimedes — was considered in 1939 of lesser mathematical interest and so dropped by Coxeter. Ball’s comment that “no doubt the problem has a history of which we are ignorant” is hardly a ringing endorsement and, for all that he describes the research [33] of Heinrich Suter (1848–1922) published in 1899 as “recent”, he did not include it in Mathematical Recreations and Essays at his first opportunity, the 4th edition in 1905. While saving space by not reproducing Suter’s diagram, Ball did revise the labels in the passage quoted above, a departure in which we follow him, beginning in Figure 1(i). Clearly Coxeter cannot be expected to have known that progress in imaging technology would make it possible to read more of the palimpsest now familiarly known as the Archimedes Codex than had been managed when Ball wrote, and certainly he was correct in that regard during his own long life. It was only in 2004 that news [23] broke of a novel proposal that the Stomachion was an early exercise in combinatorial mathematics, an interpretation since set out more accessibly in [24, Chap. 10]. This development would surely have appealed to both Ball and Coxeter, with their strong inclinations towards the mathematics of counting. But re-acquaintance with Ball’s text reminds us that it had been suggested that the puzzle was to fit the pieces back into their box long before the combinatorial considerations of [23, 24] entered the picture. Indeed, Ball’s contempory, James Gow (1854–1923) — like 2 Ball, a lawyer as well as a Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge — had already footnoted this view of the Stomachion in 1884 in his standard Short History of Greek Mathematics [13, p. 243, n. 3]. By contrast, Thomas Little Heath (1861–1940), their junior who made more of a speciality studying Greek mathematics, only speculated rather vaguely, in his study [15, p. xxii] of the works of Archimedes, that the phrase “loculus Archimedius” perhaps meant little more than it was cleverly made, in much the way Archimedes’ name had become a byword for any taxing problem. However, this comment predates Suter’s publication [33] by a couple of years — from our later perspective, including the first publication of material from Archimedes Codex by Johan Ludvig Heiberg (1854–1928), not to mention the latest tranche in [23, 24], it is instructive to see how these earlier authors recycle their phraseology in expressing a shared ignorance. Instead, when Heath came to review [17, (b), p. 51] Heiberg’s volume [17] containing material on the Stomachion, he drew the analogy with “a sort of Chinese puzzle”. By about the same time, Fritz Kliem (1887-1947?) was able to add more information about the Stomachion to the German edition [16, (a)] of Heath’s book. (i) pieces turned over (ii) no turning over Figure 2: The irregular hexagon However, if it had been a “common game to put [the pieces of the Stomachion] together again into the original square [of ivory from which they had been cut]”, as Gow suggests, even the Archimedean difficulty of this task could hardly have prevented players from noticing that the pieces fit together into a square in more than one way. So, a combinatorial interpretation brings with it a puzzle of its own: why had no one thought to mention it before? After all, it had been a commonplace to remark, with mixed amazement and frustration, on the myriad free-form figures that it is possible to shape with the pieces (compare Figures 1(ii) and 2). Could it have been that there was some restriction on how the pieces were to be played? Another traditional explanation of the Stomachion is that, although it could foster such creativity, yet it had the more serious purpose of helping children to strengthen their powers of memory and, more specifically, those of pattern recognition. But unless the idea was to learn all 17,152 solutions by heart, this in turn might suggest homing in on relatively few, perhaps just one, of those many theoretically possible ways of completing this square. 3 2 Out for the count The principal halvings of the Stomachion board lend it something of the appearance of a coat of arms on a shield — in the terminology favoured in heraldry party per pale for the vertical division; party per bend for the main diagonal; and party per chevron reversed for the v-shaped cut (see Figure 6). The purpose of these divisions in heraldry is to achieve, through marshalling and differencing the elements of the coat of arms, a unique identity for the bearer of those arms. Naturally, the elements in any heraldic composition are displayed face outwards. If the pieces of the Stomachion were fashioned in such a way as to allow obverse and reverse to be distinguished, then presumably they too would uniformly face outwards on being placed back in their box. F C S L K H (i) (ii) (iii) Figure 3: Changing orientation As it happens, the pieces of the Stomachion board in Figure 1(i) can be slid into position on the plane of the board to form the Ausonian elephant in Figure 1(ii) without any being turned over. To put this observation another way, if the elephant is to march to the right rather than to the left, all the pieces have to be turned over. Of course, it may be that a stronger sense of pattern can be imparted to a Stomachion dissection if pieces are allowed to be turned over than if not, as in the case of the irregular hexagon in Figure 2 — here and in subsequent figures, pieces that have been turned over are marked with a black spot. With an essentially empirical observation of this kind, the argument cuts both ways. For, if some classically described shape is found to require that some pieces be turned over in order to achieve it in a Stomachion dissection, then that is evidence that turning over pieces was countenanced at least in this constructive play. Still, it helps to avoid turning over pieces in creating shapes that one of the four congruent right triangles into which the board is partitioned is cut so that the pieces can also form a congruent right triangle having opposite orientation (see Figures 3(i) and (ii); other ways to reattach the pieces so that edges match are possible, too, as in Figure 3(iii)). Moreover, the sharpness of the angles of some of the pieces perhaps gives an incentive not to turn pieces over. There may be difficulty enough to work those angles in such materials as ebony, horn or ivory. But sliding the pieces would help minimise wear and tear on both pieces and players. It is instructive to compare the situation with that of Tangram, as most likely the 4 (i) double square (iii) single square (ii) two squares Figure 4: Tangram “Chinese puzzle” Heath had in mind. For a start, the pieces in Tangram are all much more well-rounded, with no sharp angles. But, in any case, only one, the rhomboid, lacks mirror symmetry. Consequently, in order to change the orientation of a Tangram design, it is enough to turn over this piece, while sliding the others into place. Alternatively, we might convene a standard orientation for our Tangram pieces and avoid turning pieces over altogether. Although Tangram has the mystique of antiquity, there seems to be little or no evidence of it before the opening in the early 1800s of more extensive contacts between China and Europe through seaborne export trade (see [32]). There is some suggestion of a much older Chinese tradition of tiles coloured only on one side. This might have helped reinforce a seeming preference on the part of Liu Hui (220–280) to take right triangles paired as rectangles rather than singly when commenting on the Jiu Zhang Suan Shu, a compilation of problems already a classic in his day. For the transformation of a single right triangle into an L-shaped trysquare (gnomon or carpenter’s square) of equal area illustrated in Figure 5 requires pieces to be turned over, which would be conspicuous if they were coloured only on one side, whereas this can be avoided by working instead with right triangles paired into rectangles. This could account in turn for using the diameter of the inscribed circle of such right triangles, not the radius. So, it is fairly natural to wonder how many ways there are of putting the Stomachion pieces back together again as a square without turning any over , especially as this is not mentioned in [23, 24]. Here we adopt the naive approach of our beginning heraldry lesson, coupled with a little elementary group theory concerning cyclic groups Cn of order n = 2, 4 and the dihedral group D4 of order 8. We might notice that the four congruent right triangles into which the shield is divided are marked 5 (i) right triangle (ii) trysquare Figure 5: Right triangle and trysquare by distinctive fractions of the main diagonal, but a touch of colour adds realism. Each rectangular half of our shield can be given a half turn in the plane of the board independenly of the other, producing the pictorial representations in Figures 6(i)–(iv), in effect a realisation of the Klein four-group or Vierergruppe, C2 × C2 . But the two rectangular halves may also be exchanged, to yield a second set of four designs in Figures 6(v)–(viii), which are, however, the first set turned upside-down in the plane of the board in reverse order, so that the whole group of eight looks the same either way up. Thus, although each of the operations of rotating the left rectangle (λ), rotating the right rectangle (ρ) and exchanging the two rectangles (η) is an involution, yet the group they generate has elements of order 4, so is not isomorphic to C2 × C2 × C2 . Indeed, with σ = λη, as ρη = ηλ, we find that ρ2 = σ 4 = ǫ, where ǫ is the identity operation leaving the shield unchanged, while ρσρ−1 = σ −1 . We can therefore take ρ and σ as the generators of this group, thereby identifying it as D4 . For that matter, any design can be rotated in this plane so that the chevron is couched dexter or sinister, as well as upright and reversed, giving in total four variants — the results in the case of Figure 6(i) appear in Figures 7(i)–(iv) and provide an illustration of the cyclic group of order four, C4 . Finally, there are two pairs of congruent pieces that can be interchanged independently of one another without turning any over, producing a further set of four variants, as illustrated in Figures 8(i)–(iv) on starting with Figure 6(i), in what is yet another instance of the Klein four-group. It might be noted here that, while △CLG and △JBP are congruent, they have different orientations, so they can only be swapped if turning pieces over is allowed. Each of the four patterns in Figure 7 can be developed in four variants as in the first row of Figure 6; and then each of these 4 × 4 = 16 patterns admits four further variants as in Figure 8. All told, there are 4 × 4 × 4 = 64 designs that can be obtained by a combination of these ways of rearranging the elements of the shield. Naturally enough, in these 64 designs, the division into two rectangles is invariant. But it is also noticeable that the v-shaped cut remains intact. However, all three 6 (i) (ii) (iii) (iv) (v) (vi) (vii) (viii) Figure 6: An instance of D4 (i) (ii) (iii) (iv) Figure 7: An instance of C4 principal halvings of the board are preserved only in the quartet in Figures 7(i)– (iv). Therefore, played this way, the Stomachion puzzle might well help strengthen our ability to reconstruct distinctive features in a pattern. Yet, even under this comparatively restrictive regime, it is readily apparent that there is a muliplicity of ways in which the Stomachion pieces can go back in their box. 3 Squaring off At this stage a more pervasive doubt might creep in concerning what we know about the Stomachion — and by no means just because the Greeks’ enthusiasm for wrestling might leave boxing beyond the π άλη. To begin with, when we turn to look up the allusion Decimus Magnus Ausonius (c. 310–395) makes to the Stomachion, we find in an appendix [11, (a), pp. 395–397] that the elephant in Figure 1(ii) is 7 (i) (ii) (iii) (iv) Figure 8: An instance of C2 × C2 the production of the translator and editor, Hugh Gerard Evelyn-White (1884– 1924), fashioned expressly in emulation of the Tangram figures displayed in a then recently published popular book of mathematical amusements [9, p. 43]. EvelynWhite was a classically educated archaeologist who had excavated in Egypt (his early death, aged forty, elicited poignant obituary notices [11, (b,c)]). So, it may be more significant that he notes [11, (a), p. 395, n. 3] that the Arabic text setting out the Stomachion board is unpointed , saying at first, by way of cautious gloss, only that the board is a parallelogram and then, after the mention of right angles, that it is a rectangle, although he continues to represent the board diagramatically as the square in Figure 1(i). Reverting to Suter’s article from two decades earlier, we find that Suter also allows [33, p. 494, n. 6] that the construction he presents works for any parallelogram and that the presence of right angles is made clear only in the course of the Arabic text. But it is clear that there is a problem with this footnote — a copying or typesetting error, if nothing else. However, Suter may, more seriously, have confused “twice” for “equals”: he volunteers [33, p. 498, n. 30] that the two expressions are sufficiently close for confusion; and an unpointed text exacerbates just such uncertainty. For all that the text from the Archimedes Codex is more fragmentary than what is available in Arabic, yet the evidence from the first proposition is much more clear cut, always assuming it to apply to the Stomachion board. As Heiberg [17, pp. 416– 424] sets it up, this first proposition tackles the angles at M in the representation of the board in Figure 1(i). Beginning with a square, the construction doubles one side, in effect creating a double square. Eduard Jan Dijksterhuis (1892–1965), in coming to tidy away the “varia” [8, (a), pp. 66–70, Figs. 168, 169] remaining from his extended study of Archimedes, concurred in this construction some thirty years later, although he does not fill out the double square as completely as Heiberg. But research can be a tricky business, faute de mieux . A prepared mind — les esprits préparés — is some advantage, as Pasteur appreciated, but an overly trained, or perhaps strained, mind is apt to prove a hindrance. Hence, Paul Erdős (1913–1996) improves on Pasteur with his dictum that research favours the open brain that still allows observations to speak to it — as Erdős never tired in pointing out, Crookes, although a gifted experimentalist who invented the cathode ray tube, noticed only that these tubes were hazardous for photographic film stored in their proximity, 8 F C P B S G R L Q E J K M N D A H (i) double square (ii) single square Figure 9: Stomachion revised leaving it to Röntgen to discover X-rays (compare [29]). As recounted in [30, pp. 151– 152], Erdős took this story to heart, personally holding it against himself that he had “missed ” discovering Extremal Graph Theory, but also because in his view Röntgen’s discovery changed the whole direction of Physics, towards the development of the Atomic bomb. So, too, if less momentously, Heiberg, and later Dijksterhuis, saw a disparity between the content of their Greek and Arabic sources, but did not put one and one together. In between, however, an outsider, the distinguished geologist, Richard Dixon Oldham, FRS (1858–1936), to whom is due the inference in 1906 that the Earth has a core of determinable radius, recognised that the two sources were brought into agreement on supposing that the Stomachion was set out on a double square board, as in Figure 9(i), rather than Suter’s square. Oldham had been researching the history of the Rhône valley, when he came upon references to the loculus of Archimedes. His letter [25, (b)] to Nature in March, 1926 brings the same practical commonsense to this new topic as he already showed in what seems his first contribution to the columns of Nature, another letter [25, (a)], in May, 1884, accounting for the presence of double-storied houses and concave roofs in the area of the Himalayas where his work with the Indian Geological Survey had taken him. Perhaps it was exactly this quality of mind that facilitated his penetrating insights even where his professional scientific interests were not primarily engaged, as he always presented himself as a somewhat reluctant seismologist, despite the acclaim accorded his research. Thus, for Harold Jeffreys (1891–1987), who capped Oldham’s work on the Earth’s core by arguing that it must be molten, Oldham had been “the only man I ever met who did first rate work in a subject that disinterested him” (for further information on Oldham’s professional work, see [25, (d,e,f)]). For Heath and Evelyn-White, Stomachion had about it something of a “Chinese puzzle”, and Oldham’s double square makes the resemblance with the tangram board more marked, and perhaps more marketable — aficionados of board games might have us recall that rithmomachy was played for at least half a millennium on a double rectangular board, usually the double chess board, but sometimes an 8 by 9 14 square grid (for a brief account of this family of games, see [10, Chap. 17]; further historical detail is provided in [22]). At all events, Oldham was clearly experienced in fingering fault lines, and his letter in 1926 triggered a Stomachion jitter, with kits of Stomachion pieces available commercially, and a write-up in The New York Times that August. This may have been more than fifteen minutes of fame, but, again, the historical irony is that it did not register with Coxeter in 1939, still less with Dijksterhuis in 1943 — indeed, a research item [25, (c)] on puzzle crazes in Nature early in 1927 makes no mention of Oldham’s letter from only the previous year. The retrospective postscript [8, (c), p. 439] of work on Archimedes after Dijksterhuis does pick up the identification of another literary allusion to the Stomachion, this time in a more celebrated composition, De Rerum Natura by Titus Lucretius Carus (c. 99 –c. 55), the subject of a learned note [26] where diligent readers can find reference to Oldham’s letter. But unfortunately this kind of referential memory is not in general transitive, although Oldham’s letter has been recalled as recently as 2000 in [21, (b,c)], seemingly on account of [26] (the double square Stomachion board is also mentioned favourably, if only in passing, in [32, (a), p. 11], copyrighted in 2001). Almost needless to say the possibility of any alternative to Figure 1(i) does not feature in [24, Chap. 10]. Yet, this confronts us more clearly than it did for Oldham, or even for Dijksterhuis. For, whereas Dijksterhuis printed his figures only on the same page of his original article [8, (a), p. 69], today we have them juxtaposed side-by-side in English translation [8, (c), p. 411, Figs. 169, 170]. On the other hand, whatever Oldham’s many skills, he was not a geometer. Indeed, he was impatient of the received geometrical details of the Stomachion board in the interests of enhancing free-form play, revising the construction so as to make LR the production of P L, rather than of BL as in the Arabic text — in this he reveals the limitations of his approach, an issue to which we return in the next section. But, having expressed concern at the practical difficulties inherent in the “very acute angles” of Suter’s board, Oldham is naturally pleased by the relief to be gained in this regard by stretching the board laterally into a double square. However, he misses a more telling geometrical argument in favour of the double square board. For, whether it be 6 ANB or 6 MNB that is obtuse depends on where N stands in relation to the foot B ′ of the perpendicular from B onto AC. On Suter’s square board, there is no question about this, as B ′ = K, the centre of the board, ensuring that already 6 AMB is obtuse, so that 6 ANB can only be yet more obtuse. In contrast, on the double square board in Figure 9(i), not only is B ′ not identified, 6 AMB is now acute, meaning that M is on the far side of B ′ to A. Thus, the first proposition of the palimpsest is much more in contention, the question being whether N is still between A and B ′ . Sad to say, Evelyn-White’s Ausonian elephant in Figure 1(ii) does not survive the lateral stretching of the board, although Oldham, for whom the working elephant equipped with howdah was no doubt a familiar sight during his time in India and Burma, musters a more than passable replacement. But there are more subtle consequences for other constructions. For example, with the pieces from the double square board, as indicated in Figures 10(i) and (ii), the irregular hexagon resembling that in Figure 2 is both more elongated and requires the turning over of some pieces — the best we can do without turning over pieces is the hexagon in Figure 10(iii) 10 (i) (ii) (iii) Figure 10: More irregular hexagons with pairs of parallel sides of three different lengths, not two. Since the Stomachion pieces from the double square board are, like the Tangram pieces, more well-rounded, there is not the same objection to turning over pieces anyway. So, the conclusion is that on the double square board turning over pieces would likely be allowed. As it happens, Oldham’s version of an elephant reproduced in Figure 11(i) requires just one piece to be turned over, the pentagon, all of whose angles are right angles or larger. If this piece is not turned over, the result is to give the elephant a higher tail, as in Figure 11(ii), where Oldham’s modified construction of the Stomachion board has also been repealed. (i) original (ii) restored Figure 11: Oldham’s elephant A more serious casualty may be the combinatorial conjecture. For, again as with the Tangram pieces in Figure 4, the double square board allows us the choice of filling in that board or, with a nod to Socrates’s dialogue with the slave in Plato’s Meno, the single square in Figure 9(ii). To be sure, both give rise to enumeration problems of theoretical interest. It is just that now the recognition of how the pieces fit together into four congruent isosceles right triangles might seem the more pressing task. 11 4 Weighing in In this final section, we turn to an Archimedean theme that seems to have been neglected in discussions of the Stomachion, perhaps because the texts, fragmented as we have them, do not provide a steer in this direction. But, whichever board the Stomachion was set out on, there is no mistaking the curious abundance of triangle centroids, a feature absent in contrast in the Tangram dissections in Figure 4. We see in Figures 12(i) and (ii) that S is the centroid of △HCF and that correspondingly Q is the centroid of △AF B. Moreover, S is also the centroid of △BDC, echoed in △DBA by M (see Figure 12(iii)). Once we discover this property of the Stomachion board, we might also notice that there are virtual centroids, too. For the erased construction lines AQ and BL intersect BN and F H respectively in the centroids of triangles △ABM and △BCH. It might also be remarked, for what it is worth, that the lines on the board defining H ensure that it is the centroid of △BKB1 , where B1 is such that A is the midpoint of BB1 ; and then, in turn, M is the centroid of △BCB1 . F C F P B S C S Q K L B J M A H (i) D (ii) A (iii) Figure 12: Centroids on the Stomachion board Now, it is sometimes said that, while Archimedes knew that the three medians of a triangle are concurrent at the point of common trisection, no complete, strictly geometrical proof has come down to us from the Greeks (see, for example, [1, p. 23, n. 60a; p. 54, n. 109]. This is all the more remarkable because in Equilibrium of Planes I.15 , the final, climactic proposition of that work, Archimedes [15, pp. 189– 190, esp. pp. 201–202] gives a stronger result locating the centre of gravity of a uniform plane trapezial lamina. This proposition implies that the centre of gravity of a uniform plane triangular lamina lies at the common trisection point of the medians of the triangle, except that, in the course of his proof for the trapezium, Archimedes [15, p. 202] makes tacit uses of the result for triangles. Moreover, after Archimedes a certain vagueness sets in, with Heron (?10–?75), and even a writer as late as Jordanus de Nemore (1225–1260), speaking of a point from which lines to the vertices of a triangle trisect the triangle’s area. Archimedes’ understanding of the way the medians trisect one another is regained by Leonardo Pisano (Fibonacci, 1170–1250). But the concurrency of the medians of a triangle can still excite interest 12 (see [14] for a recent instance and [5] for a characterisation of the medians in terms of the triangle they form). 1 1 1 2 1 1 1 1 1 2 (i) three medians (ii) two medians Figure 13: Dissections of triangles by medians Of course, the presence of several centroids on the Stomachion board might be considered merely an artefact of the definition, phrased as it is in terms of midpoints. But midpoints are conspicuous in Figure 4 without producing triangle centroids. Perhaps more instructively S, as the centroid of △HCF , is defined by one pair of medians, but looking over to the congruent triangle △AF B we find Q is the intersection of a different pair of medians, as though to remind us of the concurrency of the three medians. However, the most singular benefit these centroids confer is to make short shrift to the determination discussed in the Arabic text of the fourteen fractions into which the Stomachion board is divided, both centroids and fractions being preserved under a lateral stretch, as from Figure 1(i) to Figure 9(i). In the first place, the medians of a triangle divide it into six parts of equal area, as in Figure 13(i). Next, suppressing any one of these medians leaves four regions dividing the triangle in the proportions indicated in Figure 13(ii). Since △HCF occupies a quarter of the Stomachion board, an immediate application of Figure 13(ii) tells us that △CSL and △F KS each account for one twentyfourth of the board, while △CF S and the quadrilateral HLSK each take up double that. As noted in Section 2, there are two pairs of congruent pieces with the same orientation — △HKM with △F KS and △AHM with △CF S. So, now we know how much of the board these two further triangles represent. A second application in △AF B reveals that △P BQ is another twentyfourth of the board. After this, the fractions for the remaining seven pieces fall out quickly. Moreover, if we restore the erased construction lines for the Stomachion board, we obtain a dissection in twenty one pieces, rather than fourteen. But the determination of their proportional areas is eased with the aid of the analogue of Figure 13(ii) shown in Figure 14(i). A closely related observation is that the central triangle in the dissection in Figure 14(ii) occupies one seventh of the containing triangle. This observation is sometimes associated with Richard Phillips Feynman (1918–1988), leading to speculation as to its origin (see [6, esp. (e)]; compare [7, p. 211], publicised in [12]). So, it may be worth remarking that Thomas Rudd (d. 1656) includes 13 1 35 5 25 25 3 27 10 18 18 10 5 1 5 42 1 (i) Stomachion ? (ii) Feynman ? Figure 14: Further dissections of triangles a problem of this sort among the hundred problems appended to his Practical Geometry [28] of 1650. Rudd borrowed heavily from a Dutch source published in the early 1600s, but his Question 67 is not to be found there (which may or may not account for the misprint of CD for ED). However, in the way that it uses interlocking (5, 12, 13) and (8, 15, 17) Pythagorean triangles with common right angle and helpfully scaled by a convenient factor of 7, it is not untypical of how problems of the period were constructed. Quest. 67. There is a Triangle ADC, whose sides are known, AC is 84, AD 105, DC is √18081: In this Triangle is drawn two lines out of the angles C and D to the opposite sides, as EC and DB, these crosse one another in the Triangle in the point F , and BD is 119, and doth divide AC into two unequall parts, whereof AB is 56, and BC 28, In like manner doth CE 91 divide AD in unequall parts, AE 35, and CD [sic] 70. The Question is: How far the point F is distant from B or E? Naturally the area of the central triangle, as indeed that of other such subdivisions, can be computed more generally in terms of ratios in which lines drawn from the vertices of the triangle cut opposite sides. Edward John Routh (1831–1907), in his Treatise on Analytical Statics [27, Chap. IV, Art. 132, p. 89; 2nd ed., p. 82] of 1891, observed how areas of this sort “often occur” (the citation in [7] leads to the later dating of 1896 in [12]). Good Cambridge coach that he was, he made up for not having previously met the general formula for the area of the central triangle by presenting it in a careful footnote to his discussion of reactions at joints (compare [7, pp. 211, 219–220] and [6, (b)]). However, about a quarter of a century after Rudd’s book, in 1678, Giovanni Ceva (1648–1734) published the case where these lines are concurrent, so that this triangle vanishes, in the theorem that now bears his name. As it happens, Routh’s more general formula can be derived using a related theorem of Menelaus of Alexandria (c. 70–140), one that Ceva also proved on his own account; in fact, the two results, Menelaus’ and Ceva’s, are equivalent. But Routh 14 (i) Title page. (ii) Question 67 Figure 15: Thomas Rudd’s Practical Geometry, 1650 mentions neither Ceva nor Rudd, still less Menelaus. Strangely enough, the gist of Ceva’s theorem does not appear to have registered in English until well into the next century, when it was set as the Prize Question [2, (a)] in the Ladies’ Diary for 1735, communicated by Samuel Ashby, the author of The Young Analyst’s Exercise (1737; 2nd ed., 1741), a “choice collection of a hundred algebraical problems”, in much the same expository tradition as Rudd. It seems to have taken another century, in the 1830s, about the time Routh was born, before authors in English notice that others elsewhere show prior knowledge of it. But then, as pointed out in [18, (a), pp. 9–10], Abū ‘Āmir Yūsuf ibn Ah.mad ibn Hūd, Al-Mu’taman (d. 1085), in Al-Andalus, had already proved this theorem some six hundred years ahead of Ceva. Whether or not Al-Mu’taman would have accepted Ceva’s appeal to levers in proving the result, it might have brought a smile of recognition to Archimedes, as perhaps also to Routh, given his applied bent — that such mechanics retains its appeal today is seen in the neat proof of Routh’s generalisation given in [19]. It is quite another matter whether any of this really has bearing on the Stomachion board. But it brings us to a final link between the mechanics of centres of gravity and the angles on the double square Stomachion board. Notwithstanding Oldham’s inclination to revise the alignment of LR, the construction as it stands meshes well with the theme of fitting angles together to make right angles or straight lines with which Archimedes appears concerned in exploring the board. For, on the double square board, the tangent of 6 GLR is 1/3, and it is a curious fact that angles with tangents 1/2, of which there are several instances in Figure 9(i), and 1/3 add to π/4. In [20, (a)], this result was obtained, as suggested in Figure 16(i), by considering the 15 equilibrium of a uniform square lamina ABCD supported from B and loaded at A with mass equal to that of the lamina, so that a vertical plumb line through B hangs through the midpoint W of AK. Indeed, regarding Figure 16(ii) in the same spirit, if a uniform right triangular lamina ABD supported at B carries a mass equal to that of the lamina at A, the vertical plumb line though B hangs through N, the midpoint of AM, recalling from Figure 12(iii) that M is the centroid of △BDA. B B C C K K M W N A A H D D (i) square lamina (ii) right triangular lamina Figure 16: Weighing up angles Following up on [20, (a)], there is a connection with Pythagorean triangles that supplements the mechanics (compare [20, (b)]). For, if q/p is rational with 0 < q < p, then the right triangle with legs 2pq and p2 − q2 and hypotenuse p2 + q2 has half angles with tangents 1, q/p and (p − q)/(p + q). Thus, the tangents 1, 1/2 and 1/3 appear conspicuously in this way in that most familiar of all Pythagorean triangles, the (3, 4, 5) triangle. On the double square Stomachion board in Figure 9(i), angles with these tangents happen to appear at the corner G. If we look over at corner B on the double square board, we see angles with tangents 1, 2/5 and 3/7 that also come together as half angles in the (20, 21, 29) Pythagorean triangle. The appearance of these almost isosceles Pythagorean triangles might evoke Greek interest in rational approximations of the square root of two. Even after all these centuries, sparring partners would surely be disappointed not to go for another round. In this spirit, we leave readers to ponder a reciprocity between the two Stomachion boards hinted at in Figure 17 on considering further the triangle △BKB1 that slipped in at the end of the opening paragraph of this section. 16 (i) (ii) (iii) Figure 17: Another round? References [1] R. C. Archibald, Euclid’s book on Division of Figures, with a restoration based on Woepcke’s text and on the Practica Geometriae of Leonardo Pisano (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1915); available at hhttp://digital.library.cornell.edu/m/mathi. [2] S. Ashby, (a) Prize Question, The Ladies’ Diary, 1735; (b) Solutions by C. Mason, J. Turner and E. Enotts, ibid, 1736: reprt. available at hhttp://www.archive.org/details/diarianmiscella01huttgoogi; hhttp://www.archive.org/details/mathematicalque02leybgoogi. [3] W. W. R. Ball, Mathematical Recreations and Essays (Macmillan, London, ?5th ed., 1911; ?6th ed., 1914; 7th ed., 1917; 8th ed., 1919; 9th ed., 1920; 10th ed., 1922; 1937 reprint reissued, Kessinger Pub., Whitefish, MT, 2004); 4th (1905) ed. available at hhttp://www.gutenberg.org/etext/26939i; 7th (1917) ed. available at hhttp://www.archive.org/details/mathematicalrecr00ballrichi. [4] W. W. R. Ball and H. S. M. Coxeter, (a) Mathematical Recreations and Essays (12th ed. of [3], Toronto University Press, Toronto, 1974; 13th ed., Dover Pub., New York, NY, 1987): (b) review of [4, (a)] by G. L. Alexanderson, Two-Year College Math. J., 10 (1979), 283–286. [5] A. Bényi and I. Caşu, From Heron’s formula to a characteristic property of medians in the triangle, Austral. Math. Soc. Gaz., 34 (2007), 217–220. MR2356940. 17 [6] R. J. Cook and G. V. Wood, (a) Note 88.46: Feynman’s Triangle, Math. Gaz., 88 (2004), 299–302. (b) collated feedback from M. Eastham, B. C. Kahan, A. R. Pargeter and M. D. de Villiers, ibid, 88 (2004), 587; (c) further feedback from A. R. Pargeter, J. A. Scott, D. W. French, S. Blair, M. D. de Villiers and G. Howlett, ibid, 89 (2005), 106–107; (d) sequel by R. Kirby, A further note on Feynman’s triangle and a slight generalisation, ibid, 89 (2005), 108–111; (e) letter from D. A. Quadling, ibid, 89 (2005), 113–114. [7] H. S. M. Coxeter, Introduction to Geometry (John Wiley, New York, NY, 1961; 2nd ed., 1969; repr., 1989). MR0123930, 0346644, 0990644. [8] E. J. Dijksterhuis, (a) Hoofdstuk XV: Varia, Euclides, 20 (1943/44), 56–74; included as Chap. 15 in (b) C. Dikshoorn, transl., Archimedes. Acta Hist. Sci. Nat. et Med., Edidit Bibliotheca Universitatis Hauniensis. Vol. 12 (Ejnar Munksgaard, Copenhagen, 1956; Humanities Press, New York, NY, 1957). MR0085161; (c) reprt. of [8, (b)] with bibliographic essay by W. R. Knorr (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1987). MR1102014. [9] H. E. Dudeney, Amusements in Mathematics (Thomas Nelson, London, 1917) [10] U. Dudley, Numerology, or What Pythagoras Wrought (Math. Assoc. Amer., Washington, DC, 1997). MR1477906. [11] H. G. Evelyn-White, transl. and ed., (a) Ausonius, with an English translation. Vol. I. Loeb Classical Library (William Heinemann, London, UK; G. P. Putnam’s Sons, New York, NY, 1919); available at hhttp://www.archive.org/details/ausonius00ausoi; (b) obituary notice by W. E. C(rum?)., J. Egyptian Archaeology, 10 (1924), 331–332; (c) obituary notice by W. R(hys?) R(oberts?)., Classical Review , 38 (1924), 145. [12] M. Gardner, Mathematical Games: Elegant triangle theorems not to be found in Euclid, Scientific American, 222 (June, 1970), 132–136; edited as Chap 5 in M. Gardner, Mathematical Circus. More puzzles, games, paradoxes, and other mathematical entertainments from Scientific American. (Alfred A. Knopf, Inc., New York, NY, 1979; revised ed., Math. Assoc. Amer., Washington, DC, 1992). MR1172317. [13] J. Gow, A Short History of Greek Mathematics (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1884); available at hhttp://quod.lib.umich.edu/u/umhistmathi. [14] M. Hajja and P. L. Walker, Note 85.62: Why must the triangle’s medians be concurrent? Math. Gaz., 85 (2001), 482–483. [15] T. L. Heath, ed., The Works of Archimedes: Edited in modern notation with introductory chapters (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1897); available at hhttp://quod.lib.umich.edu/u/umhistmathi. [16] T. L. Heath and F. Kliem, eds., (a) revised and expanded German edition of [15] published as Archimedes’ Werke. Mit modernen Bezeichnungen herausgegeben und mit einer versehen von Sir Thomas L. Heath (O. Häring, Berlin, 1914); (b) review of [16] by L. C. Karpinski, Amer. Math. Monthly, 21 (1914), 263–264; (c) review of [16] by D. E. Smith, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc., 20 (1914), 491–492. 18 [17] J. L. Heiberg, ed., (a) Archimedes Opera Omnia cum comentariis Eutocii. Vol. II (B. G. Teubner, Leipzig, 1913); (b) review of mathematical books including [17, (a)] by T. L. Heath, Classical Review , 28 (1914), 50–53; (c) review of [17, (a)] by D. E. Smith, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc., 20 (1914), 489–491. [18] J. P. Hogendijk, (a) Al-Mu’taman ibn Hūd, 11th century King of Saragossa and brilliant mathematician, Hist. Math., 22 (1995), 1–18. MR1320148; (b) The lost geometrical parts of the Istikmāl of Yūsuf al-Mu’taman ibn Hūd (11th century) in the redaction of Ibn Sartāq (14th century): an analytical table of contents. Arch. Internat. Hist. Sci., 53 (2003), 19–34. MR2110737. [19] Y.-K. Man, A simple proof of the generalized Ceva theorem by the principle of equilibrium, Internat. J. Math. Ed. Sci. Tech., 38 (2007), 566–569. MR2328051. [20] A. J. G. May, (a) Classroom Notes 187: Angles whose sum is π/4, Math. Gaz., 53 (1969), 157; (b) Classroom Notes 188: Pythagorean numbers, ibid, 53 (1969), 158–159. [21] F. Minonzio, (a) Lo “Stomachion” di Archimede, Lett. Mat. Pristem, 35 (2000), 41– 47. MR1795008; (b) Lo “Stomachion” di Archimede II, ibid, 36 (2000), 36–42; (c) Lo “Stomachion” di Archimede III, ibid, 37 (2000), 38–45. MR1821362. [22] A. E. Moyer, The Philosopher’s Game: Rithmomachia in Medieval and Renaissance Europe (University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor, MI, 2001). [23] R. Netz, F. Acerbi and N. G. Wilson, Towards a reconstruction of Archimedes’ Stomachion, SCIAMVS. Sources and Commentaries in Exact Science, 5 (2004), 67–99. MR2109209. [24] R. Netz and W. Noel, (a) The Archimedes Codex (Da Capo Press, Philadelphia, PA; Weidenfield and Nicolson, London, UK, 2007). MR2479401; (b) review of [24] by J. L. Berggren, Notices Amer. Math. Soc., 55 (2008), 953–947. [25] R. D. Oldham (a) Letter: Double-storied houses and concave roofs, Nature, 30 (8 May, 1884), 30–31; (b) Letter: The loculus of Archimedes, ibid, 117 (6 March, 1926), 337–338; (c) Brief unsigned note on puzzle crazes in round up of research items, idid, 119 (8 January, 1927), 65. (d) obituary notice by P. L(ake?)., ibid, 138 (22 August, 1936), 316–317; (e) obituary notice by C. Davison, Obituary Notices of Fellows of Royal Society, 2 (Dec., 1936) No. 5, 111–113; (f) website at hhttp://cires.colorado.edu/ bilham/Oldham.htmi. [26] H. J. Rose, Lucretius ii. 778–83, Classical Review , ns6 (1956), 6–7. [27] E. J. Routh, A Treatise on Analytical Statics, with Numerous Examples, Vol. I (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1891; 2nd ed., 1896; repr., 1909); both editions available at hhttp://www.archive.org/details/atreatiseonanal02routgoogi; hhttp://www.archive.org/details/atreatiseonanal00routgoogi. [28] T. Rudd, Practical Geometry, in Two Parts: The first, Shewing how to perform four Species of Arithmetick, (viz. Addition, Subtraction, Multiplication, and Division,) together with Reduction, and the Rule of Proportion in figures. The Second, Containing 19 A Hundred Geometrical Questions, with their Solutions and Demonstrations, some of them being performed Arithmetically, and others Geometrically, yet all without the help of algebra. A Worke very necessary for all Men, but principally for Surveyors of Land, Engineers, and all other Students in the Mathematicks. (Printed by Robert Leybourn for Robert Boydell and Samuel Satterthwaite, London, 1650); available at hhttp://eebo.chadwyck.com/homei. [29] B. M. Schechter, My Brain is Open: The Mathematical Journeys of Paul Erdős (Simon and Schuster, New York, NY, 1998). MR1638291. [30] M. Simonovits. Paul Erdős’ influence on extremal graph theory, in R. L. Graham and J. Nešetřil, eds., The Mathematics of Paul Erdős II. Algorithms and Conbinatorics 14 (Springer, Berlin, 1997), pp. 148–192. MR1425212. [31] D. B. Singmaster, Walter William Rouse Ball, Mathematical Recreations and Problems of Past and Present Times First Edition (1892), Chap. 50 in I. GrattanGuinness, ed., Landmark writings in Western Mathematics, 1640–1940 (Elsevier, Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 2005), pp. 653–663. [32] J. Slocum (a) with J. Botermans, D. Gebhardt, M. Ma, X.-H. Ma, H. Raizer, D. Sonneveld and C. van Splunteren, The Tangram Book. The Story of the Chinese Puzzle with over 2000 Puzzles to Solve (Sterling Pub., New York, NY, 2003); (b) The Tao of Tangrams: History, Problems, Solution (Barnes and Noble, New York, NY, 2007). [33] H. Suter, Der Loculus Archimedius oder das Syntemachion des Archimedes. Zum ersten mal nach zwei Arabischen manuskripten der Königlichen Bibliothek in Berlin herausgegeben und übersetzt, Zeitschrift für Mathematik und Physik, Abhandlungen zur Gesichte der Mathematik , 44 (1899), 491–499; available at hhttp://quod.lib.umich.edu/u/umhistmathi. 20