Change Unsurpassable
Transcription
Change Unsurpassable
Change and Woodcut 1967, “Volution” © Duane Voskuil 2003 the Unsurpassable Duane Voskuil, PhD Change and the Unsurpassable A Gender-Conscious, Process Introduction to Philosophy For Serious Readers at All Levels By Duane Voskuil, PhD In Memory of Charles Hartshorne 1897-2000 ∞∞∞∞∞∞∞∞∞∞∞∞∞∫∞∞∞∞∞∞∞√∞∞∞∞∞∞ © Duane Voskuil 2003 1002 N 8th St. Bismarck, ND 58501 [email protected] iii iv Contents and Illustrations PART I Philosophy: The Unavoidable Subject Introduction..............................................................................................................................2 Doing Well in Philosophy ............................................................................................................. 5 Chapter 1: What is Philosophy?.............................................................................................7 Situations and Propositions Related to Necessity and Rationality ........................................................ 10 “Necessary" can mean:............................................................................................................... 10 Maya Cross .............................................................................................................................. 13 Mind Set 1: Galileo Vindicated .................................................................................................... 14 Mind Set 2: Continents Do Move.................................................................................................. 15 Chapter 2: Explaining Why Things Happen: The Principle of Sufficient Reason ..........16 Logical Contraries .................................................................................................................. 17 Logical Contradictories ........................................................................................................... 17 Quantification and Freedom......................................................................................................... 18 Relations of Necessary/Sufficient, Necessary/Contingent and Determined/Free ..................................... 19 Logical Contradictories ........................................................................................................... 20 Chapter 3: Metaphysics versus Relativism..........................................................................21 Truth and Necessity ................................................................................................................ 22 Sentence ............................................................................................................................... 22 Proposition............................................................................................................................ 22 Modal Status of Propositional Types ............................................................................................. 23 Verifiability Principle ................................................................................................................. 23 Expanded Form of the Verifiability Principle .................................................................................. 24 Problem of Self-Consistency with the Verifiability Principle .............................................................. 24 Metaphysicians and Anti-Metaphysicians ....................................................................................... 25 Absolutely!............................................................................................................................... 26 Metaphysical First Principles ....................................................................................................... 27 Hartshorne’s Five Dimensions of Potentiality.................................................................................. 28 Queen of Heaven ....................................................................................................................... 29 v Change and the Unsurpassable Contents PART II The First Worldview Chapter 4: Ancient Origins and Present Problems ............................................................31 Major Biological Events in a Female’s Life Cycle............................................................................ 33 Luna ....................................................................................................................................... 34 The Pubic Triangle ................................................................................................................. 35 Female Reproductive Organs .................................................................................................... 35 Bovine Scull.......................................................................................................................... 35 Embryos ............................................................................................................................... 36 Peace Signs.............................................................................................................................. 36 Litany of Mary of Nazareth.......................................................................................................... 37 Chapter 5: From Goddess to God ........................................................................................38 Male Student’s Response to Goddess Worldview............................................................................. 43 Female Student’s Response to Goddess Worldview.......................................................................... 48 The Hunt.................................................................................................................................. 49 Part III Change and Permanence Chapter 6: The Many Are One: The One Is Many............................................................47 Physicists hope smasher will look into God's mind ........................................................................... 51 Chapter 7: Pythagoreans: Mathematics and Salvation......................................................52 Pythagorean Gender Oppositions .................................................................................................. 53 The Divine Tetraktys .............................................................................................................. 54 Pythagorean Theorem ............................................................................................................. 54 Irrational Ratios ..................................................................................................................... 55 Alpha and Omega ...................................................................................................................... 56 Taboo U................................................................................................................................... 56 Chapter 8: Heraclitus (and Alice): Logos in the Flux and the Logic of Change..............57 Requirements for Change......................................................................................................... 59 Haiku One................................................................................................................................ 60 A Year Has Died ....................................................................................................................... 61 Chapter 9: Parmenides: The Logic of Being .......................................................................62 Absolutes and Unqualified (Necessary) Truths ................................................................................ 64 Chapter 10: Pluralists: Materialism: Atoms, Locomotion, Freedom and Determinism...............67 vi A Process Introduction to Philosophy Contents Possible Relationships of Mind and Matter ..................................................................................... 69 Potential Color Solid .................................................................................................................. 70 Problems with Materialism....................................................................................................... 73 Potential Sound Sphere ............................................................................................................... 74 Chapter 11: Ancient Buddhistic or Platonic Series versus Monadic Substance..............75 Same Thing as the Same Series ................................................................................................. 76 Charles Hartshorne..................................................................................................................... 75 Chapter 12: Epistemology: How Is Knowledge Possible?..................................................80 Symbol................................................................................................................................. 82 Yggdrasil: Scandinavian World Tree ............................................................................................. 83 Conceiv ing as Surpassing ........................................................................................................... 83 Chapter 13: Whitehead: Moments of Growth ....................................................................84 Temporal Asymmetry ............................................................................................................. 85 Two Intersecting Personal Series .................................................................................................. 86 Space and Time...................................................................................................................... 87 Two Meanings of “One” .......................................................................................................... 88 Alfred North Whitehead.............................................................................................................. 89 Nexüs...................................................................................................................................... 90 Actual Entities .......................................................................................................................... 91 The Spatial-Temporal Continuum ................................................................................................. 92 Pogo ....................................................................................................................................... 92 Chapter 14: Summary of the Problem of Change ..............................................................93 Process Philosophy Inversion.................................................................................................... 98 Part IV Historical Influences on Theistic Beliefs Chapter 15: Ascendancy of Patriarchal Concepts ............................................................100 Caduceus ................................................................................................................................103 Spiritus Gladius........................................................................................................................104 Chapter 16: Mithraism: One Hellenistic Origin of Medieval Patriarchal Philosophy ..................105 Gorgon/Medusa ....................................................................................................................106 Greek Coin with Caps ............................................................................................................107 Precession............................................................................................................................107 Winged Feet, Lion and Bull.....................................................................................................108 Tauroctony ..............................................................................................................................109 Big Dipper as Shoulder...........................................................................................................110 Dante's Version of the Cosmos ....................................................................................................112 vii Change and the Unsurpassable Contents Sky Map ca. 3000 BCE..............................................................................................................113 Chapter 17: Essenes: Another Hellenistic Origin of Medieval Patriarchal Philosophy .................114 Qumran ...............................................................................................................................115 Differences between the Essene and the Second Century Jesus Ethic ..................................................118 Jesus and the Essenes ................................................................................................................119 Nicene Creed ...........................................................................................................................123 Apostles’ Creed........................................................................................................................123 The Text from The Messiah ........................................................................................................123 Ancient Egyptian Circumcision ...................................................................................................125 Part V Ethics and Psychological Influences Chapter 18: Logic of Value Judgments .............................................................................127 Dimensions of Value .................................................................................................................129 A Student's Defense of Egoism ................................................................................................130 Value Flow Chart .....................................................................................................................131 Love God/dess Unconditionally...................................................................................................133 Orphic Cross............................................................................................................................134 Chapter 19: Two Faiths: Authoritarian versus Democratic Ethics ................................135 Two Faiths ..............................................................................................................................137 Summaries of Some Approaches to Social Ethics............................................................................139 Chapter 20: Gods and Goblins: Our Wounded Child: Psychological Influences on Theistic Concepts....................143 1. An Unpredictable, Unpleasant World: Nothing I want or do makes any difference .............................144 2. A Just World: When I do my chores, everything is OK .................................................................145 3. A Merciful World: Please don’t spank me..................................................................................145 4. A Heroic World: Big brother will help ......................................................................................146 5. An Unconditionally Loving World: They love me whatever I do ....................................................146 Anguish over Inadequate Philosophy ............................................................................................147 Summary of Wounded Child’s Gods ............................................................................................147 Safe Sects................................................................................................................................148 viii A Process Introduction to Philosophy Contents PART VI Rational Basis for a Theistic Worldview Chapter 21: Uni and the Unsurpassable: Five Concepts of God/dess and Morality.................150 Five Concepts of God/dess: From Fear to Love, From Will to Essence................................................151 Cosmology and God/dess ...........................................................................................................153 Chapter 22: The Ontological or Modal Argument: Necessity or Nonsense..........................155 The Anselmian Principle.........................................................................................................156 Anselm’s Questionable Assumption..........................................................................................157 Better Conceptual Tools .........................................................................................................158 How Surpassable and Unsurpassable Are Alike and Different ...........................................................159 NonModal, Invalid, Form of the Ontological Argument ...................................................................160 Modal Form of the Ontological Argument .....................................................................................161 None Greater Means: ..............................................................................................................162 Discussion of the Modal Theistic Argument...................................................................................162 Knowing What Cannot Be Known ...............................................................................................164 Star of David ...........................................................................................................................165 Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes..........................................................................................166 Ultimate and Supreme ............................................................................................................167 Some Proposals for Theistic Attributes .........................................................................................167 To Be Is To Be Related To Something.......................................................................................171 Freedom ..............................................................................................................................173 Tragedy...............................................................................................................................175 Evil ....................................................................................................................................175 Interaction of God/dess and the World ..........................................................................................177 Haiku Two...............................................................................................................................179 Chapter 24: Problem: How God/dess and the World Interact........................................180 Synchronization: All’s Well That Ends Well ..................................................................................185 Cosmically Mediated Influence: Action at a Distance ......................................................................186 Ankh: Key of Life.....................................................................................................................189 The Ankh's Derivation ...............................................................................................................189 PART VII Epilogue: Beyond Philosophy Chapter 25: Ritual: Where Thought Meets Action ..........................................................191 Two Kinds of Differences .......................................................................................................192 A Flow-er ............................................................................................................................193 Chapter 26: Now What?......................................................................................................194 Alpha and Omega .....................................................................................................................195 ix Change and the Unsurpassable Contents Part VIII Supplemental Material Appendix 1: Guide to Some Classical Problems ...............................................................197 Appendix 2: Historical Guide to Some Positions of the Patriarchal Period...................198 Orpheus ..................................................................................................................................200 Appendix 3: Whitehead's Categorical Scheme: The Metaphysical Logic of Change..............201 Glossary.................................................................................................................................204 Selected Bibliography ..........................................................................................................228 Creation Myths and Sex Role Stories and Legends ..........................................................................228 Contemporary Accounts of Male/Female Relationships....................................................................228 Philosophy and Religion ............................................................................................................228 Philosophy of Science................................................................................................................232 Prehistorical and Historical Social Structure...................................................................................232 Sexual Biology and Homosapian Evolution ...................................................................................233 Index......................................................................................................................................234 x 1 PART I Philosophy: The Unavoidable Subject Introduction ––––– Explaining Why Things Happen: The Principle of Sufficient Reason ––––– Metaphysics versus Relativism Copyright 2003 Duane Voskuil 2 Introduction “You’re mad.” “How do you know I’m mad?” said Alice. “You must be,” said the [Cheshire] Cat, “or you wouldn’t have come here.” Lewis Carroll, Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland, Pig and Pepper. “Take heed lest any one seduce you by philosophy.” St. Augustine, On the Morals of the Catholic Church. “Every man needs a little madness...otherwise he doesn’t dare cut the rope and be free.” Anthony Quinn in the movie, Zorba the Greek. P hilosophy,” though a familiar word, is difficult to define. This is one of many problems encountered when trying to adequately introduce the subject. Often an Introduction will list some philosophical problems and then examine proposed answers to these problems. Such an approach is flawed because one must first comprehend the philosophy in which the proposed answer is anchored before the answer can be grasped. In addition, an impression is left that one philosophical problem can be solved in isolation from others. Another approach, studying a few philosophical positions in more depth, often bogs down in details. Major themes and basic issues are forgotten or so obscured only the most perceptive and long-suffering will discover the excitement of philosophy. Furthermore, this approach can be so unhistorical or so historically juggled, insights achieved through historical development are lost. I can only hope to minimize these difficulties. The approach used here grapples with a philosophical issue through the eyes of the first major philosopher who raised it, so far as we know. In this way I hope one will more easily see, (1) why the problem is, or should be, a problem, (2) what were, or might be, the rejected alternatives, (3) how the first answers can become so influential they are seldom or never again consciously examined and (4) how many problems originally had an unsophisticated formulation. I give a list of Problems (see Appendix 1), but the traditional philosophical divisions, namely, the philosophies of religion, science, knowledge, and so on, will be de-emphasized, since none of these areas can be adequately answered before grasping more general or basic issues, for example, the relationship of parts and wholes; the identity of that which changes and yet remains the same thing; creativity; causation; and so forth. No area of philosophical concern can be adequately answered, if at all, until all are answered together. This is disconcerting, but unavoidable, as one tries to grasp what philosophy is about. Philosophy Made Simple, is simply not philosophy. Fundamental, philosophical problems are the same for everyone regardless of one’s awareness of them. An Introduction to Philosophy is an attempt to foster such awareness, using pertinent illustrations to draw one into the issues. The problems raised, the evaluation of the answers given, will be done from a standpoint largely inspired by Alfred North Whitehead and Charles Hartshorne. Reading the Suggested Readings for each chapter, which contain some primary and secondary sources, will help ameliorate the inevitable biases that come from introducing a complex subject. Philosophy is so radically reflective, a philosophy is required even to define philosophy, so one cannot pretend to be neutral or unbiased. The adage that one should not look for unbiased books, but read more books, seems sound. One difficulty I was not able to satisfactorily handle is the use of gender language for personal and nongendered references. “God” is masculine in most people’s minds, and “Goddess” is feminine. “It” refers to objects, not subjects. Divinity, I submit, has no gender but is a subject, not merely an object. However, until the English language develops nongendered or common-gendered, personal pronouns, some awkward conventions must be used. “God” will be used when referring to a divinity in the patriarchal view, “Goddess” when in the matriarchal framework and “God/dess” for a nongendered divinity. Various combined forms of personal pronouns follow suit. Some authors question calling the femalecentered worship during prepatriarchal times, worship of the Goddess. Perhaps, many at that time did believe the world was one Female reality who included all other creatures and divinities. But “goddess” can also be used as a common noun referring collectively to the many forms of worship which employed female metaphors in an attempt to understand reality. –––––––––––––o–––––––––––– A llow me a few words here about Charles Hartshorne to whom I owe much, not only in coming to philosophical insights, but also in achieving a saner approach to life. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 3 Introduction Fresh out of Hope College, rather isolated from racial conflict in the northern town of Holland, Michigan, I arrived at Emory University in Atlanta in 1960 at the height of the racial unrest and just before Vietnam became a major national issue. The Ku Klux Klan marched on one side of the street and the blacks on the other by Macy’s department store. Hartshorne (and as he points out, his name is pronounced “Hartshorn,” not “shorn”) was in the process of researching and writing some of his major works. He always struck me as a frail man, but he lived th longer than most, experiencing every year of the 20 Century when he died at 103 years old. Those of us who took his systematic classes had a standing joke that it made no difference what class one enrolled in, it would be a course in the same concepts. This was not only true, but to a great extent necessary, I later found out. He was a professor in the true sense of the word, “to profess,” and I feel fortunate to have had him as my master’s thesis advisor. Hartshorne usually rode to classes on a modest bicycle. Tea-time with him and his gracious wife Dorothy were times to see this family in a non-academic setting discussing a variety of subjects. He loved bird-watching and developed some important original work on the aesthetics of bird song. He once told me he didn’t know whether to become a poet or a philosopher. His decision to pursue philosophy was done with much seriousness. Though generally very gracious and tolerant of what he saw as others’ mistakes, I’ve seen how seriously he took philosophy in some sharp exchanges with or about other professionals he felt should think more adequately or “get out of the business.” Yet, while driving him back to his hotel from the University of Missouri, where he lectured while I was a doctoral candidate, he quipped he had never lost any sleep over philosophy––his response to my reference to an exciting all-night discussion I had had at a philosophical convention. I left Emory after one year. It took me four years of hard work on my own to digest the process philosophy he exposed me to before I felt ready to resume my formal studies. His influence was due more to the power of his ideas than to any outstanding teaching charisma. For these I am thankful and want to do what I can to share them with others. In April 1994, I sent Charles Hartshorne a draft of this book. He soon responded with a long letter in which he talked about the failing health of his beloved wife (who died a year later) and how he manages without her, bad marriages of professionals he knew, some of whom took their own lives, the wastefulness of our society, the relative merits of men and women in their social and political roles, his views on what it means to be a person (namely, “a user of language”) as he discussed abortion, the communication of animals (especially song birds for several pages), and the main failing of his otherwise loving parents, namely, letting him be circumcised. I know of no other writing where Hartshorne addresses this subject. In his words, About circumcision, the only serious mistake my parents made about me was in that. The effects you specify [desensitization and distrust] I can identify in my case, except that it was so different from all the other things my parents did that some of the shock to the child-parent relationship was mitigated. The diminution of the pleasure I believe did occur and in my marriage eventually caused some trouble. In my years of being unmarried perhaps it was helpful. But on the whole I agree such things should not be done to either sex. My sex has a lot of misbehavior to answer for. Our species is both the best and the worst of the earth’s animal species, the wisest and the most foolish. Our radical superiority in linguistic power is a somewhat self-destructive advantage. I, of course, was concerned how he would react to a book about his philosophy and yet one that introduced material on gender issues and pre-patriarchy, much of which I had never heard him speak to. He responded, Your understanding of Whitehead’s philosophy and of mine seems excellent....Your fascinating speculative views about the cosmic mother are a welcome plus. They make sense to me, I have never cared for the idea of God as a father, although (and I am aware of no good reason for this) during most of my career I have unthinkingly, like nearly all the other men, used the male gender in referring to God or to our species; but about two decades ago I did begin to think about, and began avoiding, this practice. Women are too important to be treated as secondary. Here is a man who at 97 years old, was still thinking in very complex sentences even though it had become more difficult for him to write, who was enjoying his life and suffering his losses, who was still very much concerned about the values of his fellow humans and still able to look at his own life and assess where he may have fallen short. As we look back on his life, we can be grateful to have had this man available for so many creative years. 1 1See the article on Hartshorne in a popular magazine: “A Hundred Years of Thinking About God,” U.S. News and World Report, Feb. 28. 1998. Allow me a couple comments here on the article to be discussed further later: (1) Rather than saying that he believes God exists, Hartshorne would say that “God” makes sense, and only so as necessarily existing. The point to argue is not whether God exists, but whether a “necessarily existing reality” makes sense. (2) Rather than saying God does not know the future, he would say God knows all there is to know about the future; however, not even God can know as fact what is not yet a fact without being ignorant of the difference between what is and what isn’t. The details of the future are not knowable because they aren’t yet, and, therefore, don’t exist to be known or unknown. 4 Change and the Unsurpassable Introduction T ––––––––––––o–––––––––––– his work covers a wide range of subjects and periods; I can't claim to be a specialist in all the areas, or to present the facts in a manner acceptable to all. Experts argue on just what the facts are in many cases. As for the metaphysical proposals, I do not expect agreement, of course, even though I argue for their truth. Philosophers can’t even agree metaphysical knowledge is possible, though I think those who deny it are contradicting themselves. The mix of this book will make some uncomfortable. It leaves me open to criticisms from several sides, but it’s a risk I feel I must take, although I will try to incorporate constructive criticism in future editions. The introductory chapters in Part I plus Chapter 12, raise the question of the nature of knowledge, and present the debate over the possibility of metaphysical knowledge. Part II introduces speculations on pre-patriarchal worldviews, picked up again, in Chapter 15, after the problem of change is examined. As the title suggests, the first half of the text emphasizes the meaning of “change,” by drawing on the implicit assumptions and explicit declarations of the preSocratic Greeks and Plato, on one school of Buddhism, and on Whitehead, which cover the major possibilities. The second half of the text, from Part IV on, builds towards a rational concept of theism after noting the successful subordination of femaleoriented rituals and metaphors by explanations reflecting the rise of patriarchal power. Insights gained here may help clarify the basis of some religious ideas and rituals and point in the direction of logical thought about the Unsurpassable. Chapters, 16 and 17, on European Mithraism and the Essenes, give some historical roots of the transition to more patriarchal worldviews and some influences on the philosophical theory of divinity. Part V discusses value theory (ethics and aesthetics) and its relationship to metaphysics, and also looks at God/dess as the basis for cosmic unity and ultimate purpose. Part VI centers on the logic of theism with a discussion of the Ontological Argument, but first Chapter 21 discusses psychological influences and historical theories that can cloud a rational view of the nature of God/dess. The Ontological Argument, Chapters 22 and 23, brings to a head all the philosophical issues: Whether metaphysical knowledge is possible; why theism must be discussed as a metaphysical issue; the relationship between necessity and contingency; the relationship between abstract concepts and concrete actuality; whether all concepts have a meaningful opposite; the inter-relationship of ritual and thought; the reality of the past and future; the meaning of life; the meaning of unsurpassable knowledge, power, and so on. Chapter 24 addresses a serious problem in process metaphysics. My attempted answer may be outside the scope of an Introduction text, but is included for completeness and to let students in on the excitement of discovery.2 I have had students able to think at this level. Anyone who teaches philosophy as metaphysics sooner or later has to respond to questions about the relevancy of the subject to students’ lives. Anyone teaching during the social activism of the ‘60s and ‘70s heard this question often. One motivation I had in the organization and content of this text was to make philosophy relevant, or rather make it more obvious to students how basic assumptions affect everything one does and believes. For this reason, I have not shied away from controversial and emotional issues, which in themselves are not philosophical in the narrowest sense, but do have a major impact on philosophical thought since people are not logical machines. Some of these issues can be very upsetting to students. Despite the space given to developing historical and psychological influences on philosophical thought, I think fundamental philosophical concepts must be justified, ideally, on logical grounds alone. But the gender issues brought to consciousness by the feminist writers of the last thirty years, for example, have driven home how deeply indebted even philosophers are to nonlogical influences in our worldviews. To make it somewhat easier to pick out what one’s first reading should concentrate on, each chapter will begin with an outline drawing attention to, (1) the most important issue(s), (2) some important points made to support the issue(s), and finally, (3) an evaluation of the proposals made. I will base much of my evaluation on the most logical and adequate philosophy I know, namely, the Whiteheadian/Hartshornean process metaphysic. Since an unbiased evaluation is impossible, I, as anyone else, can only hope to fairly present views I find inadequate, giving important reasons for finding fault with them, as well as giving credit for significant insights they have contributed to the history of thought. The reader is encouraged to evaluate my evaluation. This is where the excitement of philosophy begins. This is one book I wish I could have read in my youth. I wrote it to provide this opportunity for others. I hope there are some who will find my effort worthwhile. April 2003 Duane Voskuil, PhD 1002 North 8th Street Bismarck, ND 58501 [email protected] 2 The ideas in Chapter 24 have been published as “Hartshorne, God and Metaphysics: How the Cosmically Inclusive Personal Nexus and the World Interact," Process Studies, Vol. 28/3-4, Fall-Winter 1999. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 5 Introduction Doing Well in Philosophy A few words on how a student can best approach philosophy might be appropriate. Peter M. Spader, has written an essay covering this topic well which I reproduce here with his permission. P hilosophy is one of the few courses that most students face for the first time at the college level, and for many it is a scary prospect. There is nothing more frustrating or discouraging than working hard to accomplish something and then not being able to do as well as you had expected. Sometimes this occurs because you expect too much. More often it happens b ecause you have not been working in the right way. You have expended energy, it is true, but not in a way to accomplish the task before you. That is why I am writing this short essay. I want to help you focus your energies in this class. Before I can do this we must examine an assumption (an assumption is an unexamined belief often not even stated or clearly formulated). The assumption I made in the second paragraph was that it is worthwhile for you to work hard in this class. Now that we have this assumption out in the open as a stated belief (a belief is an idea you accept as true), let’s look at a reason why it may be true. One basic element of philosophy is “critical thinking,” the careful examination of what we believe to be true, and why. The goal of such examination is to be able to judge our beliefs (a judgment is a conviction arrived at by a weighing and testing of the reasons and evidence supporting competing beliefs.) The ability to analyze and judge our beliefs and their justification is one skill we all need to develop. For unless we can analyze and judge beliefs ourselves, we must depend upon others to do it for us. (This is sometimes necessary, since we do not always have the time or the resources to judge for ourselves.) Yet this can be risky, for how do we know how skilled the “experts” really are? The difference between everyday questioning and what goes on in a good philosophy class lies in the comprehensively systematic and persistent nature of philosophical questioning. Incidentally, since philosophical questioning is systematic and comprehensive, the answers philosophers give to the questions they raise are often also comprehensive. Indeed, for many people the word “philosophy” refers primarily to the fully developed systems of thought (sometimes called “world-views”) of the “great thinkers.” For us philosophy encompasses the whole process of questioning, answering, and the judging of the answers. All of what I have been saying should begin to give you a sense of why you could get off track in this philosophy class. Simply “understanding the material” is only the first step in this class. As important as that first step is, if you spend all of your time simply trying to grasp all “the main ideas” you are quite likely to end up disappointed both in what you get out of the class personally, and in your grade as well. Let us now turn to your preparation for showing me what you have learned: your preparing for the taking of tests and the writing of papers. Many classes use multiple choice or short answer tests. This is often quite appropriate (even in some philosophy classes) given the goals of such courses. But I use only essay tests and papers in this class because I want to see your reasons for believing what you believe; I want to see you making judgments and using your critical abilities. My letting you know how well you are doing by testing you is an important tool in my helping you to develop these abilities. A poor grade from me is not a condemnation, but a signal that more work is needed. In preparing for the essay tests and papers in my class always remember not merely that you understand an idea or that you believe it to be true. I want to know why you believe it, and that you know why you believe it, and that you can judge your belief (to see how good the reasons and evidence supporting it are). Your performance on my tests and papers depends to a good degree on your preparation for those tests and papers. When you are reading an essay in the text, or listening to me or others in the class, or going over your notes, don’t just try to understand what you are reading, hearing, or reviewing. In addition react to what you are given. Agree with it, or disagree with it. Then explore why you agree or disagree, in as much detail and depth as you can, and practice expressing your agreement or disagreement, and the reasons for it, as clearly and concisely as possible. Then step back and look at how good your reasons are, and practice expressing such judgments. Let me give you one final tip on preparing for tests and papers. You are writing an essay to show that (1) you understand the ideas you have studied, (2) you know the reasons and evidence supporting the ideas, and (3) you can back up your judgments concerning competing ideas. This means that you have to write down more than if you were simply trying to show you knew the “right answer” or even the “right procedure.” More here doesn’t mean more words, but rather more kinds of things you have to show. Perhaps the main reason some people do poorly on philosophy tests and papers is that they forget to write everything down. They try to condense a complex idea into one short sentence that tells too little, or they give one small part of their reasons and evidence for an idea when there are several levels 6 Change and the Unsurpassable Introduction that must be presented before their reasons and evidence make sense, or they simply tell their idea, and their reasons and evidence for believing it true, and forget to tell whether they think the reasons are good, and why, and so on. Always remember that you cannot say everything at once. You have to present your ideas, and reasons, and judgments, in steps; and you must remember to write all the steps down. Because all the steps are “in your head” and you can quickly pass from step to step mentally it is very easy to forget to put down some of the steps when you are writing. The problem is that I cannot “read minds.” All I can know of what goes on in your “mind” is what you write down on paper. Always let me know where you are in the presentation of your thoughts. Do not assume I know some thing. Even though I do have familiarity with the “material” we are working with, I do not know what you think, and I need to know it in as great detail as possible if I am to help you develop your critical thinking abilities. Finally, do not use “big words” or complicated sentences. Be as simple and straightforward as possible. Unnecessary complexity will simply hide what you know. I must now develop a very important new point. Throughout this essay I have been emphasizing that I want to help you develop your ability to clarify and judge your beliefs. Yet, as you will find, we will spend much of our time reading and examining the ideas and judgments of other people, of the philosophers you read in the text. Why, then, do I talk so much about your ideas. To see why, we must first get clear what I mean by “your ideas.” Some people think that if an idea is to be theirs, they must come up with it totally on their own, it must be a “brand new idea.” Now I do not want to rule out the possibility of such radical creativity on your part. One goal of developing one’s critical abilities is to be able to unearth new truths as well as to be able to recognize and affirm old truths. One of you may finally solve a problem that has perplexed philosophers for ages. But it would be very unfair of me if I demanded such creativity from you. I do not. When I say “your ideas” I mean simply any idea or judgment you accept as true (in other words, any of your beliefs), regardless of whether you originated them or not. An idea becomes yours when you believe it is true. There is nothing wrong with adopting and adapting ideas and judgments of other people, with learning from other people. (Though if you accept an idea exactly as it was developed and expressed by another person, always give full credit––plagiarism is stealing.) There is a danger in accepting another person’s thoughts, however. If you accept ideas and judgments without examining them first, you run the risk of accepting another person’s mistakes as well as that person’s true insights. Thus, if you do accept another person’s ideas or judgments, you ought to exercise your ability to judge what you are accepting. That is why your wrestling with the class’s readings is such an important part of your development. I give you classic examples of philosophical thinking to read not to intimidate you into accepting what a particular thinker had said, but to give you something worth reacting to. Much of what we learn in this world we will learn with the help of others, and so we must be able to understand what other people are trying to say, and be able to judge what we want to accept as our own. This is, incidentally, why it is so important to put ideas you adopt from other people into your own words. It helps you see better what you understand, and what you then accept, of their ideas. This brings me to a related point. Because any idea you accept as true is then your idea also, some people create for themselves an unnecessary problem. They feel they cannot study or try to understand an idea without it becoming theirs, without their having to accept it as true. To believe this is to confuse understanding something with having to accept it as true. They are not the same thing. Indeed, you must understand something before you can decide whether it is true. It is only after you understand all sides of a debate that you can fairly judge which side is best supported as true. Again, the faith of philosophy is that fully understanding all sides of a debate does not endanger true beliefs, but rather enhances our attempts to find truth and be secure in what we do believe is true. One last comment on the philosophical debates I will introduce you to. Because of the careful, thoroughgoing analysis philosophers try to make, the debates they get into can go on for a long time––as the combatants examine, re-examine, and challenge each other’s ideas and reasons. Some students feel the debates “go around in circles” without ever being resolved. I think a spiral is a better image, for in a spiral each time you go around you are a little higher; and in a good philosophical debate each time you “go around” an issue you gain new insight, even if you do not yet have a winner (and what, exactly, do we mean by “winner” in the search for truth?) [Let me add here, that the time to raise your concerns and possible disagreements is during class discussions, or on daily written work, not for the first time on tests. The Queen of Hearts’ observations of Alice’s behavior may be right: “You’re thinking about something, my dear, and that makes you forget to talk,” but talk you must if both you and I are to learn.] That is all I have to say for now. I wrote this essay to help prepare you for this class and to put you at ease. Some of what I have said will make more sense as the class develops, so it may be a good idea to read this essay over again later. I try to make this class reflect the nature of philosophy. I want you to do philosophy instead of trying to “learn about it” as if it were something outside of you. Give it a try. It really is fun once you get started. 7 Chapter 1 What is Philosophy? “I will not be able to sleep tonight.” Student, 1994. “Abandon hope all ye who enter.” Sign on entrance to hell. Dante, The Divine Comedy. “Rule Forty-Two: All persons more than a mile high [are] to leave the court.” Everybody looked at Alice. “I’m not a mile high,” said Alice. “You are,” said the King. “Well, I shan’t go, at any rate,” said Alice; “besides, that’s not a regular rule; you invented it just now.” “It’s the oldest rule in the book,” said the King. “Then it ought to be Number One,” said Alice. Lewis Carroll, Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland, Alice’s Evidence. “Philosophy begins in wonder. And, at the end, when philosophic thought has done its best, the wonder remains. There have been added, however, some grasp of the immensity of things, some purification of emotion by understanding.” Whitehead, Modes of Thought, 232. ****************************************************************************** Focus>>• –Issues– (1) How philosophy is alike, and different from, other disciplines. (2) Why everyone must have philosophical assumptions. –Approaches– (1) Philosophy clarifies what one means, rather than finds facts. (2) Philosophy seeks to find necessary or universal propositions that have no alternatives. –Evaluation– Agreement: (1) Most agree that philosophy asks, “What do you mean by that?” rather than, “What are the facts?” However, this agreement may not distinguish philosophy from some other disciplines. Disagreement: (2) Some say all truths have possible alternatives. They think one is arrogant to say s/he can have necessary truth. Yet to say, as they do, “All meaningful statements are contingent, that is, not necessary,” is itself a necessary assertion. *************************************************************************** P hilosophers, like poets or scientists, babies or adults, like all of us, try to make sense of the world around them. What does it mean to “make sense”? How is the sense philosophy tries to make different, if it is, from other kinds of understanding? Generally, what makes sense to us is what fits in with what we already believe to be true. New ideas, even if true, will be looked at with suspicion if they are too “far out” or “off the wall,” that is, out of the context we use to fit things together. But, (1) what makes sense, and (2) what seems to make sense to us, given our context of interpretation, may not be the same, although we may not be able to tell the difference. Emily Dickinson wrote about a sunrise that rose “a ribbon at a time.” She was making a comparison between ribbons (something she felt her reader would be familiar with) and the way the sun came up one particular morning, us ing what in literature is called a “metaphor.” Metaphorical comparisons are between something we are familiar with, know or understand, and something we do not know. The unknown becomes somewhat known because the metaphor 8 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 1: Definition tells us the unknown is somewhat like things we do know. Biologists tell us that all animals and plants contain DNA, so all plants and animals have something in common. If you were presented with an unknown object, and you learned the unknown contained DNA, you would know something about the previously unknown, namely, it is like things that contain DNA. You would also know something else: It is somewhat different from the many things that don’t contain DNA. To understand something usually means finding what some things do have in common and what they do not have in common with other things. Non-philosophical understanding finds what some things have in common; and what they do not have in common. Philosophy seeks to find what everything has in common. Philosophy uses metaphors, as does poetry and science, to explain how unknown things are like known things. However, the goal of philosophy is to find metaphors that apply to everything, not to just some things while excluding others. If successful, the metaphor literally expresses what reality is always like is some way. Its universality forms a logical bridge between all our restricted points of view. Its universality describes something characterizing all possible facts, not everything about any particular fact. Philosophy seeks what everything has in common. Many people think philosophers are trying to know everything about everything. Few have claimed to be all-knowing. But, many philosophers do claim to know something about everything. Even so, many people, and even other philosophers, declare this to be an unaccomplishable and arrogant goal. Since no one can know everything, how can anyone know what everything has in common? Must not the philosopher just assume that everything has something in common? Isn’t s/he making a leap of untestable faith? L ogic and Faith. A leap of faith in philosophy is not an acceptable procedure. Philosophy is a discipline in which reason, not faith or authority, is the only basis for making sense. Still, the pursuit of philosophical insight is based on a kind of faith. The philosophical faith, however, is not one faith among others. It is the unavoidable faith everyone must have, namely, that reality can be (partially) understood. If one were to deny this faith and claim reality is complete nonsense, that claim itself would have to assume to be asserting something meaningful. Is it meaningful to say nothing is meaningful? The claim that reality makes no sense cannot be established by using an expression that supposedly makes sense. So the claim that reality does not or cannot make sense is also a faith and a self-contradictory one at that, since this faith assumes it is meaningful to say, “nothing is meaningful.” Logic or rationality is the final arbiter of what makes sense, not because someone decides it is, but because it is the only way one can think and experience. Logic studies how things must be related. One cannot decide how things must be related. Not even God/dess can do what is meaningless to do (assuming for the moment that “God/dess” makes sense). If one starts with the assumption, for example, of a circle, then logic demonstrates that one has a figure wherein the distance across at the center and the distance around the perimeter is related by the unavoidable ratio pi, ! . Now, of course, one can avoid all circles, and in so doing, avoid the so-called unavoidable ratio !. Logical relations are necessary, and necessary relations are not created nor chosen nor the result of anyone’s desire. Logic does not and cannot demonstrate what characteristics all things might have in common, only those all things must have in common. All circles must have ! in common, but not all circles are green or blue or 2 inches or 20 miles in diameter, even though circles can be those colors and sizes. All circles are one kind of thing. What do other things have in common with circles? Circles have closed shape in common with other closed shapes. And all closed shapes are shapes, and so on. If some aspect is so basic or general that every possible thing would exhibit it, just to be a thing, this would be a necessary aspect. The common characteristic discovered would not be an arbitrary selection dependent on one’s interests or abilities. Anyone, anywhere, at anytime could discover the same commonality if they were insightful enough. Even though we can never know everything, we can still know we are not just arbitrarily assuming there are common factors to be found in everything. This is so because the attempt to find an alternative to universal knowledge must fail. To maintain, “There is always an exception to every attempt to find a universal common factor” would require one to find an exception to the statement that all statements have exceptions. Of course, this exception must be the A Process Introduction to Philosophy 9 Chapter 1: Definition statement that at least one statement has no exception, that is, at least something is true of everything. All, Some and None is all there is. One basic logical tool is the principle of quantification. When we talk about things, we always refer to All of them, Some of them or None of them. This reference may not always be expressed, but it is always implied. Words like “every,” “always,” and “all” say there is no exception to the common factor in the comparison. “Some,” “at least one, but not all” and “not all” mean the comparison applies to some things, but not everything. As an example, some things are ribbon-like or red, but not all things. Likewise, “none,” “never,” “not at all” mean the comparison fails to apply to anything at all. So look again at this statement: Philosophy seeks something that applies to all things, or something that all things have in common. To deny one can find something all things have in common is to formulate a denial that doesn’t make sense because the socalled denial is self-contradictory. The denial must assume everything has something in common in order to deny that they do. In the denial two universalities still emerge: (1) Every thing is a possible thing. All possibilities have something in common, namely, what it means to be a possibility. (2) Every fact differs from all other facts. That every fact not only is, but must be, different in some way from all others (since each fact is unique), is a factor all facts must have in common. The adventure of the following chapters is (a) learning what people have assumed are unavoidable commonalties, (b) learning whether those assumptions make sense, and (c) learning how the conclusions relate to one’s own assumptions about (ultimate) reality. Philosophy is uncompromising in its appeal to reason to justify its conclusions. –––––––––––o––––––––––– F ull, concrete reality is the result of the creative activities of individuals. Every such act always has alternatives. Circles are red or green or blue, but not because they must be. We are happy or sad, but not because we must be. Yet, a red circle or our happiness is not irrational, even though it is not rational or necessary. One’s happiness or the relationship of color and shape is nonrational. The ultra-rationalist (determinist) maintains reality is identical to what is rational. They do not distinguish between full reality and the rational aspects exhibited by reality. An ultra-rationalist must conclude either, (1) that the universe is a changeless , block universe, since everything is as it must be (Parmenides’ metaphysic discussed later is a good example of this attempted point of view as well as some modern interpretations of space-time), or (2) that every change is fully determined with no creative spontaneity (a common assumption of classical atomism). Most of what we do and experience is created. Yet each moment of our created reality contains or exhibits rationality, that is, necessary relationships, but those rational aspects themselves are not the fullness of reality. Reality is far more than the unavoidable relationships exhibited by reality. Most of life is nonrational, that is, it need not be as it is. However, no actual thing can be completely nonrational since it must have some aspects in common with others. Neither can any actual thing be completely rational, that is, necessary or determined since it will have unique aspects created at the moment that could have been different. Gottfried Leibniz (1646-1716) recognizes the two major divisions in the kinds of truth: There are two kinds of Truths: those of Reasoning and those of Fact. The Truths of [unconditional] Reasoning are necessary, and their opposite is impossible. Those of Fact, however, are contingent, and their opposite is possible. Monadology, 33. Life at each moment is a whole that could have been somewhat different from the way it is. In so far as it could have been otherwise, it is (1) nonrational. Life necessarily has aspects that are not necessary, but are created during the present moment. But each moment also necessarily contains: (2) factors that could not have been otherwise given the specific kind of creation. These factors are contingently rational. They differ from (3) factors that must turn up in every creation no matter what is created, that is, factors that are universally or ultimately rational. The major goal of philosophy is to find these. (4) Sentences that fail to be meaningful in any of the above ways are self-contradictory or incoherent, that is, irrational. Keeping these four categories straight will go a long way to furthering an understanding of what philosophy is all about. 10 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 1: Definition Situations and Propositions Related to Necessity and Rationality Type 1 Nonrational: A created relationship. Things as they are, but not as they must be. A proposition that describes an aspect of facts or possible facts that needn’t be as they are or describes possible facts as they could be . Type 2 Conditionally Rational: A necessary relationship given some conditions. If given a certain kind of thing (for example, a circle), then something necessarily is the case (that is, the relation of its diameter and circumference, !). A proposition that describes aspects of possible facts that must be as they are if those facts are to be or if the definition of that aspect is to make sense. Type 3 Unconditionally Rational: A necessary relationship given anything at all. Such and such must necessarily be the case no matter what is given. Something or other necessarily must be given (exist) because “nothingness” is irrational. A proposition that describes an aspect of all possible facts. Type 4 Irrational Expression: An impossible situation or relationship. A self-contradiction. Nonsense. Failure to make sense in any of the other three cases. A sentence that describes nothing possible: A failure to be a proposition. Reasoning can find what actual or possible situations must have in common, but only direct experience of the actual situation can discover what non-necessary relationships actually exist. Reason can also find what must follow from one’s assumptions. If one starts with true assumptions and makes no mistakes in reasoning, one’s conclusion must also be true. “Validity” is the term used to describe an argument that makes no mistakes in reasoning from assumptions to a conclusion. A valid argument can still have a false conclusion if the assumptions one begins with are false. Deductive logic examines validity or what is necessarily implied by one’s assumptions, not the grounds for the assumptions themselves. The logical relationships exhibited by the circularity of circles, for example, can be avoided by not creating circles. But something that is common to all possible creations cannot be created or avoided at any time by anyone. It can only be primordial and everlasting. It must be (1) uncreated, since it has always been, and (2) never-ending since it is and will be found wherever and whenever anything is found. Only by establishing “nothing” once was or “nothing” could come to be at some time, could one show the nonnecessity of something that is a factor of every possible fact. The nonsense of ”nothingness” existing will be examined several times as we proceed. “Necessity” has two meanings: (1) Conditional necessity and (2) Unconditional necessity. The first means: Given some particular kind of situation, what necessarily follows? This use of the term “necessary” means “necessary under these conditions.” The “necessity” can be avoided by avoiding the given conditions. “Unconditional necessity” means: Given any possible situation, what can be truly said about it that can also be said about all other possible situations? This necessity is impossible to avoid, since all possible situations exhibit it. “Necessary” can mean: 1. Conditionally Necessary: Necessary if such and such is to occur, or if such and such is the case, or 2. Unconditionally Necessary: Unavoidable under any conditions; occurring as an aspect of all possible circumstances and times. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 11 Chapter 1: Definition When one begins to understand what philosophy tries do, and even when one has no quarrel about the possibility of finding universal comparisons, still one’s reaction might be, “so what?” We know why we must learn what to eat and what not to, when to cross a busy street and when not to. The value of how things differ is very important to our survival and enjoyment. Learning what a particular group of things has in common is also important. We don’t have time to relearn each time a truck bears down on us that it can harm us. Trucks as a group have this property. This stereotyping, so necessary for survival, underlies one major philosophical mistake: The assumption that a spatially arranged group of things is one thing, or that something that lasts over time (with changes) is one thing. Alfred North Whitehead (1861-1947) calls this mistake the Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness. We generally recognize that common nouns like the “class” (of students) or the “team” do not refer to one thing but to one group. Whitehead says most common and proper nouns function the same way: One’s name, he says, refers to a temporally related group and not one thing in the most fundamental sense, a thesis to be examined later when the topic of “soul” and “personal identity” are discussed. A chair is also a group, but likely one with no unities more inclusive than those at the atomic level. But what value or interest is there in finding what all things have in common? We can never change these necessities. We cannot add to, nor subtract from, nor alter them. The world is, has always been and will always be, as it necessarily is. One cannot ask what difference they make, since no possible world could be imagined without them. However, even though the necessities never change, what we think they are does, and what we think they are affects how we interpret the meaning of life. Only when something we have taken to be necessary begins to look arbitrary, do we begin to wonder whether we really do know what life means. Charles Hartshorne (1897-2000) gives four reasons why the search for metaphysical truths is important: “To know what is common to all possible experience and existence is still to know something, though not something factual. This knowledge may be valuable; first, because its object is intrinsically satisfying or beautiful, second because it is sometimes, even if nonsensical, denied and this denial may be emotionally harmful, [to say, for example, that there is no meaning to life] and third, because it furnishes a clue or ideal standard relevant to all experiences, regardless of their specific content [for example, where the reality of the past is or what the meaning of “goodness” is] and fourth, because it may tell us that there is an exalted kind of factual reality which we can but dimly glimpse in its contingent particular content but can nevertheless have reason to believe is there in its allsurpassing and all-enfolding majesty.” (LP 291) The ultimate reason for developing an interest in philosophy is that we all either (1) philosophize at some level of awareness and competence, (2) or we have accepted another philosopher’s conclusions. Philosophizing is unavoidable. Unlike studying chemistry or getting married, we all must assume some universal knowledge . We all assume we know something about everything. One’s culture makes these assumptions. Usually our religious training supplies the most verbalized expressions of these beliefs: Catechisms often supply both the questions and the answers. We are all philosophers. Philosophizing is unavoidable. Humans have always assumed a natural, necessary or divine order to the sexes. For tens of thousands of years female metaphors explained reality. For the last 5,000 years most people have lived within cultures assuming divinity is male and males (made in God’s likeness) are universally ordained to control females. This thesis is called “patriarchy.” The arbitrariness of patriarchy is now seen by many. Gender’s arbitrariness is an indication we need to find better insights about the “natural order” of things. E thical Foundations. Ethical questions, also, can only be resolved by an appeal to a general standard of value that applies to all. Few assume this standard is merely a matter of opinion. How is it established? If it is something necessarily exhibited by everything, it is not established at all but has always been. Can we discover it? The answer to those who say, “so what?” or “who cares?” is that everything we do and believe to be good is guided and interpreted within the context of our most general beliefs . Every context, like words in a sentence and sentences in a paragraph, must itself be interpreted within a larger context. Eventually, there must be a context all things have in common that acts as the final interpreter of meaning. Philosophy tries to find the final context. This context provides the ultimate answer to the purpose of life and the structure of existence. However, the most general context for value cannot provide specific purposes for us, just as knowledge of universal characteristics cannot provide details of how one individual fact differs from another. But specific purposes are meaningless unless purpose in general makes sense. Philosophy analyzes the meaning of concepts. Few disagree with this. Philosophers of all 12 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 1: Definition persuasions ask the question, “What does that expression mean, if anything?” rather than the factual question, “What is (f)actually the case (as opposed to what might have been)?” Philosophers are not asking what the facts are. They are asking what it means to be a “fact.” If everything, large or small, that is or has been, is a fact, and if everything that will ever come to be is a possible fact, then knowing what it means to be a “fact” is to know something about everything. Yet, not all those who agree that philosophy examines the meaning of concepts, agree with those who claim there must be some ideas or concepts that are universal in scope and, therefore, necessary or unavoidable. –––––––––––––o–––––––––––– T he following articles, Mind Sets 1 and 2, illustrate how hard it is to see the world in new terms. Seeing how religious and scientific authorities have been wrong, may allow the reader to more easily entertain new ideas or ideas that are not sanctioned by the prevailing assump tions of our society. Those of us who have lived through the cynicism evoked by Watergate, JFK’s missing brain, missed employment advancement because of sex or race, people used unknowingly as guinea pigs for U.S. radiation experiments, tobacco advertising and endless holy wars, have good reasons to find a basis for knowledge other than prevailing authority or bias. Despite my emphasizing philosophy’s concern with logic––humanity’s only safeguard against misguided emotional excesses––philosophy in some guise or other has always promised to give its initiates the secrets of the universe. This knowledge is usually considered sacred and precious, and often guarded and passed on only to those deemed capable and worthy. Appendix 2, an Historical Guide, will be useful to help the reader locate where and when in the past a philosopher worked. It will also give an overview of the history of philosophy since the ancient Greeks. As one gets deeper into the subject, one might do well do return to this Guide and to Appendix 1, Guide to Some Classical Problems, that outlines the main issues with which philosophy has struggled, to see how many of the issues have been discussed. Chapter Summary Finding one definition of “philosophy” that all will agree on is highly unlikely, apart from some general observations that philosophy is seeking wisdom and clarification of one’s thoughts rather than seeking what is factually the case. Yet, philosophers must either maintain philosophy tries to discover what every possible thing has in common, or deny such knowledge is possible. The view expressed in following chapters is that some universalities, some unconditionally rational concepts, are unavoidable. The meaning of life in its most sweeping dimension is expressed by such universal statements. ******************************************************************** A Process Introduction to Philosophy 13 Chapter 1: Definition Maya Cross A pre-Colombian Mexican god, Yiacatecuhti Lord of the Vanguard, bearing a cross. “The cross shape as the emblem of the World Tree was at the heart of Maya religious thought for at least two millennia before the Spanish ever arrived. Friedel, Maya Cosmos, 254. Fix, 223. ************************************************************************************** “I want to thank you for opening my mind to philosophy. At the beginning of this class I was very skeptical, but after soaking it in for a semester, it makes sense. Hopefully, this will help me become a better person and a better student!” Student, 1994. “I wish I would have kept a journal of my thoughts while I was in class.” Student, 1994. “I made a mistake by not reading the glossary before doing the rest of the book.” My father, who often said, ‘Any fool can tear down a house,’ during my youth when I was questioning my Calvanistic upbringing. This book is one attempt to fulfill the metaphorical house-building, as my designing and building solar-heated, earthsheltered houses was the literal way I rose to his challenge. 14 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 1: Definition Mind Set 1: Galileo Vindicated A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 1: Definition Mind Set 2: Continents Do Move Only in the last few decades have geologists taken seriously the idea that whole continents have been drifting around the globe, an idea previously ridiculed. 15 16 Chapter 2 Explaining Why Things Happen: The Principle of Sufficient Reason “Provides immunity to the state and state employees for claims relating to: (n) Natural disasters or acts of God” (emphasis added). North Dakota Senate Bill 2080, passed 1995. First Question: “Why is there something rather than nothing?” “There has never been a time when nothing existed.” Leibniz, 1646-1716, Of Knowledge. ****************************************************************************** Focus>>• –Issues– (1) Assumptions one makes when giving a reason for why something happens. (2) How the nature of the universe and the meaning of life depend on the way things happen. –Approaches– (1) Something happens because someone chooses to do it. A theory often used by mythologies. (2) Something happens because it is forced by blind necessity to be as it is: A theory often used by science. (3) Something happens as it does partly because the present moment exercises some freedom, and partly because of conditions inherited from the past. –Evaluation– Cons: (1) Many things occur with lawful regularity, so an appeal to a reality that chooses these outcomes seems arbitrary. (2) Many things seem to occur because someone chose to do them, so an appeal to hidden causes of the “choice” in all cases seems arbitrary. Pros: (3) Each happening is conditioned by unchosen causes to be somewhat as it is, yet it becomes just as it is because it exercises freedom or spontaneity in the present. Common sense assumes this is the case, and logic requires a present that is both conditioned by the past and somewhat creative. ****************************************************************************** F aith in Causation. Most of us believe happenings occur. Most of us believe the changes we experience are real. Most of us believe when something happens there is an explanation for why it happened. Today’s newspaper has a story of a man who left his false teeth on the dashboard of his pickup while he was at a cattle auction for two hours. He returned to find them gone. His response was to look around the auction on the assumption that he dropped them. Not finding them, he went to the police to report them stolen. Never once, we can safely assume, did he believe the teeth just went out of existence. If the teeth are gone, someone must have taken them and they still exist and can be found, or someone took them and deliberately or accidentally destroyed them so they no longer exist for a reason. Similarly, when one finds large areas in grain fields knocked down in geometric patterns, s/he says “Who did it?” not, “My grain is knocked down for no reason.” The Principle of Sufficient Reason tells us, as Leibniz says, “that nothing happens without a sufficient reason.” We usually accept two kinds of answers for why something happens: (1) Someone chose to do it and had the power to fulfill the choice, or (2) What happened was the result of unavoidable causes; it happened because there was no other option, no choice at all. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 17 Chapter 2: Sufficient Reason D eterminism vs. Freedom. The search for an explanation for a particular happening implies we understand what a “happening” is. Notice that here again we are looking for what something means, not whether or not it exists. If we assume we or other agents have the power to do things, we can appeal to that power as the explanation, or partial explanation, for happenings. Yet, few of us assume we have the ability to do anything whatsoever. Our power or ability to cause something to happen is limited by the circumstances in which we find ourselves. But those circumstances also provide opportunities for us to do things. So freedom to act is gener ally assumed to be restricted or conditioned: We can do some things, but not anything whatsoever. Does the notion of “complete freedom” even make sense? This expression usually occurs when discussing divine power. Our power is limited, but divine power is supposedly unconditioned, wholly able to do anything at all regardless of circumstances. The examination of this completely capricious use of power or completely arbitrary fiat, will be looked into later when theistic attributes are discussed (in Chapter 23). For now “complete freedom” can be seen as one pole of the continuum: All––Some––None. The opposite pole, no freedom, has been a popular faith for scientific explanations. The faith was: We only have explained why something happens when the happening can be shown to be as it is because, given the antecedent circumstances as they are, nothing else could have happened. Only complete determinism is assumed to be sufficient to explain why something happens. A determinist’s faith says: When all the conditions are known that bear on a situation, the outcome is fully knowable. This faith has now been nearly abandoned since the introduction of quantum physics. Physical theory has come to realize we can never achieve knowledge sufficient to assert complete determinism. Many physi cists now maintain spontaneity is an essential part of reality. Logical Contraries All T is R, versus, No T is R. Logical Contradictories No T is R, versus, Some T is R. All T is R versus, Some T is not R. Between the poles of All freedom and No freedom (None determined and All determined, contraries of each other) lies Some freedom (the contradictory of both All and None). To assert happenings occur somewhat free is also to say they are somewhat determined. Some (at least one, but not all) is simultaneously the denial of both poles, and so is the logical contradictory of both All and None. Can those who insist on claiming logic is merely psychology, or merely humanity’s way of looking at things, claim All, Some and None are related in any other way? Is there an alternative to Some always contradicting All and None, that is, necessarily contradicting All and None? The room lights will not go on unless there is electricity in the wire, intact bulbs in the socket and unbroken wires. These are (some of) the necessities. If the lights are on, then we know these necessities or causes are there. But given all the necessities, can we know exactly what the outcome will be? Perhaps in this example all the necessities would require that the lights to be on in some way or other, but there are many ways they can be on. We cannot know just where every electron and photon would be. Necessities do not imply (necessitate) sufficiency. Antecedent causes or conditions are not sufficient to explain a happening, unless determinism is a meaningful philosophy. The opposite pole, “complete freedom,” asserts that no matter what is known about a circumstance, nothing can be known about the outcome. The unavoidable logic of All, Some and None makes clear there is no middle ground between Some and its contradictories, All and None. If we say we have some freedom to act on our own, then we are not fully determined. If any one of us has some freedom or power, then no one else can have it all. The options are forced. Either every happening (involving atoms, people or divinity, and so on) is an exercise of some power of choice or it isn’t. Freedom to create is either a universal fac tor in every fact (happening) or it isn’t. If it isn’t, one must explain what it means to be a fact “completely devoid of freedom.” Either all facts are devoid of freedom (which sets up complete determinism as one common factor of all existence), or only some facts are devoid. If some happenings can occur somewhat free and others completely determined, then freedom is not essential for every happening. The following matrix exhausts all the possible combinations of the quantifiers All, Some and None that can be arranged having two place-holders per statement. Number 1 is generally not interesting unless one assumes it is the same as Number 2. Lipservice is given to Number 2, but few really think God/dess acts without considering what the situation is. Religions are much concerned with the way God/dess acts depending on how we act. 18 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 2: Sufficient Reason Quantification and Freedom 1. All (complete) freedom is found in All happenings (No order at all) 2. All (complete) freedom is found in Some happenings (Some say this is God’s way) 3. All (complete) freedom is found in No happenings (Likely thesis) 4. Some freedom is found in All happenings (Likely thesis) 5. Some freedom is found in Some happenings (Same as #4 or #8 makes sense) 6. Some freedom is found in No happenings (Same as #7 and/or #8) 7. No freedom is found in All happenings (Universal determinism) 8. No freedom is found in Some happenings (Localized determinism) 9. No freedom is found in No happenings (Not meaningful) Number 3 seems to say complete freedom is not something possible to find anywhere. If so, it says the same thing as Number 4, which is the only one of the nine verbal distinctions likely to have any logical sense if “complete freedom” and “complete determinism” are self-contradictory expressions. E fficient and Final Causes. The basic logical principle concerning freedom and causation has to do with how the parts or aspects of something are related to the whole of which they are parts. The concept of “part” is meaningless unless one is referring to parts of some whole. Parts cannot exist alone. Parts are always within, or part of, a whole. The relationship of dependence is one-directional, or asymmetrical. Wholes depend on the particular parts they contain to be the specific wholes they are, but the parts do not depend on the particular whole they are in to be what they are. Likewise, a happening depends on the necessities or causes that help bring it about. The causes don’t depend on the outcome. All, Some and None exhaust all the possibilities of quantity. Other examples: An act, which as a whole exhibits freedom, can contain aspects that are necessary or determined, but the attempt to conceive a “completely determined act,” yet one somehow containing even one free part, is nonsense. Again, using slightly different language: A whole can be contingent (capable of being different from the way it is) and contain necessary parts (aspects not capable of being otherwise). However, a whole cannot be completely necessary and contain even one aspect that is contingent. “Cause” or the reason for why something happens has two meanings, (1) the unavoidable past circumstances that become parts of the present happening, and (2) the created, determinate situation made by the present whole itself. 19 A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 2: Sufficient Reason Relations of Necessary/Sufficient Necessary/Contingent and Determined/Free Whole but Free only Nonsense Det. only Whole with no real parts Nonsense Nonsense Free Det. Det. Nonsense Meaningful real parts Meaningful Free Suf. Nec. Nonsense Nec . Cont . Nonsense Aristotle’s categories of efficient cause and final cause are similar to these two meanings. These two kinds of cause are not mutually exclusive. They are likely both required to determine a sufficient reason for a happening. Past conditions are necessary for present decisions, but present decisions have no effect on past conditions. Present decisions become conditions for future decisions. Early attempts to explain the world and our existence in it, emphasized the power of choice. Even if we were powerless, things happen because supernatural powers have chosen to bring them about. This type of explanation is often called “mythological.” Early Greek philosophical or scientific explanations said choice was not a factor in some or all happenings. Events happened because there was no other possible way they could happen. No Whole. Each "Part" is a whole Nec . Suf. Meaning of Causality Cont. Nec . Meaningful so long as there must be some contingency or other. Mythological explanations in terms of capricious decisions or explanations in terms of scientific determinism are both problematic. Yet, mythological and deterministic explanations both looked for what events have in common. Parts and Wholes Appreciating that the relationship between parts and the whole of which they are parts is necessarily asymmetrical, that is, one-directional, lies at the heart of making sense of reality. Myths appeal to the actions of personal powers as the threads relating events. Determinism appeals to 20 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 2: Sufficient Reason unavoidable laws that are supposedly found in all events. The truth is likely between these historical pendulum swings: Choice is always determined or conditioned by circumstances. Circumstances are what previous choices made that now condition the present choice. Chapter Summary The reasons that can be given to sufficiently explain why something happens comes down to three mutually exclusive theories, two of which must be wrong. The way something happens is: (1) Totally because of the causes or circumstances that precede the happening (so the present does nothing), or (2) Partly because of causes or circumstances that precede the happening and partly because of freedom or creating in the present moment, (most likely thesis), or (3) Totally because of freedom in the present moment, (so past has no affect on the present). Suggested Reading: Leibniz. Chapter 3 Metaphysics versus Relativism “...Every statement has a [meaningful] denial.” Irving Copi, Introduction to Logic, 9th ed., 406. “Every rule has an exception.” Cultural aphorism. “Metaphysical categories are not dogmatic statements of the obvious; they are tentative formulations of the ultimate generalities.” A. N. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 12. “...I endeavored to demonstrate...that even if God had created more worlds, there could have been none in which these laws were not observed.” Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method, Part V, Para. 2. Alice laughed... “One can’t believe impossible things.” “I dare say you haven’t had much practice.” said the Queen. Lewis Carroll, Through the Looking Glass, Wool and Water. ****************************************************************************** Focus>>• –Issues– (1) The fundamental dispute among philosophers between relativists (or positivists) and metaphysicians. (2) The difference between two kinds of metaphysicians: Moderate Rationalists, and UltraRationalists. –Approaches– (1) Positivist or Relativist: Only sentences (a) make sense that have the possibility of being wrong (even if they are factually right), or the possibility of being right (even though they are factually wrong); or (b) make sense that follow (arbitrarily) defined rules. (2) Metaphysician: (a) Ultra-Rationalist: All meaningful sentences state necessary conditions of reality. Reality exhibits no freedom for alternatives. (b) Moderate Rationalist: Some sentences describe something about reality that has always been and will be as it is because there is no alternative to reality exhibiting these characteristics. –Evaluation– Cons: (1) Positivists fail because they use a necessary proposition to deny any necessary propositions make sense. (2a) Ultra-Rationalists fail because determinism is the denial that anything happens at all since nothing new is possible. Pro: (2b) Moderate Rationalists: Meaningful sentences either express relationships (a) among actual or possible facts that could have been otherwise, or (b) among definitions that are conditionally rational (that is, necessary, but only because they follow defined rules that can be changed), or (c) among some aspects of actuality that are unconditionally rational, that is, must be as they are. There is nothing illogical about the approach which allows all three types of propositions (that is, a, b and c) and claims there must be some of the third kind. 22 Change and The Unsurpassable Chapter 3: Relativism ****************************************************************************** T ruth and Sense. Historically and logically there are two fundamentally different attitudes towards philosophy, metaphysical and antimetaphysical or relativism. The battle between relativism and metaphysics is at the heart of philosophy. A metaphysician claims every possible thing must have at least some characteristics in common with all other possible things. These characteristics must be knowable even if all are not yet known to us. A metaphysician says at least some knowledge we have is unconditionally rational or necessary: Some things we know as true have no possibility of being false. The ultra-rationalistic metaphysician says a l l truth is necessary: Nothing could ever have been different from the way it was, is and will be. All anti-metaphysicians counter, on the other hand, that such universal knowledge is not possible. Relativists claim all truth is relative to a point of view and does not apply universally: No truth is necessary. Unsurpassable really does exist,” or “that was completely different,” are clauses with no cognitive content and, therefore, can be neither true nor false. Why some of these expressions fail to make sense may not yet be obvious, though I hope to show why they fail as we proceed. The metaphysician and the positivist do differ on the criteria used to determine whether sentences really are propositions. A positivist tries to determine which are meaningful by using the Principle of Verification. Simplified, it says only sentences are meaningful whose truth or falsity can be established by factual evidence. Truth and Necessity A (linguistic) structure conveying information. A sentence that says something meaningful. However, not all propositions are sentences: A gesture can be a proposition. All truth is necessary. Some truth is necessary. No truth is necessary. Yet, both agree philosophy is not the search for facts. Philosophy, they both maintain, is the search for meaning. Philosophy is trying to determine whether a statement really makes sense. Logical Positivism, an anti-metaphysical position of this century, and other ana lytic schools emphasize the important distinction between the meaning of a proposition and the truth of a proposition. Positivism maintains most, if not all, philosophical problems will disappear if one can determine which sentences really say something and which are merely nonsense, even if they have correct grammatical form. Metaphysicians like Alfred North Whitehead and Charles Hartshorne have no quarrel with the distinction between conceptual sense and nonsense. Both metaphysicians and relativists agree: Some sentences masquerade as meaningful propositions, and we should learn to detect them. Only sentences that make sense can be true or false. However, some meaningful sentences can only be true and never false, if metaphysicians are right. Meaningless expressions can be neither true nor false. “Round-squares are pink,” or “the greatest conceivable number is happy,” or “absolutely nothing is in the refrigerator,” or “we can prove the Sentence A linguistic structure that satisfies grammatical conditions. A sentence need not make sense. Proposition Evidence may be unavailable for some propositions, such as, “There is intelligent life on other star-systems’ planets,” but a sentence that fails to be a proposition has built-in definitions making it logically impossible or inconceivable any facts could ever be found that would be relevant to its truth or falsity. Facts cannot be relevant to nonsense. “There are little green people in the desk drawer, but anything you do to get evidence on their existence makes them disappear,” is not a proposition for positivists or metaphysicians. Merely empirical propositions are those whose truth or falsity can be determined by facts. These propositions are statements about how things one experiences happen to be or could be. Since they do not state that experience must be as stated, they are not rational propositions. They are about created relationships. Factual propositions are not the only kind of propositions that positivists say make sense. Some propositions make sense, not because they express something about possible facts, but because they follow rules defining the terms and operations they contain. These are merely rational propositions. The relationships they state are necessary, but only because the definitions happen to be as they are. Alternative definitions would be possible without self-contradiction. 23 A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 3: Relativism If a chess player moves his king off the board to avoid checkmate, he ceases playing chess as usually defined, that is, his move was not meaningful. On the other hand, “All unmarried men are bachelors” is meaningful by definition, not because of any relevant facts. Since merely rational propositions are logical propositions, the philosophers who say only these and merely empirical propositions are meaningful are called Logical Positivists. The positivist’s Principle of Verification must be expanded, then, to include merely rational propositions. Only propositions are meaningful to a positivist (1) whose truth or falsehood can be established by facts, or (2) whose meaning can be established by definition. Because a sentence’s meaningfulness depends the possibility of finding facts that can verify or falsify it, one must face the problem of defining a “fact.” For now, consider only one aspect of a possible definition, namely, whether a fact is, or is not, fully determined. Unless “complete determinism” is meaningful, no fact is necessary just as it is. The consistency of determinism, otherwise known as the metaphysic of ultra-rationalism, will be examined later. “It could have been otherwise,” is a condition all facts (seem) to display. “To have a possible alternative” is a partial definition of “fact” that all metaphysicians (who are not ultra-rationalists, that is, rigorous determinists) and all positivists affirm. Facts, in other words, are contingent. Facts are not necessarily the way they are. No particular fact must exist. But must some fact or other exist? If not, metaphysics is meaningless. If so, relativism is meaningless. Modal Status of Propositional Types Type 1 Merely Empirical Possible Fact Contingent Type 2 Merely Rational Possible Definition Contingent Type 3 Unavoidably Rational (Metaphysical) Necessary Description Noncontingent Type 4 Impossibly Rational (Nonsense) Necessarily not Possible Noncontingent Not only must all facts be contingent, but all the rules defining rational propositions must also be contingent, according to a relativist. Though meaningful propositions will necessar ily follow a given set of rules or definitions, the definitions themselves must also be given, that is, be arbitrary: Other definitions are always possible. “Necessary” to the positivist always means “necessary by definition.” “Necessary,” to a relativist, never means “unavoidable under all possible circumstances.” Positivism can now be defined as the position that says, “All meaningful propositions are contingent.” Logical Positivism maintains only merely empirical and merely rational sentences make sense (neither of which assert something universal or unqualifiedly necessary about reality). Despite disagreement among metaphysicians as to what the metaphysic is, no metaphysician can fully agree with the Verifiability Principle’s criterion for determining which expressions are meaningful. Verifiability Principle All meaningful propositions are contingent. Only propositions dependent on either, (1) factual or (2) definitional circumstances make sense. If true, all meaningful propositions could have been false; if false, they could have been true. Change and The Unsurpassable Chapter 3: Relativism Expanded Form of the Verifiability Principle Positivists say only the following two types of propositions make sense: Type 1 Merely Empirical Propositions Meaningfulness is established by the possibility of finding factual evidence that can prove the statement true or false. Type 2 Merely Rational Propositions Meaningfulness is established by conceptual (logical) definition. Truth is “necessary” if the proposition follows the given (arbitrary) definitions. Problem of Self-Consistency with the Verifiability Principle Is the Verifiability Principle a meaningful proposition? Does the Verifiability Principle itself fit either Type 1 or Type 2? Is there a possible alternative to it? If not, is it meaningful? The reason for this disagreement arises because the metaphysician finds problems with the Verifiability Principle of Meaning, the positivist’s proposal for determining which sentences makes sense. The Principle says: “All meaningful propositions are necessarily not necessary.” If this sentence is, as it seems, a self-contradiction, it cannot be a meaningful proposal. P hilosophical Procedure. A dispute between philosophical positions is not a factual issue. Philosophical disputes are over questions of meaning. The meanings, that are philosophy’s main concern, define reality in some general way. Philosophy is the discipline trying to find universal, meaningful descriptions. One or both of two opposing views on universal issues must be wrong, not factually wrong, but meaningless. One or both of the positions must be illogical. Evaluation of a philosophical position ideally proceeds by examining the logical rela tionships of the assertions within the system itself. A philosophical position will fail, if it does, not because it is different from another po sition, but because its own criterion for meaning fails to make sense of itself. Unfortunately, philoso phers have a bad habit of allowing contradictions or incoherencies in their own work while pointing them out in others'. If the positivist’s criterion for meaning (the Verifiability Principle) makes sense, it must be one of the two kinds of propositions that make sense according to its own criteria. Is the Verifiability Principle of Meaning itself an example of a merely empirical or a merely rational proposition? Is the Principle contingent? The Principle of Meaning’s own meaningfulness is established neither (1) by its ability to be true or false depending on some fact or other, nor (2) by definitions that could be set up in a different way. The Principle seems to be unqualified, unavoidable and necessary. What could possibly be a meaningful alternative to the Principle of Verification in the positivist’s mind? But necessary propositions are meaningless according to positivists and relativists. Either the criterion for meaning is not meaningful or there is an implicit appeal to a third kind of proposition. If one starts by saying: (A) “All meaningful propositions are contingent; they all have alternatives,” then one is obligated to find an alternative to A. This alternative to A can only be: (B) “At least one proposition is necessary” (or the even stronger contrary assertion, “All propositions are necessary”). So in maintaining A, one is also logically committed to asserting B, or as Parmenides will say later (see Chapter 9), one is committed to maintaining A and not-A at the same time; and B (not-A) is the logical contradictory of A. To employ a necessary proposition to deny 24 A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 3: Relativism Metaphysicians and Anti-Metaphysicians (Also see Situations and Propositions Related to Necessity and Rationality, Chapter 1.) Those who assert only Types 1 and 2: Positivists, Relativists, Anti-metaphysicians, Skeptics. All meaningful propositions are contingent. There is a meaningful opposite to everything we can say. All empirical and definitional (logical) propositions are contingent. Only propositions of Types 1 and 2 make sense. Those who assert Types 1, 2 and 3: Metaphysicians. Some meaningful propositions are necessary. Some things we say have no meaningful opposite. Propositions of Types 1, 2 and 3 make sense. Those who assert Type 3 only: Ultra-Rationalistic Metaphysicians, Determinists. All meaningful propositions are necessary. Everything we meaningfully say could not conceivably have been otherwise. Only propositions of Type 3 make sense. Those who assert Type 4: Irrationalists. Failure to assert a proposition. It is doubtful anyone deliberately fails to make sense. Zen Buddhists? necessary propositions are meaningful is a selfcontradiction. Propositions that are necessary and not self-contradictory, that is, those whose denial is impossible, are metaphysical. Metaphysical propositions are simply necessary, and must be carefully distinguished from those that are necessary by definition. A proposition that is true and cannot be false, is a philosophical (metaphysical) proposition. Whitehead and Hartshorne do not deny the existence and meaningfulness of the first two types of propositions, but they assert the heart of philosophy lies in discovering propositions and their interrelationships of the third kind. They can be variously called Metaphysical Propositions, Necessary Truths, or Ultimate Generalizations. To be a metaphysician one must believe there is some unavoidable or necessary truths––at least one. Some metaphysicians (ultra-rationalists) have often thought all meaningful propositions are necessary. Metaphysical propositions, and the necessary scheme of concepts they form, have two characteristics according to Whitehead: They are simultaneously rational and empirical. R ational Aspect. Metaphysical propositions are rational because they exhibit the properties any merely rational scheme (set of propositions) must, namely, coherence and logicality. To be logical means the sentences of the scheme are propositions. They are self-consistent. “Greatest numbers” and “round-squares” will not be among metaphysical assertions either. Coherence is a function of the interrelationships of propositions. No proposition, including an ultimate proposition, can be meaningful by itself; its meaning hinges upon the meaning of the rest of the system. This doesn’t mean one defines a metaphysical proposition in terms of others, for then the defined proposition would not be essential at the most basic level. An example of coherency is the way functional grammars demonstrate the interdependence of meanings. A “noun” is indefinable apart from other notions like “verb” and “preposition;” yet a verb or preposition is dependent on the meaning of “noun” for its explication. E mpirical Aspect. A metaphysical or ultimate generality must also interpret experience. To do so it must have application to experience. To be applicable means that there must be some items in our experience that are drawn together or exhibit the common factor expressed by the concept. But to have just some application is not enough for a metaphysical assertion. 25 26 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 3: Relativism ********************************************************************************** Absolutely! ********************************************************************************** The concept expressing the proposition must also be a d equate. All actual and possible items of experience must be capable of explanation in terms of the principle, that is, all must exhibit the characteristic. But “adequate” is ambiguous. It may mean “adequate to interpret those items of experience under consideration.” In this sense the generality of the proposition is qualified, or restricted to items considered. Propositions of this type are scientific. Each area of science seeks to find generalizations or descriptions of experience adequate to its domain. DNA goes a long way in explaining biology, but is not much help in physical geology. Metaphysical propositions are abstractions that are universally exemplified. They are necessary principles, not because of some outside agency, choosing to make them so, but because no agent could be anything at all without displaying these principles. They are not necessary by definition. They are necessary because any attempted denial turns out to be impossible. Seeming denials of metaphysical propositions can only be maintained because of confusion or vagueness. Since metaphysical propositions have al ways been as they are, we do not define them nor create them. We can only discover or become aware of them. Metaphysical knowledge is not knowledge of how things differ or how they could be different from the way they are. 27 A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 3: Relativism Metaphysical First Principles Metaphysical First Principles: Necessary Scheme of Ideas: Ultimate Generalizations Rational Aspect ("Necessary" or Analytic Truth) Coherent (Any principle abstracted from the rest will become meaningless) Logical (Self- consistency) Empirical Aspect ( Factual or Synthetic Truth) Applicable (Some ideas are capable of interpretation by the scheme) Meaning: (of those items considered) Adequate No items are incapable of interpretation Meaning: (all possible items, including those that are actual) Principles Universally Exemplified, or Necessary by Unavoidability Examples of statements that ideally fulfill the criterion for this third kind of proposition are difficult to assert with any assurance. The history of philosophy is really an examination of various proposals and how far they met the dual requirements of rationality and explanation of experience at the most fundamental level. But the assertion, “something makes sense,” seems to be metaphysically necessary. The attempted contradictory of something makes sense is, “nothing makes sense,” which is either, (1) something supposedly meaningful even though self-contradictory or, as seems necessary, (2) no assertion at all, but simply nonsense. To know what it means to be all-knowing is not to be all-knowing. Another way to approach metaphysical knowledge is to ask how much knowledge is possible. Excluding the case of “knowing nothing” as self-contradictory, a knower must either know: (1) All about All. (2) All about Some. (3) Some about All. (4) Some about Some. The meaning of “all-knowing” will be discussed in Chapter 23. One must be very careful to distinguish Number 3 from Numbers 1 and 2. To know what it means to be all-knowing is not to be all-knowing, but it does imply one knows something about everything. That everything that does or could exist is experienced by someone, is one proposal for one metaphysical truth. Hartshorne has proposed a list of metaphysical, (that is, nonrestrictive and existential) truths (MSNE): • Something must exist, 28 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 3: Relativism • Experience must occur, • Creativity must occur, • Concrete realities must exhibit both internal and external relationships, • Infallible experience must occur which includes others’ fallible experiences. Whitehead has a whole chapter of categorical conditions most of which he assumes all actualities must exhibit (see Appendix 3 and PR Chapter II). Hartshorne also proposes a list of five categories or dimensions found in all moments of existence in some way: Every experience is a whole (or a subject) that includes others as objects. (1) The whole is here, the objects there. This here-there dimension sets up spatial depth. Two or more others experienced simultaneously set up spatial width. (2) All objects are felt with more or less aggressiveness. In colors, scarlet is most aggressive, seagreen least (see the Potential Color Solid, Chapter 10). (3) All objects come with some degree of positive value or en hancement for the subject. In fully saturated colors, buttercup yellow is the least somber, violet most so. (4) Each element of experience comes with a specific degree of intensity or brightness, a valuation of importance or insistence. In color, this is the blackwhite axis. (5) Experience always moves from a somewhat general possible kind of object to one that is less so. A moment of creation specifies in some way a more general possibility. Once formulated, many metaphysical truths are so self-evident as to seem platitudinous, but the belief “that metaphysical thought started from principles which were individually clear, distinct and certain,” (Whitehead, FR, referring to John Locke) instead of meaningful only in context with all other metaphysical principles, has foiled many attempts at metaphysical formulations. These principles are usually very difficult to formulate because of their extreme generality. Hartshorne’s Five Dimensions of Potentiality Dimension Example or Meaning: 1. Self-Other 1. Spatial Depth 2. Active-Passive 2. Scarlet-SeaGreen 3. Positive-Negative 3. Yellow-Violet 4. Intense-Faint 4. Brightness 5. Generic-Specific 5. Duration (and Change) The rest of this book is an examination of proposals for statements that assume to be about the final interpretation of things: Statements that try to explain how everything fits together, or describe what everything is made of, or express what the general purpose of everything is. Chapter Summary Modality, that is, whether a statement is contingent (possible, but not necessary or nonsense) or noncontingent (necessary or nonsense) applies to all meaningful expressions whether expressed or not. A metaphysician believes either some or all meaningful statements are necessary. An anti-metaphysician believes no meaningful statements are necessary. A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 3: Relativism There can be no middle ground: Either there are some (at least one) statements that are unavoidably true or there are none. Someone who says there are no necessary truths, is saying: It is necessarily true that there are no necessary truths. Self-contradictions are evidence of nonsense, not a truth of any kind. Both metaphysicians and relativists believe some things people say are not statements at all, but merely nonsense. Suggested Reading: Whitehead, Process and Reality, Part I “Speculative Philosophy,” Sec. 1,2; Morriz Schlick, Meaning and Verification; Hartshorne, MSNE; Frankl (who can’t make up his mind about ultimates). ************************************************************************ Queen of Heaven Standing on a heavenly cloud and crowned, this representation of the Goddess in the Roman Catholic Diocese Cathedral in Rapid City, SD, is surrounded by stained glass windows proclaiming some of her titles: Mystical Rose, Queen of Peace, Queen of Martyrs, Mirror of Justice, Queen of Angels. Photo by author. ************************************************************************ 29 30 PART II The First Worldview Ancient Origins and Present Problems ––––– From Goddess to God Copyright 2003 Duane Voskuil 31 Chapter 4 Ancient Origins and Present Problems “Make love, not war.” ‘60’s antiVietnam war chant. “Celebration of life is the leading motif in Old European ideology and art. There is no stagnation; life energy is constantly moving as a serpent, spiral, or whirl.” Marija Gimbutas, The Language of the Goddess, 321. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– How gender, the first metaphor employed to understand the cosmos and our purpose in it, became (1) used to interpret the universe, and (2) misused in metaphysics. –Approaches– (1) Female physiology is used as an early metaphor to express cosmic truth. (2) The female cyclical (menstrual) period is reflected in the cosmos (the moon’s monthly rhythm). This view of reality emphasizes change, process and recycling (rebirth). (3) Menarche and menopause divide the female and her cosmic deity into the trinity of maiden, mother and crone. (4) Creating, including cosmic creation, is seen as a function of giving birth, a fundamental characteristic of divinity only females possess. –Evaluation– Pros: (1) Was life-affirming–even sexuality was integrated with the wholesome and holy. (2) Allowed a logical way to conceive of cosmic unity. (3) Provided a view of reality that allowed people to feel meaningful. (4) Saw everything related to everything else. Everything in the universe is our kin (blood relative). (5) Placed emphasis on process. Cons: (1) The system is not yet explicit on some technical problems that must be answered to have an adequate explanation of “change” or “being saved .“ (2) The use of (one) gender to explain cosmic unity and creation relegates the other gender to a secondary status. (3) Gender is not a necessary aspect of existence, and so can’t be philosophically general. ****************************************************************************** T he history of ideas is not unlike biological evolution or an oft-remodeled old building. New ideas, like new species or remodelings, depend on what has existed previously. New thoughts must be interpreted within old contexts. The more general the contexts, the harder they are to modify. One of the more persistent themes, in humanity’s attempt to understand what life is all about, is gender. We see ourselves as male or female. Most living beings in our experience are gendered. We easily assume being alive is to exist as a male or female. If we assume everything of importance has a gender, we must choose between calling it male or female. However, where there can only be one, like the whole universe, this causes serious problems as to which gender, if any, to use. At the heart of religion and philosophy is the drive to explain where everything came from or what 32 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 4: Origins the unity of everything is and how we are related to (or tied into, religio, Latin) the whole of things. Most peoples have assumed everything has been created or born. With this assumption, what kind of reality could have created or given birth to every thing that exists? What could have given birth to the whole universe? And if we are all parts of a larger reality, what gender is it? Gender is historically important, but philosophically superficial. At the earliest dawning of concern for our human origins and destinies, perhaps hundreds of thousands of years ago, the experience of our own birth-origin was used as a metaphor to explain the origin of all of us, namely, our mother. We all come from our mother. Within the all-enveloping, undifferentiated womb-liquid, the amniotic sea, we took shape. Since it is likely the male role in reproduction was either not known or considered peripheral, the all-inclusive, primordial reality was naturally thought to be female. Maria Gimbutas concludes, My archeological research does not confirm the hypothetical existence of the primordial parents and their division into the Great Father and the Great Mother figures or the division of the Great Mother figure into a Good and Terrible Mother. There is no trace of a father figure in any of the Paleolithic periods. The life-creating power seems to have been of the Great Goddess alone....the Life Giver and the Death Wielder are one deity. Her manifestations are manifold. (Gimbutas, Language of the Goddess, 316) The Universe was first seen to be a Great Cosmic Female. Only the female creates new life from her womb liquid and sustains that life with her breast liquid. From her one body comes many. We are our mother, and yet we are ourselves. How the many lives created are related to each other and to their Creatress is one of the deep mysteries all intellectual schemes try to understand (see Chapter 24, for an example). Destruction of creations is another mystery. What is death? Why does it happen? Where do we go? Where is the past? The first answers given to questions about death were also in terms of the universal female. We came from the cosmic womb and we return to the cosmic womb, the tomb. The Great Goddess creates us all from her body and takes us all back into her body, the dark underworld. The taking back is a destruction of what has been. Only the loss of present ways of existing seems to allow new forms to come into being. But people reasonably concluded the loss could only be temporary. After all, once one is back in the cosmic womb, one must be reborn, since giving birth is the womb’s essence. The unity of all reality is the cosmic body of the female mother. Symbols of the changing processes of life were boiling pots (as in pot-bellied or pregnant) or in mounds of earth (constructed or natural) swelling up from the ground like England’s Silbury Hill. The Goddess was the beginning and the end of all life, and the transformer of death into new life. Rebirth can be thought of in several ways: (1) One model is the butterfly’s emergence from the cocoon/womb after a major reordering of the physical body from a worm-type creature to a beautiful flying creature. One need not, in this case, assume a continuous consciousness or soul, but the butterfly’s body is born from the body of the worm. (2) Another form of rebirth is reincarnation, or rebodying, which assumes a continuous thread of personal identity residing in some thing other than the body. This entity (often called the “soul”) is reborn by being placed in a new body. The belief in renewal by rebirth is inspired by the great cycles of renewal we see all around us. The year lives and dies and is reborn in the spring. The day grows and dies at night to be renewed in the morning. Grain grows and dies at harvest-time, but is reborn in the spring planting from its seed/soul. Perennials return to life each spring with the renewing power of the sun. Hard archeological evidence of the Goddess as humanity’s first concept of divinity goes back a hundred thousand years and perhaps 500 thousand.3 There are thousands of artifacts from the long period of time before societies began asserting the primacy of the male, about 4000 BCE. Valuable sources for information on the time before male domination, are the surviving intellectual or religious schemes known as mythologies. Though no myth has come down to us unaffected by changes made to it by later worldviews dominated by male metaphors, still careful study of myths can extrapolate much information about the prepatriarchal period. The concept of the Goddess pulled together experiences of people’s daily bodily functions and of the larger world around and above them. The realm within the earth, though not directly observable, was assumed to be teeming with the Goddess’ activity also. Reality was seen as an interconnected whole, as the organic unity of the Goddess. Her desires, thoughts or words need only to be spoken and they become real. Her word becomes flesh and blood. The Goddess had many forms: She was personified as different kinds of ani mals either because of the animal’s ability or shape. The Goddess also 3The recent find of sophisticated throwing spears in a German coal mine dating to 400,000 BCE seems to indicate that people had the awareness and skill at that time to do so, even if a stone mentioned by Gimbutas with a pubic triangle inscribed on it is not as old as the purported date of 500,000 BCE. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 33 Chapter 4: Origins reflected the stages of a woman’s life: maiden (virgin), mother and wise old woman (hag or crone). Each of these stages was given a different name, like Hebe, Hera and Hecate, but these three were still seen as one person. Biological cycles are tied to the cosmos. Women, and their divinity, lived their lives in cycles. Years came and went with the same seasons. The stars circled around the earth in their yearly whirl. One generation went through the stages of life and gave rise to another generation. Ancestors were revered for the efforts they gave to establish those now living. Day gave way to night, but night succumbed to day. But the one cycle that must have convinced women they were part of the grand cosmic scheme of things was the mo(o)nthly cycle. The moon waxes to fullness and wanes to darkness. A women’s menstrual cycle matched that of the moon. She was tied to the moon. The very idea of measurement and math, that is, systematic repetition of space and time units, started with the moon/menstruation cycle. “Menstruation,” “measuring” and “moon” are all cognates. Even “math” and “matrix” come from “ma” the Indo-European word for “mother,” or “mama,” which is also the word for breasts: “mammaries.” Before accurate knowledge of reproductive systems was known, menstrual blood was thought to be the material of new life. Before women menstruated and after they stopped, they did not reproduce. The magic, mysterious womb fluid was blood. It was thought to coagulate or curd like that other wondrous body fluid, milk. A pregnant woman was putting her creative blood into a new life within her. Parthenogenesis was the norm for females. People often interpreted dying as being eaten. We kill plants and animals when we eat them, so by analogy, we are eaten by the God dess when we die. The Goddess in her death aspect was often pictured as a scavenging bird, a vulture. The Mother must eat us or we cannot be assimilated into her body to be reborn. Even today the Happy Buddha of Eastern religions grows fat eating the filth and negative things of the world. The close relationship of death and eating is also found in the similarity of sex and eating. Lynn Margulis, a well-known contemporary biologist, points out that the earliest life forms, prototypes of bacteria, developed the ability to use each other’s genetic material. Not only could early life forms use other life forms for building blocks, they could also use their genetic material for blueprints. The ingestion of genetic code material was done much in the same way as other chemicals were ingested for food. The ability to use code chemicals another has produced is called “sex.” Sex allowed new patterns to be inherited without the novelty of random mutations which are generally life-threatening. Radiation was one of the forces that constantly threatened the code by mutating its chemical bonds. Sexual exchange was, (1) a hedge against loss of the code since it could supply an intact code for one to use if its own code was damaged. Sexual exchange also (2) disseminated new information that allowed new kinds of behavior without the risk of random mutations. Eventually, some members of these early life forms developed specialized organs to gather the chemicals from the ocean used for building and repairing. They also developed special organs to exchange the chemical codes. Organs involved in code exchange must have differentiated early on into two complementary types to facilitate the exchange. This gave rise to gender or the male/female difference. The specialized organs of gender used for genetic material exchange eventually developed the ability to duplicate the chemical code. The duplicate could be donated to give new life to others in a new form of reproduction. The ingesting of others was biologically specialized: The mouth to gather materials for building and repairing, and the female reproductive system to gather chemical codes from another similar (male) individual which the female sex cell assimilates as it is fertilized. Major Biological Events in a Female’s Life Cycle (1) Birth, (2) menarche (childbearing-ability–dispenser of blood creations), (3) menopause (keeper-ofthe-wise-blood) and (4) death with its cyclical return to birth (rebirth) gave rise to a female’s three stages of life: maiden, mother and crone (or hag, the wise women) and then death before rebirth. Nature too had three seasons: growth, reproduction and harvest, with a period of stasis or death before rebirth. The male sex cell is sacrificed as it enters the female since its cell wall is destroyed and its genetic information is combined with the female. Sexual exchange is risky. Even for the female there is risk: Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 4: Origins The female’s cell wall, that controls the cell’s immediate environment and the stability required for life, is opened. What comes in are not relatively passive chemicals fully under the control of the cell, but chemicals capable of directing the cell itself. Luna Early people knew the female sex organs created life. They also knew mouths caused death. Birds kill insects; cats kill mice. Eating was known to be necessary to give the reproductive organs material to work with. Death and life were two aspects of the same cosmic cycle. Someone’s life was always taken to make, remake or sustain another’s life. Even the Goddess was thought to need renewal of her creative material, mainly her blood. Death renewed her. Death was not an unexplained mystery, nor punishment. Humans, animals and plants were often deliberately killed as sacrifices either to feed the Goddess (as a thanksgiving), or as a propitiation of her anger (to win her favor). Gendered sex, like eating, requires one to die for another to live. The ancient sex roles of men and women were determined by their basic body functions. Women reproduced and nurtured others with their bodies. Men were probably secondary to the basic social structure, especially as agriculture and domestication of animals became more important than foraging and the killing skill of the hunt. But both men and women could enjoy sex and eating. Often this enjoyment was expressed as a sacred ritual. Men were renewed by their sexual connection to the Goddess embodied in women. Through women, men could participate in the Goddess’ blessing, literally, “being bled upon.” Even today the male priest’s blessing retains the gesture of the hand sprinkling the blood (or salt which was a blood substitute because of the similar taste). Pornography and rape can be seen, in part, as a desperate, ritualistic attempt to keep in touch with the Goddess, the female energy, when it becomes denied and difficult to access, even though such brutal acts are also ways for men to assert control of women. Kinky sexual activities often reflect the need to have her body fluids on or in one, despite the strong menstrual blood taboos in force today or reactions of disgust some have toward those who desire Annie 34 A Process Introduction to Philosophy 35 Chapter 4: Origins Sprinkle4 to “baptize” them. Ingesting menstrual blood (and also semen) was/is a communion ritual for some Gnostic and Tantric groups. The sacredness of eating flows from its ability to sustain us as well as from the recognition that selfmaintenance destroys others. Also, in a philosophy that saw all of reality as the body of the Goddess, eating is eating the divine. Her flesh becomes our flesh which is still her flesh. Her blood gives life to our body, wisdom to our minds. The priestesses of Charis, the Goddess of sexual love, whose name is remembered in the eucharist (communion), bade worshippers to drink and bath in her lunar, womb blood, the original Holy Grail. As personal afterlife became a goal, people had to acquire the divine attribute of immortality. Only gods and goddesses were immortal because they had access to the blood of life or the fruits from the tree of life. These fruits the Goddess freely gave to all until the age of patriarchy enthroned its jealous and competitive gods, the Goddess’ sons. Symbolism during the Neolithic civilizations of the Goddess was highly developed. Gimbutas thinks the voluminous symbols inscribed on bone, clay and stone artifacts was a fully developed script that will someday be deciphered.5 Even if this is not the case, the patterns and placements of the symbols make many of them very obvious. This gives us an insight into this civilization’s mind, into the concepts developed out of that culture which we still use. Some examples: three-fold division of the universe: sky, earth and underworld. The owl with its nocturnal habit and wise look stood for the crone aspect of the Goddess, or the death Goddess. Female Reproductive Organs The crescent stood for the moon which was considered female because it waxed and waned with the female’s menstrual cycle. The moon’s three phases matched the basic female trinity: maiden, mother, crone. The forth dark, new moon phase, was the transition phase from death to new life. Bovine Scull The Pubic Triangle The triangle was inscribed on the pubic region of many female sculptures. It symbolized the female’s reproductive powers, especially the power of the cosmic female, the Goddess. It also stood for the earliest trinity: maid, mother and crone, and the 4Annie Sprinkle, a famous porn star, would urinate on men who volunteered to come up on stage with her. Perhaps it’s only coincidence that Anna is one of the oldest names for the Goddess, giving rise to “mama,” “mammaries,” and “man,” (moon people). 5Compare Ogam, a script for writing many languages that looks like tally marks, found on rocks in Europe and America. See McGlone, Celtic America. The bovine skull with horns is very similar in shape to the uterus and fallopian tubes of the female reproductive system, and so seems to have symbolized female reproductive power, not masculine bullishness, even though horns are phallic symbols referring to the pleasure the organ can give. Georgia O’Keeffe’s painting of a skull and flow-er, “Summer Days” could be a modern example of such symbolism. The snake, with its ability to shed its skin and burst forth with new life, stood for rebirth. Its unhinged mouth is like a vulva able to ingest whole individuals into its womblike body (or give birth from it). The wiggling energy of the snake stood for 36 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 4: Origins process, flux or becoming as opposed to the static existence of being. Spirals and wiggles are still shorthand today for the snake’s energy. Process is more basic than being. This distinction between being and becoming, between process (that is, coming into being or creating) as opposed to the being that has become and now is created, lies at the very core of all philosophical concepts and attempts to explain the nature of reality. The snake is also a phallus, created by the Goddess and a source of pleasure for the female. The tree with its roots in the underworld, its trunk in the world and its arms in the sky symbolizes the three-fold universe. Uni, a cognate with “yoni” (vulva), was actually one of the names of the threein-one Goddess. The tree or cross is the axis of the universe upon which the heavens were assumed to turn. The tree or pole also supposedly held the heavens and the earth apart after their initial separation. The Goddess was often seen as a bird because the universe was thought to be a cosmic egg laid by the cosmic Creatress. The egg-like structure was devised to account for the stars circling around the earth. Flies and butterflies, were thought to be souls in transition to a new life. Flies were seen leaving decaying bodies. The Lord of Flies was the chief of psychopomps, those who transport souls. Embryos The frog was symbolic of the fetus. In one of the many developmental stages a human embryo/fetus goes through, it looks very much like an amphibian. Chapter Summary Gender was a significant factor in humanity’s first attempts to understand the greatest dimensions of existence. The female gender was considered to be the inclusive gender. Female anatomy and physiological functions were the basis for the original metaphors to explain the universe, including how anything was created, that is, born, and what happened to us at death, that is, return to the womb to be reborn in some form. Life was seen as a process where each step led to another, where the periodic cycles of women were also the cycles of the cosmos: All reality was seen as one and interconnected. If this cosmic understanding is philosophy, then religion (the word derives from the Latin religio, “to be tied to or into” the whole) carries out the rituals that evoke our emotions and express our interconnectedness with the cosmos and, therefore, the meaning of our life. Suggested Reading: See the works cited in the Bibliography under the Prehistorical and Historical Social Structure and Human Sexuality section, especially, Gimbutas, Grahn, Stone and Walker. Also see The Goddess Remembered, a video by the Canadian Film Board. ************************************************************************** Peace Signs A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 4: Origins UNIVERSITY OF MARY [Handout as part of a faculty orientation ceremony] LITANY OF MARY OF NAZARETH R: Be our Guide Mary, wellspring of peace Model of strength Model of gentleness Model of trust Model of courage Model of patience Model of risk Model of openness Model of perseverance R: Pray for us Mother of the liberator Mother of the homeless Mother of the dying Mother of the nonviolent Widowed mother Unwed mother Mother of a political prisoner Mother of the condemned Mother of the executed criminal R: Empower us Woman of mercy Woman of faith Woman of contemplation Woman of vision Woman of wisdom Woman of grace and truth Woman, pregnant with hope Woman, centered in God Closing Prayer: Mary, Queen of Peace, we entrust our lives to you. Shelter us from war, hatred and oppression. Teach us to live in peace, to educate ourselves for peace. Inspire us to act justly, to revere all God has made. Root peace firmly in cur hearts, and in our world. Amen. 37 38 Chapter 5 From Goddess to God “[In a public place] O. J. grabbed Nicole’s crotch and said [to strangers]: ‘This is where babies come from, and this belongs to me.’” Denise Brown, 2/3/95. “I don’t take her for granted. I do everything for her. I give her everything.” O. J. Simpson, 1995. “She liked it.” Boxer Mike Tyson commenting on his rape victim, Desireé Washington. “Look how selfish you are...If each [man] would have a woman, there would be no war. That’s why you [women] are the source of war on the planet.” Vladimir Zhurinovski , Chechen nationalist, chiding writer, Jennifer Gould, for not agreeing to have group sex with him and his body guards, 1995. Sampson. ...Women, being the weaker vessels, are ever thrust to the wall; therefore I will push Montague’s men from the wall, and thrust their maids to the wall. Gregory. The quarrel is between our masters, and us their men. Sam. ‘Tis all one; I will show myself a tyrant: when I have fought with the men, I will be civil with the maids: I will cut off their heads. Gre. The heads of the maids? Sam. Aye, the heads of the maids, or their maidenheads, take it in what sense thou wilt. Gre. They must take it [in] sense that feel it. Sam. Me they shall feel while I am able to stand....My naked weapon is out.”6 Romeo and Juliet, Act I, Scene I ***************************************************************************** Focus>>• –Issues– (1) Social control and respect as residing in the gender that creates new life and sustains it. (2) Meaning as founded on the biological urge to survive one’s death (be saved) by passing on one’s genes. –Approaches– (1) Female-Based Theory: (a) Body fluids: Menstrual blood is the stuff of new life and breast milk sustains it. (b) Genes are passed on with every pregnancy. (c) Males’ meaning is in ((1)) furthering female ends, especially reproduction, and ((2)) being sacrifices whose blood both fertilizes nature, by returning a portion of the Creatress’ blood in thanks, and imitates the female bleeding (blessing). (2) Emerging Male-Based Theory: (a) Body fluids: ((1)) Semen is the stuff of new life in miniature. ((2)) Genital blood-letting is less an imitation of the female and more a sign of passage to manhood and commitment to a misogynist or separatist worldview. (b) Genes are only passed on if seed is placed in a unfertilized womb. A virgin womb assures a male he is not cuckolded and raising another man’s child. (c) Females find meaning by nurturing and nursing male creations. 6Some public school English textbooks that include Romeo and Juliet have had a footnote at this point saying, “Shakespeare is punning; do you get it?” The more recent ones I’ve seen leave this whole sequence out and renumber the lines leaving no indication of an ellipsis, fraudulently “sanitizing” Shakespeare by the expurgation. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 39 Chapter 5: Goddess to God –Evaluation– Pro: The female gender-based cosmology is one-sided, so a reaction can be expected. Cons: (1) Each gender-based theory implies lack of equal respect for half the population. (2) Patriarchy tends to set up groups of ins and outs to polarize society since a male’s biological success is increased by excluding other males from females and subordinating females so they can’t control when they become pregnant. ****************************************************************************** I f the female in the guise of the Goddess was the beginning and the end, the whole of reality, what was left for the male? The human male is somewhat more specialized for combat, though probably not to protect females. Females, except those who have been co-opted by the myths of male dominator societies, can generally defend themselves and others; consider the legendary ferocity of a mother defending her young. Biologists suggest the male is designed to compete with other males for access to females. So, where females tend to further their needs by cooperation and inclusion, males tend to see the world competitively, in terms of ins and outs, right down to the biology of reproduction. Biologically, males can further their genes: (1) by gaining access to females and preventing other males’ access, or (2) by having their access be more successful than other males. Access can be more successful if one has: (a) more frequent access, (b) more sperm, or (c) deposition of sperm in a more advantageous position. In all cases the female is successfully impregnated, even though some kinds of male genes may make her children more successful than others, since if her off spring die before reproducing, her genes will still fail to be passed on. Access to the female originally depended on the grace of the female. Rape, as in the rest of the animal world, was likely rare. The female chose her consorts and dismissed them as she wished. Rape as a means of access to a female would have been largely unnecessary anyway since females must have generally sought and enjoyed sexual experience, so the deprivation of sexual experience or a variety of such experiences for men would have been far more unusual than is the case in patriarchy. Judy Grahn puts forth a theory in Blood, Bread and Roses that one reason for humans to become conscious of the division into ins-and-outs groups within their own species may have came from the danger posed to menstruating females by predators attracted to blood. The females, to save themselves and lessen danger to the tribe, climbed trees or otherwise isolated themselves (or were forced) from the group, forming a separate group. The behaviors involving menstruating females became ritualized. The woman’s power to affect the lives of others was projected by sympathetic magic and empirical observations (for example, that the moon’s cycle was synchronized with the female’s ) onto the world around her. The creative power of blood, its danger and its tie to the cycles of the universe at large, made menstruation the central blood rite and first explanatory mind-set. The menstruating female was seen as the conduit of spiritual powers into the physical world. She was the first shaman, the first holy person who could unleash both positive and destructive powers. The Goddess’ priestesses combined what we today call the sacred and the profane, the holy (wholesome) and the prostituted. In an article in Penthouse 1 a priestess/prostitute restates this controversial theme: To guide another person to orgasm, to hold and caress, to provide companionship and initiation to new forms of sex, to embody the divine and embrace the seeker––these are healing and holy acts.…We show the face of the Goddess in a culture that has tried for millennia to break and deny Her....Were the attack on us over, we could begin to heal the whole world. After 7,000 years of oppression, I declare this the time to bring back our temple. Merlin Stone (When God Was a Woman, 211) points out the Hebrew word zonah is translated both as “prostitute” and “prophetess,” meaning the one with the power to reveal the Goddess. But only females had this power, the power of the blessing (bleeding on). Young females could anticipate it, old females had experienced it. It was the defining characteristic of a female’s mid-life, even more than giving birth. The great chasm between male and female was the menstrual mind-set. Men had to be brought into the scheme of explanation. Men had to bleed and have blood rites. The answer came in terms of genital and other bodily mutilations, and in the blood-letting rituals of the “kill” both in the hunt and in war and more symbolically in sports. 7 Fall 1994 , “Sacred Prostitute.” 40 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 5: Goddess to God The comfort and security all have felt at the breast evokes longings of a better, more peaceful life when we are threatened or weary of the destruction brought by competition. The pleasure of sex gives rise to metaphors of bliss that the religious mystic seeks as a perpetual state of existence. Still, the ancient male understood his existence in female metaphors. He was still seen as a means to female pleasure and a supplemental helper of her divine mission of creating and recreating life. A male had to find his purpose for existence in his relationships to the female. Even the pleasure and security of a woman’s body, suckling her breast, would come to signal to the male mind, his dependence on the female, a dependence which, in the new patriarchal social order coming into existence, could be seen as unmanly weakness. His anxiety in this vulnerable position likely underlay his need to see sexual intimacy, too often, as synonymous with male domination. Social power for the Neolithic male came from his relationship with a female. A king originally acquired power because he was a queen’s consort. But with the domestication of animals and women’s awareness of her cycle in numerical terms, came the knowledge that sex was necessary for reproduction. What the connection was, must have been vague at first. Many thought, perhaps, the male did something that awakened the natural parthenogenic process. Philosophies have struggled with this issue for thousands of years. Only in the mid-nineteenth century was the biology fully understood. As his awareness of the male role in reproduction became more obvious, his role in the theories developed to explain the meaning of life were given more prominence. The female explanatory metaphors (collectively known as the Goddess) were modified to accommodate male metaphors so gods became more important. The Goddess created, that is, gave birth to the gods. This was a natural conclusion since the Goddess was believed to create everything. Eventually, some people concluded there have always been two divine realities, one of each gender. The male child (god) and his (divine) mother is a pervasive theme in many religions, including Christianity, yet today. Eventually, the male (in later myths) becomes the mother’s mate. In this rather equalitarian mythical state they conceive the universe. One of the realities they create is other children, one of which will grow up to challenge and eventually usurp the females’ male consort or king and take his place. The old king is dead, killed by his “son” who really is the old king reborn in new form. The son is in turn killed (after he becomes a man) by his father reborn as a son. This is the fundamental menstrual cyclical pattern of reality but now with a large dose of male competitiveness. Queen matriarchs, seen as incarnations of the Goddess, embodied both the civil lawgiver and the spiritual priestess (as the collective ritual consciousness of the tribe). She could take a male for pleasure and breeding for a season or two. When she tired of him, she could have him eliminated by her new interest. The new king had to prove his worthiness by his ability to eliminate the old king. This turnover eventually became ritualized. Kings knew to be loved by the queen meant certain death. The privilege and consequence of being the mate of the Goddess’ earthly representative was to be consumed by that love, to be offered up as a blood sacrifice to placate the spirits by returning to them, in thanks, part of what the spirits had so generously given to humanity. As gruesome as it may seem to us, it is likely many men accepted death for the chance to make love to the Goddess’ representatives, the queen and the queen’s priestesses. They believed they would become gods immediately upon death because they had become divine through their sexual relationships with the Goddess’ human incarnations. The sacrificial males were suspended on poles in the fields. The divine’s son/consorts were often speared, chopped to pieces and spread on the land. Their flesh and blood were thought necessary to made the ground fertile. In death, these men become divine. Eating their flesh and drinking their blood assured others of immortality also, the main attribute that gods and goddesses had that people didn’t. We become what we eat and drink. But as the day grew near for a king to give up his life to fructify the land and make room for a new king, many must have had second thoughts. One way for a king to save his life would be to find a substitute to die for him. This substitute became known as a “sacred king. ” For a king to satisfy his death ritual by finding another to take his place suggests the queen must have been willing to keep him as her mate a while longer or that the power of the king to act independently of the queen’s wishes was increasing. The sacrifice of the queen’s consort was perhaps thought necessary to preserve the sanctity of the queen. Later, removal of his genitals and/or the substitution of sacrificial animals may have been thought sufficient. Even animal sacrifice started disappearing as vegetation metaphors became ritually more important. The story of Cain, who offered vegetation (that God rejected) rather than an animal as a sacrifice as did Abel, tells us the Hebrews were not yet willing to give up animal sacrifices. However, Abraham’s substitute of a lamb for his son’s sacrifice likely tells us that human sacrifice was being reconsidered at that earlier time. Many men choose to become eunuchs to be more like women, a practice popular in some religions well into the Middle Ages, even in Christian sects. Genital mutilation for religious or cultural purposes is still a A Process Introduction to Philosophy 41 Chapter 5: Goddess to God very common practice, even though many deny our forms of genital cutting are mutilations. The majority of American male babies have, for the last fifty years, the most innervated part of their genitals cut off, the prepuce, a practice started in the late nineteenth century to try and stop masturbation. The myth that circumcision is for medical reasons is our way of rationalizing this behavior since other “reasons” given in other times, like “God told us to do it” or pleasure is bad, are not widely accepted in our more secular world. Sometime around 2000 BCE mythologies begin to reflect the increasing male independence and dominance. The mother Goddess is killed: for example, Tiamat in Sumerian/Babylonian myth is used by the male god Marduk to make the universe. Her tears become rivers, her body the earth. Eventually, she is nearly written off all together as the male god needs her only as a passive and chaotic substratum or genderless boundless stuff (the basic cosmic life fluid) on which to impose his order, as the Hebrew tradition puts it in Genesis or the Milesians suggest (see Chapter 6). Later, with the male gods’ ability, supposedly, to create ex nihilo (make something out of nothing) the Goddess is gone completely, and all possibility of logically understanding process, change and creating is given up. The transition from the female birthing-creator to the male ex nihilo creator took thousands of years and reflects not only the transition from a female-centered culture to a male-centered one, but also the change from creating by giving birth to creating by manipulating our physical surroundings. The stories, relating how a goddess (and later gods) created by molding clay, often retain the tie to menstruation and birth creating since the clay is reddened or bloodied. For example, the Assyrians say Eve, that is, Mother-Womb, Creatress of Destiny, made humans out of clay and gave them life with her blood. Blood was thought to be the essence of life. “Adam” means “[blood] reddened earth.” Males, after thousands of years, had found the conceptual basis to turn their fate around, but at the expense of the female. The male becomes the true creator. The sperm is the source of new life. The female becomes a passive field wherein a male plants his seed when he plows her furrow; she is a nursemaid, man’s helpmate, plaything and slave. She incubates the life placed in her body which is considered sterile and passive without man’s creation. Even the moon milk of the milky way becomes the god’s cosmic ejaculate, though the asceticism of the new belief systems generally found it easier to retain the female imagery than refer to the gods’ masturbatory issue. The faith of patriarchy was being born. Patriarchal gods reflect the male’s dominant status. Not only do gods dominate goddesses, but gods dominate other gods. Even tually, the god of a particular group of male gender-worshipers claims to be the only God for the group (the god being jealous of all others) and eventually for everyone else. This is one factor in the development of monotheism, and particularly one strident form known as classical theism. Logical reasons for another form of monotheism will be discussed later along with the concept of “unsurpassability.” The question of the unity of divinities is again answered by claiming there is only one, only now the gender is male and the “unity” is usually “up there” apart from the world needing unification. But gender is an unstable attribute for cosmic unity. It either requires its opposite, and so destroys the unity, or makes one gender subordinate to the other. Patriarchy requires a man know who his offspring are. 8 His name, wealth and social status must be passed down to his sons. Since a man must still employ a womb to nurture his creation, the only way for a man to know for sure whether the child in the womb is his is to make certain no other male has planted seed in “his” womb. Womb control drives every factor of patriarchal ethics. Virginity, not in the old sense of a strong, viral and independent woman, but in the pre sent sense of an unopened vagina, is valued as assurance that the womb will nurture only its owner’s creations. Love, Honor and Obey. Marriage, meaning a woman pledges her womb only to the man who owns her, becomes an important institution, so extra-marital sexual experience becomes highly censured, at least for women. As stated in Deuteronomy: If a new bride is not a virgin...they shall bring the damsel to the door of her father’s house and the men of the city shall stone her with stones that she die. Deut. 22:21. Patriarchal societies yet today try to control female virginity and interest in sex for pleasure. The radical patriarch believes female sexual experience should be restricted to reproduction, the nurturing of a male creation. Sex for pleasure, masturbation, oral sex, sex with anyone else but her master, are all evil. 8Most of us are surprised to learn people can live together without sexual possessiveness and monogamy. Both males and females of the Amazon hunter-gatherer tribe, the Arara, have multiple sex partners, even during one night. Not knowing who has fathered the children give all men a sense of responsibility for all children. Those who are possessive and selfish are ostracized and cannot survive. 42 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 5: Goddess to God One extreme way to control frightening and unwanted female sexuality, a way that affects 100 million women alive today (though practiced for thousands of years), is amputation of a young girl’s clitoris, and often her inner labia as well, to remove the pleasure-producing tissue, before stitching her up to make intercourse impossible until cut open again. Men in these societies are making sure that genital mutilation is not only a male’s experience.9 Evidence that female sexuality was considered frightening is found expressed by many of the most revered of patriarchs. Consider St. John Chrysostum (345-407): “Among all savage beasts none is found so harmful as woman.” The subordination of women has its effect on men also. Patriarchy is not only male gender against female; it is also male against subordinate male. Dominant males only tolerate other males in so far as they are obedient. The motivation in patriarchal religions is usually fear. God loves those who do as he says. He rewards those who do and punishes those who don’t. Egoism, ultimate concern for oneself in the long run, underlies all motivation. In patriarchy, genital mutilation (for example, male circumcision) is practiced, not to imitate the female, but as an initiation sacrifice into the dominant males’ world. It is a sign that one entrusts himself or his son to the powers that be. It is the ultimate male exposure, causing deep feelings of vulnerability. It is a sign one is subordinate to those who can ask for such a sacrifice. Many believe it is also one way for the old males to strike back at the growing virility of their upstart rivals. The competition between males is reflected in their cosmic schemes. There is always one place for those who have obeyed and another place for those who haven’t. Cosmic unity can’t reside in the patriarchal God or his heaven since there is reality outside this God. If all must be in God, then the motivation based in the fear of being left out disappears and the ability to control others by fear is lost. Patriarchy uses the first breeding strategy noted earlier: Gaining access to a female (by removing her ability to reject the male) and holding her off limits to other males by physical or moral force. The more females a male controls, the more offspring he can have. Not only does the monopoly of females by dominant males leave many males without access to a female, but females now must become competitive with other females to win the favor of dominant males even when they are part of his harem. 9Sad to say this is not just an activity found in African and other foreign countries. Clitoridectomies in the U.S. was one way tried to control women’s sexuality in the nineteenth century. Fortunately, it did not catch on the way male circumcision did. There is a least one Dakota woman of Scandinavian descent who has lived her fifty years since she was three years old sexually and psychologically maimed by this operation because her parents and physicians were trying to stop her from masturbating. Females who are not controlled by a father, spouse or son are suspect. Margulis suggests that hominoids have not always functioned this way, since the relatively large size of human sex organs suggests a strategy less like the baboon model of male domination and more like the chimpanzee model of promiscuous sexuality. Many works that examine the civilization of the Goddess paint the period as cooperative with little war. Evidence does seem to support a much less contentious time. But on the steppes of southern Russia about 4000 B C E , a group arose who domesticated the horse and devised spears and daggers (first of hardened copper, but eventually of iron) for use against other humans. The ancient Mideast world had many memories of warriors from north of the Caspian and Black Seas. They were called Amazons; they were, likely, originally a matriarchal society, as all early tribes seem to be. They were among the first Indo-Europeans. Perhaps, before more evidence is in, one can conjecture that the ability to dominate others with new, more powerful weapons, along with the development of rapid transportation provided by the horse, diminished the value of (h)earth and home and enhanced the warrior ethic which valued mobility to facilitate plundering, dominating and killing. This was activity in which men could eventually excel, not having to get pregnant and care for children. In any case, the militant mentality and social structures of these proto-Indo-Europeans that developed after 5000 BCE north of the Caspian and Black Sees came to dominate most of Europe, North Africa, the Mideast and India in the two to three thousand years from 4000 to 1000 BCE. By 2000 B C E this movement was forcibly converting goddess-worshipping cultures to worship of male gods. The dominators claim to rule by the “mandate of Heaven,” as the Chinese say. They also claimed the right to rule because they were made in the image of the divine. The use of force continued for thousands of years, up to the 500 years of the witch-burning craze in the late Medieval and Renaissance periods and even up to the present day. It surfaces in sex-discrimination, homophobia and racism. The pain sustained by those subordinated and the sacrifices required of them were supposedly justified by the protection the dominators provide against other competing dominators. Women’s place was no longer her three-fold role of independent maiden, strong and nurturing mother and wise (and sometimes fearful) old women. She existed to serve men and his institutions, including his male divinities and their priesthoods. But the old tradition is not gone, it is trivialized: The Goddess in her many forms has become transformed into saints, little people, fairies and Halloween witches. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 43 Chapter 5: Goddess to God The myth that God sanctions any action, including exterminating those who are not believers, if they will not “submit” (the meaning of “Moslem”), for their own good, of course, has bathed the world in more blood than the Goddess could have ever imagined. Yet, it is sentimental to long for a return to Goddess worship. Men were not equal to women, and discrimination may have given rise to the anxiety and anger that may have produced the backlash the world has lived with for 5000 years. After examining more closely the logic of change and unity, Chapters 15-17 will look at patriarchal systems developed in the Modest in the first millennium BCE that have had a major influence on our present philosophies, religions and social orders. Finally, the philosophical basis for a genderless, but personal, cosmic unity will be examined. The conclusion will be that only such a view is logical, and only such a view can underlie an equalitarian ethic. Chapter Summary Evidence is accumulating that the first philosophies or worldviews, were based on the incorrect belief that the female’s physiology was self-sufficient in reproductive creativity. These philosophies focused on the female’s natural flow of her sacred body fluids: Blood, milk and the salt water we first developed within, the amniotic fluid. Men were drafted or volunteered to be mutilated and sacrificed as one way to find their purpose within such a world view. A reaction to this “goddess” tradition began in the late Neolithic, and by the second millennium BCE was well underway. Perhaps as men discovered their essential role in reproduction, they over-emphasized it, seeing women as incubators only. Religions developed that worshipped male gods and saviors wherein blood-letting was still important. Male gods and his sons were worshipped and sacrificed. Those who were made in the image of male gods with their aggressive behavior, became revered, reversing the view that women were to be revered because they were created in the image of the tripartite divine. Controlling women, more particularly their wombs, is a paramount motivation in cultures where there’s a strong need to know whose sons are whose. Suggested Reading: Lerner, The Creation of Patriarchy. Teubal, Sarah The Priestess; Stone, When God Was a Woman; Gallenkamp, Maya; Mallory, In Search of the Indo-Europeans; Wolkstein, Inanna: Queen of Heaven and Earth; Gardner, Gilgamesh. ************************************************************************* Male Student’s Response to Goddess Worldview “It’s very hard to believe there are women who truly believe in the Goddess as the creator. It is one thing to have thoughts [of] a time when woman was worshipped as the ‘one most powerful,’ but it’s another thing to actually voice your thoughts and beliefs to others. Coming from a background of strong Christianity, it’s difficult to believe any other belief. However, seeing the paintings and sculptures and [listening to] what these women are talking about can be very unsettling to my thoughts and beliefs.” Student response to the videos, The Goddess Remembered and The Burning Times and discussions of prepatriarchal times. 44 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 5: Goddess to God Female Student’s Response to Goddess Worldview “Many times I have wondered why God is always referred to as ‘he,’ and my questioning has often been thwarted with statements like, ‘It’s just a word. We need to call him something!’ No matter how non-sacred it may seem, many people look for the higher power that makes the most sense or works the best in their lives. I think that the Goddess is a higher power that many people have overlooked due to the social programming calling for a male deity. I also think that for many people like myself, who are searching for that ‘spirituality’ that will fulfill some emptiness, the Goddess seems to occupy certain vacancies that the religion of God has left open. “The Goddess and her aura also diminish certain feelings of insignificance or unworthiness that this patriarchal society has, purposefully or not, brought to women in general. As I viewed the video in class, the reverent way in which woman and her cycles was discussed made me feel proud and grateful for having the chance to experience it all. “In grade school when I first learned what menstruation was and what it would mean for me when it happened, I celebrated the fact that it was approaching. I researched it at the library and would spend many recesses on the playground instructing my friends on what was going to soon happen to us, first making sure I was correct in all my terminology. In sixth grade, when my friend got her first period, I made her a card and a package with feminine products and I called it her ‘Welcome to Womanhood’ present. “I can’t remember how it happened, but soon thereafter menstruation (and sometimes being a girl in general) was looked upon with disgust both by my family and others. I eventually began to dislike the occurrence and dreaded the bleeding time, as well. It wasn’t until I saw this video, The Goddess Remembered , that I realized I had forgotten how I had initially treated the event with respect. I had forgotten the kinship we felt on the playground as we excitedly awaited menarche and how worshipful we girls were of the experience when it happened. “It scares me to think of how in just a few short years I lost the excitement I initially had (even as such a young girl) for being a woman. I’m not sure where I lost it or why, but I am so grateful that it is returning. I was jealous as I watched the women at the table in the video communing with each other. Each woman seemed so powerful and wise and strong. I think just as I had lost reverence for the powers I possessed just by being a woman, I lacked other strengths; I have also lost a great deal of self-respect. “I wish I could remember how and why my enthusiasm regarding womanhood was crushed. Sometimes I blame the separate rules and treatment given to my brother and me. Call it greed, but I never understood why just because I was a girl, I could only eat a half a donut, whereas my brother could eat one or two whole donuts. Why could my brother burp out loud and enjoy laughter and encouragement from my dad? Whenever I tried it, I was called a pig. I can only deduce that eventually, I realized that being a girl wasn’t fun because there were too many restrictions and laws for behavior. “The spirituality that many people find in the Goddess seems exciting and contagious. Whenever I have been in church or when I have tried praying to God, I have felt shameful and fearful. When thinking of the Goddess, a renewed sense of self is apparent. I am able to find spirituality and calm from within instead of a tense feeling of worry.” Student response to the videos, The Goddess Remembered and The Burning Times and discussions of prepatriarchal times. A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 5: Goddess to God The Hunt My ambiguous wait broken by A flurry of leaves Rushing of brush Bunching of power bound by grace A leaping race to clear the stream–– My shot: neck-breaking, A crumpling heap of meat, kicking, My rushing, thumping joy, dying, Slicing steel sharp to the guts, My hand plunged deep in blood Wrenching out my heart And my mind deep in death. © Duane Voskuil 1965 45 46 PART III Change and Permanence The Many Are One: The One Is Many ––––– Pythagoreans: Mathematics and Salvation ––––– Heraclitus (and Alice): Logos in the Flux and the Logic of Change ––––– Parmenides: The Logic of Being ––––– Pluralists: Materialism: Atoms, Locomotion, Freedom and Determinism ––––– Buddhistic or Platonic Series versus Monadic Substance ––––– Whitehead: Moments of Growth ––––– Summary of the Problem of Change 47 Chapter 6 The Many Are One The One Is Many “And this [first principle] is eternal and does not grow old, and it surrounds all the worlds.” Hipparchus, Phil. 6. Dox. 559, describing Anaximander’s Boundless Stuff. “And from what source things arise, to that they return of necessity when they are destroyed; for they suffer punishment and make reparation to one another for their injustice according to the order of time, as he [Anaximander] says in somewhat poetical language.” Simplicius, Phys. 6 r, ca. 500 CE . ****************************************************************************** Focus>>• –Issues– (1) Seeking what all things have in common; more specifically, seeking what stuff the four elements, earth, water, air and fire, are made of. (2) Seeking to explain how changes occur and what underlies differences. –Approaches– (1) Reality is one stuff (one cosmic energy soup) that takes on different forms. (a) Thales: All is water. (b) Anaximander: All is Boundless Stuff. Vortices set up centrifugal tensions that separate out opposites. (c) Anaximenes: All is air. More or less air (quantity) explains everything (quality). (2) All changes have one explanation. (a) Determinism: Changes occur blindly (and necessarily as they do?) without any conscious agent choosing to bring them about. (b) Reductionism: All qualitative differences are merely differences of quantity; or the whole is not more than the sum of “its” parts. –Evaluation– Pros: (1) The discovery that universal knowledge is necessary in order to understand reality. (2) Natural, lawful changes are not up to arbitrary choices by any one agent. (3) The attempt to explain comic unity focused the need to find a logical way to express cosmic wholeness. Con: (1) A single stuff cannot be a unity throughout changes. Either another theory must be found, or one must deny that change and (successive) diversity is real. (2) No whole is meaningful if it is not more than the sum of the parts it contains. (3) The bias against the reality of change has an ethical side: Stability is not only seen as more real, but better than a changing reality. ****************************************************************************** T raditionally, courses in Western philosophy have started with Thales, one of three men, called Milesians, who discussed the nature of the universe in the town of Miletus in western Asia Minor, one of many Greek port cities around the Aegean Sea. The questions they asked and much in the answers they gave had been around for millennia. Their answers did differ somewhat from the earlier, more goddess-oriented attempts, however, since they did not couch their philosophies in the personalistic 48 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 6: Milesians terms used to describe the acts of the gods and goddesses. Perhaps this is one reason their names and theories survived in the increasingly patriarchal millennia ever since. Philosophy is distinguished by the generality of its questions: What is everything like? What is the stuff that everything is made from? What is the unity that holds all the many things together? What does everything have in common? Where did everything come from? These questions had been asked and answered within the philosophical assumptions of the Goddess-oriented civilizations. The Great Goddess was the whole universe. She was one reality with three parts or aspects which reflected the threefold division of a woman’s life: maiden, mother and crone. Cosmologically, there were also three realms: (1) The world we live in, called Mitgard (middle yard or home) according to Scandinavian tradition (see illustration of Yggdrasil, Chapter 12). There was also (2) the sky above or heaven, and (3) the underworld below. The tree symbolized the three regions with its roots, trunk and branches. The three regions of the universe were three-in-one. One name for the Goddess was Uni, Three-in-One. The body of the Goddess was the cosmos. Whether this is pantheism or panentheism was never clearly distinguished. Later chapters will clarify this important distinction. All reality came from the womb of the Great Female Divinity. Her womb flowed with blood. From the flow of this flow-er we all are created. Early theories were parthenogenic: She needed no help from man. Her menstrual fluid coagulated, like her curdled milk, to form the physical reality we see. Later theories, influenced by the knowledge that in some way a male was required to give birth, said male fire in the form of lightening was quenched in the female water to make blood, the fluid of creation. Another theory suggested a man stirred up the latent reproductive energy of the female. The ancient world’s cosmologies had consolidated the many things found in the universe into four kinds of things or elements: earth, water, air and fire. During the Neolithic, all elements were parts of the Goddess, even males, since they were created by her. As the male contribution to creation became vaguely recognized and men gained more social power, the elements took on different genders as did other aspects of reality. Genderizing, even of those things around us that don’t have biological gender, should be expected when the very foundation of reality is gendered. Early gender assignments gave to the female the qualities of red and active, and to the male white and passive. These divisions follow the menstrual blood and semen distinction and the earliest understanding of women as creators by giving birth. The symbolism of the red berries of holly and the white berries of mistletoe still hark back to this sexual distinction. The dark earth grows and gives birth. Water is the primal ocean, the ambiotic fluid of the womb, from which we all have come. Dark and wet is female. This left light and dry, that is, fire and air, as male. Eventually, even water was masculinized, but the dirt of the ground and the darkness of the ground and underground have remained female or become a demonized male. All patriarchal religions worship some form of a light/sun god. T hales had learned the ability to predict some heavenly events, probably from the Egyptians. He is said to have predicted the eclipse of May 28, 585 BCE . The astronomical knowledge to make these predictions was acquired over thousands of years of watching the moon. The moon represented the threefold God dess, dispenser of the water/blood of life in women’s monthly cycle. Thales is best known for saying everything in the universe is water. He is expressing the ancient belief that all reality forms from the primordial female fluid of the All-Inclusive Female. This water, the earliest myths say, had to be separated into the waters above and the waters below in the first act of creation and, then, be held apart with a pole, tree or cross: the celestial axis. We can also imagine Thales knew water could become hard and earthlike, that is, frozen, and “airy” when it evaporates. Fire would be harder to explain, since water quenched fire, though in so doing, water turned to blood according to the bi-gendered theory of elements, long before water was said to be turned into wine (the universal blood symbol) by Jesus as the Christ. Thales makes the re-assertion that everything is really water without reference to the Goddess as far as we know. His answer seems to imply the stuff of reality is not personal, nor conscious. Neither do we know for sure whether Thales’ answer is numerically monistic or pluralistic. Is there one water or many waters? He does seem to say water is the unavoidable stuff of reality. Water is. Water is, to be redundant, being. But water becomes or comes to be the other elements. So, water is a reality that is, but also one that changes into other “less real” realities. Is water no longer water when it becomes a tree? Are elements other than water not really real? Can an actual, concrete material or stuff be what it is and change? (These questions will be examined later, Chapter 9.) A naximander, born about 611 BCE, another of the Milesians, did not pick one of the four particular elements to explain the others. Particulars, like gender, are always restricted to be this and not that. A particular is set off from others or “limited” as the ancient Greeks would say. The reality from which all particulars are made and into which they all dissolve again, must itself be nonpar- A Process Introduction to Philosophy 49 Chapter 6: Milesians ticular. It must be the Unlimited, the “Unnamable,” the Indeterminate, or the Unbounded. He also calls it divine, but his divine is not conscious nor personal. Anaximander’s expression echoes how the Great Goddess was “defined” before she created anything particular, namely, by saying what the divine is not. Yet, as we will see time and time again, trying to describe something by saying we cannot say anything positive about it, is always a strange logical construction. (See Unsurpassable in Glossary.) Though he says Reality is unbounded, that is, has no particular description, he still assumes the Unbounded has certain unavoidable characteristics. It seems to be one, not many. It is capable of taking on limitations and becoming particulars. It is capable of whirling since the explanation for particulars is the separating pressure set up when vortices form in the Unbounded causing opposites to separate out like chemicals in a centrifuge. The Principle of Sufficient Reason (see Chapter 2) asserts there must be a reason why particular things exist at all. He pro vides the Vortex as the reason. It sets up a tension that separates opposites from each other. An explanation must also be given for why just the particular things that have come to be, have done so. Who desired them or designed them? Anaximander does not appeal to any personal agent. He appeals to an innate, inherent natural law or logos. This law or order is not imposed from without. It is necessary, unavoidable and immanent . Blind necessity is the sufficient reason. Belief in blind determinism as a true metaphysical principle is now used to explain why things are as they are rather than saying a goddess or god (or anyone) chose things to be as they are. This opposition in the ancient world between choice and necessity was known as Zeus versus the Vortex. Today it is often referred to as Religion versus Science. The contemporary attempt to find explanations in terms of the Grand Unified Theory or Theories of Everything which say the universe began in the undifferentiated energy soup of the Big Bang, are very similar to Anaximander’s approach. Physicists also say every particular form of energy/particle which evolved out of the primeval matter/energy soup has an opposite form, that is, antimatter/energy. Even when the Cosmic Mother is ignored or denied, the conservatism of language betrays the earlier explanations: “matter” comes from an IndoEuropean root that gave us m a t e r and meter, “mother” and “measurement.” A naximenes, another Milesian, marks the transition to a more patriarchal view. He asserts air is the stuff from which all reality is made. Air, with fire, were considered masculine by the middle of the first millennium BCE as they still are in astrology. By picking a particular to explain other particulars, he seems to be retreating from the more general position of Anaximander. Anaximenes’ contribution to philosophy lies in his reduction of the many opposites found in Anaximander’s theory: light-dark; hot-cold, and so on. He sought more coherence by suggesting one law can explain all the differences experienced, namely, the Principle of Rarefaction and Condensation, that is, more or less air. The multiplicity of things experienced, not only are made of one stuff, but change according to one pattern or law, what scientists today would call The Theory of Everything. Anaximenes looks for one principle, but he really has two: (1) Air, to satisfy the meaning of “principle” as the stuff reality is composed of, and (2) Condensation and Rarefaction, to satisfy the other meaning of ”princi ple” as the pattern, function or law, that explains the changes the first principle undergoes. Anaximenes was one of the first to express the Principle of Reductionism. The reductionist thesis which has become nearly an unquestioned dogma of scientific method, maintains an explanation is only successful when one has reduced the multiplicity of differences of complex forms of actuality to the stuff and behavior of simpler forms. Reductionism can be expressed in at least two ways: (1) All differences of quality are differences of quantity, and (2) a whole is reducible to its parts without loss, that is, a whole is not greater than the sum of its parts. Even today scientists assume the only difference in the quality of one color from another is the length, or quantitative difference, of the wave. Reductionism denies the whole is greater than the sum of its parts. The psychologist who asserts the complete explanation of higher animal behavior is a function of cell physiology, the chemist who reduces actuality to one hundred odd elements, and the physicist who reduces them further to one something like “quarks” (though there are still six kinds of these), are all in the shadow of the thinkers from Miletus about six hundred years after Troy to the north was sacked. What can be said about the Milesian assumptions lying behind their questions and answers? Their positions assume: (1) That behind the multiplicity of our experiences lies something that does not change, or if it does, it always returns to what it began with: water, boundless stuff or air. Change is not quite so real as the changeless. 50 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 6: Milesians (2) That it makes sense to reduce the multiplicity of concrete reality to one concrete stuff, either one kind of stuff or one thing numerically, that is, monism of kind or number. Monism is more real than pluralism. (3) That explanations in terms of blind necessity make more sense than appeal to decisions. Mechanistic or cybernetic metaphors are truer than those appealing to purpose and freedom. Purpose is less real than Blind Law. Freedom is less real than determinism. (4) That the world of changing experience is not so real as the changeless world of thought. What the mind determines to be logically necessary is more real than sense experience. The degrees of reality are discoverable by thinking, not sense experience. The real world is the unseen “spirit” world; the experienced world is a world of appearance or reflection of the unseen. Reality’s relation to appearance must now be explained, though it seldom is. (5) That related to the degrees of reality, are degrees of goodness. What is changeless is better than what changes (or, historically, will soon be thought to be so). With the rise of static and linear descriptions of reality, the cyclical menstrual metaphors that first explained reality, fade. But many problems remain. Traditional Western philosophy began with the Milesians saying in effect that the female’s life fluids can be the stuff of reality without the female. With Anaximander’s assertion that the stuff of reality was beyond description, philosophy took another step away from the familiar female metaphors. Finally, with Anaximenes’ formulation that the male-gendered, dry air is the only stuff of reality, the Milesians’ deprecation of the warm, wet, dark wombworld from which we came and to which we return is complete. Soon this underworld will come to be a place of fear and punishment for one’s failure to believe or obey those who proclaim the male gender supreme. Chapter Summary The drive to find one principle of explanation is valid. The assumption there must be numerically One Being or Stuff of which all reality is composed is a major mistake. The pluralists will try to overcome this mistake by saying there are many stuffs, for example, many souls or atoms. But their belief that each of the many things in reality can remain the same actuality as it moves or alters, is undoubtedly philosophy’s second biggest mistake. These mistakes will be examined in the next chapters. We are still being negatively affected by the assumptions contained in the Milesians’ proposals for what reality is like, namely, (1) that change is not real, or not so real as what does not change, (2) that one stuff is more real than many, (3) that blind determinism is more fundamental than creativity and choice, (4) that what is conceptually rational is more real than what is directly experienced with the senses, and (5) that change is less valuable than changelessness. Suggested Reading: Freeman; Nahm; preSocratic sections from Histories of Philosophy. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 51 Chapter 6: Milesians ************************************************************************** Physicists hope smasher will look into God's mind Sunday, August 28, 1988 The Bismarck Tribune Physicists hope smasher will look into God's mind LOS ANGELES (AP)—Physicists wanting to “People are frustrated, “ center director Burton “understand what's in the mind of God” are frustrated by Richter said last week. “There are thousands of comglitches in a new $115 million atom smasher that may ponents to this machine which all have to work at a someday yield secrets about the makeup of matter and high level of reliability to get everything to work the birth of the universe. properly. It's going to take months to get this thing in “It's like you've been on a long trek to a mountain top decent shape. I hope people don't get depressed and thought you were going to reach it, but discover waiting.” you're only on a ridge with another valley to cross,” said But Richter, who won the 1976 Nobel Prize in physicist Michael Riordan, spokesman for the Stanford physics, declared: “We'll make this thing work. I have Linear Accelerator Center, 30 miles southeast of San no doubt about it.” Francisco. Z particles are so unstable they existed naturally only Construction was completed May 1987 on the tax- for an instant after the “big bang,” the explosion scipayer-funded collider, a 3-mile-long underground entists believe formed the universe up to 20 billion machine shaped like a tennis racket. That summer, it was years ago. expected to start its major task: mass-producing what are By using the collider to manufacture Z particles and known as Z particles. analyze how they decay into other particles, scientists But numerous technical problems have preventedcan study the makeup of matter and the fundamental proper operation of the device, so “it's unlikely we'll forces that governed the development of the universe. make a Z particle before the end of the year,” narrowing the U.S. lead in a race against European physicists to make new discoveries, Riordan said. *********************************************************************************** 52 Chapter 7 Pythagoreans Mathematics and Salvation “The Pythagoreans say that fire is at the center and that the earth is one of the stars, and that moving in a circle about the center it produces night and day. And they assume yet another earth opposite this which they call counter-earth....” Aristotle, de Caelo II. 13. 293 a 19 in a passage that inspired Copernicus. “[Physical laws] lie within the power of understanding of the human mind; God wanted us to perceive them when he created us in His image in order that we may take part in His own thoughts....Our knowledge of numbers and quantities is the same as that of God’s, at least insofar as we can understand something of it in this mortal life.” Kepler, 1571-1630, to von Hohenberg, expressing his reasons for believing mathematical physics is well-founded. “We must fight the temptations of the vehicle [body]...overcome the world...and get out of here.” Heaven’s Gate members, who were math-computer sophisticated, just before committing suicide to reach the “next level” on their way to the Kingdom of Heaven, March 1997, by way of aliens [angels] supposedly traveling in a UFO in the wake of comet Hale-Bopp. They lived an ascetic life––several were mutilated by castration, presumably with their consent. “Life is a voyage towards home.” Tombstone inscription, St. Mary’s Cemetery, Bismarck ND. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– (1) Finding the way to salvation. (2) Finding patterns that reality exhibits. (3) Finding the ratio of the side of a square and its hypotenuse, and other irrational ratios. –Approaches– (1) Salvation is releasing the soul from the body so it can go back to heaven away from contaminating matter: (a) through ascetic living, and disparaging things female (mater), (b) through knowledge of the true nature of reality, that is, the numerical ratios things exhibit, like the Pythagorean Theorem. (2) Reality can be understood by finding common mathematical patterns (rather than a common stuff). (3) The “infinitesimal” is supposedly large enough to measure a figure (that is, it’s finite), yet not so large as to have any size (that is, it’s not finite), or it won’t fit evenly along the side and hypotenuse of a square, and other figures with irrational ratios. –Evaluation– Pro: Their approach pointed in the direction of finding patterns that all reality exhibits, rather than looking for an altering stuff of which all reality is supposedly composed. Cons: (1) They assume mind can exist independently of matter. (2) They assume the best place to be is apart from the disgusting, if not evil, physical world. (3) They assume the “infinitesimal,” a SomeNone, makes sense. ****************************************************************************** A Process Introduction to Philosophy 53 Chapter 7: Pythagoras D uring the second half of sixth century BCE, Pythagoras founded a school of philosophy in southern Italy that to our modern mentality was a curious mixture of mysticism and mathematics. He is generally credited with discovering the Pythagorean Theorem, though Egyptian and Babylonian geometers certainly knew the relationships of the sides of some right triangles. The Pythagoreans seemed to have claimed reality not only exhibited numerical patterns, but is composed of numbers. By knowing the secret numbers or numerical patterns of things, we become enlightened to the truth of reality. This truth sets us free from the physical bonds entrapping our souls in this world, allowing them to return to the stars from which they came and where they naturally belong. This Gnostic or Orphic belief in the preexistence of the soul was becoming common in the ancient world. The Pythagoreans believed people were part divine (from the heavens), and part nondivine (from the world). Souls are made of the divine heavenly star stuff, sometimes called aether (a fifth element identified with the fifth regular solid, the dodecahedron, whose mathematical description they discovered); our bodies are made of matter. Pythagorean Gender Oppositions Male Female Right Left Limited (Specific) Unlimited (Vague) One (Unity) Many (Diversity) Odd Numbers Even Numbers Changeless Changing At Rest Moving Straight Curved Light Dark Square Oblong Good Bad Air, Fire, (Aether) Earth, Water Harmony Discord Like the constellation Gemini, people were twins, living in two worlds, but the Pythagoreans deprecated the feminine physical world and longed to break the bond between body and soul so the spiritual twin could return it his natural place in the heavens. See Buddhist quotation heading Chapter 11: An insightful, virtuous “man does not return to enter a womb again....” Their dualism reflects the increasing influence of the male over the female principle. Everything was assigned to one side or the other of the dualistic opposition of gender. Each of the five elements had a natural place, and when their natural order or location was disrupted, things were out of harmony. Goodness was harmoniousness, a common Greek ethic. Since the heavens are the realm of light and goodness, they must be harmonious. Therefore, the planetary spheres that define the various levels of heaven in the ancient cosmology must be related to each other by harmonious intervals. The Pythagoreans had learned musical pitches could be assigned numbers; and the relationships of these numbers, their ratios, explained why some chords are harmonious and others not. The relationship of something vibrating twice as fast as another is the ratio of 1:2, the octave. Something vibrating two times to another’s three, 2:3, is the ratio of the fifth. Instruments that are tuned and songs composed using fifths and octaves as the only intervals are still said to use Pythagorean Tuning. The soul itself was thought to have three parts that needed to be harmonized. The insight that aesthetic integration is the meaning of positive value, so that goodness is a subclass of beauty, is a core 54 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 7: Pythagoreans theme in Whitehead’s philosophy (Voskuil, “Whitehead’s Metaphysical Aesthetic”). Physical reality reflects or mirrors the “real” world (the unseen, spiritual world) of numbers. Plato alludes to the Pythagoreans when he says knowing the truth is like looking into a clean mirror that returns to us the real world as it is. Ignorance is not seeing clearly. When looking into a clouded or dirty mirror, truth does not meet us face to face, a metaphor Paul of Tarsus borrowed. Pythagorean Theorem The Divine Tetraktys Numbers were likely seen as the stuff of reality, not mere abstractions. If so, the Pythagoreans may be atomists, though they seem to say complex things composed of many numbers are not reducible to a group of ones without loss. They saw wholes as greater than the sum of their parts, which is a denial of Anaximenes’ reductionist thesis. Numbers were arranged in geometrical patterns. The One, or point, gives rise to the line when doubled to Two. Three Ones are a triangle or the simplest plane. Four Ones define the simplest three-dimensional and regular solid, the tetrahedron, and so physical reality, which was believed to be made of regular solids, is explained. All the numbers from one to four add up to ten (1+2+3+4 =10). All things are said to be contained in ten, a sacred number. Its geometry is still used in the bowling alley. Some numbers can be geometrically arranged in a square, like four or nine. Others can only be arranged in oblong or non-square rectangles, like six or twelve. If one takes the square numbers Nine, Sixteen and Twenty-Five which have Three, Four and Five units on the sides of their squares, and places the corners of the squares together, a right triangle is formed. Take the square root of each square and you have the number of units on the sides of the square. The so-called Pythagorean Theorem states this relationship: The total number of dots in the squares on the two shortest sides of a right triangle (9 + 16) are equal to the number of dots in the square on the longest side (25). The square roots of these squares form the sides of a right triangle. Builders still use multiples of the 3-4-5 triangle to layout right-angled foundations. The attempt to find other right triangles whose sides were exact ratios of some number of units was the beginning of some serious logical problems for the Pythagoreans. Take another simple right triangle, that formed by two sides and the diagonal of a square, or what is often called the unit triangle with a unit length of one on each side. What is the number of units along the diagonal, the hypotenuse? Obviously, the unit length along one of the sides is too short to fit along the diagonal and too long to fit along the diagonal twice. But if one divides each side into two units, then three of these units comes much closer to exactly measuring the hypotenuse than one or two of the previous units did. If the unit used is one fourth the original unit, so the sides are composed of four units, the new unit will come even closer to fitting a certain number of times along the hypotenuse. But, again, not exactly an even number of times. There is always a bit too much or too little with the last application of the unit. The unit that fits exactly a certain number times along the sides is always a bit too long or too short when used to measure the hypotenuse, no matter how small it is. The diagonal of a square is incommensurable with the sides. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 55 Chapter 7: Pythagoreans Irrational Ratios 2? 1 3? 1 1 However, the smaller the unit, the closer it does come to fitting evenly along both the sides and the hypotenuse. So the Pythagoreans required a unit so small it could not be smaller. The name they used for this so-called unit is the “infinitesimal.” Now this socalled “unit” must have some size since zero size cannot measure anything, and yet if it has some finite size it cannot exactly measure the sides and the hypotenuse. So the attempted definition of the “infinitesimal” is something with no size (so it will fit) and some size (so it can measure). We have seen earlier, however, there is no middle ground between some and none, so the attempted definition is no definition at all. An “infinitesimal” cannot express a ratio; it is not rational nor nonrational; it is ir-ratio-nal or nonsense. Hippasus, the person who divulged the crisis of the irrational infinitesimal was supposedly ostracized and likely killed, a common procedure for those who disagreed or disparaged faiths in the patriarchal religious wars to come. The “infinitesimal” is nothing meaningful. Every potential finite is capable of possible division. Between any two notes there is a possible third, fourth and so on, forever. Whitehead, a respected mathematician, said all talk about “infinitesimals” is simply talk about finites so small no one is interested in the size. Since the “infinitesimal” is their attempt to conceive the “smallest conceivable number,” which is the inversion of the “greatest conceivable number,” one must show that the “greatest conceivable number,” makes sense which is impossible. Possible numbers are endless, even if actual numbers are finite. The relationship of infinity, unboundedness or indeterminateness to an attempted concept of “the Unsurpassable,” or “the greatest conceivable reality,” must be carefully thought out. (An attempt to do so will be made, most pointedly, in Chapters 21-23.) Chapter Summary Finding patterns, rather than a stuff common to actual things, was a positive direction the Pythagoreans furthered. To understand something was to know its number or numerical ratio. When common conceptual “objects” were found for which no ratio of whole numbers could be found, they invented the “infinitesimal,” a quantity both small enough to be nothing and large enough to be something. Both Zeno (Chapter 9) and Whitehead say an actual infinitesimal is meaningless. We can see the strength of patriarchy in the Pythagoreans’ sexism and their desire to be saved by being released from mater . Their characterization of the “soul” does not carefully consider how such a reality can change and still remain the same thing. Suggested Reading: Freeman; Nahm; preSocratic sections from Histories of Philosophy. ************************************************************************************ 56 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 7: Pythagoreans Alpha and Omega Stylized alpha and omega, the first and last letters of the Greek alphabet, from the pulpit of the First Lutheran Church, Enderlin, ND. Both are pictographs of the womb/tomb. Alpha, now inverted, seems to have originally been a bovine skull whose head was the womb and horns the fallopian tubes. Omega has retained its orientation with its womb/tomb opening down, not up as everyone (in our more patriarchal era) hangs horseshoes to retain good luck. ***************************************************************************** Taboo U Permission to reprint cartoon requested of Etta Hulme. Introduction to Critical Thinking––A cartoon obviously inspired by a professor run afoul academic freedom. 57 Chapter 8 Heraclitus (and Alice) Logos in the Flux and the Logic of Change “Is it me, or is it not me?” Clever Elsa. Grimms Fairy Tales. “Who are you? said the Caterpillar. This was not an encouraging opening for a conversation. Alice replied, rather shyly, “I––I hardly know, Sir, just at present––at least I know who I was when I got up this morning, but I think I must have been changed several times since then.” Lewis Carroll, Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland, Advice from a Caterpillar. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– (1) The relationship of things that change to those that don’t. (2) The logical conditions required to rationally explain what “change” means. –Approaches– (1) Heraclitus’ proposal: (a) No physical thing is changeless; everything is constantly altering. (b) Stability is appearance that arises when two fluxes balance each other. (c) Logos, or the Law of Change, is the only universal constant in the universe. (2) Logic of Change: Change only makes sense if one can, (a) simultaneously compare (b) successive differences (c) of the same thing. –Evaluation– Pros: (1) Ultimate reality is composed of doings, processes or fluxes rather than beings that simply are or that supposedly move or alter. (2) The pattern of change is the ultimate constant. Cons: (1) If the past changes, that is, is no longer what it was, it does not exist to compare the present to, so no differences exist, and change is meaningless. (2) The logos seems to be conceived like a concrete Milesian stuff that is one, yet alters, rather than an abstract principle found in all concretes. *************************************************************************** 58 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 8: Heraclitus A nother approach to the nature of reality was made by Heraclitus, born of nobility in Ephesus around 536 BCE and died in 470 BCE. He detested the hoi ploi, the common herd of people, as he called them, who were gaining political power in the growing democratic movement, because he believed they could not appreciate excellence, and certainly didn’t appreciate the aristocracy. Heraclitus, like the Milesians, also chose one of the elements to be the substratum of reality. His choice was fire which by then had become identified with male power. But the element was also chosen to emphasize his main thesis: Nothing remains as it is even for one moment. One cannot step into the same river twice, he says, because both the river and the person have changed. Everything is changing constantly into its “opposite,” that is, “something it is not.” Fire in its constant fluctuation, whether like lightning from above or like burning wood from below, symbolized well the constant change or becoming of reality. He admits we experience stability, or things that don’t change (that is, things that are not coming to be, but already are), but, he says, experience of stability is only an appearance which arises because the flux of fire in one direction is countered by fire fluxing in the opposite direction. The Upward Way of fire and the Downward Way reach an equilibrium for a while. Modern analogies might be found in a standing wave, or the constant pH of a chemical solution. Everything is changing but.... A quick reading of Heraclitus might take him to say everything changes, or all is in constant flux, but this would be logically self-contradictory, on the face of it, since “constant” means changeless. But Heraclitus has another aspect to his theory, the logos. Logos is One and changeless; it is the unity of reality, a concrete universal, the One in the Many. The logos has a long history. In the Greek world, Hermes, a virgin-born hermaphrodite and conductor of souls to and from the world, was the logos, Word, made flesh. Logos is translated as “word” in the Gospel of John 1:1: “In the beginning was the Word, and the Word was with God and the Word was God.” The idea of the logos comes from ancient word magic. The power of the Goddess’ utterance could bring something into existence, just as her word could also destroy it. The word of words that referred to the source of all creations, the Goddess’ pregnant womb, was “Om,” and many temples to the Goddess had an omphalos, a stone rounded on top said by some to represent the navel of the belly (but more likely a female om-phallus, that is, a clitoris) and the center of the universe. “Om” in Arabic means “mother, matrix, source, principle or prototype.” Om is the last letter of the Greek alphabet and is drawn like a horseshoe (omega, Ω), an Indo-European symbol for the gateway to the womb, the yoni. It is a re peat of the first Greek letter alpha, formed from the upside down (patriarchal inversion of the) cow’s skull which likely symbolized the female organs with horns as the fallopian tubes. “Å” began its symbolic life with its point down before its inversion. (See alpha and omega photographs at the end of Chapter 7.) As worship of maleness increased, many ways were devised to usurp the birth-creating and breastnurturing of the Goddess, neither of which men nor their male gods could naturally do. So strong, however, was the need for birth-giving and nursing as a sign of divinity that even male gods gave birth to female ones, the reversal of nature and previous accounts. Zeus, for example, is said to have given birth to Athena, from his head. Clement of Alexandria, a Christian patriarch of the Third Century CE writes that, The Word is everything to the child, both father and mother, teacher and nurse....The nutriment is the milk of the Father... and the Word alone supplies us children with the milk of love....For this reason, seeking is called sucking; to those infants who seek the ‘Word,’ the Father’s loving breast s supply milk. [Walker, WEMS. 547] One way the Goddess did create, that males could easily copy, was by her Word or Voice (logos) since it required no womb. The history of the logos indicates Heraclitus was appealing to a real and necessary unity (universe) despite the apparent multiverse. Change or flux is universal in the world of sense experience, but in the real world (the world “behind” sense experience for an ultra-rationalist) the logos, that is, logic, is the underlying constant. Perhaps Heraclitus was trying to express a view of reality that required both the many (the changing) and the One (the changeless), but his emphasis on the logos leads one to believe he thought the changeless is more real than that which changes. The ancient concept of the Goddess, going back thousands of years, expressed the essential nature of process, the constant change of things. Reality was a process of growth, decay and rebirth. The energy of change or becoming was symbolized by the snake with its coils and wiggles and constant renewal or rebirth because it sheds its old body and puts on a new one. The logos is the logical or intelligible aspect of reality. It is what all particulars have in common. Logically, it must be a changeless and abstract characteristic that the particulars have in common. But just as the Milesians thought there could be a common or universal stuff that is not abstract but is both universal and concrete, so does Heraclitus. This A Process Introduction to Philosophy 59 Chapter 8: Heraclitus notion in the history of philosophy is known as a “concrete universal.” Requirements for Change (1) Differences. Without differences everything is the same, that is, no possibility of change. (2) Succession of Differences. Just having two different things does not imply change. The changes or differences must come one after the other. (3) Successive Differences of the Same Thing. A car passing someone on the street is different from, and successive to, the one that passed a moment before, but the first did not change into the second. Change requires the same thing to be first one way and then a different way. (4) Comparison of Successive Differences of the Same Thing. We must be able to compare the first state of affairs with successive ones. Change is comparison. Where no comparison is possible, rationalizing change is not possible. (5) Simultaneous Comparison of Successive Differences of the Same Thing. We cannot compare, that is, contrast, differences unless they are both present at the same time in our experience. The problem, then, is: How can differences of the same thing be both present and yet successive? After millennia, philosophers are beginning to see that concreteness is always particular, and universals or necessities are necessarily abstract. A question to be examined later is, Is it possible for there be a necessarily existing reality if all acts of existence are particular and contingent? This question has significant impact on the possibility of making sense of divinity. What are the characteristics that must be considered in order to understand what “change” means? Change requires a comparison of differences. These differences must be successive differences of the same thing. They must be differences over time since anything is the same with itself at any one time. Without differences, nothing has changed. If the differences are not of the same thing, there is also no basis for saying anything changed. There is both this and that: This did not change into that. But can Heraclitus’ pure flux allow for the possibility of comparison? If it were meaningful to take an instantaneous cross-section of the flux, there would be no change in the instant selected. At the next instant, the previous cross-section would no longer exist. Even if one assumes there are differences in the second moment from the first, as Heraclitus does, there would be no way to compare them. One can’t refer to the first at all, perhaps not even to say it doesn’t exist. Its changeless retention in memory would violate the principle that nothing (even excluding the logos) can remain the same. If the first difference does exist somehow when the second occurs, then the thesis that every concrete particular changes (that no thing is ever the same for two moments), is violated. The Past is dead, not gone. To assert that everything is coming-to-be without ever achieving anything that has finally come to be and is what it is, that is, changeless, is logically impossible. If process or growth is the essence of life, then Heraclitus tries to formulate a philosophy where everything is alive. But pure life is meaningless. The process of life or coming-to-be must come to be, and in so doing, die. The end of a moment of life is its death which must then contribute to new lives. Death is changelessness. The past is dead, not gone. A rational answer to the problem of change must explain how it is possible to have: Simultaneous Comparison of Successive Differences of the Same Thing. Heraclitus’ mistake was to assume the past is destroyed or undone in order to make the present. He denies the reality of being, or things that are. We will see that process or becoming is indeed the inclusive category to explain reality, but becoming or creating includes beings which have been created. Creativity includes the results of previous creatings. Not until Whitehead in the early Twentieth Century was this insight clearly expressed. Parmenides analyses the logical problems inherent in asserting something changes by altering its state and still remains what it is. He will say nothing can possibly change, so all reality is necessarily being. Both he and Heraclitus use reason or logic, not sense experience, to come to opposite conclusions. Though they seem to be expressing very different theories, they are not all that different when the logos is interpreted as the universal constant, a “concrete universal.” 60 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 8: Heraclitus Chapter Summary Heraclitus’ valiant attempt to avoid the logical contradictions others have who maintain reality is made of a stuff that alters, fails because coming-to-be, his counter-proposal that everything is in constant change, is also self-contradictory. If the problem of unity over time cannot be solved by saying something is what it is and then isn’t what it is/was, neither can the problem be solved if nothing remains the same. The past must remain as it is throughout a change or else the comparison of what-was to the new what-is is not possible. One must distinguish parts (beings) from wholes (comings-to-be) that contain parts. One must also learn that wholes never change, that is, a whole cannot alter, nor take on new parts nor lose parts is has. Wholes come to be and remain as the beings they are. Wholes are temporally bounded or momentary, not just spatially bounded. Simultaneous Comparison of Successive Differences of the Same Thing must be possible to make sense of “change.” Suggested Reading: Freeman; Nahm; preSocratic sections from Histories of Philosophy. ************************************************************************** Haiku One The Utter-Flutter Flaggingly flops behind flip–– Pancies flirtatious. Duane Voskuil 1966 A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 8: Heraclitus A Year Has Died a year has died and no one seems to care; leaves scrape along and scatter quickly where one kicks; the dead do not resist; they roll in waves around hollow sycamores moaning in the mist from gusts too warm to nip tho cold enough to hold one ill-at-ease. a year has died; it’s so dead no one seems aware it ever lived; so what the dust that fall be Anemone? it makes one spit and swallow just the same; to ask the dust be damned is far too much to care too much beyond a cough, a spit, a stare. a year has died; its corpse lies around above the ground; no one seems aware enough to care to scrape a shallow ditch to stow away his share; it’s just another year, another year so dead it brings no tear and leans upon no ear, a year so dead so old, so far from care, so cold its death is dead. © Duane Voskuil 1967 61 62 Chapter 9 Parmenides The Logic of Being “To be or not to be, that is the question. Whether....” Shakespeare, Hamlet. “The highest Brahman–ever-shining, unborn, one alone, imperishable, stainless, all-pervading, and non-dual–That am I....pure and by nature changeless...deathless, free from old age, immortal....I am neither cause nor effect....the continual series of pain is unreal...like an object seen by a dreaming man....I have neither good nor bad deeds...nor stages of life, since I am bodiless.” Sankara (8th Century CE in the Hindu Vedanta tradition): A Thousand Teachings, Chapter 10, Seeing: Quoted from A Sourcebook in Asian Philosophy, Koller, 100. “By substance, I understand that which is in itself and is conceived through itself; in other words, its conception does not need the conception of another thing from which it must be formed.” Spinoza, 1632-1677, Ethic. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– Making obvious the logical contradictions of a stuff that alters or moves. –Approaches– (1) Reality is what is, namely, being. (a) Being is what is and cannot alter without being both what it is and what it isn’t. (b) Being is what is and has not been created. (c) Being is what is and cannot be destroyed. (d) Being is all there is, so there can only be one being. All relationships are meaningless. (2) Change, either of motion or alteration, is appearance. (3) “Nothingness” is nonsense. (4) Reality is what logic says it must be; and reality is only what logic says it must be. Contingency is meaningless (the position held by the ultra-rationalists). (5) Reason, not sense experience, discovers the true nature of reality. –Evaluation– Pros: (1) A being can only be the being it is. The Law of Self-Identity. (2) Something that is cannot change into something else and be what it now is and what it also no longer is. The Law of Contradiction: Something can’t be both A and not-A. (3) A being can’t become a nonbeing, that is, be destroyed leaving no-thing. Cons: (1) Parmenides does not distinguish between changing a being that is, and making a new being. Assumes that creation is a function of being and not something more fundamental than being, namely, coming-to-be (becoming). (2) Reality can’t be described if it has no relationships to anything. The General Theory of Relativity in some form is metaphysically true. (3) Parmenides gives no explanation of the “reality” of appearance or its relationship to reality. ****************************************************************************** A Process Introduction to Philosophy 63 Chapter 9: Parmenides W ith Parmenides (who flourished around 475 BCE ), the tendency to say the changing world of sense experience is a shadow or reflection of true changeless being, becomes fullblown. Once the unity of the universe is thought to be numerically one, not only spatially, but also temporally, logic drives us to deny change or successive differences. Parmenides thought logic even required us to deny spatial differences, that is, simultaneous contrasts, as well as successive contrasts. A unity is just what it is and cannot be anything other than it is or additional to what it is. A unity is either thought to have no parts––likely impossible––or is what it is in part because of each part contained in its unity. Different parts in a unity would imply a different unity. Parmenides was the first to correctly maintain that a unity which had parts added to it, subtracted from it or altered within it, cannot be the same unity. This means that the successive differences of the same thing (that is, the same concrete unity) required for something (namely, the unity) to change is impossible or self-contradictory. Parmenides assumes, therefore, that reality can only be (one) being. A being is something that is. It is not something that is coming into being; it already is. In this theory, predicates or attributes would have to be attributes of being. A thing is red. Another thing is green, and yet another is happy. Something cannot be red without first being a being. Red is either being or not being. The same can be said for green and happiness. But not-being (nonbeing) cannot be, that is, it cannot be something that exists–or better said, “nonbeing” or “nothingness” is a meaningless expression. Since being is being, that is, just what it is, and since red is being and green and happiness are also being, it follows, Parmenides says, that red, green and happiness are the same. The formalism is: If R = B and G = B and B = B, then R = G. Distinctions are not real. If being were to change, it would have to change into being or nonbeing. But being already is being, so no change can occur, and “nonbeing” is meaningless. Parmenides’ description of reality is: (1) It is one, numerically one, and probably spherical. (2) It is unrelated to anything, since nothing else exists. (3) It is isotropic, that is, homogeneous. (4) It cannot be experienced with the senses. (5) It can only be known with the mind. (6) It has never come into being or been created. It is and has always been. (7) It will never cease to be or become destroyed. Being cannot become nonbeing, or no-thing. The last point about nothingness deserves further comment. We use the word “nothing” assuming it makes sense. But does it, or if so, in what way? Assume one has a container with nothing in it. What’s between the sides of the container? If one says “nothing,” that means the sides of the container are touching each other, and the container cannot be a container. All attempted references to “nothing” (as attempts to mean: “no thing of any kind”) are selfcontradictory. The only meaningful use of the word is in some relative sense. We go to the refrigerator and find nothing in it. But we mean the refrigerator is filled with racks and air and light and a moldy piece of cheese. “Nothing” always means something else, but something we are not now interested in. Something or other is necessary. The realization that all attempted references to nothing are self-contradictory is a major philosophical insight. We are forced to realize something or other is necessary or unavoidable. The philosophical adventure is to meaningfully describe what it is that is necessary. Another interesting task is to determine, not only that something is necessary, but whether one can meaningfully refer to a something that is the “greatest conceivable something.” In addition to clarifying that “nothing” in an absolute sense is nonsense, Parmenides teaches us to rigorously apply the laws of contradiction and selfidentity. A being is what a being is, and a being cannot be what it isn’t. A being is determinate since it already is. For a being to change requires the being to be what it is and, also, not to be what it is/was. It would then be A and not-A, a clear self-contradiction. Zeno, a later member of the Eleatic School, became famous for pointing out the paradoxes which occur when one assumes change occurs. One familiar example concerns the race between a tortoise and a hare. The hare allowed the tortoise a head start so the hare could show off his speed. Assume the racers are beings and beings exist continuously and the distance they travel is along a continuum. Say the tortoise is at the half-way point when the hare begins. The hare quickly reaches the half-way mark, but the tortoise has moved ahead a finite amount. The hare then travels that amount, but again the tortoise has moved a finite amount ahead (even though it is a smaller finite amount). This can continue forever, so Zeno says the hare will never catch up. A stronger application of Zeno’s argument, which ignores the charm of the race would be as follows: Assume we have a finite distance from A to B, and a continuously existing object N. Before N can go from A to B it must first go to 1/2B, but before it can get to 1/2B it must go to 1/4B, and so on. Any movement must be a finite distance, since no distance is no movement, and as we saw above, an “infinitesimal distance” is either no distance or some 64 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 9: Parmenides finite distance, since nothing meaningful can exist between none and some. A Always a finite gap between A and the first place one supposedly moves to. • B 1/8 1/4 1/2 Since to move a finite amount, no matter how small, is to move through an infinity of finite amounts before any finite moment can be accomplished, no movement will ever occur. Zeno puts it another way. Say one shoots and arrow. In any part of its path, is the arrow moving where it is? He concludes it is where it is, not moving where it is. Is it moving where it isn’t? He concludes that something cannot move where it isn’t, since it would have to be there in order to move there. Zeno concludes that motion is, therefore, meaningless. The problem of the “actual infinitesimal” is real despite the fact modern mathematicians speak of infinitesimal intervals with apparent impunity. They do so only when they are dealing with possibilities. Possibilities are forever divisible. But a calculation or an actual move requires a definite finite interval, a finite difference from the previous moment. Actuality is necessarily discrete and finite. Concreteness or something actually real (not just a possibility), exists in discrete finite amounts. Money has a smallest exchange unit, the penny in the United States. Movement must occur in quantum units also. Change cannot be continuous and be rationalized. Change must come in discrete amounts with a finite difference from the previous state of affairs. An “infinitesimal dif ference” is nonsense, even though this is what many think they mean by “continuous change.” “SomeNones” are nonsense. Parmenides and Heraclitus have provided us with the two extreme possibilities for trying to answer what it means for something to change. Heraclitus says change is unavoidable and continuous and continues on forever without resulting in something that is (being). Parmenides says change is nonsense. If process is “life” and changelessness is “death,” then we should see the futility of trying to explain reality as only alive or only dead. Something dead cannot explain or contain life, and a philosophy that declares reality is only life leaves no room for death and lasting accomplishment. After examining a few more approaches to change, we will see a life, not only can, but must, include another’s death, even though, as Parmenides correctly made clear, death can only be, and remain forever, what it is. Parmenides makes several assumptions which have been accepted by many in the history of philosophy: (1) Being is the most fundamental, if not the only, category in which to explain reality. Change or process is a function or property of beings, not vise versa. (2) Being has not been created, that is, come to be. It has always been. (3) Being is devoid of qualities. It has only quantity. (4) Being is not directly experienced by the senses. It is, however, what supports the qualities (appearances) that we experience. All of these assumptions must be thrown out to make sense of reality. The failure to do so has brought down nearly every philosophical system since Parmenides. Can the Law of Contradiction be used against Parmenides’ own position? Parmenides’ Being is unrelated to anything since it is the only real thing that is. History has used the term “absolute” for something that is complete in itself, requiring nothing but itself to exist. It is unrelated, or need not be related, to anything. This is how Parmenides speaks of Being. All attempted references to an absolute are selfcontradictory. If Being were the only real thing, how could anyone one know it, since knowledge requires two, the knower and the known? Trying to make a true statement, or have knowledge, about something beyond knowability is meaningless. Another way to use the term “absolute” is as a modifier, to speak of something unrestrict edly or absolutely related to everything. In terms of the logical quantifiers, All, Some, and None, the following chart can be set up exhausting the possible positions one can take concerning Absolutes, Necessities or Unqualified Truths: Absolutes and Unqualified (Necessary) Truths (1) There are no absolutes or unqualified truths; all truth is contingent on particular circumstances. (Heraclitus in part, Sophists, positivists, relativists.) A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 9: Parmenides (2) There are some absolutes or unqualified truths, implying there are also some truths that are not necessary. (Whitehead, Hartshorne and others.) (3) There are only absolutes or unqualified truths; nothing is relative or contingent. (Pure nothingness, Parmenides’ Being, Eastern pantheism, Plato? Aristotle’s and Spinoza’s God, ultra-rationalistic metaphysicians, determinists.) ____________________________________________________ If “absolute” means “something unrelated to anything,” then there could only be one such Absolute (if any), or there would have to be some kind of relationship between then. This attempt, to describe reality with many absolutes, was undertaken by the atomists, to be examined next. To say there are no absolutes refutes itself. It is self-contradictory since it is an unqualified assertion which denies there are any such unqualified assertions. This was examined in Chapter 3. Everything must be related to something. Must something be related to everything? To say there are only absolutes is also selfcontradictory: Knowledge is a relationship of knower and known, so an Absolute would not only be unknown, it would be unknowable. All attempts to describe something that by definition is indescribable, even by trying to describe it by saying it is beyond description, are self-contradictory. Since the third position, that of Parmenides, namely, reality is unrelated to anything, is meaningless, we know everything that exists must be related to something. This is the philosophically general statement of the General Theory of Relativity. And since the first attempted position, positivism, is meaningless because it’s selfcontradictory, we know at least one something must be related to everything. “To be related” means “to know” or “take account of” or “make a difference in” or “be exemplified by,” some thing. A “thing” in this sense must be an actuality (an empirical fact). An idea, principle or concept (an abstraction from fact) is also called a “thing,” but we must be careful not to assume such an aspect of facts is itself a fact. What the relationship is between facts and common factors of facts, that is, universals or abstractions, is a fundamental philosophical issue. Facts versus Factors = Particulars versus Universals. However, no fact can be related to all possible facts. If all future facts have to be related to a present fact, before the present fact is a fact, then no fact could ever be (unless the one absolute fact of Parmenides makes sense). Although all facts are necessarily related to some other facts and principles, no one fact can be related to all possible facts. Only concepts or principles can be universally (absolutely) related to everything, that is, found as an aspect in all actual or possible facts as well as other principles. However, it may make sense to say at each moment there is a fact related to all facts existing at that moment. This would be the supreme fact or Whole of the universe at that moment. More on this later. The Milesian approach to the metaphysical question, “What is the stuff that is absolute (that is, found everywhere in everything at all times)?” goes wrong because it is the attempt to find a universal fact, substance or actuality, the so-called “concrete universal.” By this is meant a fact, not only related to all there is, but will be related to all there will be. This Fact would have to change as new things occur, or deny new things occur. The approach Anaximenes and the Pythagoreans began is more fruitful: “What are the factors (principles), facts (all possible facts) have in common?” Their mathematical method, if considered as the search for patterns displayed by all actual and possible facts, is the metaphysical method if we ask, What are the patterns displayed by all conceivable facts? But mathematics defined either as finding restricted patterns or as merely drawing conclusions from presuppositions is not the metaphysical method, for metaphysics is the search for the premises themselves that are rational and universally exhibited by all facts. The drawing of logical conclusions from premises is only a means of examining the consistency and adequacy of premises, not a method for discovering them. Now, it may be possible more than one principle can be related to or exemplified by everything, but it is not conceivable that more than one concrete individual be related to everything, since there could be no criterion to distinguish them. If “individual” must mean some grand fact related to all present and future facts (which is impossible as we have seen), then the Unsurpassable (who must have at least the attribute of omnipresence) is meaningless. But if an 65 66 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 9: Parmenides “individual” or “person” means a series of wholes (supreme facts), each one including the previous whole as a present part and all future facts when they occur, then perhaps making sense of cosmic unity and time might be possible. More on this later. Chapter Summary Heraclitus’ effort to deny being can be the ultimate category of rational explanation, is matched by Parmenides’ effort to stick with the logical consequences of such a position. Being(s) cannot change: On this point Parmenides is right. Even his attempt to assert only one (irrational) being is certainly as rational as a profusion of meaningless beings. But Parmenides’ attempt to convince us being must be eternal and uncreated, is only convincing if we accept the mistaken and long-held belief that creation is the alteration of beings, rather than the bringing into being of new beings. Parmenides’ belief that being must be eternal influenced Plato (see Chapter 11) who said the eternal, changeless patterns are more real than the actual things exhibiting patterns. When one is in love with stability and repulsed by the changing physical and biological processes of real life, seen as processes of women’s bodies and her Goddess, and when one correctly sees that abstractions are the only things that can be changeless and uncreated, then we can see how so much philosophy has been seduced into thinking the abstract aspects of reality are the real thing(s) of reality. Continuous motion of continuously existing beings, Zeno correctly points out, would require meaningless “infinitesimal” movements. However, the pluralists (Chapter 10), and many since, mistakenly, believe change can be defined as rearrangement of continuously existing beings. Suggested Reading: Freeman; Nahm; preSocratic sections from Histories of Philosophy. 67 Chapter 10 Pluralists: Materialism Atoms, Locomotion, Freedom and Determinism “All things must be moved and borne along with equal velocity though of unequal weights through the unresisting void...wherefore again and again I say bodies must swerve a little, and yet not more than the least possible....For the first-beginning of things move first themselves...The seeds of things have chanced spontaneously to clash....” Lucretius, 98-54 BCE, The Nature of the Universe (De Rerum Natura), Book II, expounding on Epicurus’ doctrine of minimal, but innate, spontaneity. “I will set out to discourse to you on the ultimate realities of heaven and the gods. I will reveal those atoms from which nature creates all things....” “Spirit is flimsy stuff composed of tiny particles....mind and spirit are both composed of matter...[and] the bodies of matter have no colour at all....”” Lucretius 98-54 BCE , The Nature of the Universe, Book III. “Absolute, true, and mathematical time, of itself, and from its own nature, flows equably without relation to anything external....Absolute space, in its own nature, without relation to anything external, remains always similar and immovable....Absolute motion is the translations of a body from one absolute place into another.” Isaac Newton, 1642-1727 CE, Principia, Scholium on Absolute Space and Time. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– (1) An attempt to explain how change is possible if each being must be what it is and cannot alter. (2) The possible relationships between mind and matter. –Approaches– (1) Change is rearrangement of internally changeless beings. (2) Anaxagoras: (a) Beings (called “seeds”) fill up reality even when they move. (b) Beings (seeds) contain some amount of every quality. (3) Democritus: (a) Beings (called “atoms”) move around in the Void, in Nothingness. (b) Each being is internally changeless, indivisible and homogeneous without any quality. (c) Beings have geometrical shapes and texture only. (d) Mind is a group of atoms: The denial that mental reality is different from atoms. (4) Epicurus: Some freedom in some of the atoms at some time is necessary. –Evaluation– Pros: (1) Change is real, not merely appearance. (2) Qualities are in the realities: Anaxagoras. (3) The basic units of reality must be (spatially) finite, not divisible forever into smaller and smaller units: Democritus. (4) Reality can only be explained by asserting the basic units have some freedom or spontaneity: Epicurus. Cons: (1) Nothing in the system can make a comparison and, therefore, nothing can make sense of differences. (2) Even if differences could be explained, there is no logical basis for sequence. (3) “Nothingness” is nonsense and cannot be a container. 68 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 10: Pluralists (4) “Continuous motion” is irrational, floundering on Zeno’s paradox: A being can’t move where it isn’t and doesn’t have to move where it is. (5) Mind must be one whole, not a group of wholes (atoms). (6) Complete determinism, despite Epicurus’ assertion of minimal spontaneity, is the dominant theme. ****************************************************************************** O nce the extreme form of monism, favored by Parmenides and much of Eastern philosophy, has been clearly stated and found wanting, the only alternative left is some form of pluralism in order to make sense of diversity and change. The history of philosophy is the proposing and disposing of various forms of pluralism, nearly all based on two assumptions: (1) the many things that exist are beings, and (2) a being can remain the same being in different places or with successively different parts or characteristics. Acceptance of these two assumptions can be defined as believing in enduring substances, or as maintaining a substance/attribute philosophy. Substance/Attribute Philosophy: A being can alter, yet remain the same being. A naxagoras, ca. 460 BCE , agreed with Parmenides that the reality of nonreality, called the “void” or “nonbeing” was meaningless. The concept of the vacuum has a long history. It originally meant the Voice Umm, the primeval state of formless chaos, not pure nothingness (Walker, WEMS 738). Reality for Anaxagoras was a plenum filled with being, or as a pluralist must say, beings. He called the beings “seeds” since they were the microscopic things that “grew” into the macroscopic things that we see. Growth meant aggregation or accumulation of many seeds that would move together as a group. Everything is everywhere (somewhat). Not only did Anaxagoras disagree with Parmenides on the number of beings, he was one of the first and one of few to disagree with him on the internal make-up of being. Rather than saying beings are devoid of qualities and the contrasts they set up, he said every being or seed contains some amount of every quality. A being/seed can’t be a being without having qualities. For Anaxagoras some beings contain more of one kind of quality than another. Large objects that are green or yellow, for example, are composed of seeds that have more of these colors than others. In this theory, every quality is a metaphysical property: Nothing can exist without necessarily exhibiting some amount of every quality. To appreciate Anaxagoras’ insight, we must examine the nature of potentiality. Hartshorne (PPS) discusses the nature of the continuum of qualities, for example, how potential colors are related. Pigments are mixed to arrive at new colors. However, potential colors are not mixed. (See the diagram of Hartshorne's theory of intrinsic color relationships, the Potential Color Solid, page 70.) No part of the continuum of possible colors is isolated from any other. Every possible color is “impure.” The attempt to conceive of a “pure” color, is like trying to conceive of a nonextended point/instant. It is a limit of possibility, not a possibility. And since every actual experience of color emphasizes a range of possible color, every actual color exhibits every other possible color in some degree. An experienced color is lo cated in the continuum of color regions, which means that region is enhanced compared to others. Anaxagoras also said seeds can be divided. No matter how small a piece of being one begins with, it can always be divided further, and every division, no matter how small, will contain some thing of every quality. Yet there is one exception: mind. Since the ancients recognized being as motionless or dead, not capable of doing anything on its own, there must be a means to move it. Mind is active and moves things that don’t move on their own. Mind is a self-mover that also moves non-mind reality. Mind is in some way “in” other things (beings), but other things are not in mind. If the mind were complex, the Pluralists (incorrectly) assumed, it could be divided. Mind, Anaxagoras correctly saw, must be a unit, a whole. The separation of mind and seeds sets up a mind-body dualism within this pluralistic theory. The truth is probably the reverse: Whitehead in Chapter 13 will argue that beings are always in some mind or other, that is, in some process or coming-tobe. Being will be seen to be settled and changeless determinations of past creations conditioning present and future creative processes (minds). There are many particular real things, but they can be placed in two major categories: mind and nonmind. Given a distinction between mind and nonmind or matter, there are only certain ways they can be related: 69 A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 10: Pluralists Possible Relationships of Mind and Matter Relationship Comment Problems (1) Mind and matter are outside each other. Neither needs the other in order to exist. Reasons can’t be given why reality contains two kinds of things rather than three or more. No sufficient reason can be given for why they are related at all. (2) Mind is in matter. A seed, for example, would not be a seed unless it also contained mind. An inactive being (as a whole) cannot contain an active being as a part. (3) Matter is in mind. Mind would not be a mind without containing matter. The need for mind to be an indivisible unity has not allowed this option to be seriously considered, since philosophers have assumed (wrongly) that distinctions, contrasts, imply divisibility. (4) Mind and matter are not really basic. Both mind and matter are characteristics of a deeper kind of reality. Reality is supposedly some kind of indescribable stuff which gives rise to both mind and matter. (5) Only mind exists. Matter is meaningless. May be interpreted to be the same as (3). (6) Only matter exists. Mind is meaningless. May be interpreted to be the same as (2) Whatever the relationship of mind and matter, of unmixed and mixed seeds, Anaxagoras’ answer to change is clear: Change is rearrangement of seeds. During this shifting around, the seeds must remain in contact since seeds are all there is, there can be no space, no non-seed, nonbeing reality, between them. D emocritus, who lived in Abdera in Thrace from about 460 to 360 BCE as a contemporary of Plato, is also a pluralist, but he believed Parmenides must not be modified any more than necessary to explain change. He said, “If there is a many, each should be as the one,” Parmenides’ One, that is. Leibniz, a seventeenth century philosopher stated a corollary to this statement, “If there is a many, there must be ones.” The one (numerical one) of Parmenides had no internal qualities. It was a pure continuum of being. Each of the beings that Democritus calls “atoms” (that is, indivisibles) is internally just like the one Being of Parmenides. Democritus says of atoms: (1) They have no internal qualities or distinctions. (2) They do have geometrical properties of size, shape and texture, (3) They have position and velocity in the void, and (4) They are infinite in number. (5) They may have holes and hooks. This is his basis for a molecular theory: Atoms get hooked together for a while, forming molecules, until they are disrupted by others. 70 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 10: Pluralists Potential Color Solid Hartshorne’s theory of the intrinsic relationships of potential colors. Note yellow is always closer to white than violet. Philosophers over the centuries have called the geometrical properties of things, “primary qualities,” and the non-geometrical qualities of things, ”secondary qualities” since they did not think these so-called secondary qualities were essential for a thing’s existence. Philosophers and psychologists even talk about tertiary qualities, or the feelings and valuations one has about the secondary qualities. The common belief is that matter can exist with only mathematical or geometrical properties (as Democritus says), yet somehow colors, sounds and smells arise in our experience from the primary properties of matter. Finally, there arises the way we feel about the colors, sounds and smells. This analysis of reality is upside down. As we will see, feelings are the stuff of reality. Colors, sounds, and the like, are feelings. They are partly describable by geometry. They are so big, just this size and shape, changing position relative to other such feelings, and so on. Since matter alone cannot be experienced except as qualified, some philosophers have denied matter makes any sense. All that exists are the qualities in one’s mind, Berkeley, a seventeenth century Idealist, said. But the faith in the existence of something lying beyond all possible experience is still maintained by most, whether it be “matter” or a divine absolute. The other reality, that Democritus says is real, is the Void or Nonbeing. His metaphysic consists of atoms and the void, or atoms “in” the void. The void cannot be experienced either, since it isn’t anything. E picurus, 344-270 BCE , is the famous founder of Epicureanism. His interest in philosophy focused on how to live the good life. He espoused atomism as a way to avoid fearing death since nothing survives beyond one’s present experiences. We only live once, so make the most of it. However, rather than seeking pleasure, as Epicureansim is now usually characterized, he emphasized avoiding pain. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 71 Chapter 10: Pluralists The aim of the life of blessedness...is the soul’s freedom from disturbance....Become accustomed to the belief that death is nothing to us. (Letter to Menoeceus) For our purposes, we should note Epicurus was one of the first to allow the basic units of reality some degree of spontaneity, or freedom. He believed the atoms were originally in a free fall. They were all falling straight down at the same rate (a thesis Galileo would make famous two thousand years later). The Greeks had no concept of inertia, so if something is moving, either it must be moving to its “natural” place (heavy things move down, light things up), or a soul must be moving it (something Epicurus did not believe in). In order for the atoms to group together, they had to start bumping into each other, so some of them had to initiate a minimal swerve from the vertical fall. The idea that somewhere in reality there is some freedom, is also essential for a successful ethical theory. Without the ability to make choices, responsibility is meaningless. Whitehead and Hartshorne, as we will see, maintain every moment of reality has some irreducible self-power or freedom. L uretius (98-54 BCE ) restates the atomistic thesis in his beautifully written De Rerum Natura: There can be only three kinds of everlast ing objects. The first, owing to the absolute solidity of their substance, can repel blows and let nothing penetrate them....Such are the atoms of matter....The second kind can last forever because it is immune from blows. Such is empty space....Last the sum total of the universe is everlasting, having no space outside it into which the matter can escape and no matter that can enter and disintegrate it by the force of impact. The Nature of the Universe, Book III. The beings, the atoms, are supposedly in the void. They are always in motion. Their motion changes when they are bumped by others. But there is always a constant amount of motion. Atoms are perfectly elastic and give up to another exactly the amount of motion they lose. This is the materialistic formulation of the Law of Conservation of Energy, where energy means “locomotion.” For Pluralists, change is rearrangement. Since atoms are never created nor destroyed, the other conservation law, that of the Conservation of Matter is also implied by Democritus’ metaphysic. The two Principles were consolidated into one law in modern physics by Einstein’s formula, Energy Equals Mass Times the Speed of Light Squared, E = mc2 . Matter and energy are convertible. However, since what is created cannot be undone, the conservation laws cannot be the unqualified truth about reality.10 The idea that energy and matter are conserved was part of the Goddess belief system for thousands of years. Life comes from the Goddess’ womb and goes back to her womb (tomb) to be reborn in some new form. Everything is recycled. Even the whole universe will come to a chaotic end only to be restructured with new divinities and creatures. Democritus gives the deterministic answer to the Principle of Sufficient Reason. Things happen, and happen the way they do, because there is no alternative. Each atom’s motion is exactly determined by the speed and direction of those that hit it, and so on backwards in time forever. Compare this to the initial swerving not caused by anything prior to the swerving that Epicurus postulates. Deterministic atomism has been the dominant metaphysic science has used to interpret its data ever since the seventeenth century when it was revived as an alternative to Aristotelian categorizing. The principles of modern empirical science were founded by men like Frances Bacon using the Inquisition’s methods, namely, torture and interrogation, to wrest the secrets from Mother Nature. Believing nature was dead, may have made this wresting torture more conscionable when it came to “live” animal experiments. But does atomism make sense? Recall that having a rational explanation of change, requires the possibility of simultaneous comparison of successive differences of the same thing. The things that are, in Democritean atomism, are the atoms, groups of atoms and the spacevoid. All the rest is, as he says, “opinion.” Either the atoms change internally or they don’t. If they do, all the problems so clearly pointed out by Parmenides of a whole existing as it is and not as it is, must be answered. If unities don’t alter internally, and 10Alan Guth and Paul Steinhardt in a chapter, “The Inflationary Universe,” The New Physics, 1989, discuss the notion that “all matter and energy in the observable universe may have emerged from almost [sic] nothing. The tradition, dating back at least as far as the Greek philosopher Parmenides in the fifth century BC, has manifested itself in modern times in the formulation of a number of conservation laws––laws which state that certain physical quantities cannot be changed by any physical process. A decade or so ago the list of quantities thought to be conserved included energy, linear momentum, angular momentum, electric charge and baryon number.... “If grand unified theories are correct in their prediction that baryon number is not conserved there is no known conservation law that prevents the observed universe from evolving out of nothing. The inflationary universe model provides a possible mechanism by which the observed universe could have evolved from an infinitesimal region. It is then tempting to go one step further and speculate that the entire universe evolved from literally nothing. The recent developments in cosmology strongly suggest that the universe may be the ultimate free lunch.” “Almost nothing,” is categorically different from “literally nothing.” I leave it to the reader to ponder the meaninglessness of “absolutely nothing.” 72 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 10: Pluralists they don’t, according to Democritus, then the only change they can undergo is locomotion or movement. As an illustration of the change of movement according to classical atomism, suppose we start with three atoms or marbles arranged in a line. Then let’s say the same three “change” into a triangular arrangement. Suppose someone walks into the room after the new arrangement is in place. If s/he were asked whether the three marbles had changed, s/he would be at a loss to know. S/he cannot compare the first arrangement of the line with the triangle. Without comparison, rationalizing change is impossible. a a b c b c So we must ask Democritus what or who is making the comparison, given the assumptions of his metaphysic. It cannot be any one of atoms in the line, for if atom a, b or c knew it was one of three in a line, it would have to change internally to know it is one of three atoms in a triangle. It would have to add the knowledge of the triangle to that of the line or comparison would not be possible. But internal alteration of a being is expressly denied by Parmenides and Democritus, and for very good reasons. So what or who does the comparing? Democritus and Lucretius do talk about mind. They say mind is (or is composed of) very small, smooth and round atoms that move in subtle ways. Let’s try to make a mind of these atoms that can retain the arrangements of material atoms. Take a line of atoms to represent “the” mind: A. The three material atoms above, that were in a straight line, must somehow rearrange these mind atoms in order for the so-called mind to have a memory or brain-trace of the line; something like this: B. The material atoms then change or rearrange into a triangle, and “the mind” experiences this arrangement also. Three different mind atoms must be arranged or the brain-trace of the original line will be lost: C. But what is it that compares the brain-trace of the line to that of the triangle? Once again, it cannot be any one of the mind atoms. Is there anything that can experience the whole group of mind atoms with all their different patterns? In other words, what is the unity or wholeness of the so-called mind? What does the “the” refer to in the phrase, “the mind?” Democritus has two different realities and two kinds of unities: The oneness of the Void, and the oneness of each atom. A unity (atom) that contains other unities (atoms) as parts is not anything possible in his metaphysic. Some reality must experience the line and the triangle at the same time in order to compare them, just as one must see all three of the atoms in the line or the triangle at the same time, or there would be no way to say what the pattern is. Can the Void be the unity and retainer of past arrangements? Nothing can do nothing, and even if it could do something, it would be a unity that changes with each new arrangement and still remains the same unity, which is a self-contradiction, as Parmenides points out. The sense in which the atoms are “in” the void is not clear. How a unity can be a unity of parts and not be affected by the new arrangements of parts is a mystery. How nothingness can do anything is a mystery, a paradox. Parmenides is right: Non being, or nothingness, is not capable of rational articulation. But even if we allowed Democritus to mysteriously have a unity of atoms that could compare one part of a group to another, this would still not solve the logical requirements for a meaningful answer to change. Not only must there be differences, the differences must be sequential. Inspection of the last diagram, C, above shows different patterns, but nothing intrinsic to the patterns themselves gives any clue as to which one came first and which second. We, of course, remember that it was the line that changed into the triangle, but as diagrammed they exist simultaneously. Reality does not come to us with a, b, c’s, nor l, 2, 3’s, nor arrows, nor right and left as expressions for then and now. Beings, in whatever guise they take, are things done. Whether a being is primordial or created, nothing new can be done to it once it is. The only thing that supposedly changes is the arrangement, but what is an arrangement? Where is it? What is its reality status? It is not a being because only atoms are beings. It is not the void since the void is numerically one, and it can’t have numerical differences since “it” is nothing to have differences. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 73 Chapter 10: Pluralists Finally, even if one were to overlook the inability of Democritus’ metaphysic, (1) to have any way that can compare differences, (2) to have any way to logically explain sequence and (3) to have any way explain how nothing (the Void) can contain something (atoms), still his system flounders on (4) Zeno’s paradox. Each atom is a continuum of being, that is, a being that always is. When it moves, it moves through a continuum of distance (the Void, nothingness?). It is not in one place and then in another place a finite distance away a moment later. A being must exist fully as it is halfway to halfway to halfway, and so on, forever, since every division of a finite distance still leaves a finite distance to traverse. The attempt to define continuous motion as moving an infinity of ”infinitesimal” distances makes little sense. Every difference, or arrangement or state, must be a finite difference from the original state or place, or nothing has happened, but every finite difference is divisible (on a continuum) into an never-ending series of differences. Motion, not only in fact, but in principle, is necessarily quantified; not continuous. We must be suspicious of someone who says actual motion is continuous. Democritus correctly recognizes that the basic things that exist must be spatially quantified. They are just the amount they are, no more nor less. Their beings have forever just the spatiality they have. But Democritus fails to see that the basic units of reality must be temporally finite also. Even modern physics recognizes there is a smallest act or change that cannot be analyzed into smaller acts. Actual events “jump” from one state to another, the so-called quantum leap that Einstein discovered and so disliked because he realized it made his belief in a deterministic universe problematic. In his concern to avoid wholes that don’t alter internally, Democritus has not been able to make sense of wholes at all, wholes, that is, besides in- dividual atoms and the Void. Atoms are wholes that have no meaningful relationship to others. All their relationships to each other are external, but if all relationships are external, no reality could know anything exists external to itself (see Chapter 12). Knowing or experiencing is in some sense having others internally as objects of the experience. If an object is not in the subject, the subject cannot know the object. Apart from the strange relationship of atoms being “in” the Nothingness, all relationships (of atoms to each other) for Democritus are external. If the arrangement presents more reality than the atoms alone that make the arrangement, Democritus has not explained what the “more” is. Yet he needs a reality that is or contains the reality of the patterns. But his socalled whole is equal to the abstract mathematical sum of the parts. To be real, the concrete or actual pattern must be more than the atoms themselves. A pattern might require the atoms, but cannot be reduced to them. Problems with Materialism (1) No way to compare differences. (2) No way to logically express sequence. (3) No way to explain “nothingness.” (4) No way to explain continuous motion. The inadequacy of atomism breeds dualism. Yet a mind or soul doesn’t solve the problem of something that can somehow simultaneously gather up many parts and yet, somehow, retain their sequence. Dualism just raises another problem: How are material atoms and spiritual “atoms” (souls), that is, matter and mind related? This question is never adequately answered. Dualism is a metaphysic with a basic incoherence built into it. The thesis of determinism, however it is stated, does not allow anything new to really happen. Since patterns or arrangements don’t really exist in atomism, they can’t really change. At least Parmenides was up front with the consequences of a universe of being: It is a block universe. A universe of being only does nothing. Chapter Summary The pluralists hoped to avoid Parmenides’ analysis that all change is meaningless by not allowing their beings to change, that is, not allowing them to alter. They believed beings that moved around could do so without destroying the being’s self-identity, so change was defined as the difference between an arrangement and a rearrangement of “changeless” beings. But as intuitive as this attempted notion seems to be, if no differences last, no change has occurred. No one can know an arrangement, much less the 74 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 10: Pluralists difference between one arrangement and another. Succession is meaningless where there is no logical way to explain temporal order. Also, continuously existing beings would have to somehow move in “infinitesimal” amounts. And, finally, there is the problem of “nothingness” in which all the so-called moving takes place. Space cannot be one; it cannot be the container of the many without altering when its “parts” move. Suggested Reading: Freeman; Nahm; preSocratic sections from Histories of Philosophy; Lucretius. ****************************************************************** Potential Sound Sphere (Compare to the Color Solid, page 70) Sounds have an intrinsic, logical relationship best described as a spiral on a sphere. Sounds, also like colors, lose saturation at high and low intensities. But potential sounds don’t seem to be located within the sphere like the grays and browns of color. Chords are the way sounds achieve a similar effect. 75 Chapter 11 Ancient Buddhistic and Platonic Series versus Monadic Substance “Every Monad is subject to change, and indeed...this change is continuous in each.” Emphasis added. Leibniz, Monadology, 10. “Not falling into wrong views, virtuous and endowed with insight, one gives up attachment to sensedesires. Verily such a man does not return to enter a womb again....A vision of true knowledge arose in me....Being dispassionate, he becomes detached; through detachment he is liberated....Now there is no more rebecoming (rebirth).” Emphasis added. Samyutta-nikaya, XXXV, 28. Quoted from A Sourcebook in Asian Philosophy, Koller, 196-199. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– (1) How to avoid one’s soul going through endless reincarnations in this world of painful suffering. (2) How to explain “change” if beings can’t alter nor move. –Approaches– (1) Some early Buddhists maintain basic realities are moments of experience that do not alter. (2) Change is the exchange of one moment for another, sequentially, in a series. Change is the comparison of one moment (or its copy?) to another in a series. (3) A moment of experience occurs and then disappears (is added to?) as a new one appears. (4) “Souls” (spiritual beings that alter and yet remain the same souls) are meaningless. –Evaluation– Pros: (1) The ultimate units of reality are not only spatially finite, but are temporally finite, that is, momentary. (2) Realities that last over time are composed of a series of different units that are somewhat the same, rather than one reality that alters and somehow remains somewhat the same. (3) A “subject” or subjectivity is not the same as the identity of a person over time. Cons: (1) No way to compare one being (difference) to another, if each disappears as the next one occurs, as some interpreters maintain. (2) If moments are only related externally to each other, comparison would be impossible. (3) For those who maintain cosmic reality is pantheistic, this explanation of change may be more about appearance than reality. (4) The temporal extent of a moment is a concern. If any temporal extension is composed of smaller temporal durations, the basic moment seems to occur infinitesimally fast. ************************************************************************************ I f making sense of beings that alter their state or position is not possible, other approaches must be tried. Two other ways have been tried. They both have one fundamental insight in common: The basic units of reality are temporally finite. They are spatially and temporally quantified, not just spatially finite. More specifically, whenever there is a change, whenever there is a difference from a previous situation, there is a new basic unity of reality. For the ancient Sarvastavadin and Sautrantika Buddhists (first heard of around 300 BCE ), a person, or anything that lasts or changes over time, is a series of units, rather than one substance or being that alters its state or position. Anything that lasts through 76 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 11: Ancient Series changes is a series of concrete acts, not one concrete actor having many acts. Same Thing as the Same Series t1 t2 t3 t4 Being Being Being Being The direction arrow is assumed but is not allowed in reality if there is only one being at a time, so the actual past does not survive into the present. These units have some of the same properties Parmenides attributed to beings: (1) They are what they are. (2) They cannot alter nor move. For these Buddhists, a reality that lasts over time and changes is not one being that somewhat alters. It is a series of many contiguous beings that are somewhat the same. The projection of a movie on a screen might be an analogy. An object persists on the screen only because it is projected again and again (thirty times a second or so), faster than one’s ability to see each separate flash. Some interpreters of this momentary thesis say each moment last for only an infinitesimal length of time, but this would be a very questionable thesis, given Zeno’s analysis of “infinitesimals” as irrational. This theory of momentary actuality was likely proposed as an alternative to the endless cycle of reincarnations found in Hindu metaphysics. The belief that everything is recycled is a major point Hinduism maintained from the Goddess cultures. That everything is endlessly recycled in some sense is probably a metaphysical truth, as we will see, when better solutions to the meaning of “change,” “value” and the unity of the universe are explored. A one that is successively somewhat different, versus successive many that are somewhat the same. But by the first millennium BCE the idea of rebirth was not just that some new life comes from the death of previous life, but each particular life continues on into a new life. Each person is reborn in a new form. The new form depended on the kind of life one had led in his/er previous life. The types of lives were arranged hierarchically, from lowly and disgusting physical forms to pure, intangible forms. Only by great effort and many reincarnations could one reach the point of salvation sought by the Hindus (and Plato), namely, the cessation of the painful and disgusting rebirth into this physical world of maya (maria, mary) and reabsorption into the spiritual and changeless One. Since reality is only one being for the Hindus, just as is was for Parmenides, the world of change and diversity cannot be really real. They see salvation as an escape from suffering which is caused by one’s attachment to appearance, that is, the unreality of the diversity of the world. We should stop longing to maintain our individuality. All [particular] existence is like a reflection in a mirror, without substance, only a phantom of the mind. When the finite mind acts, then all kinds of things arise; when the finite mind ceases to act, then all kinds of things cease. (Bardo Thodol, quoted by Walker, WEMS.) These ancient Buddhist sects not only introduced, (1) temporal atomism, but also (2) the subjective or experiential approach to philosophy that our western tradition did not embrace until Descartes and Bacon during the late Renaissance period. These Buddhists were asking: What is a human being? What is human experience? What makes one the same person throughout this life and all his/er reincarnated lives? They understood that a “soul” (supposedly a reality that remains the same soul, day in and day out, lifetime after lifetime) is logically impossible: A being cannot be what it is and alter. They concluded that the “soul” was a fiction. The so-called soul was not only problematic rationally, it was also never experienced. They reflected on their experiences and could not find a soul. To these Buddhists sects, we are our experiences. Just as on a movie screen where something continues to last only as long as a new frame is flashed on the screen, so too we only exist as long as new experiences occur in our series. Death of a person is simply the end of a series. There is no finite soul stuff that lives on to be re-embodied, to be trapped again in mater. One can be said, perhaps, to be “reborn” in this view, but only in the sense that there is a new experience each moment renewing his/er series. But when the series ceases to have a new moment, the person ceases to exist. Only the welter of fleeting moments of experience is real. There is nothing behind the experience that “has” the experience. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 77 Chapter 10: Pluralists Though this metaphysic emphatically denies beings can alter into another state or position, according to some interpreters, it does allow beings to come and go; “discrete moments arise and then cease to be” (Datta). A being is in some sense “created” when it occurs as an experience in a person’s series, and it is uncreated, or goes out of existence, as it is replaced (some say infinitesimally fast) with another being. “Their essence is to disappear without leaving any trace behind” (Stcherbatsky, Logic, Vol. I, 80).11 There is much to learn from the view that an enduring thing is a series of temporary things, as well as from the emphasis on the introspective approach to philosophical questions. However, some serious logical problems may remain. Can this position satisfy the necessary conditions for rationalizing change: Simultaneous comparison of successive differences of the same thing? Obviously the “same thing” cannot be the same being, if a being only lasts for a moment. The same thing can, however, refer to the same series. Unfortunately, what defines the “same series” is not clear. Presumably, all the beings of one series have something in common that sets them off from other series, perhaps their contiguity to one another. But how is it possible to know or experience whether two or more beings or experiences are contiguous to each other if each is mutually external to the other unless former beings continued to exist for more than a moment and survived into the next being of the series? It is logically impossible for a knower to know something external to the knower (see Chapter 12). How the past is in the present was a debated issue for many Buddhists, and still is.12 To have something in common or to be somewhat different requires comparison of one being to another. But comparison is impossible in a metaphysic that says the old being is gone when the new one occurs. And if it is still around, how is it related to the present? We seem to be faced with the same problem Heraclitus had in a pure flux: If the past is undone, it cannot be compared to the present. In fact, this has been the problem with all attempts to explain change. A being that alters place or state or disappears does 11 According to Gene Reeves, whose opinion I value, this interpretation of the reality of the past is a straw man posed by nonBuddhists looking in from the outside, and if true, not generally true of Buddhism. But despite the oversimplifications involved, I hope the characterization helps students see the issues involved in understanding what it means for something to change. 12 Characterizing the thought of even this one early branch of Buddhism as denying the past survives into the present in some way, is undoubtedly setting up a straw man. Hopefully, stating the issue in such unambiguous terms will allow one to see clearly what is at stake in coming to a rational answer to the problem of change. not remain as it was, so comparison of how-it-was to the way-it-now-is is not possible. Where is the past? The reality of the past is such an important issue that an adequate answer to what the past is or where it is, will be the key to most problems in philosophy. To say the past is in memory, is not an explanation of what memory is or how it can work. If memory of the past were somehow “built into” (copied into) the present experience (that is, the present being) of a series, how could one know the so-called memory is of anything that was? Memory cannot literally be the being (reality) of the past if the past beings disappear or are copied into the present. If the past isn’t anymore, there is nothing for the memory to be a memory of. To have a socalled memory of something that doesn’t exist, is to have a false memory, that is, no memory at all, just a fantasy. P lato (428/7-348/7 BCE), writing about the same time as the ancient Buddhists, has another way of describing the world of sense experience as a series. In one of his attempts (perhaps not his most sophisticated) to explain how reality changes, he says that the beings of reality remain changeless. They are not created nor destroyed. They exist in a changeless “heaven,” and are flashed like the frames of a movie into the world of sense experience. Plato agreed with Parmenides that beings cannot alter nor move. Plato’s main difference from Parmenides is in the number of beings his worldview has. The beings which Plato calls Ideas 13 or Forms are distinguished from each other by quality and geometrical properties. They exist in a realm of pure changelessness, organized by the Form of Forms which he calls the Form of the Good. This static realm of abstractions is further deified by Aristotle who calls it the Unmoved Mover since everything is moved by being attracted to the fully actualized Form contained in divinity that it finds partially actualized in itself. This changeless realm of pure abstractions is thought by Plato and Aristotle, and many others in philosophy and religion, to be the most real reality, rather than a reality deficient in concrete fullness. This realm of changeless, abstract beings is inherited as a major part of our classical, western concept of divinity. Plato’s concept of change is the exchange of one being for another in the spatial manifold, matrix or matter of sense experience. The beings come and go in experience, probably by the agency of souls, but they are eternally changeless in themselves. 13 “Idea” means “goddess in me” or “goddess within. ” 78 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 11: Ancient Series Plato’s tie to ancient Buddhism and the older Goddess concepts can be seen in the meanings of “matter” “maya,” “matrix” and “manifold.” They all are cognates and derived from M, originally a sign of waves that are part of the original waters from which we all came, the amniotic fluid of the mother womb. Ma, mother, personified as Maria , or Mari or Mary, the sea that waves, was the stuff of reality, still today called the “marine.” M also symbolized the mother’s mammaries, breasts, which like two mountains, twin peaks, sustain all life. But mater, which changes and fluctuates, is not seen by the patriarchal philosophers of the first half millennium BCE , and many since, as fully real. It is maya or illusion. One does not do well to become attached to her or long for her. Matter may reflect, like a mirror, the dea (the Goddess), but does so cloudily, imperfectly, distortedly. The taboo about breaking mirrors goes back to the belief that broken mirrors distort a true refection of reality. True knowledge, for a rationalist like Plato and much of Eastern philosophy, occurs only when we are face to face with the thoughts of the divine. Then we have dea (or deo, god) in us (I-deas). But mother matter cannot give us this truth of the divine. In the increasing patriarchal view of cosmic reality, the God dess becomes a “he” or an “it” and resides changelessly apart from the world of changing matter. Plato assumes there are no new Ideas; the real beings, or Ideas, have always been. The underlying mistake philosophy made at this early period, that is still plaguing us, is the assumption that beings are not created, that they have always been. All beings (results of wholes) are created. Only metaphysical characteristics of beings have always been. We must regain the insight that all beings are created, all beings, that is, except the common characteristics of all possible beings and comings-tobe. The common factors of all possible creations cannot themselves be created. They must have always been. Even divinity, as with anything that lasts through time, cannot be one, eternal being. Divinity, if anything meaningful, must be a series of creations related in a unique way. More on this later under the topic of “unsurpassability.” Chapter Summary Though some ancient Buddhists’ analysis of change may be motivated by a desire to show the superficiality of all changing things, they do suggest a very important direction required to make sense of change: Change is the comparison of changeless units in a series. Units of reality are moments of experience that are temporally finite, “atomized,” not capable of being or becoming something other than they are for the moment they are. However, if when the unit’s time is up and another replaces it, it’s gone, it cannot be compared to anything, so change cannot be rationalized. A clearer answer to this problem had to wait for Whiteheads analysis discussed in the next chapter. Plato’s approach, keeping the units around as eternal and changeless (though they appear and disappear in the world of sense experience), also interprets that which changes as deficient in reality compared to Idea-beings that already, eternally, are. He seems to speak of souls as the active agents in the exchange of beings, but then souls must alter and be, contradictorily, both changeless and changing units. If the basic units of reality are units of making, then what is made can then remain to be parts of successive others’ makings. Once made, beings are everlasting. Only metaphysical abstractions are eternal and changeless “beings,” that is, characteristics descriptive of all possible comings-to-be. Suggested Reading: Datta; Gross; Koller; Hiriyanna on Buddhism; Plato’s dialogues: the early dialogues are easy to read; Hartshorne and Reese, section on Plato; Histories of Philosophy; Collett Cox, Disputed Dharmas: Early Buddhist Theories on Existence (Tokyo: The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 1995). ************************************************************************ A Process Introduction to Philosophy 79 Chapter 10: Pluralists Charles Hartshorne14 June 5, 1897–October 9, 2000 Signature from letter mentioned in the Introduction 14Reprinted by permission of Open Court Publishing Company, a division of Carus Publishing Company, Peru, Il, from The Logic of Perfection by Charles Hartshorne, © 1962 by the Open Court Publishing Company. 80 Chapter 12 Epistemology How Is Knowledge Possible? “I am, I exist, is necessarily true each time that I pronounce it, or that I mentally conceive it.” Descartes, Mediations on the First Philosophy in which the Existence of God and the Distinction between Mind and Body Are Demonstrated, II. “Cogito ergo sum” (I think, therefore I am.”) Descartes. “I doubt that I exist, therefore I do.” Augustine, 354-430 CE. “The absolute existence of unthinking things , without any relation to their being perceived, that is to me perfectly unintelligible. Their esse is percipi; [to be is to be perceived]; nor is it possible they should have any existence out of the minds or thinking things which perceive them.” Principles of Human Knowledge, Part I, 3. “The notion of it [material substance] is inconsistent.” Three Dialogues, III, Bishop Berkeley, 1685-1753. “Ideas which are clear and distinct can never be false.” Spinoza , 1632-1677, On the Improvement of the Understanding. ****************************************************************************** Focus>>• –Issues– How it is possible to know something, especially if one assumes either that: (1) the thing known is not inside the knower, or (2) the thing known is the one and only real thing, or (3) the thing known is incapable of being known by limited, human minds. –Approaches– Knowing something has been taken to mean: (1) Having a copy of the thing known, (2) Becoming one with the One, (3) Receiving a revelation, (4) Grasping another directly. –Evaluation– Pros: “Knowing” (the fourth proposal) is having in experience a symbol that is relatively clear and somewhat like what is fully and directly grasped in experience, but vaguely so; or grasping the known object directly and with awareness. Cons: (1) A copy can never be just like the original, and since the original is unknowable, knowing whether the copy is in any way like the original is impossible. (2) If the mind were to be “one with the One,” it would be impossible to know it is. (3) There is no way to check whether a revelation is of reality as it is. ****************************************************************************** E pistemology” is the Greek word philosophers use for The Theory of Knowledge. Philosophical problems can be approached from several sides. Many of the problems of the last few chapters on change have been approached by asking, how can someone know what must be known for him/er to assert what s/he does about reality? 81 A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 12: Epistemology How could Parmenides know, for example, that reality was One if knowing something necessarily involves two, namely, the knower and the known? Is a state of homogeneous being a state of knowledge? Since Parmenides says there is only one Being, the mind either is the one Being or knows it. But since Parmenides says there is only one reality, either mind or Being cannot be real. How can unreality know reality? How can appearance know what is not appearance? Is appearance really appearance? Calling something “appearance” does not avoid the problem of explaining how appearance and reality are really related. A theory that proposes that the reality referred to (known?) is beyond knowability could not know it is beyond being knowable. And appealing to a revelation to give us “knowledge” of what cannot be otherwise known, is not knowledge, for how could one know the revelation is true? A theory of reality in which there are no real relations cannot express a consistent theory. All theories that deny relationships are self-contradictory. This forces a Universal Theory of Relations on us. Even mind must be complex, that is, contain relations, in some sense. The simplest duality, or better, dipolarity, that can be expressed is knower and known (or feeler and felt). The Representational Theory of Knowledge: We know copies of the real things. Democritus, or anyone who tries to explain reality by beings that move, has another problem: How can the knower know anything if the things known are not part of the knower? Again, how can one know something existing apart from and outside the knower, that is, externally related to the place wherein knowing occurs? The atoms, and their changing relationships to each other, are what must be known. But atoms continue on their merry way and, therefore, cannot be part of the knower. This problem is supposedly solved in many systems by what is called The Representational or Copy Theory of Knowledge. The knowing mind has a copy of the thing known. Yet, how can anyone ever know whether the copy is like the original? The socalled known, that is, the original, can never be known; only the “copy” is knowable. How can a copy be called a “copy” if it cannot be compared to the original? Since it is logically impossible to know both the copy and the original, this theory is groundless, a pure leap of faith at best. It is actually a self-contradiction since one must know there is an original to speak meaningfully about a copy. If one cannot possibly know there is an original, the whole theory becomes meaningless as Berkeley pointed out. When is a copy not a copy? The possibility of knowing simultaneous differences of the same thing is meaningless in the Representational Theory of Knowledge since one never knows the thing, much less differences of the thing. Solipsism (see Glossary) plagues all philosophical theories of knowledge that assume the basic units of reality are beings. The Sautrantika Buddhists who propose an event theory of human identity have a similar problem. The knower, which in their scheme is the present being of experience, must be able to compare itself to previous beings of the series. But the past is gone when the present occurs. Their attempt to build memory of the past into the present, by saying the present being contains memory of the previous beings, can only mean the present being has characteristics of the socalled past beings. They cannot literally mean the present has the past beings themselves. “In every next moment, there is not the slightest bit left of what has existed in the former moment. [Their so-called memory can only be a representation or copy of the previous beings:] “...An exact facsimile of the previous entity crops up.” (Datta, 73). But how could one know whether the copy is accurate? All the problems with the Representational Theory of Knowledge apply here also. Knowledge cannot mean the knower and the known are external to each other no matter how close together they are, even if they are contiguous, that is, next to but external to each other. An adequate metaphysic requires a theory of internal relations as well as external relations. Known Knower Yet, internal relationships make no sense without external relationships. If something A is in something B, then B cannot be in A. It must be outside or external to A. The known A is part of the knower B. The knower B is not part of the known A. The past must be in and part of the present. The present actuality cannot be in, nor part of, the past. Known Knower Known To know things are outside each other, and to know they set up a pattern by the way they are related 82 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 12: Epistemology outside each other, logically requires they not only be simultaneously in the knower but they be what they are, as they are, in the knower. Copies, representations and the like cannot provide an adequate theory of what it means to know. A copy only makes sense if it is a stand-in for the original that must also be knowable, even if it is not yet known, or not known as clearly, as the copy at the moment. Symbol: Something used to stand for something else. Symbols are usually simple and easy to manipulate and stand for things more vague or complex. A copy, as a stand-in, is a symbol. It refers to the original. The act of referring the symbol to the original takes place in the present which is the knower. The knower knows, or could know, both the symbol and what it refers to. When the symbol is like the original in the ways one takes it to be like the original, the knower is said to have the truth. Symbolic truth is always abstract and can never capture the complete reality of the original. Only the original is just like the original. But symbolic truth can capture how things are partially alike. It can find and express changeless characteristics, Forms or I-deas (Goddess within) as Plato noted and made famous. But knowledge of these Forms cannot ex press the full reality of the original. The rich content of actual reality, can only be known by grasping it as it is within the coming-tobe of the knower. The knower by embracing or including the known must be more than the known. “More than” cannot be “other than,” the embraced. So the one embraced is not next to and outside, but rather within the reality of the embracer. To know is either (1) to embrace the known directly or (2) to embrace a symbol directly and refer it to the original (that is, compare it to the original) in some way that the original does in fact exhibit and can be known to have. Only by embracing and gathering the past into the present can solipsism be rationally confronted. Whitehead says the very act of consciously perceiving the world around us necessarily abstracts from the welter of entities there and presents to us a useful but greatly simplified version of our surroundings. To assume one’s experience of a visual object is a single item that lasts over time (when it really is a complex, lineal society of moments), is to commit the Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness. Committing this fallacy gives rise to the mistaken notion of beings that alter or move. Perceptual objects of conscious experience are really symbols (appearances) of what exists and what is experienced less clearly at a more visceral and preconscious level. Chapter Summary Either one contains, grasps, embraces another, or one doesn’t. Insofar as one does, one can know the other. If one partially grasps another, one can have truth of that aspect. If one doesn’t contain anything of another, one cannot even know there is another. If things in reality are only externally related, knowledge is not possible. If all relationships are internal, there is only one thing, one reality, and knowledge is not possible despite Parmenides’ attempt to tell us he can know the One. So-called copies of reality aren’t copies if the so-called original is not only unknown, but unknowable. If reality is composed of units of making, which can only begin their making by grasping the accomplishments of others, the main problem of knowledge is solved before it is a problem: To exist is to exist in relationship to others. To exist is to include some others as parts of oneself. The attempted theory of self-sufficient and isolated souls “knowing” only their own ideas or copies of a world supposedly outside themselves, is called “solipsism;” it is merely an interesting fiction. Suggested Reading: Whitehead, Symbolism; Woozley. ************************************************************************* A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 12: Epistemology Yggdrasil Scandinavian World Tree The tree, as the axis of the universe from which Odin hung for nine days before descending and then returning from the underworld with women’s secrets to share with men. Drawn from a picture in Fix, 127. ***************************************************************** Conceiving as Surpassing “If you can conceive of the unsurpassable, the unsurpassable has been surpassed....The unsurpassable, I feel, is nonsense. If you think of unsurpassability and know the essence, existence and actuality, then you have surpassed the unsurpassable. Some of the things Positivists believe, I don’t go along with, but I do believe that the unsurpassable is nonsense.” Student, 1994. 83 84 Chapter 13 Whitehead Moments of Growth “The ultimate metaphysical principle is the advance from disjunction to conjunction, creating a novel entity other than [that is, in addition to] the entities given in disjunction....The many become one, and are increased by one.” A. N. Whitehead, Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– Answering how it is possible to have simultaneous comparison of successive differences of the same thing. –Approaches– Whitehead proposes that each moment is a coming-to-be of a new being around the results of previous comings-to-be. His position draws from: (1) the Goddess tradition by including the physical (things done) in the really real (his moments of process creativity), and by recycling or retaining old accomplishments in the new present, (2) the Milesians by asking the universal question, How is everything alike? (3) the Pythagoreans by emphasizing the patterns realities exhibit rather than the stuff they are made of, (4) Heraclitus by seeing the fundamental reality as a coming-to-be rather than being, (5) Parmenides by agreeing once a being is, it can never change in any way, (6) Anaxagoras by maintaining all things in reality have, or are, qualities, (7) Democritus by saying all moments have a finite spatial size that is indivisible, (8) Buddhists by agreeing anything lasting over time is a series of wholes or moments, rather than one whole that alters with each new difference. –Evaluation– Pro: Seems to give a logical explanation for how change is meaningful. Con: Is vague on the unity of the universe: On whether the universe over time is the same whole or a series of wholes. ***************************************************************************** T hough there are a few, for example, Henri Bergson (1859-1941) who countered the emphasis on being over becoming, it was not until Alfred North Whitehead (1861-1947) that the logical relationship between being and becoming was sufficiently clarified to avoid obvious selfcontradictions. The answer to how simultaneous comparison of successive differences of the same thing is possible begins by maintaining that life, process, growth, that is, coming-to-be, is the basis of what is really real. “Really real” here means something that actually exists by acting or creating. Full reality is, (1) not just a possible act, (2) nor aspects common to some or all possible acts, (3) nor an act already done. Acts that are finished are beings, and all beings are parts of fully real things, namely, actors or makers of beings. Act-uality is acting. It is an effort to get something done. Whitehead realized coming-to-be, the effort of creating something, makes sense only when the effort pays off and the coming-to-be comes to be. The process of creating15 creates something that has 15Whitehead’s term for process is “concrescence,” a growing together of many into a whole. Actually, the 85 A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 13: Whitehead never been before. A process creates, and what it creates is a creation, a thing that now is, namely, a being. Each process is a moment of life that does something with its life, but once that something is accomplished, the process of that life is ended. A moment of life must die, come to be, or nothing new ever gets done. Heraclitus missed this essential point. He proposed reality was life or process, that is, coming-to-be, but nothing ever came to be. He had no real beings that are. Every coming-to-be must end with an accomplishment, that is, as a being. A being is created by a moment of life. So Whitehead’s view requires beings to be real. They are the real things created by present acts. They are the things already created by past (dead) actors or, as Whitehead says, by past and “objectified” actual entities. They are no longer subjects, but objects for other subjects. But though the life is ended, what the life finally did is in new lives forever, and so will continue to be as it is forever. The past is being. Beings are created, and are always parts of new comings-to-be. They are changelessly forever what they are. Beings are created, and are always parts of new comings-to-be. ––––––––o––––––– The Past is here, in the present! This is the answer to the question, “Where is the past?” that too few have handled adequately. Where does being exist? Parmenides says one being is all there is, so he dismisses the question. Democritus says beings exist in the Void and have always been there. Whitehead says beings cannot exist by themselves. The substantial or self-supportive stuff of reality is not being nor the Void. It is creative process or coming-to-be, as Heraclitus suggests. The fundamental stuff of reality is doing, not something done. However, a unit of making can (and in principle must) contain, as parts of its unit of becoming, things already done. Every act begins somewhere with something already done. The moment of creating does not leave behind what it begins with. It enfolds it and carries it along. To be is to be as a part of some becoming or other. Becoming is always a whole; a being is always a part of some whole or other and always something past, that is, something done. To be past is not to be gone. To be past is to be a part of the present. To be part of the present is not to be the present. To be past is to be settled. Nothing about the past can ever be changed. Being is completely changeless. process itself is the whole. Wholes create beings that are parts of successive wholes. Those from Parmenides on who have insisted on the changelessness of being were not wrong. However, just because being must be changeless once it is, does not logically require beings cannot be created. Every being has come to be, except metaphysical characteristics of beings (see footnote 29, Chapter 22). Every being has been created, therefore, every being is contingent, that is, could have been different from the way it is. But once it is, it must forever be as it is. Being is not capable of any alteration nor locomotion. Beings cannot change. What changes is the series, as some Buddhists insisted. Change is the difference of one being from another in the same series. Since Whitehead says the series is a series of creatings or comings-to-be and not a series of beings, it is possible for him to get two or more beings together in the same moment simultaneously so they can be compared. The present moment, the process in cluding the results of previous processes, is the comparer. The (past) beings are the objects compared. So how is it possible to know which being came before another if they are all together as parts of the present? There must be a way of knowing which beings necessarily come before others. The logic here is one of nesting or depth of inclusiveness. Beings contain other beings as parts because the processes that made them also contained beings as parts. In the following diagram, C is not just the shaded area; C is the whole, complex area with three patterns as parts. If A or B were different parts, C would be a different whole. Likewise, B is an area of two patterns. If A were different, B would be different also. But it is important to notice that C could be different (or not be at all), and B and A would be just the same. If B had been different, A would still be the same, but not C. This illustrates the logical asymmetry of succession or time. Temporal Asymmetry A B C A process ends up as a new being. The new being, however, contains the beings the unit of creating began with. In this way comparison of beings is not only possible but inevitable. A process can compare (1) a being to a part of itself which is what time or succession of the same thing (series) means, or a process can compare 86 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 13: Whitehead (2) two or more beings that are independent of each other. If two beings, newly created, are taken into a process, they are said to have occurred simultaneously from the point of view of the process. But simultaneity is only meaningful if the two simultaneously occurring beings are both in, that is, past to a process that contains them both. Part of the realization of physical science’s Theory of Relativity is that two occurrences, that some moment experiences as happening at the same time, need not be experienced as occurring at the same time by another moment. Larger (later) beings include smaller (earlier) beings, (and will do so forever). Two Intersecting Personal Series Two Series, M and N M's Future Boundaries of M and N's experience and influence. N's Future m n (present N's Past x • moment of N) y • M's Past For M, xyand y occur simultaneously. x occurs first–– For M, x and occur simultaneously. ForFor N, xN,occurs first. x and y are contemporaries. x and y are contemporaries. Disagreement as to the order of occurrences is possible, but only when the occurrences being compared are causally independent of each other. If one being contains another as part of itself, every point of view in the universe must see the one included as happening before the one that includes it. To illustrate, take two light flashes, x and y, a few million miles apart. If a person M equal-distant from x and y sees them at the same time, then someone N closer to x will see x first, and someone closer to y will see y first. What does it mean to say the lights were flashed at the same time? Relativity physics says that question is meaningless apart a from a reference to a particular series in the world which organizes the transmitted signals. Despite the truths of relativity physics, is there, perhaps, some way to refer to a cosmic unity, a cosmic present? Transmissions between noncontiguous individuals within the universe require the transmission be mediated by others. Every experience (every creating pre sent) takes a perspective on the rest of the universe. Perspective is failure to include most of the things that have just happened. An actuality in the world must take a perspective on the world. It can only experience as simultaneous those beings that have been created contiguous to it or have been transmitted to it by others as it begins. Most acts do not spread over, that is, include all, or even very much, of what has just happened in the universe. What has just happened somewhere cannot yet have been transmitted anywhere. A being that has just come to be exists immediately and without transmission (that is, without mediation) within the successive moments contiguous to it which must spread over and include it. Transmitted beings are experienced from the point of view of the process that receives the transmission as carried to it by A Process Introduction to Philosophy 87 Chapter 12: Whitehead others. A moment, or series of moments (like a person), experiences a transmitted being from a perspective within the universe. Perspective arises from experiencing part of the universe from within the Whole. But there is the logical possibility one creative act, or series of acts, takes no perspective at all on the universe. The possibility of cosmic experience contiguous with all the beings just created will be examined in later chapters (especially Chapter 24). But when that possibility is examined, we must be very careful not to confuse one moment (even a cosmically inclusive one) that lives and dies in the present, with a personal series of such moments. Perhaps there is a series that doesn’t have a first or last member, even if the notion of one moment that lasts forever adding new changes is not meaningful. Each moment of a series begins its creating using the opportunities and limitations provided by the beings of the environment with which that moment begins. The moment ends with a new being. The new being contains the old beings within the novelty created by the present moment itself. What defines a series is the common past, the core, that each member of the series inherits. Each series is unique because no two series can have exactly the same beings in their growing core. Yet, the defining uniqueness of a series is not always quite so straightforward. A series of beings can be found in two or more series because a series of beings, a single past, can be inherited by two or more presents. This is the converse of a present simultaneously inheriting many beings or pasts. inheritance of the same being. (See illustrations under Nexüs at the end of this chapter.) Once one appreciates that process, not be ing, is the stuff of reality, finding a being in more than one place (process) at the same time will not seem so strange. Being is a conditioning of becoming or process. One being can condition more than one process simultaneously. A being does not have to be in just one place (one process) at a time, but each process is a unique once-in-a-universe occurrence. What it makes can be inherited by many creatings and must always be inherited by at least one, or else what is in existence, would no longer be. That some-thing becomes nothing is nonsense. Something (a being or process) cannot even become something different from what it is. The only “something” that can change is a series, that is, one moment can become and be different from previous beings in the same series. By now the reader may have become very impatient with the demands of logic. After all, experience shows us things changing much of the time: Objects like chairs do change their places, and people do change their minds. Whitehead has an explanation for the tendency to assume things move, rather than realize that what is really happening is the creation of something new each moment. The human mind is, first of all, designed for surviving. We need to know when danger is present, food is available, and how to satisfy other concerns for survival. We must group things together that are similar so we are not overwhelmed with detail. The brain is an au tomatic stereotyper. Generally we have no reason to distinguish one atomic event or even one cellular event from another. So those the characteristic that dominates a group (as Anaxagoras would say) is experienced rather than the many, somewhat unique, individuals. Space and Time (1) a (2) b Coordination: Space a b Succession: Time Each of the two presents must contain some beings the other does not, and must be using its creativity in a somewhat different way, but they could both have a core past in common. What was one series, one person, can branch into two or more. The phenomenon of multiple persons in psychology and the ability of something to be in two or more places at once in physics are examples of multiple A spatial or temporal group may not be a concrete reality [in addition to the concreteness of its members]. A green book cover is called “one” cover. The book is called “one” book. But the cover is not one thing. It is a very complex society of atomic processes. To believe a society is really one thing rather than one group is to commit what Whitehead calls the Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness. We do not assume all the people of the United States are one thing, even though the image of Uncle Sam is used to stand for all, and so no fallacy is committed. Assuming something is concretely one when it is really an abstraction or collection is a fallacy either (1) when many in a spatial group are taken to be one concrete whole or 88 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 13: Whitehead (2) when many in a temporal group (series) are taken to be one thing. The chair at any one moment is a contemporaneous (spatial) group, but the chair as it survives through time is also composed of a large number of series. Since the many series which comprise the chair inherit each others’ pasts and stay together even when “moved,” we mistakenly assume a common stuff, a single matter, exists that supports the changing qualities of the chair over time and throughout space. Two Meanings of “One” ONE moment of a series (concrete sense), versus ONE series of moments (abstract sense) and/or group of moments. But the support for the qualities of the chair resides in the many momentary processes. Successive processes in the series of a group are very much like previous ones because they inherit the same beings, so a complex society of many spatial and temporal things may continue to exist and hang together. Ordinary, macroscopic objects are not single things. Their unity is in social cooperation––not in numerical singularity––even though we often preconsciously eliminate much of the insignificant diversity of the society and experience it consciously as one quality. The question remains: Is the whole universe one or many? In Whitehead’s categories: Are the many beings created by the many processes of the cosmos (at each moment) all within one unifying process which is one cosmic moment in a series of allinclusive, unifying processes? Chapter Summary Whitehead accepts both Parmenides’ belief that being must be changeless and Heraclitus’ assertion that coming-to-be is the meaning of full reality. He does not seek fire or anything else to be the common stuff that fluxes. Each flux is unique; its own “stuff,” even though they are all alike in abstract ways, such as, being creative. Whitehead also accepts some Buddhists’ belief that reality is composed of many units, but units which are temporally thick or finite, not “infinitesimally quick” as some Buddhists say, and not just spatial units that are temporally infinite like Democritean atoms. Each unit is a creation of a new being around the results of previous creatings. Beings come to be and remain forever as they are in new comings-to-be. Suggested Reading: Leclerc; Hartshorne, PSG, WP; Whitehead. *************************************************************************************** A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 13: Whitehead Alfred North Whitehead 1861-1947 Photo from The Philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead, Paul Schilpp, ed., 1941. 89 90 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 13: Whitehead Nexüs A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 13: Whitehead Actual Entities (Numbers in brackets are Categoreal Conditions. See Appendix 3.) 91 Change and the Unsurpassable 92 Chapter 13: Whitehead The Spatial-Temporal Continuum For more advanced contemplators POGO16 And before the “REAL big bang” 16 Reprint permission applied for. 93 Chapter 14 Summary of the Problem of Change L “Time went by And the boy grew older.” Shel Silverstein, The Giving Tree. ife makes a death that “lives” (is) in other lives forever. This insight has been part of culture and religion as far back as Neolithic time, 10,000 years ago, and likely ten times that long. But an idea is generally vague at first, and with time various ways of interpreting it are discovered. A death that lives again may have first been likened to the way animals die in order to give us life when we use them for food, or the way we become leaves of grass, to use Walt Whitman’s phase. We live after death in the affects we have in others. If we identify with a group, a tribe, we are born again in each one born into the clan. The blood ties were thought to be literal. The menstrual blood, the stuff of life, flowed in all of those who had the same mother or mother ancestor. Today we speak of genetic similarity. When one died, the blood was returned to the Great Mother to be used again. As the clan ties were weakened and paternity became recognized and substituted for maternal creation, there was more concern for what happened to each individual. The “living again” took the form of personal rebirth. So long as maternal concepts dominated society’s worldview, rebirth was seen as happening over and over as one’s life went through the five stages: birth, puberty (menarche), maturity (reproduction), sage (post reproductive––menopause), and death that set up the female trinity of life: maiden, mother and crone. Death was going back into the Great Mother’s womb to be reborn. The grim reaper was also the birth-giver. But as patriarchs gained social power, men felt less need to copy females and their life stages (like the genital blood-letting males still are subjected to in the circumcision rite at puberty in some cultures), and became motivated to find alternatives to female categories. The cyclical pattern of dying in order to live again gave way to a view of death that offered new life forever, apart from Mater. One never had to be born again. Being born of woman was even seen as the worst possible event a person must endure. It is the original sin of existence, according to St. Augustine, who has been influential since the Fourth Century. In patriarchal cultures, the new life one acquires after death is with the father, not the mother, and it lasts forever. Patriarchal ethics is based in a concern to please the father, to be worthy enough in his eyes to be allowed the never-ending life in his kingdom. Patriarchal ethics is also deeply concerned with womb control in order to assure a male’s creation will not be thwarted, to assure his “blood line” (seed) will be the only creation nurtured by his helpmate. The disgust of the female, probably arising from male jealously of her creative monopoly, produced a theory of afterlife rather than a theory of new life. One’s life after death, however, could never be removed from the female metaphors of rebirth, but the patriarchal salvation scheme was very definite on one point: the afterlife is not a coming back to life within the physical earth mother and her kin; it is a better, glorified life with a better glorified body that is not ever again subject to the cycles of female created life. Never again will one be born, as St. Augustine coarsely says, between piss and shit. Our new spiritual kin are in a separate kin-gdom. This theory of physical life, death, and new spiritual life (which we have seen as early as the Pythagoreans) finally concludes that the physical body is not essential nor even natural for man. It was thought to be a prison locking up the real man, the soul. The soul was alive before birth. To be born of woman was to tie up a soul in matter (that is, mater, mother stuff). To die was to be born into real life with father, or simply to get back to the natural state of the soul: pure, unadulterated, unrecycled. A price must be paid for acquiring this union (reunion) with the father. Only the worthy are given the happiness of this state (stasis). The unworthy are punished: Punishment is not a return to the world where a second chance might bring about its cessation, as Plato said. Punishment now is everlasting. The depreciation of women went so far as to deny they even had this essence of real life, the soul, even though the word for “soul” in most languages is feminine, the Greek, psyche, for example. The ultimate men’s club would not admit women. The one-sidedness of matriarchal religious/philosophical schemes that assigned creative power to the female as well as social status, had been turned around. There still was blood shed, but it was from death and wounds, not from life-giving menstrual cycles, yet it was glorified just the same. War and conflict was part of life and afterlife. Gods fought gods and goddesses and men imitated them as holy duties in endless holy wars whose virulence is still rampant. Society set up stringent ins and outs, the blessed and the damned. Even the universe was no longer a 94 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 14: Change unity as the duality of heaven and hell grew ever more mutually exclusive. Reality was no longer seen as one unity embraced within the one body of the Goddess. –––––––––––o––––––––––– The ancient truth that life creates death that lives again is true for Whitehead and Hartshorne also, but with a reinterpretation that a better understanding of change allows. The duration of the moment varies with the kind of species, lasting about a twentieth of a second for people. A moment of life creates something, a being. The being is the result of the life. The death of the momentary life is its being. Death is the “loss” (completion) of a life since the creating that was the moment of life is over and can never live again without self-contradiction. The momentary life is not killed; it is satisfied. Life would be meaningless without a result, the problem we saw with Heraclitus’ pure flux. After death, the being, “lives” again in the next moment of life. A moment of life begins with the accomplishments of previous lives. A life takes these doings, these beings, into itself and uses them to make a new result containing them. So every being is alive in one important sense: It has effects or conse quences for other lives. It is enjoyed or suffered by others’ lives, forever. Only by being dead can a life change or affect other lives. A moment of creative life, during its creating, does not change other moments of life. They are, as a physicist would say, contemporaries; they are mutually independent, causally unrelated. Only a moment’s death can be a cause. Only a death can make a difference in another. Each death is reborn, resurrected in other lives. If one wants to call a moment of life a ”soul,” then a soul dies by becoming a body, a being. Soul, or creative process, is not capable of being experienced as an object. It is always a subject with beings as its objects. The soul dies by becoming an object for other momentary souls. So, if beings are thought of as bodies, that is, physical, then rebirth happens by resouling bodies rather than reincarnating, that is, re-embodying, souls. Reality is unavoidably dipolar. Each moment of reality is a creating subject experiencing objects. Objects cannot exist except in subjects and subjects cannot exist without experiencing objects. But subjects and objects are not on equal footing: Subjects or processes are the inclusive pole. Objects are in subjects; never vice versa. The older, more naive, formulations of reality said there were subjects (souls, lives and comings-tobe) and there are objects (matter and changeless beings). Each was thought to be able to exist apart from the other. This is dualism, not dipolarity. The old attempts to overcome dualism were expressions of monism. Heraclitus says reality consists only of life or subjectivity, there are no real objects or stability. Parmenides says the opposite: Reality is only an object that is dead, changeless, lifeless. Democritus basically agrees with Parmenides, though he tries to get life back into reality as locomotion. But locomotion cannot explain coming-to-be. Process must make something new, a new death or result. Locomotion cannot introduce anything new. Dead realities can never do anything new. Life can make a death, but even life cannot re-make or alter a death. A death is changeless and incorruptible. Every death will, however, partially determine how future lives will be lived since every death must be included in some life. A Life must include others’ deaths, but a death cannot contain life. In terms of the categories of change: A whole in its creative coming-to-be can contain changeless parts, but a static whole (a being) cannot contain parts that are coming to be. The following chart summarizes most of the attempted relationships of being and becoming. The major distinction among these theories hinges on the difference between, (1) a single concrete actuality defined as a unit that is the same unit throughout changes, a unit supposedly capable of surviving differences, and (2) a concrete actuality that lasts for only one moment as fully concrete—a unit that can only do one (complex) thing. This distinction is that between a theory of enduring substance and that of momentary substance. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 95 Chapter 14: Change 1. Being Only––Parmenides; perhaps most of Eastern pantheism and mysticism. Since being is being, propositions asserting distinctions in reality must be attributing something to reality other than being, like red or happy. Change is seen as meaningless since (1) being can only change into being which is no change, or (2) the being must be what it is and then not be what it is after the so-called change. The same being must be A and notA, a logical self-contradiction. Anything but Being is called “appearance.” But is appearance real? How does it come into being ? How can we, as appearances, know reality is not like any of our experiences? Reality as one absolute can have no real relationships to anything, including our attempt to know it. 2. Becoming Only––Heraclitus; perhaps Henri Bergson and modern wave physics. This position denies anything remains or endures for two or more moments of time. Yet time is meaningless apart from succession, and succession implies something new exists to compare to the old. With the past gone before, or as, the present comes into being, reality is only the present. With no possibility of comparison, change is meaningless. Only by surreptitiously assuming a changeless memory does this seem at all reasonable. What is the stuff that is changing? Fire, matter, energy, space, soul? 3. Beings That Alter Internal State Enduring Substances––Common sense; Milesians, Pythagorean’s soul, and some aspect of most philosophical positions. Alteration of A to B This common position maintains a thing that can have different states or attributes internally and yet remain the same thing. The most common type of reality thought to be alterable is mind or soul. If so, a mind must be what it is and then be other than it was (or is?) when the new state of mind comes into being, since a mind is a whole with its thoughts or experiences as parts or it is nothing. Parmenides’ position is an adequate rebuttal of all positions that hold that any kind of being can alter. A being, as a concrete state of affairs, is what it is because of all its aspects; it cannot change some of its characteristics and still be the same being. Every whole is what it is because its parts are what they are. Parmenides also claimed that a whole cannot have distinct parts within it, even if they were unalterable. This cannot be true, unless a theory of reality makes sense without any external relations, something that’s never been successful. 96 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 14: Change 4. Beings That Alter Position: Enduring Substances––Democritus; Newton; Common sense; much of science, and many philosophical positions. Concrete beings that only change position, and not internal state, are usually called “material substances.” Democritean or classical atomism has been very influential in Western science. Each atom is like the Parmenidean One with no internal distinctions or qualitative attributes. They are in a Void which also has no distinctions within it. Atoms can only have quantita tive variations of shape and size, and they can do nothing but move and rearrange. They have never been created, nor can they be destroyed. They have always been in motion, and change of direction results from external and “random” collisions with others. Change means “rearrangement” of the internally changeless beings within the one void or space. Can nothingness be the unity of the many? Can one say the atoms are in the Void if they have no affect in or on it when they rearrange? Take three atoms in a line: Change supposedly occurs when they are moved to a triangle. But the first arrangement is gone before (as) the second comes into being , so there is no chance for comparison of successive differences (see A). Perhaps memorycan be the solution: Mind, if anything, must also be atoms. If “the mind” is represented by a row of atoms (see B), then rearrangement of some of the row could be what happens in experience, A. like the three atoms in the line C. Then when the new triangular arrangement happens, “the mind” could also rearrange some of is atoms, though not the same ones that record the previous experience or else the past arrangement would be gone again (see D). Yet even with both B. patterns in existence (in being), there is still no reality they are in that can compare them to each other. The so-called mind not is one atom, “it” is an aggregate. The experience of a group requires something that is not a group; it requires a C. singular whole with the group as parts. There is also no way to know temporal order. Both arrangements are on equal logical footing. They seem to have occurred at the same time; they seem to be contemporaries. Democritus' metaphysics does not allow one to know contrast, much less sequence, without violating the ultimate D. assertion he makes that reality consists only of atoms “in” the void. 5. Beings As Changeless Ideals and the Fully Real and Becoming As Comings and Goings of Beings and Not Fully Real––Plato Plato can be read as an attempt to come to grips with Parmenides. Changeless Beings are the fully real; but only concepts are exempt from change; therefore, they are the really real. The world of thought or mind is the only way to experience reality, namely, the changeless. The body with its emotions and sense experience only hinders achieving the truth of reality. Change is the replacement of one Being, Form, or Idea, by another in the world’s spatial manifold. Matter can never accept the Idea ideally, that is, perfectly, since mater is intrinsically imperfect, so sense experience is always imperfect. Plato also has souls in his world view. They are the movers that are self-moved. Since the whole world moves, he even posits a World Soul . The relation of the manifold of matter, the World Soul, and the Realm of Ideal Beings is not clearly worked out. Different traditions emphasized various aspects of his thought; yet common themes are: other-worldliness, disembodied souls, and deprecation of the value of the world as opposed to the value of a changeless heaven to contemplate––with God (Plato’s Form of the Good) as a Being changeless in all ways. Plato is close to the Buddhists’ position below. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 97 Chapter 14: Change 6. Series of Changeless Beings: Some Ancient Buddhists. Reality consists of experiences. Not only is this a denial that reality consists of dead stuff or altering substance, but also the denial there is even a living substance that has the experiences. A person is just the series of experiences; each one is what it is, as Parmenides would say. It does not alter. It occurs and disappears(?) as another occurs. They are externally related. Death of a person is the failure to have another experience in the series. The denial of persistent substance through change is important to some Buddhists’ idea of salvation, namely, escape from suffering, which the nearly endless reincarnations of Hinduism does not allow. Perhaps, when all is said, some Buddhists, like Hindus, still hold positions similar to Parmenides’: Brahman or Nirvana is the wholeness of reality, and is the only really real. In this ultimate The direction arrow is assumed but is reality here can be no suffering since there are no contrasts to set not allowed in reality if there is only up conflicts. There can be no joy either. one being at a time, so the actual past does not survive into the present. In a series of moments where the former moment is gone as the present occurs, no comparison is possible. In Parmenides’ Being or Hindu’s Brahman there, too, is no way for the present to logically indicate temporal direction. Temporal direction must make sense without arrowheads or other conventions. Simultaneous and contemporaneous complexity defines space, not time. Time is successive or accumulative complexity that results from the past becoming a part in the present. Given B, B must be partly what it is because of A that occurred before B, but not vice versa. 7. Series of Becomings with Each Coming To Be Growing Around and Sustaining Previous Beings As Parts: Whitehead. Whitehead says ultimate reality is both being and becoming, though not on equal footing. He agrees with Parmenides that being cannot contain becoming or change, but becoming can have beings as parts of its moment. A whole must remain self-identical. Wholes for Whitehead are units of process, becomings, or flux as Heraclitus says, but they do come to be during some finite temporal duration. The being that becomes is then changeless forever. Being is everlasting once created, but not eternal as are Democritean atoms or souls in some theories of reincarnation; all beings (which are always the results of process wholes) have come to be except the metaphysical characteristics (common factors) of all beings. Being survives by being included in, or used as, the raw material for, new units of creative becoming. Beings necessarily condition future comingsto-be, not by doing anything new themselves, but simply by being the stepping stones or stumbling blocks they are for present and future creatings. 98 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 14: Change *********************************************************************************** Chapter Summary Process Philosophy Inversion The boy grew older, So time went by. 99 PART IV Historical Influences on Theistic Beliefs Ascendancy of Patriarchal Concepts ––––– Mithraism: One Hellenistic Origin of Medieval Patriarchal Philosophy ––––– Essenes: Another Hellenistic Origin of Medieval Patriarchal Philosophy Copyright 2003 Duane Voskuil 100 Chapter 15 Ascendancy of Patriarchal Concepts “Wives submit yourselves to your...husbands....” Paul of Tarsus. “Woman is a temple built over a sewer, the gateway to the devil.” Church Father Tertullian, ca. 200 CE. “Every woman should be overwhelmed with shame at the thought that she is a woman.” St. Clement of Alexandria, ca. 200 CE. “Simon Peter said to them, ‘Let Mary [Magdalene] leave us, for women are not worthy of Life.’ Jesus said: ‘I myself shall lead her in order to make her male, so that she too may become a living spirit resembling you males. For every woman who will make herself male will enter the Kingdom of Heaven.’” Gospel of Thomas, Second Century, quoted from Filoramo, 117. “I happen to believe in traditional American values.” Cincinnati judge Albert Mestemaker, ordering a man to marry the girlfriend he was convicted of punching in the mouth. Newsweek, 7/24/95. “She’s wearing a ring that makes her the property of this U.S. male.” Lyrics from ‘50s song, U.S. Male, a pun on U.S. Mail. Emphasis added. ******************************************************************************** Focus>>• –Issues– The increasing prominence of male-centered metaphors to explain reality and control society. –Approaches– (1) Asceticism and male separatism were used to remove males from the female “threat.” (2) Sperm theory of creation is substituted for the menstrual-blood theory. (3) Male heroes are worshipped for their sacrifices and sufferings and ability to free men from the world of mater. –Evaluation– Pro: Male sacrifice becomes questioned. Cons: (1) Substitution of one gender for the other to explain reality is not a rational approach, since gender is not a metaphysical characteristic. (2) Greater emphasis on “ins and outs” becomes a rationalization to justify imposing the truth on the “outs,” enslaving and eliminating them, in the name of God’s will. ********************************************************************************* A Process Introduction to Philosophy 101 Chapter 15: Patriarchy T he female metaphors first purporting to explain reality have never been fully discounted, though, they have often been usurped by men and given a new slant. Most people still live in male-gender-based societies. However, the ideals of democracies, especially the attempt to separate patriarchal religious bureaucracies from political structures, has allowed much more opportunity for the prepatriarchal worldview (or its modern counterpart) to have a hearing. Much is now being written about Goddess civilizations and morals. Much of it sees The Patriarchy as an unmitigated evil: Wars, overpopulation, loss of reverence for life and the environmental disasters, slavery, sexism, an antipleasure, life-denying ethic, and so on. Much in these judgments is likely true, but much is likely half-true and sentimental. Men lived for tens of thousands of years within a matrifocal framework. Why did this philosophical system begin to break down around 4000 BCE? Why did men find a need to subordinate, or withdraw from, the Female? This need is not yet satiated despite the large number of women tortured and burned at the stake during the European witch craze. Even today women are killed and mutilated (hundreds of millions of women and children have been forced to undergo unnecessary clitoridectomies, infibulations hysterectomies and episiotomies). Many women in our own armed services find their fellow male comrades as dangerous as any enemy. Yet, despite what many apologists for the Goddess-worshipping, matrifocal societies say, men were discriminated against in her societies. Perhaps they did not even realize that they were, or they had compensating activities that gave their lives meaning. But the female reproductive system was the ultimate metaphor of explanation and meaning, and men did not have it. Many tried to become as much like females as possible. This often meant cutting off all their genitals in order to become a priest/ess. They offered their most valued body parts to please the Goddess. They wore women’s style clothing as priests still do today. As hunting became more superfluous with the success of animal domestication and agriculture, purpose for men must have waned even further. After all, this was a period in history where the reproductive function of males was not clear. Sexual activity and its relationship to reproduction was vague. Likely women first figured it out. Their telling men may have been their biggest mistake. Men were taken as consorts by women as desire dictated, a relationship often temporary. Women owned the land, ran the governments. A queen who was thought to be an incarnation of the Goddess (just as kings would also come to claim they are divine) could take a consort, a king, until she tired of him. One way to get rid of him was to have his rival competition kill him off. In fact, a pretender to the office of king often had to prove his worthiness to be with the queen by his ability to vanquish the present king. He sometimes had to prove his sexual virility with an erection at the sight of the queen while she bathed. However, the king’s death at the hand of his “son” (any male the Goddess begets is a son, since the king is seen as her mate and, therefore, father), was ritualized into a necessary and inevitable outcome. The son in turn is killed by his son who is really his father now reborn as a son, in the cyclical manner of one season giving way to another. Blood, the stuff of life and reality in the Goddess tradition, is still important in the transition to more male-centered worldviews. But males did not bleed, nor flow, naturally. They had to be mutilated or killed to bleed. Their bleeding was taken to be a pleasing thing to the Goddess who took blood as an offering, a returning of part of what she had given. One way men could fit into the female blood rituals was by their death. A king was allowed the blessings of the Goddess by way of her earthly stand-in (the queen/priestess), but he had to give up his life as a sacrifice. Many men must have longed for the opportunity for the love-death, the death-kiss. To become king was to gain power, privilege, but also death. His death symbolized the annual cycles of grain that grow and die in order to grow once more again. Unless the seed “die,” new life is impossible. The king’s blood and flesh were scattered over the fields to insure fertility, just as a woman’s blood must flow for her to be fertile. The sacred soter (sower/savior), king must die. The king also (by the blessings he received) became divine, and in the old view, one becomes what one eats; we are what we eat, as the saying goes. So the body of the sacrificed king was often eaten and his blood drunk to insure one would become immortal like the divinities. Eventually, a substitute king, called a “sacred king,” developed who had for a time all the privileges of the real king. This sacred king was then sacrificed and was assured immediate immortality. He died not only for the king, but for everyone. Without the bloodletting people be lieved their divinity would not be pleased and their crops would not grow. Human sacrifice as a form of worship was common. The practice was eventually changed to substituting animals and even grain, though giving up animal (and even human sacrifice) was resisted by some. The story of Cain and Abel points out that Cain’s vegetarian offerings were not so pleasing to Yahweh as Abel’s meat sacrifice. The variations on male human sacrifice are many and unpleasant: From flaying of the sacrifice (so as to use his skin in symbolic rebirth dramas) and impaling 102 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 15: Patriarchy on spears, to the variations on genital mutilations ranging from ripping out the testicles (that are were considered the external intestines) to circumcision. It is hard to say how much of this pain was matriarchally inspired and how much was the result of the transition philosophies to patriarchy. We know, of course, that many forms of blood-letting and genital mutilation still persist in patriarchy. Some female forms, particularly, seem clearly invented within the worldview of patriarchy. The point of the previous paragraphs (with the confusing sons of the Goddess who grow up to be her mate/lover, who die and are dismembered like ground grain and are reborn from the same Goddess’ womb/tomb) is to suggest men may have had some reasons to turn on woman or to turn away from women. Many men must have felt relatively meaningless in societies dominated by female metaphors of meaning. Even the enjoyment of sex was infused with fear. The vagina has been referred to as a vagina dentata, a vagina with teeth. This may have been a reference to the womb/tomb that eats the dead like a vulture to prepare one for the rebirth, but the fear of being consumed in sexual consummation was, and probably still is, real to many. Intercourse was referred to as the woman engulfing the man, not the man penetrating the woman, as is common today. The sex act was a consuming when it was consummated. The fear of women and the jealousy of her creative power and socio-religious standing is certainly one reason for the reaction to matriarchy. When the new theory of sperm creation was discovered, there was a further movement from the son/lover of the Goddess to a Father/Creator which eventually led to the complete denial of the Goddess/Mother in many quarters, except as embodied in evil forces in the world or trivialized into fairy tales. Asceticism, a philosophy of denying one’s enjoyment of life, especially sexual enjoyment as way of dealing with the female threat, seems to have begun with Buddhism about 500 BCE . It spread to the Mideast in Zoroastrianism with its dualism and warring angelology. It then may have influenced a Hebrew sect called the Essenes (see Chapter 17), who were very influential at the time Christianity was founded. Another religion that appealed to a divine hero, a son of God, and one even more misogynous than Christianity, was Mithraism which started a century before we hear of the ascetic, Saul/Paul of Tarsus, in the very city in which Mithraism began. Even this religion with its emphasis on a male hero, who saved men to be with a father god, nevertheless initiated its members by “washing” them in blood, or marking their chests with crosses of blood, from the death of a sacrificial bull. Perhaps men’s fear of women had another dimension. The people in the Steppes of Russia just north of the Black and Caspian seas, known as the Kurgans, developed hardened copper weapons and domesticated the horse. They also invented iron. They became raiders of European and Mediterranean Goddess-oriented civilizations from 4300 to 1500 BCE. The ancient Greeks called the aggressive people from this region who had even conquered north Africa, Amazons, “moon-women.” The Greeks also had legends of the centaur, a feared horse/human. Much myth abounds about Amazons, including a island where they lived and killed off all the men. The moon-sickle, the scythe, was a Scythian (Kurgan) weapon or tool also used to cut off male genitals in ritual mutilations. Two things seem clear, (1) human sacrifice and genital mutilation were practiced in societies dominated by matriarchal ethics, and (2) aggressive war, at least in Eurasia, began in a society still controlled by women and female metaphors of purpose. The mobility provided by the horse and their superior weapons gave them the opportunity to impose themselves on others, and they did. Males may have been a major force in the warring activities, but with the information now known, men cannot simply be blamed for the disruption of the so-called peaceful Goddess civilization. Chapter Conclusion Much of the history of the rise of patriarchy is still speculative, but only one who has not tried to find the information can assume the way societies are now structured has always been, or that our way is the natural or God-given way. Our way may be “God-given,” but only in the sense that “god” as opposed to “goddess” reflects male-dominated societies and the biased philosophies that developed to justify this dominance. Of course, prepatriarchal worldviews were undoubtedly just as biased towards the veneration of female creative and nurturing abilities which, likewise, philosophy justified. We are just becoming aware of the negative consequences of demonizing this earlier view. But the one-sidedness of any gender-based philosophy will always generate bad metaphysics and be ethically disastrous. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 103 Chapter 15: Patriarchy Suggested Reading: Walker, Encyclopedia; Tannahill, Sex in History, Barker-Benfield; Ritter; the videos: “The Burning Times” and “Boxing Helena;” Lerner, The Creation of Patriarchy; Mallory. *************************************************************** Caduceus The serpent was an ancient symbol associated with physical and spiritual health before Biblical writers gave it a negative image. It is a symbol found in ancient India, and North America as well as the Near East. The double-sexed, two-headed serpent of the caduceus was also associated with the hermaphrodite, Hermes, whose staff (topped with the winged solar disc) reputedly had enough healing power to raise the dead (Walker). Compare the staff (perhaps another symbol of the celestial pole) and the winding serpent to the serpent-wound Gorgon that symbolized the universe with its seven heavens (Chapter 16). Also recall the paragraph on the “snake” (Chapter 4). 104 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 15: Patriarchy Spiritus Gladius Relief of a sword/cross on the pulpit of Trinity Lutheran Church, Enderlin, ND. Spiritus Gladius means “Sword of Spirit,” that is, true eternal life, which depicts well the patriarchal ethic of dying courageously to obtain the real life supposedly found in death. The sword also symbolizes division and separation compared to the cauldron/womb which symbolizes creation of life and inclusiveness. 105 Chapter 16 Mithraism: One Hellenistic Origin of Medieval Patriarchal Philosophy “If we understand salvation to be a divinely bestowed promise of safety in the deepest sense, both during life and after death, then the god...of Mithraic iconography was well suited to perform the role of savior.” David Ulansey, The Origins of the Mithraic Mysteries: Cosmology & Salvation in the Ancient World, 125. “I am not alone; the Father is with me.” Tombstone engraving for Edna Drennen St. Mary’s Cemetery, Bismarck, ND. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– (1) How God/dess is related to the universe. (2) Why the divine father/son relationship usurps the mother/child relationship. –Approaches– (1) God/dess is outside the universe (outside the celestial sphere): (a) And apart from the universe (the conventional view of heaven). (b) And includes the universe as a part of his/er reality (the realm of Glory or the hypercosmic sun that shines through holes in the celestial sphere as stars). (2) The mother who gives birth to the male child is no longer divine. The creator of the child is the father whose unsolicited impregnation takes on mater (flesh) that must be cast off to enter heaven, the realm of pure spirit, which is apart from the world. –Evaluation– Pros: (1) Insofar as ancients thought of the divine realm as encompassing the cosmic sphere, the possibility exists of having a logical wholeness or unity of the universe. (2) The incarnation of the divine in his/er child expresses the truth that divinity cannot be pure spirit any more than any actual moment of creativity can. The really real is a dipolar moment of life (spirit) bringing into actuality new being that contains old beings (matter). This truth is lost on those who bemoan our entrapment in matter. Cons: (1) A God that is apart from the rest of the universe cannot logically be the greatest conceivable reality. (2) The loss of the divine dimension of the Cosmic Female and her creation leaves women with no divine model in whose image they are created. (3) The hatred and disgust of mater has distorted philosophical insight and promotes the evils of misogyny. ****************************************************************************** T arsus, the capital of the province of Cilicia in southeastern Asia Minor, the reputed hometown of the biblical Saul/Paul, was the location of a major Stoic university during the First Century BCE . Paul was probably instrumental in helping reformulate the hard-line ritualism and messianism of the Essene Zealots (see the next Chapter) and their theocratic, nationalistic politics into an other-worldly kingdom inclusive of Gentiles that 106 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 16: Mithraism could survive the Roman Empire’s political dominance and cultural imperialism. A century before Saul was born, the Stoics at Tarsus reformulated their beliefs to account for the shifting of the heavens, known today as the precession of the equinox, and developed a religion whose son-of-god, Perseus/Mithras, born of a mortal woman Danae, did not himself die, like Jesus, but killed the feminine, symbolized by the Gorgons and Taurus the Bull, to make souls safe on their treacherous journey to the outer heavens as far away from Mother Earth as possible. The story of the rise of European Mithraism, as opposed to Persian Mithraism, is a great detective story with many subplots. Though Mithraism outdrew Christianity until the Fourth Century, it eventually succumbed to the even more militant and uncompromising Essenic temperament of the early Christians during the final days of the Roman Empire. Philosophically, Mithraism is interesting because its blatantly anti-female standpoint so obviously stands in the way of achieving a more meaningful concept of divinity as the greatest conceivable reality. It is also a good example of how science, especially astronomy, affects philosophy and religion. The sky is like a huge stained-glass window in nature’s cathedral, telling its drama in the changing patterns of the stars and planets. Of further note is the Mithraic concern for blood. Bathing in bovine blood, killed to imitate Mithras/Perseus’ victory over the forces of the world that hold us captive, was a central Mithraic ritual. Producing, sacrificing and immersing in blood was, also, a central theme in prepatriarchal goddess worship forms. Another patriarchal culture whose gods where very thirsty for blood was the Maya in Central America during the First Millennium CE. They also saw the sky as the divine book of knowledge and home of the gods and goddesses whose hunger could only be satisfied with quantities of blood from genital and other forms of blood-letting sacrifices (see Freidel, Maya Cosmos). Dissatisfied gods are dangerous, but satisfied gods will help us get into their otherworld. Many of the Stoics, philosophers of Greece and Rome during the first centuries BCE and C E , were pantheists, believing, as the Stoic Chrysippus said, that “The kosmos is a living being, rational, with soul-life and mind.” All the heavenly bodies and cosmic forces were personified as divine beings. All things in the universe were seen to be linked together in cosmic sympatheia. This cosmic interconnection fostered a belief that an all-pervading fate determined all events. Stoics also thought the cosmos went through cyclical ages or epochs of thousands of years. At the end of each, the world would be destroyed by a conflagration and then restored as before. This was a common doctrine in the ancient world; for example, Heraclitus said the cycle was 10,800 years. Hipparchus, who discovered the precession of the equinoxes on the island of Rhodes around 100 BCE , said it would be 36,000 years before the sun crosses the celestial equator in the same constellation again. The precession period is actually 25,920 years. The god Perseus, who came to be called Mithras, the mythic quest hero of European Mithraism, was the patron god and founder of the town of Tarsus which took its name from Perseus’ swift tarsos, foot. Perseus was said to be born of Danae, impregnated by the philanderer Zeus who came down the “chimney” of her underground prison into her lap as a golden stream (that is, sunlight, and/or fertilizing urine). Gorgon/Medusa Lion-headed god/dess (Gorgon) symbolic of the universe. The snake divides it into seven parts: the seven planetary spheres. S/he often stands on a globe with an X across it, holding the keys to the gates in the heavenly spheres and a staff representing the celestial pole and all the power one has who controls it. CIMRM 312. Ulansey, OMM, 33 The king, Acrisius, had Danae, his only daughter, put in the cave rather than kill her after a priestess at Delphi told the king that Danae would bear a son who would kill him. Danae with her son Perseus were placed in a chest and put out to sea to drown. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 107 Chapter 16: Mithraism Zeus, however, took pity on them and had a fisherman rescue them who then taught Perseus the humble fisherman’s trade. Beautiful Danae then acquired a human lover, Polydectes, who did not want her son, Perseus, and sought his death. Perseus at their wedding had no gift, being a poor fisherman, so he decided he would fetch Medusa’s head, a feat many had tried, but no one had yet been able to accomplish. Thus begins the typical heroic quest so basic to patriarchal ethics. Medusa was one of the three Gorgon s who stood for the Goddess’ trinity already demonized into winged figures with monstrous heads who turned anyone to stone who looked on them. Polydectes gladly thought this quest would surely be his step-son’s death. With the gods’ help, however, Perseus brought Medusa’s head back and turned the king to stone. Perseus used a hookedbladed dagger and a polished shield given to him by the gods so he need not look at the Gorgon, Medusa. When he killed her, the winged horse, Pegasus, emerged and carried him away from the scene of the crime. Perseus/Mithras is usually depicted wearing a Phrygian hat that makes its wearer invisible, a Santa Claus type hat made of felt with the tip bent over. Perseus is also a constellation in the Milky Way right above Taurus in the polar region and can be at zenith (directly overhead). Perseus’ close connection with the axis of the universe is stated by an ancient author: “Perseus is the winged axis which pierces both poles through the center of the earth and rotates the cosmos.” (Ulansey, OMM, 94). The Stoics apparently opted for having the celestial sphere shift since the Pole was the foundation upon which the whole universe hung. It held the universe together; for it to move was unthinkable. But nothing in the heavens moved, in their astrological mind-set, without a god, a lord, to move it. Since the movement of the “fixed” stars required more power than any of the lords who controlled the spheres below the sphere of the fixed stars, and since each lord was under the control of the lord above him, this new god must be, as they said, the Lord of Lords, the King of Kings. This Lord could demand one’s worship, total worship and submission. Precession Greek Coin with Caps Coin from Sparta with felt caps of Dioscuroi (Santa Claus type caps?) with stars. Ulansey, OMM, 113. News that the fixed stars are not fixed must first have been received by the Stoic astrologers as shocking, but they eventually came to see this knowledge as a new divine revelation reinforcing several important ideas they already held. Only two ways exist to explain the precession: Either the celestial pole is wobbling, or the fixed stars, in their rotation around the earth each day, do not come back to the same spot but move a bit more than one complete revolution. Modern interpretation of the reason for the precession of the equinoxes: As the North Pole rotates around the Pole of the Ecliptic during 25920 years, the two equinox points on the ecliptic move along the equator. Fix, 23. Their present age was the Age of Aries (sheep). This meant the place where the sun crosses from one side of the celestial equator to the other at the spring equinox was in the constellation of Aries. But according to Hipparchus’ discovery, the spring equinox would have been in Taurus a couple 108 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 16: Mithraism thousand years earlier. The bull had been sacrificed on the cosmic cross to bring in the present new age. For millennia in the Near Eastern mythologies, the bull, Taurus, had been said to have been killed by the lion, Leo, because as Leo came to dominate the zenith, Taurus, 90 degrees away, slipped behind the western horizon to his “death.” Also, the Bull is said to die (on the cross) as the sun’s equinoctial crossing precessed out of Taurus and into Aries, symbolized the dawning of a new age. In the sky, directly above Taurus, is the constellation Perseus in the same relative position as the lion in artwork depicting the lion/bull conflict. Perseus, the son of Zeus, by a mortal (virgin ) woman was the natural symbol to kill the bull. He was Tarsus’ city god. He was probably portrayed, locally, in star maps large enough to have his knee on Taurus near the Pleiades. Perseus already had a reputation for killing, since he did away with the Gorgon, Medusa, symbol of the earlier Goddess tradition, and did so by looking away from her as he killed her so her reputed ugliness would not kill him. This is why almost all authentic depictions of the tauroctony (the bull-killing scene) show Perseus/Mithras looking out and away from the bull. Other depictions in the tauroctony include a scorpion, for Scorpio, the place of the fall equinox; a raven, Corvus; a snake, Hydra; a dog, Canis Minor. All these constellations lie on or between the equinoctial points along the ecliptic, the apparent yearly path of the sun through the sky, and below the celestial equator, that is, below Perseus. Only the cup, Crater, is missing. Perhaps this was to keep all the symbols as animals to help conceal their meaning from outsiders. Winged Feet, Lion and Bull Coin from Tarsus showing Perseus with his hooked weapon and winged feet, and the Lion killing the Bull. Ulansey, OMM, 44. Leo at this time was also the location of another major solar event, the summer solstice. The cup may also have been used to symbolize Aquarius, water, location of the winter solstice. Mithras was said to be born at the winter solstice (that is, at Christmas-time) that marks the dominance of darkness, a darkness that gradually gives way to the ever-increasing light of day until the summer solstice marks the height of light and the gradual return to darkness. The tauroctony is usually framed by two torchbearers, one, Cautes, with the torch pointing up, symbolizing the spring equinox, the other, Cautopates, with torch pointing down symbolizing the fall equinox. Their crossed legs symbolize the celestial cross where the sun crosses the celestial equator. Perseus’ dagger enters the bull in the shoulder, the spot in the sky where the Pleiades form a small oval. New wheat, symbol of spring and rebirth, grows from the dagger’s wound. Wheat also replaces the hair at the tip of the bull’s tail. In Mithraic artwork Medusa’s decapitated head, now much like a lion’s head,17 is often given a body, one encircled six times by a snake to form seven body regions (on which the symbols of the seven known planets are placed) signifying the seven cosmic spheres. S/he often holds a key to open the celestial gates while standing on a sphere upon which a cross is drawn. This cross is that formed by the celestial equator and the ecliptic, the main outline of the heavens as Plato says in the Timaeus. This lionheaded god/dess stands for the whole cosmos, for the whole organizing cosmic machinery and power that man is caught in and from which he is seeking an escape. The lion-headed god/dess is Perseus’ worthy opponent. He conquers this god/dess and assumes his/er powers. In the astrologer’s worldview, and especially in the Stoic’s doctrine of sympatheia, activity in the heavens controls our destiny here. This vast power Perseus as the son of the Lord of Lords, if not that Lord himself, is able to control. Anyone with a special connection to this deity is in a very advantageous position when it comes to making sure s/he makes it through the treacherous journey from earth to heaven. Perseus, in star map terms, is in the right place to help man, since he is in the Milky Way, the way to heaven (also the way a latter day sky traveler comes to town according to the 1930’s song, “Santa Claus Is Comin’ To Town”). He is also the “Lord of Genesis,” 18 which means he controls the comings and goings of souls into and out of bodies. The movement from the Stoics’ intellectualastrological formulation of the precession of the equinox to a practicing religion outside of intellectual circles seems to have taken place within the circle of 17Perhaps because even the Bull-slaying Leo is now controlled by the extra-cosmic power of Mithras and his father. 18Other names for this function is “Psychopomp,” a sender of souls, and “Lord of the Flies,” since flies were considered carriers of souls leaving dead bodies. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 109 Chapter 16: Mithraism Cilician pirates who hobnobbed with intellectuals and politicians and were given respectability when they were persuaded by Mithridates IV to become part of the Persian navy to fight the Romans. They would be quick to adopt a belief, (1) that was based on familiar stars and made navigation more accurate, (2) that addressed their vanity by telling them they were important and part of the “in” group sharing a secret few others had, and (3) that was begun under the political rule of the king, Mithridates IV, who claimed to trace his family’s ancestry to Perseus, and who considered the pirates a valuable social force rather than a band of outlaws. To call their religious hero “Mithras” rather than “Perseus” in honor of their king would be a natural move. It would also help preserve the secret knowledge. Tauroctony Tauroctony scene showing a tree with leaves, an upraised torch and a bull’s head indicating the spring equinox; and a tree with fruit, a lowered torch and a scorpion indicating the fall equinox, as do the two figures with crossed legs and torches. Other animals are other constellations between the ecliptic and the equator and the equinox points. CIMRM 335. Ulansey, OMM, 65. Mithras was worshipped in underground sanctuaries, like the place the maiden Danae birthed him after her impregnation by Zeus. These caves probably symbolized the cosmos below the celestial sphere as cathedral domes and arches still do. Mithras is often portrayed emerging from a rock or cave and even from an egg (the cosmos). Upon that rock Mithraism was founded. If the cave from which 110 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 16: Mithraism Mithras emerges is the universe, then Mithras is being portrayed as emerging beyond the visible universe. Mithras/Perseus is called the kosmokrator (ruler of the cosmos), a title often given to the sun. There are images of the sun, Apollo (Helios), kneeling before Mithras, who demands homage from the visible sun of the universe. This explains why Mithras is associated with the major solar events: equinoxes and solstices. But Mithras was also called the “sol invictus,” the “unconquered sun.” There are two “suns.” The unconquered or hypercosmic sun (the sun beyond the cosmos) is the intelligible light of truth and goodness, an idea traceable to Zoroastrianism and Platonism. It came to be seen to be as the power controlling the precession of the equinoxes (Ulansey, MHS). The idea that God is beyond the universe, not in it, or that God is beyond the heavens, not in heaven, is a very important step towards Hartshorne’s panentheistic position in which the cosmos (and heaven) is in God/dess. Most people still define God as residing in some part of the universe, like heaven (or the north pole?), or they place God apart from the universe, or they identify God with the universe––namely, pantheism (and some confusedly assert several of these together). Big Dipper as Shoulder Mithras holding the Bull’s shoulder (Big Dipper) symbol of power over the whole universe as Helios, symbol of power within the visible universe, accepts his secondary position. CIMRM 1430. Ulansey, OMM, 104. By taking a supracosmic view of the cosmos, that is, looking at it from the outside, the cosmos looks like an egg. From this cosmic egg, often entwined with a snake (like the lion-headed god/dess), Phanes, the Orphic god, also emerged. When one looks at the cosmos from this divine, supracosmic point of view an explanation can be given for a very puzzling aspect of the tauroctony: Perseus/Mithras and the Bull are always facing the opposite way from the orientation they have when one looks up at the constellations from the earth. But looked at from the outside, the stellar figures would be oriented as they are in Mithric religious artwork. Mithras would then be looking away from the kill, as did Perseus while killing Medusa, and into the eternal realm of light and truth occupied by his Father, the “unconquered sun” (Ulansey, MHS). Mithraism, which ended up with Roman soldiers bathing in the blood of sacrificed bulls, dominated the religious scene in the later period of the Roman Empire until Christianity and a more symbolic bathing in the blood of the lamb became more popular. Paul (of Tarsus) a hundred years after Mithraism began and in a somewhat different tradition, expressed the belief of cosmic salvation with a cosmic savior: Our homeland is in the heaven, from where we also expect a savior…who will transform our humble bodies so as to resemble his glorious body, by means of the power which he has to subdue the entire universe” (Phil. 3:20-21) “When we were children, we were enslaved to the elemental forces of the cosmos, but when the fullness of time came God sent his son… in order to free [us]. (Gal. 4:3-5) This secret knowledge (gnosis) was guarded and given only to those who proved themselves worthy in the initiation process. Paul later would declare no one is worthy (of heaven), so the Son of God, himself, must die in our place to placate the Lord of Lords so he will let us into heaven. This Son, whom later Christians will claim to be born of a virgin (though Paul and others at the time never claim this), is symbolized as a lamb (the zodiacal species symbol of their present astrological age) and as a shepherd (who brings peace to all creation as did Orpheus), and was sacrificed like Taurus to bring in another New Age, a new heaven and a new earth. Paul’s world could contain no heroes but the Messiah who, he declared, was embodied in Jesus now (back?) in heaven with his Father, the Lord of All, fixing things so we can also get into heaven even though we don’t deserve it. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 111 Chapter 16: Mithraism Chapter Summary We must interpret new information in terms of old. The precession of the equinox could only be understood as the outer, star-studded sphere of the universe being moved by the greatest force conceivable. And in an age where social order was highly hierarchical, goodness could only be seen as obedience to the powers above. The improvement of one’s lot, something unlikely to happen in this life, might happen in the next life, but only if one knew the Power who controlled life and dispensed rewards. For those in the Near East (and elsewhere) during a millennium before and after the time of Christ and Mithras, this greatest power was usually thought to be a male power. Those in the world are too unworthy for this power to deal directly with them. Only someone who could offer a worthy gift could gain access. For a patriarchal potentate the most valued thing is his son who really is the patriarch himself incarnate who would carry on his likeness and values. Both Mithraism and Christianity find the worthy intermediary in God’s son. Both say the reason their hero is concerned with us is his blood-relatedness, his (half) humanity, passed on by the less worthy female side of his parents. Christianity, following the ancient tradition of sacrificing the sacred king, says Christ’s shed blood and death satisfies God’s demand that our short-comings be paid for. Mithras’ father (and other divine relatives) helped him because he was a blood-relative, and they appreciated his ridding the world of the vestiges of matriarchy. Of special note is the ambiguity of God “being in heaven” or out of this world. It could mean God/dess is outside the world by including it, or it could mean God is outside and apart from the world. The latter won out because the thought of having a pure spirit contaminated by mater was unthinkable, despite the saying, quoted by Paul, Acts 17:28, stating that “we live and move and have our being” in God. Suggested Reading: Ulansey; Clark, Selections from Hellenistic Philosophy; Oates, The Stoic and Epicurean Philosophers. ********************************************************************** 112 A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 16: Mithraism Dante's Version of the Cosmos Dante’s depiction of the Ancient World’s Ptolemaic view of the cosmos with heaven apart from mater and hell within, as the womb of mater. Sketch from Dante's The Divine Comedy, ca. 1300 CE. A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 16: Mithraism Sky Map ca. 3000 BCE Some constellations and celestial events important for understanding the Tauroctony. 113 114 Chapter 17 Essenes, Sons of Zadok Another Hellenistic Origin of Medieval Patriarchal Philosophy “We are the [true] spiritual heirs of our founding fathers.” Spokesman for the American Christian Patriot movement, 1995. “All sentences of death are to be carried out by the Gentile authorities.” Dead Sea Scrolls, Zadokite Doc. ix, 1. “No one is to lie with a woman in the city of the sanctuary, thereby defiling the city of the sanctuary with his impurity.” Zadokite Doc. xii, 2. ****************************************************************************** Focus>>• –Issues– (1) Effects of conceiving of the universe and society hierarchically. (2) Purpose of suffering and sacrifice. –Approaches– (1) One is closer to God who is ritually clean and obedient to God and his chosen. (2) Entrance to the kingdom either requires cleanliness and obedience or a compensation paid by a worthy stand-in. Earthly or other-worldly suffering is punishment for failing to be obedient. –Evaluation– Pro: Divinity is seen as the final judge of value. Cons: (1) God is seen as a threat to be placated with sacrifices and obedience, not a loving reality to love. (2) The universe can’t be one unity since it has eternal camps contending with, and external to, each other. (3) Suffering is thought to be deliberately imposed by God. ************************************************************************************ E ver since the discovery of religious documents at Nag Hammadi in Egypt (1945), and especially since the discovery of the scrolls in caves along the Dead Sea (1940s) written two millennia ago, speculation on the origin of Christianity and its influential concepts has accelerated. No consensus has yet been reached, and emotions surrounding the search for the history behind the mythologizing and moralizing run high. Few scholars doubt that a Jewish faction, known as Essenes (likely a Greek translation of an Arabic term meaning “pious”) is somehow influential at the birth of Christianity. One author (see Ellegard), whose thesis runs counter to our cultural mindset, makes a strong case for seeing Christianity as an evolution within the Diaspora Essene Church of God. In his thesis, some members, including Saul/Paul, during the first decades of the Common Era claimed to receive heavenly revelations from their founding hero, the Teacher of Righteousness, who was likely martyred during the Second Century BCE . These visions were taken as evidence that the Teacher had overcome death. The Pauline good news was that their hero, now risen, can also grant immortality to those who believe in his power. Nowhere does Paul, nor any of the of the authors of Biblical and extra-Biblical documents written during the middle of the First Century CE , discuss the A Process Introduction to Philosophy 115 Chapter 17: Essenes earthly life of Jesus. If Jesus lived in the Second Century BCE , they would not know such details. Their interest lay in the spiritual Jesus, believed to be the Messiah/Christ whom the Essenes had long awaited. Whereas Paul’s Messiah (incorporating much of Gnosticism) hailed a heavenly kingdom, the Essene community, generally, awaited a political and military leader to re-establish the glory of King David and the bene, Zadokite lineage of the Temple priesthood. Not until Gnosticism threatened to dominate Christian theology at the beginning of the Second Century CE, did Ireaneas, Bishop of Antioch, lay the groundwork for the earthly Life of Jesus—the model followed by the popular Lives of the Saints in years to follow. Christian Gnosticism claimed the human side of Jesus was not real; that Jesus had existed since the beginning of time, came down to earth in human form and returned to heaven. He wasn’t really human, and didn’t really die. circumcised at puberty, probably because it was a common practice for Egyptians. This act, along with Abraham’s own circumcision, seems to have been a bone of contention between Sarah and Abraham perhaps because Sarah would have seen it as one more patriarchal influence (see Teubal, 39) and a move away from the religion of their homeland.20 Qumran E ssene” was only one of several terms describing the Jewish sect that maintained strong ties to older Jewish ritual law yet adopted some beliefs from the Persians and Greeks. Though some maintained a retreat community in the “wilderness” at Qumran along the Dead Sea, by the beginning of the First Century C E they were also well-represented among the many Jews dispersed throughout the Gentile world. The Essenes, like all Jews, claimed decent from Abraham (immigrants from Babylon) and from Moses (immigrants from Egypt). Another Jewish source, Levites, the ruling priestly class of Israel, may be from a subgroup of Indo-Europeans who moved down from the mountainous region in northwestern Asia Minor in the second millennium BCE bringing with them their militant, pastoral and patriarchal lifestyle to be imposed on the more agricultural and Goddessworshipping people of the coastal plains in the Palestine region. Abraham, probably a cognate with India’s “Brahman,” means “Father Brahm,” the legendary founder of the patriarchal lineage of the Hebrew Semitic tradition. Sarah and Abraham and their tribe moved into the Canaanite region from the Babylonian area. At least one researcher thinks Sarah was a priestess and Abraham her consort. They came from a culture where women were heads of households and circumcision was not performed. Three generations of women went back to their previous homeland to find suitable husbands, perhaps because the men in Canaan were too patriarchally inclined for Sarah, her daughter-in-law and grand-daughter. Abraham’s first son, Ishmael, born of the Egyptian Hagar who was Sarah’s surrogate, 19 was 19Priestesses, and Sarah may have been one according to Teubal, were not expected to have children. If they did become pregnant during the sacred marriage ritual, the Photo: David Harris, from Shanks, Illustration 1. Qumran (upper left) overlooking the Dead Sea. Scrolls were found in caves just right of center. Abraham’s covenant with Elohim (God) was tested again when another son, Isaac, was born (this time "miraculously" to Sarah) who was expected to be sacrificed. God told Abraham he did not need to kill Isaac as a sacri fice because he had demonstrated his obedience; he could worship instead by sacrificing an animal. This may signal the beginning of the break from human (male?) sacrifice and the substitution of animals. However, since Abraham had adopted the artificial genital blood-letting of ritual circumcision 21 at puberty (that echoes the natural life-giving blood of menstruation which begins flowing at female puberty), Sarah may have feared losing Isaac to the new patriarchal covenant signed with male genital blood. Circumcision was practiced in northeastern Africa for several thousand years BCE and by many child was considered God’s son and often sacrificed. See Sarah the Priestess. 20Some outspoken Jewish women today have said the helplessness they feel at the brit milah (circumcision rite) to protect their children is another means to control women. 21Until the Second Century CE , when, some say, Jewish boys had most of their prepuce amputated to discourage them from passing as gentiles, circumcision was likely only the removal of the frenar band or even a pricking or slicing of the skin to draw blood as it was for the Maya, except, of course, where the term means “castration,” a practice Jews apparently did not adopt because they believed God wanted them to respect and keep the body whole. 116 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 17: Essenes Semitic peoples elsewhere (see the ancient relief pictured at the end of this chapter, Ancient Egyptian Circumcision). Joshua says those who had been raised in the wilderness after leaving Egypt had not been circumcised (Joshua 5:2-5). Moses (an Egyptian name) is called a bloody bridegroom by his nonEgyptian, Midianite wife, probably because he had her son circumcised, a ritual common in Africa but foreign to her. Yahweh’s lineage, represented by those born within the anointed Levitical pedigree, were called “sons of god.” The Essenes used a solar/lunar calendar with 52 seven-day weeks in which the Jewish holy days occurred at somewhat different times from those established by the older lunar calendar. They were much concerned with hierarchy and its order of privilege, theirs having sixteen levels of social order with women on the bottom four along with new intact gentile recruits. Lack of purity was mainly tied to sexual activity and failure to follow ritual behavior.22 ––––––––––––o––––––––––– Much of what we know about the beliefs and social structure of the earliest Christians can be found in Essene society, especially so in the more liberal Essenes found throughout the Roman Empire: 1 2 They were called “the saints,” “the brethren,” “the elect,” “they that believe,” “they that are in the Messiah,” “they that are of the Lord,” “the Sons of Light,” “the disciples,” “the poor,” “they that are of the Way,” “Hebraists” and “Nazarenes.” They practiced ritual eating. They had meals in which bread and wine (for the higher ranks) were used to represent the invisible presence of the Messiah. The ritual banquet meal was also expected to be held by God’s emissary when he returned to gather up the saved. Jesus’ followers discussed who would be seated where in line with their belief in hierarchical order. 3 They were baptists. They had ritual bathing, though reportedly not in the nude. Baptism was “for repentance unto remission of sins” and “to fulfill all righteousness.” Baptism and ritual meals may have been a way to compensate for their exclusion from the Temple cult rituals which included, for example, the offering of burnt flesh, a practice some say the Essenes despised. 23 Essenes apparently downplayed the cult of animal sacrifice when they split around 200 BCE with the mainstream Sadducees and Pharisees who dominated the main22In a recent publication of some Dead Sea scroll fragments is a record of a man who was censured because “he loved his bodily emissions” (Eisenman and Wise, The Dead Sea Scrolls Uncovered). 23This is disputed by Eisenman and Wise in light of some Dead Sea fragments they have translated that discuss burnt offerings. stream worshipping practices in the Jerusalem Temple. The early Christians also usually deprecated the Temple priest and were sure it was God’s wrath that destroyed the Temple (with Roman help) in 70 CE.24 4 The Essene life-style was very ascetic. A high ideal was celibacy. Also, most abstained from alcohol, except for its ritual use. If one wanted to marry, one could, but he shall not approach a woman to have sexual relations with her, unless he has reached his maturity of twenty years, so as [to be able] to know good and evil. (Rule of the Congregation, QSa: 10.) Women are not discussed. All marriages were unclean but could be purified with the right rituals. The Nazirite vow of celibacy which all holy ones took (that is, priests and warriors preparing for war) seems to have been extended to others in the congregation, perhaps, as a reaction against the corrupt (from their view) Hellenized priesthood of the Jerusalem Temple. James, (said to be a brother of Jesus after 100 CE ), was a Nazirite. Of the three nets Belial (Satan) uses to entangle and snare mankind––“fornication,” riches and pollution of the sanctuary––it is sex that was the most deadly sin. The Jewish historian Josephus (37-95 CE ) who lived with the Essenes for three years wrote: They reject pleasure as an evil and esteem continence and the conquest over our passions to be a virtue. They neglect wedlock, but choose out others persons’ children, while they are pliable, and fit for learning; and esteem them to be of their children, and form them according to their own manners. (Potter 105) This puritanism was not typical of Rabbinial Judaism, though it was a strong element in the early Christian church. 5 They used an older form of the Pentateuch or Torah, fragments of which have been found in the Qumran Caves. They believed they had the true Law and were rightfully those chosen by Yahweh (Jehovah) to be the priests and kings of the less worthy Jews (like “Christian” vs. “true Christian”). 6 They maintained that they came from an older priestly lineage direct from Aaron (Moses’ brother and leader of the first Yahweh Levitical priests in Palestine) and from the bene Zadok (the first High Priest of Solomon’s Jerusalem Temple 24Again passages from the Dead Sea fragments Eisenman and Wise translated indicate that the Qumran people were not against temple worship as such, but against those who controlled and corrupted, in their minds, the worship there, namely the “evil Zadokites.” God would bring in the new age with a new Jerusalem and temples staffed with “bene Zadokites,”those holding their beliefs. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 117 Chapter 17: Essenes who, supposedly, was never born nor died––Heb. 7:3) to Onias (the High Priest deposed by Antiochus Epiphanes (175-164 BCE ) when he opposed Antiochus’ desecration of the Temple and his Hellenistic influences. Essenes opposed the instituted Jerusalem priesthood which was not in the bene Zadokite lineage but was composed of “evil” Zadokites who they believed were desecrating the Temple. 7 The Essenes believed, as did most Jews, that Yahweh had chosen them for a special mission in the world. From them and their lineage of bene Zadokites, Yahweh would choose the priests for the New Jerusalem. The existing Temple priests, the evil Zadokites, would perish when the New Jerusalem was established by Yahweh's messiah. They believed that Yahweh had made an everlasting covenant with them: He would be their protecting God, but he must be their only God, and they must do what the Covenant (Law) requires. But they were also people of a New Covenant (a New Testament), originally outlined by Jeremiah, that (a) rested on a reaffirmation of their contract with Yahweh and his forgiveness and mercy (if one is contrite), and (b) promised a New Age ushered in by Yahweh’s chosen. For the Essenes it was also a call for reaffirmation of the original lineage and their expectation for a messiah as a Teacher of Righteousness, Yahweh’s Suffering Servant and politico-military leader. For Jewish believers in the Way it meant continuing to live by the Law. Pauline converts, however, were allowed to ignore much of the Law (especially circumcision) in favor of faith in the Messiah’s redemptive self-sacrifice as Yahweh/God’s final act of mercy. 8 Some Essenes maintained some of the tenets of Gnosticism, believing they had special knowledge of the divine plan for salvation, namely, a divine, cosmic and heavenly Redeemer who will come to earth to give men this saving knowledge. More establishment Jews saw the Essene belief in a divine and heavenly Redeemer as a threat to the Jewish doctrine of monotheism. 9 They had messianic hopes: They expected the coming of a Messiah, the Anointed One who would re-establish King David's kingdom and glory. Yahweh would send his Anointed to end the existing world order and start a new one. The Essenes were highly eschatological: When the final days come, evil will be overcome and burned up in a great conflagration. This has ties with Stoicism and other beliefs of that time and is a theme still popular in Christianity. Essenes accepted the prophets’ pronouncements that salvation will come only when Yahweh’s Chosen return to righteousness. God cannot (will not?) save those who do not heed His call to righteousness (faithfulness and obedience). This meant they had to be loving to those of the in-group, but they ought to hate the “evil ones” of the out-group, eliminating them when possible, fol lowing Yahweh’s (the Godof-wrath’s) example when his will is not obeyed. The faithful will be redeemed by God because of their “faith in the Teacher of Righteousness, the true Doctor of the Law”––a doctrine of salvation found in the Dead Sea scroll fragments translated by Eisenman and Wise––foreshadowing the Pauline doctrine of justification by faith, however, most Palestinian Essenes followed James in maintaining faith without works (following the ritual laws) was dead. 10 The Essene community developed a martyr complex. Their group was seen as the Suffering Servant of Yahweh (Isaiah 53) who was to bear witness to Yahweh’s plan (as prophet), atone for men’s waywardness (as priest) and judge the deeds of men in the kingdom to come (as king). A holy house of Israel, a most holy institution of Aaron, . . . to make atonement for the earth, and to decree the condemnation of wickedness that there may be no more perversity. (Dead Sea Scrolls, IQS, 8:10) By the first millennium, the various versions of the Anointed One (or Messiah) which included: (a) the one called the Teacher of Righteousness, (b) the one in the lineage of Moses and the prophets (c) the one in the priestly lineage of Aaron, Zadok and Onias, (d) the one in the lineage of David and the anointed kings of Israel and Judas, (and perhaps others), at times seem to merge into the one Suffering Servant who through his sufferings, and perhaps his death, will bring in the New World Order. This person was to be Prophet, Priest and King in one. 11 The Essenes were fatalistic like the Stoics. The main events in history were believed predestined according to God’s plan. But many of them were militant Zealots, sicarii, who worked as hard as any Calvinistic predestinationist to help God’s preordained plan come out as they wanted it to. 12 Their thought was apocalyptic. They believed they had special secret knowledge (gnosis) revealed only to those to whom Yahweh has entrusted it. This gnosis had to be kept from infidels. Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 17: Essenes Differences between the Essene and the Second Century Jesus Ethic. 1. Essenes were very hierarchically ordered and concerned with behavior appropriate in a hierarchical society. In the Second Century CE synoptic lives of Jesus, Jesus says (also a Greek Cynic aphorism) that the greatest is the servant of all and not above menial tasks (like washing feet). 2. Essenes believed in separation from the polluted, the “sinners.” Jesus is said to have been a friend of “sinners,” for example, tax gatherers and women (perhaps to emphasize his humanity during the Christian fight with Gnosticism). 3. Essenes defined “goodness” as serving God. Jesus said goodness was loving God (though “love” might have meant "obey"). 4. Essenes valued asceticism. Jesus is portrayed as drinking wine and enjoying relationships with women. 5. Essenes were strict about keeping the Sabbath. Jesus (or those speaking for him) said the Sabbath was made for man, not man for the Sabbath. 6. Essenes were preoccupied with ritual and prayer. 7. Essenes strived to give an eye for an eye (justice) and assumed God behaved likewise. Jesus is claimed to have said, “Do not make long prayers, asking God for foolish things. He knows what is good for you better than you do, and needs no prompting to keep him interested. When you pray, try to understand what God wants from you; it is much more important than what you want from God.” (Matt. 6) Jesus said (after a Cynic saying), “Return good for evil; love your enemies. God sends his rain on the evil and on the good alike; be equally impartial. Be perfect as your heavenly Father is perfect” (Luke 5). Love God with your whole being and your neighbor as yourself, a quote from Deuteronomy. 13 They believed war was always inevitable; but not just “against flesh and blood but against principalities, against the powers, against the world-rulers of this darkness, against the spiritual hosts of wickedness in the heavenly places” (Eph. 6:12). 14 They were dualistic, seeing the world fundamentally in opposing terms, Light and Dark, Good and Evil between which there is always war. The people of “God’s lot” are in a struggle with the “Sons of Belial” that will end when the cosmic Sons of Light win the ultimate battle over the “Sons of Darkness.” 15 16 The Essenes looked for a divine appearance. They expected Yahweh or his Messiah to appear visibly and in glory. The Essenes believed in a bodily resurrection. They seem to have some expectations of rising from the dead that went beyond the Jewish belief in an underworld, Sheol. This was likely a bodily or wholistic resurrection, though the resurrection of the soul only does seem to be assumed at times, a popular Hellenistic Gnostic theme where the soul is trapped in the body. 17 They believed in heaven or in celestial salvation. Heaven, or the way to heaven, was thought to be to the north. Their dead at Qumran were buried aligned in an unusual northsouth orientation with their feet to the north, probably so they could see God or the Messiah in his glory as he came to get them from the celestial north pole. The north celestial pole was thought to be the gateway to heaven. 18 The Essenes believed in the millennium. Many thought the end will come after a thousand years of peace, when their calendar supposedly ended at the year 4900 CE. ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––o–––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– 118 A Process Introduction to Philosophy 119 Chapter 17: Essenes Jesus and the Essenes Q uotations from Second Enoch. The moral tone found in Biblical sayings attributed to Jesus can also be found in Second Enoch written between 1 and 50 C E , one of the many scriptural writings known as the Pseudepigrapha composed from just before to just after the time of Jesus and not found in the Biblical canon. Since this document is not generally available, the following selections are provided:25 “Now then, my children, dwell in patience and peace...and every blow...and every evil word ....endure them; and although you may be able to repay with interest, do not retaliate upon your neighbor, since it is the Lord Who recompenses...,” or “When you might have vengeance, do not repay, either your neighbor or your enemy.” (50:2-4) “I saw the key-holders and guardians of the gates of hell standing....” “I saw the keepers of the keys of hell, standing near the very high gates....” 42:1 Cf. Rev. 1:18; 9:1. “Man was made in the image of God : To load with shame the face of man is to load with shame that of the Lord. He who gets angry with a man, without having been wronged, will reap the great anger of the Lord. He who spits in the face of a man will reap disgrace at the great judgment of the Lord.” 44:1-30 Cf. Matt. 5:22. “I [God] said: You [Adam] are earth, and you will go into that same earth from which I took you. I shall not annihilate you, but I shall be able to take you again at the time of My second coming” 32:1 Here God’s appearance is of God himself, not of his emissary, a point made by several authors of Jewish pseudepigrapha who were trying to counter the Essenic and Nazarene (Christian) belief that God sends someone in his place. This is one reason Second Enoch is somewhat different from other Essenic writings. An angel guides Enoch to the “northern side” of the same third heaven in which Paradise is located, and there shows him “a very terrible place” where “all is agony and torment, darkness and mist, “ where “there is no light save a dim fire which keeps flaring up. A fiery stream moves close by...yet cold and ice are there; and in the dungeons angels bearing rude and sharp instruments torture without mercy.” 10:1-3 Cf. Matt. 25. After Enoch records what he has seen in the seven heavens and what the Lord has told him, he is sent back to earth to deliver the books to his children “and they to their children, parents to parents, generation by generation.” 33:9 “Then, in the later history of that race, will come to light the books written by your hand and by your father’s, when the angel-guardians of the earth will show them to men of faith,...and the books will be praised thereafter more than at first.” 35:2,3 And they were discovered nineteen hundred years later. “Blessed is the man who fears the name of the Lord and serves before his face faithfully and regulates his donations by life’s gifts to him: he shall live his life through to the full before he dies.” 42:6 25 From Charles Potter’s out-of-print translation, Did Jesus Write This Book. “Blessed is he who recognizes the works of the Lord and glorifies Him, knowing the Craftsman by His handiwork” 42:14 “Blessed is he who glorifies all the works of the Lord” 52:5 Woe to him who despises one of the Lord’s creatures” 52:6 “Blessed is he who preserves the institutions of the old-time fathers” 52:9 “Woe to him who nullifies the statutes and destroys the landmarks of his ancestors” 52: 10 “Blessed is he who goes out to seek peace and leads others to peace.” 52:11 “Woe to him who discourages the preparers of peace.” 52:12 “This place [Paradise], Enoch, is prepared for the righteous who...give bread to the hungry, cover with their own robe the naked, lift up the fallen, help the wronged, and walk blameless in the sight of the Lord.” 9:1 “Is it that the Lord has need of offering of bread or candles or sheep or cattle? (These are nothing: He desires a pure heart.) But with these He tests the heart of man.” 45:3 “Explain my books to all who ask, that they may be for you a heritage of peace.” 54:1 “At the end of seven thousand years,...a millennium of rest and peace, when years will end....” 33:1-2 “The Lord summoned all the wild and domestic animals of the earth and all the living birds, and brought them before our father Adam...for complete submission and obedience to man. For the Lord created man to be the steward of all his possessions. Therefore there will be no judgment of every living soul, but of man alone. For in the Great Age there will be one place, one fold, one pasture, for all the souls of animals. For the case will not be closed for one animal soul...until the Judgment. But all animal souls will accuse man at the Judgment if poorly fed” 52:2-3 “Whoever feeds poorly the soul of animals is unfair to his own soul.... Whoever does harm to an animal in secret, that is a bad custom: it is a defilement of his own soul.” 59:1,5 “I [God] contrived to make man of a nature which was at the same time material and spiritual, of both death and life, and although resembling in appearance any other creation . . . , yet he alone knows speech. And on the earth I set him like a second angel, noble, great, and glorious. I established him as King of the Earth, having the Kingdom by My Wisdom….I gave him his free will, and I showed him the two roads, the Road of Light and the Road of Darkness, and I said to him: This one is good and that one is evil....” 30:10 “He who commits a murder kills his own soul, and there is no healing for him forever. He who drives a man into a net will be caught in it himself, and he who drives a man into court will not escape his own judgment in Eternity.” 60:2-4 Blessed is he on whose lips are both truth and gentleness. 42:13 “Now then, my children,....abstain from any prejudice against any living soul which the Lord has created. That which a man asks from the Lord for his own soul, let him pray that He do it likewise for every living soul.” 61. In the second heaven Enoch encounters condemned angels dismally weeping who ask him to pray for them. “Who am I, a mere mortal, to intercede for angels!...And who, indeed, is going to pray for me?” 7:5 120 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 17: Essenes J esus. It is hard to say anything about Jesus and Christianity without raising many emotions. We live in an age when we will be learning much more about the historical Jesus and the near Middle East region from 200 BCE to 200 CE . As the First Millennium CE began, the ancient Biblical world was dominated by Roman power, Hellenistic culture and the Herodian family. Rabbinical Judaism was developing as a moderate religious influence and controlled Jerusalem temple worship. These establishment Jews were despised by the Essene Zealot resistance that continued to fight foreign military power and cultural influences. Their resistance occasionally flared up into overt armed revolt. The half-Jewish, half-Gentile (or Arab) Herodian family hegemony who were ruling as Roman puppets, symbolized for the insurrectionists all that was evil. If Jesus lived in the first decades of the first millennium, he was likely raised as an Essene, perhaps even spending time at Qumran to prepare for a life dedicated to Yahweh (and resistance to foreign influences) as did his reputed cousin John the Baptist. "Simon the Zealot" and James, said to be brothers of Jesus (though this is likely meant in the sense of their being of the same Brotherhood), also took the Nazirite vows of dedication and celibacy common to both priests and warriors. Nazareth did not exist at the time of his birth (see Theiring), a confusion arising because of the Nazirite name. If Jesus were active in the first half of the First Century CE , he must have been seen as a leader in the movement to win Jewish political freedom, since crucifixion was the Roman method of executing insurrectionists, whereas stoning to death was the punishment meted out to blasphemers. Ananus, an establishment High Priest, was stoned to death in an uprising by the Zealots with Arab help in 66 C E , likely in response to Ananus' having had James, an Essene High Priest, stoned to death in 62 CE by the establishment Jews. The Essene Zealots considered Ananus and the Establishment Jews to be traitors and appeasers because they were "seekers after smooth things," that is, they sought to get along with the foreign occupiers. Eisenman in James the Brother of Jesus believes one of the Righteous Teachers (a follower in the tradition of the original Teacher of Rightousness) mentioned in the Dead Sea Scrolls is James, and the Wicked Priest, Ananus. Eisenman outlines the infighting between the establishment Jews and the Essenes, especially the sicarii, the right-wing militants who carried concealed daggers (sicae). This fighting became so fierce that Herod Agrippa II called in Roman troupes to suppress it, 70 CE, which eventually led to the Temple destruction by Titus. Into this religious and political turmoil arrives Saul of Tarsus, later known as Paul. If Paul was from Tarsus, he was raised in the city that saw the development of European Mitharism discussed in the previous chapter. In any case, he was a Diaspora Jew and probably a Roman citizen, one related to the Herodians with close ties to those in Caesar's household. Paul's message began with much the Essenes accepted but took a turn they eventually despised when he lobbied for a heavenly Messiah and Kingdom rather than the re-establishment of the Davidic political regime. Paul's Kingdom would also include Gentiles. To the fundamentalist writers of the Dead Sea Scrolls, Paul became the "Spouter of Lies" because Gentiles were the worst source of ritual pollution and must be excluded at all costs. For the conservative Palestinian Essenes, only if non-Jews converted to Judaism and became circumcised, could they be accepted into their society, and even then only as second-class members. In addition, Paul was preaching a blood-and-body-of-Christ communion, common in Greek mystery religions, including Mithraism, which the Essenes considered blasphemous. Paul who had never met Jesus, and never discusses his earthly life, was in a battle with James and Cephas/Peter, who were leaders of the resistance. Much in Paul's writings aims at establishing his authority because of his late arrival to the movement. He claims to have been a Nazirite from the womb, to have had a direct divine revelation (Gal.1) and to have "worked harder than any" (1 Cor. 15:10). That Paul was on fairly even footing with others who venerated the Teacher of Righteousness, indicates that Jesus likely lived some time before the First Century CE. If he had died only a decade before Paul’s vision of the risen Christ, Paul would have had an impossible time establishing his authority in the face of those who lived with Jesus. With Paul, the concept of Jesus as the "Christ," the supernatural savior, begins. Paul supports his rather Gnostic claim using the Dead Sea Scroll writers' favorite technique: exegesis of scriptural texts as illustrating present times and themes. Through all the suffering the Jews sustained at the hands of foreign invaders for centuries, they had come to believe their suffering was both God’s punishment for not being faithful enough and a means of purification to prepare them for a divine mission. This mission would be lead by a messiah, God's chosen. They saw themselves as paying the price for man’s disobedience to Yahweh, a price that must be paid to be accepted into his Kingdom. But Paul not only saw Jesus as the Suffering Servant and Messiah, a personification of the Suffering Remnant and keeper of true Judaism; Paul also sees God’s Servant and Son as having overcome death, a sign that we can all conquer death. Paul interprets Hosea 6, "He has torn [hurt us], that He may heal us; He has stricken [us], and He will bind us up. After two days He will revive us; on the third day He will raise us up, that we may live before Him…" in the singular, rather than the plural "us" claiming this is a prophecy of Jesus' death and resurrection. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 121 Chapter 17: Essenes Paul claims Jesus' resurrection is factual proof that he was from another world, a spiritual world, much more important than the world James and his "circumcision party" (Gal. 2) were fighting to establish. It was also proof that a similar immortality was possible for us if we are worthy. But at the heart of Paul's message is the belief that no one can earn his way into heaven. Only an “act” of faith that maintains Jesus was the scapegoat who suffered and died for us, can make one worthy. Not everyone is saved; only those who believe can enter the Kingdom. The Jamesian/Essene belief in good works became for Paul a mental exercise for the believer––the real “work” having been done by Jesus’ suffering. Paul is particularly wrought over circumcision since it hinders building the Church in the nonJewish areas of Asia Minor where he spent most of his time. Paul goes so far as to say that "every man who receives circumcision…[is] severed from Christ….I have confidence in the Lord you will take no other view than mine….I wish those who unsettle you [James and his ‘circumcision party’] would mutilate themselves!" Gal. 5. Paul never refers to, or uses, the concept of a virgin birth as proof of Jesus' divine origin, a common practice in the ancient world first applied to Jesus in the Second Century CE . Paul establishes Jesus as the risen Messiah by quoting Jewish Scripture. So the question remains: What is known about Jesus independent of Paul's mission? History is, as the saying goes, written by the winners, and Paul's doctrines have definitely survived as the dominate Christian religion, as has Rabbinical Judaism, because neither went head to head with Roman political goals: They gave to Caesar the things that were Casesar's, as the Essenes never would. The Essene Zealots continued to harass Rome until the Second Messianic Jewish Revolt, 132-136, when Bar Kochba, Son of the Star (see Num 24:17 for the Star Prophecy), again without the support of the Rabbis, was defeated. We do know that the Arab regions to the East (that were not dominated by Rome) were at times in league with the Essenes; also the Queen of Sheba from Adiabene (now in Irag) gave them aid during some tough times. Cephas/Peter is said to have done mission work with groups to the East. Given that Muhammand (ca. 570-632 CE ) in founding Islam reached back to Abraham, perhaps it is not too far-fetched to see the energy of the Essenes residing in Muslim Arabs yet today. If so, the threeway internecine battle between Rabbinical Jews, other-worldly Pauline messianists (Christians) and this-worldly Essenic messianists (Islamic Arabs) still plagues the world today, with the United States playing Rome's role as the world's police, and seen by the Arabs as infidels who gave up the true, bene, tradition from Abraham and the belief in a kingdom on earth. Since Jesus did not leave any writings (nor have we any contemporaries’ writings about his life), we cannot know how much the theologized Jesus, as portrayed by Paul and later Gospel writers, is like the historical person. The fact that he is said to be executed for sedition rather than blasphemy, means the gentle person he is often portrayed as, is either a heavy theological overlay (likely influenced by Orphic, Cynic and Mithric beliefs—see Orpheus, page 200), or the Romans were completely hoodwinked, or, what is more likely, Jesus was a figure who lived in an earlier time. –––––––––o–––––––––– A s the Essene/Christian movement gained political power in the following centuries, true believers inherited much of the earth. The unbelievers must suffer forever their rejection of God’s Son. Because God has made clear the truth and shown the way, believers have the right and obligation to spread the truth to others. God’s ends justify any means (see Mack, A Myth of Innocence), including destroying the evil ones along with their goods and lifestyles in holy wars. The apocalypses of the preChristian era were given new life. Christians were operating on a cosmic stage with the help of Christ and his angels against Satan and his legions, human and superhuman. The eschatology of the imminent End and Judgment gave way to the End at some indeterminate future time. But judgment and those eternal “in” and “out” groups, heaven and hell, that war with each other until the end of time, remained and still remain. The power of hating the “evil” forces, was seductive and was justified as a way of loving God. The concept of God’s Anointed had not only become God’s Son but had become God Himself, indistinguishable from the Father; and the Father’s role was seen again to be Lord and Master. The God (once seen as a baby in humble surroundings, symbolizing love and accessibility) died of infanticide under the success of the sword, especially so after Emperor Constantine’s Milan Edict formally recognized Christianity in 313 CE as the state religion. Love is defined as obedience. We “love” our enemies by forcing them to be saved (or, as Islam says, to submit). God loves, but only those who first love (obey) God. But loving a fearsome God is not only hard; it is impossible. Is it any wonder the few Christian images of tenderness are held so dearly, if not overly sentimentally: The lovable baby, the mother and child. B etter Good News. Perhaps, all is not yet lost to the power and the glory. Perhaps fantasies of holy wars and everlasting rewards and pun- 122 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 17: Essenes ishments will give way to another motivation: Love of God/dess. But this cannot happen so long as divinity is conceived as fearsome. Our examination of the meaning of “Unsurpassable” will clarify that fear is an illogical response to an adequate theism. To anticipate the conclusions to come: None are rejected from God/dess’ love. For the Unsurpassable there are no “outs.” All are in. Our salvation does not consist in being rewarded, but in being loved forever. The knowledge one is unconditionally loved is all the reward one could have. Being unconditionally loved gives everlasting meaning to our life even if we do not know it, and when it is understood, it gives us the peace that surpasses understanding. Our failure to love God/dess as we should, is not complete failure to love the Unsurpassable (which is impossible), and it is definitely not God/dess’ failure in any degree to love us. Yet our failures are suffered, if not by us, by others and always by God/dess. Each of us, caught in another’s evil or a tragedy, is a suffering servant of God/dess. And each one who initiates an evil is putting hell in others, and always in God/dess. The notion that the suffering Messiah was divine is the logically correct insight that God/dess suffers more than any reality. God/dess suffers with us. God/dess suffers our suffering when we are suf fering, and suffers our sufferings after we have fortunately lost (forgot) our sufferings. In this way even our sufferings are meaningful, are saved, not just our joys. Everything of everyone is saved, but not everyone enriches the divine eternal life equally. Some are “resurrected” in God/dess tragically, others by their deliberately destructive or evil acts. But all are resurrected or reborn in God/dess’ memory, not some in God (heaven) and some in hell. This message could not be well-formulated in ages dominated by political and religious hierarchies wherein obedience is the meaning of “goodness,” where respect is as close as one could come to loving God and where mercy is as close as God could come to loving us. The message of love could not be formulated until God/dess was clearly seen to include “heaven” (and all of reality), rather than be (localized) in heaven. Time has come to stop the irrational worship of a monopoly of power and glory. As the following chapters try to clarify, only a cosmic lover is rationally and unqualifiedly lovable. Reality is a realm of shared power where powers are used more or less lovingly. Only God/dess can and does use power in unsurpassably loving ways. If feminism’s influence on theology can avoid the temptation to institute the power of glory over the power of nurturing , there may yet come a new age when the intrinsic logic of love is valued over that of the myopic expediency of power. The logic of heaven is found in what it means to use power lovingly, not in what it means to use power. Mankind has long felt that incomprehensible and capricious power is not the ultimate order of things. Perhaps, we say, God deals justly with us. But, on second thought, we hope God is not just, for then we would all suffer since we can never live up to our side of the contract. God is not just, we conclude; God is merciful, giving us more than we deserve, but only if we are thankful or love God for his mercy. God will love us if only we love him. This probably should read: God will have mercy on us only if we obey him. The message of life and love that flickers throughout history is one of a loving God/dess, not a just, nor even a merciful divinity. God/dess, in loving the world, is enjoying and suffering the joys and sorrows of the world, a world experienced not at a distance, but a world closer than a mother is to her unborn child, a child who begins living and moving and having his/er very existence within her and whose arms encircle the suckling infant taking his/er life from hers. This is the unqualifiedly Good News, news that has some very strong reasoning to back it up: God/dess so loves the world, that s/he saves it all, and not by choice, but necessarily. Chapter Summary One might easily see the demand for sacrifice as a patriarchal form of subordination. So much blood is shed in these societies. But though the gender may have changed, the deeper motivation of blood-letting, flesh-eating and dismemberment likely lie in prepatriarchal beliefs: We owe our life to the Goddess’ body and blood, and we should feel obligated to return to her some of our bounty in thanks, and if not in thanks, then in petition that our bad times will get better. Religions in some way or other incorporate this thought as well as interpreting or reflecting what was known of astronomy at the time, like the waxing and waning of the sun and moon and the precession of the equinoxes. Discovering that one’s religion is not unique in much of its motivation and interpretation of reality, and particularly that some of the philosophical assumptions one has used to explain reality are questionable, can be painful. However, if excitement and creativity are valued, rather than obedience and security, these new insights give one a chance to work out more enriching concepts and new depths for ritual. Seeing ourselves as The Chosen, is a dangerous myth (see Mack, Myth of Innocence) . The motivation for good behavior should not stem from fear of being left out, but from love of him/er who must include and love us all. The Essenes’ pain of being rejected from their earthly temple, found solace in a future kingdom A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 17: Essenes of glory where enemies would be excluded. When ultimate reality (metaphysics) is seen as divisive, logic is being violated. Suggested Reading: Fox, The Unauthorized Version; Filoramo; Mack, A Myth of Innocence and The Lost Gospel; Thiering, Jesus and the Riddle of the Dead Sea Scrolls; Shanks, Understanding the Dead Sea Scrolls; Guignebert, Jesus; Legge, Forerunners and Rivals of Christianity. Eisenman, James the Brother of Jesus, and The Dead Sea Scrolls and the First Christians; Ellegard, Alvar. Jesus: One Hundred Years Before Christ. *************************************************************************************** Nicene Creed26 We believe in one God, the father, the almighty, maker of heaven and earth, of all that is, seen and unseen. We believe in one lord, Jesus Christ , the only son of God, eternally begotten of the Father, God from God, light from light, true God from true God, begotten, not made, of one being with the Father. Through him all things were made. For us and for our salvation he came down from heaven; by the power of the Holy Spirit he became incarnate from the virgin Mary, and was made man. For our sake he was crucified under Pontius Pilate; he suffered death and was buried. On the third day he rose again in accordance with the scriptures; he ascended into heaven and is seated at the right hand of the Father. He will come again in glory to judge the living and the dead, and his kingdom will have no end. We believe in the Holy Spirit, the lord, the giver of life, who proceeds from the Father and the Son. With the Father and the Son he is worshipped and glorified. He has spoken through the prophets. We believe in the one holy catholic and apostolic church. We acknowledge one baptism for the forgiveness of sins. We look for the resurrection of the dead, and the life of the world to come. Amen. Apostles’ Creed I believe in God, the Father Almighty, Creator of heaven and earth; and in Jesus Christ, His only son, Our Lord, who was conceived by the Holy Spirit, born of the Virgin Mary, suffered under Pontius Pilate, was crucified, died, and was buried. He descended into hell; the third day He arose again from the dead. He ascended into heaven , sits at the right hand of God, the Father Almighty; from thence He shall come to judge the living and the dead. I believe in the Holy Spirit, the Holy Catholic Church, the communion of saints, the forgiveness of sins, the resurrection of the body, and the life everlasting. Amen. Because The Messiah is often heard in our culture, and because it embodies much of the Essenic/Christian theology that harks back to the sacred kings from the Goddess worshipping cultures, to blood and sacrifice and God’s conditional love and power, and on to the Pauline/Augustinian theory of the Fall and Redemption, I am providing the text: The Text from The Messiah The Glory of the Lord shall be revealed and all flesh shall see it together. Thus saith the Lord, the Lord of Hosts: Yet once a little while, and I will shake the and the earth, the seas and the dry land and all nations. The Lord whom ye seek shall suddenly come to His temple.... But who may abide the day of His coming: and who shall stand when He appeareth: For He is like a refiner’s fire. He shall purify the sons of Levi that they may offer unto the Lord an offering in righteousness. For unto us a Son is given and the government shall be upon his shoulder, and his Name shall be called Wonderful, Counselor, The mighty God, The everlasting Father, The Prince of Peace. Glory to God in the highest and peace on earth good will towards men. Rejoice greatly, O daughter of Zion! Behold, thy king cometh unto thee. He shall feed his flock like a shepherd....Come unto Him, all ye that labor, come unto Him, ye that are heavy laden, and He will give you rest....Take His yoke upon you, and learn of Him, for He is meek and lowly of heart, and ye shall find rest, and ye shall find rest unto your souls. His yoke is easy, His burden is light. Behold the Lamb of God, that taketh away the sins of the world. 26A confession formulated and decreed by the First Council of Nicaea, 325 CE, to separate “true” belief from other Christian beliefs which then became known as heresies. Many of these heresies were forms of Gnosticism. The Creed was expanded at the Council of Chalcedon, 451 CE to the form now in use except for one clause added by a church council, 589 CE. 123 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 17: Essenes His was despised and rejected a man of sorrows and acquainted with Grief. He gave His back to the smiters and His cheeks to them that plucked off the hair: He hid not His face from shame and spitting. Surely He hath borne our griefs, and carried our sorrows. And with His stripes we are healed. All we like sheep have gone astray; we have turned every one to his own way; and the Lord hath laid on Him the iniquity of us all. All they that see Him, laugh Him to scorn; they shoot out their lips and shake their heads saying: 'He trusted in God, let him deliver him, if he delight in him, let him deliver him.' Thy rebuke hath broken His heart; He is full of heaviness. He looked for some to have pity on Him, but there was no man, neither found He any to comfort him. Behold and see if there be any sorrow like unto His sorrow. But Thou didst not leave His soul in hell, nor didst Thou suffer Thy Holy One to see corruption. Lift up your heads, O ye gates, and be ye lift up, ye everlasting doors, and the King of glory shall come in. Who is the King of glory? The Lord of Hosts, He is the Kind of Glory. Let all the angels of God worship Him. The Lord gave the word: great was the company of the preachers. How beautiful are the feet of them that preach the gospel of peace, and bare glad tidings of good things. Their sound has gone out into the all the lands and their words unto the ends of the world. Why do the nations so furiously rage together? And why do the people imagine a vain thing? The kings of the earth rise up and the rulers take counsel together against the Lord against His anointed. Let us break their bonds asunder and cast away their yokes from us. He that dwelleth in heaven shall laugh them to scorn; the Lord shall have them in derision. Thou shalt break them with a rod of iron; Thou shalt dash them in pieces like a potter's vessel. Hallelujah! for the Lord God Omnipotent reigneth. The kingdom of this world is become the Kingdom of our Lord and of His Christ, and He shall reign for ever King of Kings for ever and Lord of Lords. I know that my Redeemer liveth, and that He shall stand at the latter day upon the earth. And though worms destroy this body, yet in my flesh shall I see God. For now is Christ risen from the dead, the first fruits of them that sleep. Since by man came death, [so] by man came also the resurrection of the dead. For as in Adam all die, even so in Christ shall all be made alive. Behold...we shall not all sleep, but we shall all be chang’d in a moment, in the twinkling of an eye, at the last trumpet. The trumpet shall sound and the dead shall be raised incorruptible. For this corruptible must put on incorruption, for this mortal must put on immortality. Death is swallow'd up in victory. O death, where is thy sting? O grave, where is thy victory? The sting of death is sin, and the strength of sin is the law. But thanks be to God who giveth us the victory thro' our Lord Jesus Christ. If God be for us, who can be against us? Who shall lay anything to the charge of God's elect? It is God that justifieth. Who is he that condemneth? It is Christ that died, yea rather, that is risen again, who is at the right hand of God who makes intercession for us. Worthy is the Lamb that was slain, and hath redeemed us to God by His blood, to receive power, and riches, and wisdom, and strength, and honour, and glory, and blessing. Blessing and honour, glory and pow'r be unto Him that sitteth upon the throne, and unto the Lamb forever, glory unto the Lamb. Amen. 124 A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 17: Essenes Ancient Egyptian Circumcision This carving at the Wellcome Institute Library, London, found in the Sakkara Cemetery, Memphis, Egypt, dating to about 2500 BCE., depicts a circumcision ritual; one of the individuals requires restraining which would have been considered a sign of weakness, a failure to be a man. For more information on how genital cutting and philosophical worldviews are related see the history section of the website: BoysToo.com < http://www.boystoo.com/history1.htm> 125 126 PART V Ethics and Psychological Influences Logic of Value Judgments ––––– Two Faiths: Authoritarian versus Democratic Ethics ––––– Gods and Goblins: Our Wounded Child: Psychological Influences on Theistic Concepts 127 Chapter 18 Logic of Value Judgments “To base all actions simply on living for God is ridiculous––nobody can do that without thinking a little about himself.” Student 1990. “Living for God is ridiculous.” Student, 1995. “DID THEY DIE F OR NOTHING?” Bismarck Tribune Headline responding to ‘60’s Defense Secretary, Robert McNamara, who in his 1995 book, In Retrospect: The Tragedy and Lessons of Vietnam, said we had no business in Vietnam. “If only I had known [my work would lead to the atomic bomb], I would have become a watchmaker.” Albert Einstein, who (ironically) believed in determinism, 1955. “…I have learned my lesson well: You can’t please everyone, so you gotta please yourself.” 1950’s Song Garden Party, Rickie Nelson. ****************************************************************************** Focus>>• –Issues– (1) Definition of “value,” “meaning” and “being saved.” (2) Where differences can be made that last. (3) Logical requirements for a value judgment. (4) Proposal for an ultimate standard of value. –Approaches– (1) Being “saved,” having “value” or being “meaningful” means making a difference in wholes, and doing so in some wholes forever. (2) Differences can be made in: (a) Myself, (b) Others, and/or (c) God/dess. (2) Value judgments require a premise that defines the meaning (standard) of “value” and a factual situation being evaluated by the standard. (3) Loving a loving God/dess (conceived as including all reality) is the ultimate (positive) purpose or value. –Evaluation– Pro: God/dess (conceived as all-inclusive) is the only logical possibility to evaluate and retain all values forever. Cons: (1) Egoism, saving one’s own past, isn’t a logical possibility if Whitehead’s analysis of a person as a series of momentary egos is correct. (2) Humanism, others saving us, can only be a theory of partial retention; and a theory of saving that can’t be everlasting. ****************************************************************************** M eaning of Meaning. Among the “big questions” philosophers are known for asking is, What is the meaning of life? This completely general question is not the same as the more restrictive one, What should I do with my life? We are always searching for the purpose or reason for doing what we do. But particular purposes and meanings have meaning only as examples of what it 128 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 18: Value means in general to be meaningful. Is there a most general meaning? Is there a meaning so basic or general no other meaning can be conceived to be more fundamental? Understanding what it means to be meaningful, requires understanding the characteristics all meanings exhibit. This may sound as if one is looking for what makes meaningful things different from those that are not meaningful. But what if meaning is a necessary characteristic? What if everything must be meaningful? If so, then any attempt to refer to something as having no meaning would be self-contradictory. If meaningfulness is necessary, then the meaning of “meaning” is not something decided nor created, not even by divinity. Discovering the basic meaning of life, would be discovering how reality has always been and must always be. Of course, the positivistic or relativistic response is that there is nothing about reality and the meaning of life that does not have an alternative, but then, as we have seen (Chapter 3), having alternatives does not have an alternative, so this position is self-contradictory. Anything common to two, much less all conceivable acts, is an abstraction. So ultimate purpose must be completely abstract, which is another way of saying it is necessary. Necessities have never been created, and can never be changed. Further, we all know, more or less clearly, what we do is only meaningful if we change something; we are meaningful only if we make a difference. If what we do gets undone, if we rake up leaves and the wind blows them around again, we say what we did had no purpose; it was meaningless. So making a difference somehow to something is necessary as one condition for being meaningful. One must make a lasting difference to be meaningful We do A to affect B, and B to affect C, and so on. We easily conclude the purpose for which everything is done is the last thing done. Most people envision a final end to reality (just as most try to conceive a first moment of reality), as the most logical way to explain what the purpose of everything is. But we have seen in studying the meaning of “change” that everything done or created by a process of coming-to-be must contribute to some superseding process(es) or other forever, so the attempt to conceive of a last thing done that sums up the differences (meanings) of everything, is highly problematic. We also saw how change is always an evolutionary process of growth around what has been done before. Nothing can change the past, so one cannot be meaningful by making a difference to the past despite the many fantasies of time travel. The definition of “meaning” is abstract, but all meanings (differences) are concrete. All differences are made within a present coming-to-be. The new creations of the present, which contain all or part of the past, “change” future comings-to-be by requiring them to conform to what was created in earlier processes. So the question of meaning is two-sided, concerned with: (1) What “value” means, that is, what the abstract meaning or characteristic is that everything exhibits, and (2) Where value is placed, that is, where the differences are made. ”Value” refers to the difference something makes. Everything not only makes a difference; each and everything must make differences. Being meaningful is not a contingent characteristic of reality. Everything must make a difference somewhere and forever. That everything makes a difference is a changeless and ultimate characteristic of reality. This is the general meaning of having a value, whether the value or difference made be positive or negative. The actual differences made cannot be necessary or unavoidable, at least in detail. All things done are contingent. Ethics is meaningless if one must do what one does. But it is necessary that everything that happens makes a differences somewhere or other. The difference between positive and negative value has usually been attempted in two ways: (1) By an appeal to direct experience, or (2) By an appeal to an authority, usually God or backed up by God. In both cases, however, the end result is not all that different. Positive value is always said to be pleasant, enrich ing and productive of further pleasantness. Philosophers differ, however, when it comes to asserting whose experience is to be enriched. The contribution or difference made must last or what was meaningful, no longer is. Since to say something was meaningful, but no longer is, is selfcontradictory, logic forces us to conclude differences must be made forever. If all contrasts of differences have always been as they are, and will always be as they are (or if Reality contains no contrasts), then nothing changes––and we can make no changes––so life is meaningless. This result always follows from a block view of reality like Parmenides’. But also notice, if the meaning of all we do were to reside in a last thing done, and the last thing done does nothing, makes no difference to anything, then the last thing done is meaningless. Contributing to something that is meaningless is not to be meaningful. The following chart points out some of the general characteristics of value which really are aesthetic cannons. Change and the Unsurpassable 129 Chapter 18: Value Dimensions of Value Value : the difference parts make in wholes that include them. Wholes are not static but are creative unifications of diversity that are (1) experiencing or valuating the variety presented to them. Each whole creates only one result. The value of this created result lies in (2) how it influences other wholes which include its created result as a part. Enrichment: positive value. Enrichment refers to feelings in an experience. Every experience is a feeling of the past and an anticipation of how the past will affect the future. Each moment is new or different as a unifying whole, but also somewhat old or the same, because the parts being unified and added to are not created by the present moment. They existed before, and are, therefore, more or less old. Unity and Diversity: requirements for enrichment. Contrasts must be strong and mutually reinforcing. A unity must arise from mutually reinforced diversity; not from homogeneity. The opposite of enriched experience is an experience that is either (1) trivial (feelings lacking depth or variety), or (2) painfully chaotic (strong, but clashing, feelings), or (3) boring (feelings of trivial variety and too much repetition contrasted with possible, but unfulfilled enrichments). Depth: strength, more of the same, that is, spatial/temporal repetition of some characteristic. Many similar things experienced simultaneously by means of the same characteristic results in the strength of spatial size. A characteristic repeated or maintained sequentially (maintenance is repetition since nothing lasts unless it is repeated in a new present moment) results in the strength of temporal endurance. When anticipations are nearly always fulfilled, enrichment is diminished due to boredom. Variety: new spatial/temporal characteristics. When one experiences many different items simultaneously, spatial variety is established. When each new moment experiences little of what was experienced before, temporal variety is achieved. When anticipations are seldom fulfilled, enrichment is diminished due to chaos. Rhythm: the middle ground to enrichment. It allows strength through repetition, interspersed with novelty to avoid boredom. Rhythm allows novelty, but not the chaos of too much novelty. Examples of characteristics that can be varied: Size, Line, Shape, Texture, Light Value, Color Hue, Color Saturation, Pitch, Volume, Timbre, Smells, Tastes, Direction, Point of View, Focus, Speed, Symmetry, Weight, Symbolism, Representationalism, Abstractness, and Gender. Where might differences be made? Three places come to mind: Me, Others and Divinity. These three give rise to three labels used to describe ethical systems: (1) Egoism, (2) Humanism (and more broadly, Environmentalism), and some form of (3) Theism. Though contributions may be made to more than one of these locations at the same time, one can still try to specify which location is the final purpose for the differences made. In religious language, this comes down to where, and how, one is “saved.” If the ultimate place of meaning is in oneself, then one must justify what one does in light of the long-term results to oneself. This does not imply that Egoism must in practice be a selfish ethic. Being kind to others or doing what God supposedly wants, may be the best for one’s own enrichment, if not now, then in some future state of affairs. The logical question this theory must address is whether or not contributing to one’s self is even a possibility. And if so, for how long? We do seem to die, and if, when we are dead, we can no longer retain the differences we made to ourselves, Egoism, as a theory of ultimate meaning, would be questionable. 130 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 18: Value Differences can be made to/in: (1) Oneself (2) Others (3) Divinity (if meaningful). Finding one’s salvation or meaning in the larger social context has become a common attempted solution to Egoism’s failure. In a theory of social salvation, our life is still meaningful when we die because others continue to be affected by what we did. But there are still some serious problems having others be the meaning of our life: (1) No one seems to be changed by what I really am: All the feelings and thoughts I have are not at all, or only partially, transmitted to others. (2) What does get into others seems to be so watered down and forgotten, I would eventually become meaningless. (3) The group, whether it be humans or the larger natural environment, will eventually die or disappear as it is. No group or particular form of the world is forever. Social salvation always depends on some kind of ark to get meaning passed on through times of group disaster. God, in the mind of many, is a reality that cannot be affected or changed by us. God is often thought to be changeless. If God cannot be affected by us, he cannot be the measure of the meaning of our lives. Most people who think about this problem come back to the individual ego as the only place where all the intimacy of one’s being resides. In order to satisfy the logic of meaning, the ego cannot die. The ego, namely, that “stuff” which is supposedly the same “stuff” from moment to moment and continues to be even after we physically die, is usually called a “soul.” The soul is supposedly a person, the same person from moment to moment. It is affected by the experiences one has during life and is able to retain those values despite death of the body. But is this a rational or meaningful idea? If the analysis of change has been right, then the substantial creative moment, the “soul” of the moment, ceases when its coming-to-be has come to be. All egos are momentary, according to the Sautrantika Buddhists and Whitehead. Even though these Buddhists seem to deny one moment contributes to another as Whitehead affirms, still they would agree with Whitehead that a moment cannot contribute to itself. The present ego, according to Whitehead, can only be affected by the past, that is, the accomplishments of previous “souls.” The Buddhists seem to say there is no real cause at all affecting the present. Egoism, in the Whiteheadian theory, can only be defined as concern to further the interest of one personal (lineal) society, as opposed to considering the values of other societies. A person is really a lineal society, each member inheriting its dominant influence from its immediate predecessor in the series. Egoism has the additional logical problem of forgetfulness. Much of the value of the past seems to be lost. We forget much of what we ourselves have done. Many believe it is still around in some unconscious form. But the reality of our past as we experienced it does not seem to be saved. And, further, for egoism to succeed as an ethic, one must believe what no experience has established: We do not die. The belief in everlasting life is a rational argument that Plato and many others have put forward. I think the rea sons advanced for everlasting life are correct: Life is meaningless if the differences one makes do not last forever. I am not convinced, however, that one’s ego (as a “soul” or a never-ending series of “souls”) can be the place which stores those differences forever, even though we each store our life in part as long as we exist. But an ego that is the same stuff or whole from moment to moment and yet is different because of its internal changes from moment to moment, is the attempt to conceive of a self-contraction, as Parmenides correctly noted. The problems can be resolved if divinity (the divine series) is capable of change, if divinity can and must retain forever all the differences anything makes. This would not satisfy the egoist who enjoys thinking s/he has the divine attribute of everlasting life, but it would solve the logical problems raised by the meaning of meaning. Whether or not a cosmically inclusive and neverending life (series of creations) makes sense will be discussed further in Chapters 21-23. The following quotation from a student clearly states what many believe: A Student’s Defense of Egoism Why can’t egoism be justified: To me, life is not a team sport. People must base their actions on how it will affect them in the future. To base all actions simply on living for God is ridiculous––nobody can do that without thinking a little about himself. For example, if you love God all your life and end up going to hell anyway, wouldn’t you think you were cheated out of Heaven––after all, that is egoism. I believe everyone, deep down, is egoistic. (1990) Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 18: Value Value Flow Chart 131 Change and the Unsurpassable 132 Chapter 18: Value V alue Judgments. The logical requirements for making a judgment about the value of an actual or possible situation are those of a syllogism. 27 One of the syllogism’s premises must be a principle of value which cannot be derived or substantiated by factual evidence. It must be established by reason (some say by authority). The other premise must be a statement of fact, a statement of how things actually are. The deduced conclusion asserts that the fact does or does not exhibit the value. All facts are evaluated within the context of a whole that contains them. A fact in isolation from the evaluating context can never be known to be good or bad, ugly or beautiful. Both concrete fact and abstract meaning of “value” are required for an evaluation. The abstract definition of “value” in itself says nothing about the actual world. Only when both are present can a judgment be made: Only when one knows what it means in general to be good or bad, and one also knows the facts of a particular situation, can one assert the particular situation exhibits good or bad value. We seldom, if ever, make actual judgments using the ultimate value principle as a premise, but the justification and evaluation of any value less than ultimate is in terms of its ability to fulfill the ultimate purpose. Ultimate purpose cannot be found in a final state of affairs. It is a characteristic exhibited by all states of affairs. It is a logical “end” (a necessity), not a temporal end. One proposal for the ultimate value is to unqualifiedly love God/dess. Depending on what this means, it can be seen as an egocentric or theocentric ethical foundation (see the following chart). If we love God/dess, that is, obey God/dess, because we want to avoid punishment or gain pleasure for ourselves while we are alive or after “death,” we are still functioning with an egocentric ethic. But perhaps it is possible to love God/dess by trying to make life enriching for his/er cosmic life. When we really love someone, we either do things for them they think will be enriching for themselves or that we think will be enriching for them. Deity, if meaningful, cannot be mistaken about what is enriching, though we, not knowing all there is to know, may be mistaken about what we should do to enrich the loved one. We may also have grounds for knowing God/dess is an unsurpassable lover, and not just a reality to be loved (as was Aristotle’s Unmoved 27A syllogism is an argument using two premises to reach a conclusion. See entry in Glossary. Mover, the great Unloving Beloved). If so, then we know God/dess can never threaten us, punish us or cause us mental or physical pain. Every pain or pleasure we feel, God/dess would feel, as an omniscient, all-loving reality must. To love all is not something God/dess could choose or s/he would not necessarily be omniscient or all-loving. More on theistic attributes in following chapters. At the core of philosophical problems is our inability to know for sure that we know. This is certainly the case when it comes to knowing what the meaning of “value” is and whether one is making correct judgments. Even the meaning of “knowledge” depends on what one assumes the universe is like, that is, what is metaphysically true. The assumptions argued for here are those generally called “process metaphysic,” and more specifically those inspired by Whitehead and Hartshorne. Some metaphysical insights must be knowable since the attempted anti-metaphysical statement that we can always be wrong is selfcontradictory. Reason tells us that we must make a difference, that is, have value. Experience shows whether it was a pleasant or unpleasant value, that is, h o w the difference is made. A whole that has inadequate understanding of the meaning of value or incomplete factual information may make a judgment of value that is good for it now, but only a Whole that unmistakably knows what good value means (that is, what enriches the Whole) and has all the facts (as only the cosmic Whole can), can say that what s/he takes to be valuable or good, is unqualifiedly good. Good for the all-inclusive Whole is good. Good for a whole less than all-inclusive can be bad if it is not also good for that which measures all value. Fortunately, most often what is good for a part of the Whole is also good (for the Whole). Value is determined by the difference a part makes in a whole. The value one has is the difference one makes in the present all-inclusive, but one’s value must also last or continue to make a difference in the presents of future moments or one is valueless or meaningless. All wholes (values) are contingent selections. But all concrete values, even those of the allinclusive Wholes’, are simultaneously incompatible with other possible concrete values, that is, every value excludes other possible values at the same time. Time is the way by which simultaneously incompatible values can be actualized, that is, successively. Possible values are endless, as is time. Change and the Unsurpassable 133 Chapter 18: Value Love God/dess Unconditionally How? By obeying God/dess Why? To please God/dess. How? versus versus Why? To avoid punishment and gain rewards for myself everlastingly. versus To enrich God/dess. To increase joy and minimize suffering for the One everlasting life. How? versus Where? In myself and others as they affect my welfare. Why? Why? How? By following old patterns ––not risking something new. By enjoying God/dess and God/dess enjoying us. By creating new positive feelings––risking failure to make new joys. Where? versus Why? In God/dess (and neighbors and myself as felt by God/dess as part of his/er own reality). Why? Concern for myself now and how I will be in my life (in heaven or hell) forever. versus Concern for God/dess now and how I and others will be in God/dess’ life forever. Egocentric ethic. versus Theocentric ethic. Ultimately, the parts of each all-inclusive Whole, as well as the Whole itself, must make a difference to a new Whole with a new value judgment that includes the values of the old Wholes plus all newly created values inherited from others. So ideally, value is always a judgment (or evaluation) of what one has done for the present allinclusive Whole simultaneously compared to, (1) the complete history of the universe, and (2) the anticipations of how one might affect the future. Even though only the Whole which is experiencing all the actual contrasts as unified is capable of evaluating the concrete world without error, still there are some universal characteristics which both the all-inclusive Whole and all restrictive wholes must exhibit (see the chart above, Dimensions of Value). These necessities have never been created, but have always been, as have all necessities. They are not contingent, but define a characteristic always exhibited by the primordial and everlasting Series of all-inclusive, unsurpassable, concrete Wholes. Since all wholes, small and great, exhibit the same principle of value (namely, what it means to be a “whole”), the meaning of “good” (which is the most value possible for the all-inclusive Whole) is also exhibited by all less than all-inclusive wholes and so is knowable by all wholes, or is at least is not intrinsically unknowable. Since each all-inclusive Whole of the cosmic series must include our experience, we must be able know something of the concrete content of value as well as the abstract meaning of value. Since the meaning of “good” is knowable, and since some of the facts are knowable, making well-founded judgments of good and bad about actual or possible situations is possible. 134 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 18: Value But for us who are not all-inclusive, error is also possible in respect to both the ultimate meaning of “value” and to the facts. So a measure of humility and openness to others along with the willingness to teach the best one knows is the only practical way to assure maximizing positive value. Chapter Summary Moral judgments require knowledge of what “value” means and knowledge of the situation being evaluated. Facts cannot define “value,” and the meaning of “value” points to no particular facts. Only experience can discover the facts, and only conceptual analysis (some might say revelation) can disclose the universal meaning of “value.” To be meaningful one must make a factual difference. One must condition future facts so as to partly determine their outcomes. To remain meaningful, what one does must always be conditioning some creation or other. Egoism maintains I will always be influenced by my acts, so my death cannot be real. Altruism or environmentalism maintains others in the world will always be changed by my actions and thoughts. It is questionable any individual or society has the flexibility to survive forever having new experiences, or even the ability to be influenced by the full reality that one is. Hartshorne agrees that our actions affect ourselves and others as long as we exist, but they also affect the all-inclusive reality, a reality that is infinitely flexible and cannot die. Living for God/dess is seldom a sacrifice of one’s self, since one can only give to a lover something to love if one’s self is enriched. Sacrifice of oneself is only justified when such a loss gives to others and the Whole more potential for enrichment than the loss of oneself. Enrichment requires diversity, but also depth or strength that comes from repetition. To live a good life, one must attempt to avoid both extremes of chaos and trivialization. Suggested Reading: Hartshorne, The Philosophy and Psychology of Sensation and Creative Synthesis & Philosophic Method; Plato, Euthyphro; Voskuil, “Ethical Meaning’s Theistic Implications,” and “The Logic of Death;” Navia; Frankl (but notice that he confuses the general meaning of “value,” which can be ultimate, with specific goals, that can never be ultimate). Orphic Cross A Third Century CE rock seal with an image of Orpheus/Bacchus. This cross is likely a preChristian symbol . Christianity adopted the cross as a symbol in the Sixth Century CE . according to Walker, WEMS. Fix, 223. 135 Chapter 19 Two Faiths Authoritarian versus Democratic Ethic “Hence arises that principle on which we have all along insisted, that there is nothing more wholesome in the Catholic Church than using authority before argument….We are required to despise all sensible things, and to love God alone.” On the Morals of the Catholic Church, Saint Augustine. “The utilitarian standard…is not the agent’s own greatest happiness, but the greatest amount of happiness altogether,…[that is,] the collective interests of mankind,…the interest of the whole.” The Ethics of Utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill. “‘Morality of outlook is inseparably conjoined with generality of outlook. The antithesis between the general good and the individual interest can be abolished only when the individual is such that its interest is the general good, thus exemplifying the loss of the minor intensities in order to find them again with finer composition in a wider sweep of interest.” Process and Reality. “[T]he major advances in civilization are processes which all but wreck the societies in which they occur.” Symbolism, Alfred North Whitehead. ********************************************************************* Focus>>• –Issues– (1) Comparing the logical insights and failings of authoritarian and democratic ethical systems in both their social and theistic dimensions. (2) How to act given our ignorance of the complete circumstances in which we find ourselves and our inadequate grasp of the ultimate meaning of value. –Approaches– (1) Authoritarian (autocratic): One point of view weighs the worth of all others in light of its own interest. (2) Democratic (utilitarian): Everyone’s interest is valued insofar as it increases the group’s total happiness. (3) Hartshorne/Whitehead: Each interest is valued for itself and its contribution to a Whole which includes every interest as part of its interest. –Evaluation– Pros: (1) The authoritarian view is right insofar as it recognizes the need for one standard and one whole to weigh the merits of everyone. (2) The democratic view is right insofar as it recognizes the need for everyone to have his/er own worth that is justified only insofar as it contributes positively to a totality of value (happiness). (3) Hartshorne’s view combines the best of both by positing a whole that contains what is being evaluated as parts of itself. Each part has its own worth, yet its merit (relative to others) is determined by how it contributes to the whole it, and everything else, is in. Cons: (1) The authoritarian evaluator is apart from those being evaluated. There is no way for such a judge to know for sure exactly what is being evaluated, so the judgment may not be appropriate. (2) The utilitarian’s totality of value (the greatest happiness) resides nowhere. No member of a group can grasp all the members of the group, and so no one has all the information required to evaluate the relative merits of the members of the group, so no one actually has the greatest happiness. An 136 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 19: Two Faiths abstract collection of happinesses is not the same as a concrete, happy whole that contains the collection of happinesses as parts of its one happiness. ************************************************************************* D ivine commission. Recall from the previous chapter that a value judgment requires both knowledge of a general principle of value and knowledge of the facts being weighed by the principle. Ideally, the principle will be applicable to any possible fact and, thereby, be metaphysically true. This would place the basis for ethical judgments beyond relativism even though its application to particular situations could still be uncertain. Insofar as either the principle or the facts are not known, the evaluation is in doubt. Yet life does not wait for us to be absolutely certain about what it means to be good or bad, nor does it allow us to marshal all the facts before we must act. It is disconcerting, if not agonizing, not to be sure we are doing the right thing, so we seek ways to be reassured we know what is right. If one feels his/er knowledge is inadequate, s/he may find assurance by accepting what an authority says is valuable. Often one’s acceptance of an authority is based on fear the authority will make one suffer if s/he does not agree. A parent may respond to a child who asks why s/he should act in a certain way by threatening, “Because I told you so.” In some theistic contexts this comes down to saying something is good or bad because God told us so: Believe it, and do it or go to hell. In this authoritarian approach, only the autocrat knows what the meaning of good and bad is, because the meaning is dependent or contingent on the will of the autocrat and is knowable only if he decides to disclose or reveal it. A special “in” group usually claims God has revealed true knowledge to them, and further that they have been commissioned by him to dispense and guard its truth. They often claim the exclusive right to tell others what to do or believe and to protect those who do believe from those who don’t; even by the use of force if necessary. The meaning of “value” in this case is not an unavoidable necessity of reality because it is not unconditionally rational. It is nonrational (if not irrational) because it is decided by the authority and could have been decided otherwise H umanism. On the other hand, the essence of the democratic approach lies in the belief that the meaning of “value” is accessible to all. It may not be easy to discover, but it is discoverable because the principle is a necessity exhibited by all possible actualities. Necessities (unlike nonrational statements) are never created but have always been and always will be exhibited by every actuality. They are, therefore, available to be discovered by anyone with sufficient insight. The ancient Greeks argued over who to include in their democracy (polis), just as we do today. They assumed some groups knew more or better than others and had more right to be among those deciding what all should do. But since not all the members of any group will agree all the time, the members of a democracy must agree to compromise when they disagree. But the Greeks assumed any compromise must be somewhat wrong and, therefore, not as good a decision as the right decision would be if one could know what it is. Therefore, Socrates, and especially Plato, argued against establishing a democratic social order. They maintained only those who know for sure should rule. The common people (hoi poloi) are a flock to be lead by a shepherd king who must also be a philosopher since, of course, only philosophers can know the truth. Utilitarianism appeals to everyone’s immediate experience of enrichment or suffering to determine what is good or bad, rather than to some special knowledge held by a privileged individual or autocratic group. Whether the positive or negative value which the individual experiences is unqualifiedly good, however, depends on its relationships with all the other experiences of the group’s members. What is defined as unqualifiedly “good” is “the greatest amount of happiness altogether,” not just any one individual’s happiness. But where is this totality of happiness? It does not reside in any member of the group, nor can it reside in an abstract collective since abstractions have no feelings. Only concrete unities have feelings. Neither is an abstract collective anything to which one can contribute to a difference. The greatest happiness, in other words, must be an actual experience of happiness, not an abstract mathematical sum. It must be a whole, not a collective. John Stuart Mill (1806-1873), the famous utilitarian quoted above at the beginning of this chapter, is confused on this point since he uses the terms “whole” and “collection” interchangeably. K nowledge required for judgment. So in practice, we either believe a special individual or small group (a priesthood) has a divine commission (a unique relationship to the divinely based meaning of value), or we believe reason can find the principle upon which we make value judgments. But to make correct judgments also requires knowledge of what the facts are. How is it possible to obtain this information? Knowing the actual concrete facts is only possible if: (1) the facts are tran smitted or carried by other people, cells, chemicals, and so on, to the whole supposedly knowing the facts. But what one takes to be the facts (known by way of transmission) may not be A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 19: Two Faiths the case because: a. the transmission of the facts to the one who is making the judgment may be faulty or b. the total factual situation may not be transmitted, or (2) the facts are known (included) immediately as they are within a Whole with no mediated transmission nor selection. Concrete facts can be fully known if they are included in such a whole because: a. no inference need be made that is susceptible to error, and b. an all-inclusive Whole would contain all the facts and their relationships. So if cosmic Wholes make sense, one’s value is always a combination of what one has done for the present all-inclusive Whole simultaneously compared to the complete history of the universe, and to anticipations of how one might affect the future. All wholes exhibit the same principle of value, namely, what it means to be a “whole,” that is, to feel the positive and negative aesthetic worth of its parts and to anticipate a new goal to be achieved which will contribute to superseding wholes forever. But for us who are a series of wholes, but not all-inclusive Wholes, error is also possible in respect to both the principle and the facts. Thus a large measure of humility and openness to others, along with the willingness to teach the best one knows, is the only way to assure maximizing positive value in an actual social context. The agony of being human and having to live with uncertainty because we are not all-knowing, is what every “faith” tries to soothe––be this a faith in the ultimacy of science and its methodology, or the faith that one’s religion has cut the knot of radical fallibility and given one indubitable truths by way of revelation. These faiths are often held to be so true and important one is justified removing other’s opportunities for alternatives since all other thoughts would only be falsehoods. Even killing those in error has been rationalized to prevent the cancerous spread of heresies. Convert or die: Better dead than a heathen infidel. Better dead than red. Better dead than…. The following outline makes more succinct how these two contending views of social and cosmic order differ. Life is always a mix of these two faiths. Only when they conflict do we discover which is more important to us or what is lacking in one. These can be times of hard moral introspection. A democracy has principles common to all members of the group. The group enlarges as moral sensitivity increases as Whitehead noted above in the opening quote to this chapter, so “common” means “applying to all” as a common denominator, rather than “vulgar” or “not of the privileged,” the meaning used in an autocratic environment to label the lower or “out” class. The other faith is called “autocratic” from the Greek meaning “self-empowered” or “authoritarian.” Not everyone is self-directed. Only the one who controls, directs or informs everyone else is so empowered. No one has any power but that received from the authority. The autocrat’s decisions are not up for review nor require any justification by any standard outside his own will. Religions still debate whether we even have the power (the free will) to decide to accept or reject God’s authority or grace. Most of us are sympathetic to the democratic ideals because our political system tries to embody many of them. Yet most religious traditions are deeply indebted to the autocratic ideal. However, both have logical problems. Two Faiths Autocratic Assumptions: The Kingdom Democratic Assumptions: The Polis 1. One could exist alone. 1. Life is unavoidably social. 2. The universe makes sense, but only those with special or revealed knowledge know what it is. The order of the universe (or society) stems from the autocrat’s will, not from any intrinsic rational necessity. 2. The universe can make sense; it is not intrinsically unknowable. 137 138 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 19: Two Faiths 3. Discussion in an open forum is a waste of time at best. It is the wrong approach to deciding issues because common folk are not capable of deciding what is best for them: They cannot understand the special knowledge. Discussion of authority’s pronouncements implies one doubts the authority’s correctness. 3. Agreement is possible through discussion in an open forum. 4. Cliquish, divisive (“ins” versus “outs,” heaven/hell, rich/poor). The “ins,” the special or autocratic group, are better than common folk who can do nothing to deserve to be part of the in or “saved” group. The commoners can get in only: (a) if they are considered a curiosity by the privileged 4. Accepting of others. (b) if they agree to do and to believe everything the authoritative, that is, the better, group says, or (c) if one of the ins is magnanimous enough to fix it for those wanting to get in by giving them special access. Who one knows, not what one knows or does, is what counts. 5. There is always agreement with the authority. Those who would disagree are wrong and not tolerated. 5. When agreement cannot be attained, all agree to disagree until further discussion. 6. One must act as the authority or his representatives say. 6. One accepts the majority decision when action must be taken. 7. Only by being indoctrinated with the autocrat’s designs and following his will can one improve. 7. Belief that ignorance can be overcome, that people can become better informed and better themselves. 8. Education is not important. Tolerant only of the “true” or right decision made by the autocrat. Education is indoctrination. 8. Everyone must be educated to help insure better decisions. 9. Justified in restricting others to avoid their going counter to the will of the authority. 9. Willing to live with a bad decision freely made until it can be changed rather than restrict others’ freedom to decide. 10. The autocrat always knows best. Common folk are means to the autocrat’s ends. 10. No one special group is able to decide what is best for others all the time. 11. The authority has the true knowledge. One must not accept nor entertain other positions. 11. Accepting another’s opinion must be freely done and capable of being rejected. 12. Laws are what the authority wants everyone else to do. They can only be changed by his say so. 12. Laws are guidelines for action when the forum is not in session. They can be improved or ignored only by the group’s consent. 13. Betrayal: Questioning the authority. 13. Betrayal: Acting to subvert the general will. 14. Ultimate betrayal: Insubordination. 14. Ultimate betrayal: Refusing to take responsibility; giving up one’s freedom of choice to another. A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 19: Two Faiths 15. Motto: Trust me. 15. Motto: Come let us reason together. 16. Injunction: Be pure (Be exclusive). 16. Injunction: Enjoy (Be inclusive). 17. Problem: One (unity/whole) cannot weigh values that are not parts of oneself. 17. Problem: An aggregate cannot weigh values nor maintain them. These problems can be resolved if there exists a universal Unity that includes (evaluates) all others as parts. This reality must be a real whole (or a series of Wholes), not an aggregate, and the whole cannot exist apart from the parts. Since a Whole that includes all else as parts must be or include the universe itself, this position is some form of theism. A serious logical problem, however, resides in conceiving of the universe as just one whole throughout temporal changes, that is, over time. A whole is just what it is. One whole cannot have or contain different parts from the ones it does, in fact, contain. So what happens to the universal Unity when new things happen, when new parts come into existence? The present whole cannot be the same whole that existed a moment before if it now contains different or additional parts from the previous whole. At each moment the Cosmic Unity contains all else as parts. But when new things occur, a new Whole must also occur. This new Whole must not only contain the new parts, but also the previous cosmic unity as one of the parts in its new, all-inclusive unity. In this view, though each of us acts to enrich his/er own experience, we also ought to act in light of others’ enrichments and how all acts affect the Whole, since affecting the Whole is unavoidable. Our ultimate value can only reside in the only place where everlasting differences can be made. This location must also be able to weigh everything simultaneously that presently exists as well as be able store it forever, otherwise what has been, would no longer be, presenting a serious logical contradiction. This location is a series of Wholes, where each is all-inclusive, and where each contributes to the next. Each moment of the series must be a whole summing up all that has previously happened, and the series must never have a last moment. G Summaries of Some Approaches to Social Ethics reek City States: (First Millennium BC). They nurtured (now and then) democracy, that is, the faith that justice and well-being will be found by those who discuss issues in an open forum, namely, voting on what to do, which laws to establish and who will be in charge of carrying them out until the voters decide otherwise. This was a revolution against the belief that a privileged class of people had access to revealed or cult knowledge or had better genes. It was a revolt against rule by a priesthood (theocracy) or by a secular king and his court or by anyone with a monopoly of power. It may have been a position not uncommon during the prepatriarchal period. These democratic societies were very restrictive, however, in their membership, excluding many classes of men, all women and slaves––much as did the original, “democratic” political system in the United States. S ocrates: (Died 399 BC ). Socrates believed knowledge is virtue: To know the right is to do it. The difficulty of really knowing what the good or just is spawned: (a) Skeptics who dogmatically “know” one cannot know what is right, or anything else, (b) Tyrants who say it is as right as anything else for us to do as they say, and (c) Platonists who believe only a few can know what is good and right, and they are the ones who do. Platonists were ultra-rationalists who believed only concepts that don’t change or have never been created are the only true ones, that is, necessary truth is the only truth. Skeptics and relativists agreed with this definition, but assumed no one could obtain such knowledge. P lato: (Died 347 BC). Plato believed only those who are fully knowledgeable should rule. All souls have been imprinted with eternal knowledge of the Good and True, but only the philosopher knows what it is. The common man is ignorant, confused by the influence of the body and can only see the truth hidden in the soul as if obscured by a dirty glass (mirror). The knowledge or revelation every soul has in heaven before becoming entrapped in the confusions of the body, is rediscovered by the philosopher. This special knowledge gives him the right to rule. Since knowledge supposedly makes one virtuous, he will presumably rule justly. In practice the ideal society for Plato is a monarchy guided by the philosopher. This good shepherd will tend his flock with care. In exchange the flock will blindly follow without question since for them to do the right is to fulfill their work-station 139 140 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 19: Two Faiths in life as defined by the enlightened one who knows what it is. Plato’s view of reality is very dualistic: (1) Cosmically there is (a) a “heavenly” world of true reality where nothing changes (which is the natural home of the soul), versus (b) the changing physical world of opinion and ignorance that commoners think is real. (1) Politically there is (a) a shepherd who has special knowledge and so has the divine right to rule, versus (b) the flock who must have faith that the shepherd is right. Even to question the shepherd/king is to jeopardize his good will. (3) Ethically personal virtue comes from (a) virtuous contemplation of the eternal realities (definitions) by the hoi oligoi (the privileged), versus (b) fulfilling work duties (defined by those with special knowledge) for the hoi poloi. (the commoners). God is not a clear idea for Plato. The Form of the Good, that is, the form of organization of all the other Forms or Patterns, is the highest reality. Plato does speak of a Demiurge, the world’s soul, that uses the Forms (I-deas) to create and move the world. Soul is central to Plato’s concept of salvation. It is what has the knowledge that sets us free from the body to go back to heaven (a heaven of Forms) where it came from. If the soul is simple (as Plato at times argues), salvation is its release from the body; if it is compound (tripartite, as Plato also argues), salvation is the harmonization of its three parts: the vegetative, the animal and the rational. Motivation for ethical concern comes from our ability to make a difference to ourselves by releasing the soul from the body. We cannot make a difference to the Form of the Good or anything eternal since they are changeless. It is doubtful we can even make a difference to our soul since it has all knowledge from eternity, and if it is simple, it is completely unalterable. So the only difference we make is in the clarity of knowledge we recover from the soulintellect that is confused on earth by one’s bodily emotions. If one has sufficient knowledge (attainable only by denying the body’s impulses), our soul will not be punished for its ignorance by being sent to hell for a while before being put back into another body. It may go to heaven for a while, but from there too it will eventually fall again and be trapped in another earthly body. Are we responsible for our ignorance and do we have the power to change it? If not, what is the motivation for ethical concern? Definitions that do not change are mistakenly seen by Plato to be the concretely real things. They are the things not seen, because they are objects of thoughts, but he assumes they are more real than the things seen because he assumes what is changeless is more real than what changes. A ristotle: (Died 322 BC). Aristotle backs away from the Socratic/Platonic view that (theoretical) knowledge is virtue. Knowledge is necessary, but not sufficient for virtue. He says there are two kinds of knowledge: theoretical and practical. Practical knowledge is imprecise but sufficient to guide behavior according to the Golden Mean: the middle-of-the-road, nothing-to-excess model for good behavior. Good character, the desire to be just or good, comes from the intrinsic social nature of man, from his interaction with good role models and a desire to be rational, that is, to fulfill our unique capacity or potentiality which for a man (but not for a woman) is to be rational. Ultimate motivation for being good is love of “God.” It is God (pure form or pure actuality) that has from eternity the fulfillment of each species’ form including the form that is uniquely man, namely, rationality. God does not contain nor know any detailed actions. Each primary substance (that is, a particular example of a species) ought to become fully what it is capable of being. Man ought be become fully rational since this is assumed to be what is uniquely human. Aristotle is not presenting an egoistic ethic because each of us is essentially a social creature, so fulfilling our rational end can only be done in a social context that requires that one consider more than his own narrow (irrational) interests. Soul, defined as the essence of what one is and as something that maintains its own separate existence apart from rationality in general, is not an obvious belief for Aristotle. God is changeless since change means fulfilling a potentiality not yet fulfilled: God is pure Form or Pure Actuality with no potentiality. God changes the world by being the object everything else desires to be like. To be good is to be God-like, to love God, not for a reward later but to live as enriching and pleasant life possible in this world. Definitions (the forms of actualities) are parts of full concrete wholes, what Aristotle calls “primary substances” which also have potentiality (that is, matter). God is the exception; God is all form and no potentiality. Salvation or living the good life is enhanced by emotional involvement in life’s experiences, especial those that have an insightful resolution of a conflict. Identification with a surrogate hero in a dramatic presentation can also help us to live the good life, by way of the aesthetic catharsis (cleansing renewal) we receive. A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 19: Two Faiths R oman Empire’s Climate: (200 BC-400 AD). The period during which Rome controlled much of the Mediterranean world was dominated by: (a) Worship of power rather than worship of goodness and truth; (b) Concern with salvation and otherworldliness, rather than man and reason; (c) Cults, each claiming special knowledge, but from revelation, not from a rational or empirical process. Most were quite antiintellectual; (d) Many religious movements, such as: Mystery cults; Dying and rising saviors. These were survivals, with masculine modifications, of the rituals underlying the cyclical female-centered worldviews of earlier times; Judaism: Zealots, Pharisees, Sadducees, Essenes, God-fearers, Jesus people, mysticism, apocalyptic pseudepigrapha, Gnosticim; Christianity: Jesus people, Pauline and Marken synthesis, patristics, Augustine, western literalism vs. eastern symbolism; Zoroastrianism (Manicheanism), Gnosticism, Mithraism, Stoicism, Epicureanism, Cynicism, Skepticism, NeoPlatonism (Plotinus), astrology. A ugustine: (354-430 A D ). He considered himself privy to special knowledge first as a Manichean and then as a Christian. Virtue is faith in Christian authorities who speak God’s truth, though he did try to find reasons to support belief. The unseen or immaterial realm of heaven is what we ought to desire and contemplate. However, we naturally desire things of the world, so the soul is naturally evil and must be saved from these evil desires. Ascetic denial of fleshly desires is one’s only hope of being saved. Salvation is from the temptations of the flesh and also from the uncertainties that come from being human. A fallen soul cannot save itself. Only special knowledge of God’s plan can save us if we also beg God to forgive us and have faith in the authorities who tell us that God will accept Christ’s suffering as payment for our wrongs. When God saves us, we will no longer feel uncertain about what life has in store for us, and we will be rewarded in heaven (for following the good shepherd like a good flock) with everlasting joy, even if this life does not give us such joy justly. If we refuse to believe God’s plan to redeem us (or perhaps even if we have not had the chance to hear it) we will be punished forever after “death” for our insubordination or lack of special knowledge (faith). Our soul is saved to have new experiences forever. In one’s soul are kept or saved all the experiences that one has had. One makes a difference to his soul forever (there was debate over whether women had souls). We do what we do to ensure getting our soul to heaven. We love God and others now to gain rewards later. This is an egocentric ethic. Love of God (faith in God) pleases God. We are rewarded with God’s love in return (heaven) rather than God’s wrath (hell). Salvation is not just for the privileged class but for anyone who declares his faithfulness, that is, capitulates his own will and power and accepts the authority. U tilitarians: (ca. 1800-1850). Virtue is action that furthers pleasure (Bentham). Virtue is action that furthers refined, rather than base, pleasures (Mill). The utilitarian ethic is a worldly and anti-ascetic ethic (though heavenly pleasures could also be motivations). No special knowledge or revelation is needed to understand what has positive value, since everyone knows what is pleasurable. And reason, which is available to everyone, can determine how to evaluate whose pleasure is ultimately good. Our experiences are meaningful since they have an affect in ourselves and others. If we cease to exist, and if all those we have affected cease, we would no longer be meaningful since nothing of us would go on forever making a difference. In the utilitarian ethic, the more pleasure generated, the better. Yet what does “more” mean. Should a little pleasure be experienced by many or much pleasure be experienced by a few? Is one justified in acquiring much pleasure at the expense of some pleasure for many others? Should we give one man pleasure or many pigs? Or many piggish men? How can one distinguish higher or better pleasures from lower or worse pleasures? Who do we ask to decide which are higher pleasures? Mill says we can appeal to one who knows both. One (a whole) who can directly compare both can directly experience the relative merits of two pleasures. But no human person has enough intimate information about others to experience the relative differences of the different amounts, kinds and distributions of their pleasures. One never experiences just what another does. This humanistic approach to value found its way into the United States’ anti-authoritarian Constitution. However, the actual social structure of the United States’ military, corporations, religious groups, racial and even family relations, still embody much of the autocratic structure that Socrates longed for and for which Plato tried to give a metaphysical justification. 141 142 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 19: Two Faiths P rocess Theistic Aesthetic: (Best formulated since 1930). All value is judged (evaluated) by its relation to all others at each moment. Value is intrinsically social. A “soul” is a moment of creation. A soul does not last more than a moment. It actualizes some potentiality of the moment and dies with its accomplishment. What it creates as it dies is a value to be given to other moments to experience, either in the same or some other series of creations or both. Our gaining knowledge of the meaning of “good” and other ultimate, abstract value concepts is possible, though not always easy to achieve. Our knowing all facts, all concrete creations relevant to a value judgment, is impossible. However, all facts are known by a cosmically inclusive reality, as is the meaning of “value,” so a true measure of everyone’s value exists which we may dimly grasp. Love of God/dess is the ultimate motivation, not so we will be rewarded later, but for its intrinsic value to oneself, others and God/dess now, and to God/dess and others later. We make a difference to others at each moment and always to the present and future cosmic unities. The differences (changes) made in the divine cosmic Series are forever, so we are always meaningful. Many others (and always the most recent Cosmic Whole) make a difference in us at each moment. God/dess is more than the world but not apart from the world. The world’s pleasures are pleasures for God/dess; our pains are pains for God/dess. Restraint of others to prevent aesthetic degradation is justified; punishment or revenge that causes more pain is not. The definition of “value” (positive or negative) is “contributing something to others.” Definitions, including the definition of “good and bad,” are aspects of concrete wholes. All definitions are abstract. Some definitions are completely abstract, that is, necessary, because they are aspects which all possible concrete wholes must have. So all values, all differences made, must be in concrete wholes. Yet no whole can be the final storehouse of all values, since there are endless possible states of value that can be created. So even the present all-inclusive Whole must become a part (one value amongst others, though the greatest) in the next, new all-inclusive Whole. Chapter Summary History is filled with socio-political systems that claim to be the only true or necessary social order. But even if the meaning of value is necessarily what it is, still how to fulfill it in personal and social contexts is not a fixed necessity. The autocratic view of social order is right to insist that the value, each member of a society or the cosmos has, can only be determined by a single, all-knowing individual. Yet the utilitarians are right to insist that each member of society has its own value. But they fail to appreciate that the relative value of the members of a group to each other cannot be determined apart from a whole that has the values of all the members. A whole cannot evaluate the group unless the members of the group are parts of the whole. Two questions should not be confused: (1) What does it mean to be good or bad? and (2) How are one’s acts known to be good or bad? The previous chapter concluded that the meaning of value is to make an everlasting difference, and that the meaning of positive value is to create the greatest amount of joy possible. A theistic authoritarian says this means making God happy by obeying him, regardless of the suffering created in the world to do so, probably because the pain in the world is assumed to be blocked from God, or because the pain is compensated for by the everlasting joy we will receive later in heaven as a reward for our obedience. The utilitarian says value is only found in creatures. Hartshorne finds value in both creatures and God/dess since the world is included in God/dess’ experience. Suggested Reading: Navia; Hartshorne, Beyond Humanism; “Nairn, Hartshorne and Utilitarianism.” 143 Chapter 20 Gods and Goblins Our Wounded Child Psychological Influences on Theistic Concepts “If you love it, set it free. If it doesn’t return, hunt it down and kill it.” Bumper Sticker on a 4x4 pickup. “Violence is an expression of intimacy.” Mobster Santo Trafficante. “Others who hate you don’t win unless you hate them and then you destroy yourself.” Richard Nixon, as he was forced to resign his presidency after the Watergate scandal. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– The affect of childhood neuroses on a rational worldview. –Approaches– (1) Capricious environment produces fearful and withdrawn people. (2) Rule-bound environment produces fearful and obedient people. (3) Harsh and occasionally merciful environment produces fearful and manipulative people. (4) Threatening environment controlled by a heroic friend produces fearful and thankful people who feel some relief but retain internal conflict. (5) Loving environment produces loving people. –Evaluation– Pro: Only love is unqualifiedly healthy and rational. Con: The first four environments are crazy-making situations to be avoided as much as possible. ****************************************************************************** S ometime in the womb each of us (as a unity of experience that integrates large numbers of brain cells), begins to feel our surroundings. Physiology dictates the primary elements of our surroundings are those very brain cells being integrated. The first faint unified feelings are not likely remembered. A personal series of experiences (that includes the memory of previous unities of experience as an element in the present unity of experience) may take some time to become established. Eventually, however, memory becomes consistent. Experience can then compare the new environmental sensory inputs presented by the brain cells with previous, re membered experiences. “Familiar experience” becomes meaningful, and so does the possibility of “unfamiliar.” Feeling the unities of past feelings is our true birth as a person. We feel the feelings of those momentary lives of our past series within our present moments of life. If our brain cells are feeling pleasantly, they will contribute this feeling to our whole; if they are suffering, so will we (the present whole) suffer in part. Not only must we accept, and be affected by, those in our immediate environment, but we find ourselves more or less affecting our environment, even though the awareness that we can control our environment arises at a somewhat later stage. We desire to experience others who are not feeling pain 144 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 20: Wounded Child and those who are not too unfamiliar. Our comfort zone requires we are, (1) living where others are comfortable so we don’t feel their discomfort as physical pain, and (2) living where those others are not presenting experiences to us with so much novelty they shock us and cause us mental pain or trauma. We are first alive and experiencing unconsciously in the womb and then pushed, unwombed, into the world, neither of which we ask for. The intraand extra-womb world is a given we each must contend with. We react to it emotionally and try to make sense of it with whatever conceptual power we have. We all live in an emotionally crazy-mak ing world that can only contribute to our devising irrational theories. Most theories have rational problems even under the best of conditions. Insanity or irrationality in some degree or other is our lot. We have no choice but to be both feeling and theorizing creatures. Thinking gives us a chance to overcome our emotional inconsistencies by understanding the structure of the world as it really is. As adults we can only hope we are now reflective enough to find saner theories to help direct saner emotional reactions to the world, so we are not fully at the mercy of our neuroses. The healing of the sickand-wounded child upon which our adulthood is built can be furthered, if not fully brought about, by reflecting on what theories we hold, the reasons we hold them and what may be irrational about them. Then, when we feel again our wounds, we will have the power to drain the poison, stitch ourselves back together and live with the scars. What follows attempts to show (1) how we have reacted emotionally to our environment in four unhealthy ways, reactions that are “normal” given our inadequate nurturing, but reactions that are irrational nevertheless, if the metaphysic expounded in this book is true, (2) how we hypothesize the nature of our immediate surroundings to account for these emotions, (3) how we often project the theory into cosmological (and religious) dimensions and, (4) how these four theories exhibit irrationalities in light of (5) a more adequate (theistic) cosmology. 1. An Unpredictable, Unpleasant World Nothing I want or do makes any difference. Environment: Unfamiliar, unpredictable and painful. Examples: Extreme bump or sudden loud noise while in the womb. Birth without familiar voices, temperature, and so on. Childhood neglect and abuse interspersed with nurturing. Pleas and hopes that have no effect on treatment received. Sudden transitions. Trauma. Reaction: Fear, panic, screaming and, finally, various degrees of withdrawal, really degrees of death that range from an inability to concentrate or contribute, to catatonia and split person. Rationale: (not necessarily conscious): No one seems to care for me. I make no difference: I’m meaningless. If no one cares for me, it is either because (1) I am not worthy of anyone’s concern or (2) the world imposes no obligation to be caring. My participation in the world must be minimized to avoid pain. Projection: The universe exhibits no intrinsic order. If there is such an order, it is not an order that cares for me, therefore, I have no obligation to care for the world, in fact, attachment will often cause pain, so disinterestedness is a virtue (Buddhists’ ethic). Holes in Theory: We are forced to accept our environment without knowing or feeling that the acceptance is reciprocated. The desire to continue to live, which requires us to continue to accept much of our environment, is countered by the desire to stop living to avoid the pain. Our desire to stop re-living the painful experiences presented by the environment evokes hate, namely, the desire not to experience what one has already unwillingly experienced. A theory of hate or withdrawal drives the neurotic conflict until we desire the stilling peace of our own death. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 145 Chapter 20: Wounded Child 2. A Just World When I do my chores, everything is OK. Environment: Orderly but conditional. Nurturing is earned by obedient behavior. Examples: We believe every aspect of behavior is guided by a rule to measure its appropriateness or value. We become fashion-conscious, outwardly directed to make sure we do not stand out. Rule-directed behavior leads to conformity. Reaction: Tell me what the rules are. One will not easily try anything new. Rationale: I am worthy only if I earn it by obeying the rules. Projection: The universe is controlled by a rule-giver and judge. Everything is good or bad depending on whether it follows the judge’s expectations. The world is a testing ground for obedience , not a place of excitement, creativity nor love. Holes in Theory: One who is comfortable following rules seldom asks whether a rule is good or bad. A world-in-creation cannot be interpreted within all the old categories. Yet, no one can always follow all the rules, so our positive self-image that comes when we are in control of our destiny, is turned against us when we find we can’t fulfill our duty. This causes us either to react and become dissocial, denying we are dutybound, or to adopt the next position. 3. A Merciful World Please don’t spank me. Environment: Harsh but forgiving, at least occasionally for those who beg. We give up our own desires in order to fulfill another’s desire as a way to avoid suffering. We have been convinced we are bad (that is, we don’t do what we are told or what the rules require) and deserve the pain as punishment (contrary to Number 1 where pain was not believed to be related to our behavior). We are often ostracized from our in-group or family because of our failings. Examples: Father spanking us when we didn’t do what he asked. Little sister begging to be let into a clubhouse clique. Begging to go to school even though we haven’t finished our asparagus. Asking for a second chance to do the work so we can go to the movie. Reaction: Manipulation of those in control, that is, “loving” the world so the world will us love back, but eventually feeling our destiny is out of our control. Our value depends on the whim of the one holding power. Rationale: The world will respond favorably to me if I know what strings to pull. Perhaps if I plead hard enough someone will pity me. The world knows that I am, but only cares how I am if I plead, sacrifice, grovel and try to please. Projection: The universe thinks more of me than others because I am part of a favored in-group which makes me more lovable. Those of the in-group will be valued (perhaps, forever); others will suffer and be lost. We give thanks to a merciful God for saving us when he could have decided to cast us out. The more we pray, petition and stay pure, the more God is likely to have mercy on us. Holes in Theory: We each feel we (or our group) is special. The energy spent to continually convince ourselves we are better or special (probably to compensate for the capitulation of our own creative excitements) keeps us from living a full life. We can’t know for sure our sacrifice is a good thing or a waste that is fulfilling another’s evil desires. God is not defined as “loving” but as “magnanimous.” Love is not a necessary part of God since God could decide not to love us. Our destiny is up to another’s caprice, so we must always fear that we will not be loved or saved. Change and the Unsurpassable 146 Chapter 20: Wounded Child 4. A Heroic World Big brother will help. Environment: My interests are being threatened (1) by others outside my group or (2) by a dominant member of my group. Big brother will step forward and (1) beat-up those picking on me if Mom and Dad are absent or (2) ask Mom/Dad not to punish me if s/he is the one who is angry with me, or even take his/er abuse for me. Examples: One’s parents protect the family from outsiders. Big brother stands in for a sibling in face of threats from either (1) others outside the family or (2) punishment from the parent him/herself. Reaction: Relief that I don’t have to always fend for myself. Intense internal conflict that my group’s champion who is protecting me from external threats can become my worst threat. My caretaker can become my undertaker, psychologically, and perhaps physically. Rationale: The in-group will take care of its own. If my parent is threatening me, I must not be worthy of his/er protection or “love; “perhaps another, a blood relation, loves me enough to help me. Projection: There is a cosmic hero who will save me, be my champion, in face of (1) evil forces or (2) God’s desire to punish me. This superhero is often a blood (or half-blood) relative; he is half human which prompts his concern, yet also a divine relative so divine concern and power is available to help us. Holes in Theory: What if my parent (God) sent the bullies (or disease) to punish me? The primary caregiver is often the primary source of fear, which is a bottomless pit of internal conflict (insanity). Can God be all-loving and, supposedly lovable, and punish us or even send us to hell forever? Our major neurosis stems from our not knowing whether one’s parent (or whomever we must depend on) is someone who is our common threat, or our primary protector. 5. An Unconditionally Loving World They love me whatever I do. Environment: Consistent nurturing, loving, providing adventure with security without pain. Challenge without undo risk. Examples: Touching, hearing, seeing are neither painful nor threatening. Reaction: Joy, love: mutual acceptance, trust and desire to further others’ enrichment. No fear. Rationale: What I do is unique, exciting and makes a difference. Not concerned to acquire rewards in another life to make up for deficiencies now. There are no deficiencies now as long as what I do continues to be meaningful, valued or make a difference. What I do will continue to make a difference since the world loves what I do and will nurture it. Projection: God/dess accepts me no matter what I do, but since I love him/er, I want to affect him/er positively by enjoying life and helping others to do likewise, so God/dess’ accepting love of the world will be enjoyable not painful. Holes in Theory: None obvious. A theory of all-inclusive love is only applicable in the “projected” or cosmological dimension. A creature by definition cannot love all. With a theory of intrinsically shared power (which Hartshorne and Whitehead see as the only logical possibility), how an all-loving God/dess and creaturely suffering co-exist, can be understood. ************************************************************************************ A Process Introduction to Philosophy 147 Chapter 20: Wounded Child Anguish over Inadequate Philosophy “I don’t understand God. If he is supposed to be all-loving, all-wonderful, why does he allow ‘bad things to happen to good people’? Last night a relative met with a violent end. How can this kind man, whom practically everyone likes or loves, deserve to meet such a fate: I’ve heard all of the excuses––when it’s your time, it’s your time; God needed a new angel; he’s better off now, etc., but this is what caused me to loose faith in God in the first place––the seemingly needless deaths of people, especially young people. I have come to believe that if there is a God, he is not all good; he must have some evil in him. My beliefs may be wrong, but I haven’t found anyone to change them.” Student, 1994. ************************************************************************************ Summary of Wounded Child’s Gods Environment is God/dess is Relation to God/dess Personal Action is Capricious Willful, Powerful Fear Withdrawal Orderly, but conditional Just Fear and Hate Obey or pay Harsh and occasionally forgiving Merciful Fear and begging Manipulation Threatening from without and from within Father: Just Half-Son: Merciful and heroic Fear, belief and thankfulness Relief but internal conflict Loving and nurturing All-loving Mutual love and enrichment Feeling meaningful and joyful 148 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 20: Wounded Child Chapter Summary Freud and others may be wrong to say all notions about divine reality are projections of psychological conditions, but we must recognize the great influence such experiences have had on how we think of God/dess. Even if it be true that our socialization has been the reason we think of God/dess at all, that would still not be sufficient to determine whether such a concept has any logical basis. Humanity has always seen nature as something to enjoy and fear. The unpredictable threats of nature are often thought to be directed at us on purpose. We see ourselves as the objects of rewards and punishments, so we fear stepping on God/dess’ toes. Yet, a rational view of cosmic unity and control should dispel the notion the cosmos is out to get us or test us, or that our suffering is to be welcomed as a virtue. Suggested Reading: McFague; Bible; Koran; Popol Vuh, also done as a PBS video special. ****************************************************************************** SAFE SECTS Please Practice SAFE SECTS Religion, Science, Advertising, the Medical and Legal Systems Have Proved Conclusively: Accepting Beliefs on Faith Alone Can Be Hazardous to Your Well-Being 149 PART VI Rational Basis for a Theistic Worldview Uni and the Unsurpassable: Five Concepts of God/dess and Morality ––––– The Ontological or Modal Argument: Necessity or Nonsense ––––– Theistic Attributes: Ultimate and Supreme Problem: How God/dess and the World Interact Copyright 2003 Duane Voskuil 150 Chapter 21 Uni and the Unsurpassable Five Concepts of God/dess and Morality “O Wakan-Tanka, be merciful to me! I am doing this that my people may live!” Sun Dance chant (sung during participant’s willingly sustained torture) as recorded by Black Elk, The Sacred Pipe. “There is no fear in love, but perfect love casts out fear; for fear has to do with punishment....” 1 John 4:18 “Love is patient and kind...Love bears all things.” 1 Cor. 13. “[O]ur God is gracious to all who seek him, but his power and his wrath are against all who forsake him.” Ezra 10:14. “The wrath of God is coming on those who are disobedient.” Col. 3:6. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– (1) Characterizations of God/dess’ personality. (2) Some possible relationships of God/dess and the world. –Approaches– (1) Divine Personality: (a) Willful, capricious. (b) Just. (c) Merciful. (d) Just in part and Merciful in part. (e) All-loving. (2) Relationship of God/dess to the world. (a) God/desses are in the world: Animism. (b) God/dess is the same as the world: Pantheism. (c) God/dess is apart from the world: Classical Theism. (d) God/dess includes the world: Panentheism. (e) God/dess is good versus another, similar power that is bad: Theistic Dualism. –Evaluation– Pros: (1) Only a concept of an all-loving deity is rational and healthful. (2) Only panentheism allows cosmic unity and change to make rational sense. At least, the usual criticisms of “God” do not affect panentheism as Hartshorne conceives it. Cons: (1)The prevalence of those who maintain the first four beliefs of God/dess’ personality says more about how we are raised, than about the logic of cosmic unity. (2) Guilt and fear often accompany even the attempt to rethink what “God” means. ****************************************************************** e as a species have always been aware of the supernatural power because the idea that events forces around us that shape our lives happened blindly without a purpose or end was not a whether or not we want them to and in consideration for humanity’s early consciousness. ways we may or may not desire. If we understand the The supernatural powers were seen to be related forces, we call them natural; if not, supernatural. The to each other in two ways, reflecting how we relate to gods and goddesses were thought to be the sources of each other: W A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 20: Five Concepts (1) loosely with each power affecting others somewhat and not answering to a higher or more inclusive power, though each power has more control over some parts of the world than others, or (2) hierarchically, where each power is more or less controlled by a higher power. The first approach left vague, (a) why the power did what it did, and (b) how it fit into a larger scheme of understanding. Even if all the powers were thought to be in some democratically ordered, cosmic society with its own particular set of laws, how the laws were established is vague. The hierarchical structure saw the source of law in the will of the more powerful (wise?) gods. The logic of the hierarchical position eventually led to a concept of a God to whom all other gods in the universe were subjected (see Chapter 16, Mithraism). A further step consolidated all power to be in one reality, in one God controlling all of us. Few have taken this step, for better or worse. Divine powers, for good and evil, like devils, angels and gnomes, populate the worldviews most people hold. Eventually, the thought occurred that God is not just the power over all in the universe, rather divinity is the unity of the universe, either as identical to the world (pantheism), or as including but being more than the universe (panentheism). This view may have been close to one of the ways the Goddess was conceived in prepatriarchal times. A final insight is to see the ultimate “laws” or meanings of the universe as necessary or eternal, never created by the will of any agent, not even God/dess. Parallel with how we conceive of the powers that be, run beliefs about how we are to relate to the powers, and how this relationship may allow us to join their supernatural society (usually after we are dead). Consider the progression of the five positions below. The first three are illustrated with passages from the Koran. Most can find Judaeo-Christian similarities. The masculine gender is used for divinity in the first four to conform to its historical and dominant use in these categories. Five Concepts of God/dess: From Fear to Love, from Will to Essence I. The Power(s): WILLFUL, whimsical, fickle, mischievous or capricious. Our attitude: Fear, since no matter what we do we may suffer the caprice of the gods. This is the first step toward finding a rationale for reality, here understood as the acts of conscious agents even if they are unseen and unpredictable. Our actions: Placating, begging, prostrating, and groveling. Problem: What is the meaning of life? God exhibits no necessities. Examples: “Allah doeth what He will” II: 253 “He it is who fashioned you in the wombs as pleaseth Him.” III: 6 “They [i.e. people] shall not enter them (the sanctuaries of Allah) except in fear.” II: 114 “When He decreeth a thing, He saith unto it only: Be! and it is.” II: 117 II. The Power: JUST, abides by a covenant (contract, constitution) which even if not mutually written, still allows us to know what is expected and what to do (supposedly) to avoid suffering. First step towards a rational or lawful view of reality. Our attitudes: Fear God when one is bad, and hate the bad. Our action: Paying the price, meeting the terms––no begging. We earn the kingdom by obeying; We can decide to accept the consequences of not paying. Problem: Theodicy: Why do we suffer when we are not bad? Examples: “Those who believe and do good works: such are the rightful owners of the Garden” II:2. “O Children of Israel! Remember My favour wherewith I favoured you, and fulfill your (part of the) covenant, and I shall fulfill My (part of the) covenant, and fear Me” II:36. “Every soul will be paid in full that which it hath earned” II: 281. “Hell [for the sinner] will settle his ac count.” II: For our shortcomings we “must pay a ransom of fasting or almsgiving or offering.... Observe your duty to Allah, and know that Allah is severe in punishment” I:196. “Those who buy the life of the world at the price of the Hereafter, their punishment will not be lightened” II:86. 151 152 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 21: Five Concepts III. The Power: MERCIFUL and forgiving, (always) giving more than one deserves. Our attitudes: Belief and fear modified with hope that we will get more than we deserve since we always fall short of fulfilling our side of the contract. We must have fallen short, because suffering is seen as God punishing us, and we all suffer. Our actions: Begging, prostrating, groveling, placating, self-deprecating to make ourselves pitiful so God will take pity on us. Obeying God’s commands and believing what God is supposed to have said as a way proving our love for God so God will return our love or at least be merciful and allow us in. We “love” in order to be loved (rewarded). Problems: How can we know God will show mercy? Why is God merciful? Is all suffering punishment? Examples: “Ask forgiveness of Allah. Lo! Allah is Forgiving, Merciful” II: 199. “Allah chooseth for His mercy whom he will” I:105. “Allah is the protecting friend of those who believe” II: 257. “Allah loveth those who turn unto Him [obey Him], and loveth those who have a care for [moral] cleanness” I:222. IV. The Powers: The Father, King or Lord of Lords is JUST and changeless; his son (half divine and half human) is MERCIFUL or magnanimous (or loving of his mother’s kind) and pays the price to the Father for our shortcomings so we can be part of the in-group. Death (on a cross, at the crossroads) of the old age brings in the new age. Our attitudes: Belief that the divine family will let us in if we are thankful for its magnanimity, yet fear that we are not thankful enough to get in. Our actions: Prove our belief by our faithfulness and lack of doubt. Keep ourselves pure so we will be acceptable to the in-group. Problems: Polytheism: How are the divinities related? Father or Son can decide not to let us in anyway. Once in, can we be kicked out, like Satan? Belief may not be strong enough. Examples: Pauline Christ: “Christ died for our sins [on the cross?]. . . was buried; . . . was raised on the third day . . . and appeared to Cephas, then to the twelve” (1 Cor. 15:3-5). Jewish Son of Man. Mithraic Mithras (Perseus). V. The Power: ALL-LOVING, never punishing, use of power everywhere at all times, that enjoys and suffers all necessarily. Essential, not willful love. Our attitude: Love of God/dess, returning love for love, no ground for fear only desire to enrich God/dess. Worship of goodness, not power. Our actions: Loving God/dess, not because we seek a reward or fear punishment, but because we desire to enrich God/dess. Enriching the world as the means to enrich God/dess. Spreading the good news of love as one means of enriching the world. Problem: None(?) Some think (a) without reward and punishment there is no reason to do one thing rather than another, (b) someone must be to blame for every suffering since “tragedy” is not real to them and (c) God/dess exhibits only changeless necessities and not the contingencies of ever-new creative and loving responses. These beliefs, though common, are not persuasive. Examples: None. Can only be one. The meaning of the attributes of God/dess are formed within these five contexts also. For example, the idea of God/dess as “all-knowing” is understood (in the first four examples) to mean we can never get away with disobedience towards God/dess because s/he always knows when we’ve been good or bad, so A Process Introduction to Philosophy 153 Chapter 20: Five Concepts we’d better watch out. One must be careful, however, not to commit the Genetic Fallacy: assuming the origin of an idea is its logical meaning. The various ways deity has been thought to be related to the world, if at all, can be partly depicted in graphic form: Cosmology and God/dess A. B. C. God(s) God is World Pre-speculative Animism Pantheism or Emanationism World D. God World(s) Classical Theism/Deism Pre-speculative Animism: Nature is alive, usually in the sense of being moved, or animated, by invisible souls or spirits, that may or may not be friendly. The more powerful of these are gods, usually related to each other in ways reflecting human societies. Gods and goddesses are in the world as part of the natural processes of the world, not outside nor containing the world. Little thought is given to what makes the world one, or whether the gods are necessary or contingent. Pantheism: The universe and God/dess are the same. It has always been in existence. Change, if anything, is alteration of the one reality; ultimately change is unreal. Reality is unified because there is only one real thing; diversity is not fully real, but explanations of how appearance and Reality are related are not satisfactorily handled. The One necessarily exists, so this position must make sense of a necessary actuality, a necessarily existing concrete. Since very good arguments can be found that all concrete wholes must be contingent, establishing a necessary concrete is likely impossible. Classical Theism: God has always been, but at some time created the world, so the world is not necessary for reality, though God is necessary and is numerically one whole through time. God is usually thought to be out of time, that is, changeless, since anything God could change into, God already is. All possibilities for “future” changes are already fulfilled making it questionable what “future” means. Deism is the belief that God set the world in motion according to natural laws after creating it and does not interfere with its changes. The unity of the universe is space, not God. God does not contain any spatiality or the world, since the world is changing and contingent and God’s whole is supposedly necessary. How God can be all-knowing without containing the reality God knows, is questionable, as E. God/dess World Panentheism F. God God World only Positivism, Atheism? World Theistic Dualism is how time and changes (futurity) can be real if God does not change, or how God can know what “future” means if everything is already done. Panentheism: God/dess has always been, as has the world in some form or other. God/dess is the unity of the world, and the world is what God/dess experiences and helps create. Each requires each other. God/dess is necessary, that is, the unique series of all-inclusive cosmic unities is necessary. The world is necessary also, but only in some way or other. No particular state of the world is necessary. Every state of affairs is contingent, but some state of the cosmos or other must always be occurring. Everything created by the universe is in God/dess, whose most recent creation is also in every part of the universe. Cosmic unities are concrete but momentary, giving way to a new unity that includes the old. God/dess is necessarily related to all, is necessarily a part of all and is the unity of all; God/dess is not apart from all. Positivism, Atheism : Atheism denies God exists. Positivism is more subtle, neither asserting nor denying anything about God since they treat “God” as a meaningless expression. The world is often assumed to have always existed in some way. Theistic Dualism: Close to classical theism but with two supernatural powers in contention, usually a good power and an evil power. The world is a stage where the power of the gods is tested, for instance, which god has the ability to persuade more people to worship him. Sometimes the two gods came from a common source, at other times one was created by the other and reacted to his subservient position, so evil becomes defined as insubordination. Sex is dangerous, often leading to insubordination because, as George Orwell portrayed in 1984, it empowers people to risk enjoyment and love over obedience. 154 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 21: Five Concepts Chapter Summary Not only does our personal and social history affect how we conceive divinity, but our concept of God/dess affects how we feel, act and interpret the meaning of life. Living in a country founded on religious freedom, does not mean all religious beliefs and rituals are equally true or valuable. It only means we have agreed not to kill and torture, nor even harass, those who do not believe as we do. Uni, one name for the Goddess whose womb is filled with the universe, inspires actions that are different from Yahweh, the Lord of Hosts, who sees the world as a battleground for testing the worthy. Theism is not illogical, though many formulations of theism are. Religious rituals express much that is nonrational (recall that “nonrational” is not the same as “irrational”), but may also make irrational utterances. To declare God is beyond knowing is to know more than one can know. To say God is apart from the world, is to require an explanation of how they are related. God/dess must be unique but the uniqueness cannot be a “complete difference” or uniqueness of the categories used to understand God/dess. If there were such a “complete difference” between divine and worldly things, we could not know there was, and such a theistic reality would be “completely” irrelevant to us, that is, meaningless. The uniqueness of theism is in the categorical application of the same categories or concepts that underlie all possible explanations: God/dess exhibits metaphysical categories without any qualification. S/he is what the categories mean. For example, God/dess is not beyond knowledge or beyond our ability to know anything about him/er, rather s/he has complete, or unsurpassable knowledge, whereas we are deficient in knowledge. Or again, s/he loves; we love some things, to some degree. Suggested Reading: McFaye; Bible; Koran; Popol Vuh, also done as a PBS video special; Hartshorne and Reese, PSG; Whitehead, Religion in the Making. Copyright 2003 Duane Voskuil 155 Chapter 22 The Ontological or Modal Argument Necessity or Nonsense “I can think of a perfect island.” Gaunilo in response to Anselm. “Who’s buried in Grant’s tomb?” Groucho Marx to quiz show losers. “By cause of itself, I understand that whose essence involves existence; or that whose nature cannot be conceived unless existing.” Spinoza, Ethic. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– Determining whether “unsurpassability” makes sense. More specifically, determining whether one aspect of unsurpassability makes sense, namely, “necessary existence.” –Approaches– To make sense of “unsurpassability,” consider the following: (1) “Contingently existing versus necessarily existing,” is not the same as “existing versus not existing.” (2) Knowing that something exists does not imply knowing how it exists; it only implies knowing that it exists in some way or other. (3) All actual wholes that exist are concrete and contingent, and all necessities are abstract (that is, aspects of wholes). (4) That which exists necessarily is a series of wholes, not one whole. No whole is necessary. What is necessary is that the series must always have some whole or other at each moment. –Evaluation– Pro: Avoids the positivists’ criticism that “God/dess” is meaningless because all beings, or wholes, are contingent. This criticism is correctly leveled only at theists who say God/dess is one necessary whole. It misses the mark for theists who say God/dess is a necessary series of contingent wholes. Con: Requires one to think explicitly in modal terms; something most are not used to doing since all other issues are contingent, even though this is not explicitly recognized nor taught. ****************************************************************************** F ew philosophical arguments have been debated pro and con for so long by so many. Even though the modern relativistic mentality has dismissed the Argument, in part from having grown weary of the search for nec essary truth altogether, the Argument has been around for at least a thousand years and maybe twice that long. Most authors say that the Argument tries to establish that God necessarily exists. It is usually called the Ontological Argument for the Existence of God. Onto means “being,” so philosophers see the Argument trying to establish the existence of God from the nature of God’s being. God’s being is defined as “necessary being,” so God must exist. One might remember Parmenides who said Being must be (exist) since nonbeing (and even change of being) is nonsense. The positivist counters by saying all being is contingent, anything that actually is or does, is as it is because of conditions or decisions that did not have to be made as they were. The positivists are right. All acts are contingent. Does this imply all existing realities must be contingent? To answer this question, we must examine the ambiguity in the use of the term “being.” After discussing “change” in earlier chapters, it should be clear the term “being” has been used in different 156 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 22: Modal Argument ways. I have suggested Parmenides is right when he says “being” is changeless reality, but he is wrong when he says being has always been. A being, as concrete actuality , is the result of a creative act. It has come into being, which is contrary to Parmenides’ belief that Being must be eternal and necessary. All acts are contingent. Anselm uses the term “being” to refer both to, (1) the unavoidable characteristics (abstract-ions) that define what “God” means, and (2) God’s actual (concrete) reality. Since God is necessary, and since what is necessary must be as it is, it follows God cannot change. Historically, this has meant God’s concrete actuality must be changeless, since (a) the definition of “God” and (b) God’s existence have not been distinguished from (c) the way God concretely exists. Many agree, including positivists, existentialists and process metaphysicians, that every concrete reality (whole) is contingent (since all concrete being is the result, in part, from free decisions). The positivists then conclude no thing (being) must exist, nothing is necessary. But a process metaphysician can respond that “thing” can refer (1) to each concrete moment itself, or (2) to a series of beings (or concrete moments). This distinction, learned when we examined the problem of change, must be kept in mind as we examine the Ontological or Modal Argument. Anselm, a monk who died in 1109 CE , for mulated the Ontological Argument. Actually, he formulated two different arguments. One argument, the weak, invalid argument, tried to establish that actual existence is better or greater than mere conceptual existence, that is, an existing thing is greater than an idea of the thing, therefore, the greatest conceivable reality must exist in addition to the idea one has of that reality. This argument is stated in Proslogium, Chapter II, where he says, Therefore, if that, than which nothing greater can be conceived, exists in the understanding alone, the very being, than which nothing greater can be conceived, is one, than which a greater can be conceived. But obviously this is impossible. Hence, there is no doubt that there exists a being, than which nothing greater can be conceived, and it exists both in the understanding and in reality. (Emphasis added.) The above argument is a bad28 argument. It assumes the idea of unsurpassability can make sense in 28I use this pejorative term, rather than the more neutral terms “weak” or “invalid,” since many often think this is the understanding alone, that is, it assumes that the idea in the understanding is contingent, since whether or not it is of anything existing must be argued for. This invalid argument tries to move from a reality implicitly conceived as not necessarily existing, to that reality necessarily existing. This is never a valid logical procedure. But he has another formulation in Chapter III (the quotation is separated into paragraphs to make it easier to examine. Emphasis added). [1] And it assuredly exists so truly, that it cannot be conceived not to exist. [2] For, it is possible to conceive of a being which cannot be conceived not to exist; [3] this is greater than one which can be can be conceived not to exist. Hence if that, than which nothing greater can be conceived, can be conceived not to exist, it is not that than which nothing greater can be conceived. But this is an irreconcilable contradiction. [4] There is, then, so truly a being than which nothing greater can be conceived to exist, that it cannot even be conceived not to exist; and this being thou art, O Lord, our God....Why, then, has the fool said in his heart, there is no God (Psalms xiv. I), since it is so evident to a rational mind, that thou dost exist in the highest degree of all: Why, except that he is dull and a fool? Anselm is not arguing in this paragraph that existence is greater than nonexistence (that an actuality is greater than the idea of that actuality). He is here pointing out that necessity surpasses contingency. Even if two realities both existed, the one that exists in such a way that it must exist will surpass the one that exists in such a way that it might not exist. An idea cannot be of the greatest reality possible, the Unsurpassable reality, unless the idea is a noncontingent idea. An idea defining a necessarily existing reality (if successful) will be about a reality that necessarily surpasses all realities existing contingently. The Anselmian Principle Necessity Surpasses Contingency, or The Unsurpassable Cannot Exist Contingently since a necessarily existing reality surpasses a contingently existing one (if meaningful). An idea defining a necessarily existing reality cannot be a contingent idea, that is, an idea that has a one of two valid arguments, or even fail to move on to the second argument (a failure of many philosophers also). A Process Introduction to Philosophy 157 Chapter 22: Modal Argument logical alternative. If all ideas must have logical alternatives, then we can never have an idea of Unsurpassability (of course, by now one should notice that the statement that all ideas have alternatives, is an idea that does not have and alternative). Positivists (as pointed out in Chapter 3), not only believe all beings are contingent, but all concepts or propositions are contingent, necessarily contingent. But the logical self-contradiction of a proposition stating, “It’s necessary that all meaningful propositions are not necessary,” suggests some propositions are necessary or metaphysical. Only metaphysical propositions which have no meaningful alternatives can make sense of “unsurpassability,” if any can. If there is a concept of “unsurpassability,” it must be a necessary concept, that is, one with no logical alternative. The question is not whether or not God/dess (which here means “that than which nothing greater can be conceived” or “the Unsurpassable”) exists, but whether or not “God/dess” makes sense. If “God/dess” is non sense, then asking whether nonsense exists is meaningless. Careful positivists never deny God/dess exists. For them to deny God/dess exists, would logically imply they know what God/dess means. One would be foolish, as Anselm says, asking whether or not something exists that must exist. Anselm clearly points out in Chapter III of the Proslogium (though not in Chapter II) that the real question is not whether God exists, but whether or not we know what “God” means. As a medieval monk, he naturally assumed he knew what he was talking about when he referred to “God,” so Anselm did not analyze carefully enough whether “That Than Which Nothing Greater Can Be Conceived” makes sense. Anselm’s Questionable Assumption “It is possible to conceive of [a necessarily existing reality or] that than which nothing greater can be conceived.” The second sentence of Chapter III says: “And it is possible to conceive of a being which cannot be conceived not to exist;” but is it? One must not take this for granted. It must be demonstrated, and the positivists have given good reasons for doubting one can have a meaningful concept of a “necessarily existing being.” A bstract-Concrete Dilemma: Amongst the many problems that must be faced and answered in a attempt to achieve a concept of a necessarily existing reality, is the nature of necessity itself. Necessity is something that is as it is and could not be any other way. It has no alternative, and is, therefore, changeless. Yet anything that concretely exists, exists as a moment of creation (as was seen in the previous discussions of change), that is, everything created, is contingent. If one accepts the strong argument that all actuality is contingent, since it results from creative activity, and if one fails to distinguish existence from actuality, then all existence must be contingent, as the positivists maintain. On the other hand, if one maintains that something’s existence is necessary, and if one still does not distinguish existence and actuality, then its actuality must be necessary, as Anselm and many theists have historically said. The attempt to conceive of a “necessary being” that is, a “necessary actuality” fails. Insofar as being is the result of a creative coming-to-be, all being is contingent. The attempt to refer to a “necessary being,” that is, a “necessary actuality,” is just another example of a self-contradiction, like many we have run into. The truth about this matter is that all necessities are abstract, and abstractions do not act. They are changeless. They are not actualities; they are unavoidable characteristics of actualities. That necessity must be abstract can be understood when we remember that all abstrac tions, not just necessary ones, are characteristics of actualities. Abstractions are characteristics that are or could be found in more than one act or whole. Anything found in more than one whole, as an aspect of wholes, is not a whole itself. This truth is the direct denial of the influential Platonic tradition that says (the Oneness of) each changeless Idea is not only one thing, but is also a whole that is fully real, not just an abstraction. Abstractions are merely aspects of the fully real.29 For Plato the changing world that exhibits the characteristics in Many ways is deficient in reality. The changing world is a shadow or flickering refection of the full reality of the One Idea. Only wholes are concrete, and ideas or concepts are not wholes. “Motherhood” has never had labor pains. “Happiness” is not happy; and the definition of “God/dess” is not God/dess. Necessities are abstract. Necessities are completely abstract. 29Whitehead calls these Ideas, “eternal objects” that ingress into the processes of creating actual entities. Hartshorne, to my mind, makes more sense when he says only metaphysical ideas (objects) are eternal. Metaphysical objects are, always have been and will be descriptive of every moment of actuality. All other abstractions have been created at some time as a unique, specific feeling. They become abstract (in more than one place at a time) as their characteristics are inherited by, and passed on to, other acts of creativity. 158 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 22: Modal Argument Necessities are abstractions not only capable of being found in many wholes, but must be found in all wholes. They are found, (1) in all actual wholes, and would be found (2) in any whole that could have happened and did not, and will be found (3) in every whole that comes to be. They are the universal common denominators of all possible acts. So necessity is not only abstract; it is completely abstract. It is a universal factor, applicable to, or exhibited by, all possible facts (wholes). So what? someone might ask. Even if we can have this universal knowledge, how can this knowledge of necessities give any knowledge about contingent actualities? How can general abstract knowledge about a necessarily existing reality, be informative about its concrete existence? How can conceptual necessities say anything about actual, concrete existence which, it seems, is always a particular, contingent actuality that doesn’t have to be as it is? Aren’t we simply committing the basic error logicians call the Fallacy of Existential Import: Assuming because we have an idea of a kind of thing, that there must be an existing example of the class? Just because we can talk about unicorns and even how they necessarily have one horn (by definition), still it is not necessary there be any unicorns. Hartshorne establishes how one can validly move from knowledge of the abstract to knowledge of necessarily having some concrete or other, while avoiding the Fallacy of Existential Import. In one of his more important insights, he points out there are three terms that need to be analyzed in clarifying the Modal Argument: essence, existence and actuality, not just essence and existence. (1) Essence: What we are trying to talk about or define, namely, “Unsurpassability,” which includes as part of its definition, necessary existence. (2) Existence: That a reality is actual in some contingent way or other. There are two kinds of existences: a. Contingent or surpassable existences that may or may not have some contingent actuality or other. b. Necessary or unsurpassable existence that must have some contingent actuality or other. (3) Actuality: How the (contingent) acts are done. Specific acts could have been done otherwise, both for surpassable existences and the Unsurpassable existence. But if the Unsurpassable makes sense, it is not possible there be no acts at all. The members of the class (that is, members of the series of acts) are contingent, but the class must be necessary, which means the class must always, necessarily, have some contingent members. The class will always be exhibited in what is concrete. This Series must always be doing something or other, must always have a concrete fulfillment. If Anselm and Hartshorne are right, then when we know what we are talking about (if we have successfully defined a necessarily existing reality), we know that it must exist. The WHAT and the THAT are the same. To see why this is the case, take a closer look at what “existence” means. Someone exists when s/he is doing something, that is, acting or creating, which for Whitehead, we recall, is the meaning of a “whole.” Parts do not act, only wholes do, though they contain parts. Even though all realities exist by acting, only the Unsurpassable actor must act. Our existence is contingent, not because we do contingent things, but because we do contingent things contingently. It is not necessary that we act at all. What distinguishes unsurpassable existence (which means at least necessary existence) from ordinary existences is not that the particular acts of the Unsurpassable are necessary (no actuality is necessary, as the positivists also point out). Better Conceptual Tools –Three Is Better Than Two– Essence: What kind of existence is being defined. Existence: That the defined kind of existence is actual in some way or other. Actuality: How the existence exists at some particular moment. What distinguishes the Unsurpassable is that s/he must act in some contingent way or other. It is necessary the Unsurpassable act contingently, but it is contingent that we (and everything else) act contingently. We do not have to exist, but something or other must exist. “Complete nothingness” is mere nonsense. There is no alternative to something. We started out trying to define “that than which nothing greater can be conceived.” To do so we needed to know what it means to “exist necessarily,” which we now see means “necessarily always doing something contingent.” What is done could have been done differently, but it is impossible that “nothing is”––a nonsense expression. The remainder of the Argument consists in trying to determine whether other possible attributes of Unsurpassability make sense and whether all the required attributes are coherent together. This is taken up in the next chapter. Anselm, however, did formulate the Argument in an invalid form. The usual responses to Anselm, even in the most recent textbooks, criticize him on the weak Argument correctly but fail to appreciate the strong Argument. The following paragraph is from such a book: A Process Introduction to Philosophy 159 Chapter 22: Modal Argument “The ontological argument . . . attempts to deduce the existence of God from the concept of God. . . . Anselm assumed that to exist in the understanding and in reality is greater than to exist in the understanding alone.” Another author says the Argument’s “genius is its demonstration that the sentence, ‘God does not exist,’ is a self-contradictory sentence.” This is true, but not for the reasons given, since this author also thinks Anselm believes “it is obviously more perfect to be than not to be,” that is, nonexistence, rather than contingency, is assumed to be the defect by this author also. But Anselm in his strong argument in Proslogium III is not first assuming a concept of That Than Which Nothing Greater Can Be Conceived and then deducing from this concept that it must exist. If one supposedly has a concept of Unsurpassability without knowing that it must exist, then one’s socalled concept of a necessarily existing reality is really a concept of a contingently existing reality. There is no way to logically move from the concept of a reality that may or may not exist to knowing it does in fact exist. Only direct experience can so inform us of what is actual. But a necessarily existing reality cannot be conceived without knowing that it has always been and will always be. There is no deduction, only clarification. We are either confused when we use the word “God/dess” or “Unsurpassable” since it can refer to nothing meaningful, as a positivist maintains, or we discover that the reality must exist, that the “possibility” of its nonexistence is meaningless. People spend much time and effort trying to prove that God/dess does, or does not exist. When the debate cannot marshal enough facts to prove either side, some conclude they cannot know whether or not God/dess exists. They become agnostics. These three positions, Empirical Theism, Atheism and Agnosticism are all illogical if God/dess must at least mean the “Unsurpassable,” which at least means, “a necessarily existing reality.” All three assume they can know what “God/dess” means, before or without, knowing that s/he exists. This is why Anselm is right to say only a fool, that is, someone who is confused, will deny God exists, since who but a fool would say, “Something that must exist, does not exist” or even “might not exist”? How Surpassable and Unsurpassable Are Alike and Different Surpassable Unsurpassable Contingent Existences: Necessary Existence: Existence: evidence required evidence required What same That How evidence required 160 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 22: Modal Argument Gaunilo, a fellow monk of Anselm, tried to play the fool and give a counter-example. He said he could conceive of a perfect (complete) island, but the island didn’t have to exist. Gaunilo did not understand that examples of “perfection,” in the unqualified sense Anselm was using the term, are not possible. An island, by definition, can be surpassed since it must be set off by something from something else. That which would contain both the island and that from which the island is set off would logically surpass the island, or the mainland. Contingently creating contingently. versus Necessarily creating contingently. Anselm responded to Gaunilo’s challenge. Gaunilo did not reply. Did he get the point a thousand years before Hartshorne clarified it, or did he conclude Anselm is beyond help, so why waste more time communicating with him? Before going on to examine other attributes of the Unsurpassable (since necessary existence is only one of many), the following summaries of the valid (or modal) and invalid (or nonmodal) forms of the Argument might help get an overview of the first attribute of That Than Which Nothing Greater Can Be Conceived. “Perfection (Unsurpassability)” must include, as part of its meaning the attribute of “noncontingency.” There really is no inference, only clarification. In every other case, neither existence nor nonexistence can be inferred from the concept alone. In all other cases we need to know not only what we are talking about, but also whether it does in fact exist: Factual knowledge is always open to doubt as Plato noted. Gaunilo’s “perfect island” can only mean “perfect of its kind;” it cannot mean “Unqualifiedly Perfect” or “Complete.” NonModal, INVALID, Form of the Ontological Argument The invalid or non-modal form of the Ontological Argument attempts to use “existence” or “nonexistence” as a predicate or attribute of Unsurpassability. It tries to argue from the “conceivability of Perfection or Unsurpassability” to “Perfection conceived as existent.” This argument assumes that (simple) nonexistence is an imperfection, therefore Perfection exists; or again, it is better (more perfect) to exist than not to exist, therefore Perfection exists. It assumes that Perfection is conceptually meaningful without simultaneously knowing it must exist. Since (supposedly) it is possible that Perfection does not exist, (the critic aptly replies) that more than concepts are required to know that Perfection (as for anything else) does in fact exist. This approach implicitly argues, invalidly, from the mode of contingency to the mode of necessity, that is, from possible to necessary existence. 1. Conceivable (possible) and existing (Proslogium II / Empirical Theism) or 2. Conceivable (possible) but not existing (Atheism) or 3. Conceivable (possible) but perhaps not existing (Gaunilo /Agnosticism) There is no way to validly move from “conceivable” to ‘“existing” without questionable assumptions. God/dess (if s/he means at least a reality that is unsurpassable) is not meaningful as a reality that exists but could possibly not exist. Contingent All All Factual Factual Oppositions Oppositions A (The?) Perfect or Complete Being (Individual?) is (supposedly) either: premises can only establish contingent conclusions. The Argument must use necessary premises, that is, metaphysical propositions. Since all necessary propositions are on equal footing, there is no deduction from one to another, only clarification. Copyright 2003 Duane Voskuil A Process Introduction to Philosophy 161 Chapter 22: Modal Argument Modal Form of the Ontological Argument I 1. Conceivable, but only as necessarily existing (i.e., possible or meaningful only if necessary––Proslogium III and Replies), or 2. Not conceivable, i.e., impossible (Positivism. Anselm ignored this). No examples nor counter-examples: only one possible case, if any. One begs the question to collapse No. 1 into No. 2 or vise versa as both Anselm and the positivists do. Opposition Conceptual Conceptual The Perfect or Complete Being (or Unsurpassable Individual) is One that is either: Factual Oppositions 1. Conceivable (i.e., might be possible) and does, in fact, exist because of these facts: miracles... 2. Conceivable but does not, in fact, exist because of these facts: evil, can't see him... 3. Conceivable and perhaps exists (factually determinable, but as yet undetermined. Possible An imperfect or incomplete (surpassable) being (individual) is one that is either: Actual Actual Contingent Mode: Possible Beings or Individuals NonContingent Mode: Necessary or Impossible Individual The valid, or modal form of the Ontological Argument uses “noncontingent (existence)” or “contingent (existence)” as possible predicates or attributes of the Unsurpassable. It then argues that Perfection or Unsurpassability is “conceivable only as existentially noncontingent,” that is, as something so great it cannot be conceived not to exist. Unsurpassability can only be conceived as necessarily existing. The possibility of nonexistence is the imperfection, therefore Perfection cannot not exist; or again, it is better (more perfect) to be noncontingently existing than contingently existing, therefore Perfection exists necessarily (if meaningful). Since it is impossible that Perfection could possibly not exist, either Perfection necessarily exists, or (as the critic who gets the point of the Anselmian Principle, namely, that Perfection Cannot Exist Contingently, might yet reply) “perfection” is nonsense, as the positivists assert. The modal form of the Argument argues that noncontingent existence (necessary existence) surpasses contingent existence (if meaningful), and then argues that noncontingent or necessary existence (“Perfection” or “Unsurpassability”) is meaningful. Examples: (a) Any particular actuality or possible actuality which is finite and fragmentary like unicorns, islands or people, or (b) any actual or possible state (Being) of the Unsurpassable Individual which is finite and surpassable but nonfragmentary, that is, Whole. f (and note well the “if”), if the concept of the Perfect (Unsurpassable) Being (Individual) is conceivable, that is, not an inconsistent and/or an incoherent idea, the individual does not still require additional proof to show its possible existence actually exists since it is impossible that its existence is merely possible (so much for Agnosticism). It is also not meaningful that, (a) the Unsurpassable exists and might not have existed or (b) might cease to exist, or (c) does not exist and might come to exist (so much for Empirical Theism and Atheism). T he Whole and The Infinite. Before proceeding to examine other possible attributes of the Unsurpassable, carefully distinguish the following terms: (1) Finite, as fragment, (2) Finite, as whole and (3) Infinite. Copyright 2003 Duane Voskuil Change and the Unsurpassable 162 Chapter 22: Modal Argument F F inite Part: Fragment: A fragment is part of the present Whole. Fragments are bounded by potentiality and other actualities, that is, there are other actualities that are not part of a fragmentary whole. inite (Actual) Whole: All that is actual. An actual whole is finite but not bounded by other actualities. It is only “bounded” by potentiality. Every actuality is finite in this sense: Whatever it is, there is always something else it could have been, and something else the future will add to it. The greatest present whole can have nothing actualized outside it, and all potentiality (which is really all past beings, see Chapters 23 and 24) also reside within the present Whole. If Whitehead’s analysis of change is right, every whole, even the greatest present Whole (though Hartshorne makes this clearer), becomes a part of another whole at the next moment. The “Greatest Conceivable Being” is a nonsense expression if it means the “greatest conceivable whole.” Possibilities for wholes are endless, that is, infinite, so no one whole can logically sum up all possible wholes as actual parts. I nfinite: (a) All that has been and is, that is, all actuality (which may be argued is infinite into the past, even though each moment has a beginning and is a finite selection), and (b) all that could be and could have been, that is, all potentiality (which is always an abstract aspect of actuality). Infinity means “unbounded.” It is meaningful to be unbound in one way or many ways, but to be unbound in all ways is meaningless. Trying to conceive of infinity as something unbounded in all ways is the attempt to try to conceive of reality as pure potentiality (like Anaxi mander’s Boundless Stuff) which is meaningless. All potentiality exists only as characteristics of actuality. Only actuality has potentiality. Only actuality that has come to be can present possibilities for other acts. Possibility cannot exist by itself. “Pure potentiality” is a nonsense expression, and so is “pure actuality,” despite Aristotle’s (and many others’) attempt to say this is God. All actualities contain the potential to be included in future possibilities forever. “None Greater” Means: One Series of Wholes, not One Whole So if we try to mean by Anselm’s “none greater can be conceived” that we can conceive of an actual whole (or being) such that no other actuality could conceivably be greater, we are bound to fail, since even if there is a supreme or greatest whole at each moment, there will always be greater wholes in the future. Values (possible actualities) cannot be exhausted. There is no perfection that could be the perfection or completion of all possible states of value simultaneously. Every actual value is a creation of a specific act fulfilling one of the boundless realm of possible acts. But, perhaps, we can conceive of the Unsurpassable as a series of wholes. The Buddhists and Whitehead conclude this must be the case for something that exists for more than one mo ment, and Hartshorne clearly asserts this is the way to conceive of the necessary existence of the Unsurpassable. Process, or the successive creation of new states of value (building on past states), is the only way to fulfill the greatest conceivable value. The question of conceivability then be comes, Can we conceive an individual (that is, a series) such that no other individual (series) could conceivably be greater? (Hartshorne, PSG, 105.) Any individual (1) exhibits abstract characteristics that define the individual (personality traits), (2) includes all or part of the concrete results of previous acts in its series and (3) may continue to have future acts. The Unsurpassable Individual would be unique by being required to (a) exhibit eternal, that is, necessary, personality traits, (b) include all previous actualities and (c) include all future acts as they occur. The following chapter examines some traits this individual must have and those s/he could not have. ************************************************************************************* Discussion of the Modal Theistic Argument (A Letter to a Colleague Whose Textbook Discussing Theistic Issues Ignored Hartshorne’s Evaluation of the Ontological Argument) F rom a pedagogical point of view the argument can be thought of as having two emphases: (1) to learn a bit about modal logic and (2) to do what one can to make sense of “Unsurpassability” (“that than which nothing greater can be conceived”). A Process Introduction to Philosophy 163 Chapter 22: Modal Argument I think one main task of philosophy is to clarify which propositions have no logical alternatives. If one begins by assuming all meaningful propositions have logical alternatives, then the alternative that there are propositions with no alternatives never even gets examined. Plato’s and the determinists’ belief that only necessary propositions, that is, those with no alternative, make sense (or can be true) is likely wrong also. So the main point of modal logic, and the point which all students being introduced to philosophy need to learn, in my view, is that meaningfulness is unavoidably modal, that is, the attempt to say all (meaningful) propositions are contingently true or all (meaningful) propositions are necessarily true will always be self-contradictory. The position that does seem to make sense is: “Some propositions are contingently true and some are necessarily true, and this is one that is necessarily true.” I understand Anselm to be saying in his clearer moments that any discussion of Unsurpassability must, (1) recognize the unavoidable modal structure of meaning and (2) recognize that the Unsurpassable cannot be meaningfully conceived as contingent, that is, as something that may or may not exist. “That than which nothing greater can be conceived (ttwngcbc)” can only be conceived as necessary (if at all), and anything that is necessary has no alternative to its existence. One does not first conceive of Perfection or Unsurpassability and then try to conceive of Perfection as something that must exist “out there” in addition to the idea in one’s head. This is what history has taken him to say, and he does seem to say this in some places (see Proslogium II), but this is not what he is saying in the first paragraph of Proslogium III. Anselm, however, did not prove what he assumes to be true, namely, that Unsurpassability makes sense and, therefore, Unsurpassability must exist. He says “it is possible to conceive of that than which nothing greater can be conceived.” This may be true, but it is certainly not obvious and certainly not true as he thought is was. His so-called concept of “Unsurpassability” was vague or self-contradictory. Unsurpassability as a changeless realm containing all that is and could be as eternally done is nonsense. Given his attempt to conceive of God as ttwngcbc, he should have concluded “God” is meaningless, as the positivists do. Again, he should not have concluded God does not exist, because this would assume he knew what “God” meant, but he should have concluded “God” has no meaningful content (like “round squares”), if he were to be consistent with his modal logic. Trying to make sense of ttwngcbc is not easy. It is the whole philosophical problem. One main part of the problem comes from the realization that necessity must be changeless and abstract, and yet actuality must be created and contingent. Insofar as one is referring to God/dess’ necessity, one is referring to God/dess as an abstraction or mere concept. And when one refers to God’s actual existence, one is referring to something necessarily contingent since no actuality can be necessary as it is; a ”necessary act,” despite the determinists, is a self-contradiction. In order to handle this abstract-concrete dilemma, Hartshorne points out that the attempted clarification of the concept of “unsurpassability” requires three distinctions, not the usual two of “ essence” (or definition) and “existence” (that the definition is actualized). We need to add “actuality” (how the actuality is actual). The argument may have a chance, then, to establish that part of God/dess’ definition (essence) is a necessarily existing reality, and to establish this without having to maintain that the way God/dess acts is necessary, since at each moment there are endless co-equally good ways to exist. It is only necessary that s/he act in some (contingent) way or other in order to exist. So God/dess is both necessary and contingent: Necessary in definition (and therefore, existence) and contingent in concrete content (the particular way of existing). The divinity worthy of Anselm’s worship must, as he clearly understands, be necessary and not just a possibility, but God/dess must also be much more than a pale description. God/dess is the full majesty of the unimaginable, contingently created content of the universe which includes the changeless aspects that define him/er. Contrary to what many believe, the contingent or concrete moments can contain the abstract necessities so long as it is not contingent there always be some contingent (and supreme) actuality or other to contain or exhibit them. It is this all-inclusive, never-beginning, never-ending noncontingent series of contingent acts that always exhibits the necessary essences in an unsurpassable way. It is this Anselm might better have claimed to be the reality that was his God/dess. God/dess (or anything that survives through time) cannot be conceived as one Being. Unsurpassability is an individual, composed (as all individuals are) of a series of beings, or better, a series of creations of beings. A Whiteheadian process metaphysician would say the series is a series of comings-to-be (rather than a series of beings as some Buddhists suggested). The present moment includes, as parts, the beings that previous members of the series brought to be plus new input from others. No doubt most students will not be able to follow the second step of the argument to its end, since this means coming to a satisfactory answer to all the philosophical problems. But this is why the theistic issue is so important: It forces all the other issues (including those in value theory) to be clarified. Not the least of these is the clarification of what philosophy is: 164 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 22: Modal Argument The one discipline trying to discover what the necessary or unavoidable propositions are. They must be discovered, not created, because no reality, not even God/dess, could have made them up (since they are unconditionally necessary). They have always had to be. We either explicitly or covertly teach students there is always a meaningful alternative to every position or belief (the positivists’ position) or there are some beliefs or truths that are unavoidable, that is, necessary (the metaphysical position). This bit of modal logic is being taught, and I think explicitly teaching it is better than avoiding the subject. Chapter Summary Something that must exist, must exist. The real question is not: Does something that must exist, exist? The real question is: Does “something that must exist” make sense? Suggested Reading: Hartshorne, Natural Theology, Anselm’s Discovery, (Hartshorne discusses criticisms of his position), Logic of Perfection, The Divine Relativity, Philosophers Speak of God. ******************************************************************************* Knowing What Cannot Be Known “The unsurpassable can mean many things to many different people. Anselm tried to define it [by saying] the unsurpassable is a necessity because it surpasses contingency, but the unsurpassable cannot exist because everything [moment, or series?] is contingent....Although the human mind is a wondrous thing, if it could figure out what the unsurpassable is, it would become the unsurpassable.... Relatively speaking, when trying to conceive of the unsurpassable, the human mind is too pea-brained to conceive of such a grand notion....The meaning, if any, of the Unsurpassable is meaningless. If humans could find the meaning, what use would it be to us. The meaning of the unsurpassable is useless even if it were to be found. The knowledge of the meaning of the unsurpassable would ultimately be useless....there is no meaning for the unsurpassable.” Student. ********************************************************************* A Process Introduction to Philosophy 165 Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes Star of David Female Pubic Triangle + Male Inversion = Union The hexagram is from India (Kali and Shiva in perpetual sexual union). It reached Judaism through medieval cabalists speaking of the union between God and his spouse (Shekina). It also meant the union of water (female) and fire (male) and so the fertilization of the primordial Deep by lightning, the “fire from heaven.” The hexagram was also a Maya symbol of the sun’s rays, and became officially Jewish only about a century ago, according to Walker (WDMS, 69, 306 and 340). 166 Chapter 23 Theistic Attributes “For in much wisdom is much grief, and he who increases knowledge increases sorrow.” Eccl. 1:18. “Cleanliness is next to godliness.” Cultural aphorism. “What sort of things do you remember best,” Alice ventured to ask. “Oh, things that happened the week after next,” the Queen replied. Lewis Carroll, Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland, The Mock Turtle’s Story. “The divine attributes are abstract types of social relationship, of which the divine acts are concrete instances or relations.” Hartshorne, The Divine Relativity, 156. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– Determining whether “unsurpassability” makes sense, by examining several other suggestions for necessary characteristics of unsurpassability: (1) Unsurpassable as supreme and/or ultimate. (2) All-powerful (omnipotent) and all-good. (3) All-knowing (omniscient). –Approaches– (1) “Supremacy” refers to a concrete whole that surpasses all other wholes at that time. Only the next moment of the unsurpassable series can surpass it. “Ultimacy” refers to abstract characteristics of the unsurpassable series that is always changelessly unsurpassable, even by itself. (2) To be “all-powerful” means to use some (appropriate) power everywhere at all times. “Complete power” anywhere at any time is meaningless. (3) To be “all-knowing” means to know all there is to know. Knowledge of actual situations is supreme. The content of knowledge will be surpassed the next moment when there is more to know, but only by the Unsurpassable him/erself. The series is changelessly (ultimately) always allknowing. –Evaluation– Pro: Distinguishing the supremacy of a Whole from the ultimacy of the series, allows a concept of God/dess that can create and change with no defect. Con: Conceiving of how the moments of the unsurpassable series are in step with world’s surpassable acts, is not obvious (see Chapter 24). ****************************************************************************** A theistic attribute is a characteristic that must be part of the Unsurpassable’s definition. It is, as we might say, a personality trait, but in this case, an unavoidable trait of the all-inclusive person. Any attribute that makes sense in an unsurpassable way is necessarily part of the definition of the Unsurpassable. Because a meaningful clarification of change requires a distinction between the individual as a series of creative wholes and each present whole itself, a distinction must be made between, (1) attributes applying to the series, that is, to all Wholes generally, and A Process Introduction to Philosophy 167 Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes (2) attributes applying only to the most recent or present Whole which sums up the series at that moment. Those attributes describing the series are unsurpassable in the ultimate degree. These attributes are true of the Unsurpassable regardless of time. They are true without reference to any particular Whole or moment of time. The other attributes are unsurpassable in the supreme degree. These attributes refer to concrete actuality, to actual Wholes. They refer to the present state of affairs now unsurpassed (a state of affairs no reality could have conceivably surpassed), though God/dess could have equaled it. The next Whole in the unsurpassable series not only will, but must, surpass all past Wholes since the new Whole must include the old Whole now as a part. The Unsurpassable’s creations are supreme since even the Unsurpassable could not do better (though s/he could have done equally well). Even though nothing can surpass the Unsurpassable, s/he, not only can, but must surpass what s/he has concretely done in previous moments.Attributes may have both an ultimate and a supreme formulation. Take “knowledge,” for example. The Unsurpassable is always, ultimately, all-knowing, but the content of knowledge can only be supreme. So, a theistic attribute must be meaningful either in an ultimate or a supreme sense, and may exhibit both. Ultimate and Supreme An ultimate attribute is one no reality can surpass, not even God/dess –––––––––––––– A supreme attribute is one no reality can surpass except another act of God/dess. The following list contains a few proposals for attributes that have had some historical in terest. They overlap, since understanding one of them requires understanding others. The right-hand column gives the three logical quantifications of the attribute: None, Some and All and how they relate (if they do) to Unsurpassable and surpassable realities, and whether they make sense in any way. Some Proposals for Theistic Attributes 1. Mode of Existence (First Step of the Ontological Argument, see Chapter 22) • logically impossible (not conceivable) • logically contingent (may or may not exist, if conceivable--creatures) • logically necessary (must exist, if conceivable– God/dess) 2. Life span (temporal extent; time is experience of succession, of other moments within, or part of, one’s present moment) • none (never exists at all) • some time a. beginning and ending (all moments begin and end) b. beginning but no end (everlasting) (creatures’ acts as retained in the Unsurpassable’s memory) • all time (primordial, no beginning; and everlasting, no end) (God/dess) 3. Form of Endurance • one actuality (minimum maintenance: events in “empty” space) • a series of actualities with a first and last member (creatures) • one Series with no first member nor last member (God/dess) 168 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes 4. Spatial Extent (simultaneous inclusiveness; experience of the external relatedness of others) • none (not conceivable) • some (finite, meaning: fragment) • all (finite Whole––God/dess as concrete) 5. Relations (to) • none (not conceivable) • some (creatures) • all (that were and are and will be related to all that come to be––God/dess) 6. Feeling (caused by) • none (not conceivable) • some (creatures) • all (God/dess) 7. Knowledge (of) (or consciousness of, or feeling of, alternatives) • none (not conceivable) • some (creatures) • all a. all possibilities as actual (impossible; would deny possibilities are real) b. all actualities that are actual and possibilities as possible (God/dess as omniscient) 8. Freedom (power in oneself) • none (not conceivable) • some a. less than most conceivable (creatures) b. most conceivable (God/dess) • all a. only or complete power (not conceivable) b. most conceivable (God/dess) 9. Power (in others) (influence; to flow into or cause) • none (not conceivable) • some power in some (creatures) • some power in all (God/dess as omnipotent) • all in all, or complete power in another (not conceivable) 10. Goodness (appropriate use of power) • none (not conceivable––nothing can be all bad) • some (creatures) • all, or only good a. good because the power does it (power worship). b. done because it is good (God/dess) A Process Introduction to Philosophy 169 Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes 11. Evil (deliberate destruction of future, good possibilities) • none (unreflective creatures) • some (possible for reflective creatures) • all or complete (not conceivable––to do evil requires doing some good or loving something) 12. Suffering (resulting from evil or tragedy) • none (not conceivable) • some (creatures) • all a. only (not conceivable) b. most (God/dess) Unsurpassable suffering is logically supreme because God/dess experiences all the creatures’ sufferings plus the suffering arising from commiseration with their sufferings. “Tragedy” (non-deliberate loss of future good possibilities: bad luck) 13. Happiness • none (not conceivable) • some (creatures) • all a. only (not conceivable) b. most (God/dess’ happiness is logically supreme because God/dess experiences all the creatures’ happiness plus the happiness arising from the enjoyment of their happinesses. 14. Loved (embracing as is) • none (not conceivable) • some (creatures) • all (God/dess) 15. Love (desire to enrich) • none (not conceivable) • some (creatures) • all––as would enrich the Whole (God/dess) 16. Hate (desire not to love) • none (God/dess) • some (creatures) • all (not conceivable; one must love something in order to exist; nonexistence does not hate) 17. Subject (coming-to-be) of others • none (not conceivable) • some (all creatings are subjects of some others) • all (God/dess is experiencing every actuality and possibility) 18. Object (being) in others • none (not conceivable) • some (creatures are objects for some others as objects) • all (God/dess’ creations are experienced by every actuality and experiences the results of all actualities.) 170 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes U nsurpassable Mode of Existence (1). Necessity surpasses contingency, therefore, if the “Unsurpassable” makes sense, s/he can only do so as something necessary. This at tribute was discussed in detail in Chapter 22. U nsurpassable Life Span (2). In the strictest sense, life is the making-of-a-being, and death is the end of the making-of-a-being; it is what is made. Life is the present whole, and death refers to the beings that have been created by other moments of life that are now in, or parts of, the present life. So a “life span” in this technical sense refers to how long a moment takes to finish a creation, what Whitehead calls a “duration.” However, more commonly “life span” refers to a number of momentary lives or moments that are arranged as a lineal series. Each moment begins with many beings and ends in one new being that includes the many it started with. Each series of moments has a first moment and a last moment, each series, that is, except the Unsurpassable who can have no first nor last moment, if the “Unsurpassable” makes sense. Most people have a hard time trying to conceive of “begininglessness.” Yet, trying to conceive of an absolute beginning is even more dif ficult, and for good reason: “Nothingness,” from which the absolute beginning of something must come, is not a meaningful expression, as we have seen several times. Nearly all religious and scientific myths refer to a beginning. But a close examination of them finds a reference to a reality that existed before the creation of the beginning or to a formless state of something existing prior to the creation that forms or orders it. Having something appear out of “nothing” (nonsense) is not part of the general human intuition. Even when the theological God of classical theism supposedly creates the universe out of nothing, he is creating something from something else, namely, himself. If the idea of an unsurpassable life span makes sense, it must be a life span with no first moment nor last moment, otherwise one could conceive of the possibility of a life (series) that began a moment before or will last a moment longer. So even though each moment must have a beginning and an end, there can be no first moment and no last moment. Time is the experience of one actualized being existing inside another, that is, of succession. U nsurpassable Form of Endurance (3). Since much of this book has focused on what it means for something to exist over time, little more need be said here. The attempted concept of one act lasting over time (throughout changes), much less over all time, is not conceivable. To exist for more than a moment is to be a characteristic inherited by a series of moments. An unsurpassable series must be a series that exhibits supremacy in the way each of the moment’s acts and ultimacy in the way the series exists. U nsurpassable Spatial Extent (4). As with any attribute, an attempt to understand what an attribute means in an unsurpassable way, requires one to have some idea of what the attribute means in a surpassable or ordinary way. Space has a long history of nonsense formulations, starting with Democritus and those who think as he did, up to the present: (1) Space is said to be a Void or Nothingness. Parmenides has correctly pointed out that all attempted references to “nothingness” are meaningless. (2) Space is said to be singular: There is only one space. Einstein, for example, argues there can only be one space (spatial-temporal continuum), and before him the cosmic aether was the monistic, ubiquitous stuff of space. (3) Space is referred to as a different kind of being from the many material beings that are “in” the one space. The Michelson-Morley speed-of-light experiments showed empirically that space cannot be identified with one, all-pervasive aether, adding factual evidence to the logical nonsense of monistic space. If space is numerically one over time, then we are trying to conceive of a reality that can be what it is and alter internally since the one space is modified by changes of density, position of objects within it, and so forth. Again Parmenides seems to be right: A being, by whatever name, is just what it is. It cannot be what it is and alter (change) without self-contradiction. Diversity can be experienced successively or simultaneously. Space is the experience of more than one being simultaneously within a moment of creativity. Space is an abstract characteristic of wholes; not a whole itself. Wholes, that is, acts or comings-to-be, are not in space. Space is in acts. Space is an aspect of creative wholes. Reality is not in space. Space is in reality. Spatiality is abstract. Only wholes are actual containers. Surpassable acts are fragments that do not include all the diversity created by previous, contemporaneous acts. A surpassable individual is a series of acts located within the total diversity. It can be said to be “in space.” However, a series of acts wherein each act includes all there is, that is, all other beings in each of its acts, cannot be said to be in space or to be located in space. Reality is at each moment the supreme action of the Unsurpassable who is a never-beginning, never- Copyright 2003 Duane Voskuil A Process Introduction to Philosophy 171 Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes ending series of such supreme acts. All spatiality is in the Unsurpassable. All locations are in the Unsurpassable. There is no distance between what we do and the Unsurpassable. There is no time nor transmission of us or anything (as beings) to the Unsurpassable, so s/he takes no perspective on the world. Space is expanding in the sense that there are always more beings added to the infinite total each moment. Each moment of creating, whether Unsurpassable or surpassable, steps off from the edge of space, reaches beyond relationships already created and makes a new determination (being) that adds to all previous spatiality. Ordinary creating steps off from some others, from some space, and by necessarily excluding from its experience some previous creations, has a perspective on the world. This selection establishes a partiality, a point of view, which the Unsurpassable does not take on the world. If the Unsurpassable did not include all others’ accomplishments as causes in his/er present moment of creating, something would be actual and not part of God/dess’ process of creation, so his/er process would not be “that than which nothing greater can be conceived.” Even though every creaturely moment can only include what some others have just done, one of the others every moment must include as a cause in itself, whether a moment in God/dess’ series or the world, is what the last moment of God/dess just created. See the next chapter for a through discussion of what each moment inherits as it begins its process of creation. U nsurpassable Relationships (5). To exist is to evolve out of, or better, grow around, what two or more30 moments have already done. So someone can only exist as related to others included in oneself. We are only related to some others. An unsurpassable relater would have to be related to all creations created. We, on the other hand, can be mutually causally independent of others, that is, others we don’t include and who don’t include us, what physicists call “contemporaries” (see diagram, Two Intersecting Personal Series, Chapter 13, and Relations in the Glossary). But what the Unsurpassable creates cannot be contemporary to anything already accomplished by others. This would imply something would exist that is not part of the Unsurpassable’s all-inclusive, present Whole. A larger whole that did include all accomplishments could be conceived. This all-inclusive Whole would then be “that than which nothing greater can be conceived” at this m o m e n t . It would be the supreme Whole. As 30At least two are required to provide the necessary novelty for the initiation of a new moment. See Voskuil, “Hartshorne, God and Metaphysics” and Chapter 24. comings-to-be, however, not beings that have already come to be, all wholes are contemporaries of all others then in process and so are not parts of, nor causally effective in, another.31 To Be Is To Be Related To Something To exist is to be related to others around which we grow. Others in the future will be related to us by growing around us. ___________ Surpassable realities include some others for some time. The Unsurpassable includes all others always. All spatial/temporal relationships are either internal or external. But for something to be “in” another logically implies the other reality is outside the one that is in it. All relationships cannot be external. Even Democritus, who tried to maintain all relations are external, said all beings are internal to the Void. All mutually external relationships of two or more beings must be in a reality (a process) including the external relationships of others who are contemporaries with each other.32 On the other hand, all relationships cannot be internal or we end up trying to conceive of the Parmenidean Being which could have no diversity since nothing is outside anything else to set up the contrasts we know as space and time. U nsurpassable Feeling (6). Feeling is the most fundamental way moments are related to each other. What one moment does is included in other superseding moments. Inclusion is not just passive acceptance. No thing can be included or experienced without feeling the feelings that the included being is. A being is how a previous moment ended up feeling. That feeling causes the present feeler to feel more or less the way the previous feeler felt (depending on the present moment’s level of freedom and inclusiveness). A complex moment includes many previous feelings. The characteristics created by previous moments (comings-to-be) are inherited by one or more moments. Feelings need not be conscious. Even the most trivial events going on in “space” or within atoms, feel, though they cannot be said to know. Feelings of others are causes in those who feel them. 31The argument, that only moments in their processes of coming to be can be contemporaries, is expanded in Chapter 24. 32Comings-to-be, units of process, however, do exist as contemporaries without existing within another. 172 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes The Unsurpassable feeler feels every feeling that has ever been created; that is, the Unsurpassable is caused by every being that has ever been brought into being and every non-divine feeler feels the Unsurpassable’s feelings. Each moment of the Unsurpassable is a supreme feeling, leaving no feeling out that exists. It will be surpassed, but only by the next supreme feeling in the Unsurpassable’s series. U nsurpassable Knowledge (7). Knowledge is not only feeling what is the case, but also feeling alternatives to what is the case. Unsurpassable knowledge must know all there is to know. What is there to know? Process, or coming-tobe, is not yet. Reality that is not yet being, is not something to know. But all the past is done; it is being. So an omniscient or unsurpassable knower must know all the past. Again, the present process is not yet a thing to know, and neither is the future. This is not to say the future has no reality. It exists, so far as it does, as potentiality. And all potentiality for future actuality exists in present actuality. Possibilities for future acts are not yet acts. Possibilities are never fully specified possibilities. Whitehead seems to speak as if potential acts are specific possibilities which he calls “eternal objects” (see footnote, 25, Chapter 22, p. 160). Hartshorne, however, points out that specifying is what creativity really does. A fully specified potential is a self-contradiction. Once something is fully specified it is determinate; it is an act done, that is, a being in the past. Possibility is generic and continuous. Between any two possible acts an infinity of somewhat different possible acts could be specified. Actuality is atomic or quantified. Every act is finitely different from every other actuality, and from every possible actuality. The present is a continuum of creating. The result of a present moment of creating must result in a finite difference from its inception: a quantum leap. The future, however, is not completely unknowable. We know much about the future because we know the past and present must be included in the future which will cause the future to conform to the acts already done. The further one projects into the future, the less one can know, however, since the accumulated freedoms of the moments up to that increasingly distant time can range over an everwidening volume of potentiality. Possibility is generic and continuous. Actuality is atomic and quantified. Recent mathematical theory called “chaos theory” recognizes the accumulated effect of small differences. As usually stated in chaos theory, these small differences (which have a large and somewhat unknowable effect on the outcome) are differences in the initial conditions of the event. However, a better understanding of change will see each moment as a new beginning adding its own somewhat unknown effect (its own initial condition) to the event’s outcome. Acts already done set limits to what can be done. They also provide opportunities for action. We know something of the future’s limits and opportunities. Unsurpassable knowledge knows all there is to know. However, if one proposes that omniscience knows the future in the same determinate, specific way the past exists, then there is no logical way to separate knowledge of the past from knowledge of the future. God/dess would not know the difference between past and future. They would be the same. So the proposal that the past and future are known in the same way by omniscience, implies either, (1) omniscience must be ignorant of the difference between past and future, or (2) the difference between past and future is not real. To know the future as already settled logically implies either: (1) ignorance of the difference between what is and what is not done, or (2) the unreality of change. Again, either one thing happens after another, that is, successively (the meaning of “time”), or not. If succession is real, then the Unsurpassable (supposedly knowing the details of the future as already settled) would not know succession, and would be ignorant. If succession is not real, then we are in error to think change is real, as Parmenides and many Eastern thinkers assert. Rather than saying the attempted concept of “omniscience” is self-contradictory , as Hartshorne seems to say (OOTM), I would suggest the term means, “knowing all there is to know,” but knowing what there is to know requires a metaphysic to explain what reality is like. The process metaphysic, argued for here, takes creativity as fundamentally real. A creation adds new actuality to reality. Even though the kinds of things that can be created may be knowable, exactly what will be created is not knowable. To know a specific before it has been specified is to know something as done before it is done, that is, to be ignorant of the difference between the settled determinations of the past and the generic quality or openness of the future. S upreme Freedom (8). If determinism or ultrarationalism is an illogical theory of realty, as argued here, then nothing exists unless it is a process exercising some amount of freedom. Even the smallest and most determined events studied by physics cannot be known in detail before they occur. W. Heisenberg’s formulation of the Indeterminacy A Process Introduction to Philosophy 173 Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes Principle (1926) makes clear that physical science cannot be formulated with a deterministic metaphysic. What we are able to know scientifically is always statistical. We can know how large groups of somewhat free moments of reality will generally behave, but never exactly how any one will exactly behave. Freedom Life can be created or destroyed, but freedom is not given nor can it be taken away. To exist at all is to be somewhat free. So what might “unsurpassable freedom” mean? Can it mean a reality that has all the freedom, or a reality that is “completely free” compared to the rest of us who are only partly free? “Complete freedom” would be an act that does not have to consider anything already done. An act done with “complete freedom” would create out of “pure potentiality.” Nothing actual would condition or cause the act. An actor who had all the freedom would imply, of course, the rest of us could have none. Either expression, “completely free” or “completely determined,” is nonsense. So, is “unsurpassable freedom” nonsense? “Unsurpassable freedom” means more freedom than anyone else has, and more freedom than anyone else could possibly have. Since freedom depends on opportunities, and opportunities are presented with the beings one includes in one’s creative acting, it follows that only a reality including all beings, all actualized creations, could possibly have access to the greatest range of possibility for new acts. The one who is caused (that is, conditioned) by all others is the one who is most free. Subatomic events are strongly influenced by only a few others and are the least free of all. Since only one reality can include all others, only one reality can create within the widest range of possibilities, and so this reality is unsurpassable in its exercise of freedom. S/he exercises supreme freedom at each moment. The usual hyperbole in religious discourse about God/dess being the only creator (exerciser of freedom), is self-contradictory if taken literally. Freedom is the power one has in the present moment to affect the outcome of the moment in a range of ways. But one must start with something. Starting with nothing is nonsense. The something started with determines a range of possible outcomes. The Unsurpassable has the greatest conceivable range, not a “completely unspecified range,” which is a meaningless expression. U nsurpassable Power (9). Freedom or creativity is self-power, power to shape the outcome of the moment within a range of possibilities. But we can also speak of a power that controls others. The power one can have in others can either be the power of, (1) force, (2) obligation, or (3) charm (love). If one wanted another to do something, say something simple like move to the other side of room, there are three ways to control the person’s action. The person could be (1) physically forced to move, that is, dragged, (2) s/he could feel obligated to move, fearing the consequences if s/he did not move, or (3) s/he could move because s/he loves to do what you want him/er to do or enjoys the experiences provided at the other end of the room. When looked at closely, the first two kinds of power depend on the last one. One must be charmed to initiate force or obligations. In the military it is called “morale.” When the desire to fight is gone, all the weapons of force are useless. “Unsurpassable power,” in theological circles known as “omnipotence,” means what? For many the attempted definition implies “having all the power.” But this is likely a meaningless expression. Something only exists if it exercises some power, both the power of partial self-creation and the power to partially affect others. If one reality were to have all the power, there would be no others to have power in. It would also mean nothing could influence (flow into or cause) the reality that had no power, so the socalled omnipotent power would be powerless. Love makes the world go ‘round. Give half o’ one to Aristotle. Propositions expressing the exercise of power have two placeholders where logical quantifiers occur. The following sentences exhaust all the combinations (ignoring the uninteresting case of “none”): (1) Having all power in all. (2) Having some power in all. (3) Having all power in some. (4) Having some power in some. The first seems self-contradictory as noted above: A monopoly of power, a reality with only one actor acting, is the attempt to conceive of reality as one thing. The problems Parmenides’ position has, should make one suspect that reality must be essentially social. To say “omnipotence” means “having all power in all” implies the second “all” is referring to nothing (and so is meaningless), since to be one of Change and the Unsurpassable 174 Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes the “all” requires one to be something, or better, to do something, that is, exercise some power. So, to paraphrase number one above: The allpowerful exercises all the power, complete control, in all others who must have some power. Since all and some are logical contradictories, the sentence is not a meaningful proposition. The same reasoning applies to number three. Complete control of even one other means that the other does not exist to control. The fourth proposition expresses surpassable power. We are always exercising some control in others as long as our series of acts continues. Even a actuality not found as part of our own series still affects other events in the field around us that eventually will affect us. It is also swept up into the all-inclusive series and is then a cause in all superseding others of that series forever (see Chapter 24). A moment is able to be an influence in others only because it has had the power to create itself anew. “Omnipotence” means “exercising an appropriate amount of power everywhere at all times.” The second proposition, “having some power in all,” can meaningfully express Unsurpassable power, a power that affects in some way everything else. Some power or influence of the Unsurpassable is found absolutely everywhere at all times. Those who think it is a defect not to exercise all power (whatever that could mean) are valuing power above goodness. "Goodness" means “the appropriate use of power.” More power is not always better. Too much control of others reduces their opportunities for enrichment. Somewhere between negligence and suffocating domination is the appropriate use of power. Parents, teachers, friends and lovers with good intentions are always trying to find the right amount of control or influence. Those who are successful are good. U nsurpassable Goodness (10). Many youngsters learn the invocation: God is good; God is great. What could it mean to be the greatest conceivable goodness? To paraphrase Plato (Socrates) in his Euthyphro, is God good because God is great (powerful), or is God great (unsurpassable) because God is good? (1) Are God’s acts good because God does them, or (2) does God do what God does because they are good things to do? The first formulation is clearly power worship, equivalent to the parent who responds to a child asking why s/he should do something with, “Because I said so.” Might makes right, versus Right dictates might. If the Unsurpassable does things because they are good, the meaning of “good” has never been created; it must have always been since the Unsurpassable has always been. This is why the definition of what it means to be fundamentally valuable can only be expressed with necessary propositions. For now, say the meaning of positive value, that is, goodness, means “enriched experience,” or experience that satisfies the basic aesthetic cannon of unified diversity (see Chapter 18). Valuable experience has depth by way of repetition of spatial (contemporaneous) and temporal (successive) characteristics, and breadth by way of novelty, all working together to reinforce each other. But whose experience is to be enriched? There are three possible approaches: (1) The one with the power (as is the case in an authoritarian ethic), (2) The collective (as a utilitarian or democratically structured ethic proposes) or, if the Unsurpassable makes sense, (3) the wholeness of each moment of the Unsurpassable series. Only the Unsurpassable can evaluate all, and only the everlastingness of the Unsurpassable series can forever contain the differences (values) made. Only if one’s differences are kept just as they are, can one’s meaning (differences made) always be just what they are as they logically must be. “Unsurpassably good” means “always creating in only good ways.” The Unsurpassable does things within an unsurpassable range of possibilities. Any act of the Unsurpassable could be otherwise than as it is, but it would have to be as good as any other possible act at that moment. Every level of value has co-equals. “the best” or “the worst” are meaningless expressions, unless they refer to a range or class of co-equal values. Since being good enhances the experience of the Whole (and probably of most parts of the Whole), reality does not disintegrate or become impossible from good influence. B adness: Evil and Tragedy (11). We cannot pick and chose the attributes we would like the Unsurpassable to have. If negative value can have an unsurpassable meaning, it must also be part of the attempted definition. But all the attempts to define “unsurpassable negativeness,” seem to fail because they are self-contradictory. Why is this the case, and how does negative value relate to unsurpassability? Negative value comes from a loss, but the only things that can be lost are future possibilities, since the past is saved changelessly forever as it is. Of A Process Introduction to Philosophy 175 Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes course, only the loss of negative possibilities is bad. No one mourns the loss of an auto accident they might have had coming home. Tragedy Accidental loss of possible future good. No one is to blame. Losses, however, can come about in two different ways: accidentally and deliberately. Accidental loss is best called “tragedy.” No one is to blame. Bad luck is possible in a world that must be populated with somewhat free individuals. Even with the best of intentions and with as much knowledge as one could possibly have, free acts can and do conflict to bring about losses. When no one is obviously to blame for the loss, those, who don’t understand that the world can only exist with creative freedom, “blame” God. The loss becomes, even in legal papers, an “Act of God.” People assume God did it or could have prevented it and so is to blame/praise for it. But unsurpassable power, used in unsurpassably good ways, cannot completely control others nor prevent all possible conflict. Yes, it would be possible for unsurpassable power to exercise power in ways other than the way s/he did exercise power; and, yes, the world could be different. The specific “Act of God” referred to would not have happened. But other possible conflicts would necessarily be part of this hypothetical world, and also necessarily part of any possible world. All negative value must be part of a larger whole, a whole that exists because it has man aged to integrate its influences into a unity with some positive value in spite of the negative. Evil Deliberate prevention of future positive value. To say there is a whole, is to say the negative value, though causing a whole to be less rich than would have been possible, has not destroyed the whole––and all wholes must have some positive value. God/dess does not cause negative value. S/he suffers the loss it brings to the larger context of positive value. Deliberate loss of future positive value is called “evil.” Can we conceive of “unsurpassable evil”? No evil can be so great one could not conceive of having more evil. Since negative value is only negative as it disrupts the amount of positive value of a whole, there must always be some positive value left to disturb. The attempt to conceive of a situation where there is no positive value, is the same as trying to conceive of “nothing,” which, we have seen, is meaningless. This means an evil cannot be created without doing some good, so a reality doing only evil is nonsense. During a summer working on a German farm I asked why Germans put up with Hitler. They said things like, “Hitler built the Autobahn (freeway system)”, a positive value in their mind. At any particular moment there may be an evil that is the greatest evil for that moment, but it could conceivably be (or have been) surpassed, not just during some future moment, but in the present moment. Since evil does not have a supreme or ultimate degree, it cannot be an attribute of the Unsurpassable. Evil personified as the Devil cannot mean a reality that only does evil, whatever misguided comfort the idea may give those who cannot face the tragedy of the world or our own desire to do bad things. S upreme Suffering (12). Suffering is the feeling a moment endures as it inherits loss of value felt by others directly (physical pain) or of conflict with one’s own desires (mental pain). Whether the loss comes from tragedy or evil, it is still suffered. But the sufferer is not made evil because an evil-doer causes him/er suffer. An unsurpassable sufferer would suffer all the sufferings there are. The pain could not kill nor stop the whole from coming to be. If it did, there would be no suffering because the sufferer would be dead. The Whole, we need also to realize, has all the joys there are to experience, and these must always outweigh the pains or the pains would not be in existence since the whole they are in, the whole that keeps them in existence, would have died and felt nothing. God/dess suffers all sufferings. To suffer is not to be evil. Deliberately causing suffering is to be evil Unsurpassable suffering makes sense as supreme suffering only. No actual suffering can be so great that more suffering cannot be conceived. But the present moment of the Unsurpassable does have all the suffering there is. Only in the next moment is it conceivable for the suffering to be greater. Suffering is something no one wants to bear. We often try to handle it by denying our suffering is bad. We may say to ourselves: If only we knew more, we would see it as a good (as God supposedly does). This view of the world makes people neurotic. We often respond to suffering by making others suffer, especially those who we think caused our suffering, as a way to get even. But the Unsurpassable endures all suffering, whether from evil or tragedy, without wishing to pass it on to others, that is, without revenge. Returning suffering, Change and the Unsurpassable 176 Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes deliberately, is evil, and doing so out of ignorance is tragic. Neither evil nor ignorance are capable of being attributes of the Unsurpassable. Yet once creations exist, the most anyone can do is to lessen their influence on future actions––eliminating them from having any affect, is impossible. S upreme Happiness (13). Happiness also, just like suffering, can be unsurpassably conceived, but only as supreme. “Ultimate happiness” is nonsense. No happiness can ever exhaust all possible happinesses. However, the Unsurpassable is changelessly the reality that enjoys every change, including all happinesses. This is an ultimate expression, because its meaning does not depend on any particular moment. God/dess necessarily enjoys all enjoyments. So the Unsurpassable is both the greatest conceivable sufferer and enjoyer. Life is always a mixture. One possible meaning of the Christian christology is that God suffers, not just some things, but everything there is to suffer. But, even so, life triumphs over tragedy and evil, and all value is stored forever in “heaven” (the Unsurpassable). “Hell” cannot be a place apart from the Unsurpassable, and “heaven” cannot be a place the Unsurpassable is in or it would surpass the so-called unsurpassable. God/dess must include as part of his/er reality all there is, or s/he would be surpassable by something that could. That which is in something is surpassed (in some way or other) by that which contains it. U nsurpassable Love–Embracing As Is (14). Love is two-sided, reflecting the dipolar nature of every creating whole. Love takes the beings others have created and makes them parts of one’s self. Each process must begin with what others have done, so each moment must love something or other to exist at all. We love or embrace some things. An unsurpassable love must embrace all that there is, the very meaning of “uni-verse.” The poem Paul quotes in 1 Cor. 13 expresses much of this aspect of love: Love is patient and kind; love is not jealous nor boastful; it is not arrogant nor rude. love does not insist on its own way; it is not irritable nor resentful; it does not rejoice at wrong, but rejoices in the right. Love bears all things, believes all things, hopes all things, endures all things. Love never dies; [everything else will cease], but when the perfect comes, the imperfect will pass away. Rather than “pass away,” the imperfect is contained in the fullness of the perfect, complete life of the Unsurpassable. And though love “bears” and “endures,” it also hopes and works for the joys of the loved ones. Love is also balanced between concern for oneself and others. Too much self-sacrifice or selfeffacing will only generate resentment in the long run which is definitely not a pleasant feeling to give to any loved one. Loving others as oneself, not instead of oneself, is still a good rule for us. It really comes down to the same thing as loving the Unsurpassable. We are always loving some others in some way, namely, those we embrace as we begin each moment of our series. But we are always loving or embracing the Unsurpassable as an unavoidable influence in our creativity. We include the Unsurpassable (as each process of creating begins) and become part of the Unsurpassable (in the results each moment creates). In between the influences at the inception of a moment and its determinant result, we are somewhat free. Love embraces––Love desires. We may need to grow up and put away childish ways of loving, but the Unsurpassable lover is always fully aware. We see as if looking in a cloudy mirror (as Paul quotes Plato, 1 Cor. 13:12), but insofar as we understand the meaning of “unsurpassability,” we see face to face. U nsurpassable Love–Desire To Enrich (15). Embracing (Whitehead’s term is “prehending”) can never be a passive reception of another. We feel what we include, not only what it is, but for what it can be. Someone who is good, desires to return what has been loved back into the world beyond their present moment with more positive value added than was received. The momentary lover’s desire is to further the enrichment of future lovers, be they moments in one’s own series, others’ series or God/dess’ series. The Unsurpassable lover desires to further the value of those in the world as they are experienced and evaluated together within the unsurpassed Whole of each moment. God/dess’ desire for the welfare of others cannot be surpassed. It is always as good as any other desire s/he could have at that moment. Change and the Unsurpassable 177 Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes Interaction of God/dess and the World All actualities must include or embrace the being that God/dess has created and given to the world to experience. We all must love God/dess (and be loved by him/er) whether or not we know it. Knowing it, and knowing what it means to be alive and be enjoyed by God/dess forever, gives one the additional enrichment Hartshorne calls “worship.” This knowledge, and the emotions it carries, is the meaning of living a sane life, of being “saved.” Copyright 2003 Duane Voskuil 178 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 23: Attributes H ate (16). In order to hate something or some one, one must first know (take in) what one is hating. So, in order to hate something, one must have first embraced it, that is, loved it to some degree. Hate has two sides: (1) Hate is the desire not to love what one has loved, and what one is still loving in some way. Hate is loving (desiring) to get rid of, desiring to stop some desire. The Unsurpassable cannot desire to exclude anything. The Unsurpassable cannot desire to be something other than what s/he must be, namely, allinclusive. If even one thing could be excluded from the Unsurpassable, s/he would not be that than which nothing greater can be conceived. Something could conceivably exist that would include both the excluder and the excluded. The logical opposite of love is not hate. It is indifference, and the Unsurpassable cannot be indifferent to anything. Hate, ultimately, is a neurotic, self-destructive emotion, a sick form of love. Hate regrets former loves. Hate loves others to suffer. (2) Hate is also a desire for revenge, an attempt to balance out the pain one feels because one is not able to be indifferent to the one hated. This supposed balancing out is called “justice.” In reality, that is, within the Unsurpassable’s experience, every pain is added to every other. One pain does not cancel out another. The notion of “balance” or getting even is myopic confusion. Furthermore, if the Unsurpassable were to desire another be in pain because the other is causing pain for him/er, the unsurpassable would be desiring to cause pain to him/erself, since every pain anywhere must be felt by the Unsurpassable. No hate can desire to dismiss everything since one can never stop loving, in some degree, those who make it possible to hate in the first place, namely, one’s own brain cells. So “unsurpassable hate” is not meaningful, and cannot, therefore, be an attribute of the Unsurpassable. As difficult as it is for us to suffer without striking out to hurt others, the real heroes among us are those who are strong enough to suffer, whether from tragedy or evil, without desiring to cause others to suffer. S upreme Subjects–Comings-To-Be (17). A (momentary) subject feels something others have done and a range of possibilities that it might become. All subjects are momentary as some Buddhists and Whitehead point out. The Unsurpassable, as a lasting reality, is the unsurpassable series of Subjects, not one subject that changes. Each moment of the series exhibits the characteristics of being a subject in a supreme way. Each supreme Subject contains all the beings (objects) that all other previous subjects have made, including the all the supreme Objects created by previous Subjects in the unsurpassable series. Since each supreme Subject contains everything there is, it contains the ways that objects are related to each other, both externally (spatially) and internally (sequentially, that is, temporally). The supreme Subject necessarily compares every object to all the others. All comparison is evaluation, that is, feeling a certain way along various continua of possible ways to feel, such as some degree of pleasantness, intensity, nearness, urgency, and so forth (see Hartshorne’s Five Dimensions, Chapter 3). Subjects must include objects; never vice versa. Objects can only be found in subjects. Besides containing all completed actualities, each supreme Subject contains or exhibits all the metaphysical “objects,” that is, universal characteristics of all actual and possible acts. 33 In this way the potentiality for all future acts and the meaning of possibilities not yet fulfilled is also contained in each present supreme Subject. But every subject is dipolar. It not only contains actual and potential objects, it creates a new complex object. Each subject is fundamentally a coming-to-be containing beings previously come to be. Even though no moment of reality can exist without each pole of this contrast of being/becoming, the two poles are not on equal footing. If they were, they would exhibit a dualism with no fundamental unity. Beings (objects) are always part of, or within, some subject. As soon as a subject has satisfied its process, the being (the determination that is the end result of the process) is already in some other coming(s)-to-be. S upreme Objects–Beings (18). The simplest object would be a small quantity of one quality felt by a subject. The particular quality an object has (as felt by a present subject), was determined to be as it is by previous subjects. But subjects feel more than one quality at a time and create objects for others to feel that contain complex relationships of qualities. The Unsurpassable is a supreme Subject at each moment that creates the supreme Object of the moment. Each divine Subject contains all the objects of the past. The being (object) created by each moment of the unsurpassable series is an object for 33In an attenuated sense, all potentiality is in every subject, a rewriting of Anaxagoras’ idea that every thing is in everything. An argument can be made that every actuality will be in every future actuality, since all are in the Unsurpassable and every actuality includes the Unsurpassable’s actuality. See Chapter 24. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 179 Chapter 23: Theistic Attributes every subject from then on, including the next creative process of the unsurpassable series. Objects only exist within subjects, never floating around, as Democritus said, in a subjectiveless void. Objects cannot get into other objects already made. To do so would change the past. But objects are parts of subjects, and subjects come to be, that is, they make new determinate reality around the objects that are actualized already. So in this way beings that come to be (objects) can be found in, or surrounded by, other objects. makes sense. But if it fails to make sense, it will fail for reasons quite different from those usually given. I think it makes more sense than any other metaphysical proposal and more sense than all attempts to deny metaphysical knowledge. But clarity is always a matter of degree. The next chapter explores some problems with the process metaphysic, especially how the unsurpassable series can relate to the world’s series and be omniscient. The Unsurpassable surpasses him/erself unsurpassably. S ummary and Problem. Perhaps this review of proposals for meaningful attributes has not settled the question Anselm so quickly dis missed, namely, whether “That Than Which Nothing Greater Can Be Conceived” is an expression that Chapter Summary If every concept had an opposite, then the concept that all concepts have an opposite must also be meaningful. This nonsense was examined in Chapter 3. The Unsurpassable exhibits all concepts that have meaning in an unsurpassable way. Not all concepts admit of an unsurpassable degree. Evil, the deliberate destruction of value, can’t be ultimate since the absence of any value is “nothingness” which is nonsense. Evil can’t be supreme, either, because no matter how evil one is, one could conceivably have been more destructive at that moment. “Supreme” means the characteristic under consideration can be surpassed, but only by a later moment, and only by a later moment of the unsurpassable series. The present unsurpassed moment exhibits the characteristic fully at that moment. More happiness may be created than now exists, but not even the Unsurpassable can have more happiness at this moment since no more exists. Whether or not “necessarily existing” makes sense depends on whether all the concepts that have an unsurpassable meaning are also all meaningful together. This is the coherence of the various aspects of the concept. Clarity on this, as on any subject, will always be partial, but even to say this with meaning requires we know what “nonpartial” or “completeness” means. The proposal here is that “complete clarity” is how the Unsurpassable knows. Suggested Reading: Hartshorne, Natural Theology, Anselm’s Discovery (Discusses criticisms of Hartshorne’s position), Logic of Perfection, The Divine Relativity, Philosophers Speak of God. Griffin. **************************************************************** Haiku Two The utterable Flows glibly––The Other is Lisped in mute stutters. Duane Voskuil 1966 180 Chapter 24 Problem How God/dess and the World Interact “No two actualities can be torn apart: each is all in all...the perfected actuality passes back into the temporal world, and qualifies this world so that each temporal actuality includes it as an immediate fact of relevant experience....What is done in the world is transformed into a reality in heaven, and the reality in heaven passes back into the world.” Whitehead, PR, Part V. “The ’ontological principle’....is the principle that everything is positively somewhere in actuality, and in potency everywhere.” Whitehead, PR, Part II. Emphases added. “...Indetermination, rendered determinate in the real concrescence, is the meaning of ‘potentiality.’ It is a conditioned indetermination, and is therefore called a ‘real potentiality.’” Whitehead, PR, Part I. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– (1) How the moments of the unsurpassable series of cosmic creatings interact with the countless moments of the world. (2) The relation of relativity physics and the physical conservation laws to metaphysics. –Approaches– (1) Every moment of God/dess’ series must begin before any actual entity in the world ends, that is, each actual entity’s temporal duration in the divine series must be as short as, or shorter than, any other actual entity’s duration, and (2) Each moment of God/dess’ series must begin by inheriting all the beings created up to that moment (including God/dess’ own past and every worldly creation), and (3) Each nondivine actual entity, as it begins, must inherit all that God/dess has done, and all of what some others have just done (that is, it must begin with all of every being contiguous to its initiation–which is a unique set for every actual entity sets up its unique perspective and goal. (4) Physical relativity theory and conservation laws are compatible with process metaphysic if they are not taken to be metaphysically general themselves. –Evaluation– Pro: (1) Requiring the temporal durations of God/dess’ actual entities to be as short as, or shorter than, any other, and requiring every actual entity to inherit all of each it does inherit, assures every being will be saved, and ultimately forever in the all-inclusive series of God/dess. (2) Physical relativity theory and conservation laws need not be metaphysically general, and the restricted truth they contain is interpretable within the process metaphysic. Con: Some may not be convinced the arguments given are more than ad hoc suggestions to save the system. ****************************************************************************** O ne major problem of concern to process philosophers who take theism seriously is the way the unsurpassable series of all-inclusive creative moments is able to embrace all beings created by all the world’s processes without loss, and how every actual entity can be influenced by the Unsurpassable’s creations. Beings can only be experienced or embraced by the Unsurpassable (as with any actual entity) after they have come to be. The process-of-creating-abeing is not an object for another to experience. Yet A Process Introduction to Philosophy 181 Chapter 24: Problem the countless number of sur passable processes of the world may, it seems, begin and end at different times. So, how long can a processing moment of the Unsurpassable series endure if God/dess must gather up all the beings others create as they are created? “Instantaneous” process is meaningless, so divine processes must have some temporal extension. However, they can’t be so long other moments come to be between the Unsurpassable’s determinations, or the Unsurpassable would not contain or know all the beings created. How the moments of the Unsurpassable series and the world interact is related to another problem: How can omniscience and the Category of Transmutation (which eliminates detail from experience), be reconciled? I’m convinced Transmutation can’t be a metaphysical category since the Unsurpassable can’t exhibit it (see Appendix 3; Chapter 13, the Complex Actual Entity diagram; and Voskuil, Whitehead’s Metaphysical Aesthetic). Some readers may want to skip the following technical discussion and go on to the next chapter. P reliminaries to a Proposed Answer. The best answer I have to the interaction problem considers the following: (1) A being, once made, cannot sit around by itself waiting to be included in a process. Being is simultaneously the terminal result of a process and the initial conditioning of subsequent processes. Every being must continue to condition some processes or other forever. If beings could exist on their own, process philosophy would flounder on the incoherency of Dualism (see Glossary). Even if the problems of dualism were avoidable, there would still be something in existence unknown to God/dess until the next cosmic moment intercepted it, so omniscience would fail. Objects, that is, beings, can only get into a process as the process begins. Once a process is underway conditioned by its causal base of being, only its own creative freedom shapes the final outcome of the whole. A being, as it comes into being as the satisfaction of a process, must be immediately in another process. If it isn’t, a being has lapsed into “nonbeing” (or being and process are two independent, dualistic realities), which is nonsense. (2) The Unsurpassable is a series of Wholes. All attempts to say the Unsurpassable is only one whole that changes by the addition of new acts as they are created by the world, fail, even though Whitehead seems to say God/dess is one such actual entity. Such an approach would violate, (a) his system which only allows a moment to be affected at its inception by others’ creations, (b) how an actual entity affects another, namely, by reaching a determinate satisfaction that is then an object for others. Once a process has come to be, it is an object and ceases to exist as a processing whole. (c) the meaning of a “whole.” A whole is a reality that can’t alter without self-contradiction. The reasoning for this, was extensively presented in the earlier chapters on change. Allowing God/dess to be an exception to the metaphysical system, as has been the style in theology and philosophy for millennia, is not acceptable. God/dess’ uniqueness lies not in violating the metaphysic, but in being its only possible, unqualified exemplification. (3) There must be a finite duration between the beginning and end of God/dess’ moments. The Unsurpassable can’t be, (a) a series of moments occurring “infinitesimally fast” as some Buddhists would have us believe, nor (b) one actual entity that never began and continues on forever like a Heraclitian flux. Still, each duration of an actual entity in the unsurpassable series must be as short as any other in order to assure every being is included before it is lost at the hands of occasions that cannot inherit all the past, nor retain all the past they inherit. S olving the Interaction Problem. In addition to the principles of a process metaphysic above, the following concepts must be carefully considered: (1) Each actual entity of the unsurpassable series must begin just as the previous one of the series ends. The end of one must be the beginning of another to maintain omniscience of the Unsurpassable’s own past. The demarcation of one process from the other Whitehead calls the “subject/superject:” The satisfaction of one is the instantaneous initiation of the next moment of the divine series. (2) Every actual entity (coming-to-be) must start with what previous entities have accomplished (that is, their being). Starting from “nothing” is nonsense, and starting merely from the determination made by one previous actual entity is equally impossible since with no novelty, there can be no new actuality. Why this is the case is explained further on below. (a) Each actual entity of the divine series must start with all the beings just created, including all the being just created by the previous member of the divine series itself. (b) Each actual entity of the world must start with some of the beings just created, including all the being just created by the previous member of the divine series.34 34The diagram in Chapter 23, Interaction of God/dess and the World, shows each fragmentary actual occasion including only some of the most recent being created by God/dess. I have come to believe that including only part of a being is not possible because every being is a continuum of potentiality. 182 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 24: Problem (3) Every actual entity must end with all that it accomplished remaining in existence as potency for others. No process can end without another accepting hasevery actual the gift of being it So, created. entity must end with the beginning of some moment of the unsurpassable series (4) Having an all-inclusive Whole start at the end of each randomly occurring act (an act that may end with no way of predicting when, and an act probably out of step with countless others in the world), stretches credulity to the limit. This is so for the following reasons: (5) Potentiality is never pure nor absolute but always a function of what beings are inherited, and there never was a time when “nothing” existed to be inherited. So all potentiality is “real potentiality” which is the range of possible outcomes for a particular moment. Every actual entity must begin with some predetermination of its potency. An actual entity’s range is determined by which beings are contiguously inherited by the moment in addition to its inheritance of God/dess’ creation. (6) No actual entity can exist without a subjective aim, the feeling of real potentiality for its outcome. But since potentiality is continuous, 35 all potentiality must have some degree of relevance. Potentiality is one, not a multiplicity. Looking at the diagrams, Interaction of God/dess and the World, (Chapter 23) and the one below, Cosmically Mediated Influence, notice that a moment of creating steps off from a creation of a cosmic Whole, not just from a previous moment of one’s own series, nor even from what one has done and from what others in one’s contiguous world have done. So every subjective aim, every actual entity’s feeling of real potentiality, whether of a moment of God/dess or one in the world, will have a feeling of potentiality that will include, (a) all the potentiality presented by the cosmic unity of being created by the previous moment of divinity, and (b) the potentiality presented by other actual entities that are spatio-temporally prior and contiguous to it. Since every satisfied actual entity is contiguous to the next moment of the unsurpassable series, ((1)) God/dess has a subjective aim conditioned by all the beings that exist, and so has the widest possible range of real possibility, which also means s/he has no perspective on reality, whereas ((2)) all other actual entities can only be contiguous to some of the determinations (beings) just made by previous moments of the world. Their range of real potentiality is restricted, which means they must have a perspective on reality. (7) Every actual entity must begin with a unique combination of being. Doing (“redoing”) exactly what one actuality has done before, or doing exactly what another is doing, is meaningless. (8) Every actual entity is influenced by (contains the results of) others. (a) Every actual entity in the unsurpassable series is influenced by the results of, ((1)) all others from the infinite past as mediated by the most recent divine accomplishment (all of these now mediated were at one time directly embraced by God/dess just as they reached their satisfied determinations), and by ((2)) all others directly that have just reached their satisfied determinations that were contemporaries of the previous divine moment. (b) Every actual entity (except those in the unsurpassable series) ((1)) is influenced by the results of all others from the infinite past as mediated by the divine accomplishment (most of these were never immediately embraced), but only by ((2)) is influenced by the results of some others directly (without mediation) that have just reached their satisfied determination, namely, those spatio-temporally prior and contiguous to the new moment. Actual entities in the world must end with the exact beginning of some moment or other of the unsurpassable series. This proposal, that all actual entities in the world must begin (whenever they do) with the last accomplishment of the unsurpassable series, and end exactly in step with the beginning of some moment or other of the divine series, assures omniscience and no loss of being. Diagramming every actual entity as including all of God/dess, can be very confusing, however. A attempt is otentiality and Death. A further point, made below in the diagram, Cosmically Mediated process, once started, Influence. Though every actual entity includes all of what (1) must continue until it reaches a new state of God/dess has done, only that which is also created by completion with the creation of a new being, or contiguous fragmentary moments has much impact on the (2) die with no accomplishment. present. P 35Not a multiplicity of specifics, “eternal objects,” as Whitehead often seems to say. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 183 Chapter 24: Problem Whitehead seems to deny that death of a process is possible without the moment creating a new being once it starts. If he’s right, then the permanent death of a series would only occur because no new moment in the series could start, rather than dying because its last moment was unable to make a result once it had begun. Temporary death of a series occurs (a) when a moment of a creature’s series fails to begin contiguously with the end of the previous moment of the series, but (b) when a moment does eventually occur that inherits the results of previous members of the series. The lapse could be microseconds or years. The proposal that a whole, a coming-to-be, can fail to come to be or reach even a minimal satisfaction of the potentiality it began with, may be a questionable hypothesis. At issue is whether one can refer to potentiality for a new accomplishment as a real potential, a real sub jective aim, if it could fail to accomplish anything. If it must fail, the moment had no potentiality for fulfillment. Even if a process can have the possibility of failure within its range of real potentiality, this could only be possible with a couple qualifications: ((1)) The Unsurpassable, could not have the possibility of failure in his/er range: The unsurpassable series is necessary. The other qualification is that ((2)) all creatures could not fail to come to be: Some world or other is necessary. D iscussion of the Proposal. Every moment, including those of the cosmic series, must begin by including everything the last cosmic moment just accomplished. Every actual entity must end in step36 with the cosmic series at some (not necessarily all) of the series’ subject/superject 36Being “in step” here does not mean the actual entities have to be occurring at the same rate, only that the unsurpassable series is occurring at least as fast as any others, and that all other series be in step either as subharmonics (beginning with one and ending with some other moment of the divine series) if the creaturely moments are temporally contiguous. If moments of a series in the world are not successively contiguous, (or if a moment is not a member of series), they still must end as some cosmic moment begins (regardless of when the processes begin). Science News, 2/21/98, Vol. 153, No. 8, contains an interesting article by Bruce Bower, “All Fired Up: Perception May Dance to the Beat of Collective Neuronal Rhythms.” Evidence is accumulating that “widely scattered neural clusters build a foundation for perceptual binding by synchronizing their electric discharges....rhythmic electric output among far-flung neurons lies at the heart of visual perception and perhaps other aspects of thought...and my act...as an information gate in the brain....” Such empirical evidence cannot establish metaphysical truth, but it may be an interesting illustration of a basic truth: Coordination of a complex environment requires the elements of the complex be presented simultaneously. Also see Llinás, 30. transitions in order to be included without loss in the cosmic series. However, every actual entity must also be grounded differently from every other: Each must begin with a somewhat unique physical base of being, which establishes its unique subjective aim, its feeling of real potentiality. Every aim will be unique even though every process must include the same cosmic result. The uniqueness of the unsurpassable series is not its ability to experience all the divine past (while others only experience some). Such a proposal would ignore two necessities: (1) Being is a determination which a present moment creates, but is immediately potency for all future creatings; and since potentiality is continuous, any moment that supposedly experiences part of a being must in reality contain (be influenced by) the whole being. (2) The Unsurpassable’s experience of the infinite history of reality (as contained in the last moment of his/er series) is not sufficient to be grounds for a new divine moment: The novelty necessary to establish a new and unique subjective aim would not exist. Experiencing again exactly what was previously experienced is meaningless. To experience what was done, exactly as it was done, is possible, but only if it is experienced along with something new so the whole experience of the actual entity, as it repeats the past, is unique. As Hartshorne points out, a whole that combines old and new is new. The uniqueness of the divine case, has to do with his/er ability to experience all the contemporaneous multitude of surpassable creations that have just come to be rather than merely some which is the lot of all others. Though every actual entity must begin by completely embracing all of the last moment of the divine series, only one actual entity can extend over and embrace the complete multiplicity of creations the world has just brought into being, namely, an actual entity in the unsurpassable series. Every other actuality can only include or extend over some of that multiplicity, namely, those that are contiguous to it. Those embraced must always be, (1) fewer than all (to logically distinguish it from a moment of the unsurpassable series); and (2) a somewhat different selection from any other actual entity (to distinguish it from that entity); however, (3) it may include many in its selection that others have also included. The possibility of communication and the solidarity of the universe we experience, result from these intersecting inclusions. Even though we all must inherit the complete cosmic creation, each nondivine moment is unique by having a perspective, a perspective that provides the variety necessary for cosmic experience. The world’s novel contribution is necessary, for without the Change and the Unsurpassable 184 Chapter 24: Problem world’s new creations, as noted above, there would be no novelty to initiate the next moment for God/dess. With only the perfect memory of the previous cosmic Whole’s result, a new coming-to-be could not begin. Though everyone in the world must inherit the same beings of the one and only cosmic series, God/dess need only inherit some world or other. Any world, or state of the world will do, so long as all that has happened is inherited. Every moment must not only begin by embracing all of the last cosmic creation, it must also end by contributing all it has done to actual entities occurring after it. Though some actual entities in the world can inherit some (perhaps all—see footnote 33, page 181) of what another has done for some time, only the unsurpassable is logically able to embrace all that has been done, and continue to do so forever. So, every actual entity must end as some moment of the divine series begins. All moments that end with the beginning of a cosmic moment will be taken into the new divine moment (including the result of the previous cosmic Whole). This fulfills the requirement of omniscience and assures that all creations are saved, even when the world fails to maintain them. We can only begin to exist by ingesting all the divine and some neighbors. –––––––––o––––––––– What we become can only remain in existence forever by way of the divine’s complete ingestion of us. B eing’s Availability. What if omniscience were nonsense, so actual entities need not end in step with some divine moment? The many beings created by the welter of processes in a person’s immediate environment are not likely to reach their satisfactions at the same instant. So where could their beings reside before another includes them? Some moment or moments in the environment could retain the beings (or some of them) until experienced by a moment that overlaps and embraces that region, so most of the beings of the region would be available even if the many processes do not end just as overlapping and superseding moments begin. This would be possible because the being another has in its process is still available for inclusion in other processes (even though process itself is not an object for another to experience). Just because an actual entity, m, includes the results of others, that is, their beings, does not preclude those beings from being accessible as another actual occasion, n, begins contiguous to beings contained in m at any stage in the process of m. However, if a being is not carried forward, either (1) because no process begins that includes the being, or (2) because a process eliminates what it inherited as it proceeds, or (3) because the process including the being dies before carrying it forward long enough for it to be inherited by another, there would be a major problem with the metaphysical system, since once a being exists, it, or any part of it, cannot become nonbeing. Having some processes in the world inheriting some others’ results and only for awhile, does not satisfy the necessary requirement that being remain forever just as it is. The nonsense of “being becoming nonbeing” is avoided if an all-inclusive experiencer makes sense. Even though each moment of the cosmic series must begin immediately upon the satisfaction of its predecessor, there is no logical necessity for actual entities in the world to be so tightly related. Actual entities in the world can begin at any point, since all of what has been done is retained by each all-inclusive process of the Unsurpassable, so all beings are constantly available for other actual entities to inherit since they all are in the last creation of the unsurpassable series. And even though each moment of the divine series must begin immediately upon the completion of the previous one, a surpassable series may have gaps, since the beings (that are eventually inherited by the next moment of a creature’s series) have at least been retained by God/dess making them available for others. A Process Introduction to Philosophy Chapter 24: Problem Synchronization All’s Well That Ends Well Temporary death of a surpassable series is logically possible. A body is one’s immediate environment. It supports the possibility of the series by retaining an order sufficient for another moment of the series to occur. Lapses between moments of a creature’s series may be common, but each moment of the unsurpassable series must be contiguous to the next. Logically, there is no necessity for a process to begin at any set instant relative to the divine rhythm, nor must it begin exactly at the instant other processes in the world end. The logical requirements for a theistic process metaphysic are satisfied so long as the end of every process, worldly and divine, is instantaneously inherited by the next moment of the unsurpassable series: Every satisfaction of every subject must always be a “superject” (in Whitehead’s vocabulary) in God/dess. An actual entity (other than one of God/dess) can begin at any point (by extending over and inheriting the beings contiguous to it, always including the last unsurpassed creation) because, (1) it is not possible for a surpassable process to inherit all that the beings that were created contemporaneously with the last divine process, (2) some of the beings created by others in the world will be saved by moments in the world, and (3) what is retained by others is available to be inherited at any point in their process durations (as is also the case with the divinely created and retained being). Again, the only logical constraint required by this metaphysic, is that no actual entity can end until some moment of the Unsurpassable begins, which assures the moment’s creation is, and will be fully forever, what it is. Here is a good example of how philosophical problems are focused by consideration of the cosmic or unsurpassable dimension. If the reader has made it this far, s/he will see that philosophy is not a set of facts or rules, but is an ongoing process of clarification of the basic notions to which we appeal to make sense of our existence. 185 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 24: Problem Cosmically Mediated Influence Action at a Distance 186 A Process Introduction to Philosophy 187 Chapter 24: Problem M ultiplicities and Perspective. At each transition from subjectivity to objectivity, measured by the rhythm of the cosmic series, a complex multiplicity of beings form the physical base for all the processes that will come to be the next moment. At this transition there are three possible situations (see the diagram above, Cosmically Mediated Influence): (1) Subgroups of the multiplicity of beings (including the last cosmic being) exist too unorganized to allow any process with limited creative ability to use their potentiality to make a new being. More inclusive and more creative processes may include these subgroups, and they are always part of the next all-inclusive process of the unsurpassable series. (2) Another all-inclusive process of the unsurpassable series prehends all the beings of the multiplicity without loss. It contains no “negative prehensions,” in Whitehead’s language. It is contiguous to (extends over) all that has come to be. (3) Each less-than-all-inclusive process takes a unique perspective on the universe by embracing subgroups that must include, (a) all of the cosmic unification of the previous multiplicity, but only (b) some of the results just created by the world, that is, those contiguous to it. Every actual entity is affected by all the be ing included in the cosmic creation. All of the cosmic creation is part of the actual world initiating every process since the cosmic result is a Whole, indivisible and unavoidable by its omnipresence. Every actual entity (other than one in the unsurpassable series) is completely u naffected b y creations that are contained for the first time in the present cosmically inclusive process (since they have not yet been given back to the world as parts of a cosmically created satisfaction/being for all to feel), unless they are directly embraced. But an actual entity can only be directly affected by some of the world’s beings, namely, those in the environment contiguous to it, which sets up its “perspective.” Perspective is a function of, (1) which beings are contiguous to a new moment, that is, those directly embraced, and (2) which part of the cosmic potentiality is enhanced as most relevant at each moment for each actual occasion’s subjective aim, that is, which aspects of the whole volume of potentiality are “real” for that moment. Embracing only some of the beings others have created (except for the Unsurpassable) enhances some aspects of the total realm of potentiality and changes potentiality-in-general into the real and unique potentiality found in each subjective aim. Perspective may be further enhanced by the moment’s own creative process, by the simplification of Transmutation, for example. For processes that are not all-inclusive, and in light of the proposal that such processes may fail to come to a satisfaction: (1) Some actual entities may have a range of possible outcomes which will include the possibility of failing to make anything new. They may bite off more than they can chew, as the saying goes. (2) Some (including, especially, every moment of God/dess) will have a range of possible outcomes which excludes the possibility of failing to make anything new, though some of these will be less enriched than possible, (a) because of unfortunate circumstances (which God/dess also must always inherit and suffer) or (b) because of deliberate misuse of freedom (possible only for creatures). P hysics and Metaphysics. Relativity physics claims (1) there is no privileged standpoint in the universe ordering temporal succession, and (2) there is no such thing as action at a distance, that is, effects from one place to another faster than physical transmissions in the world occur, which is likely the speed of electromagnetic transmissions in space. But, the cosmically inclusive God/dess does not have a standpoint in the universe. All other actual entities do have such a standpoint in the universe and must, therefore, have objects transmitted to them. Different transmission times require each moment to see causally independent events temporally ordered in different ways, as pointed out above in Chapter 24. All actual entities that are in process are contemporaries and causally independent of each other and of the Unsurpassable. They exist neither in the past nor future of each other. The results of an actual entity, say m, in an Mseries that is contemporary to another, say n, cannot be transmitted instantaneously to another process in, say, series N which is spatially distant from it, that is, not contiguous to it. However, m-satisfied is contiguous with the next moment of the all-inclusive series, and so is instantaneously (immediately) in that process as it begins its process. Only after that contiguous moment of God /dess has reached a satisfaction and is available as a superject for inclusion in all new actual entities, can the result of m be causally effective in some member of the N-series. This does violate the usual interpretation of relativity physics (by saying the effect of m in the N-series is nearly instantaneous 37), 37Griffin (see Bibliographical entry), if I read him right, says, incorrectly, that there is instantaneous transmission from one creature to another. I think he is right, however, to say there is a cosmic, nonperspectival experience of all that exists that sets up a cosmic past and future not incompatible with the observations of physics; it is only incompatible with a physical theory inappropriately pushed to metaphysical generality. 188 Change and the Unsurpassable Chapter 24: Problem but as long as the effect of m in the N-series is slight, physics has no way of ruling it out. As a matter of fact, there are physical experiments that seem to indicate action at a distance quicker than electromagnetic actual occasions in the world can transmit them. One known as Bell’s Theorem is especially intriguing. Twin, “entwined” particles, emitted from an atom must maintain opposite spins or polarizations. One seems to react to the other’s spin determination faster than electromagnetic transmission can occur. An apparatus can trap one of the particles by forcing which spin it will exhibit, and the other will then have the opposite spin, even though the detectors are separated far enough that electromagnetic transmissions from the first detector cannot reach the second detector before the second particle’s spin is determined. What happens in the brain/mind of a human experience is another example of a whole that is simultaneously influenced by it parts, and then influences its parts, simultaneously, the next moment. One part of the brain stimulates an actual entity of the inclusive personal series which at the next moment is a simultaneous cause in each subordinate member of the collective brain. Though I remain rather skeptical of those claiming remote viewing and other reported psychic communications, nothing obvious in this metaphysic can rule it out so long as detailed experience of the future (future to God /dess’ present) or new communications from the dead are not claimed to be possible. Another dogma of physical science that can’t be a metaphysical truth is the absoluteness of the conservation laws. Even though in the world of experimental physics, the rise of new events seems to require the destruction of the old, metaphysical necessity requires the old still be in existence––some in our memory for a while, and all of it in the divine series of experiences forever. Perhaps the conservation laws express the total amount of creative energy available at each moment. When a actual entity reaches a satisfaction, its process of creating ceases. Perhaps its satisfaction requires another to begin. Entropy, the theory that the universe is running down to a state of equilibrium, can’t be a final truth either. It ignores the constant creative building and storing of the past, a constant increase of order and determination out of the generic indeterminacy of potentiality. I hope this technical discussion of some aspects of the process metaphysic will alert the reader to some unfinished avenues of thought waiting to be explored by those who have been captivated by the Adventure of Ideas. Chapter Summary The end of each moment of the Unsurpassable is immediately the beginning of another. All of the cosmically inclusive satisfaction (created Whole) of a moment of the divine series is part of the beginning of all others that begin to exist after that creation. The endings or satisfactions of some perspectival processes or other are at the beginning of some new processes in the world. All processes end at the beginning of some cosmic moment or other. All processes must end with some moment or other of the unsurpassable series because (1) only God/dess can clearly and fully retain all the being created at that moment, and (2) only s/he can retain it forever. All processes must begin with some cosmic creation since the determination of the Unsurpassable’s creation is everywhere. It provides the total realm of potentiality, since potentiality is continuous. Some of this total realm is enhanced for a moment of process by the efforts of others prior and contiguous to it. This enhancement becomes the real range, its subjective aim, of possible outcomes for that moment. Suggested Reading: Voskuil, “Hartshorne, God and Metaphysics,” and “Discussion.” ************************************************************************************** A Process Introduction to Philosophy 189 Chapter 24: Problem Ankh Key of Life Egyptian word for: = Life From Rossini, Egyptian Hieroglyphics, No. 109. The Ankh’s Derivation The t j e t , a sacred, red Egyptian amulet representing the vulva of Isis, the blood of life: or from a Libyan and Phoenician symbol for the Goddess: flow The symbol has also been modified: This symbol, still used for Venus and female gender, is derived from the ankh: The Labarum, a modified ankh, was a favorite symbol for Mithraism (see Chapter 16): Though Rossini gives the origin of the phonetic ankh hieroglyphic as a sandal strap, Walker’s sources (WDSSO) suggest other origins: The ankh was also called the Key of the Nile, standing for the union of Isis and Osiris that initiated the annual Nile flood. It symbolized the key to knowledge about the afterlife, and was the original key “held” (or spoken) by the gatekeepers of the celestial mansions, or of the underworld held by Persephone. The lower part, like a tau cross, was associated with male gender and the upper oval with female. 190 PART VII Epilogue: Beyond Philosophy Ritual: Where Thought Meets Action ––––– Now What? Copyright 2002 Duane Voskuil 191 Chapter 25 Ritual Where Thought Meets Action “A ritual is a patterned, repetitive, and symbolic enactment of a cultural belief or value; its primary purpose is transformation....Ritual is a powerful didactic and socializing tool....Ritual works by sending messages to those who perform and those who receive or observe it.” Robbie Davis-Floyd, Birth as an American Rite of Passage. 8-9. ****************************************************************************** Focus >>• –Issues– Relationship of what one thinks to how one acts. –Approaches– (1) Habits and feelings will dictate actions whenever deliberate determination is weak or missing. (2) The most powerful rituals are often unconscious, and are, therefore, the most difficult to change. –Evaluation– Pro: Ritual behavior is conservative and can mitigate behavior misguided by irrational theory and false information. Con: Ritual behavior is conservative and will perpetuate negative behavior despite attempts to change it guided by rational theory and accurate information. ****************************************************************************** F inding those aspects of reality common to all actual and possible situations, gives one the most general outline for rational thought and action, but such universally general characteristics of reality do not in themselves provide the details for daily activity. Between the general patterns, (which all activity must follow) and the moment to moment creations (which are always partially unique) lie the recurring patterns of life. These patterns are often so ingrained and habitual they seem to be metaphysical. Sometimes they are consciously followed, if not devised. Not surprisingly, when assumptions about the structure and meaning of life are examined and new information is discovered, there is often a need to rethink one’s ritual behavior. Rituals emotionally reinforce behavior patterns that exist before intellectualizing begins, and emotionally reinforce intellectual beliefs we already have. Since life is the flow of feeling, if there is a change in the conditions that generate or reinforce feelings, one feels differently. But we also have feelings about the thoughts we have. These feelings may be out of step with the feelings generated by the rituals one participates in. One may learn that eating differently from the way one does would be healthier, and change the ritual of one’s eating habits. Or one may learn the ritual of hanging stockings by the fireplace for Santa to fill is out of step with the way gifts are really dispensed. Both cases require giving up an old, comfortable pattern. A feeling of loss is inevitable. Either (1) new patterns must be found to compensate for the loss, or (2) the old patterns will be maintained despite the new evidence, since giving up rituals altogether isn’t possible. The pain of the loss and the failure to find new patterns often makes holding on to inadequate rituals the easiest path to take. Yet, this approach can extol a heavy price. My first philosophy teacher was known for saying: “The first generation Christians felt saved by their religion. The second generation Christians (and those since) worked hard at saving their religion.” Consider one of the Christian Church father’s, Tertullian’s, desperate apologetic for Christianity: “It is believable, because it is absurd; it is certain, because it is impossible” (ca. 200 CE ). Change and the Unsurpassable 192 Chapter 25: Ritual However, old ritual patterns are never completely inadequate, so it’s easy to ignore or miss where they may be wrong or inappropriate. And no ritual can exhaust the many equally appropriate ways to express metaphysical truth, even though there certainly are many ways, also, that are inappropriate. There are two dimensions to differences: (1) those that are found along the good-bad dimension, and (2) those that lie on the same level of value. Relativism and tolerance are appropriate for differences on the same level. And since we are all fallible, we must be very careful about intolerance even of those whose differences that seem to be negative. Two Kinds of Differences Differences Differences Good Bad The ritual of formal education often provides for two semesters of instruction which end close to Christmas and Easter, two rituals of importance for many people in our culture. Though a particular religion may interpret the importance of these and other times of year in different ways, one can see a basic theme upon which they are built. Whatever else the Christmas season means to people of the northern latitudes, they cannot escape the loss of light and increase of cold as winter sets in. The winter solstice marks the time when the loss of light is reversed and a new year is born. With it comes renewed hope that “dead” plants and missing animals will return. Without the renewal of warmth and light, we would all die. Rituals emphasizing that hope are nearly universal. Candles, songs, greenery and meals abound; and sexual symbols celebrating the source of life are found everywhere––in red berries, harking to the life-blood of the female, to white berries reminding us of the male seed that grows into new life when sown. In spring, when the day’s length has once again caught up with the night’s, time comes for the hope of life’s rebirth to be actualized. 38 The profusion of life-forms, and especially those very prolific forms, like rabbits, are celebrated as symbols of abundant life. Eggs, an ancient symbol of the universe and source of life, fill our baskets of plenty. The ancient belief that renewal of life only will come if we pay a price, lies at the basis for offerings and sacrifices. Some may even give their life, willingly or not, to assure the continued abundance. Patriarchy seems to look for a hero whose quest makes sure the world stays on track so we will be secure. Our whole life is filled with ritual: Life is a ritual. What is often missing is the sense of the sacred in the rituals. Our society has split the sacred from the secular, and for practical political purposes this compromise may be the best possible for us now. But when the feeling of holiness, wholeness, is missing from our daily activities, we have lost the sense of the sacred that gives us the emotional basis for acting in good ways. We also lose the sense of our fragmentariness: our being part of a larger whole. We then fail to know or feel the truth that we do ingest the divine, and that divinity, the fullness of reality, also ingests us, taking in all we do and think. I grew up in a family where daily prayers and scripture readings were rituals seldom missed. But the rituals I feel more deeply yet today are those I never considered to be anything special: Picking endless quarts of strawberries with Mom and making shortcake for dessert for weeks; walking through a large field of peas, eating some, pulling some thistles and perhaps discussing with Dad what he liked and regretted about his life; or smelling the freshly turned soil as I sat on our little Ferguson tractor surrounded by a small patch of light in the middle of a large field late at night; or looking at the moon on a sweltering summer’s night or a crisp winter’s night and sensing, vaguely that it tied me into the larger scheme of things. One can feel the passage of time in falling leaves, an empty sea shell or a wrinkled face. And one can feel the renewal of life in the first plants to push the ground away in spring, the first geese hooking northward or the baby a mother pushes from her womb. These are sacred feelings. Without them we are not tied into the Whole; we live with out purpose and insight, without worship: the conscious feeling of our fragmentariness. These feelings are not just superficial sentiments, but are as soundly and logically based as any can be. Logic is but the bones of life, yet without it, misplaced sentiments and rituals can turn into tragic or evil results. 38The date for Easter brings together both male and female traditions by being celebrated on the first Sun-day after the first full-moonday after the solar equinox. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 193 Chapter 25: Ritual A Flow-er A small, crystalline, three-dimensional Omega with red flowings from its opening, hung as a symbol on the ever-green (undying) tree during the season when the sun’s power is at its weakest and when the Mother of God is remembered for giving birth to her (God’s) son. Also hung are globes and lights symbolic of the hope for the renewed power of the sun (son) to overtake the darkness at Easter (equinox) bringing a rebirth of life from death. Chapter Summary Changing ideas is not enough. We must find patterns of behavior that reinforce and exhibit our beliefs. Changing our rituals, which work on our feelings in unconscious ways, is much harder than changing our ideas. Rituals define who we are, what small and large social groups we grew up in or adopted. Rituals can further enrichment, but, likewise, they can hinder it. Suggested Reading: Walker, WEMS; Gimbutas, The Language of the Goddess. Ferguson, Signs and Symbols in Christian Art. ************************************************************************** 194 Chapter 26 Now What? The awesome indistinctness of lines not yet lived Nor drawn before they breathe Drowns the day’s shallow roots And withers the entwined lines of hollow vines. Duane Voskuil, 1969. “Lord, we know what we are, but know not what we may be.” Ophelia, Hamlet, Act IV. E ver since First Woman was brought face to face with dangers of her cyclical bleeding by Creator Coyote (one of her predators), blood and gender have been basic themes in human worldviews. Ever since Coyote was persuaded by his brother to create different languages so peoples would go to war so men could gain the glories and spoils of war, blood-letting has escalated, from the thousands of Maya and Aztec human sacrifices to the genocidal sacrifices of millions on all continents in the name of purity and truth. God/desses demand sacrifice. The predator gods and goddesses that devoured the life-giving blood and flesh of those very women who gave us life, were envisioned as both creators and destroyers. Destruction was believed necessary as a prelude to new life. The old and the new were not compatible. The new destroyed the old. Each animal of the Zodiac must die for the next age to occur. The son must kill his father who is reborn to be sacrificed by his son. But the metaphysical truth is not that simple. If truth does not lie with Parmenides’ wish to stop the cycling (so the reality of the “past” is not lost because change is not real), it also does not lie with those who claim beings can alter their internal state or external relationships, since this too fails to makes sense of the past. The present cannot change nor alter anything of the past. Reality, from the grand view, is, necessarily, creative addition. Cycles that bring nothing new each time around are meaningless, just as a linear “concept” of change is meaningless that would leave behind, and not recycle, the past into the present forever. Understanding how we have come to interpret the world as we have and finding more rational ways of doing it, is not an idle past-time. We live in a very dangerous world. Many are taking their lives as they kill others to further what they believe is God's will: beliefs based on frightful metaphysics. We still love the excitement and glory and spoils of war. We still draw blood from millions of helpless male and female children’s reproductive organs in the name of purity and order. We race away from our past behavior, but it still looms ominous in the clouds polluting our brains and the life-fluids dripping from our wounded bodies. Reality is necessarily creative addition. We need a rational view: We must love and embrace the past and the world we live in and helped create. The cosmic womb we live in will not expel us with its rebirth contractions into another kingdom. Never-never land is never. Life is not meaningless, but life cannot be rationally lived trying to fulfill goals that are irrational without neurotic pain and denial. Philosophy can be the most dangerous and painful adventure one sets out on. Yet, it offers a hope the pain can be endured while enjoying the anticipation of a better understanding of Reality. Perhaps Brother Coyote was wrong. Perhaps differences bring exciting variety to feel, not justification for insensitivity. But only a view of cosmic sensitivity and all-inclusiveness will empower us all to risk the adventure beyond our cocoon and make a lie of Robert Frost’s observation that “good fences make good neighbors.” This book has put a high value on logic, especially metaphysical logic or propositions that have no meaningful denial. Students are often upset with logic. Some women claim it is male logic. Others just claim reality (God/dess) is beyond logic. Of course, full reality is always “beyond” logic. Reality is always more than the logic it exhibits since logic can only describe what reality is like in general ways, and metaphysical logic can only describe what reality is like in its most general or universal and, therefore, unavoidable aspects. In my more poetic moods when the con creteness of reality sweeps over me, I too express the paleness of logic’s ability to capture the feelings that compose the fullness of actuality (see Haiku Two, Chapter 25, p. 197). Finally, let me end on a hopeful note. The world seems less willing to tolerate repressive political and social orders than it has for several thousand years. The Copyright 2002 Duane Voskuil A Process Introduction to Philosophy 195 Chapter 26: Now What? philosophical underpinnings of dominating hierarchies and all its forms of inequality like sexism, racism , nationalism, that is, the elect or chosen of whatever type, though still strong, are weakening, requiring those who hold such beliefs to become more defensive and desperate. People cannot change, or they change slowly, without having an awareness of possible ways to change. Philosophy tries to find the broadest dimensions of all changes. It also has the responsibility to make clear the logical consequences of choices made. It must encourage novel proposals, but it must not allow poetic license to speak for the rigorous test of intrinsic rationality. Chapter (Book) Summary Now is the time to start reading philosophy: The only way to read philosophy is to reread it. ********************************************************************************* Alpha and Omega Photo by author. Altar Ark from which, some believe, comes the body of the soter, savior/sower, which when eaten puts one in communion with the divine. Note the alpha and omega symbols and a form of the labarum (Christ-monogram), once a symbol of Bacchus and Mithras derived from the Egyptian ankh, that is, a male cross with a female oval above the crossbar representing (everlasting) life coming from the union of the sexes (see Walker WEMS, 522). “Eucharist,” meaning “communion,” comes from Charis, a goddess of sexual love whose lunar blood was ritually drunk and bathed in. Copyright 2002 Duane Voskuil 196 PART VIII Supplemental Material Appendix 1: Guide to Some Classical Problems ––––– Appendix 2: Historical Guide to Some Positions of the Patriarchal Period ––––– Appendix 3: Whitehead's Categorical Scheme: The Metaphysical Logic of change ––––– Glossary ––––– Selected Bibliography ––––– Index A Process Introduction to Philosophy 197 Chapter 26: Now What? Appendix 1 Guide to Some Classical Problems 1. Problem of Self-Definition , or Relation of a Definition of Philosophy to the Philosophy Offering the Definition. (Can one define what philosophy is?) 2. Problem of the Solidarity of the Universe, or Relation of the One and the Many, or Relation of Whole and Parts. (In what sense, if any, is the world a one of many? The metaphysical issue. How can the many in an experience be one experience? An epistemological issue. How and why is the Whole, if it is, more than the sum of its parts? The value issue.) 3. Problem of Change, or Relation of Being and Becoming and Perishing. (How can something change and still be that which changed? Which is more real, being or becoming? What is the past? Memory? How does time differ from duration?) Problem of Metaphysical Dipolarity, or Relation of Subject-Object to Appearance-Reality, or 4. Relation of Mind and Matter. (What is a subject? Object? Appearance? Reality? Is an object always appearance?) 5. Problem of Knowledge, or Relation of Knower and Known. (How can I know something and leave the thing known as it is? Problem for classical realism. How is what I know related to what you know? Problem for solipsistic idealism). 6. Problem of God/dess, or Relation of God/dess and the World. (How is God/dess one with and/or different from the world? Concerns for metaphysics. How can God/dess, if defined as necessary knowledge, know the contingent world? What can one know about God/dess? Concerns for epistemology. Is God/dess purely abstract? Purely actual? Immutable? Omniscient? Conceivable at all?) 7. Problem of Value, or Relation of Values to Each Other. (What are ethical values? Aesthetic values? How are they brought about? Related? Can all values be simultaneously realized? What is tragedy? Evil? Can survival of a person or species be its own justification? Is that which survives always best? Use of ritual?) 8. Problem of Modality, or Relation of Conceptual Opposites to Each Other. (What is the relation of freedom and determinism, of contingency and necessity? Active-passive, cause-effect, good-evil perfectimperfect, actuality-potentiality, love-hate, finite-infinite versus fragment-whole. Are all concepts meaningful in the ultimate or supreme degree?) 9. Problem of Relations, or Relation of Relations to Their Terms. (What is a relation? Are all relations internal or external to their terms? Both? Neither?) 10. Problem of Science and Methodology, or Relation of Science, Logic, and Philosophy. (How are scientific and philosophic methods similar? Different? What is logic? Permanent objects? Other topics: particles versus waves, causa tion, probability, quantum, wave, relativity, congruence, straight line, laws, “c,” contemporaries, energy, flux, change, duration, particles, entanglement.) 11. Problem of Philosophical Efficacy, or Relation of Philosophy as Theoretical Knowledge to Practical Affairs. (Can or should philosophy affect the way one worships, votes, raises a family or enjoys recreation, and so on?) 12. Problem of Problems, or Relation of Problems to Each Other. (How does an answer to one problem affect the answers to other problems?) Copyright 2002 Duane Voskuil 198 Appendix 2 Historical Guide to Some Positions of the Patriarchal Period The following historical outline of some noteworthy individuals and schools of Western thought will help one locate the source of many intellectual assumptions and trace the way they have affected other positions. Most fundamental issues in Eastern thought have a Western corollary. I. Pre- and non-Greek. (9000? BCE to 400 BCE). Egyptian and other preGreek influences on the Greek and Western intellectual history are becoming increasingly evident: soul; immortal personal salvation; sophisticated mathematics; the changeless as real; dying and rising savior. Ideas are often expressed in myths or linguistic puns (perhaps deliberately to make them less accessible to the uninitiated). The rise of patriarchal Buddhism, contemporaneously with the ancient Greeks, developed the idea of personal identity as residing in a series of moments, rather than a single substance that alters. This influence is just being felt in the West, especially since Whitehead. II. Pre-Socratic Greek Philosophy (600 BCE to 350 BCE ). Being versus becoming; thought versus sense experience; monism versus pluralism; objective versus subjective qualities; mathematical relations versus classification as key to understanding; eternal versus relative truth in ethics and politics. Cosmological period: What is the nature of the stuff of reality. Milesians (600-500 BCE). What is permanent in change? Thales, Anaximander, Anaximenes. Pythagoreans (b. 530 BCE). numerical patterns; numerical atomism; star stuff: reincarnation. Heraclitus (Flourished ca. 500 BCE ). Process more real than being; inspiration for relativism. Parmenides (65 years old ca. 450 BCE) and Zeno (b. 489 BCE ). Changelessness is real; the changing is appearance; how to define “appearance.” Democritus (b. 486 BCE ) and Anaxagoras (b. ca. 500 BCE): Atomists: Change is rearrangement of changeless beings. Ethical Period: What is the purpose and nature of man? Sophists: ethical relativism. Protagoras, Gorgias, Thrasymachus, Callicles, Antiphon. Socrates (470-399 BCE ). Ethical absolutism. III. Plato (427-347 BCE ) and Aristotle (348-321 BCE). Cosmological and ethical synthesis. Plato: Matter/mind dualism; really real is changeless; soul as mediator and answer to change. Aristotle: Really real as primary substance, that is, formed matter; or reality is potentiality becoming actual; God is the exception as pure form or pure actuality. IV. Late Ethical and Religious Greek Philosophy (300 BCE -CE). Salvation as the goal, namely, peace. security or happiness. Epicureanism: Epicurus (432-270 BCE) and Lucretius (wrote De Rerum Natura, 54 BCE): Avoidance of pain. Atomism. Primordial, but limited freedom allowed in the basic units of reality. Stoicism: Indifference to worldly vicissitudes; major influence on Christianity. Skepticism: Absolute relativism. V. Semitic Inheritance Hebrew: Legalistic morality: priests; individualistic moral concern and dilemma: Job versus prophets. Jesus and Essenes (200 BCE- 100 CE ). Messianic; interim ethic. VI. Hellenistic and Roman (200 BCE -400 CE ) Alexandrian and Roman Christian Disputes: (150-250. Jesus becomes the Christ, the mediator between a transcendent God and insignificant mankind. Gnostic formulations. Plotinus (204-269). Neo-Platonism, emanationism, ultra-transcendent God, salvation as elimination of personal identity and mystical union with the One. Augustine (354-430). Patristic, Manichean and Platonic synthesis; major source of Christian doctrine, especially Protestantism. VII. Scholastic Synthesis: Christianized Neo-Platonism and Arabian Aristotelianism. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 199 Appendix 2 Anselm (1035-1109). Platonist; formulated the Ontological or Modal Argument, a major clarification of the nature of philosophy and an adequate definition of “God.” Aquinas (ca. 1206-1280). Aristotelian; a major influence on present Roman Catholic doctrine. Late Scholastics: Relation of reason and faith in arriving at truth. VIII. Descartes (1596-1650). Rebirth of Greek mechanism (though not atomism) and denial of explanation by genus; extreme dualist (or rather 3 kinds of substance: mind, matter and God); subjectivism as basis for certainty: cogito ego sum, I think, therefore I am (compare Augustine’s “Even though I doubt that I am, I am”): major turning point in philosophical analysis. Retention of changing substance as basis of reality. IGalileo1 X. 5 (6 4 - 1 6 4 2 ) and Newton (1642-1727). and time. Rebirth of Democritean atomism, space with X. Continental Rationalism: Some conclusions of Cartesianism. Spinoza (1632-16770. Numerical monism as logical consequence of Aristotle’s primary substances (as reformulated by Descartes). Leibniz (1646-1716). Numerical pluralistic conclusion of substance philosophy, but monism in kind, that is, all substances are mental; spiritual atomism; transcendent God; no interaction between substances; relative space (a concept yet to be learned). XI. British Empiricism: Substance philosophy’s conclusions of Cartesian subjectivisim. Locke (1632-1704). Dualist; perceptive as well as physical atomism. Subjective emphasis. Berkeley (1685-1753). Numerical pluralist, though one kind of substance, that is, mental; subjective idealist. Hume (1711-1776). Bankrupt Berkeleanism: theoretical skepticism; practical faith as basis of reconstruction; synthetic a posteriori (factual statements) versus analytic a priori (conditional logical) statements. XII. Kant (1724-1804). A rational and empirical synthesis; another tour de force of substance philosophy; concerned with the synthetic a priori or necessarily true statements about facts. Necessity is exhibited by nature of substance, that is, mind or that which experiences nature, the ding an sich. XIII. Post-Kantian or Absolute Idealism: Only one Mind. Hegel (1770-1831). Dialectical idealism (basis for Marxist inversion) Schopenhauer (1788-1860). Pessimist; all is Will. Bradley (1846-1924. Relationships are paradoxical in the world of appearances, but somehow resolved in the Absolute; compare to Parmenides and many Eastern absolute monisms. XIV. 20th Century: Reaction to intellectualistic idealism, yet with many carry-overs. Logical Empiricism or Positivism: No necessary truths: logical truth may be “necessary” but only by definition which can be changed; and all factual truths are contingent. So-called statements of necessity are neither true nor false––they are nonsense, thus all talk of “God” as necessary is meaningless or emotive only. Existentialism: Irrational or non-rational and positivistic; freedom to create one’s reality is main theme; Kierkegaard: Either/or emotional reaction Hegel’s both/and systematizing. Nietzsche: reaction to transcendent God ; slave-master morality. Sartre: atheistic Tillich: theistic? XV. Whitehead (1861-1947) and Hartshorne (1897-2000). Contemporary reconstruction; reality is a plenum of quantum creators of beings that are used by superseding spatial-temporally finite quanta to create additional beings; one necessity is that quanta must create; panentheistic; absolute space of Democritus, Newton and Einstein is meaningless; mind creates matter for other minds; dipolar, but not dualistic. ***************************************************************************************** absolut 200 Change and the Unsurpassable Appendix 2 Orpheus One of the Olympian gods, Orpheus, an ancient combination of a shepherd and pied piper, could charm all nature’s creatures with his beautiful lyre. Before the cross became an important Christian symbol, Orpheus calming the animals was used to portray Christ as does this image from the Christian catacombs. Fix, 227. 201 Appendix 3 Whitehead's Categorical Scheme The Metaphysical Logic of Change. (The following is a list of the Categories Whitehead gives in Part II of Process and Reality that purport to be descriptive of the most general aspects of actual entities, the most fundamental moments of reality.) A. Category of the Ultimate: The Many Become One and Are Increased by One: Actual Entity as “Primary Substance.” B. Categoreal Obligations: Most General Descriptions of All Becomings. (1) Subjective Unity: The Many (beings) in all incomplete stages of process, though not fully integrated, are compatible for such determination. (2) Objective Identity: All things in process or coming-to-be, do one and only one thing in the outcome. This is one of the unavoidables of all logics, which is required to make rational sense of experience: x equals x; each thing is just itself. (3) Objective Diversity: Each thing in process must do its thing: Unity cannot destroy the diversity of that unified: x does not equal y. (4) Conceptual Valuation: Each physical feeling (that is, aspect of the given actual world or data or cause) in an actual entity gives rise to a conceptual (“mental”) feeling that is not neutral: Denial of mere perception without an evaluation of the “given” for what it means for the moment; good-bad, beautiful-ugly, and so on, though seldom with any reflectiveness. 5) Conceptual Reversion: Creative process can generate somewhat new feelings; conceptually only. (6) Transmutation: The Many, when diversified mainly by position but qualitatively similar, can come to be felt only by their similarities, with their “insignificant” qualitative differences suppressed or lost. (This Category raises some real problems with Omniscience and probably should not be of metaphysical generality. See Voskuil, “Whitehead's Metaphysical Aesthetic,” Chapter VI.) Not understanding this aspect of human experience gives rise to the Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness that plagues all theories tied too closely to what is obvious in visual experience, a type of experience highly abstracted from the nature of the physical causes of the experience. (7) Subjective Harmony: Valuations are made in context with all others in the process as parts of one Subjective Aim: The denial of this gives rise to the Aesthetic Fallacy: What a Part is, is not fully determined apart from the Whole of which it is a Part. (8) Subjective Intensity: Final Causation or the Subjective Aim is relevant to the immediate circumstances (physical feelings) and the relevant future: What one (whether an actual entity or an individual) can and should come-to-be is relevant to what one is and has been. (9) Freedom and Determination: Every act (actual entity) is caused to be as it is by its given physical and conceptual prehensions, but these parts in the experience never exhaust the self-determination required to bring about the final and settled result. Conceptual feeling (the Subjective Aim), though given, can be embodied in an indefinite number of ways even though they must all be relevant to the given circumstances. C. Categories of Existence: Descriptions of the Kinds of Ultimate Realities. (1) Actual Entities: Final Realities: Res Verae. (2) Prehensions: Concrete Facts of Relatedness: Denial of Leibniz' windowless monads. (3) Nexüs: Public Matters of Fact. Any way Actual Entities are related: next to, or within, each other. (4) Subjective Forms: Private Matters of Fact. How one feels other realities. (5) Eternal Objects: Pure Potentials for the Specific Determination of Fact: Forms of Definiteness. (Hartshorne more accurately says “pure potentiality” has no definiteness and is meaningless. Metaphysics tries to find those aspects of definiteness that have always been exemplified by every creator, that is, every actual entity.) (6) Propositions: Matters of Fact in Potential Determination: Impure Potentials for the Specific Determination of Matters of Fact: or Theories. Anticipation of a kind of outcome given some specific initial situation. (7) Multiplicities: Pure Disjunctions of Diverse Entities. (All multiplicities that are objects that are in some actual entity or other.) (8) Contrasts: Modes of Synthesis of Entities in one Prehension. D. Categories of Explanation: The Most General Vocabulary Descriptive of Reality. (1) Actual Entities (Actual Occasions). 202 Change and the Unsurpassable Appendix 3 (2) Actualization of Potentiality: Meaning of Process. (3) Complex Ways of Being Together Also Come to Be (Nexüs). (4) Principle of Relativity: Every Being, Created or Eternal, is a Potential for Every Becoming. (5) The Actual World, the Past or Causes of each moment is irreducibly unique: Each moment is a once-in-a-universe. (6) Conditioned or Real Potentiality versus Pure Potentiality: Circumstances bring to each moment the range of possibility for that moment (or as Whitehead might say: Circumstances bring to each moment the number of eternal objects relevant to that moment.) (7) Eternal Objects are describable only in terms of how they are felt by a particular actual entity, that is, how they Ingress. (Whitehead's most questionable thesis is this Theory of Potentiality as a multiplicity which has an indefinite (infinite) number of possible ways to be determinative of actual processes, which yet are only known in each case by the one way they are “substantiated.” (8) Internal and External explanations of an actual entity: Its Concrescence and its Objectification. (9) Principle of Process: How an actual entity comes to be, is what it is: The final stage of Concrescence is two-edged: Satisfaction/Objectification. Denial of any Representational Theory of Knowledge or Pre-established Harmony. (10) Analysis of Concrescence into its most concrete aspects discloses its Prehensions. Such analysis is called Genetic Division. (11) Three aspects of a Prehension: (a) Subject or prehender, (b) Datum prehended, and (c) Subjective Form, or how the subject feels the datum. The subject's aim is a complex subjective form of all the prehensions descriptive of the moment's possible outcomes. (12) Positive Prehensions are Feelings and Negative Prehensions are lack of feeling due to the perspective on the given actual world. (13) Many kinds of Feelings: Emotions, valuations, purposes, adversions, consciousness, etc. (14) Nexüs: Many objectifications felt by one actual entity. The Many may be contemporaries of each other, or form a series going back in time, or (and this is nearly always the case) be a mix of both. (15) A Proposition is the potential for Many to be together in One. The Many is (are) the Subject of the proposition; the potential Oneness is the predicate of the proposition. Whitehead calls the predicate a complex eternal object. (16) Unity is unique and complex: Denial of the Parmenidean type of homogeneous unity and of the materialistic (atomistic) type of unity that is really a multiplicity since it is capable of dissolution and recombining with nothing lost nor gained: A Whole is greater than its unique Parts; Parts must be parts of some Whole or other. (17) All data have a felt unity: All contrasts are felt differences in the unity of the feeler. (18) Ontological Principle: or Principle of Efficient and Final Causation: All explanation is found in the actual world (givens) of an actual entity or in the Subjective Aim (that is, felt goal) of the actual entity. (19) Actual entities (units of process) and eternal objects (pure potentiality) are ultimate; all other realities are derivative. Reality is irreducibly dipolar. [Actual entities include eternal objects and so are more basic, that is, potentiality is an aspect of actuality. Hartshorne says only the metaphysical dimensions of potentiality are primordial.] (20) To Function, or to have Meaning, is to contribute a determination to an actual entity, that is, either a quality of definiteness or position; one is not found without the other. (21) Actual process has significance for itself: Each moment feels (is determined by) its givens and its aim, and yet what it becomes is not exhausted by its efficient and final causes as initially given. (22) Self-creation or process is the bringing into coherence or integration an initial indetermination; with the Satisfaction of this Aim, the actual entity as substance ceases and is an attribute or cause in one or more superseding processes. (23) Self-functioning is the reality of an actual entity: it is its Immediacy: it is the Subject, and not an aspect of a subject (that has more than one self-determination or change). (24) Objectification is the reality of the subject as completed, as a being. It is all there is; and it will be forever. Being (except for pure potentiality, that is, metaphysical generalities) is not eternal (primordial), but it is changelessly what it is forever, that is, everlasting once it is. (25) The Satisfaction is fully determinate relative to, (a) the actual world it began with, (b) its character for the next moments of creative process, and (c) how much of the total universe it included positively as feeling or rejected from positive feeling. (26) Each element in the process has only one (though often complex) function in the final satisfaction. (27) Process gives rise, between its initiation and satisfaction, to prehensions of more complex contrasts than it began with which will also contribute to the final determination it becomes. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 203 Appendix 3 E. Topics of Emphasis: Actual Entity as Subject and Superject: (1) Concrescence: Substance as a Creative Spatio-Temporal Quantum: A look from inside. (a) Proposition Coming-to-Be: Dipolar. (b) Caused by Past: Necessary Conditions or Causes of the Actual Entity. (c) Contiguous to Some, and Contemporary with All Other Processes. (2) Objectification: Being as Potentiality and Necessarily Conditioning Some Processes Forever: A look from outside. 204 Glossary Absolute: A reality that supposedly has no relations to anything. Sometimes the term refers to something that has, but does not require, relationships to anything else. Often, as with Parmenides’ Being, it refers to the one and only thing that can exist, therefore, relations to others are meaningless since nothing else can possibly exist to set up a relationship. Anything else that seems to exist, is dismissed as appearance, usually with little attempt to explain how the Absolute gives rise to that which is not really real, or explain what the relationship is between the real absolute and the not-so-real appearances. As the modifier, “absolutely,” it can refer to any metaphysical statement. All metaphysical propositions are related to, or exhibited by, absolutely everything. The Unsurpassable is necessarily (absolutely) related to all, which is the logical contrary of the first meaning of “absolute,” namely, something unrelated to all. Abstract(ion): A characteristic (or part) of a whole, or a common aspect of wholes. Something found in more than one whole. Parts can be of two types: (1) parts that at some time in the past were (created by) wholes, and (2) aspects of all possible wholes that could never have been the result of a whole at any time. Members of the first type are facts that have become factors in other facts. They are the memories we carry for a while and the Unsurpassable carries forever. Members of the second type are metaphysical. They are the common denominators of all possible memories or facts. The principle, “a whole creates novelty,” is not something that ever was a whole. It partially defines what every “whole” must do. A metaphysical proposition is not only abstract, it is completely abstract, being exhibited by actual wholes and would have been exhibited by any other whole that could have become actual, and will be exhibited by any whole (of the endless possible wholes) that do become actual. Abstract-Concrete Dilemma: All wholes, as wholes, are contingent. Since nothing is concretely real except wholes which are contingent, where can the necessities exist, if anywhere? How is a necessary reality possible if all necessities must exist as aspects of contingent wholes? Necessities are necessarily abstract. Since a necessity is a common aspect of all possible concretes, a necessity cannot be identified as one of the concretes. As with all abstractions, necessities mu st be aspects of wholes. It is possible for wholes (that must be contingent in some ways) to contain necessities, because necessities are only some of a whole’s characteristics. A whole is contingent if only one thing in it is contingent. Since one contingent aspect in a whole is sufficient to make a whole contingent, a whole is not necessarily as it is as a whole because it is exhibits some necessities. One necessary aspect exhibited by all wholes is the truth that, “All wholes are necessarily contingent in concrete content.” Necessities can only be necessary if they must be part of some whole or other (not just might be part of some whole or other), so if no whole had to exist, necessities could not be assured of having a concrete place to reside. This implies that some whole or other must exist at all times, even though no whole that does exist has to be just as it is. Because necessities are common factors of all possible wholes, as long as some contingent whole or other must occur, the necessities must be exhibited as part of reality. Only if it were conceivable no whole at all “occur,” would necessities fail to exist. But since “nothingness” is nonsense, some reality (some concrete whole) or other must occur. It is not contingent that some contingent whole or other occurs. A contingent creation of some kind at all times is necessary, so necessities will always be displayed by some contingent whole or other. Actual Entity: Whitehead’s term for a moment of reality, a coming-to-be, a whole that includes others’ results (beings) as parts of its makeup, or as conditioning its process. Actuality, How Something Exists: The fullness of reality. A whole. An act or doing, a moment of creativity. Whitehead says all acts are temporally finite, perhaps, just fractions of a second for a human person. No moment of actuality ever changes: It comes to be and is forever what it is. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 205 Glossary In the Ontological Argument, Hartshorne points out that a person’s acts are not logically the same as the person’s existence. How one exists can vary and the individual will still exist, as long as there is some how or other. This distinction between a series (of moments) which may or may not be contingent and each moment of the series which must be contingent, allows the possibility of discussing the difference between a necessarily existing reality and a contingently existing reality, while at the same time agreeing with those who correctly insist that all hows, all moments of existence, could have been different. A necessarily existing reality will be a reality necessarily acting in some contingent way or other. Agnosticism: The suspension of judgment as to whether or not God/dess exists. Implicit in this suspension of judgment is the statement: “I know what ‘God/dess’ means.” This statement, Anselm correctly points out, cannot be understood and at the same time say God/dess might not ex ist without being a fool, since “God/dess” means in part “necessarily existing reality.” Only a fool will say “I know what ‘something that must exist’ means, but I do not know whether or not it exists.” Altruism: Actions done to help others without (expectation of) reward. Atomism (pluralism): Originally (with reference to Democritus), the theory that reality is composed of many absolutes, many internally changeless, homogeneous and qualitativeless beings. The only relationships they supposedly can have are external, namely, to bang into each other and move around in the Void. The only internal relationships in this attempted metaphysic are the way the atoms are supposedly “in” the nonbeing called the Void. Yet, in what sense the atoms are in the Void is not clear since the rearrangement of the atoms do not seem to change the (non)reality they are in. A whole, which must have parts, cannot still be the same whole when “it” supposedly acquires new parts, loses parts or has its parts rearranged. Since a change in an atom’s position is supposedly continuous and forced from without, at no time is anything in reality able to act with its own power and exhibit self-determination. Freedom is meaningless, if this theory makes sense. A metaphysic of only external relations can never explain the asymmetry of sequence (time), nor can it ever explain how it is possible to compare two or more atoms to establish the meaning of an “arrangement.” If “arrangement” does not make sense, then neither can “rearrangement.” In addition, Democritus must still explain how movement is possible given Zeno’s critique of “infinitesimals.” Democritus must also explain what possible meaning “the Void,” or “nothingness,” can have. Modern atomism, particleism, is still one of two dominant theories in physical science. The other is the belief in Energy, or the One stuff of reality that takes on many forms as specific things come to be and disappear, the modern version of the Milesians’ theories. Apocalypse: Theories, supposedly revelations, of the nature and purpose of the cosmos. Usually concerned the nature of life after death, the warring factions of gods and supernatural powers and how people will be treated by them. Appearance and Reality: The traditional attempt to put things into two camps, real things (sometimes, the “really real” things) and apparent things, fails to explain the reality of the appearance. Yet, not everything is as it seems to be, so philosophy must explain why not. There have been those who try to explain the relationship by denying one or the other: Either Reality is just what appears, or Reality can’t be discovered since we can only have appearances. Whitehead says appearance arises in the experiential mode called Presentational Immediacy. Appearance is a kind of simplification of the more basic, and error-free (but unconscious) mode of Causal Efficacy, but the simplification is useful because it brings the possibility of awareness not possible in the causal mode, because that form of experience makes no conscious comparisons. The simplification is, of course, just what it is, but when one assumes the complex causal mode is just like the simplified presented mode, one is in error. The presentation is a symbol that can be true of what it symbolizes, but it is always only true of an aspect of that symbolized. Abstractions need not be false unless one assumes the abstraction is fully like the concrete. Atheism: The belief that God/dess does not exist. Implicit in this denial is the statement: “I know what ‘God/dess’ means.” Anselm correctly points out that one cannot know what God/dess means and deny 206 Change and the Unsurpassable Glossary his/er existence without being a fool, since “God/dess” means in part “necessarily existing reality,” and only a fool will say “There is something that must exist, but it does not exist.” BCE: Before the Common Era. Replaces “BC” which means, “Before Christ.” Being: One of the first words philosophers used to characterize anything that existed. A being is something that is. The assumption this theory makes is that reality means “what is.” Only Heraclitus tried to stop this assumption in its early phases. Because equating “being” with “reality” cannot explain reality, the word took on several meanings which still confuse us today, namely: (1) Something that lasts over time, like a human being or atom (soul or matter), a mistake according to Whitehead and the Buddhists. (2) Something that is past, and so is (in being), (though many theorists say the past is gone and doesn’t exist, so it no longer is). (3) Something that is abstract like “motherhood.” Since we can talk about and define abstractions, some philosophers like Plato think they are beings (perhaps the only real beings) that exist and exist apart from physical things. (4) Something that has always been what it is, and must remain as it is; the way reality is according to Parmenides. Perhaps the word should be thrown out. The attempt here is to use it with as much of its Greek root meanings a possible. A “being” is something that is. Things not yet done, are not yet beings. Since the past is done, the past is being(s). Also, in agreement with Parmenides, a being is what it is, and will always be what it is. Beings cannot be what they are and alter. Every being is changeless and not capable of being destroyed. But contrary to Parmenides, all beings have been created; they have come to be. The only things that are, always have been and always will be as they are, are metaphysical abstractions or characteristics of all possible beings, not some stuff. The common denominator of all possible beings, perhaps should not be called a “being” in order to avoid confusion, since as the term is used here, every being has been created at some time. The coming-to-be of being is more fundamental than being. This is the most basic tenant of process philosophy. Also, contrary to Parmenides, being is felt; it is quality, not just an amount of some neutral stuff. Being is usually referred to as one of three concepts: Being, becoming and nonbeing. The history of philosophy is mostly the ill-fated attempt to explain becoming or change in terms of being, or in terms of being and nonbeing. To a process philosopher, nonbeing is nonsense, and being is contained in, and the result of, a coming-to-be, or creativity. More specifically, being results from finite units of comingto-be, rather than the becoming and rebecoming of the same material or mental whole, as many philosophical positions maintain. Cause and Effect: A cause can be: (1) The conditions or environment around which a whole creates a new result: The necessities for something to be partly as it is. Determinists (ultra-rationalists) believe causes force the outcome, that is, the effect, to be exactly as it is. (2) The power of the moment to do (become) one of an indefinite number of possible things within the range of possibility set by the causes. A cause in the second sense is an active, partially free, agent. A cause in the first sense is passive, but the creative agent (in the second sense) must conform to causes in the first sense because they are there. The moment would not be the moment it is without the causal base from which it arose. Causes in the first sense condition, but do not do the doing for the moment which creates (causation in the second sense) the effect for others. Every effect occurs within a range of possibility given by the past which conditions the self-causation of the present. Causes have been classified since Aristotle in several ways, including: Efficient Cause, the agent bringing about the change; Final Cause, the end or reason for the change; Material Cause, the stuff used in the change; and Formal Cause, the pattern followed in a physical or mental change. CE: Common Era. Replaces A.D., Anno Domini, “In the year of our Lord.” A Process Introduction to Philosophy 207 Glossary Circumcision: Literally, “to cut around.” The surgical amputation of the male prepuce causing the internal organ, the glans penis to be permanently exposed, causing desensitization, a sense of exposure and vulnerability, and many other physical problems including, some authorities estimate, about 200 deaths a year in the U.S. The mutilation removes about 15 square inches of highly sensitive adult tissue. Originally a puberty rite (as it still is in some societies), probably as an imitation of female menstruation, it became an infant rite and a tribal mark for some about 1000 BCE. In the anti-sexual, anti-pleasure world of Victorian English-speaking countries, circumcision was promoted as a rite of the medical priesthood mostly carried out in their hospital temples where childbirth had become commonplace and treated like a physical disease. Given our skeptical attitude towards traditional mythological explanations, the rite had to be justified on grounds compatible with our secular values, namely, health. Yet, no medical reason can be given to justify the negative effects of circumcision despite a century of attempts to do so. The operation is a violation of an individual’s right to determine for himself whether he wants to live life without a fully intact body. Female genital mutilations are also common, but probably became so only after the rise of patriarchy as a means to control women’s sexuality and to help assure they will be virgins at marriage. North Dakota became the first state to specifically outlaw this practice in 1995 after legislators were informed, among other things, that a young Dakota girl (now grown) had her clitoris cut out by a local physician to stop her from masturbating. It didn’t. Federal law to prohibit such female mutilations also became active in April 1997. These laws are being challenged in federal court on Constitutional grounds of unequal protection for males. The relevance of these kinds of physical maimings to philosophy is not always easy for some to see. Two or three of the chapters of this book and the essay “From Genetic Cosmology to Genital Cosmetics: Origin Theories of the Righting Rites of Male Circumcision,” (Voskuil, 1994), show how a female-based cosmology in which a woman’s body fluids, blood and milk, are the stuff of creation and its continual maintenance, left men out of the philosophical loop, so they tried to become more like women by causing genital bleeding, or even more so by removing their external genitals altogether. As patriarchy took over the socio-religious scene, the reason men mutilated themselves and their sons changed, (1) to a sign of their obedience to, and trust in, the social hierarchy (including God), or (2) to a way to stop desiring women. The effect these genital blood-lettings have on one’s view of reality has hardly been studied, but even a quick look at the vocabulary used to describe reality and the words used in rituals of passage in our society, will reveal a deep debt to blood and genitals. Much can be learned in studying the relationship between cosmology and cosmetics, between genesis and genitals, between the kingdom and kin (blood relative), etc. If one wants to discover the power of ritual to bend and mold intelligent minds, ask professionals in law, education, welfare, medicine, and so on, why this sexual child abuse is tolerated. Even those who say it should stop, usually pass the buck, saying it’s someone else’s job to stop it, exhibiting what might be called the Little Red Hen Syndrome. Further information can be found online at: http://www.BoysToo.com Classical Theism: The belief that God is apart from the world he created. God is conscious, all-knowing (somehow including the details of the future) and changeless, since God is already “perfect,” any change can only be for the worse. God is often said to be located someplace, namely, in heaven, from which those who have not obeyed God will be excluded. Coherence: The interdependence of propositions in a system. The meaning of any proposition at the most basic level is unclear without the others. If the fundamental propositions do not require each other, and are arbitrarily put together, the system is incoherent. One example of incoherence is Dualism (see below), the belief reality is both mind and matter, capable of existence independent of each other. Concept: An abstraction; a characteristic of some, or of all, actual or possible moments of creation. Usually used to refer to an abstraction one is conscious of. If the characteristic is exhibited by some things, it is a contingent concept; if exhibited by all possible things, it is a necessary concept. Concrete: The opposite of abstract. The fully real, a whole. Every metaphysic makes a claim about this most fully real. For Democritus it is the atoms; for Berkeley it is mind; for a dualist it is both matter and mind. Whitehead says the most inclusive reality is not some kind of altering or moving being. He says 208 Change and the Unsurpassable Glossary it is process, the creating, the coming-to-be of a being that is fully concrete. He calls this moment of reality an “actual entity.” Abstractions are only found as parts (or aspects) of the concrete, not apart from it. Concrete Universal: Something that is numerically one and is concretely everywhere at all times as a stuff, not just as an abstract concept or aspect of concrete things. Examples are: Heraclitus’ logos, Democritus’ void, the physicist’s Nineteenth Century aether, contemporary notion of space-time and a pantheistic God. Conservation Laws: First formulated by Democritus. The Conservation of Matter meant atoms could not be created nor destroyed (or even altered). The Conservation of Energy meant the total amount of motion of atoms is constant. Einstein brought the two together in the famous E = mc2 formula. From the process philosophy point of view, reality is always increasing in content, though this may not be empirically verifiable since the final storehouse of all creations is in the cosmic unifications of the Unsurpassable series. Contemporaries: Two (or more) events that are causally independent of each other so neither is a condition or cause of the other. A contemporary can have no knowledge of another, but the created results of two or more contemporaries can be simultaneously inherited and, thereby, be causes in, and known by, a present moment that extends over them both. See Relativity. Contiguous: External to, but right next to, something. In process philosophy, when one process is contiguous to another successively, the processes as comings-to-be are external to each other. However, the nonextended boundary (or being) that is between the two is simultaneously the result which the first moment creates and a datum which the successor inherits. In this way, even though a whole (as process) is not in other wholes, still all the reality created by a whole is in other wholes, and forever, since the result of every whole also flows into (conditions) wholes of the divine series which never ends, never rejects and never forgets anything once it is inherited. Contingent: Capable of alternatives. If a statement is true, it could have been false, and vise versa. If something exists, it might not continue to exist. If it doesn’t exist, it is possible that it might have. “Possible” here does not mean “likely” or “possible given the world as it is.” It is a logical possibility, which means, the possibility of being otherwise is not logically self-contradictory. The logical opposite (contradictory) of “contingent” is “noncontingent” which includes both necessity and impossibility (nonsense). Contraries versus Contradictories: The “contrary” of All of something is None of it. This is the strongest quantitative opposition possible. Logicians call the weakest opposition possible to All (or to None) a “contradictory.” One less than All or one more than None contradicts All or None. “Some” is usually used to mean “one more than None,” or “one less than All,” but “Some” may also mean “at least one, possibly All.” See Quantification. Cosmology: Study of the cosmos, the universe, in its largest dimensions: origin, final end (if any) and the types of objects developed. Draws on astronomy, physics and most other sciences. Because cosmology examines the most general characteristics of the universe, it sits on the border between metaphysic and science, that is, between characteristics exhibited because they are unavoidable and those exhibited in our cosmic epoch but could be absent in another epoch. Some form of a Theory of General Relativity and a Theory of Evolution are likely metaphysical. Crone (Hag): The third stage of a woman’s life, coming after maiden and mother and before her death and reabsorption into the cosmic tomb/womb. In this menopausal stage the woman was thought to retain her wise menstrual blood becoming even wiser and more venerable. Grannies (and witches) in our society are what is left of the crone who was the storehouse of domestic, medical and religious knowledge and who also kept her eye on things as the judge of social behavior. In patriarchy her eye becomes “the evil eye.” Cross, Cauldron: The cross has many origins and many symbolic uses. The walking cross stood for the cyclical nature of reality. The four directions form a cross. The celestial pole in the Ptolemaic cosmology is crossed by the celestial equator, and the equator is crossed by the ecliptic. Plato speaks in the Timaeus of these crosses as laying the foundations of the cosmos. The cross was also a “tree” upon A Process Introduction to Philosophy 209 Glossary which many sacred kings were sacrificed to placate goddesses or be initiated into the mysteries of the Goddess’ cosmology. The Norse god Odin is such an example, who upon his death hung on the tree for three times three days, then descended into the underworld to learn women’s secrets of the runes, which he shared with men when he returned. The shape of many crosses is also like that of daggers or swords, symbolic of cutting and dividing. For an example, see the photograph of the sword/cross pulpit relief at the end of Chapter 15, page 104. This blood-letting tool, symbolic of patriarchal saviors like Christ and Mithras who shed blood traumatically, stands in contrast to the cauldron, symbolic of the matriarchal goddess-worshipping cultures. The cauldron is inclusive, it mixes all things together. As a womb symbol, it generates and gives birth to new life. Even today the cauldron is a common item on lawns and gardens, usually bursting forth with flowers. A flower is a flow-er, that is, a menstruant, a source of life-blood. Since men are not natural flow-ers, instruments of pricking and cutting must be used to cause a flow (see Circumcision). Death: Once the distinction is made between the life of the moment, a whole, and the life of a se ries of wholes, two different meanings of “death” can be distinguished: (1) death of the moment, and (2) death of a series. Every moment of life must die. Without death nothing is accomplished, no change has occurred (despite Heraclitus’ attempt) and no value has been created. Every moment is a moment of life, of enjoyment of what others have done (that is, of their being or matter) and the anticipation of an accomplishment to come (that is, the present’s potentiality). But the accomplishment can only occur with the exhaustion of the life that brought about the result. This death is not a negative thing; it is the only way reality can fulfill further enrichment. The death of the moment is enjoyed by superseding lives, that is, those who include the previous moments of a series. Insofar as there is retention or saving of the past in the present, there is no loss, and no regret that moments have died. But when memory is faulty or the series (the person) dies, one wonders where the reality of the experiences of the personal series exist. Death seems to be loss. Death raises the question of meaning. If death is the end of differences one makes, then death means one has become meaningless. We spend our life trying to find ways to make lasting differences, that is, be meaningful. Of special concern is how we can be meaningful after we are dead. We write books, raise children, make objects, and so on, hoping all these will continue to make differences when we are gone. Even though we partly or completely lose our past due to bad memory or death, Hartshorne proposes our past is not lost because each moment that dies also contributes its novel creation completely to the cosmic series that has no last moment. Deduction: The process of making explicit what is logically implied in a statement (a premise) or a group of statements together. If one can deduce two propositions that are contradictory, the premise(s) are expressing nothing meaningful. Some logicians like to say contradictory premises allow one to deduce anything, due to the way the logical operation of “material implication” (a relationship between propositions in symbolic logic) is defined, but here self-contradictory “statements” are taken to be a failure to be statements at all. They are sentences without logical content. One should make a list of such utterances: “Completely different,” “round square,” “greatest conceivable number,” “continuous motion,” and so on. The positivists would also add all metaphysical propositions to this list, including all statements about the Unsurpassable. Deism: A theory about God who is little more than the originator of the world, a world created with a set of causal laws God made but does not tinker with. The world goes on without divine interaction, so God is apart from (absent from) the world (unless there is a miraculous intervention). Determinism A metaphysical position that maintains reality contains no room for freedom, creativity or spontaneity. Every happening can be fully explained in terms of the circumstances from which it arose. Causes add up to a sufficient explanation of the effect. Two major forms of determinism are: (1) materialism (atomism), the basic faith during the rise of modern science, and 210 Change and the Unsurpassable Glossary (2) one form of theism, wherein (a) God does all doings and (b) God must do the best thing, and (c) there is only one best thing to do at each moment. A determinist is an ultra-rationalist, one who believes reality exhibits only necessary relationships, not just some rational or necessary relationships. Dipolarity: A theory that each concrete moment has two aspects, (1) determinations settled by the past (that is, objects in the present subject), and (2) feeling of possibility to be fulfilled (that is, the processing subject which includes the objects and the possibilities they provide). Another way to express this is: Every moment is both subject and object, but the problem of dualism (see below) is avoided by maintaining that one pole of the dipolarity is inclusive of the other. Subjects include objects, never vice versa, and neither can exist alone without the other. Dualism: A metaphysical theory maintaining two fundamentally different kinds of reality exist, usually matter, and mind. The persistence of this division probably indicates an important truth (see Dipolarity), but the usual formulations are philosophically dissatisfying since there seems no way to explain one reality in terms of the other or to explain why there are two realities at all and what their relationship is. Whitehead’s theory is that each moment, or actual entity, is dipolar, exhibiting physicality and mentality. The “matter” of the moment is the past that is done and dead but causing the present moment to be like the past because the present actuality had to include it. The “mind” of the moment is the feeling of possible ways the moment can achieve a somewhat novel outcome. The mentality, or creativity of the moment, makes or evolves a result that is passed on to the next moment as new “matter,” new being. “Dualism” may also refer to the existence of two divine realities: one all-good, the other all-bad. “Completely evil” is likely a meaningless expression, since nothing can exist without some positive value. Egoism: Belief that the welfare of one’s self is the ultimate justification for judging the rightness of behavior. Egoism is often disguised as altruism, as for example, when one is urged to be kind to one’s neighbor, but to do so in order to win rewards now or in some future life. Empirical: Having to do with experience. Since every experience could have been somewhat different from the way it is, every experience is, as a whole, a contingent fact. But not everything about a fact is contingent. To be “empirical” means “capable of being experienced.” The positivist will say all aspects of experience are capable of being absent in some particular case. However, the metaphysician claims some (not all, unless determinism makes sense) aspects of all experiences are unavoidable and occur as characteristics of any possible experience. These are empirical aspects, but not factual aspects, since “factual” means occurring as it does, yet possible it could have occurred another way. Empiricism: The belief that experience, not reasoning, is the way to achieve truth. Truth about factual matters can only be determined by experience, but there are many truths about reality that cannot be arrived at by sense experience. These are truths about the meaning of “fact,” the meaning of “meaning,” the meaning of “truth,” and so on. Only reasoning can determine what these truths are, which is what Rationalism is about. But a rationalist who thinks all truth is rational, denies the contingent character of facts. Such a rationalist is an ultra-rationalist, a determinist. Environmentalism: Belief that the welfare of the environment should guide one’s behavior. Like altruism, concern for the environment raises logical issues, like deciding what part of the environment one should be concerned with. Can one act for a group? Or is the environment not a group, but a whole? Whitehead points out that morality of outlook is tied to generality of outlook. Hartshorne makes the point that the environment at each moment is in itself a collection, and that the collector of the collection, the whole of which the group is a part, is the present moment of the Unsurpassable. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 211 Glossary Epistemology: The study of how we come to know anything. The examination of the basis for the possibility of knowledge (see Chapter 12). Eschatology: Theories of the final days. Based on the belief the world will come to an end. Usually combined with theories of how we will be rewarded or punished in a supernatural existence. Essence, What Something Means: The definition of something. What something must be like to be that kind of thing. In the Ontological Argument, essence refers to the definition of the Unsurpassable, minimally, that the Unsurpassable is a necessarily existing reality (if meaningful). Anselm points out that in the unique case of the Unsurpassable, part of the definition or essence of what we are referring to, is identical to his/er existence, so if we know what we are talking about (essence) we know that s/he must exist. The history of philosophy is full of those mistaken, like Plato, who think the essence of something is its full or concrete reality rather than abstract characteristics of concrete wholeness. Essenes One of several Jewish sects during the Second Century BCE through First Century BCE . They considered themselves to be the true heirs of the Zadokite priestly tradition and the only remnant of the true religion. They probably established the site at Qumran and were involved in writing and/or storing the documents known as the Dead Sea Scrolls. Many of their beliefs and organizational structures were similar to those of another group that arose in the First Century that eventually were called “Christians.” So similar are they that an argument can be made that those of the Way were first Essenes, though the first Christians were Jews, likely Essenic Jews, who accepted Paul’s interpretation of the Messiah that eventually set brother against brother. Eternal: Having no beginning nor end: both primordial and everlasting. Never-changing, that is, necessary. Some try to say “eternal” means “being out of, or unrelated to, anything temporal or changing “(see Absolute), but nothing exists apart from process. Everlasting: The ability of something to remain in existence once begun. Different from “eternal” which means “never beginning, nor ending.” Evolution, Theory of: Another way to talk about change, originally biological change. A philosophically general form of the theory says everything comes from something else (in part). All changes contain something of the past, but also, necessarily, something new; without novelty no change has occurred. Often the Theory of Evolution is used to deny creativity, especially of a divine sort, but every change requires creative addition and every creating is influenced by divinity. Existence, That An Essence Has A How: To exist is to do something, to act or be actual in some way or other. Existence is an abstraction from acts, something Hartshorne finally made clear. One can exist given many different kinds of acts, so one’s existence is exhibited by one’s acts; it is not identical to them. In order to exist necessarily, it is necessary that a person act in some way, but it is not necessary just how one acts (contingently). Even though all acts are necessarily contingent in the way they occur (since each is a creative process), it still does not follow that all existences are contingent. If there is a concept of a reality that is acting (in contingent ways), but must act in some way or other, then, part of what this reality is, namely, its essence, is that it must act, and anyone who must act, must exist. Knowing that Unsurpassability must exist, is not the same as having knowledge of how this reality acts. Logically, one cannot move from a general statement to knowledge of a specific case without committing the Fallacy of Existential Import. Knowing that such a reality must exist is only to know that this reality must act in some way or other at all times, that is, to exist necessarily. We, however, exist contingently, as everything else does, not because we do contingent things, but because it’s contingent (not necessary) that we do any contingent things at all. We can fail to do anything: We die, and we could have failed to be born. Existentialism: Philosophical position, or attitude, asserting existence precedes essence: What we are is not predesigned nor predefined. We are free to create what we become as we live. 212 Change and the Unsurpassable Glossary Fact: An actual occurrence, a creating whole and its result. Often used to refer to a group of wholes or related facts, that is, an event. Every fact is as it is, but could have logically been different since its occurrence is contingent on circumstances and decisions. Factual (Empirical) Theism: The belief that God must exist because of the particular way the world exists, that is, facts supposedly prove God’s existence. Implicit in this position is the statement: “I can know what ‘God’ means without knowing whether or not God exists (until the facts prove it).” This position, like atheism and agnosticism, defines “God” as a “contingently existing reality,” and then tries to prove God necessarily exists. This can’t be done. Fallacy: An invalid argument. Failure to make sure the chain of reasoning from assumptions to conclusion is faultless. In a valid argument the conclusion is unavoidable given the premises. The conclusion can be wrong, even in a valid argument, but only if something is wrong with the premises. The conclusion follows necessarily from the premises in a valid argument. A fallacious argument fails to demonstrate this necessity. Fallacy of Existential Import: Assuming a class is not empty without a definite assertion that the class does have at least one member. In traditional (Aristotelian) logic the following argument is valid because every class was assumed to have members, but in modern logic all universal classes are assumed to be empty unless another proposition asserts it has at least one member. (1) All mermaids have tails. (2) All creatures with tails run. (3) Therefore, some mermaids run. Those with Tails Mermaids Runners The conclusion assumes there must be at least one mermaid, one creature with a tail and one runner. However, the diagram only tells one what does not exist, or what something would be like if it were to exist; it says nothing about what does exist. The areas that are not crossed out may also be empty. The Ontological Argument is often accused of committing this fallacy because it argues from the definition of “The Unsurpassable” as a reality that belongs to the class of realities that must exist, to God/dess’ actual existence. However, “existence” in this case is just as abstract as the definition of what “The Unsurpassable” means. Part of the definition of “The Unsurpassable” is a reality that must exist; not in this or that way, but in any way whatsoever. No particular form of existence is asserted by the argument, only that there must be some particular form (actualization) or other. Since “some or other” is a universal proposition, no fallacy of asserting a specific particular is committed. Only someone who can establish it makes sense to say “nothing at all could exist,” can say Hartshorne commits this fallacy in the following argument. (1) The Unsurpassable is a reality that must exist (or s/he would be surpassable). (2) To exist is to be actual (to act) in some way or other. (3) Therefore, the Unsurpassable is a reality that must be actual (in some way or other). A Process Introduction to Philosophy 213 Glossary Admittedly, the definition of the “Unsurpassable” is a unique case (referring to a class with one member), since all other definitions are of realities that may or may not exist. In these contingent cases knowing what something is, cannot establish that anything actually exists that fits the definition. Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness: The false assumption either: (1) that a spatial region like a book is a single whole rather than a group of wholes, or (2) that something that lasts over time, like a person or a physical particle, is one whole rather than a series of wholes (or many series of wholes, like a book or one’s brain). Forms: See Idea. Gnosticism: Knowledge. Compare “agnosticism,” not having knowledge. A term referring to religious groups during ancient Greek and Roman times who claimed to have secret knowledge of the nature of the universe and the way to achieve salvation. Many of their beliefs seem to carry forward into patriarchy concepts from the goddess traditions, though they exhibit the usual patriarchal way to salvation with a male savior. Christ was viewed as being with the Father from the beginning, but became embodied in human form to show us the way. Humans (males, anyway––see quotations heading Chapter 15) were seen as naturally divine. They contained the heavenly spark of life, but this life-force or soul had become dispersed into disgusting mater and needed to be gathered up and purified to release it back into the divine realm. God/dess A term with many different meanings. See Pantheism, Classical Theism, Deism, Panentheism, Dualism. Here the term is used as a synonym for the Unsurpassable. Anything not logically required as part of the definition (essence) of the Unsurpassable should not be assumed to part of his/er definition. Personal and gendered pronouns are used to refer to this reality because “it” in English usually refers to objects, and objects are always surpassable by subjects, since objects can only exist as parts of subjects that include them. Unfortunately, English does not have a nongendered, personal pronoun or noun to refer to cosmic unity as a cosmic Subject. Hypothesis: A theory. An empirical hypothesis must be able to be proved wrong by some possible facts. If it has been tested and not disproved, it is said to be corroborated, giving some ground for believing it may be correct. A correct metaphysical hypothesis cannot be proved wrong by any facts since it is a common denominator of all possible facts. A proposal for the metaphysic, however, can be disproved if not all facts exhibit the proposal, or if a proposal exhibits internal conflict. Often, when this happens, a metaphysician will deny the facts are real (a procedure scientists and others have also been known to use). Hylozoism: The belief that matter is alive, that matter moves itself, though not necessarily towards any conscious end. The belief that nature is alive or animate. In some form or other, this was the general belief of the Goddess philosophies. As carried over into the more patriarchal traditions, like the Milesians, the element of consciousness or direction of purpose of the one or more life forces in Nature, is dropped in favor of blind, unconscious activity that has no freedom. Eventually, the idea that Mother Nature, mater, was anything active at all, was dropped, and matter was seen as dead. We are still exercised by the question of the origin of life, how dead matter can give rise to life. Whitehead and Hartshorne propose a theory that all existence is alive, though few things are conscious, but theirs is a theory wherein each life dies and leaves forever the result of its moment of life as a being (matter) for other lives to enjoy or suffer. Reality also contains chains or series of lives where each present moment of the series is privileged relative to past members of the series because it is in a position to inherit the series past. Only one series, that of the Unsurpassable, has never had a first moment of life and will not have a last one, and is able to inherit all the past of everyone. Idea: Dea is the feminine form of deo, God. “Idea” was originally, “I-dea,” or “Goddess in me.” This expression refers to the in-sight one can have about how things in experience are alike (a generality on experience, a concept) and, probably, the excitement one can have obtaining such an insight. Plato’s use of “Idea” emphasizes the changelessness of a general idea, and for Plato and many others, changelessness was a hallmark of divinity. This is a half-truth. God/dess must always exhibit eternal personality characteristics, but the way these characteristics are expressed can be fulfilled in an infinity of new ways. It is fulfilled in a new way every moment since the content of the divine’s experience is ever-changing; ever being added to without loss. The definition of the “Unsurpassable” is changeless, 214 Change and the Unsurpassable Glossary so it must be expressed with metaphysical propositions, but the concrete content of the divine life is ever new (though always containing all that has been). Idealism: A theory proposing the basic units of reality are mental, that things are ideas in a mind. Idealism strives to overcome the incoherence of Dualism by denying “matter” makes sense. Idealists may assert there are many minds as did Bishop Berkeley or only one mind, the cosmically inclusive mind, of which we are all parts (“modes”). In either pluralistic or monistic Idealism, the basic units of reality are usually conceived as wholes that remain, contradictorily, self-identical throughout successive alterations, except for those who like Parmenides’ say reality is changeless. Infinitesimal: An “infinitely small” amount. Likely a meaningless expression. Whitehead says all attempted references to “infinitesimals” refer to finites so small no one is interested in their size. The attempt to conceive of an infinitesimal occurred as an effort to solve the problem of the irrational number (the irrational ratio), that is, a relationship of two quantities that could not be expressed as a ratio of one whole number to another. The Pythagoreans knew no such ratio could exist between the sides and the diagonal of a square unless the unit was so small it had no length, and yet it had to have some length or it would be worthless for measuring anything. The unit would to have some size and no size. This SomeNone is a logical contradiction. Logic: Specifically, deductive logic. The study of necessary relationships. Conditional logic studies what necessarily is the case given certain conditions. Metaphysical logic studies what necessarily is the case given any possible condition. Sometimes “logic” is used to refer to the process of arriving at empirical generalizations, as in inductive logic. Modal logic makes explicit the unavoidable modal aspect every statement has, namely, to be (1) Contingent: A statement that is true or false depending on certain conditions, or (2) Noncontingent: A statement that is either (a) necessarily true in all circumstances or (b) necessarily false in all possible circumstances, that is, is nonsense. Many logicians still think the second kind is only noncontingently necessary by definition, therefore, they see them as also dependent on the arbitrariness of definitions. The metaphysician says there are statements describing some aspects of reality that must be the way reality is, and are that way independent of any particular kind of definition. They are discovered, not defined. Whitehead’s Catagoreal Obligations (see Appendix 3) express some proposals for unavoidable characteristics all logics must exhibit. Logos: Greek for “word.” Creation was thought possible by the utterance of a word. By a deity speaking the word of something, that is, naming something, the word would become flesh, that is, actualized. Since male deities did not have wombs, this was a popular theory for creation by male deities. Cloning is likely a modern counterpart. Hermes in ancient Greek mythology was said to be the logos spermatikos, the seminal Word that came from the mouth (meatus?) of Zeus. Goddesses had originally brought things into existence with their word “Om,” which was the original logos, the supreme word, and an invocation to the Goddess’ pregnant womb. “Om” was Alpha, Å, the letter of creation, and also Omega, or “great Om,” the last letter of the alphabet, Ω, a womb pictograph. Eventually logos came to designate discourse, logical order and rationality. Heraclitus’ use of the term seems to refer to logos as both (1) the source and resolution of particular changing things, and (2) the pattern or ratio that describes the changes things go through. So the logos was seen both as the stuff (embodiment) of reality and the logic (necessary patterns) reality exhibits, and was often personified as a deity like Hermes or Christ, who originated with God’s Word that became incarnate in the world, and who was the source of insight and salvation since he was Reason, that is, Truth and Reality, itself. Luck: The unintentional result of the confluence of actions by somewhat free agents. If we believe there is a single agent for everything that happens, and if we cannot find someone to praise or blame for some happening, we will often attribute the result to a supernatural good or evil power: Good luck is called “God’s grace” and bad luck is called “the Devil’s doing;” yet, there are times when bad things are called “acts of God,” perhaps as punishment. If luck is not a factor in existence, and particularly if A Process Introduction to Philosophy 215 Glossary God/dess is thought to control, or be able to control, everything, eventually Job’s question will arise, “Why me?” when bad things happen. Meaningful: We can speak of (1) propositions or (2) life as being meaningful: (1) A proposition is meaningful when something (a symbol) is like something else (the symbolized). Meaning in this case is a function of symbolic reference. The meaning of proposition can also be a function of logical consistency. If an attempted symbolic reference is self-contradictory, the attempted reference is impossible, meaningless. (2) Life is meaningful only if two conditions can be fulfilled: (a) that what one does make a difference, and (b) that the difference last (be saved) forever. Most of our concern about salvation (being saved), comes down to finding ways these conditions can be fulfilled. “Egoism” is the belief (1) we must maintain our own experiences, since no one else seems to do so, and (2) we must live forever or the meaning of our experiences will disappear. Various forms of tribal, social and environment ethics come down to saying others will save us. Hartshorne’s theism says we make a difference, whether or not we want to, to ourselves and others, but also always to the Unsurpassable; and when we and all others die or forget, the all-inclusive, neverforgetful and never-ending memory of the divine life will always remember us, be affected by us, and, therefore, give us the logical basis for being meaningful forever. Metaphysic(s) The word was first applied to an untitled work by Aristotle about First Principles. It was bound together with, and after, a book called the Physics. “Meta” means “after” or “beyond.” In popular usage metaphysics is often believed to deal with a world beyond our present world, a world not capable of being experienced with our ordinary senses. The only sense in which metaphysics is beyond this world is in its ability to apply to any conceivable situation in addition to those that have happened: those that could have happened and didn’t and all the possibilities that can yet happen. In this sense metaphysic transcends the present. Metaphysics is the attempt to find the broadest, the most basic, the unavoidable characteristics every moment of reality must exhibit, not because someone is forcing reality to be as it is, but because the possibility of occurring without exhibiting these universal characteristics is meaningless. Metaphysical understanding sets the context of meaning for everything else. No idea or experience can be understood apart from a context of interpretation, and the metaphysic is the most general context. Only one metaphysic is logically possible, but the plural, "metaphysics," is used because many attempts to find the metaphysic have been suggested. Some philosophers even claim no metaphysic is possible (see Positivism). Every attempt to deny universal knowledge, however, requires one to assume s/he has some such knowledge. To a metaphysician, metaphysics is the heart of philosophy. Analytic philosophers emphasize clarifying the meanings of concepts, rather than building comprehensive metaphysical systems. Yet, a metaphysician will reply that clarity and analysis cannot proceed without conceptual tools, and these tools ultimately are the assumptions or beliefs of a metaphysic. Mind/Soul: (See also Soul) Usually thought to be a reality, a stuff or substance, that can experience diversity and still remain the same mind. Often thought to exist inside bodies, though usually capable of surviving on its own apart from bodies or matter. Mind is a good example of the attempt to explain change by allowing a single entity to alter internally by having new thoughts and memories without losing its identity. Parmenides’ challenge to this notion is sound. Monism: The belief that reality is composed of (1) one thing or (2) one kind of thing. The first is the Milesians’ and Parmenides’ position which also underlies much of Eastern philosophy and religion. The Milesian approach, echoed by the modern use of the term “energy,” believes the One (numerically) can somehow give rise to many changing things and still be one. Parmenides says a one can only be the one it is; change is meaningless. Change and the Unsurpassable 216 Glossary The second approach allows many things in the universe, but they are all alike in the kind of stuff they are. Democritus says the many are all internally alike, namely, like Parmenides’ being, that is, dead and changeless. Berkeley and Leibniz say there are many minds, and that matter, as a stuff independent of minds, is meaningless since matter is just ideas in minds. Monism is attractive, since in some sense the uni-verse must be one. The oneness of reality can partly reside in the uni-versality of metaphysical principles. Concrete unity, in process philosophy, is only momentary: Each cosmic moment can gather everything up into a Whole, but the novelties created the next moment (by everything that exists) must be gathered up again. The temporal unity of reality resides in the inheritance of past unities by the present one, not in claiming the past is the same stuff as the present, yet somehow different from the past because “it” has altered. Myth: A symbolic way of expressing a basic truth. Often the symbol is taken to be the reality itself. Though myths give us a handle on understanding reality, they usually fail to capture reality at its most basic level. Contending formulations give rise to much conflict since the meaning of our lives is directly tied to the symbols we use to explain our lives. Nonrational: Created relationships. Necessary relationships are rational. Most of life, however, consists of relationships that need not be as they are. These are not irrational relationships (namely, the failure to be a relationship at all), but simply nonrational, or created relationships. Necessity: A term that has two meanings: (1) Conditional necessity; for example: Given that one has a circle, its perimeter is necessarily related to its diameter by the ratio pi, !. (2) Unconditional necessity; for examples: (a) Given anything at all (and something or other must exist since “nothingness” is nonsense), creativity is necessarily occurring, or (b) the result of each moment of the unsurpassable series will contain more diversity than the moment before. Metaphysic is the systematic discovery and clarification (not invention) of unconditional necessities. Noncontingent: Usually means “unconditionally necessary.” However, one should realize that nonsense, or logical self-contradictions, are also noncontingent since what they attempt to describe is not possible in any way. So the strict contradictory of “contingent” is “noncontingency,” not “necessity.” “Necessity” and “Nonsense” are logical contraries. After Anselm had correctly clarified that the concept “unsurpassability” cannot be meaningfully unless it is described as noncontingent, he failed to make clear how Unsurpassability is noncontingently necessary, rather than noncontingently nonsense as positivists claim. Hartshorne has dedicated his long life to doing what Anselm didn’t, and probably couldn’t do given the conceptual world he lived in, namely, making sense of “That Than Which Nothing Greater Can Be Conceived.” Nonsense: Logically impossible. Necessarily not contingent, and necessarily not necessary. A selfcontradiction. The failure to express either a contingent or necessary proposition. Nothingness: The attempt to refer to the absence of every thing. Parmenides is undoubtedly right here: All attempted references to nothing (or nonbeing, in his words), are impossible, that is, self-contradictory. All meaningful negative terms like “not” and “nothing” are relative. They refer to something, but something that is different from what one is presently interested in. The logical preface “non” is used to refer to all that is not included in the present class of interest. A necessary idea is one that cannot be excluded from any class that describes a concrete moment of existence. It says something about every concrete thing. A contingent idea is one that refers to some (actual or possible), but not all. Object: See Subject. Omnipotence: Literally, “all-powerful.” A major failure of theology has been the assumption one reality can have all the power, leaving none to anything else. But to exist is to do something, that is, exercise some self-power, and theories that claim only One reality exists are highly problematic. Power is a dyadic relationship, requiring A Process Introduction to Philosophy 217 Glossary (1) one who exercises the power and (2) one who receives the affect of the action. Exercising “complete power” anywhere is impossible, a failure to make sense because the exerciser of all the power has no place to exercise any power at all. “Omnipotence” can mean “having appropriate power everywhere.” Universality of power is possible when referring to where power is exercised, that is, in others. The amount of power, however, must be characterized by always being appropriate or good, not the logical nonsense of always doing others’ doings for them. More power is not always better, as power worshippers naively assume. Ontological Argument: Often characterized as the attempt to establish: “God must exist because God’s being (onto) is necessary being.” Somewhat naively put, this attempt tries to say the greatest reality one can think up must also exist (in addition to the idea) or the reality would not be great. In this illogical approach, existence is assumed to be a factor in greatness, that is, to exist (in addition to the concept) is assumed to be greater than the concept alone of something existing. But the Argument’s real strength lies elsewhere, since it’s probably not possible to prove existence must always be greater than nonexistence. The real insight of the Argument, so seldom seen even by philosophers, is the modal status of the attempted concept of “Unsurpassability.” Necessity surpasses contingency, so a necessarily existing reality surpasses a contingently existing one, even if the contingently existing one also exists. This is true, however, only if “necessarily existing reality” is meaningful, not mere nonsense. Anselm was correct to insist that That Than Which Nothing Greater Can Be Conceived must be noncontingent, but he did not establish that a “noncontingent reality” made sense and, therefore, was necessary rather than being noncontingent as nonsense. A necessary being, or act, or state of affairs, is likely nonsense as the positivists (and Hartshorne also) insist. Since Anselm seems to think the Unsurpassable refers to a necessary state of affairs (a necessary Being), he must show how this makes sense. Since he probably can’t do so, he might have done better to conclude the notion of “unsurpassability” is meaningless rather than identity it with his God. Orphism: A Greek mystery religion begun in the middle of the first millennium BCE. It maintained men had souls that longed to be freed from their earth-bound bodies. Denial of life’s pleasures could help free it, an idea that influenced many Greek philosophers, including Pythagoras and Plato. Its emphasis on individual salvation was a threat to the more bureaucratic priesthoods. Orpheus, the ancient world’s pied piper, was at times said to be the son of a Muse because his music was so seductive. He was ritually sacrificed and descended into the underworld controlled by women to discover the secrets of the mysteries so he could return and share them with men, as did the Norse deity, Odin. Orphism was a major rival of Christianity, which absorbed much of its doctrine by identifying Christ with Orpheus. According to Walker (WEMS, 747) “Fourth-century Christian art showed Christ in the guise of Orpheus, wearing a Phrygian cap [as did Mithras], playing the lyre, a sacrificial lamb under his foot.” See pictures of Orpheus end of Chapter 18, page 134, and Appendix 2. Panpsychism: The belief that reality consists only of mental realities; that “dead matter” is meaningless. Process philosophy accepts a form of panpsychism: Anywhere there is anything there is at least a minimal amount of creativity, subjectivity and feeling. Consciousness is not necessary for a psyche (mind). Hartshorne prefers the term “psychicalism. ” Pantheism: All is God/dess. Theistic position identifying God/dess with the world, or vise versa. Usually this results in the diversity of the world being dismissed as superficial, and the belief that change is either impossible or fully determined. “The beginning and the end are the same,” as T. S. Eliot says in “Four Quartets,” echoing the Eastern philosophies (see Voskuil, “Some Philosophical Ideas in T. S. Eliot’s ‘Four Quartets’”). Panentheism: All is in God/dess. The divine is the unity of the universe. God/dess is not apart from the universe, but is more than the universe. The present moment of the divine’s creativity is outside the universe as it has just previously come to be. The universe is inside and, therefore, less than, the present moment of the divine that includes it. Parthenogenesis: The ability of a female to reproduce without being fertilized by a male. 218 Change and the Unsurpassable Glossary Particular/Universal: A particular is opposed to “universal.” For those who believe in enduring substances that alter over time, a particular is a unique, individual thing that can be found in only one place at a time but can exist as the same thing at many times and places successively. For the some Buddhists, a particular is the present, instantaneous moment, found only at one place and only at one time. For Whitehead, the creating moment is also a once-in-a-universe creation, the process of the present moment is a particular, but its created result will be found in many places and times. For Democritus, atoms were the particular things; for Plato or Pythagoras and many since, souls are particular or single realities. A “universal” is a general characteristic that can be found in more than one place and at different times. All the qualities one can identify are universals, that is, abstractions. Some universals are (1) somewhat general, like Redness, Happiness or Tree. Others are (2) fully general, truly universal, because they are necessarily found in every place and at all times. These universals are metaphysical characteristics. Whitehead’s theory of creative moments puts a new slant on the old division of particular and universal. Each moment of creative activity is a particular, but the result of that moment is found in other moments; it can even be found in several other future moments at the same time. This means that the coming-to-be of a being is a particular, but the being that comes to be is a “universal” characteristic (a general) that qualifies others’ creativity, since it is transmitted from moment to moment around the universe. So Whitehead’s philosophy is unique in that particulars become universals, whereas in most other philosophies (known as substance-attribute philosophies), a particular remains a particular while the universals that qualify it are exchanged, a theory that is self-contradictory, as Parmenides points out. Since universals are changeless, and since particulars supposedly change in the substance-philosophy theory by altering their attributes, and since change was thought to be a defect because change brought loss, the changeless universals were identified with the really real by Plato and many since. Eventually they were seen as the changeless content of God’s reality, as first stated by Aristotle in his description of the Unmoved Mover. Patriarchal: Cultures or belief systems that venerate maleness and deprecate females and female metaphors used as fundamental explanations. Opposed to matriarchal or matrifocal. The movement to overthrow the dominance of female-based cultures symbolized by the Goddess, began around four thousand BCE. Much of the older tradition is just below the surface in patriarchal cultures where it constantly threatens the established assumptions. Patriarchy is not as such a recognized religion, but it is a common factor in nearly all world religions, so much so that many refuse to recognize any other form of religion. The American Indian’s religion, in which the Great Mother is a major element, was called devil worship (Spirit Lake becomes Devil’s Lake, for example) and exterminated. Only recently has Wicca been legally recognized as a religion in the United States. The United States’ concern for freedom of religion only extends to those religions it is comfortable with, which in the past has been (if not still for many) some forms of Judaeo-Christianity. Patriarchy has been defined as veneration of warrior cults led by sky gods. The generation of life from the earth’s dirt and the natural issue of body fluids to create and nourish life are denigrated while at the same time lauding the hero who conquers or kills Mother Nature and traumatically spills her blood in his battles (see Perseus/Mithras, Chapter 16, who slays the Gorgon, Medusa, symbol of the natural cosmos). Person: In the process metaphysic, “person” is a term referring to a series of creations where each superseding creation includes the previous one’s results. Something that can change and still remain the same is a person or individual. What is the same is the series. It is the same series as long as the same past is retained in each present. What is different is the result of each new present moment of the series. Philosophy: Love of wisdom. Here used nearly synonymously with metaphysics. Plenum: To be filled. The belief reality has no “nothingness,” which is a well-founded belief since “nothingness” is impossible to conceive. Anaxagoras says beings, “seeds,” fill reality. Democritus says there is a nothingness, the Void, in which his somethings, atoms, bang around. Whitehead says reality is filled, but with moments of creating, comings-to-be, not with being(s). A Process Introduction to Philosophy 219 Glossary Positivism (Relativism): Most generally, the position that metaphysics is not meaningful knowledge. The belief that all meaningful propositions and situations are contingent, or have a meaningful alternative, even though the alternative need not actually exist. Every true statement could possibly (logically) have been false, and every false statement could have possibly been true, even if, in our present world, it is not a factual possibility (likelihood). As generally used here, the term, “positivist” refers to any anti-metaphysician, that is, anyone who believes all statements of “unconditional necessity” are meaningless. Potentiality: The openness of the future to become something new. Whitehead calls potentialities, “eternal objects”, and talks about a potential as if it were a specific, or a complex of specifics. Creativity “ingresses” the specific possibility and makes it actual. Hartshorne refers to potentiality as a generic characteristic only specified to some degree by past actualities. Creativity is the process of making a specific within the continuum of a generic characteristic. “Pure potentiality” is a meaningless expression. “Complete openness” is not possible since all potentiality resides in the opportunities presented to the present moment by previous actualities. Likewise “pure actuality” is meaningless since every actualization provides a range of possibilities capable of new specifications forever. Potentialities are on a continuum, and all continua are capable of endless divisions or specifications. Potentiality is not another kind of reality from actuality: It arises from the completion of an act (or acts) as it influences the outcome of the present moment of creating. To be actual is to be in process of accomplishment, and what is specifically accomplished is something never before done. But the doing is done within the range afforded by the standpoint, the actualized world of beings, with which the moment begins. Actuality, or coming-to-be, is dipolar. It contains some things already actualized, that is, beings, and projects a generic range of possible doings, that is, potentiality. The “real potentiality” of the moment (which is the range of potentiality capable of being realized in some way) is established by just those beings which are included that had just come to be. All possibilities can never be fulfilled, so there can never be a time when there is nothing more to do, and since “nothingness” is meaningless, there can never be a time when “nothing” is being done. Precession of the Equinox: The progressive change of where the sun crosses the celestial equator on the two equinox days, the beginning of spring and fall when day and night are of equal length. The earth wobbles like a top causing the plane of the earth’s equator projected out to the sky to change relative to the orbit of the sun, the ecliptic. This wobble takes 25920 years to complete. Astrologers have divided this into twelve units of 2160 years each, and each associated with an animal, therefore, the Zodiac (from zoo). When the sun crosses the equator in the constellation named for that animal, we are said to be in that Age. The ancient Greek and Romans were in the Age of Aries, the Ram. The previous Age was that of Taurus, the Bull, who was said to have “died” to bring in the Age of the Ram. The New Age to come for the ancients was Pisces, the Fish, and the Ram had to die to bring in that Age which we are still in. In 200 years the next new Age of Aquarius will begin. Much is made of these Zodiac symbols, and the constellations generally, to help create religio-philosophical interpretations of the world (see Chapter 16, Mithraism, for example, or Freidel, Maya Cosmos). Primary Qualities: Characteristics which physical objects supposedly have in themselves apart from any interaction with minds. These are usually said to be, by John Locke, for example, nearly the same characteristics Democritean atoms had: size, shape and texture, motion, number, solidity. Secondary qualities, such as color, sound, smells, etc., supposedly arose in the mind in contact with the physical things. Still others talk about tertiary qualities, which are emotional reactions to the secondary qualities, like pleasure or fear. Process philosophy stands this arrangement on its head. We first feel and react to the world. Then we give definition to the feelings by forming classes of feelings, that is, qualities; and finally we see that kinds of feelings are somewhat quantifiable and external to each other, that is, the characteristics of objects in abstraction from their qualities. Primordial: Having no beginning. 220 Change and the Unsurpassable Glossary Principle of Sufficient Reason: As first articulated by Leibniz, it is the belief there must be a reason sufficient to explain every occurrence. This reason, when sufficient, is said to exclude any free choice. But three kinds of reasons can be given: (1) causes or conditions that others have created that the present must contend with (efficient causes), (2) the attractiveness of the future for the present (final causes), and (3) the freedom of the present to somewhat shape the outcome of the present moment after it has begun. The determinist believes past conditions (or the attractiveness of the future) fully conditions the present to be what it must be. Determinists believe an outcome is only sufficiently explained if the present must do what it does. Science tends to looks for physical causes that force the present to be what it is because of past conditions. Leibniz and others allow minds that supposedly have choices, but one’s final cause is so much more persuasive than others that one’s “choice” is determined. Leibniz, for example, says God must choose to create the best possible world, and since there is only “one best,” God is determined to choose what he does. Leibniz erred not by saying God/dess must choose supremely, but by assuming “one best” makes sense. There are always co-equally good values to choose amongst (see Chapter 23, Unsurpassable Goodness). Those who maintain the third position say the present is more than the conditions of the past, and though they need not deny causes of the first kind, they assert such causes are never sufficient to explain the details of the event’s outcome. Process philosophy’s position is that causal conditions are necessary, but never sufficient to explain what happens. This position gains some support even in physical science from Heisenberg’s Principle of Indeterminacy, where, given all there is to know about what goes into a quantum event, the exact outcome is not fully knowable. Probability: The likelihood of one kind of thing occurring compared to another. For some things to have a statistical probability, it is logically impossible that everything be statistically based. In order for one side of a die to have a one in six chance to occur, there must be no chance the die will evaporate. All statistical conditions occur within broader contexts of constancy. The widest bounds, and the completely constant conditions of reality, are the metaphysical aspects. Mathematical chaos theory might say these are the universal “attractors.” Proposition (Statement): A sentence that makes sense. More generally, an idea or expression conveying information or evoking an actual or possible feeling, for example, a gesture is a proposition. In Whitehead’s philosophy, every actual entity is a proposition. The moment’s causal base is its collective subject, and its unity is the predicate (the moment’s goal) which expresses the unity of process during its actualization, an act that will fulfill the predicate in some way or other within the bounds of possibility named by the predicate which, in Whitehead’s vocabulary, is called the Subjective Aim. Quantification: In logic, the recognition that every proposition, whether or not explicitly stated, refers to All, Some or None of it subject. All and None are universal quantifiers. Some is the particular, or restrictive, quantifier. Both All are None are contradicted by Some since Some means “at least one less than all (perhaps, none) or one more than none (perhaps, all)”. All and None are the limiting cases of Some, so if None is true, then Some (at least one) and All must be false. If All is true, then None and Some (at least one less than all) must be false. The contradictory of a universally quantified proposition asserts the least one needs to know to prove the universal proposition is false, namely Some (one less than All or one more than None). The contrary of a proposition states the most one can know, the limiting case, which is the other universal extreme, All or None. Quantum Physics: The theory stating every change in physical reality comes in an indivisible, finite amount, a certain quantity, a quantum. An event can be analyzed into smaller units of happening, but not ad infinitum. There is a smallest happening for each kind of event, and this unit is not capable of being analyzed into smaller units. Even given complete knowledge of the situation that precedes or goes into this smallest unit, no one can know exactly how it will conclude a quantum moment later. This “all or none” thesis was first stated by the atomists, but only for spatial extension. Einstein later rediscovered the quantum principle while trying to explain how a warm body radiated its energy. He found radiation was not continuously lost or absorbed, but was radiated or absorbed in finite packets. As a determinist, he was never comfortable with the indeterminacy Heisenberg showed was implied in his discovery. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 221 Glossary Physics at the quantum level has all but given up on particle theory. Reality (including all of space) is seen as a plenum of quantum occurrences called a “field” in which the results of happenings in one place of the field are transmitted throughout the field by intervening members of the field. Large-scale, observable, matter appears where a constant field pattern is maintained analogously to a standing wave. Rationalism: The belief that reason, not sense experience, is the way to knowledge. The search for necessary relationships. Every philosophy is based on some rational, that is, necessary, assumptions, about the way the world is and must be. The ultra-rationalist believes only necessary relationships are real or true; happenstance, or contingency, is appearance or maya, and unreal. Since sense experience cannot discover necessities, the empiricist denies they are real. Yet, the empiricist cannot define what “sense experience” means without appeal to the generalities afforded by reason. Reason: The process of comparing abstractions and discovering their unavoidable relationships. More broadly defined, it refers to the process of discovering relationships among experiences and ideas one has. Reason is often opposed to sense experience, though only a radical empiricist will dismiss reason. The ultra-rationalists, or the other hand, will dismiss the experience of change and free choice as not (fully) real, even though they must still act as if they are real. Reductionism The belief that a whole can be analyzed into the parts it contains without loss. The so-called container is just the “parts.” This belief continues to be perpetuated because we tend to confuse a whole with an aggregate or collection, whether in physics, sociology or cosmology. The contrary belief, that what is really a collection is treated as a single whole, Whitehead calls the Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness (see Glossary entry). Relations, Internal/External: Two acts can be related to each other by being outside of each other, that is, mutually externally related, or by one being internal to the other. A close inspection of relationships will show that one who maintains all relationships are external could never know this, since nothing could be in one’s knowledge. The relationship of M existing inside of another N necessitates there be something outside M (“outside” in the sense of being around the one contained). Any theory of reality that tries to deny either internal or external relationships is bound to fail. In the Whiteheadian process metaphysic, many new, mutually externally related creations (contemporaries) are taken into a moment of actuality, so they are inside the moment including them. All processes are external to other units of process since a process cannot be a part in another process. A subject (which is a process) cannot be in another subject as a subject, as Aristotle pointed out, but the result of a subject (its “satisfaction” which is the subject completed and objectified), can be in other subjects. The analogous statement in a substance-attribute metaphysic is: A substance cannot be in another substance––which leads substance philosophies into solipsism (see Glossary entry) because traditional substances are not momentary and so are not open to the created results of other subjects. If the Unsurpassable makes sense, all beings made by anyone at anytime are in the next cosmically inclusive process. In discussions of internal and external relations that ignore the language of parts and wholes, something B is said to be internally related to another A when B is affected by A. A is not affected by B, so A is said to be externally related to B. It is impossible, in Whitehead's analysis, that B can affect A for this would be saying the present can alter the past. This use of “internal/external” is the opposite that used to describe parts and wholes. Parts are in a whole that contains them, and so the whole is outside the parts (though not a part from the parts). A whole is conditioned by its parts because it is, in part, what it is because of its parts; but its parts are not affected by the whole they are in. This dual use of internal and external to describe relationships can be confusing, but this book uses the language of part (as internal or inside) and whole (as external but partially determined by its parts), unless otherwise noted. Also see Contemporaries. Relativism: See Positivism. 222 Change and the Unsurpassable Glossary Relativity, the Special and General Theory of: The Special Theory explains why the temporal ordering of events and the spatial sizes they appear to have, depends on one’s location and motion. When two or more events are casually independent, that is, when neither event is in the causal past of the other, they are contemporaries. The temporal order in which contemporaries are experienced to occur by some future moment that includes them both depends on the location within the universe of the one experiencing them. However, when events are causally related, every point of view must experience the cause as occurring before the effect. One’s constant motion (for Special Relativity) relative to another determines how one experiences the other’s temporal extension and spatial size. The faster one moves relative to another the smaller they appear in the direction of motion and the slower their clocks seem to run, although the effect is not noticeable until speeds approaching that of light. General Relativity considers the affects of the change of rate of motion (acceleration and deceleration) and gravity (the affect of which is the same as acceleration). These forces seem to act on an individual to slow down the temporal extensions of its moments, that is, to extend the time taken for a moment to reach a result (to reach a satisfaction, in Whitehead’s vocabulary). Whereas Special Relativity explains that the perceived differences in timing and size as due to spatio-temporal perspective, General Relativity describes a real affect in the constitution of the moments of an individual’s moments of creating. Gravity is the expression in our cosmic epoch (perhaps in all possible epochs) of the attraction of one thing for another. The stronger the force acting on an individual, that is, the more others’ creations there are for an individual’s moments to embrace and integrate, the more effort it takes to bring the integrating moment to completion, so time slows down. Similarly with any form of acceleration: More effort is required to alter the path of an individual’s endurance than to continue as before. To alter (“revert,” Whitehead’s term for novelty) the initial path of continuing on as one has in the past takes effort which slows down a series of creative processes and the time measured by the differences they create. Causal interaction (transmission) in the world is necessarily finite; it seems to be limited to the speed of light in our epoch. Since transmission within the world must be carried out by moments that occupy a finite space and require some finite temporal extension to occur, transmission cannot be instantaneous, even if some form of transmission is discovered that occurs faster than light. However, if the Unsurpassable makes sense, there must be a unique and cosmic division between past and future. The only contemporaries from this cosmic view would those creating themselves simultaneously with a present moment of the Unsurpassable. This means that influence between distant parts of the world would occur very rapidly, similarly to the way a localized pain is experienced by someone but the pain’s effect in the person is quickly feed back to all the cells that are influenced by that person. Some physicists deny there is any such cosmic effect on everything, but if it is sufficiently subtle (and there are good reasons to say it must be––see Chapter 24), there is no way or reason to rule it out. The philosophically general form of the theory of relativity says that nothing can exist in isolation from everything else. An “absolute” (as having no relationships to anything) is meaningless. To exist is necessarily to exist in relationship to something(s). The metaphysical statement of relativity can also be seen as a statement of the Theory of Evolution since every thing must be related to the past from which it evolves, around which it grows. Every fully real (whole) thing is at least related by being somewhat like everything else. Every whole exhibits the universal or metaphysical characteristics. Expressions like “completely different” are literally meaningless. However, is there something concrete (not just abstract metaphysical principles) necessarily related to everything? This is the search for the concrete unity of the universe. Since a concrete whole, even a cosmic unity, can only unify what has been done, it is not possible for a whole to unify new things done without being what it is and also not being what it is, as Parmenides pointed out. Hartshorne proposes that the something (God/dess) related to everything is a series of unities; each one of which unifies all there presently is (in being), including the previous unity of all there was. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 223 Glossary Religion: Rituals designed to evoke emotions and put into action what one believes or assumes is true about the ultimate nature of reality, including beliefs about how the universe is structured and what one’s purpose is for existing and dying. Representational Theory of Knowledge: Belief that the knower has a copy of the things known. In most forms of this theory, it is impossible to check out whether the copy is indeed a copy or likeness of the original. In which case, calling it a “copy” is a shot in the dark, impossible to verify. Therefore, some philosophers, like Berkeley, deny there is any such thing as the original, and others, like Whitehead, say the original is also part of the knower, though usually in a way that is not easily accessible by consciousness. The copy is supposedly transmitted from the original (at a distance from the knower) to the knower, so there is also always the possibility that the transmission is faulty. Revelation: Insight into the nature of reality. Often said to come from God/dess or one of the divine family, the Muses or angels. Divine revelations, by their nature, are not open to rational inspection. Those in power often try to have accepted without question what they claim to be truths by calling them divine revelations. Threats of eternal punishment for disbelief are common sanctions. Doubters have also been killed or tortured by those in power, often by the millions in holy wars (see Mack, A Myth of Innocence). Skepticism: Belief that sure knowledge is not possible. Most skeptics seem to be very dogmatic about their skepticism. They are sure no one can be sure about anything. Secondary Qualities: See Primary Qualities. Self-Contradiction: Trying to assert something and the logical contradictory of the assertion at the same time. Often self-contradictions are not explicit. One task of philosophical analysis is to make explicit, implicit contradictions, for example, “All statements have an alternative,” is a statement that implicitly implies the statement, “Some statements have no alternative,” as the alternative to the first statement. Since All and Some are logical contradictories, they both cannot be true, and, therefore, the first statement contains, or implies, its own contradiction. If one starts with the second statement, “Some, but not all, statements have no alternative,” implicit in it is, “Some statements do have an alternative.” But these two are logically compatible. This is Whitehead’s and Hartshorne’s position. The determinist would have us believe the contrary of “All statements have an alternative,” is necessarily true, namely, “No statements have an alternative,” or “All true statements are necessarily true” which is the denial of any real novelty. Solipsism: The belief that only the self and its internal ideas can be known, since there is no way to get in contact with or know anything else besides oneself. If the self is believed to be a substance, a soul, that alters and needs nothing else to sustain its existence, solipsism seems unavoidable, like the windowless monads in Leibniz’ cosmology. Whitehead attacks the assumptions underlying the seeming possibility of a solipsistic self. Each moment of an enduring person for Whitehead is a new reality that exists only because it depends on, and grows around, the results of others. To exist is to necessarily be in relationships to others. Soul: Creative energy, life force. Often thought to be a stuff that alters and yet remains the same stuff despite its successive changes. This theory develops as an attempt to answer Alice’s problem (see quote heading Chapter 8): Is Alice still Alice after she changes and no longer is just what she was? Whitehead says “soul” or self-creativity is an essential part of all acts, all wholes, but the soul of an actual entity comes to be and dies with its accomplishment which it offers to other souls to enjoy. “Soul” is coming-to-be. Being is what has been brought into being by a soul: To be is to be dead. Without death nothing is accomplished, which is the problem with Heraclitus’ system. To be dead is not to be gone, a mistake too many make. To be dead is to be a changeless part of others’ lives. The final question is: Is there a series of momentary lives (souls) in which our accomplishments will be forever enjoyed (or suffered)? Hartshorne makes a strong case for there being only one series of momentary lives always capable of having a new life, with each new life including all others’ deaths, namely, the Unsurpassable’s primordial and everlasting series. Change and the Unsurpassable 224 Glossary Space/Time: Originally, space was thought to be either the absence of all things, or a thing different from other things (objects). Things were in this space. Space has often been given characteristics, such as the Nineteenth Century’s aether, and the Twentieth Century’s space with variable geometry. But common to most theories has been the unity of space. Space has been thought to be numerically one. Everyone from Democritus to Einstein have concluded the real unity of the uni-verse, is the one container of all, namely, space. As space is either thought to be a part of Mother Nature, (the physical universe) or her container, those whose religious agenda was to remove oneself from the clutches of mater, sought a refuge in a realm beyond space. Whitehead and Hartshorne, emphasize that moments of process are the only wholes or “containers” reality can have. They invert our understanding of space: Space is not a thing containing things, it is an abstract characteristic found in processes, the characteristic of including others’ creations simultaneously. Space is the experience of the results of others as they are external to each other, though, of course, internal to the one experiencing them. Space is the experience of others coördinately. Time is the experience of others’ completions successively, that is, as nested within another. Neither spatiality nor temporality can be experienced alone: At least one moment of time is required to experience others coördinately, and the inclusion of others always includes diversity simultaneously experienced, because experiencing only the results of one previous other is impossible (see rationale for this in Chapter 24). Stoicism: A religio-philosophical system with strong deterministic beliefs. Stoics saw the cosmos as fully interconnected, where events at one place effect everything else. Since we have little or no say in what happens to us, their moral advice was to be indifferent to pleasure and pain. The expression, “He took it philosophically,” still harks back to when Stoicism was a major philosophical position. Many Stoic beliefs influenced Christianity; even the prayer of the Twelve-Step programs comes from the Stoics. Many Stoics were astrologers, believing the locations of heavenly objects had an effect on their lives. They believed in a series of cosmic epochs. At the end of each everything will be consumed in fire before the cosmos is recreated. Stoics at their school in Tarsus were probably instrumental in translating Hipparchus’ discovery of the precession of the equinoxes into a mythology that underlay the religion of western Mithraism. Subject, Object: A subject must include objects to be a subject. An object must be in a subject to be an object. Objects cannot include subjects. An object is a dead subject. An object is being; a subject is a comingto-be. There are not two kinds of reality. Only subjects are fully real; objects are necessarily parts or characteristics of subjects. Substance: In substance-attribute metaphysics, substance is the basic stuff of reality. This stuff can be material, or mental, but the common (and contradictory) theme is its supposed ability to alter by changing its attributes while still remaining the same substance. In linguistic terms, the substance is the subject, the attributes the predicates. Whether language developed the subject-predicate structure because of philosophical assumptions or vice versa, the subject-predicate structure of language makes it difficult to think of reality in other ways. This structure helps perpetuate the Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness. Parmenides’ criticism of a stuff that remains self-identical despite alterations should be carefully studied. The process philosophy criticism of substance philosophy is similar to that of some Buddhists: Each moment is its own substance. A “substance” is just the coming-to-be it is. It cannot be, or come to be, in more than one way, though it could occur somewhat differently from the way it does. It is a unique once-in-the-universe act. Supreme: See Ultimate. Syllogism: A form of deductive reasoning where two premises support a conclusion. Of the 256 syllogistic forms, only some are valid. Moral reasoning can be put into valid syllogistic forms known as AAA or A Process Introduction to Philosophy 225 Glossary AII: One premise stating the meaning of value, the other an actual or possible situation. The conclusion is a judgment of the value of the situation, arrived at by applying the value premise to a type of factual situation, for example, A A A (1) All lying is bad (the class of liars that are not bad is empty). (2) All Thespians are liars (the class of Thespians that are not liars is empty). (3) Therefore, All Thespians are bad. Bad Liars Thespians Just knowing that all Thespians are liars, does not in itself tell us that Thespians are good or bad. Likewise, knowing that lying is bad, does not in itself tell us that there is anyone who lies or is bad even if we assume the class of Thespians is not empty. See Fallacy of Existential Import. However, if we know Jim is a Thespian, we know he is also bad. A I I (1) All lying is bad. (2) Plato is a liar. (3) Therefore, Plato is bad. Bad Liars Plato One task of ethics is to determine whether there is a value premise that is applicable under all possible circumstances, that is, an ultimate value. Symbol: Something that stands for something else. Often a symbol stands for a very complex set of ideas and feelings which are, or nearly, impossible to articulate. An attack on the symbol is taken to be an attack on the whole complex. One task of philosophy is to clarify what symbols stand for and to search for more adequate symbols to express the most general thoughts and feelings. Change and the Unsurpassable 226 Glossary Trinity: Divinity was first conceived as multiple, the Goddess trinity, a projection of women’s biological life: pre-menarchal maidenhood, menstrual motherhood, and postmenopausal hag or wise crone. The trinity is also a corrective brake on the Parmenidean kind of monism often attributed to divinity. Reality is intrinsically social, even at the divine level, or perhaps one should say, especially so at the divine’s allinclusive level of reality. The divine family of Mother and Child is still a strong emotional image in the age of patriarchy, though the emphasis is often on the maleness of the child and servitude of the mother to the father. Ultimate and Supreme: Two ways attributes of the Unsurpassable can be formulated. An ultimate attribute (characteristic) is one describing the unsurpassable series. It states a quality the series has that is impossible to change or surpass by any reality, including the Unsurpassable him/erself. The Unsurpassable is always all-knowing, all-inclusive, influencing everyone, and so on. A supreme attribute is one that describes the present moment of the Unsurpassable series. It describes a condition that is unsurpassable by any reality except the Unsurpassable. To be unsurpassable, divinity need only be unsurpassable by another. Self-surpassing need not be excluded and cannot be excluded if change is meaningful. The Unsurpassable is supreme in the content of knowledge, the amount of happiness or sadness, the number of others influenced and included, and so forth, but as the universe creates new content to know, new individuals to influence and include, new feelings of joy or sadness, and so on, a new moment of the Unsurpassable must include, feel and influence them all. Only by surpassing the previous all-inclusive, all-feeling, all-influencing moment, can the Unsurpassable remain unsurpassable by any conceivable other. Ultra-Rationalist: One who believes all relationships are necessarily as they are. Most thinkers accept the relationship of pi or √2, the square root of 2 (the ratio of the length of the diagonal to the sides of a unit square), to be necessary (conditionally necessary) relationships. But the ultra-rationalist says the relationship of the color of a square to its shape is also necessary, as is the hair-do one is wearing, and everything else. All has to be as it is. This is a faith based on a belief all events are determined, a faith not even physical science maintains with much enthusiasm today, because Heisenberg’s Indeterminacy Principle seems well-founded (see Quantum Physics). A whole is always somewhat self-creative and is not reducible, as the reductionist thesis asserts, to the parts (causes) that it contains. 2+2 = (is identical to) 4 is only true at a high level of abstraction. Universals: See Particular. Unsurpassable: See Ultimate. A short way to state Anselm ’s That Than Which Nothing Greater Can Be Conceived. One must be careful to distinguish “unsurpassed” from “unsurpassable,” and “unsurpassable even by self” from “unsurpassable by another.” The Unsurpassable’s aspects that cannot be surpassed even by him/erself, are the eternal, changeless aspects of his/er personality. Those ways in which the Unsurpassable can surpass him/erself, express how the Unsurpassable changes. The way the Unsurpassable changes is unsurpassable even by him/erself. The Unsurpassable surpasses him/erself unsurpassably in concrete content each moment. Hartshorne in a typed letter with handwritten corrections, 5/22/97, wrote, “There is, if I may say so, one difference between your philosophy and mine. I emphasize positive concepts, you negative ones, e.g., Unsurpassable. My basic concept is the worship-worthiness of God as universally sympathizing with the creatures.” Since the list of positive ultimate and supreme attributes is long, and since it is misleading if many are not asserted together, I have chosen this shorthand. The reader should be advised, however, that Hartshorne is right. A negative by itself is not a definition. He did add, as if to say his criticism should be put in context, as a response to this book, “You are indeed a brilliantly original and resourceful person. I regret that you are, as it seems, no longer teaching philosophy classes.” Utilitarianism: An ethical theory, the basis of democratic assumptions, that states the ultimate justification for action is its tendency to further the greatest amount of happiness for the greatest number. Sometimes J. S. Mill (1806-1873) says we ought to act to further the well-being of the whole, but what is the whole? A collection is not a whole, a confusion that plagues Mill’s theory (see quote on page 143). Hartshorne correctly points out that a collection treated as a unity is an abstraction, and one cannot act so as to A Process Introduction to Philosophy 227 Glossary further the happiness of an abstraction. All value resides in wholes. How is one to determine which of the many wholes in society one ought to further? Utilitarianism is opposed to an autocratic, authoritarian ethic that bases goodness on obedience to an authority, as in “He is a good child; he always does what he’s told.” An autocratic ethic often has a whole that is to be pleased, but the whole is usually apart from those being judged, as in classical theism’s God , therefore, the judgment is logically in question because, if God does not contain what is known, then as in a Representational (Transmittal) Theory of Knowledge, the original is either not accessible or may be only partly transmitted. Whole: The fullness of reality, the concrete. Wholeness is process or creativity, not being. The unity of reality over time (through changes) cannot be one whole. It must be a series of wholes, each one containing the results of the former. All wholes, as wholes, are contingent. Since nothing exists except wholes (and their parts), and since wholes are contingent, how is a necessary reality possible and where are the necessities of reality, if anywhere? See Abstract-Concrete Dilemma. Zeno’s Paradox: Discloses the absurdity of assuming actual changes occur continuously. He points out that an arrow supposedly shot into the air does not move where it is, and cannot move where it isn’t, so motion is meaningless. For anyone who believes reality is composed of beings that exist continuously, there is no resolution to this paradox. He also tells the story of the tortoise and the hare, where the hare can never catch up to the tortoise that is supposedly moving continuously. All picturesque analogies aside, can a being B move from point X to point Y which is a finite distance from X? Since a finite continuum of distance can be divided in half, B must go half way to Y first. Then half way to half way, and so on, forever, since a finite amount can always be divided again. So the first movement of B towards Y must be a finite amount. An “infinitesimal amount” Zeno correctly points out is either no amount or some finite amount. Since he as sumes one cannot move a finite amount, because being exists contiguously and a finite amount would be a quantum leap, he concludes motion (change) is meaningless. The answer to Zeno’s Paradox is: Change does require a quantum leap, a finite difference between the new and the old. The leap is only a leap, however, insofar as one only looks at being: the being at the beginning and the new, different being at the end of the finite spatial-temporal change. In between the two observable beings is the fundamental reality of coming-to-be, the making of the new, finitely different being. Becoming is not observable because it is not an object. Only objects can be in and observed by subjects. Subjects cannot be observed. Subjects are observers and feelers of objects (beings) and feelers or anticipators of possible future accomplishments to be objectified for future subjects. So the making of a new being is a continuum, but an unobservable continuum, of effort: The observable result is a finite spatio-temporal difference from the moment’s beginning. 228 Selected Bibliography Creation Myths and Gender-Role Stories and Legends Campbell, Joseph. The Hero with a Thousand Faces, Princeton, 1972 (1949). Filoramo, Giovanni. A History of Gnosticism, Blackwell, 1990. Shows the extreme sexism of the centuries around the beginning of the Common Age. Fix, Wm. R. Star Maps, Octopus, London, 1979. Gardner, John and John Maier, trans., Gilgamesh, Vintage, 1984. Graves, Robert. The White Goddess: A historical grammar of poetic myth, Beacon, 1948, Amended and enlarged 1966.. Hadingham, Evan. Early Man and the Cosmos, Walker, 1984. Erdoes, Richard and Alfonso Ortiz, eds.. American Indian Myths and Legends, Pantheon, 1984. Dennis Tedlock, trans.. Popol Vuh: The Definitive Edition of the Mayan Book of the Dawn of Life and the Glories of Gods and Kings, Touchtone,1985. Walder, James R.. Lakota Myth, Elaine Jahner, ed., Nebraska, 1983. Wolkstein, Diane and Samuel Noah Kramer. Inanna: Queen of Heaven and Earth: Her Stories and Hymns from Sumer, Harper & Row, 1983. Contemporary Accounts of Male/Female Relationships Bly, Robert. Iron John, Addison-Wesley, 1990. Still a patrist point of view: must cut male off from the mother/feminine. Barker-Benfield, G. S.. The Horrors of the Half-Known Life: Male Attitudes Towards Women and Sexuality in Nineteenth Century America, (out of print and very depressing reading). Bryk, Felix. Sex & Circumcision: A Study of Phallic Worship and Mutilation in Men and Women, Random House, 1967. Out of print but packed with information. Daly, Mary. Gyn/ecology: The Metaethics of Radical Feminism, Beacon, 1978. Faludi, Susan. Backlash: The Undeclared War Against American Women, Crown, 1991. Sam, Keen. Fire in the Belly: On Being a Man, Bantam, 1991. Disappointing. Johnson, Miriam M.. Strong Mothers, Weak Wives: The Search for Gender Equality, University of California, 1988. Noble, Vicki. Shakti Woman: Feeling Our Fire, Healing Our World: The New Female Shamanism, HarperSan Francisco, 1991. Confuses, as most shamanism does, wholes which are alive with groups (collections) which are not except as each member is. Ritter, Thomas J. MD. Say No to Circumcision! Hourglass, 1992. Romberg, Rosemary. Circumcision, The Painful Dilemma, Bergin & Garvey, Massachusetts, 1985. Spretnak, Charlene, ed.. The Politics of Women’s Spirituality: Essays on the Rise of Spiritual Power within the Feminist Movement, Doubleday, 1982. Walker, Barbara G.. The Crone: Woman of Age, Wisdom, and Power, Harper & Row, 1985. Philosophy and Religion Brown, James and Reeves, eds. Process Philosophy and Christian Thought,Bobbs-Merrill, 1971. In four sections: Philosophy and Theology; God; Christ; and Man and Society. Contributors: George Allan, Delwin Brown, Don Browing, John Cobb, Malcolm Diamond, Lewis Ford, David Griffin, Charles Hartshorne, Ralph James, Jr., Bernard Loomer, Victor Lowe, Bernard Meland, Schubert Ogden, Thomas Ogletree, Gene Reeves, Donald Sherburne, Walter Stokes and Daniel Williams. CIMRM: Vermaseren, Maarten, Corpus Inscriptionum et monumentorum religionis mithracae. 2 vols. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1956, 1960. Cobb, John B, Jr. and Gamwell, Franklin, eds.. Existence and Actuality: Conversations with Charles Hartshorne, Chicago, 1985. Essays by Eugene Peters, Schubert Ogden, R.M. Martin, William Alston, John Smith, Paul Weiss, Manley Thompson, John Cobb, Jr., and George Wolf with responses by Hartshorne who often seems stiltedly kind to authors who miss some important points or misunderstand him. Cobb, John B. Jr. and Griffen, David. Process Theology: An Introductory Exposition, Westminster, 1976. Some merit; a few serious errors, viz: they say, “God is responsible for evil; . . .” confuse evil and tragedy; and want Whitehead to say that never-ending new experiences after ‘death’ is possible. Best feature: A lengthy “Guide to The Literature” with historical and biographical data in an appendix. Copleston, Frederick S.J.. A History of Philosophy, Vols. 1-8, Doubleday (Image), finished 1965. Very good though lengthy history. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 229 Bibliography Cox, Collett Disputed Dharmas: Early Buddhist Theories on Existence (Tokyo: The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 1995) Das Datta, Rama. “Self and Causality in Hume and the Sautrantika,” University Microfilm International, Ann Arbor, MI, 1984. Dombrowski, Daniel A., Analytic Theism, Hartshorne, and the Concept of God, SUNY, 1996. Eisenman, Robert H. and Michael Wise. The Dead Sea Scrolls Uncovered: The First Complete Translation and Interpretation of 50 Key Documents Withheld for Over 35 Years. Element Books Ltd., 1992. Reprinted by Barnes and Noble, 1994. Eisenman, Robert. The Dead Sea Scrolls and the First Christians. Elements Books, 1996. ______________. James the Brother of Jesus, The Key to Unlocking the Secrets of Early Christianity and the Dead Sea Scrolls, Penguin Books, 1997. Freeman, Kathleen. Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers: A complete translation of the Fragments in Diels, “Fragmente der Vorsokratiker,” Harvard, 1970. Freidel, David, with Linda Schele and Joy Parker. Maya Cosmos: Three Thousand Years of the Shaman’s Path, William Morrow, New York, 1993. Gaster, Theodor H. The Dead Sea Scriptures in English Translation, Doubleday, 1956. Griffin, David. “Hartshorne, God and Relativity Physics, ”Process Studies, Vol. 21, No. 2. Gross, Rita M. Buddhism After Patriarchy: A Feminist History, Analysis, and Reconstruction of Buddhism, Suny, 1993. Guignebert, Charles. Jesus, 560p., University Books, trans. from French by S. H. Hooke, 1956. First published about 1930. Still insightful and readable. Hartshorne, Charles: AD––Anselm’s Discovery: A Re-examination of the Ontological Argument for God’s Existence, Open Court, 1965,. His major statement on this commonly misunderstood issue. AW––Aquinas to Whitehead: Seven Centuries of Metaphysics of Religion, Marquette, 1976. The Aquinas Lecture, 1976. BH––Beyond Humanism: Essays in the Philosophy of Nature, 1937; reprinted Peter Smith, 1975. Excellent examination of the weakness of many forms of humanism. CAP––Creativity in American Philosophy, Paragon, 1984. DR––The Divine Relativity: A Social Conception of God, Yale, 1948. Discussion of how universal relativity or unlimited flexibility, rather than changeless self-sufficiency, is the divine attribute. IOGT––Insights & Oversights of Great Thinkers: An evaluation of Western Philosophy, SUNY, 1983. Comments on the history of philosophy. LP––The Logic of Perfection, Open Court, 1962. Essays on many subjects: ontological argument, organic structure of reality, meaning of ‘causation,’ eschatology, symbolic and literal theistic language, and definition of ‘metaphysics’. MVG––Man’s Vision of God, 1941, Archon Books.1964. Ideas developed that are full-blown in Philosopher’s Speak of God. MSNE––“Metaphysical Statements as Nonrestrictive and Existential,” The Review of Metaphysics, Sept. 1958, XII. No. 1. NT––A Natural Theology for Our Time, Open Court, 1967. Readable introduction. Gets into the subject through the concept of “worship.” OOTM––Omnipotence and Other Theological Mistakes, SUNY, 1983. Finally decides to give up trying to convince people that “omnipotence” means “having appropriate power everywhere” and simply deny that it makes sense. A tactical change only. PPS––The Philosophy and Psychology of Sensation, 1934, Kennikat, 1968. His theory of potentiality developed, a major difference from Whitehead’s ‘eternal objects’ and probably equally important in the history of thought as his clarification of the issues around the Ontological Argument. WP––Whitehead’s Philosophy: Selected Essays, 1935-1970, University of Nebraska, 1972. Some of the best material written on Whitehead by anyone. Hartshorne, Charles and Peden, Creighton. Whitehead’s View of Reality, Pilgrim, 1981. PSG––Hartshorne, Charles and Reese, William. Philosophers Speak of God, 1953, Midway, 1976. Comprehensive collection of primary sources from ancient to modern, from Eastern and Western thought, with comments. An excellent Introduction to theistic discourse that presents a system to classify theistic doctrines. Hershel Shanks, ed.. Understanding the Dead Sea Scrolls, Random House, 1992. Essays on the relationship of the Scrolls to the Essenes and other forms of Judaism. Hiriyanna, M. Outlines of Indian Philosophy, Allen & Unwin, 1932, 1964, Koller, John M. and Patricia Koller. A Sourcebook in Asian Philosophy, MacMillian, 1991. 230 Change and the Unsurpassable Bibliography Leclerc, Ivor. Whitehead’s Metaphysics, Allen and Unwin, 1958. Old copyright but still the best nonHartshornean secondary source on Whitehead I’m aware of. Lee, Jung. The Theology of Change: A Christian Concept of God in a Eastern Perspective, Orbis, 1979. Mistakenly sees Whitehead and Hartshorne as thinking of God in monopolar terms. Says the I Ching maintains change (God) is the ultimate reality beyond descriptive terms, but goes on the say many things, for example, it is beyond being a subject or object. Says change produces creativity rather than creations making change meaningful. “Change itself is changeless,” not just in the abstract, but as the concrete reality. Caught in the necessary-as-abstract and the concrete-as-contingent dilemma. The book is another example, this time in the Eastern tradition, of the inconsistencies of the negative theology and an enduring substance-based ontology. Loisy, Alfred. The Birth of the Christian Religion and The Origins of the New Testament, English trans. L. P. Jacks, University Books, 1962. French edition: 1936. Loisy and Guignebert stand at the beginning of the attempt to discover what can be known historically about Christianity rather than remythologize it. Lucretius. The Nature of the Universe, Penguin, 1951, trans. R.E. Latham. Mack, Burton. The Lost Gospel: The Book of Q & Christian Origins, HarperSanFrancisco, 1993. ____________. A Myth of Innocence: Mark and Christian Origins, Fortress Press, 1988, 432p. McFague, Sally. Models of God, (A discussion of McFague’s ideas in this book on a television special seem to complement my five-fold division of theistic concepts). Moyers, Bill. “Spirit and Nature,” PBS video special discussing various models of God/dess. Nahm, Milton C.. Selections from Early Greek Philosophy, 1934, Appeton-Century-Crofts, 1962. Nairn, Thomas A. "Hartshorne and Utilitarianism: A Response to Moskop," Process Studies, Vol. 17, No. 3, Fall 1988. Lewis S. Ford, ed. Navia, Luis E. & Eugene Kelly, eds. Ethics and the Search for Values, Prometheus, 1980. Noss, John. Man’s Religions, Macmillan, 1949, revised 1956. Odin, Steve. Process Metaphysics and Hua-Yen Buddhism: A Critical Study of Cumulative Penetration versus Interpenetration. SUNY, 1982. Scholarly discussion of the difference between (1) Buddhism’s interpenetration based on the belief that the logic of strict symmetry is applicable to all reality so that everything, past present and future is in everything else and (2) Whitehead’s cumulative penetration where the logic of symmetry is applicable to the infinite realm of possibility but where asymmetry is the truth in the relations of actuality, that is, the past is in the present and will be in the future, but the present is not in the past, nor even less so is the future. Some lessons to be learned here about how to meaningfully conceive of Omniscience and Omnipotence. Some interesting discussion of Jungian archetypes. Potter, Charles. Did Jesus Write This Book? (Essay on “The Book of the Secrets of Enoch” or “Second Enoch”), Universal, 1965. Fawcett, 1967. Despite the popularizing title, this is one place to find this interesting piece of pseudepigrapha written at the time of Jesus and discovered in Serbia in 1892. Many parallels and additions to the “blesseds” and “curseds” of the New Testament. Potter discusses this literature in relation to the Essenes. Process Studies, Barry L. Whitney, ed., Vol. I, No. I, Spring 1971 to present. The Journal for those interested in Process Philosophy. Radhakrishnan, S. Eastern Religions and Western Thought, Oxford, 1939, 1969. Segal, Alan F. Paul the Convert: The Apostolate and Apostasy of Saul the Pharisee, Yale, 1990. Analysis of the origins and rise of Pauline Christianity. Discusses the relationships between various Jewish groups, Jewish Christians and gentile Christians. Also insights one how conversion experiences shape religions and vice versa. Extensive notes and bibliographical material for further research. Suchocki, Marjorie. God-Christ-Church: A Practical Approach to Process Theology, Crossroads, 1982. First half a fairly accurate though watered down introduction to Whitehead’s metaphysic as related to Christian concepts with a short Glossary. Diagrams throughout are not helpful. The remainder on Christology, Eschatology, Trinity, and so on is not likely to be convincing to either well-versed process thinkers or traditional Christians Thiering, Barbara. Jesus and the Riddle of the Dead Sea Scrolls: Unlocking the Secrets of His Life Story, HarperSanFrancisco, New York, l992. Ulansey, David. OMM, The Origins of the Mithraic Mysteries: Cosmology and Salvation in the Ancient World, Oxford, 1989. Essential reading. Finds the origin of Christianity’s major competitor in the discovery of the precession of the equinoxes around 120 BCE. The religious formulation of this emotional insight that the universe was not stable was forged by the Stoic university at Tarsus and soon found believers in the Cilician-based pirates who spread it widely but secretly, not wanting others to have the power their insight controlled. The mover of the “fixed” stars and power over all lesser powers was called the Lord of Lords. The celestial Perseus (Mithras), His son by the mortal virgin Danae, “kills” Taurus to bring in the then new age of Aries. Perseus because of his location in the (Milky) Way to the heavens, and his influence with his Father, was able to help men who petitioned him to get through the treacherous after-life journey. Taurus (the Bull) had died on the celestial cross (where the equator and ecliptic cross on the equinox). A Process Introduction to Philosophy 231 Bibliography This crossing which was in Taurus had precessed into Aries (the Ram) who must also “die” to bring in the future age of Pisces (the Fishes). The implications for Christianity’s version of the Messiah (Christ) are interesting, but the main philosophical point to evolve from this movement is that the universe is in God, not God(s) in the universe. This insight and its implications for universal monotheism are still being worked out. Some of Ulansey’s illustrations are from CIMRM: Vermaseren, Maarten, Corpus Inscriptionum et monumentorum religionis mithracae. 2 vols. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1956, 1960. ___________, MHS, “Mithras and the Hypercosmic Sun,” Paper delivered at the Fourth International Congress of Mithraic Studies in Rome, Sept., 1990. Voskuil, Duane. “Disassembling the Mantra: Part/Whole Equivocation in the Category of the Ultimate,” Process Studies, Vol. 29.2, Fall-Winter 2000, Barry L. Whitney, ed. ___________. “Hartshorne, God and Metaphysics: How the Cosmically Inclusive Personal Nexus and the World Interact,” Process Studies, Vol. 28/3-4, Fall-Winter 1999, Barry L. Whitney, ed. ___________.“Discussion of Palmyre M.F. Oomen’s Recent Essays in Process Studies,” Process Studies, Vol. 28/1-2, Spring-Summer 1999, Barry L. Whitney, ed. ___________.“Ethical Meaning’s Theistic Implications,” Vol. 14, Winter 1975, Dialog: A Journal of Theology, Robert W. Jenson, ed., Dialog, Inc. ___________. “The Logic of Death,” Vol. 15, Autumn 1976, Dialog: A Journal of Theology, Robert W. Jenson, ed., Dialog, Inc. ___________. “Grace: God as Not Free Not to Love,” Vol. 17, Winter 1978, Dialog: A Journal of Theology, Robert W. Jenson, ed., Dialog, Inc. Asserts there is a metaphysical dimension to love that is an aspect of God’s essence. It does not deny co-equally good ways to love at each moment; so the way God actually loves does require a creative, free choice. ___________. “Some Philosophical Ideas in T. S. Eliot’s ‘Four Quartets,’” North Dakota Quarterly, Vol. 40, No. 3, Summer 1972. ___________. “Whitehead’s Metaphysical Aesthetic,” Dissertation, University of Missouri, Columbia, 1969. Whitehead, Alfred North: AI––Adventures of Ideas, 1933, Free Press, 1967. Readable history of ideas (especially the idea of “Freedom”) with some systematic items he didn’t develop in PR. AE––Aims of Education, 1929, Free Press, 1967. A series of essays on education and science. CN––Concept of Nature, 1920, Cambridge. An early work that continues the analysis began in PNK. PNK––The Principles of Natural Knowledge, 1919). Whitehead develops what he calls “panphysics,” an analytical point of view between physics and metaphysics. Both this and CN (all his work in some way) draw heavily on his insights in symbolic logic and mathematical relations. Dialogues of Alfred North Whitehead, written by Lucien Price, Greenwood, 1977. Price’s rendering of conversations in which ANW took part. Declared to be extremely accurate by ANW himself. “They reveal the charm and personality of a great man in his less formal moments as he discusses almost anything.” ESP––Essays in Science and Philosophy, 1968, Greenwood. Whitehead's last essay on his personal life, some philosophical issues, education and science. Personable as always and frank. PNK––An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge, 1919; Dover 1982. FR––The Function of Reason, 1929. Beacon, 1958. IM––Introduction to Mathematics, Oxford, 1959 rev. MT––Modes of Thought, 1938. Free Press, 1968. One of his last works and most readable with the pressure of his difficult systematic works behind him. NL––Nature and Life, 1934; Greenwood, 1969. PR––Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology, 1929; Free Press, 1978 corrected ed.. His major work. Heavy reading. Begins with an excellent statement of what philosophy is trying to do; presents a bare- bones categoreal scheme and then develops it. Along the way he has some unsurpassed insights into the history of systematic thought and presents his best effort at his life-long goal of providing foundations (a) for interpreting the notions of post-relativity physics, and (b) for how the abstract, definitional discipline of mathematics and logic has anything to say about the contingent, given world of sense experience. Though Whitehead discusses “God” and has some valuable insights, he is not so clear on this issue as one would wish, here or in any of his work. RM––Religion in the Making , 1926, Meridian, 1960. Readable account of the development and purpose of religion and its relation to rational understanding. SMW––Science and the Modern World, 1925. Free Press, 1967. Readable history of ideas with some obscure systematic chapters. S––Symbolism: Its Meaning and Effect, 1927. Fordham, 1985. Short development of some of the important vocabulary found in PR and a discussion of causation and the meaning of “meaning” as symbolic reference within an experience. 232 Change and the Unsurpassable Bibliography Philosophy of Science Aczel, Amir D.. Entanglement: The Greatest Mystery in Physics, Four Walls, Eight Windows, 2001. Beckman, Petr. A History of ! (pi). St. Martin’s Press, 1971. Davies, Paul. The New Physics. Cambridge, 1989. Einstein, Albert. Relativity: The Special and The General Theory, Crown, 1916. Gleick, James. Chaos: Making a New Science, Penguin, 1987 Gribbin, John. In Search of Schrödinger’s Cat: Quantum Physics and Reality, Bantam, 1984. Lederman, Leon with Dick Teresi. The God Particle: If the Universe is the Answer, What is the Question? Delta, 1993, Llinás, Rodolfo Rl, I of the Vortex, From Neurons to Self, MIT Press, 2001 Herbert, Nick. Quantum Reality: Beyond the New Physics, Doubleday, 1985. “An Excursion into Metaphysics and the Meaning of Reality.” Peat, F. David. Einstein’s Moon: Bell’s Theorem and the Curious Quest for Quantum Reality, Contemporary Books, 1990. Demonstrates once more the bankruptcy of the foundation of physical theory. _____________. Superstrings and the Search for the Theory of Everything, Contemporary Books, 1988. Silva, J. Andrade e, & G. Lochak. Quanta, World, 1969. Prehistorical and Historical Social Structure Barker-Benfield, G .J.. The Horrors of the Half-Known Life: Male Attitudes Toward Women and Sexuality in Nineteenth-Century America, Harper and Row, New York, 1976. Davis-Floyd, Robbie. Birth as an American Rite of Passage, University of CA, 1992. DeMeo, James. Saharasia: The 4000 BCE Origins of Child Abuse, Sex-Repression, Warfare and Social Violence in the Deserts of the Old World, Orgone Biophysical Research Lab, 1998. _____________.“The Origins and Diffusion of Patrism in Saharasia, c. 4000 BCE : Evidence for a Worldwide, Climate-Linked Geographical Pattern in Human Behavior,” World Futures, Vol. 30. _____________. On the Origins and Diffusion of Patrism: The Saharasian Connection, University of Kansas, 1986. Doctoral dissertation. Reprinted in Journal of Orgonomy, issues: 21(2), 22(1), 22(2), 23(2), 24(1). Eisler, Riane. Sacred Pleasure: Sex, Myth, and the Politics of the Body, HarperSanFrancisco, 1995. Ellegard, Alvar. Jesus: One Hundred Years Before Christ, Overlook Press, Woodstock, New York, 1999. Ferguson, George. Signs and Symbols in Christian Art, Oxford, 1958. Fox, Robin Lane. The Unauthorized Version: Truth and Fiction in the Bible, Knopf, 1992. Gallenkamp, Charles. Maya: The Riddle and Rediscovery of a Lost Civilization, Viking, 1959. Third revision, 1985. Gimbutas, Marija. The Civilization of the God dess, HarperCollins, 1991. Gimbutas is essential reading for seeing our culture from a prepatriarchal perspective. _____________. The Language of the Goddess, HarperCollins, 1989. _____________. The Goddesses and Gods of Old Europe, University of Calif. Press, 1981, reprinted 1992. Grahn, Judy. Blood, Bread and Roses: How Menstruation Created the World, Beacon, Boston, 1993. Herm, Gerhard. The Celts: The People Who Came Out of the Darkness, St. Martin’s Press, 1975, 312p. Excellent analysis of the Celts and their interaction with the Mediterranean powers from 400 BCE . through the Romanization of Europe and its collapse and its rechristianization by Irish missionaries. Karlsen, Carol F.. The Devil in the Shape of a Woman: Witchcraft in Colonial New England, Vintage, 1987. Lerner, Gerda. The Creation of Patriarchy, Oxford, 1986. _____________. The Creation of the Feminist Consciousness, From the Middle Ages to Eighteen-Seventy, Oxford, 1993 Mallory, J. P.. In Search of the Indo-Europeans: Language, Archaeology and Myth, Thames and Hudson, London, 1989. McGlone, William R. and Phillip M. Leonard. Ancient Celtic America, Panorama West Books, 1986. Popol Vuh: The Definitive Edition of the Mayan Book of the Dawn of Life and the Glories of Gods and Kings, Dennis Tedlock, trans., Touchtone, 1985. Rossini, Stéphane. Egyptian Hieroglyphics: How to Read and Write Them, Dover, 1989. Sjoo, Monica and Barbara Mor. The Great Cosmic Mother: Rediscovering the Religion of the Earth, HarperCollins, New York, 1987. Spretnak, Charlene. Lost Goddesses of Early Greece: A Collection of Pre-Hellenic Myths, Beacon, 1978. Stone, Merlin. When God Was a Woman, Harvest, 1976. Tannahill, Reay. Sex in History, Stein and Day, 1980. Teubal, Savina J.. Sarah the Priestess: The First Matriarch of Genesis, Swallow, Athens, 1984. A Process Introduction to Philosophy 233 Bibliography The Truth Seeker, July/August 1989. Contains the addresses of the First International Symposium on Circumcision (including female infibulation and clitoridectomy). Voskuil, Duane. “From Genetic Cosmology to Genital Cosmetics: Origin Theories of the Righting Rites of Male Circumcision,” presentation at the Third International Symposium on Circumcision, 1994. Published in Circumcision, A Virtual Journal , 1997. <http://faculty.washington.edu/gcd/CIRCUMCISION/v2n1.html#reprint3> also at <http://www.boystoo.com/history1.htm > a website concerned with the moral issue of genital integrity. Walker, Barbara. WDSSO, The Woman’s Dictionary of Symbols and Sacred Objects, HarperCollins, 1988. ____________. WEMS, The Woman’s Encyclopedia of Myths and Secrets, HarperCollins, 1983. The information in this work is essential for understanding the forces at work in our culture. Woolger, Jennifer Barker and Roger J. Woolger. The Goddess Within: A Guide to The Eternal Myths That Shape Women’s Lives, Fawcett Columbine, 1987. Sexual Biology and Homosapian Evolution Fagan, Brian M.. The Journey from Eden: The Peopling of Our World, Thames and Hudson, 1990. Morgan, Elaine. The Descent of Woman, Stein and Day, New York, 1972. Evolution from a woman’s point of view. Margulis, Lynn and Dorion Sagan. Mystery Dance: On the Evolution of Human Sexuality, Summit Books, 1991. ___________. Origins of Sex, Three Billion Years of Genetic Recombination, Yale, 1986. 234 Index A Aaron, 116 abandon hope, 7 Abel, 40 abortion, 3 Abraham, 40, 114 absolute, 64, 65, 67, 80, 198, 199, 204, 211 absolute beginning, 170 absolute motion, 67 absolute place, 67 absolute space, 67 absolutely nothing, 22 abstract, 59, 82, 157, 163, 204 abstract knowledge, 158 abstract meaning, 128 abstract meaning of value, 134 abstract necessities, 163 abstract-concrete dilemma, 163 abstractions, 26, 77, 157, 158 access, 39 accidentally, 16, 175 act of God, 175 active-passive, 28 actual container, 170 actual entity, 85, 182, 187, 204 actual existence, 156 actual infinitesimal, 64 actual reality, 82 actual whole, 162 Actuality, 64, 156-158, 162, 163, 172 actuality as potentiality, 162 Actuality, How Something Exists, 204 Adam, 41, 119 adequate, 26 adventure, 146, 194 Aegean Sea, 47 aesthetics, 3 aether, 53 Africa, 115 afterlife, 35, 93 Age of Aries, 107 aggressive, 28 Agnosticism, 159, 161, 205 air, 49 Alice, 2, 6, 7, 57, 166, 223 All, 9, 17, 27, 167 all in all, 180 all possible acts, 158 all possible facts, 10 Allah, 151 all-inclusive, 133, 163, 166 all-knowing, 27, 152 all-loving, 146, 147, 152 all-loving, 132 all-powerful, 174 almighty, 123 alpha, 58, 195, 214 Alpha and Omega, 56 alteration, 85 alternative, 8, 163 altruism, 134, 205 Amazons, 42, 102 American Christian Patriot, 114 amniotic fluid, 78 amputation, 42 analytic philosophers, 215 analytic schools, 22 Anaxagoras, 68, 87, 218 Anaximander, 49 Anaximenes, 49, 54, 65 angels, 147, 119, 151, 223 angels, 117, 119, 121 animal sacrifice, 40, 115, 116 animals, 3, 32 animism, 153 ankh, 195 Annie Sprinkle, 35 annual cycles, 101 Anointed One, 117 Anselm, 156-158, 159, 163, 179, 205, 211, 216, 217, 226 anti-metaphysicians, 22 Antiochus Epiphanes, 116 antipleasure, 101 apocalypse, 121, 205 apocalyptic, 117 Apollo, 110 appearance, 50, 95, 153, 204, 205 applicable, 25 arbitrary, 11 Aristotelian, 71 Aristotle, 19, 52, 77, 132,162, 206, 215, 218, 173 arrangement, 72 arrow, 64 art, 31 artifacts, 32 ascetic, 52, 115 asceticism, 102 Asia Minor, 47, 114 assumption, 5, 8, 9, 10 Assyrians, 41 astrologer, 108 astronomy, 106 Atheism, 153, 159, 161, 205 Athena, 58 atomism, 9, 71, 205 atomists, 54 atoms, 71, 73, 81, 171 attribute, 63, 160 Augustine, 80, 93 authoritarian, 174 authority, 12, 132 awareness, 143 axis of the universe, 107 Aztec, 194 B baboon, 42 Bacchus, 195 bachelors, 23 Bacon, 76 bacteria,, 33 bad, 132 bad luck, 175 baptism, 123 baptists, 116 basic aesthetic, 174 bathing in bovine blood, 106 beautiful, 11, 132 beauty, 53 becoming, 36, 59, 94 beginning, 170 behavior patterns, 191 being, 36, 59, 64, 68, 77, 84, 85, 87, 94, 155, 156, 171, 173, 181, 206 being only, 73 beliefs, 5, 6, 11, 151, 191 believe, 5, 6 believing, 5, 6 Bell’s Theorem, 188 bene Zadokites, 116 Bergson, 84, 95 Berkeley, 70, 80, 207, 216, 223 better person, 13 bicycle, 3 Big Bang, 49 biological evolution, 31 bird, 3, 36 bird song, 3 bird-watching, 3 birth, 93 birthing-creator, 41 Black and Caspian seas, 102 Black Elk, 150 blacks, 3 blessing, 39 blind determinism, 49 blind necessity, 49 bliss, 40 blood, 33-35, 39, 41, 101, 110, 194 blood and flesh, 101 blood line, 93 blood of the lamb, 110 blood rite, 39 blood sacrifice, 40 blood shed, 93 blood ties, 93 blood-letting, 101, 106, 115, 194 A Process Introduction to Philosophy 235 Index bodiless, 62 body fluids, 34 body of the Goddess, 94 boredom, 129 born again, 93 born of woman, 93 boundless stuff, 41 Brahman, 62, 97, 114 brain, 188 brain cells, 143 brain-trace, 72 breast, 40, 58 brethren, 115 broken mirrors, 78 Brown, 38 Buddhism, 102 Buddhists, 76, 81, 85, 97, 130, 144, 162, 178, 181, 206, 218 C Caduceus, 103 Cain, 40 Cain and Abel, 101 Calvinistic, 117 Canaan, 115 Canis Minor, 108 Carroll, 7, 21, 57, 166 Caspian and Black Seas, 42 castration, 52 cat, 2 catechisms, 11 categories, 88 caterpillar, 57 cathedral, 29 cathedral domes, 109 cauldron, 208 causation, 2, 16 cause and effect, 206 causes, 18, 171, 206 Cautes, 108 Cautopates, 108 caves, 109 celestial cross, 108 celestial equator, 108 celestial pole, 107 celestial salvation, 118 celestial sphere, 109 celibacy, 115, 116 centaur, 102 Central America, 106 chair, 11 challenge, 6 change, 2, 94, 195 change, 41, 49, 59, 64, 69, 85, 162 changeless, 9, 58, 62, 128, 163, 157 changeless is better, 50 changeless reality, 156 changeless realm, 77 changelessness, 77 chaos, 68, 134 chaos theory, 172, 220 chaotic, 71, 129 characteristics, 157, 162 charm, 173 chess player, 22 childish, 176 Chinese, 42 choice, 49 chords, 53 Chosen, 117, 195 Christ, 48, 117, 123, 214 Christ, 121, 152, 209, 213 Christian, 40, 115, 176, 211 Christian patriarch, 58 Christianity, 40, 102, 106, 110, 111, 117, 119 Christians, 110, 191 Christmas, 108, 192 christology, 176 Chrysippus, 106 Chrysostum, 42 Cilicia, 105 circle of Cilician pirates, 109 circles, 6, 10 circles, 8 circumcision, 3, 42, 93, 115, 102, 115, 117, 207 circumstances, 17 civilization of the Goddess, 42 clarification, 159, 160 class, 158 Classical, 153 classical theism, 170, 207 cleanliness, 166 clear and distinct, 80 clear, distinct and certain, 28 Clement of Alexandria, 58, 100 Clever Elsa, 57 clitoridectomies, 101 clitoris, 42, 58 coagulate, 33 co-equals, 174 Cogito ergo sum, 80 coherence, 49, 207 coherency, 25 coherent, 158 comet, 52 comfort zone, 144 coming-to-be, 84 94, 157, 178 common denominators, 158, 204 common factor, 8, 78 common past, 87 communion ritual, 35 comparison, 9 comparison, 59, 72, 77, 85, 178 competitively,, 39 complete control, 174 complete determinism, 17, 23 complete freedom, 17, 18, 173 complete nothingness, 158 completely abstract, 128 completely determined, 18 completely different, 22 completely free, 173 conceivable, 160 concept, 11, 160, 207 concepts, 12 conceptual existence, 156 conceptual necessities, 158 concrescence, 180 concrete, 157, 207 concrete actuality, 94, 156 concrete content of value, 133 concrete individual, 65 concrete unity, 63 concrete universal, 58, 59, 65 concrete Wholes, 133 concretely exist, 157 concreteness, 59, 64 conditional necessity, 10 conditionally, 10 conflagration, 106, 117 conscious, 171 conservation laws, 71, 208 Conservation of Energy, 71 Conservation of Matter, 71 consort, 39, 40, 101 Constantine, 121 container, 63 contemporaneously, 185 contemporaries, 94, 96 contemporary, 187 context, 11 contiguous, 76, 81, 87, 187 contingent, 19, 23, 85, 128, 153, 155-157, 158, 160, 163, 208, 214 contingent actualities, 158 contingent idea, 156 contingent in concrete content, 163 contingent premises, 160 contingently existing reality, 159 contingently rational, 9 continuous, 172, 182 continuous change, 64 continuous motion, 73 continuum, 63, 68, 69 continuum of being, 73 continuum of creating, 172 continuum of distance, 73 contradiction, 24, 156 contrast, 96 contribution, 128 cooperation, 39 Copernicus, 52 Copi, 21 Copy Theory of Knowledge, 81 236 Change and the Unsurpassable Index core, 87 Corvus, 108 cosmic, 3, 42, 151, 194 cosmic aether, 170 cosmic cross, 108 cosmic egg, 110 cosmic egg, 36 cosmic experience, 87 cosmic hero, 146 cosmic life, 132 cosmic lover, 122 cosmic moment, 184 Cosmic Mother, 49 cosmic reality, 78 cosmic salvation, 110 cosmic savior, 110 cosmic series, 183 cosmic stage, 121 cosmic unity, 41, 86 cosmic unity, 42, 43, 66 cosmic womb, 32 cosmic womb, 32, 194 cosmological, 144 cosmologies, 48 cosmology, 53, 144 cosmos 110 cosmos, 33, 48,, 88, 106, 107, 109, 110 covenant, 116 Coyote, 194 Crater, 108 created, 9, 163 created determination, 18 created reality, 9 creating, 158, 170 creation, 48 creations, 10, 78, 191 creations are supreme, 167 creative, 9 creative addition, 194 creativity, 28, 172 creatures, 2 crescent, 35 crisis of the irrational, 55 critical thinking, 5 crone, 33, 35, 208 crone, 35 cross, 36, 134, 108, 134, 208 cup, 108 curd, 33 cybernetic, 50 cycle, 40 cycles cycles, 32, 33, 194 cyclical ages, 106 cyclical bleeding, 194 D dagger, 108 Danae, 106, 109 Dante, 7 David, 117 dea, 78 Dead Sea Scrolls, 114, 117, 119, 211 death, 32, 34, 35, 59, 76, 93, 94, 114, 132, 170, 209 deduction, 159 deductive logic, 10 deism, 153, 209 deity, 132 deliberate loss, 175 deliberately, 175 Delphi, 106 democracies, 101 democratic, 58, 151, 174 Democritus, 71, 81, 85, 170, 171, 179, 205, 207, 208, 216, 218, 224 deo, 78 depth, 129, 174 Descartes, 21, 76, 80 destruction, 194 determinate, 172, 180 determined, 9, 19 determinism, 17, 23, 50, 73, 172 determinist, 9, 17, 163 deterministic atomism, 71 deterministic metaphysic, 173 determinists, 23, 25, 163, 206 Deuteronomy, 41 Devil, 175 Dickinson, 7 die, 87, 130 DIE FOR NOTHING, 127 differences, 59, 72, 194 dilemma, 157 dimensions, 192 dipolar, 94, 176, 178 dipolarity, 81, 94, 210 disciples, 115 discovered, 164 discrete amounts, 64 dispassionate, 75 diversity, 134, 170 divine, 40, 49, 78 divine order to, 11 divine plan, 117 divine power, 17, 151 divinities, 2 divinity, 2, 78, 192 divinity, 2, 11 divisible, 73 dodecahedron, 53 dominant males, 42 Dorothy, 3 Downward Way, 58 dualism, 68, 73, 94, 178, 181, 210 dualistic, 118 duality, 81, 94 duration, 181 dying, 33 E E = mc2 , 71 Easter, 192, 193 Eastern philosophy, 78 eating, 33, 34 eats, 101 eclipse, 48 ecliptic, 108 efficient, 19 egg, 109 ego, 130 egocentric, 133 Egoism, 42, 129, 130, 210 Egypt, 114, 115 Einstein, 71, 73, 208, 220, 224 Eleatic School, 63 elect, 115, 195 electromagnetic, 187, 188 elements, 49 Eliot, 217 Emanationism, 153 embrace, 82 Embryos, 36 Emory University, 3 empirical, 25, 210 empirical fact, 65 empirical science, 71 Empirical Theism, 159, 161 end of a series, 76 endurance, 167 enduring substance, 68, 94 energy, 71 enjoying, 3 enjoyment, 153 enriching, 152 enrichment, 146, 193 entropy, 188 environment, 143, 144, 184 environmental, 101 Environmentalism, 129, 134, 210 Ephesus, 58 Epicurus, 67 episeotomies, 101 epistemology, 211 epochs, 106 equally well, 167 equinox, 108 equinoxes and solstice, 110 error, 134 eschatological, 117 eschatology, 121, 211 esse is percipi, 80 essence, 155, 158, 163 Essenes, 102, 105, 114 eternal, 162 ethical, 11 ethics, 128 eunuchs, 40 A Process Introduction to Philosophy 237 Index Europe, 42 evaluation, 132, 178 Eve, 41 everlasting, 10, 133, 211 everlasting life, 130 evidence, 5, 6 evil, 41, 121, 147, 153, 169, 175, 176, 178, 192 evil Zadokites, 116 evolution, 211, 222 evolutionary, 128 ex nihilo, 41 examination, 5 exception, 8, 9 exchange, 77 existence, 11, 77, 157, 158, 163, 211 existence of God, 155 Existentialism, 211 existentialists, 156 expect, 5 experience, 9, 11, 28, 77, 86, 132, 143, 159 expression, 12 external, 73 external intestines, 102 external relations, 81, 95 external relationships, 28, 171 extra-marital, 41 eye for an eye, 118 F face to face, 54, 176 fact, 4, 9, 10, 11, 22, 23, 134, 212 factor, 9, 10 Factual (Empirical) Theism, 212 Factual knowledge, 160 faith, 6, 8, 17, 70, 81, 148, 226 fall equinox, 108 fallacy, 212 Fallacy of Existential Import, 158, 211, 212 Fallacy of Misplaced Concreteness, 11, 87, 221, 224 fallible, 192 fallopian tubes, 35 false, 22 false teeth, 16 familiar experience, 143 fatalistic, 117 fate, 106 father, 3 Father Brahm, 114 father god, 102 fear, 42, 119, 121, 144, 147, 150, 151 feeler, 81 feeling, 143, 171 feeling (caused by), 168 feeling alternatives, 172 feeling of loss, 191 feelings, 70 eemale, 2, 39 female metaphors, 11, 50, 93, 101, 102 female reproductive system, 101 female trinity, 93 females, 40 feminism, 122 fences, 194 fertility, 101 fetus, 36 fiat, 17 final causes, 19 final context, 11 final end, 128 final interpreter, 11 final state, 132 finite amount, 63, 64 fire, 48, 58 first moment, 128, 170 First Woman, 194 fixed stars, 107 flaying, 101 flesh, 35, 194 flesh and blood, 40 flies, 36 flow of feeling, 191 flow-er, 209 flux, 36, 58, 77 fool, 156, 159 force, 173 forever, 93, 128 forgetfulness, 130 forgotten,, 130 Form of Forms, 77 Form of the Good, 77 Forms, 77, 82, 213 founding fathers, 114 fragment, 161 fragmentariness, 192 free will, 119 freedom, 17, 18, 50, 67, 168, 172, 173, 201, 205, 231 frog, 36 Frost, 194 full reality, 9, 82, 84 future, 65, 128, 133, 172, 178 G gaining access, 42 gates, 119 Gaunilo, 155, 160 gender gender, 2, 3, 31-33, 41, 151, 194 genderless, 43 genders, 48 general beliefs, 11 General Theory of Relativity, 65 generic, 172 generic-specific, 28 genes, 39 genetic code, 33 genital blood-letting, 93 genital mutilation, 40, 42, 102 genitals, 40, 101 Gentile, 114 geometric patterns, 16 geometrical, 69, 77 geometrical patterns, 54 geometrical properties, 70 Gimbutas, 31, 32, 35 given, 9 glory, 122, 194 gnosis, 117 gnostic, 35, 53, 114 Gnostic Christians, 117 Gnosticism, 117, 213 goal, 5 goblins, 143 God, 2-4, 8, 11, 16-18, 21, 29-44, 48, 49, 51, 52, 58, 65, 66, 71, 76, 78, 80, 82, 84, 93, 94, 96, 100-102, 105, 107, 108, 110, 111, 114-124, 127-129, 130, 132-134, 143, 145-148, 150157, 159, 160, 162-182, 184, 185, 187-189, 193, 194, 197199, 205, 207-210, 212, 213, 214, 217, 218, 220, 223, 226233 God loves, 42 God/dess, 2, 8, 17, 110, 121, 122, 146, 151, 157, 159, 160, 163, 172, 173, 175, 185, 213 God’s likeness, 11 God’s plan, 117 God’s Son, 121 Goddess, 2, 32-34, 35, 39-41, 58, 71, 101 Goddess cultures, 76 Goddess tradition, 108 Goddess’ blessing, 34 Goddess-worshipping, 101 God-of-wrath, 117 gods, 93, 153 gods and goddesses, 150 God's mind, 51 good, 5, 6, 132, 174, 217, 192 Good News, 121, 122, 152 goodness, 11, 53, 168, 174 Gorgon, 106, 107, 108 Gould, 38 grace, 39 Grahn, 39 Grand Unified Theory, 49 Great Cosmic Female, 32 Great Father, 32 Great Goddess, 32, 48 Great Mother, 32, 93 238 Change and the Unsurpassable Index Greatest Conceivable Being, 162 greatest conceivable number, 55 greatest conceivable reality, 156 greatest conceivable whole, 162 greatest present whole, 162 Greeks, 47, 114 Groucho Marx, 155 group, 11 growth, 128 H hag, 33 Hale-Bopp, 52 happiness, 169 Happy Buddha, 33 Hartshorne, iii, 2, 3, 4, 11, 22, 25, 27, 28, 29, 65, 68, 70, 71, 78, 79, 88, 94, 110, 132, 134, 146, 150, 154, 157, 158, 160, 162, 163, 164, 166, 172, 177, 178, 179, 183, 188, 199, 201, 202, 205, 209, 210, 211, 212, 213, 215, 216, 217, 219, 223, 224, 226, 227, 228, 229, 230, 231 hate, 169, 178 hating, 121 have in common, 8 heaven, 94, 110, 111, 121, 122, 123, 130, 176 Heaven’s Gate, 52 heavenly Redeemer, 117 Hebrew, 41, 40, 102, 114 Heisenberg, 172, 220, 221, 226 Helios, 110 hell, 7, 94, 121, 123, 130, 176 Hera, 33 Heraclitian, 181 Heraclitus, 58, 64, 77, 85, 94, 95, 206, 208, 209 hermaphrodite, 58 Hermes, 58, 103, 214 hero, 109 heroes, 110, 178 heroic quest, 107 hierarchical, 111, 117, 195 hierarchical order, 116 hierarchically, 151 hierarchy, 115 High Priest, 116 Hindu, 62, 76 Hinduism, 97 Hindus, 76 Hipparchus, 47, 106, 107, 224 Hippasus, 55 history of philosophy, 27, 68 Hitler, 175 hoi ploi, 58 holiness, 192 holly, 48 holy, 39 Holy Spirit, 123 holy wars, 12, 93, 121, 223 hominoids, 42 homophobia, 42 hooks, 69 hope, 192 hope of life’s rebirth, 192 horse, 102 how, 158 human sacrifice, 40, 102, 194 Humanism, 129 humility, 134 hunt, 143 hunting, 101 Hydra, 108 Hylozoism, 213 hypercosmic sun, 110 hypotenuse, 54 hypothesis, 183, 213 hypothesize, 144 hysterectomies, 101 I idea, 6, 213 idea, 5, 6, 156, 157 Idealism, 214 Idealist, 70 ideas, 5, 6, 77 I-deas, 82 identity, 2 ignorant, 172 illogical, 159, 172 illusion, 78 immanent, 49 immortal, 62, 101 immortality, 40, 101 impossible, 10, 26 impossible things, 21 impure, 68 impurity, 114 inadequate rituals, 191 inclusion, 171 inclusiveness, 85 incoherence, 73 incoherent, 161 inconsistent, 161 incorruptible, 94 incubates, 41 Indeterminacy Principle, 173, 226 Indeterminate, 49 indeterminateness, 55 India, 42 indifference, 178 individual, 65, 162 individual as a series, 166 indivisible, 187 indivisibles, 69 IndoEuropeans, 42, 49, 58, 114 inequality, 195 Infallible experience, 28 infibulations, 101 infinite, 161, 162, 171 infinitesimal, 55, 73, 214 infinitesimal distance, 63 infinitesimally, 77, 181 infinity, 55 in-group, 145 inheriting, 87 initial conditions, 172 Inquisition, 71 insanity, 144 insight, 6 instant, 68 instantaneously, 185, 187 insubordination, 153 intense-faint, 28 internal, 28 internal alteration of a being, 72 internal relations, 81 intolerance, 192 invalid, 156, 158 iron, 102 irrational, 9, 10, 55, 144 irrationality, 144 Islam, 121 J James, 116, 120 Jehovah, 116 Jerusalem, 116 Jesus, 48, 110, 116 Jewish, 116 Jewish people, 114 Jewish ritual law, 114 Jews, 117 JFK, 12 Job, 215 John the Baptist, 120 Josephus, 116 Joshua, 115 Judaeo-Christian, 151 judge, 5, 6, 145 judging, 5 judgment, 5, 6, 101, 119, 132, 133 just, 122, 147, 151 justice, 178 justification, 132 justification by faith, 117 K karmic cycle, 76 Kepler, 1571-1630,, 52 key, 119 kill, 143 kind of creation, 9 king, 40, 101, 117 King of Kings, 107 King of the Earth, 119 king, Acrisius, 106 A Process Introduction to Philosophy 239 Index Kingdom of Heaven, 52 kinky, 34 knowable, 22 knower, 65, 81 knowing, 73 knowledge, 2 knowledge, 11, 168, 172 known, 81 Koran, 151 kosmokrator, 110 kosmos, 106 Ku Klux Klan, 3 Kurgans, 102 L labarum, 195 land, 101 language, 3 last moment, 170 last thing, 128 lasting over time (throughout changes), 170 Law of Contradiction, 64 Leibniz, 9, 16, 69, 75, 216, 223 Leo, 108 Levites, 114 Levitical, 115 life, 59, 64, 84, 170, 191, 194 life span, 167, 170 limit, 68 limited, 48 lineage of David, 117 lineage of the Levites, 117 lineal society, 130 little green people, 22 little people, fairies, 42 living for God, 127 Locke, 219 locomotion, 85 Logic, 8, 12, 63, 87, 85, 128, 192, 194, 214 logic of love, 122 logical, 4, 9, 25, 130, 132, 157, 172, 185 logical alternative, 157, 163 logical consequences, 195 Logical Contradictories, 17, 174 Logical Contraries, 17 Logical Positivism, 22, 23 logical possibility, 87 logical propositions, 23 logical relationships, 10 logically, 82, 85, 157, 159, 160 logically impossible, 22, 77 logicians, 158 logos, 49, 57, 58, 59, 208, 214 lord, 121, 107 Lord of Flies, 36 Lord of Hosts, 154 Lord of Lords, 107, 110 love, 31, 121, 143, 150, 151, 169, 173, 176, 194 Love of God/dess, 121 loved, 169 love-death, 101 loving God, 122 luck, 214 Lucretius, 67, 71 Luna, 34 lunar calendar, 115 M M, 78 ma, 33, 78 mad, 2 made in the image of God, 119 magic, 39 magnanimous, 145 maiden, 33, 35, 42 make a difference, 94 make sense, 8, 22 male, 39 male gender, 3 male hero, 102 male logic, 194 male-gendered, 50 mama, 33 mammaries, 33 mandate of Heaven, 42 manifold, 77, 78 many, 69, 84 Marduk, 41 Margulis, 33, 42 maria, 76, 78 marriage, 3, 41 martyr, 117 Mary, 37, 76, 78, 123 masculine, 2 master, 41, 121 masturbation, 41 mater, 49, 55, 78, 96, 111, 213, 224 material, 96 Materialism, 67, 73 math, 33 mathematical time, 67 matriarchal, 2, 42, 93 matriarchs, 40 matriarchy, 102 matrix, 78 matter, 49, 68, 69, 71, 78, 93, 96, 197, 198, 208 maya, 76, 78, 106, 194 McNamara, 127 meaning, 11, 128 meaning of, 128, 174 meaning of concepts, 12 meaning of life, 191 meaning of meaning, 130 meaning of value, 132 meaningful, 8, 146, 215 meaningfulness, 163 meaningless, 8, 128, 173, 130 measurement, 33 mediation, 86 Medieval, 42 Medusa, 107, 110, 218 memory, 59, 72, 77, 81, 95, 96, 121, 143 men, 3 men’s club, 93 menarche, 33 menopause, 33 menstrual blood, 35, 48, 93 menstrual cycle, 33 menstrual cyclical pattern, 40 menstrual fluid, 48 menstrual metaphors, 50 menstrual mind set, 39 menstruation, 33, 39, 41, 115 mental pain, 144, 175 merciful, 145, 147, 150, 152 mercy, 122 merely empirical propositions, 22, 24 merely rational Propositions, 22, 24 Messiah, 110, 115, 117, 121 metaphor, 32 metaphors, 2, 40 metaphysic, 77 metaphysical, 25, 68, 157, 164, 178, 179, 192, 220 metaphysical insights, 132 metaphysical knowledge, 26, 179 metaphysical logic, 194 metaphysical method, 65 metaphysical principle, 49 metaphysical proposals, 4 metaphysical propositions, 25, 160 metaphysical truths, 11, 194 metaphysician, 22, 156 Michelson-Morley, 170 Middle Ages, 40 Mideast, 42 might, 174 Milesians, 41, 47, 58, 65, 95, 205, 213, 215 Miletus, 47, 49 milk, 33, 48 milk of the Father, 58 Milky Way, 107, 108 Mill, 227 millennium, 118, 119 mind, 6, 12, 13, 14, 15, 50, 67, 68, 69, 76, 80, 87, 96, 188, 197, 199, 215 mind atoms, 72 mirror, 54, 76, 78, 176 mistakes, 6 240 Change and the Unsurpassable Index mistletoe, 48 Mitgard, 48 Mithraism, 102, 106, 110 Mithras, 195, 209, 217 Mithridates IV, 109 modal, 23, 155, 156, 158, 161, 162, 163, 199, 214 modal logic, 162, 163, 164, 214 modality, 28 mode of Existence, 167, 170 modern wave physics., 95 moment, 77, 156 moment of creating, 85 moment of creation, 157 moment of life, 85, 94 momentary lives, 143 momentary substance, 94 monad, 75 monism, 50, 68, 94, 215 monistic space, 170 monk, 157 monotheism, 41, 117 moon, 33, 35, 39, 48 moon milk, 41 moon-sickle, 102 moon-women, 102 morale, 173 more than, 82 Moses, 115, 117 Moslem, 43 mother, 3, 33, 35, 42 mother and child, 121 Mother Earth, 106 Mother Nature, 213 Mother of God, 193 mother stuff, 93 Mother-Womb, 41 motion, 71, 73 movie, 77 multiple inheritance, 87 multiple persons, 87 multiplicity, 183, 187 musical pitches, 53 mutations, 33 mutilate, 52 mutilations, 39 mystic, 40 mysticism, 53, 95 myth, 19, 32, 41, 43, 48, 122, 170, 216 mythological, 19 mythologies, 32 N nationalism, 195 natural order, 11 nature, 33, 71 Nazarenes, 115 Nazareth, 120 Nazirite, 116, 120 Near East, 111 Near Eastern mythologies, 108 necessarily contingent, 157 necessarily existing being, 157 necessarily existing reality, 156, 159 necessarily existing reality, 156, 159 necessary, 5, 8, 9, 10, 19, 22, 23, 25, 64, 153, 158, 163, 203, 216 necessary actuality, 157 necessary being, 155, 157 necessary by definition, 23, 25 necessary essences, 163 necessary existence, 160 necessary if, 10 necessary in definition, 163 necessary premises, 160 necessary principles,, 26 necessary proposition, 24 necessary relationships, 9 necessary scheme, 25 necessary truth, 25 necessary truth, 25, 155 necessities, 11, 17, 18, 128, 133, 157, 158 necessity, 10, 22, 25, 49, 155, 156, 157, 163, 170, 199, 216, 217 negative prehensions, 187 negative value, 128, 174, 175 negative-positive, 28 neighbors, 194 Neolithic, 40, 48, 93 neurotic, 175, 178 neurotic, 194 never-beginning, 163, 170 never-ending, 163, 171 new age, 108, 110, 116 New Covenant, 116 New Testament, 116 New World Order, 117 Newton, 67, 96 nonbeing, 70, 72, 184 noncontingency, 160, 216 None, 9, 167 nongendered or commongendered, 2 non-necessity, 10 nonrational, 9, 10, 216 nonsense, 22, 23, 155, 157, 216 North Africa,, 42 north pole, 110 not necessary, 9 nothing, 10, 16, 27, 63, 72, 158, 173, 175 no-thing, 87 nothingness, 10, 63, 68, 73, 96, 170, 216 novelty, 174 O obedience, 117, 119, 122, 145 obeying, 152 object, 73, 94, 169 objects, 28, 71, 94, 178 obligation,, 173 Odin, 209 offspring, 41 om, 58, 214 omega, 58, 214 omega, 193, 195 omnipotence, 173, 174, 216 omnipresence, 65 omniscience, 172, 181, 184 omniscient, 132, 172 omphalos, 58 once-in-a-universe, 87 one, 69, 76, 81, 84, 87 one group, 87 one in the many, 58 one series, 77 one whole, 153 Onias, 116, 117 Ontological Argument, 155, 217 or other, 163 orderly, 145 ordinary existences, 158 ordinary objects, 88 orgasm, 39 original, 81 original waters, 78 Orpheus, 110, 134 Orphic, 53, 110 Orphism, 217 owl, 35 P Paleolithic, 32 panentheism, 48, 151, 153, 217 panentheistic, 110 panpsychism, 217 pantheism, 48, 95, 110, 151, 153, 217 pantheists, 106 paradoxes, 63 parents, 3 Parmenides, 9, 24, 59, 63, 65, 68, 69, 72, 73, 76, 77, 81, 85, 95, 94, 97, 128, 130, 155, 156, 170173, 194, 204, 206, 215, 216, 223, 224 part of the present, 85 parthenogenesis, 33, 218 parthenogenic, 40, 48 particular, 59, 65, 218 parts, 2, 18, 84, 85, 158 past, 32, 59, 77, 85, 86, 128, 130, 172, 179, 172, 174 past circumstances, 18 A Process Introduction to Philosophy 241 Index past conditions, 19 paternity, 93 patriarch, 41 patriarchal, 2, 48, 78, 93, 106, 107, 114, 218 patriarchal ethics, 93 patriarchal God, 42 patriarchal gods, 41 patriarchal lineage, 114 patriarchal philosophers, 78 patriarchal religions, 42 patriarchal religious bureaucracies, 101 patriarchal salvation, 93 patriarchy, 11, 35, 41, 42, 101, 102, 192 patterns, 65, 191 Paul, 100, 105, 110, 176 Paul of Tarsus, 54, 102 Pauline/Augustinian, 123 Pegasus, 107 Pentateuch, 116 Penthouse, 39 perfect (complete) island, 160 perfect island, 155, 160 perfect of its kind, 160 perfection, 161, 162, 163 Perseus, 106, 110, 108 Persian navy, 109 Persians, 114 person, 3, 6, 75, 87, 130, 143, 218 personal identity, 11 personal pronouns, 2 personal series, 143 perspective perspective, 86, 171, 187 pH, 58 Phanes, 110 Pharisees, 116 philosophers, 2, 3, 5, 6, 11, 12, 24, 70, 127, 128, 155 philosophical, 2, 3, 5, 6, 65 philosophical adventure, 63 philosophical positions, 24 philosophical problems, 2 philosophical system, 64 philosophies, 2, 40 philosophize, 11 philosophy, 2, 3, 5, 6, 9, 11, 13,, 22, 24, 25, 31, 35, 48, 59, 78, 106, 163, 194, 195, 218 philosophy class, 5 Phrygian, 217 Phrygian hat, 107 physical pain,, 144, 175 physical reality, 54 physical science, 86 physical theory, 17 physicists, 17 physics, 73, 87, 172 pi, !., 8 pigments, 68 Pilate, 123 plagiarism, 6 planetary spheres, 53 Plato, 69, 77, 163, 176, 211, 217 Plato, 54, 77, 78, 82, 130, 157, 160, 174, 206, 208, 213, 218 Platonic, 157 Platonism, 110 pleasure, 3, 40, 132 Pleiades, 108 plenum, 68, 218 pluralism, 68, 205 pluralistic theory, 68 poet, 3 point, 68 point of view, 86, 171 pole, 107 Polydectes, 107 polytheism, 152 pornography, 34 positive value, 174 positivism, 22, 23, 153, 219 positivist, 155, 159 positivistic, 128 positivists, 156, 157, 158, 163, 164, 209, 217 possibilities, 9, 64 possibility, 159, 172 possibility of nonexistence, 161 possible, 9 possible acts, 162 possible actualities, 162 possible fact, 10, 22, 65 potential, 68 potentiality, 28, 68, 162, 172, 178, 182, 219 Potter, 118 power, 16, 108, 122, 168, 173, 174 power of glory, 122 power of nurturing, 122 power of the cosmic female, 35 power of the Goddess, 58 power worship, 174 prayers, 118 precession, 106 precession of the equinoxes, 106, 110, 219 preChristian, 134 predators, 39 predestinationist, 117 predestined, 117 pregnant, 58 prehending, 176 premise, 65, 132 premises, 65 prepatriarchal, 2, 101, 106, 151 prepatriarchy, 3 present, 81, 172 present decisions, 19 present whole, 166, 170 priest, 34, 117 priestess, 39, 40, 101, 106, 114 priesthoods, 42 priests, 101, 116 primal ocean, 48 primary qualities, 219 primordial, 10, 32, 72, 133, 220 principle, 9, 49, 65 Principle of Rarefaction and Condensation, 49 Principle of Sufficient Reason, , 49 71, 220 principle of value, 132 Principle of Verification, 22, 23 probability, 220 problem, 2, 6 problem with Heraclitus’ system, 224 process, 5, 36, 41, 58, 84, 87, 94, 162, 172, 184 process ends, 85 process metaphysic, 172 process philosophy, 3, 206 professionals, 3 professor, 3 pronouns, 2 prophet, 117 Prophet, Priest and King, 117 propitiation, 34 proposition, 22, 163, 173, 202, 203, 220 Proslogium, 156 pseudepigrapha, 118 psyche, 93, 217 psychic, 188 psychology, 17, 87 psychopomps, 36 puberty, 93 pubic, 35 pubic triangle, 35 punish, 132 punishes, 42 punishment, 34, 93, 121, 132, 133, 152 pure, 68 pure abstractions, 77 pure flux, 59 pure potentiality, 162, 173 puritanism, 116 purity, 115, 194 purpose, 50 purpose of life, 11 Pythagoras, 53, 217, 218 Pythagorean, 95 Pythagorean Theorem, 54 Pythagorean Tuning, 53 Pythagoreans, 52, 65, 93, 214 242 Change and the Unsurpassable Index Q qualities, 64 quality, 178 quantification, 9, 18, 208, 220 quantified, 73, 172 quantifiers, 17, 64, 173 quantity, 178 quantum leap, 73 quantum physics, 17, 220 quarks, 49 queen, 21 40, 101 questioning, 5 Quinn, 2 Qumran, 114, 115, 116, 118, 120, 211 R racism, 42, 195 radiation experiments, 12 rape, 39 ratio !., 8 rational, 9, 191, 194 rational aspects, 9 rationalism, 221 rationalist, 78 rationality,8 195 reabsorption, 76 reality, 2, 8, 9, 17, 32, 36, 48, 63, 70, 75, 77, 94, 128, 153, 172, 191, 194, 205 really aesthetic, 128 really real, 84 rearrangement, 69, 73 reason, 9, 10, 132, 221 reasons, 5, 6 rebirth, 32, 75, 76, 93, 194 recycled, 71, 76 reduction, 49 reductionism, 49 re-embodied, trapped again in mater, 76 refer, 82 refrigerator, 22, 63 regular solids, 54 reincarnation, 32, 76 related, 65 relations, 221, 168 relationships, 73, 171, 178 relativism, 21, 22, 23, 192, 198, 219, 222 relativists, 22 relativity physics, 86 Relativity, the Special and General Theory of, 222 religio, 36 religion, 2, 31, 93, 106, 108 ,191, 223 religion religion versus science, 49 religions, 40, 48 religious, 11, 12, 32, 40, 110, 144, 170, 173 religious wars, 55 remember, 72, 166 remembered, 143 Renaissance, 42 repetition, 134 Representational Theory of Knowledge, 81, 223 reproduction, 32, 40, 101 reproductive organs,194 restricted, 26 resurrected, 94, 121 resurrection, 123 revelation, 223 revenge, 178 reward, 121, 148, 152 Rhodes, 106 right, 5, 6, 174 right triangle, 54 risky, 5 ritual, 34, 40, 115, 154, 191 ritual bathing, 116 ritual eating, 115 ritual mutilations, 102 Road of Darkness, 119 Road of Light, 119 rock, 109 Roman, 110, 116 Roman Empire, 110 Romans, 109 Rule Forty-Two, 7 rules, 23 Russia, 42 S s/he, 146 Sabbath, 118 sacred, 12, 192 sacred and the profane, 39 sacred king, 40, 101, 111, 123 sacred number, 54 sacrifice, 40, 101, 134 sacrificed, 33, 110 sacrificed bulls, 110 sacrificed king, 101 sacrifices, 34, 106 sacrificial bull, 102 sacrificial male, 40 Sadducees, 116 saints, 42, 115 salvation, 105, 117 same being, 77 same thing, 77 Samyutta-nikaya, 75 saner, 2 Sankara, 62 Santa Claus, 107, 191 Sarah, 114 Satan, 121, 152 Sautrantika Buddhists, 75, 77 savage beasts, 42 saved, 129, 184 saving knowledge, 117 savior, 105, 110 Scandinavian, 48, 83 scars, 144 Schlick, 29 science, 2, 106, 173 scientific, 12, 17, 26 scientific method, 49 Scorpio, 108 Scythian, 102 seal, 134 search for meaning, 22 seasons, 33 Second Coming, 118, 119 Second Enoch, 118 secondary qualities, 223 secret knowledge, 109, 110 secrets of the universe, 12 SECTS, 148 seed, 41, 68 self-contradiction, 10, 22, 25, 29, 63, 81, 84, 94, 157, 163, 170, 172, 223 self-contradictory, 8, 9, 27, 58, 63, 65, 128, 132, 159, 163, 172-174 self-creation, 173 self-mover, 68 self-other, 28 self-power, 173 self-sacrifice, 117, 176 semen, 35, 48 sense experience, 50, 77 sentence, 5, 9, 22 separation, 117 sequence, 73, 96 sequential, 72 series, 75, 85, 86, 87, 97, 133, 143, 162, 167, 170, 171, 181 series of acts, 158, 170 series of beings, 85, 156 series of contingent acts, 163 series of creatings, 85 series of experiences, 97 series of moments, 170 series of subjects,, 178 series of units, 75 serpent, 31, 103 seven heavens, 119 sex, 3, 33, 40, 102, 116, 153 sex cell, 33 sex roles, 34 sexes, 11 sexism, 101, 195 sexual connection, 34 sexual consummation, 102 sexual virility, 101 Shakespeare, 62 A Process Introduction to Philosophy 243 Index shaman, 39 shame, 100 shape, 8 Sheol, 118 shepherd, 110 Silbury Hill, 32 Silverstein, 93 Simplicius, 47 Simpson, 38 simultaneity, 86 simultaneous, 188 simultaneous Comparison, 59, 71, 84 simultaneous differences, 81 simultaneously, 82, 85 skeptical, 13 Skepticism, 223 Skeptics, 25 skull, 35 slave, 41 slavery, 101 sleep, 3, 7 smallest conceivable number, 55 snake, 35, 110 social cooperation, 88 social salvation, 130 society, 3 Socrates, 174 soil, 192 sol invictus, 110 solar events, 110 solar/lunar calendar, 115 solipsism, 82 (see Glossary entry), 221 Solomon’s, 116 Some, 9, 17, 27, 167 SomeNones, 64, 214 son, 40, 41, 101, 110, 147, 152, 194 son of God, 102, 110 Son of Man, 117 son-of-god, 106 Sons of Darkness, 118 sons of god, 115 Sons of Light, 115, 118 sons of the Goddess, 102 sorrow, 166 soul, 32, 76, 93, 94, 215 soul, 36, 53, 93, 94, 118, 130, 153 souls of animals, 119 sound sphere, 74 space, 67, 71, 74, 87, 97, 153, 170, 171, 224 Spader, 5 spatial, 174 spatial extent, 168 spatial-temporal continuum, 170 species, 3 specific possibilities, 172 speculative philosophy, 29 sperm, 39, 41, 102 Spinoza, 62, 80, 155 spiral, 6 spirits, 153 spiritual and changeless One, 76 split person, 144 spontaneity, 17 sports, 39 spring, 32 square root, 54 standard, 11 standard of value, 11 standing wave, 58 statement, 8 statement of fact, 132 static whole, 94 steppes of Russia, 102 Stoics, 106, 107, 224 Stoic university, 105 Stoicism, 117, 224 stuff, 65 stuff of reality, 85 subject, 73, 94, 169, 178 subjective, 76 subjective aim, 182, 187 submission, 119 submit, 121 substance, 62, 224 substance/attribute philosophy, 68 substitute king, 101 substratum, 41 succession, 59 successive differences, 59 successive many, 76 successively, 172 suffer, 152, 175, 178 suffered, 3, 94, 121, 143, 175 Suffering Servant, 116, 117, 121 suicide, 52 Sumerian/Babylonian, 41 summer solstice, 108 superject, 185 supernatural, 150 supernatural powers, 150 supremacy, 170 supreme, 162, 167, 226 supreme degree, 167 supreme Object, 178 supreme Subject, 178 supreme suffering, 175 supreme whole, 171 surpass, 160 syllogism, 132, 225 symbol, 32, 82, 134, 192, 215, 226 symbolic truth, 82 symbolism, 35, 82, 129, 232 symbolized, 101, 108, 109 sympatheia, 106, 108 systematic, 5 T talk, 6 tarsos, 106 tauroctony, 108 Taurus, 106, 107 Teacher of Righteousness, 116, 117 temple, 100, 116 temporal, 174 temporary death, 185 temptations, 52 tertiary qualities, 70 Tertullian, 100, 191 testing, 154 tests, 119 tetrahedron, 54 Thales, 47, 48 Thales thanksgiving), 34 that, 158 that than which nothing greater can be conceived, 157, 159, 160, 162, 179 the best, 174 the Chosen, 122 the Unsurpassable, 160 theism, 129 theistic, 144, 153 theistic attribute, 167 theistic concepts, 143 theocentric, 133 theodicy, 151 Theories of Everything, 49 Theory of Knowledge, 80 Theory of Relativity, 86 thing, 65, 156 thinkers, 5, 6 thinking things, 80 third heaven, 119 Tiamat, 41 Timaeus, 108, 208 time, 66, 67, 87, 93, 97, 122, 170, 172, 224, 229 tobacco advertising, 12 tolerant, 3 tomb, 32, 71 Torah, 116 torchbearers, 108 tortoise, 63 torture, 119 tragedy, 152, 175, 178 tragic, 176, 192 transmissions, 86, 181 trauma, 144 tree, 36 tree of life, 35 triangle, 35 trinity, 35, 107, 226 trivialization, 134 Troy, 49 244 Change and the Unsurpassable Index true, 6 truth, 6, 9, 22, 24, 210, 214, 232, 233 Tyson, 38 U UFO, 52 ugly, 132 ultimacy, 170 ultimate ultimate, 9, 11, 129, 151, 167, 226 ultimate battle, 118 ultimate characteristic, 128 ultimate degree, 167 ultimate generalizations., 25 ultimate happiness, 176 ultimate metaphor, 101 ultimate order, 122 ultimate purpose, 128 ultimate value principle, 132 ultra-rationalism, 23, 172 ultra-rationalist, 9, 58, 210, 221, 226 ultra-rationalistic metaphysician, 22 unavoidable, 8, 23 unavoidable causes, 16 unavoidable commonalties, 9 unavoidable relationships, 9 unbiased, 2 Unbounded, 49, 162 Uncle Sam, 88 unclean, 116 unconditionally necessary, 10, 164 unconditionally rational, 22 unconquered sun, 110 underground sanctuaries, 109 understand, 5, 6 undertaker, 146 underworld, 32, 35 unhealthy, 144 Uni, 36, 48 unicorns, 158 unified diversity (see Chapter 18), 174 unique, 87 uniqueness of a series, 87 units, 75 unity, 41, 53, 48, 63, 72, 94, 129, 201, 202 unity of all reality, 32 unity of experience, 143 universal, 8, 12, 23 universal characteristics, 11, 133, 178 universal comparison, 11 universal fact, 65 universal factor, 17, 158 universal female, 32 universal knowledge, 8, 11, 158 universalities, 9 universally exemplified, 26 universally general characteristics of reality, 191 universally or ultimately rational, 9 universals, 65 universe, 36, 110, 133 universe, 65, 71, 88, 107, 132, 163 University of Missouri, 3 unknowable, 133 unlimited, 49 Unmoved Mover, 77, 132, 218 unnecessary, 6 unpredictable, 144 unqualifiedly necessary, 23 unspecified range, 173 unsurpassability, 41, 78, 159, 163 unsurpassable, 83, 121, 133, 150, 210, 226 Unsurpassable, 22, 162, 163, 174, 181, 204 unsurpassable evil, 175 unsurpassable existence, 158 unsurpassable existence, 158 unsurpassable freedom, 173 unsurpassable individual, 162 unsurpassable lover, 132 unsurpassable series, 174 unsurpassed, 167 unsurpassed whole, 176 unthinking things, 80 Upward Way, 58 urine, 106 uterus, 35 utilitarian, 174 Utilitarianism, 227 V vacuum, 68 vagina dentata, 102 valid, 156 validity, 10 valuations, 70 value, 128, 129, 132, 162, 174, 191 value theory, 163 values, 3 variety, 194 Vedanta, 62 velocity, 69 vengeance, 119 Verifiability Principle of Meaning, 23, 24 Vietnam, 3, 31, 127 violated, 59 virgin, 33, 58, 108, 110, 123 virginity, 41 voice, 58 voice umm, 68 void, 70, 72, 73, 170, 171, 179, void, 72 vortex, 49 vulva, 35, 36 W Wakan-Tanka, 150 Walker, 58 war, 42, 118, 194 warrior, 116, 218 Washington, 38 wastefulness, 3 water, 48 Watergate, 12 Western philosophy, 47, 50 what, 158 wheat, 108 Whitehead, 2- 4, 7, 11, 21, 22, 25, 28, 29, 54, 55, 59, 65, 71, 82, 84, 85, 87- 89, 94, 97, 127, 130, 132, 146, 154, 157, 158, 162, 170, 172, 176, 178, 180-183, 185, 187, 198, 199, 201, 202, 204- 207, 210, 213, 214, 218224, 228-231 Whiteheadian process, 163 Whitman, 93 whole, 2, 9, 18, 28, 73, 95, 129, 132, 157, 161, 162, 167, 175, 183, 192, 204, 227 whole of things, 32 whole, or a common aspect of wholes wholeness, 72 Wholes, 18, 157, 158, 171 wholesome, 39 Wicca, 218 wife, 3 will, 151 willful 151 winter solstice, 108 witch craze, 101 witch-burning craze, 42 witches, 42 wives, 100 Woman, 100, 114 womb, 41, 48, 58, 71, 75, 78, 143, 144, 192 womb control, 41, 93 womb liquid, 32 womb/tomb, 102 womb-liquid, 32 women, 3, 115, 117, 118, 194 Word, 58 World Soul, 96 World Tree, 83 world-views, 5 worship, 2, 122, 163, 177 worthiness, 40 A Process Introduction to Philosophy Index worthy, 93, 110 wrath, 150 Y Yahweh, 101, 116 Yggdrasil, 48, 83 yoni, 36 Z Z particles, 51 Zadok, 116, 117 Zeno, 205 Zeno’s paradox, 73, 227 Zeus, 58, 106, 109 Zeus versus the Vortex, 49 Zhurinovski, 38 Zodiac, 194, 219 Zoroastrianism, 102, 110 245 246 Duane Voskuil studied under Charles Hartshorne at Emory University for a masters degree in philosophy during 1960-61. He went on to finish his doctorate at the University of Missouri, Columbia in 1969 after some time away from formal studies to start a family and teach secondary English and German. He has since taught philosophy for the university of North Dakota system for 16 years, and Chaired the Department of Philosophy at the University of North Dakota, Grand Forks. _________ After completing a Bachelor of Fine Arts, 1976, he taught visual arts for four years, during which time he developed the concepts to build solar-heated, earth-covered residences, and spent several years as a contractor in Bismarck, North Dakota, during the ‘80s designing and building these interesting and environmentally low-impact homes. _________ An interest in advanced woodworking prompted him to build his daughter’s first fullsized violin in 1973. Over the years, this craft has grown into a full-time business, partly out of necessity when controversy made teaching contracts in philosophy scarce. The science and art of violin acoustics and the theory of sound potentiality have merged to produce a theory of violin tuning that is now being tested and published. Duane Voskuil, 1991, b. 1938 Social justice, whether for gender equality or to restrict the arbitrary exercise of power, has always been a concern for Dr. Voskuil. He wrote the North Dakota bill which became the first law in the United States in 1995 to forbid non-consensual genital mutilation, and has now gone to court to ask the law be expanded to protect male minors, since the state law in the form it was eventually passed, like the recent federal law, only protects females. _________ Voskuil was born in South Dakota, raised in Wisconsin, many years on his mother’s folks’ farmstead near Baldwin. He has 5 children and a step-son from two marriages. He is presently working on manuscripts for publication that range from a ceramic testing lab manual, and a book on verbals, to poetry and philosophical essays, while building master violins and lecturing. 247